This is a modern-English version of A critical history of Greek philosophy, originally written by Stace, W. T. (Walter Terence). It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

[Transcriber's Notes]

[Transcriber's Notes]

This text is derived from a copy in the Ave Maria University library, catalog number "B 171 .S8"

Page numbers in this book are indicated by numbers enclosed in curly braces, e.g. {99}. They have been located where page breaks occurred in the original book.

This text comes from a copy in the Ave Maria University library, catalog number "B 171 .S8"

Page numbers in this book are shown as numbers in curly braces, like {99}. They have been placed where page breaks happened in the original book.

[End Transcriber's Notes]

Understood! Please provide the text you would like me to modernize.


A CRITICAL HISTORY OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY

MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED
LONDON - BOMBAY - CALCUTTA - MADRAS
MELBOURNE

MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED
LONDON - MUMBAI - KOLKATA - CHENNAI
MELBOURNE


THE MACMILLAN COMPANY
NEW YORK - BOSTON - CHICAGO
DALLAS - SAN FRANCISCO

THE MACMILLAN COMPANY
NEW YORK - BOSTON - CHICAGO
DALLAS - SAN FRANCISCO

THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd
TORONTO

THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd
TORONTO


A CRITICAL HISTORY OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY

BY

W. T. STACE

MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED
ST. MARTIN'S STREET, LONDON
1920

BY

W. T. STACE

MACMILLAN AND CO., LIMITED
ST. MARTIN'S STREET, LONDON
1920

COPYRIGHT

COPYRIGHT

GLASGOW: PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO. LTD.

GLASGOW: PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO. LTD.

PREFACE

This book contains the substance, and for the most part the words, of a course of public lectures delivered during the first three months of 1919. The original division into lectures has been dropped, the matter being more conveniently redivided into chapters.

This book includes the content, and mostly the exact wording, of a series of public lectures given during the first three months of 1919. The initial division into lectures has been removed, and the material has been more conveniently reorganized into chapters.

The audience to whom the lectures were delivered was composed of members of the general public, and not only of students. For the most part they possessed no previous knowledge of philosophy. Hence this book, like the original lectures, assumes no previous special knowledge, though it assumes, of course, a state of general education in the reader. Technical philosophical terms are carefully explained when first introduced; and a special effort has been made to put philosophical ideas in the clearest way possible. But it must be remembered that many of the profoundest as well as the most difficult of human conceptions are to be found in Greek philosophy. Such ideas are difficult in themselves, however clearly expressed. No amount of explanation can ever render them anything but difficult to the unsophisticated mind, and anything in the nature of "philosophy made easy" is only to be expected from quacks and charlatans.

The audience for the lectures included members of the general public, not just students. Most of them had no prior knowledge of philosophy. Therefore, this book, like the original lectures, requires no specialized knowledge, but it does assume that the reader has a general level of education. Technical philosophical terms are explained clearly when they are first mentioned, and special effort has been made to present philosophical ideas as clearly as possible. However, it should be noted that many of the deepest and most challenging human concepts originate from Greek philosophy. These ideas are inherently complex, even when expressed clearly. No amount of explanation can make them easy for someone who isn't familiar with the subject, and anything claiming to be "philosophy made easy" should be viewed with skepticism, as it's typically offered by frauds and charlatans.

Greek philosophy is not, even now, antiquated. It is not from the point of view of an antiquary or historian {vi} that its treasures are valuable. We are dealing here with living things, and not with mere dead things--not with the dry bones and debris of a bygone age. And I have tried to lecture and write for living people, and not for mere fossil-grubbers. If I did not believe that there is to be found here, in Greek philosophy, at least a measure of the truth, the truth that does not grow old, I would not waste five minutes of my life upon it.

Greek philosophy isn't outdated, even today. Its treasures aren't valuable just from the perspective of an antiquarian or historian {vi}. We’re engaging with living ideas, not just remnants of the past—it's not about the dry bones and debris of a bygone era. I've aimed to lecture and write for people who are alive today, not for those who just dig up fossils. If I didn't think that Greek philosophy offers at least some enduring truth, something that doesn't fade with time, I wouldn't spend even five minutes on it.

"We do not," says a popular modern writer, [Footnote 1] "bring the young mind up against the few broad elemental questions that are the questions of metaphysics.... We do not make it discuss, correct it, elucidate it. That was the way of the Greeks, and we worship that divine people far too much to adopt their way. No, we lecture to our young people about not philosophy but philosophers, we put them through book after book, telling how other people have discussed these questions. We avoid the questions of metaphysics, but we deliver semi-digested half views of the discussions of, and answers to these questions made by men of all sorts and qualities, in various remote languages and under conditions quite different from our own. . . . It is as if we began teaching arithmetic by long lectures upon the origin of the Roman numerals, and then went on to the lives and motives of the Arab mathematicians in Spain, or started with Roger Bacon in chemistry, or Sir Richard Owen in comparative anatomy .... It is time the educational powers began to realise that the questions of metaphysics, the elements of philosophy, are, here and now to be done afresh in each mind .... What is wanted is philosophy, and not a shallow smattering of the history of philosophy ... {vii} The proper way to discuss metaphysics, like the proper way to discuss mathematics or chemistry, is to discuss the accumulated and digested product of human thought in such matters."

"We do not," says a popular modern writer, [Footnote 1] "confront young minds with the few essential questions that are the questions of metaphysics.... We don’t have them discuss, correct, or clarify these ideas. That was how the Greeks did it, and we revere that remarkable culture too much to adopt their approach. No, we educate our young people about not philosophy but philosophers; we take them through book after book, explaining how others have debated these questions. We steer clear of the questions of metaphysics, but we present semi-digested half-understandings of the discussions and answers to these questions from men of various backgrounds, in different languages, and under conditions quite separate from our own. . . . It’s like teaching arithmetic through lengthy lectures on the origins of Roman numerals, then moving to the lives and motivations of Arab mathematicians in Spain, or starting with Roger Bacon in chemistry, or Sir Richard Owen in comparative anatomy .... It’s time for our educational systems to understand that the questions of metaphysics and the basics of philosophy need to be explored anew in each individual mind .... What’s needed is real philosophy, not a shallow overview of the history of philosophy ... {vii} The right way to approach metaphysics, like the right way to tackle mathematics or chemistry, is to engage with the accumulated and processed results of human thought in these areas."

[Footnote 1: H. G. Wells in "First and Last Things."]

[Footnote 1: H. G. Wells in "First and Last Things."]

Plausible words these, certain to seem conclusive to the mob, notwithstanding that for one element of truth they contain nine of untruth! The elements of truth are that our educational system unwarrantably leaves unused the powerful weapon of oral discussion--so forcibly wielded by the Greeks--and develops book knowledge at the expense of original thought. Though even here it must be remembered, as regards the Greeks, (1) that if they studied the history of philosophy but little, it was because there was then but little history of philosophy to study, and (2) that if anyone imagines that the great Greek thinkers did not fully master the thought of their predecessors before constructing their own systems, he is grievously mistaken, and (3) that in some cases the over-reliance on oral discussion--the opposite fault to ours--led to intellectual dishonesty, quibbling, ostentation, disregard of truth, shallowness, and absence of all principle; this was the case with the Sophists.

These words may seem convincing to the masses, but for every piece of truth, there are nine pieces of falsehood! The truths are that our education system recklessly neglects the powerful tool of oral discussion—so effectively used by the Greeks—and instead promotes theoretical knowledge at the cost of original thinking. However, it's important to remember regarding the Greeks that (1) if they explored the history of philosophy very little, it was because there was hardly any history of philosophy to study at that time, (2) anyone who thinks that the great Greek philosophers did not thoroughly understand the ideas of those who came before them before developing their own theories is seriously mistaken, and (3) in some cases, an over-reliance on oral discussion—the opposite issue we face—led to intellectual dishonesty, frivolous arguments, showiness, neglect of the truth, superficiality, and a lack of principles; this was especially true of the Sophists.

As to the comparisons between arithmetic and philosophy, chemistry and philosophy, etc., they rest wholly upon a false parallel, and involve a total failure to comprehend the nature of philosophic truth, and its fundamental difference from arithmetical, chemical, or physical truth. If Eratosthenes thought the circumference of the earth to be so much, whereas it has now been discovered to be so much, then the later correct view simply cancels and renders nugatory the older view. {viii} The one is correct, the other incorrect. We can ignore and forget the incorrect view altogether. But the development of philosophy proceeds on quite other principles. Philosophical truth is no sum in arithmetic to be totted up so that the answer is thus formally and finally correct or incorrect. Rather, the philosophical truth unfolds itself, factor by factor, in time, in the successive systems of philosophy, and it is only in the complete series that the complete truth is to be found. The system of Aristotle does not simply cancel and refute that of Plato. Spinoza does not simply abolish Descartes. Aristotle completes Plato, as his necessary complement. Spinoza does the same for Descartes. And so it is always. The calculation of Eratosthenes is simply wrong, and so we can afford to forget it. But the systems of Plato, Aristotle, Spinoza, Leibniz, etc., are all alike factors of the truth. They are as true now as they were in their own times, though they are not, and never were, the whole truth. And therefore it is that they are not simply wrong, done with, finished, ended, and that we cannot afford to forget them. Whether it is not possible to bring the many lights to a single focus, to weld the various factors of the truth into a single organic whole or system, which should thus be the total result to date, is another question. Only one such attempt has ever been made, but no one will pretend that it is possible to understand it without a thorough knowledge of all previous systems, a knowledge, in fact, of the separate factors of the truth before they are thus combined into a total result. Besides, that attempt, too, is now part of the history of philosophy!

When it comes to comparing arithmetic and philosophy, chemistry and philosophy, and so on, those comparisons rely on a misleading parallel and completely miss the nature of philosophical truth and how it fundamentally differs from arithmetic, chemical, or physical truth. If Eratosthenes estimated the circumference of the earth to be a certain number, and it’s now been found to be a different number, the new understanding simply invalidates the old one. One view is correct, the other is not. We can disregard the incorrect view entirely. However, the development of philosophy follows a different set of principles. Philosophical truth isn’t a simple arithmetic sum that results in a definitive correct or incorrect answer. Instead, philosophical truth reveals itself gradually, piece by piece, over time through the different philosophical systems, and it’s only in the complete collection that we find the full truth. Aristotle’s system doesn’t just negate Plato’s. Spinoza doesn’t simply eliminate Descartes. Aristotle adds to Plato as a necessary counterpart. Spinoza does the same for Descartes. This pattern continues. Eratosthenes’ calculation is simply wrong and can be forgotten. But the systems of Plato, Aristotle, Spinoza, Leibniz, and others are all essential components of the truth. They are as valid now as they were in their own times, even though they are not, and never were, the totality of truth. That’s why they aren’t just wrong or over and done with, and we can’t afford to forget them. Whether it’s possible to unify all these insights into a single coherent system that represents the total result so far is another question entirely. Only one such attempt has ever been made, but no one would claim it can be understood without a deep knowledge of all the previous systems, actually knowing the individual components of the truth before they are combined into a comprehensive result. Furthermore, that attempt is also now part of the history of philosophy!

Hence any philosophical thinking which is not founded {ix} upon a thorough study of the systems of the past will necessarily be shallow and worthless. And the notions that we can dispense with this study, and do everything out of our own heads, that everyone is to be his own philosopher, and is competent to construct his own system in his own way--such ideas are utterly empty and hollow. Of these truths, indeed, we see a notable example in what the writer just quoted styles his "metaphysic." This so-called metaphysic is wholly based upon the assumption that knowledge and its object exist, each on its own account, external to one another, the one here, the other there over against it, and that knowledge is an "instrument" which in this external manner takes hold of its object and makes it its own. The very moment the word "instrument" is used here, all the rest, including the invalidity of knowledge, follows as a matter of course. Such assumption then--that knowledge is an "instrument"--our writer makes, wholly uncritically, and without a shadow of right. He gives no sign that it has ever even occurred to him that this is an assumption, that it needs any enquiry, or that it is possible for anyone to think otherwise. Yet anyone who will take the trouble, not merely superficially to dip into the history of philosophy, but thoroughly to submit himself to its discipline, will at least learn that this is an assumption, a very doubtful assumption, too, which no one now has the right to foist upon the public without discussion as if it were an axiomatic truth. He might even learn that it is a false assumption. And he will note, as an ominous sign, that the subjectivism which permeates and directs the whole course of Mr. Wells's thinking is identical in character with that {x} subjectivism which was the essential feature of the decay and downfall of the Greek philosophic spirit, and was the cause of its final ruin and dissolution.

Any philosophical thinking that isn't based on a thorough study of past systems will inevitably be shallow and worthless. The idea that we can ignore this study and come up with everything on our own, that everyone should be their own philosopher and can create their own system however they like—these ideas are completely empty and hollow. A clear example of this is found in what the author just mentioned as his "metaphysic." This so-called metaphysic is entirely founded on the assumption that knowledge and its object exist separately, one here and the other there, and that knowledge acts as an "instrument" that grasp its object in this external way. The moment the term "instrument" is mentioned, the invalidity of knowledge follows naturally. This assumption—that knowledge is an "instrument"—is taken by our writer without any critical thought, and he doesn't seem to realize that this is an assumption needing examination, nor does he consider that others might think differently. However, anyone willing to take the time to deeply engage with the history of philosophy, rather than just skimming it, will learn that this is indeed an assumption, a highly questionable one, that shouldn't be presented to the public as if it were an unquestionable truth. They might even discover that it is a false assumption. Additionally, one should notice, as a troubling sign, that the subjectivism running through Mr. Wells's entire argument is strikingly similar to the subjectivism that characterized the decline and downfall of Greek philosophical thought, ultimately leading to its ruin and dissolution.

I would counsel the young, therefore, to pay no attention to plausible and shallow words such as those quoted, but, before forming their own philosophic opinions, most thoroughly and earnestly to study and master the history of past philosophies, first the Greek and then the modern. That this cannot be done merely by reading a modern resume of that history, but only by studying the great thinkers in their own works, is true. But philosophical education must begin, and the function of such books as this, is, not to complete it, but to begin it; and to obtain first of all a general view of what must afterwards be studied in detail is no bad way of beginning. Moreover, the study of the development and historical connexions of the various philosophies, which is not found in the original writings themselves, will always provide a work for histories of philosophy to do.

I would advise young people to ignore superficial and convincing words like those mentioned, and instead, before forming their own philosophical views, to thoroughly and seriously study and understand the history of past philosophies, starting with the Greek ones and then moving on to modern philosophies. It's true that this can't be achieved just by reading a modern summary of that history, but only by engaging with the original works of the great thinkers. However, philosophical education must begin somewhere, and the purpose of books like this is not to complete that education but to start it; gaining a general overview of what needs to be studied in depth later is a good way to begin. Furthermore, studying the development and historical connections between different philosophies, which isn't found in the original texts, will always give historians of philosophy something to explore.

Two omissions in this book require, perhaps, a word of explanation.

Two omissions in this book might need some explanation.

Firstly, in dealing with Plato's politics I have relied on the "Republic," and said nothing of the "Laws." This would not be permissible in a history of political theories, nor even in a history of philosophy which laid any special emphasis on politics. But, from my point of view, politics lie on the extreme outer margin of philosophy, so that a more slender treatment of the subject is permissible. Moreover, the "Republic," whether written early or late, expresses, in my opinion, the views of Plato, and not those of Socrates, and it still remains the outstanding, typical, and characteristic {xi} expression of the Platonic political ideal, however much that ideal had afterwards to be modified by practical considerations.

Firstly, when it comes to Plato's politics, I've focused on the "Republic" and haven't mentioned the "Laws." This wouldn’t be acceptable in a history of political theories, or even in a philosophy history that emphasizes politics. However, from my perspective, politics is on the far edge of philosophy, so a more limited exploration of the topic is justified. Furthermore, the "Republic," regardless of whether it was written early or late, represents Plato's views, not Socrates', and it remains the most prominent, typical, and defining expression of the Platonic political ideal, even though that ideal later had to be adjusted due to practical considerations.

Secondly, I have not even mentioned the view, now held by some, that the theory of Ideas is really the work of Socrates, and not of Plato, and that Plato's own philosophy consisted in some sort of esoteric number-theory, combined with theistic and other doctrines. I can only say that this theory, as expounded for example by Professor Burnet, does not commend itself to me, that, in fact, I do not believe it, but that, it being impossible to discuss it adequately in a book of this kind, I have thought that, rather than discuss it inadequately, it were better to leave it alone altogether. Moreover, it stands on a totally different footing from, say, Professor Burnet's interpretation of Parmenides, which I have discussed. That concerned the interpretation of the true meaning of a philosophy. This merely concerns the question who was the author of a philosophy. That was a question of principle, this merely of personalities. That was of importance to the philosopher, this merely to the historian and antiquary. It is like the Bacon-Shakespeare question, which no lover of drama, as such, need concern himself with at all. No doubt the Plato-Socrates question is of interest to antiquarians, but after all, fundamentally, it does not matter who is to have the credit of the theory of Ideas, the only essential thing for us being to understand that theory, and rightly to apprehend its value as a factor of the truth. This book is primarily concerned with philosophical ideas, their truth, meaning, and significance, and not with the rights and wrongs of antiquarian disputes. It does indeed purport to {xii} be a history, as well as a discussion of philosophic conceptions. But this only means that it takes up philosophical ideas in their historical sequence and connexions, and it does this only because the conceptions of evolution in philosophy, of the onward march of thought to a determined goal; of its gradual and steady rise to the supreme heights of idealism, its subsequent decline, and ultimate collapse, are not only profoundly impressive as historical phenomena, but are of vital importance to a true conception of philosophy itself. Were it not for this, Mr. Wells would, I think, be right, and I for one should abandon treatment in historical order altogether. Lastly, I may remark that the description of this book as a critical history means that it is, or attempts to be critical, not of dates, texts, readings, and the like, but of philosophical conceptions.

Secondly, I haven't even mentioned the viewpoint held by some that the theory of Ideas actually belongs to Socrates rather than Plato, and that Plato’s philosophy was more about some sort of secret number theory mixed with theistic and other beliefs. I can only say that I don't agree with this theory, as outlined, for instance, by Professor Burnet. In fact, I don't believe it, but since it's impossible to discuss it properly in a book like this, I thought it would be better to leave it out entirely instead of addressing it insufficiently. Moreover, it’s completely different from Professor Burnet’s interpretation of Parmenides, which I have discussed. That dealt with understanding the true meaning of a philosophy. This simply asks who the author of a philosophy is. That was a matter of principle; this is about personalities. That matters to philosophers; this only matters to historians and collectors. It’s like the Bacon-Shakespeare debate, which doesn’t concern any true lover of drama at all. No doubt the Plato-Socrates issue interests antiquarians, but ultimately, it doesn’t really matter who gets credit for the theory of Ideas; the essential thing for us is to understand that theory and accurately grasp its value as a part of the truth. This book primarily focuses on philosophical ideas, their truth, meaning, and significance, not the arguments of antiquarian disputes. It does intend to {xii} be a history, as well as a discussion of philosophical concepts. But this simply means it addresses philosophical ideas in their historical sequence and connections, and it does this only because the evolution of philosophy, the progression of thought toward a determined goal, its gradual and steady climb to the highest levels of idealism, followed by its decline and ultimate collapse, are not only impressively significant as historical phenomena but are also crucial for a proper understanding of philosophy itself. Without this perspective, Mr. Wells would be right, and I, for one, would abandon a historical approach altogether. Lastly, I should mention that describing this book as a critical history means that it is, or at least tries to be critical, not of dates, texts, readings, and so forth, but of philosophical concepts.

I owe a debt of thanks to Mr. F. L. Woodward, M.A., late principal of Mahinda College, Galle, Ceylon, for assisting me in the compilation of the index of names, and in sundry other matters.

I want to thank Mr. F. L. Woodward, M.A., former principal of Mahinda College, Galle, Ceylon, for helping me put together the index of names and for various other things.

W.T.S.

W.T.S.

January, 1920.

January, 1920.

{xiii}

{xiii}

CONTENTS

CONTENTS

CHAPTER PAGE
I. THE IDEA OF PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL. THE ORIGIN AND DEVELOPMENT OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 1
II. THE IONICS. THALES. ANAXIMANDER. ANAXIMENES. OTHER IONIC THINKERS 20
III. THE PYTHAGOREANS 31
IV. THE ELEATICS. XENOPHANES. PARMENIDES. ZENO. CRITICAL REMARKS ON ELEATICISM 40
V. HERACLEITUS 72
VI. EMPEDOCLES 81
VII. THE ATOMISTS 86
VIII. ANAXAGORAS 94
IX. THE SOPHISTS 106
X. SOCRATES 127
XI. THE SEMI-SOCRATICS. THE CYNICS. THE CYRENAICS. THE MEGARICS 155
XII. PLATO 164

(i.) Life and writings
165

(ii.) The theory of knowledge
177

(iii.) Dialectic, or the theory of Ideas
183

(iv.) Physics, or the theory of existence
207

(a) The doctrine of the world
207

(b) The doctrine of the human soul
211
{xiv}

(v.) Ethics
217

(a) Of the individual
217

(b) The State
225

(vi.) Views on art
229

(vii.) Critical evaluation of Plato's philosophy
234
XIII. ARISTOTLE:

(i.) Life, writings, and overall character of his work
249

(ii.) Logic
260

(iii.) Metaphysics
261

(iv.) Physics, or the philosophy of nature
288

(v.) Ethics:

(a) The individual
314

(b) The State
320

(vi.) Aesthetics, or the theory of art
325

(vii.) Critical evaluation of Aristotle's philosophy
331
XIV. THE GENERAL CHARACTER OF POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY 339
XV. THE STOICS. LOGIC. PHYSICS. ETHICS 344
XVI. THE EPICUREANS. PHYSICS. ETHICS 344
XVII. THE SCEPTICS. PYRRHO. THE NEW ACADEMY. LATER SCEPTICISM 361
XVIII. TRANSITION TO NEO-PLATONISM 368
XIX. THE NEO-PLATONISTS 372

INDEX OF SUBJECTS 378

INDEX OF NAMES 382
{1}

A CRITICAL HISTORY OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY


CHAPTER I

THE IDEA OF PHILOSOPHY IN GENERAL.

THE ORIGINS AND DEVELOPMENT OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY


It is natural that, at the commencement of any study, one should be expected to say what the subject-matter of that study is. Botany is the knowledge of plants, astronomy of the heavenly bodies, geology of the rocks of the earth's crust. What, then, is the special sphere of philosophy? What is philosophy about? Now it is not as easy to give a concise definition of philosophy, as it is of the other sciences. In the first place, the content of philosophy has differed considerably in different periods of history. In general the tendency has been to narrow down the scope of the subject as knowledge advanced, to exclude from philosophy what was formerly included in it. Thus in the time of Plato, physics and astronomy were included as parts of philosophy, whereas now they constitute separate sciences. This, however, is not an insurmountable difficulty. What chiefly militates against the effort to frame a definition is that the precise content of philosophy is differently viewed by different schools of thought. Thus a definition of {2} philosophy which a follower of Herbert Spencer might frame would be unacceptable to an Hegelian, and the Hegelian definition would be rejected by the Spencerian. If we were to include in our definition some such phrase as "the knowledge of the Absolute," while this might suit some philosophers, others would deny that there is any Absolute at all. Another school would say that there may be an Absolute, but that it is unknowable, so that philosophy cannot be the knowledge of it. Yet another school would tell us that, whether there is or is not an Absolute, whether it is or is not knowable, the knowledge of it is in any case useless, and ought not to be sought. Hence no definition of philosophy can be appreciated without some knowledge of the special tenets of the various schools. In a word, the proper place to give a definition is not at the beginning of the study of philosophy, but at the end of it. Then, with all views before us, we might be able to decide the question.

It's natural that at the start of any study, one is expected to explain what the subject is about. Botany is the study of plants, astronomy is about heavenly bodies, and geology focuses on the rocks of the earth's crust. So, what is the specific area of philosophy? What does philosophy deal with? It's not as easy to define philosophy clearly as it is for other sciences. First, the content of philosophy has changed significantly over different historical periods. Generally, the trend has been to narrow the field as knowledge has progressed, excluding things that were once part of philosophy. For example, during Plato's time, physics and astronomy were considered parts of philosophy, while today they are recognized as separate sciences. However, this isn't an insurmountable issue. The main problem in trying to define philosophy is that different philosophical schools have different views on its content. A definition from a follower of Herbert Spencer would be unacceptable to a Hegelian, and vice versa. If we were to include a phrase like "the knowledge of the Absolute" in our definition, it might resonate with some philosophers, while others would argue that there is no Absolute at all. Another school might concede that there could be an Absolute but claim it is unknowable, so philosophy can't be the knowledge of it. Yet another perspective would argue that it doesn't matter if there is or isn't an Absolute, or if it can be known, since knowledge of it is ultimately useless and shouldn't be pursued. Therefore, no definition of philosophy can be fully appreciated without some understanding of the specific beliefs of various schools. In short, the right time to define philosophy is not at the beginning of studying it but at the end. Only then, with all views laid out, can we hope to answer the question.

I shall make no attempt, therefore, to place before you a precise definition. But perhaps the same purpose will be served, if I pick out some of the leading traits of philosophy, which serve to distinguish it from other branches of knowledge, and illustrate them by enumerating--but without any attempt at completeness--some of the chief problems which philosophers have usually attempted to solve. And firstly, philosophy is distinguished from other branches of knowledge by the fact that, whereas these each take some particular portion of the universe for their study, philosophy does not specialize in this way, but deals with the universe as a whole. The universe is one, and ideal knowledge of it would be one; but the principles of specialization and division of {3} labour apply here as elsewhere, and so astronomy takes for its subject that portion of the universe which we call the heavenly bodies, botany specializes in plant life, psychology in the facts of the mind, and so on. But philosophy does not deal with this or that particular sphere of being, but with being as such. It seeks to see the universe as a single co-ordinated system of things. It might be described as the science of things in general. The world in its most universal aspects is its subject. All sciences tend to generalize, to reduce multitudes of particular facts to single general laws. Philosophy carries this process to its highest limit. It generalizes to the utmost. It seeks to view the entire universe in the light of the fewest possible general principles, in the light, if possible, of a single ultimate principle.

I won't try to give you a precise definition. But maybe I can achieve the same goal by highlighting some key traits of philosophy that set it apart from other areas of knowledge, illustrating them by listing—though not exhaustively—some of the main problems that philosophers usually aim to tackle. First, philosophy is different from other fields because, while they each focus on specific parts of the universe, philosophy looks at the universe as a whole. The universe is a single entity, and ideally, knowledge of it would be unified. However, the principles of specialization and division of labor apply here, just like everywhere else, so astronomy studies the segment of the universe we call heavenly bodies, botany focuses on plant life, psychology examines the mind, and so forth. But philosophy doesn’t look at just one specific area of being; it examines being in general. It aims to perceive the universe as a single coordinated system of things. You could say it's the science of things in general. Its subject is the world in its most universal aspects. All sciences tend to generalize, reducing a multitude of specific facts to general laws. Philosophy takes this process to its highest extent. It generalizes as much as possible. It tries to understand the entire universe through the fewest possible general principles, and ideally, through one ultimate principle.

It is a consequence of this that the special sciences take their subject matter, and much of their contents, for granted, whereas philosophy seeks to trace everything back to its ultimate grounds. It may be thought that this description of the sciences is incorrect. Is not the essential maxim of modern science to assume nothing, to take nothing for granted, to assert nothing without demonstration, to prove all? This is no doubt true within certain limits, but beyond those limits it does not hold good. All the sciences take quite for granted certain principles and facts which are, for them, ultimate. To investigate these is the portion of the philosopher, and philosophy thus takes up the thread of knowledge where the sciences drop it. It begins where they end. It investigates what they take as a matter of course.

As a result, specialized sciences often take their subject matter and a lot of their content for granted, while philosophy aims to trace everything back to its fundamental reasons. One might argue that this view of the sciences is inaccurate. Isn't the core principle of modern science to assume nothing, to take nothing for granted, to assert nothing without proof, and to prove everything? This is certainly true to an extent, but beyond that, it doesn't apply. All sciences accept certain principles and facts as ultimate without question. Examining these is the role of the philosopher, and philosophy picks up the thread of knowledge where the sciences leave off. It starts where they finish, investigating what they assume to be obvious.

Let us consider some examples of this. The science of geometry deals with the laws of space. But it takes {4} space just as it finds it in common experience. It takes space for granted. No geometrician asks what space is. This, then, will be a problem for philosophy. Moreover, geometry is founded upon certain fundamental propositions which, it asserts, being self-evident, require no investigation. These are called "axioms." That two straight lines cannot enclose a space, and that equals being added to equals the results are equal, are common examples. Into the ground of these axioms the geometrician does not enquire. That is the business of philosophy. Not that philosophers affect to doubt the truth of these axioms. But surely it is a very strange thing, and a fact quite worthy of study, that there are some statements of which we feel that we must give the most laborious proofs, and others in the case of which we feel no such necessity. How is it that some propositions can be self-evident and others must be proved? What is the ground of this distinction? And when one comes to think of it, it is a very extraordinary property of mind that it should be able to make the most universal and unconditional statements about things, without a jot of evidence or proof. When we say that two straight lines cannot enclose a space, we do not mean merely that this has been found true in regard to all the particular pairs of straight lines with which we have tried the experiment. We mean that it never can be and never has been otherwise. We mean that a million million years ago two straight lines did not enclose a space, and that it will be the same a million million years hence, and that it is just as true on those stars, if there are any, which are invisible even to the greatest telescopes. But we have no experience of what will {5} happen a million million years hence, or of what can take place among those remote stars. And yet we assert, with absolute confidence, that our axiom is and must be equally true everywhere and at all times. Moreover, we do not found this on probabilities gathered from experience. Nobody would make experiments or use telescopes to prove such axioms. How is it that they are thus self-evident, that the mind can make these definite and far-reaching assertions without any evidence at all? Geometricians do not consider these questions. They take the facts for granted. To solve these problems is for philosophy.

Let's look at some examples of this. The science of geometry focuses on the laws of space. But it accepts space just as it appears in everyday life. Geometry assumes space is a given. No mathematician questions what space actually is. This, then, becomes a philosophical issue. Additionally, geometry is based on certain fundamental propositions that it claims are self-evident and require no further investigation. These are known as "axioms." For instance, the idea that two straight lines can't enclose a space and that when you add equals to equals, the result is equal, are common examples. The geometrician doesn't investigate the foundation of these axioms. That's something for philosophy to tackle. Not that philosophers doubt the truth of these axioms, but it is indeed very strange—and worthy of study—that some statements require extensive proofs while others don't seem to need any. Why can some propositions be accepted as self-evident while others must be proven? What underlies this distinction? When you think about it, it's remarkable that the mind can make broad, universal claims about things without any evidence or proof. When we say that two straight lines cannot enclose a space, we aren't just saying that this has been true for every specific pair of straight lines we've tested. We mean it never could be otherwise, and it never has been. We assert that millions of years ago, two straight lines did not enclose a space, and that this will still hold true millions of years from now, just as it is true for those distant stars, if there are any, that are beyond the reach of even the best telescopes. Yet, we have no experience of what will happen millions of years from now or of what could occur in those faraway stars. And still, we confidently assert that our axiom is and must always be true everywhere and at all times. Moreover, we don't base this on probabilities from experience. No one would conduct experiments or use telescopes to validate such axioms. Why is it, then, that they seem self-evident, allowing the mind to make definitive, far-reaching claims without any evidence? Geometricians don't ponder these questions. They take facts for granted. Solving these issues is the domain of philosophy.

Again, the physical sciences take the existence of matter for granted. But philosophy asks what matter is. At first sight it might appear that this question is one for the physicist and not the philosopher. For the problem of "the constitution of matter" is a well-known physical problem. But a little consideration will show that this is quite a different question from the one the philosopher propounds. For even if it be shown that all matter is ether, or electricity, or vortex-atoms, or other such, this does not help us in our special problem. For these theories, even if proved, only teach us that the different kinds of matter are forms of some one physical existence. But what we want to know is what physical existence itself is. To prove that one kind of matter is really another kind of matter does not tell us what is the essential nature of matter. That, therefore, is a problem, not of science, but of philosophy.

Once again, the physical sciences assume that matter exists. But philosophy questions what matter really is. At first, it might seem like this question is meant for physicists rather than philosophers. The issue of "the composition of matter" is a well-known scientific problem. However, a bit of thought shows that this is quite a different question from the one philosophers are asking. Even if we can prove that all matter is made up of ether, electricity, vortex-atoms, or something similar, it doesn’t address our specific question. These theories, even if validated, only show us that the various types of matter are forms of a single physical existence. What we really want to understand is what physical existence itself is. Demonstrating that one type of matter is actually another type doesn’t reveal the essential nature of matter. Therefore, this is a problem for philosophy, not science.

In the same way, all the sciences take the existence of the universe for granted. But philosophy seeks to know why it is that there is a universe at all. Is it {6} true, for example, that there is some single ultimate reality which produces all things? And if so, what sort of a reality is it? Is it matter, or mind, or something different from both? Is it good or evil? And if it is good, how is it that there is evil in the world?

In the same way, all sciences assume the existence of the universe. But philosophy tries to understand why there is a universe at all. Is it {6} true, for instance, that there is one ultimate reality that creates everything? And if that’s the case, what kind of reality is it? Is it matter, or mind, or something entirely different? Is it good or evil? And if it’s good, why is there evil in the world?

Moreover every science, except the purely mathematical sciences, assumes the truth of the law of causation. Every student of logic knows that this is the ultimate canon of the sciences, the foundation of them all. If we did not believe in the truth of the law of causation, namely, that everything which has a beginning has a cause, and that in the same circumstances the same things invariably happen, all the sciences would at once crumble to dust. In every scientific investigation, this truth is assumed. If we ask the zoologist how he knows that all camels are herbivorous, he will no doubt point in the first instance to experience. The habits of many thousands of camels have been observed. But this only proves that those particular camels are herbivorous. How about the millions that have never been observed at all? He can only appeal to the law of causation. The camel's structure is such that it cannot digest meat. It is a case of cause and effect. How do we know that water always freezes at 0° centigrade (neglecting questions of pressure, etc.)? How do we know that this is true at those regions of the earth where no one has ever been to see? Only because we believe that in the same circumstances the same thing always happens, that like causes always produce like effects. But how do we know the truth of this law of causation itself? Science does not consider the question. It traces its assertions back to this law, but goes no {7} further. Its fundamental canon it takes for granted. The grounds of causation, why it is true, and how we know it is true, are, therefore, philosophical questions.

Moreover, every science, except for the purely mathematical sciences, assumes the truth of the law of causation. Every logic student knows that this is the ultimate principle of the sciences, the foundation of them all. If we didn’t believe in the truth of the law of causation—that everything with a beginning has a cause, and that in the same circumstances the same things always happen—all the sciences would immediately fall apart. In every scientific investigation, this truth is assumed. If we ask the zoologist how he knows that all camels are herbivorous, he will likely point to experience at first. The habits of many thousands of camels have been observed. But this only shows that those specific camels are herbivorous. What about the millions that have never been observed at all? He can only refer to the law of causation. The camel's structure is such that it cannot digest meat. It’s a case of cause and effect. How do we know that water always freezes at 0° Celsius (ignoring issues of pressure, etc.)? How do we know that this is true in areas of the earth where no one has ever been to see? Only because we believe that in the same circumstances, the same thing always happens, that like causes always produce like effects. But how do we know the truth of this law of causation itself? Science does not address this question. It traces its assertions back to this law but does not go any {7} further. Its fundamental rule is taken for granted. The reasons behind causation, why it is true, and how we know it is true are, therefore, philosophical questions.

One may be tempted to enquire whether many of these questions, especially those connected with the ultimate reality, do not transcend human faculties altogether, and whether we had not better confine our enquiries to matters that are not "too high for us." One may question whether it is possible for finite minds to comprehend the infinite. Now it is very right that such questions should be asked, and it is essential that a correct answer should be found. But, for the present, there is nothing to say about the matter, except that these questions themselves constitute one of the most important problems of philosophy, though it is one which, as a matter of fact, has scarcely been considered in full until modern times. The Greeks did not raise the question. [Footnote 2] And as this is itself one of the problems of philosophy, it will be well to start with an open mind. The question cannot be decided offhand, but must be thoroughly investigated. That the finite mind of man cannot understand the infinite is one of those popular dogmatic assertions, which are bruited about from mouth to mouth, as if they were self-evident, and so come to tyrannize over men's minds. But for the most part those who make this statement have never thoroughly sifted the grounds of it, but simply take it as something universally admitted, and trouble no further about it. But at the very least we should first know exactly what {8} we mean by such terms as "mind," "finite," and "infinite." And we shall not find that our difficulties end even there.

One might wonder if many of these questions, especially those related to ultimate reality, go beyond human understanding altogether, and if we should focus our inquiries on matters that aren't "too high for us." One can question whether it's possible for limited minds to grasp the infinite. It's important that we ask these questions and seek correct answers. However, for now, there's not much to say besides the fact that these questions form one of the most significant issues in philosophy, though it hasn't been fully explored until modern times. The Greeks didn't raise this question. [Footnote 2] Since this is itself a philosophical problem, it’s best to approach it with an open mind. The question can't be answered quickly; it needs to be thoroughly examined. The idea that the finite mind of man can't understand the infinite is one of those popular claims that circulate as if they're self-evident, leading to a sort of mental dominance over people's thoughts. Yet, most who make this claim haven't closely examined its basis, simply accepting it as universally acknowledged, without probing any deeper. At the very least, we should first clarify what we mean by terms like "mind," "finite," and "infinite." And we’ll soon realize that our challenges don't end there.

[Footnote 2: The reasoning of the Sceptics and others no doubt involved this question. But they did not consider it in its peculiar modern form.]

[Footnote 2: The reasoning of the Skeptics and others definitely involved this question. But they did not view it in its unique modern form.]

Philosophy, then, deals with the universe as a whole; and it seeks to take nothing for granted. A third characteristic may be noted as especially important, though here no doubt we are trenching upon matters upon which there is no such universal agreement. Philosophy is essentially an attempt to rise from sensuous to pure, that is, non-senuous, thought. This requires some explanation.

Philosophy, then, looks at the universe as a whole and tries not to assume anything. A third important characteristic can be noted, although we might be getting into areas where there isn't universal agreement. Philosophy is fundamentally an attempt to move from sensory to pure, or non-sensory, thought. This needs some explanation.

We are conscious, so to speak, of two different worlds, the external physical world and the internal mental world. If we look outwards we are aware of the former, if we turn our gaze inwards upon our own minds we become aware of the latter. It may appear incorrect to say that the external world is purely physical, for it includes other minds. I am aware of your mind, and this is, to me, part of the world which is external to me. But I am not now speaking of what we know by inference, but only of what we directly perceive. I cannot directly perceive your mind, but only your physical body. In the last resort it will be found that I am aware of the existence of your mind only by inference from perceived physical facts, such as the movements of your body and the sounds that issue from your lips. The only mind which I can immediately perceive is my own. There is then a physical world external to us, and an internal mental world.

We are aware, in a sense, of two different worlds: the external physical world and the internal mental world. When we look outward, we recognize the former; when we turn our focus inward, we become aware of the latter. It might seem inaccurate to claim that the external world is purely physical, since it also includes other minds. I am aware of your mind, and that is part of the world outside of me. However, I’m not talking about what we know through inference; I’m only referring to what we can directly perceive. I can’t directly perceive your mind, only your physical body. Ultimately, I recognize the existence of your mind only by inferring it from what I see, like your body movements and the sounds you make. The only mind I can perceive right away is my own. So, we have a physical world outside of us and an internal mental world.

Which of these will naturally be regarded as the most real? Men will regard as the most real that which is the most familiar, that which they came first into {9} contact with, and have most experience of. And this is unquestionably the external material world. When a child is born, it turns its eyes to the light, which is an external physical thing. Gradually it gets to know different objects in the room. It comes to know its mother, but its mother is, in the first instance, a physical object, a body. It is only long afterwards that its mother becomes for the child a mind or a soul. In general, all our earliest experiences are of the material world. We come to know of the mental world only by introspection, and the habit of introspection comes in youth or manhood only, and to many people it hardly comes at all. In all those early impressionable years, therefore, when our most durable ideas of the universe are formed, we are concerned almost exclusively with the material world. The mental world with which we are much less familiar consequently tends to appear to all of us something comparatively unreal, a world of shadows. The bent of our minds becomes materialistic.

Which of these will naturally be seen as the most real? People will see as the most real what is most familiar, what they first encountered, and what they have the most experience with. And this is definitely the external material world. When a child is born, it turns its eyes to the light, which is a physical object. Gradually, it learns about different objects in the room. It comes to recognize its mother, but initially, its mother is just a physical object, a body. Only much later does its mother become, for the child, a mind or a soul. Generally, all our earliest experiences are with the material world. We learn about the mental world only through introspection, and the habit of introspection typically develops in youth or adulthood, and for many people, it may never happen. In those early impressionable years, when our most lasting ideas of the universe are formed, we are focused almost entirely on the material world. The mental world, which we are much less familiar with, tends to seem to all of us somewhat unreal, like a world of shadows. As a result, our thinking becomes materialistic.

What I have said of the individual is equally true of the race. Primitive man does not brood over the facts of his own mind. Necessity compels him to devote most of his life to the acquisition of food, and to warding off the dangers which continually threaten him from other physical objects. And even among ourselves, the majority of men have to spend most of their time upon considering various aspects of things external to them. By the individual training of each man, and by long hereditary habit, then, it comes about that men tend to regard the physical world as more real than the mental.

What I’ve said about individuals also applies to humanity as a whole. Primitive humans don’t spend a lot of time reflecting on their own thoughts. They are forced by necessity to focus most of their lives on gathering food and avoiding dangers from their environment. Even today, most people tend to spend the majority of their time thinking about things outside of themselves. Through individual training and long-standing habits, men generally end up seeing the physical world as more real than the mental one.

Abundant evidences of this are to be found in the structure of human language. We seek to explain what is strange by means of what is well-known. We try to express the unfamiliar in terms of the familiar. We shall find that language always seeks to express the mental by the analogy of the physical. We speak of a man as a "clear" thinker. "Clear" is an attribute of physical objects. Water is clear if it has no extraneous matter in it. We say that a man's ideas are "luminous," thus taking a metaphor from physical light. We talk of having an idea "at the back of the mind." "At the back of"? Has the mind got a front and a back? We are thinking of it as if it were a physical thing in space. We speak of mental habits of "attention." "Attention" means stretching or turning the mind in a special direction. We "reflect." "Reflection" means bending our thoughts back upon themselves. But, literally speaking, only physical objects can be stretched, turned, and bent. Whenever we wish to express something mental we do it by a physical analogy. We talk of it in terms of physical things. This shows how deep-rooted our materialism is. If the mental world were more familiar and real to us than the material, language would have been constructed on the opposite principle. The earliest words of language would have expressed mental facts, and we should afterwards have tried to express physical things by means of mental analogies.

Abundant evidence of this can be found in the structure of human language. We try to explain what’s unfamiliar by using what we already know. We aim to express the unknown in terms of the known. We’ll see that language consistently seeks to convey mental concepts through physical analogies. We refer to someone as a "clear" thinker. "Clear" is something we usually associate with physical objects. Water is considered clear when it’s free of impurities. We say a person’s ideas are "luminous," borrowing a metaphor from physical light. We talk about having an idea "at the back of the mind." "At the back of"? Does the mind even have a front and back? We visualize it as if it’s a physical object in space. We mention mental habits of "attention." "Attention" refers to directing our minds in a specific way. We "reflect." "Reflection" implies turning our thoughts back on themselves. Yet, strictly speaking, only physical objects can be stretched, turned, and bent. Whenever we want to express something mental, we do it with a physical analogy. We describe it in terms of physical things. This shows how deeply rooted our material perspective is. If the mental realm were more familiar and real to us than the material, language would have been formed on the opposite principle. The earliest words in language would have expressed mental realities, and we would have later tried to describe physical things using mental analogies.

In the East one commonly hears Oriental idealism contrasted with Western materialism. Such phrases may possess a certain relative truth. But if they mean that there is in the East, or anywhere else in the world, {11} a race of men who are naturally idealists, they are nonsense. Materialism is ingrained in all men. We, Easterns or Westerns, are born materialists. Hence when we try to think of objects which are commonly regarded as non-material, such as God or the soul, it requires continual effort, a tremendous struggle, to avoid picturing them as material things. It goes utterly against the grain. Perhaps hundreds of thousands of years of hereditary materialism are against us. The popular idea of ghosts will illustrate this. Those who believe in ghosts, I suppose, regard them as some sort of disembodied souls. The pictures of ghosts in magazines show them as if composed of matter, but matter of some thin kind, such as vapour. Certain Indian systems of thought, which are by way of regarding themselves as idealistic, nevertheless teach that thought or mind is an extremely subtle kind of matter, far subtler than any ever dealt with by the physicist and chemist. This is very interesting, because it shows that the authors of such ideas feel vaguely that it is wrong to think of thought as if it were matter, but being unable to think of it in any other way, owing to man's ingrained materialism, they seek to palliate their sin by making it thin matter. Of course this is just as absurd as the excuse made by the mother of an illegitimate child, that it was a very small one. This thin matter is just as material as lead or brass. And such systems are purely materialistic. But they illustrate the extraordinary difficulty that the ordinary mind experiences in attempting to rise from sensuous to non-sensuous thinking. They illustrate the ingrained materialism of man.

In the East, people often hear about Oriental idealism being contrasted with Western materialism. These terms might hold some truth, but if they imply that there’s a group of people in the East, or anywhere else, who are naturally idealists, that’s nonsense. Materialism is built into all of us. We, whether from the East or the West, are born materialists. Therefore, when we try to consider things that are usually seen as non-material, like God or the soul, it takes constant effort and a huge struggle to avoid imagining them as material objects. It goes completely against the grain. Perhaps it’s due to hundreds of thousands of years of inherited materialism working against us. The common notion of ghosts illustrates this well. Those who believe in ghosts probably think of them as some sort of disembodied souls. The images of ghosts in magazines depict them as if they’re made of a material substance, but a very thin type, like vapor. Certain Indian philosophies, which consider themselves idealistic, still claim that thought or mind is a highly subtle form of matter, much subtler than what physicists and chemists usually deal with. This is quite interesting because it shows that these thinkers sense that it’s incorrect to think of thought as if it were matter, but since they can’t conceive it any other way due to humanity’s deep-rooted materialism, they try to soften the blow by calling it thin matter. Of course, this is as ridiculous as a mother of an illegitimate child saying it was a very small one. This thin matter is just as material as lead or brass. And these systems are purely materialistic. Yet they highlight the immense difficulty that the average person faces when trying to shift from physical to non-physical thinking. They demonstrate the inherent materialism of humanity.

This natural human materialism is also the cause {12} of mysticism and symbolism. A symbolic thought necessarily contains two terms, the symbol and the reality which it symbolizes. The symbol is always a sensuous or material object, or the mental image of such an object, and the reality is always something non-sensuous. Because the human mind finds it such an incredible struggle to think non-sensuously, it seeks to help itself by symbols. It takes a material thing and makes it stand for the non-material thing which it is too weak to grasp. Thus we talk of God as the "light of lights." No doubt this is a very natural expression of the religious consciousness, and it has its meaning. But it is not the naked truth. Light is a physical existence, and God is no more light than he is heat or electricity. People talk of symbolism as if it were a very high and exalted thing. They say, "What a wonderful piece of symbolism!" But, in truth symbolism is the mark of an infirm mind. It is the measure of our weakness and not of our strength. Its root is in materialism, and it is produced and propagated by those who are unable to rise above a materialistic level.

This natural human materialism is also the cause {12} of mysticism and symbolism. Symbolic thought always involves two elements: the symbol and the reality it represents. The symbol is typically a physical object or a mental image of that object, while the reality is something non-physical. Since the human mind struggles so much to think in non-physical terms, it uses symbols for help. It takes a tangible thing and makes it represent the intangible thing that it finds too difficult to understand. For example, we refer to God as the "light of lights." This is a very natural expression of religious feeling, and it has meaning. But it’s not the whole truth. Light is a physical entity, and God is no more light than He is heat or electricity. People often talk about symbolism as if it were something lofty and noble. They say, "What a wonderful piece of symbolism!" But, in reality, symbolism reflects a weak mind. It shows our limitations, not our strengths. Its foundation is in materialism, and it’s created and spread by those who can't rise above a materialistic viewpoint.

Now philosophy is essentially the attempt to get beyond this sort of symbolic and mystical thinking, to get at the naked truth, to grasp what lies behind the symbol as it is in itself. These inferior modes of thought are a help to those who are themselves below their level, but are a hindrance to those who seek to reach the highest level of truth.

Now, philosophy is basically trying to move past this kind of symbolic and mystical thinking, to get to the raw truth, to understand what lies behind the symbol as it is on its own. These lesser ways of thinking help those who are not quite at their best, but they can be a barrier for those who aim to reach the highest level of truth.

It is often said that philosophy is a very difficult and abstruse subject. Its difficulty lies almost wholly in the struggle to think non-sensuously. Whenever we {13} come to anything in philosophy that seems beyond us, we shall generally find that the root of the trouble is that we are trying to think non-sensuous objects in a sensuous way, that is, we are trying to form mental pictures and images of them, for all mental pictures are composed of sensuous materials, and hence no such picture is adequate for a pure thought. It is impossible to exaggerate this difficulty. Even the greatest philosophers have succumbed to it. We shall constantly have to point out that when a great thinker, such as Parmenides or Plato, fails, and begins to flounder in difficulties, the reason usually is that, though for a time he has attained to pure thought, he has sunk back exhausted into sensuous thinking, and has attempted to form mental pictures of what is beyond the power of any such picture to represent, and so has fallen into contradictions. We must keep this constantly in mind in the study of philosophy.

It’s often said that philosophy is a really challenging and complex subject. Its difficulty mostly comes from the struggle to think in non-sensory ways. Whenever we {13} encounter something in philosophy that feels beyond our grasp, we usually find that the root of the issue is that we’re trying to think about non-sensory objects in a sensory way; in other words, we’re trying to create mental images of them. However, all mental images are made up of sensory material, so no such image can adequately represent pure thought. This difficulty can't be overstated. Even the greatest philosophers have fallen victim to it. We will often have to point out that when a great thinker like Parmenides or Plato struggles and starts to get lost, the reason is usually that, even though they may have briefly achieved pure thought, they’ve become exhausted and slipped back into sensory thinking, attempting to visualize what no image can truly capture, leading them into contradictions. We need to keep this in mind constantly as we study philosophy.

In modern times philosophy is variously divided, as into metaphysics, which is the theory of reality, ethics, the theory of the good, and aesthetics, the theory of the beautiful. Modern divisions do not, however, altogether fit in with Greek philosophy, and it is better to let the natural divisions develop themselves as we go on, than to attempt to force our material into these moulds.

In today’s world, philosophy is categorized in different ways, such as metaphysics, which deals with the nature of reality; ethics, which focuses on what is good; and aesthetics, which concerns beauty. However, these modern categories don’t completely align with ancient Greek philosophy, and it's preferable to allow natural divisions to emerge as we progress, rather than trying to fit our material into these predefined categories.

If, now, we look round the world and ask; in what countries and what ages the kind of thought we have described has attained a high degree of development, we shall find such a development only in ancient Greece and in modern Europe. There were great civilizations in Egypt, China, Assyria, and so on. They produced art and religion, but no philosophy to speak of. Even {14} ancient Rome added nothing to the world's philosophical knowledge. Its so-called philosophers, Marcus Aurelius, Seneca, Epictetus, Lucretius, produced no essentially new principle. They were merely disciples of Greek Schools, whose writings may be full of interest and of noble feeling, but whose essential thoughts contained nothing not already developed by the Greeks.

If we look around the world today and ask which countries and time periods have developed the kind of thought we've described, we'll find that it has only really flourished in ancient Greece and modern Europe. There were powerful civilizations in Egypt, China, Assyria, and others. They created art and religion, but not much in the way of philosophy. Even ancient Rome didn’t contribute anything new to the world’s philosophical knowledge. Its so-called philosophers—Marcus Aurelius, Seneca, Epictetus, Lucretius—didn't introduce any fundamentally new ideas. They were simply followers of Greek schools, and while their writings may be filled with interesting concepts and noble sentiments, their core ideas were nothing that hadn't already been explored by the Greeks.

The case of India is more doubtful. Opinions may differ as to whether India ever had any philosophy. The Upanishads contain religio-philosophical thinking of a kind. And later we have the six so-called schools of philosophy. The reasons why this Indian thought is not usually included in histories of philosophy are as follows. Firstly, philosophy in India has never separated itself from religious and practical needs. The ideal of knowledge for its own sake is rarely to be found. Knowledge is desired merely as a means towards salvation. Philosophy and science, said Aristotle, have their roots in wonder,--the desire to know and understand for the sole sake of knowing and understanding. But the roots of Indian thought lie in the anxiety of the individual to escape from the ills and calamities of existence. This is not the scientific, but the practical spirit. It gives birth to religions, but not to philosophies. Of course it is a mistake to imagine that philosophy and religion are totally separate and have no community. They are in fact fundamentally akin. But they are also distinct. Perhaps the truest view is that they are identical in substance, but different in form. The substance of both is the absolute reality and the relation of all things, including men, to that reality. But whereas philosophy presents this subject-matter scientifically, in {15} the form of pure thought, religion gives it in the form of sensuous pictures, myths, images, and symbols.

The situation in India is less clear. People may disagree about whether India ever developed a true philosophy. The Upanishads reflect a type of religious and philosophical thinking. Later, we have the six so-called schools of philosophy. The reasons why Indian thought is typically excluded from histories of philosophy are as follows. First, philosophy in India has never really separated from religious and practical needs. The pursuit of knowledge for its own sake is uncommon. Knowledge is usually sought as a means to achieve salvation. Aristotle said that philosophy and science stem from wonder—the desire to know and understand just for the sake of knowing and understanding. However, the roots of Indian thought are in the individual's anxiety to escape the suffering and challenges of existence. This reflects a practical spirit rather than a scientific one. It leads to the creation of religions, but not philosophies. It's certainly a misconception to think that philosophy and religion are entirely separate and have no connection. They are, in fact, fundamentally related. Yet they are also distinct. The most accurate perspective might be that they are identical in substance but different in form. The essence of both lies in the absolute reality and how all things, including humans, relate to that reality. But while philosophy addresses this subject matter in {15} a scientific manner through pure thought, religion presents it through sensory images, myths, symbols, and representations.

And this gives us the second reason why Indian thought is more properly classed as religious than philosophical. It seldom or never rises from sensuous to pure thought. It is poetical rather than scientific. It is content with symbols and metaphors in place of rational explanations, and all this is a mark of the religious, rather than the philosophical, presentation of the truth. For example, the main thought of the Upanishads is that the entire universe is derived from a single, changeless, eternal, infinite, being, called Brahman or Paramatman. When we come to the crucial question how the universe arises out of this being, we find such passages as this:--"As the colours in the flame or the red-hot iron proceed therefrom a thousand-fold, so do all beings proceed from the Unchangeable, and return again to it." Or again, "As the web issues from the spider, as little sparks proceed from fire, so from the one soul proceed all living animals, all worlds, all the gods and all beings." There are thousands of such passages in the Upanishads. But obviously these neither explain nor attempt to explain anything. They are nothing but hollow metaphors. They are poetic rather than scientific. They may satisfy the imagination and the religious feelings, but not the rational understanding. Or when again Krishna, in the Bhagavat-Gita, describes himself as the moon among the lunar mansions, the sun among the stars, Meru among the high-peaked mountains, it is clear that we are merely piling sensuous image upon sensuous image without any further understanding of what the nature of the absolute being in its own self is. {16} The moon, the sun, Meru, are physical sense-objects. And this is totally sensuous thinking, whereas the aim of philosophy is to rise to pure thought. In such passages we are still on the level of symbolism, and philosophy only begins when symbolism has been surpassed. No doubt it is possible to take the line that man's thought is not capable of grasping the infinite as it is in itself, and can only fall back upon symbols. But that is another question, and at any rate, whether it is or is not possible to rise from sensuous to pure thought, philosophy is essentially the attempt to do so.

And this gives us the second reason why Indian thought is more accurately classified as religious rather than philosophical. It rarely, if ever, moves from the sensory to abstract thought. It's more poetic than scientific. It relies on symbols and metaphors instead of logical explanations, which indicates a religious rather than a philosophical approach to truth. For example, the main idea of the Upanishads is that the entire universe comes from a single, unchanging, eternal, infinite being known as Brahman or Paramatman. When we face the critical question of how the universe comes from this being, we encounter passages like this: "Just as colors in the flame or red-hot iron arise in countless forms, so do all beings arise from the Unchangeable and return to it." Or again, "Like the web spun by a spider, or sparks that come from fire, all living beings, all worlds, all gods, all creatures emerge from the one soul." There are thousands of such passages in the Upanishads. But clearly, these do not explain or attempt to explain anything. They are merely empty metaphors. They are poetic, not scientific. They might appeal to the imagination and religious sentiments, but not to rational understanding. When Krishna, in the Bhagavad-Gita, describes himself as the moon among the lunar mansions, the sun among the stars, and Meru among high mountains, it’s evident that we are just stacking sensory images without gaining any deeper understanding of what the absolute being is in itself. The moon, the sun, Meru—these are all physical objects. This is purely sensory thinking, while the goal of philosophy is to elevate to pure thought. In these passages, we remain on the level of symbolism, and philosophy only begins when symbolism is transcended. Of course, one could argue that human thought is incapable of grasping the infinite as it truly is and can only rely on symbols. But that is a separate issue. Regardless of whether it is possible to move from sensory to pure thought, philosophy is essentially the effort to achieve that.

Lastly, Indian thought is usually excluded from the history of philosophy because, whatever its character, it lies outside the main stream of human development. It has been cut off by geographical and other barriers. Consequently, whatever its value in itself, it has exerted little influence upon philosophy in general.

Lastly, Indian thought is often left out of the history of philosophy because, regardless of its significance, it exists outside the mainstream of human development. Geographical and other barriers have isolated it. As a result, despite its intrinsic value, it has had minimal impact on philosophy as a whole.

The claim is sometimes put forward by Orientals themselves that Greek philosophy came from India, and if this were true, it would greatly affect the statement made in the last paragraph. But it is not true. It used to be believed that Greek philosophy came from "the East," but this meant Egypt. And even this theory is now abandoned. Greek culture, especially mathematics and astronomy, owed much to Egypt. But Greece did not owe its philosophy to that source. The view that it did was propagated by Alexandrian priests and others, whose sole motive was, that to represent the triumphs of Greek philosophy as borrowed from Egypt, flattered their national vanity. It was a great thing, wherever they found anything good, to say, "this must have come from us." A precisely similar motive lies behind the {17} Oriental claim that Greek philosophy came from India. There is not a scrap of evidence for it, and it rests entirely upon the supposed resemblance between the two. But this resemblance is in fact mythical. The whole character of Greek philosophy is European and unoriental to the back-bone. The doctrine of re-incarnation is usually appealed to. This characteristically Indian doctrine was held by the Pythagoreans, from whom it passed to Empedocles and Plato. The Pythagoreans got it from the Orphic sect, to whom quite possibly it came indirectly from India, although even this is by no means certain, and is in fact highly doubtful. But even if this be true, it proves nothing. Re-incarnation is of little importance in Greek philosophy. Even in Plato, who makes much of it, it is quite unessential to the fundamental ideas of his philosophy, and is only artificially connected with them. And the influence of this doctrine upon Plato's philosophy was thoroughly bad. It was largely responsible for leading him into the main error of his philosophy, which it required an Aristotle to correct. All this will be evident when we come to consider the systems of Plato and Aristotle.

The claim is sometimes made by people from the East themselves that Greek philosophy came from India, and if that were true, it would significantly change the point made in the last paragraph. But it isn’t true. It was once believed that Greek philosophy had origins in "the East," but that referred to Egypt. This theory has since been discarded. Greek culture, especially in areas like mathematics and astronomy, gained a lot from Egypt. However, Greece did not derive its philosophy from that source. This belief was promoted by priests in Alexandria and others, who were motivated by a desire to claim that the achievements of Greek philosophy were borrowed from Egypt, thus boosting their national pride. It was a big deal, wherever they found something good, to say, "this must have come from us." A similar motive lies behind the {17} claim from the East that Greek philosophy originated in India. There isn’t any evidence to support this, and it only relies on the supposed similarities between the two. But these similarities are actually mythical. The overall nature of Greek philosophy is fundamentally European and not at all Eastern. The idea of reincarnation is often brought up. This distinctly Indian concept was embraced by the Pythagoreans, then passed to Empedocles and Plato. The Pythagoreans likely got it from the Orphic sect, which might have received it indirectly from India, although even that is uncertain and highly questionable. But even if this were the case, it doesn’t prove anything. Reincarnation holds little significance in Greek philosophy. Even in Plato, who emphasizes it, it isn’t essential to the core ideas of his philosophy and is only connected to them in a forced way. Moreover, the influence of this doctrine on Plato’s philosophy was largely negative. It significantly contributed to leading him into the primary mistake of his philosophy, which required correction by Aristotle. All this will be clear when we examine the systems of Plato and Aristotle.

The origin of Greek philosophy is not to be found in India, or Egypt, or in any country outside Greece. The Greeks themselves were solely responsible for it. It is not as if history traces back their thought only to a point at which it was already highly developed, and cannot explain its beginnings. We know its history from the time, so to speak, when it was in the cradle. In the next two chapters we shall see that the first Greek attempts at philosophising were so much the beginnings of a beginner, were so very crude and unformed, that it is {18} mere perversity to suppose that they could not make these simple efforts for themselves. From those crude beginnings we can trace the whole development in detail up to its culmination in Aristotle, and beyond. So there is no need to assume foreign influence at any point.

The origin of Greek philosophy isn't found in India, Egypt, or any other country outside Greece. The Greeks themselves were entirely responsible for it. It's not like history only tracks their thought from a point where it was already advanced, without explaining where it started. We have a clear history from the time, so to speak, when it was just beginning. In the next two chapters, we'll see that the first Greek attempts at philosophy were very much the starts of beginners, so crude and unformed that it's just silly to think they couldn't make these simple efforts on their own. From those rough beginnings, we can trace the whole development in detail up to its peak in Aristotle, and beyond. So, there's no need to assume any outside influence at any point.

Greek philosophy begins in the sixth century before Christ. It begins when men for the first time attempted to give a scientific reply to the question, "what is the explanation of the world?" Before this era we have, of course, the mythologies, cosmogonies, and theologies of the poets. But they contain no attempt at a naturalistic explanation of things. They belong to the spheres of poetry and religion, not to philosophy.

Greek philosophy starts in the sixth century BC. It begins when people first tried to provide a scientific answer to the question, "What explains the world?" Before this time, we had, of course, the mythologies, cosmogonies, and theologies created by poets. However, these works do not make any attempt at a naturalistic explanation of things. They belong to poetry and religion, not to philosophy.

It must not be supposed, when we speak of the philosophy of Greece, that we refer only to the mainland of what is now called Greece. Very early in history, Greeks of the mainland migrated to the islands of the Aegean, to Sicily, to the South of Italy, to the coast of Asia Minor, and elsewhere, and founded flourishing colonies. The Greece of philosophy includes all these places. It is to be thought of rather racially than territorially. It is the philosophy of the men of Greek race, wherever they happened to be situated. And in fact the first period of Greek philosophy deals exclusively with the thoughts of these colonial Greeks. It was not till just before the time of Socrates that philosophy was transplanted to the mainland.

When we talk about the philosophy of Greece, we shouldn't assume that we're only referring to the mainland of what we now call Greece. Early on in history, Greeks from the mainland migrated to the Aegean islands, Sicily, southern Italy, the coast of Asia Minor, and other locations, founding thriving colonies. The philosophy of Greece encompasses all these areas. It's better understood in terms of ethnicity rather than geography. It represents the philosophy of people of Greek descent, no matter where they were located. In fact, the first period of Greek philosophy focuses exclusively on the thoughts of these colonial Greeks. It wasn't until just before Socrates' time that philosophy was brought to the mainland.

Greek philosophy falls naturally into three periods. The first may be roughly described as pre-Socratic philosophy, though it does not include the Sophists who were both the contemporaries and the predecessors of Socrates. This period is the rise of Greek philosophy. {19} Secondly, the period from the Sophists to Aristotle, which includes Socrates and Plato, is the maturity of Greek philosophy, the actual zenith and culmination of which is undoubtedly the system of Aristotle. Lastly, the period of post-Aristotelian philosophy constitutes the decline and fall of the national thought. These are not merely arbitrary divisions. Each period has its own special characters, which will be described in the sequel.

Greek philosophy naturally divides into three periods. The first can be roughly termed pre-Socratic philosophy, though it doesn't include the Sophists, who were both contemporaries and predecessors of Socrates. This period marks the emergence of Greek philosophy. {19} Secondly, the time from the Sophists to Aristotle, which includes Socrates and Plato, represents the peak of Greek philosophy, with Aristotle’s system being the clear high point. Finally, the era of post-Aristotelian philosophy signifies the decline and fall of national thought. These divisions are not just arbitrary. Each period has its own unique characteristics, which will be explained later.

A few words must be said of the sources of our knowledge of pre-Socratic philosophy. If we want to know what Plato and Aristotle thought about any matter, we have only to consult their works. But the works of the earlier philosophers have not come down to us, except in fragments, and several of them never committed their opinions to writing. Our knowledge of their doctrines is the result of the laborious sifting by scholars of such materials as are available. Luckily the material has been plentiful. It may be divided into three classes. First come the fragments of the original writings of the philosophers themselves. These are in many cases long and important, in other cases scanty. Secondly, there are the references in Plato and Aristotle. Of these by far the most important are to be found in the first book of Aristotle's "Metaphysics," which is a history of philosophy up to his own time, and is the first attempt on record to write a history of philosophy. Thirdly, there is an enormous mass of references, some valuable, some worthless, contained in the works of later, but still ancient, writers.

A few words must be said about the sources of our knowledge of pre-Socratic philosophy. If we want to know what Plato and Aristotle thought about any issue, we can simply look at their works. However, the writings of the earlier philosophers have only survived in fragments, and many of them never wrote down their ideas. Our understanding of their teachings comes from the careful work of scholars who sift through the available materials. Fortunately, there is a significant amount of material. This can be divided into three categories. First are the fragments of the original writings of the philosophers themselves, which can be extensive and significant in some cases, while in others they are minimal. Second, there are references in the works of Plato and Aristotle. Among these, the most important can be found in the first book of Aristotle's "Metaphysics," which offers a history of philosophy up to his own time and is the earliest known attempt to write a history of philosophy. Third, there is a vast amount of references—some useful and some not—found in the writings of later, yet still ancient, authors.

THE IONICS.

THE IONICS.

The earliest Greek philosophers belong to what in after times came to be called the Ionic school. The name was derived from the fact that the three chief representatives of this school, Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, were all men of Ionia, that is to say, the coast of Asia Minor.

The earliest Greek philosophers are part of what later became known as the Ionic school. The name comes from the fact that the three main figures of this school, Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, were all from Ionia, which refers to the coast of Asia Minor.



Thales

Thales

As the founder of the earliest school in history, Thales of Miletus is generally accounted the founder and father of all philosophy. He was born about 624 B.C. and died about 550 B.C. These dates are approximate, and it should be understood that the same thing is true of nearly all the dates of the early philosophers. Different scholars vary, sometimes as much as ten years, in the dates they give. We shall not enter into these questions at all, because they are of no importance. And throughout these lectures it should be understood that the dates given are approximate.

As the founder of the first school in history, Thales of Miletus is usually considered the founder and father of all philosophy. He was born around 624 B.C. and died around 550 B.C. These dates are estimates, and it's important to note that the same goes for almost all the dates of the early philosophers. Different scholars can vary by as much as ten years in the dates they provide. We won’t be discussing these issues because they don't really matter. And throughout these lectures, it should be understood that the dates given are approximate.

Thales, at any rate, was a contemporary of Solon and Croesus. He was famous in antiquity for his mathematical and astronomical learning, and also for his practical sagacity and wisdom. He is included in {21} all the accounts of the Seven Sages. The story of the Seven Sages is unhistorical, but the fact that the lists of their names differ considerably as given by different writers, whereas the name of Thales appears in all, shows with what veneration he was anciently regarded. An eclipse of the sun occurred in 585 B.C., and Thales is alleged to have predicted it, which was a feat for the astronomy of those times. And he must have been a great engineer, for he caused a diversion of the river Halys, when Croesus and his army were unable to cross it. Nothing else is known of his life, though there were many apocryphal stories.

Thales, in any case, was a contemporary of Solon and Croesus. He was well-known in ancient times for his knowledge of mathematics and astronomy, as well as for his practical wisdom and insight. He is included in {21} all the accounts of the Seven Sages. The tale of the Seven Sages isn’t historically accurate, but the fact that different writers provide varying lists of their names—while Thales appears in all of them—demonstrates the high regard in which he was held in ancient times. A solar eclipse happened in 585 B.C., and Thales is said to have predicted it, which was quite an achievement for the astronomy of that era. He must have also been a remarkable engineer, as he diverted the river Halys when Croesus and his army couldn't cross it. Not much else is known about his life, though many apocryphal stories exist.

No writings by Thales were extant even in the time of Aristotle, and it is believed that he wrote nothing. His philosophy, if we can call it by that name, consisted, so far as we know, of two propositions. Firstly, that the principle of all things is water, that all comes from water, and to water all returns. And secondly, that the earth is a flat disc which floats upon water. The first, which is the chief proposition, means that water is the one primal kind of existence and that everything else in the universe is merely a modification of water. Two questions will naturally occur to us. Why did Thales choose water as the first principle? And by what process does water, in his opinion, come to be changed into other things; how was the universe formed out of water? We cannot answer either of these questions with certainty. Aristotle says that Thales "probably derived his opinion from observing that the nutriment of all things is moist, and that even actual heat is generated therefrom, and that animal life is sustained by water, ... and from the fact that the seeds of all things possess {22} a moist nature, and that water is a first principle of all things that are humid." This is very likely the true explanation. But it will be noted that even Aristotle uses the word "probably," and so gives his statement merely as a conjecture. How, in the opinion of Thales, the universe arose out of water, is even more uncertain. Most likely he never asked himself the question, and gave no explanation. At any rate nothing is known on the point.

No writings by Thales existed even during Aristotle's time, and it's believed that he didn't write anything. His philosophy, if we can call it that, consisted, as far as we know, of two main ideas. First, that the essence of everything is water, that everything comes from water, and to water, everything returns. Second, that the earth is a flat disc floating on water. The first idea, which is the primary one, means that water is the fundamental kind of existence and that everything else in the universe is just a variation of water. Two questions naturally arise. Why did Thales choose water as the first principle? And how does water change into other things in his view; how was the universe formed from water? We can't answer either of these questions for sure. Aristotle suggests that Thales "probably derived his opinion from observing that the nourishment of all things is moist, that actual heat is generated from it, and that animal life is sustained by water, ... and from the fact that the seeds of all things have a moist nature, and that water is a first principle of all things that are wet." This is likely the real explanation. However, it's worth noting that even Aristotle uses the word "probably," making his statement just a guess. How Thales believed the universe came from water is even more unclear. He probably never questioned it or provided an explanation. At any rate, nothing is known on the matter.

This being the sum and substance of the teaching of Thales, we may naturally ask why, on account of such a crude and undeveloped idea, he should be given the title of the father of philosophy. Why should philosophy be said to begin here in particular? Now, the significance of Thales is not that his water-philosophy has any value in itself, but that this was the first recorded attempt to explain the universe on naturalistic and scientific principles, without the aid of myths and anthropomorphic gods. Moreover, Thales propounded the problem, and determined the direction and character, of all pre-Socratic philosophy. The fundamental thought of that period was, that under the multiplicity of the world there must be a single ultimate principle. The problem of all philosophers from Thales to Anaxagoras was, what is the nature of that first principle from which all things have issued? Their systems are all attempts to answer this question, and may be classified according to their different replies. Thus Thales asserted that the ultimate reality is water, Anaximander indefinite matter, Anaximenes air, the Pythagoreans number, the Eleatics Being, Heracleitus fire, Empedocles the four elements, Democritus atoms, and so on. The first period is thus {23} essentially cosmological in character, and it was Thales who determined the character. His importance is that he was the first to propound the question, not that he gave any rational reply to it.

This summarizes Thales's teaching, and we can naturally wonder why he is called the father of philosophy, given such a basic and undeveloped idea. Why is philosophy said to begin particularly with him? Thales's significance isn't that his idea of water has inherent value, but that it was the first documented attempt to explain the universe based on natural and scientific principles, without relying on myths and human-like gods. Additionally, Thales raised the problem and set the course and nature of all pre-Socratic philosophy. The core idea of that time was that beneath the diversity of the world, there must be a single ultimate principle. The question for all philosophers from Thales to Anaxagoras was, what is the nature of that first principle from which everything arises? Their systems are attempts to answer this question and can be categorized by their different responses. Thales argued that the ultimate reality is water; Anaximander proposed indefinite matter; Anaximenes suggested air; the Pythagoreans focused on numbers; the Eleatics claimed Being; Heraclitus identified fire; Empedocles spoke of the four elements; Democritus introduced atoms, and so on. The initial period is thus {23} essentially cosmological in nature, and Thales defined that nature. His importance lies in being the first to raise the question, not in providing a rational answer to it.

We saw in the first chapter, that man is naturally a materialist, and that philosophy is the movement from sensuous to non-sensuous thought. As we should expect, then, philosophy begins in materialism. The first answer to the question, what the ultimate reality is, places the nature of that reality in a sensuous object, water. The other members of the Ionic school, Anaximander, and Anaximenes, are also materialists. And from their time onwards we can trace the gradual rise of thought, with occasional breaks and relapses, from this sensualism of the Ionics, through the semi-sensuous idealism of the Eleatics, to the highest point of pure non-sensuous thought, the idealism of Plato and Aristotle. It is important to keep in mind, then, that the history of philosophy is not a mere chaotic hotch-potch of opinions and theories, succeeding each other without connection or order. It is a logical and historical evolution, each step in which is determined by the last, and advances beyond the last towards a definite goal. The goal, of course, is visible to us, but was not visible to the early thinkers themselves.

We saw in the first chapter that humans are naturally materialistic and that philosophy is the shift from tangible to abstract thought. So, it makes sense that philosophy starts with materialism. The initial answer to what ultimate reality is centers on a physical object: water. Other thinkers from the Ionic school, like Anaximander and Anaximenes, are also materialists. From their time onward, we can see the gradual development of thought, with some setbacks, from the sensualism of the Ionics, through the semi-sensuous idealism of the Eleatics, to the highest level of pure non-sensuous thought, as seen in the idealism of Plato and Aristotle. It’s important to remember that the history of philosophy isn’t just a random jumble of opinions and theories that come one after the other without any connection or order. It’s a logical and historical evolution, where each step is influenced by the previous one and progresses toward a specific goal. This goal is clear to us now, but it wasn’t apparent to the early thinkers themselves.

Since man begins by looking outwards upon the external world and not inwards upon his own self, this fact too determines the character of the first period of Greek philosophy. It concerns itself solely with nature, with the external world, and only with man as a part of nature. It demands an explanation of nature. And this is the same as saying that it is cosmological. The {24} problems of man, of life, of human destiny, of ethics, are treated by it scantily, or not at all. It is not till the time of the Sophists that the Greek spirit turns inwards upon itself and begins to consider these problems, and with the emergence of that point of view we have passed from the first to the second period of Greek philosophy.

Since humans start by looking outward at the external world instead of inward at themselves, this fact shapes the character of the initial stage of Greek philosophy. It focuses entirely on nature, on the external world, and only on humans as a part of nature. It seeks to explain nature, which is the same as saying it is cosmological. The {24} issues of humanity, life, human destiny, and ethics are hardly addressed, if at all. It isn't until the time of the Sophists that the Greek spirit looks inward and begins to explore these issues, marking the transition from the first to the second phase of Greek philosophy.

Because the Ionic philosophers were all materialists they are also sometimes called Hylicists, from the Greek hulé which means matter.

Because the Ionic philosophers were all materialists, they're sometimes referred to as Hylicists, derived from the Greek hulé, which means matter.



Anaximander

Anaximander

The next philosopher of the Ionic school is Anaximander. He was an exceedingly original and audacious thinker. He was probably born about 611 B.C. and died about 547. He was an inhabitant of Miletus, and is said to have been a disciple of Thales. It will be seen, thus, that he was a younger contemporary of Thales. He was born at the time that Thales was flourishing, and was about a generation younger. He was the first Greek to write a philosophic treatise, which however has been unfortunately lost. He was eminent for his astronomical and geographical knowledge, and in this connection was the first to construct a map. Details of his life are not known.

The next philosopher from the Ionic school is Anaximander. He was a highly original and bold thinker. He was probably born around 611 B.C. and died around 547. He lived in Miletus and is said to have been a student of Thales. This means he was a younger contemporary of Thales. He was born while Thales was thriving and was about a generation younger. He was the first Greek to write a philosophical treatise, although it has unfortunately been lost. He was well-known for his knowledge of astronomy and geography, and in this context, he was the first to create a map. Details about his life are not well-documented.

Now Thales had made the ultimate principle of the universe, water. Anaximander agrees with Thales that the ultimate principle of things is material, but he does not name it water, does not in fact believe that it is any particular kind of matter. It is rather a formless, indefinite, and absolutely featureless matter in general. {25} Matter, as we know it, is always some particular kind of matter. It must be iron, brass, water, air, or other such. The difference between the different kinds of matter is qualitative, that is to say, we know that air is air because it has the qualities of air and differs from iron because iron has the qualities of iron, and so on. The primeval matter of Anaximander is just matter not yet sundered into the different kinds of matter. It is therefore formless and characterless. And as it is thus indeterminate in quality, so it is illimitable in quantity. Anaximander believed that this matter stretches out to infinity through space. The reason he gave for this opinion was, that if there were a limited amount of matter it would long ago have been used up in the creation and destruction of the "innumerable worlds." Hence he called it "the boundless." In regard to these "innumerable worlds," the traditional opinion about Anaximander was that he believed these worlds to succeed each other in time, and that first a world was created, developed, and was destroyed, then another world arose, was developed and destroyed, and that this periodic revolution of worlds went on for ever. Professor Burnet, however, is of opinion that the "innumerable worlds" of Anaximander were not necessarily successive but rather simultaneously existing worlds. According to this view there may be any number of worlds existing at the same time. But, even so, it is still true that these worlds were not everlasting, but began, developed and decayed, giving place in due time to other worlds.

Now Thales claimed that the fundamental principle of the universe is water. Anaximander agrees with Thales that the fundamental principle of things is material, but he doesn’t specify it as water; he actually believes it isn’t any specific type of matter. Instead, it is a formless, indefinite, and completely featureless type of matter in general. {25} Matter, as we understand it, is always some specific type of matter. It has to be iron, brass, water, air, or something similar. The differences between various kinds of matter are qualitative; we recognize air as air because it has the qualities of air, distinguishing it from iron, which has the qualities of iron, and so on. The primeval matter of Anaximander is simply matter that hasn’t yet been divided into different types. Therefore, it is formless and has no defining characteristics. As it’s indeterminate in quality, it is also limitless in quantity. Anaximander believed that this matter extends infinitely through space. He argued that if there were a limited amount of matter, it would have been used up long ago in the creation and destruction of the "countless worlds." Therefore, he referred to it as "the boundless." Regarding these "countless worlds," the traditional view of Anaximander held that he believed these worlds succeed each other over time: first, one world was created, developed, and then destroyed, followed by another world that arose, developed, and was destroyed, and this cycle of worlds continued indefinitely. However, Professor Burnet believes that Anaximander's "countless worlds" were not necessarily sequential, but rather existed simultaneously. From this perspective, there could be any number of worlds coexisting at the same time. Nevertheless, it remains true that these worlds were not eternal; they began, evolved, and decayed, making way for other worlds in due time.

How, now, have these various worlds been formed out of the formless, indefinite, indeterminate matter of {26} Anaximander? On this question Anaximander is vague and has nothing very definite to put forward. Indeterminate matter by a vaguely conceived process separates itself into "the hot" and "the cold." The cold is moist or damp. This cold and moist matter becomes the earth, in the centre of the universe. The hot matter collects into a sphere of fire surrounding the earth. The earth in the centre was originally fluid. The heat of the surrounding sphere caused the waters of the earth progressively to evaporate giving rise to the envelope of air which surrounds the earth. For the early Greeks regarded the air and vapour as the same thing. As this air or vapour expanded under the action of heat it burst the outside hot sphere of fire into a series of enormous "wheel-shaped husks," resembling cart wheels, which encircle the earth. You may naturally ask how it is that if these are composed of fire we do not see them continually glowing. Anaximander's answer was that these wheel-shaped husks are encrusted with thick, opaque vapour, which conceals the inner fire from our view. But there are apertures, or pipe-like holes in the vapour-crust, and through these the fire gleams, causing the appearance of the sun, stars, and moon. You will note that the moon was, on this theory, considered to be fiery, and not, as we now know it to be, a cold surface reflecting the sun's light. There were three of these "cart wheels"; the first was that of the sun, furthest away from the earth, nearer to us was that of the moon, and closest of all was that of the fixed stars. The "wheel-shaped husks" containing the heavenly bodies are revolved round the earth by means of currents of air. The earth in the centre was believed by {27} Anaximander to be not spherical but cylindrical. Men live on the top end of this pillar or cylinder.

How have these different worlds come to be formed from the formless, indefinite matter described by Anaximander? Anaximander is vague on this issue and doesn’t offer anything very concrete. Indeterminate matter separates itself, through a vaguely understood process, into "the hot" and "the cold." The cold is moist or damp. This cold and moist matter becomes the earth, located at the center of the universe. The hot matter shapes itself into a fiery sphere surrounding the earth. The earth at the center was originally fluid. The heat from the surrounding sphere caused the waters of the earth to gradually evaporate, leading to the creation of the envelope of air surrounding the earth. The early Greeks viewed air and vapor as the same thing. As this air or vapor expanded due to heat, it broke the outer hot sphere of fire into a series of huge "wheel-shaped husks," resembling cart wheels, that encircle the earth. You might wonder why we don’t see these glowing if they are made of fire. Anaximander explained that these wheel-shaped husks are covered with thick, opaque vapor, hiding the inner fire from our sight. However, there are openings, or tube-like holes in the vapor layer, through which the fire shines, creating the appearances of the sun, stars, and moon. It’s interesting to note that, according to this theory, the moon was considered fiery, not, as we now understand it, a cold surface reflecting the sun's light. There were three of these "cart wheels": the furthest one was for the sun, the next one closer was for the moon, and the closest was for the fixed stars. The "wheel-shaped husks" containing the heavenly bodies revolve around the earth due to air currents. Anaximander believed that the earth at the center was not spherical but cylindrical. People live on the top end of this pillar or cylinder.

Anaximander also developed a striking theory about the origin and evolution of living beings. In the beginning the earth was fluid and in the gradual drying up by evaporation of this fluid, living beings were produced from the heat and moisture. In the first instance these beings were of a low order. They gradually evolved into successively higher and higher organisms by means of adaptation to their environment. Man was in the first instance a fish living in the water. The gradual drying up left parts of the earth high and dry, and marine animals migrated to the land, and their fins by adaptation became members fitted for movement on land. The resemblance of this primitive theory to modern theories of evolution is remarkable. It is easy to exaggerate its importance, but it is at any rate clear that Anaximander had, by a happy guess, hit upon the central idea of adaptation of species to their environment.

Anaximander also came up with a fascinating theory about the origin and evolution of living things. In the beginning, the earth was liquid, and as this liquid gradually dried up through evaporation, living beings emerged from the heat and moisture. Initially, these beings were basic forms of life. They slowly evolved into increasingly complex organisms by adapting to their surroundings. Humans were originally fish living in the water. As the land dried up, some marine animals moved onto land, and their fins adapted into limbs suitable for walking. The similarity of this early theory to modern evolutionary concepts is striking. While it’s easy to overstate its significance, it's clear that Anaximander, through a fortunate insight, stumbled upon the core idea of species adapting to their environment.

The teaching of Anaximander exhibits a marked advance beyond the position of Thales. Thales had taught that the first principle of things is water. The formless matter of Anaximander is, philosophically, an advance on this, showing the operation of thought and abstraction. Secondly, Anaximander had definitely attempted to apply this idea, and to derive from it the existent world. Thales had left the question how the primal water developed into a world, entirely unanswered.

The teachings of Anaximander show a clear progression from Thales’ views. Thales believed that the basic substance of everything is water. Anaximander's idea of formless matter is, from a philosophical standpoint, a step forward, highlighting the use of thought and abstraction. Moreover, Anaximander actively tried to apply this concept to explain the existence of the world. In contrast, Thales didn’t address how the original water transformed into the world at all.



Anaximenes

Anaximenes

Like the two previous thinkers Anaximenes was an inhabitant of Miletus. He was born about 588 B.C. and {28} died about 524. He wrote a treatise of which a small fragment still remains. He agreed with Thales and Anaximander that the first principle of the universe is material. With Thales too, he looked upon it as a particular kind of matter, not indeterminate matter as taught by Anaximander. Thales had declared it to be water. Anaximenes named air as first principle. This air, like the matter of Anaximander, stretches illimitably through space. Air is constantly in motion and has the power of motion inherent in it and this motion brought about the development of the universe from air. As operating process of this development Anaximenes named the two opposite processes of (1) Rarefaction, (2) Condensation. Rarefaction is the same thing as heat or growing hot, and condensation is identified with growing cold. The air by rarefaction becomes fire, and fire borne aloft upon the air becomes the stars. By the opposite process of condensation, air first becomes clouds and, by further degrees of condensation, becomes successively water, earth, and rocks. The world resolves again in the course of time into the primal air. Anaximenes, like Anaximander, held the theory of "innumerable worlds," and these worlds are, according to the traditional view, successive. But here again Professor Burnet considers that the innumerable worlds may have been co-existent as well as successive. Anaximenes considered the earth to be a flat disc floating upon air.

Like the two thinkers before him, Anaximenes was from Miletus. He was born around 588 B.C. and died around 524 B.C. He wrote a treatise, of which only a small fragment remains. He agreed with Thales and Anaximander that the first principle of the universe is material. Like Thales, he believed it to be a specific type of matter, not the indeterminate matter proposed by Anaximander. Thales identified it as water, while Anaximenes named air as the first principle. This air, similar to Anaximander’s matter, extends infinitely through space. Air is always in motion and has inherent motion, which led to the universe developing from air. Anaximenes described this development process in terms of two opposing processes: (1) Rarefaction and (2) Condensation. Rarefaction corresponds to heat or increasing warmth, while condensation is associated with cooling down. Through rarefaction, air turns into fire, and fire lifted by air becomes the stars. Through condensation, air first becomes clouds, and with further condensation, transforms into water, earth, and rocks. Over time, the world eventually breaks down back into primal air. Like Anaximander, Anaximenes believed in the theory of "innumerable worlds," which, according to traditional views, occur in succession. However, Professor Burnet suggests that these countless worlds might be co-existent as well as successive. Anaximenes thought of the earth as a flat disc floating on air.

The origin of the air theory of Anaximenes seems to have been suggested to him by the fact that air in the form of breath is the principle of life.

The origin of Anaximenes' air theory appears to have been inspired by the idea that air, in the form of breath, is the essence of life.

The teaching of Anaximenes seems at first sight to be {29} a falling off from the position of Anaximander, because he goes back to the position of Thales in favour of a determinate matter as first principle. But in one respect at least there is here an advance upon Anaximander. The latter had been vague as to how formless matter differentiates itself into the world of objects. Anaximenes names the definite processes of rarefaction and condensation. If you believe, as these early physicists did, that every different kind of matter is ultimately one kind of matter, the problem of the differentiation of the qualities of the existent elements arises. For example, if this paper is really composed of air, how do we account for its colour, its hardness, texture, etc. Either these qualities must be originally in the primal air, or not. If the qualities existed in it then it was not really one homogeneous matter like air, but must have been simply a mixture of different kinds of matter. If not, how do these properties arise? How can this air which has not in it the qualities of things we see, develop them? The simplest way of getting out of the difficulty is to found quality upon quantity, and to explain the former by the amount or quantity, more or less, of matter existent in the same volume. This is precisely what is meant by rarefaction and condensation. Condensation would result in compressing more matter into the same volume. Rarefaction would give rise to the opposite process. Great compression of air, a great amount of it in a small space, might account for the qualities, say, of earth and stones, for example, their heaviness, hardness, colour, etc.

The teaching of Anaximenes may initially seem like a step back from Anaximander's ideas because he returns to Thales' view that a specific substance is the first principle. However, in at least one respect, Anaximenes makes progress compared to Anaximander. Anaximander was unclear about how formless matter transforms into the world of objects. Anaximenes identifies the specific processes of rarefaction and condensation. If you agree with these early physicists that all types of matter ultimately come from one source, it raises the question of how the different qualities of the existing elements appear. For instance, if this paper is really made of air, how do we explain its color, hardness, texture, and so on? Either these qualities must have originally existed in the primal air, or they didn't. If the qualities were present, then it wasn’t truly a homogeneous substance like air; it would simply be a mixture of different kinds of matter. If they weren't there, how do these properties emerge? How can this air, which lacks the qualities of visible objects, develop them? The easiest way to resolve this issue is to base quality on quantity, explaining the former by the amount of matter present in the same volume. This is exactly what is meant by rarefaction and condensation. Condensation would mean packing more matter into the same space, while rarefaction would lead to the opposite effect. A significant compression of air, with a lot of it in a small area, might explain the qualities of earth and stones, such as their heaviness, hardness, color, and so on.

Hence Anaximenes was to some extent a more logical and definite thinker than Anaximander, but cannot {30} compare with him in audacity and originality of thought.

Hence Anaximenes was somewhat more logical and clear-headed than Anaximander, but he can't {30} compete with him in boldness and originality of thought.



Other Ionic Thinkers

Other Ionic Theorists

We have now considered the three chief thinkers of the Ionic School. Others there were, but they added nothing new to the teaching of these three. They followed either Thales or Anaximenes in stating the first principle of the world either as water or as air. Hippo, for example, followed Thales, and for him the world is composed of water, Idaeus agreed with Anaximenes that it is derived from air. Diogenes of Apollonia is chiefly remarkable for the fact that he lived at a very much later date. He was a contemporary of Anaxagoras, and opposed to the more developed teachings of that philosopher the crude materialism of the Ionic School. Air was by him considered to be the ground of all things.

We have now looked at the three main thinkers of the Ionic School. There were others, but they didn’t bring anything new to the ideas of these three. They either followed Thales or Anaximenes in identifying the first principle of the world as either water or air. For example, Hippo followed Thales and believed the world is made up of water, while Idaeus agreed with Anaximenes that it comes from air. Diogenes of Apollonia is notable mainly because he lived much later. He was a contemporary of Anaxagoras and contrasted the more advanced ideas of that philosopher with the basic materialism of the Ionic School. He considered air to be the basis of everything.

THE PYTHAGOREANS

THE PYTHAGOREANS

Not much is known of the life of Pythagoras. Three so-called biographies have come down to us from antiquity, but they were written hundreds of years after the event, and are filled with a tissue of extravagant fancies, and with stories of miracles and wonders worked by Pythagoras. All sorts of fantastic legends seem to have gathered very early around his life, obscuring from us the actual historical details. A few definite facts, however, are known. He was born somewhere between 580 and 570 B.C. at Samos, and about middle age he migrated to Crotona in South Italy. According to legend, before he arrived in South Italy he had travelled extensively in Egypt and other countries of the East. There is, however, no historical evidence of this. There is nothing in itself improbable in the belief that Pythagoras made these travels, but it cannot be accepted as proved for lack of evidence. The legend is really founded simply upon the oriental flavour of his doctrines. In middle age he arrived in South Italy and settled at Crotona. There he founded the Pythagorean Society and lived for many years at the head of it. His later life, the date and manner of his death, are not certainly known.

Not much is known about Pythagoras's life. Three so-called biographies have survived from ancient times, but they were written hundreds of years later and are full of extravagant tales and miraculous stories about him. Various fantastic legends appear to have formed around his life very early on, obscuring the actual historical details. However, a few definite facts are known. He was born between 580 and 570 B.C. on Samos, and in middle age, he moved to Crotona in Southern Italy. According to legend, before arriving in Southern Italy, he traveled extensively in Egypt and other Eastern countries. However, there’s no historical evidence to support this. While it isn’t inherently unlikely that Pythagoras made these journeys, we can't accept it as proven due to a lack of evidence. The legend likely comes from the Eastern influences in his teachings. In middle age, he settled in Crotona, where he founded the Pythagorean Society and led it for many years. The details of his later life, along with the date and circumstances of his death, are not definitively known.

Now it is important to note that the Pythagorean {32} Society was not primarily a school of philosophy at all. It was really a religious and moral Order, a Society of religious reformers. The Pythagoreans were closely associated with the Orphic Sect, and took from it the belief in the transmigration of souls, including transmigration of human souls into animals. They also taught the doctrine of the "wheel of things," and the necessity of obtaining "release" from it, by which one could escape from the weary round of reincarnate lives. Thus they shared with the Orphic religious Sect the principle of reincarnation. The Orphic Sect believed that "release" from the wheel of life was to be obtained by religious ceremonial and ritual. The Pythagoreans had a similar ritual, but they added to this the belief that intellectual pursuits, the cultivation of science and philosophy, and, in general, the intellectual contemplation of the ultimate things of the universe would be of great help towards the "release" of the soul. From this arose the tendency to develop science and philosophy. Gradually their philosophy attained a semi-independence from their religious rites which justifies us in regarding it definitely as philosophy.

Now, it's important to highlight that the Pythagorean {32} Society wasn't primarily a school of philosophy. It was actually a religious and moral Order, a group of religious reformers. The Pythagoreans were closely linked to the Orphic Sect and adopted the belief in the transmigration of souls, including the idea that human souls could be reborn into animals. They also taught the concept of the "wheel of things" and the need to achieve "release" from it, allowing one to escape the exhausting cycle of reincarnated lives. Thus, they shared the principle of reincarnation with the Orphic religious Sect. The Orphic Sect believed that "release" from the wheel of life could be obtained through religious ceremonies and rituals. The Pythagoreans had a similar practice but added the belief that intellectual pursuits, the study of science and philosophy, and the overall intellectual contemplation of the universe's ultimate truths would greatly aid in the "release" of the soul. This belief led to the development of science and philosophy. Over time, their philosophy gained some independence from their religious rites, which allows us to view it distinctly as philosophy.

The Pythagorean ethical views were rigorous and ascetic in character. They insisted upon the utmost purity of life in the members of the Order. Abstinence from flesh was insisted upon, although this was apparently a late development. We know that Pythagoras himself was not a total abstainer from flesh. They forbade the eating of beans. They wore a garb peculiar to themselves. The body, they taught, is the prison or tomb of the soul. They thought that one must not attempt to obtain "release" by suicide, because "man is the {33} property of God," the chattel of God. They were not politicians in the modern sense, but their procedure in practice amounted to the greatest possible interference in politics. It appears that the Pythagoreans attempted to impose their ordinances upon the ordinary citizens of Crotona. They aimed at the supersession of the State by their own Order and they did actually capture the government of Crotona for a short period. This led to attacks on the Order, and the persecution of its members. When the plain citizen of Crotona was told not to eat beans, and that under no circumstances could he eat his own dog, this was too much. A general persecution occurred. The meeting place of the Pythagoreans was burnt to the ground, the Society was scattered, and its members killed or driven away. This occurred between the years 440 and 430 B.C. Some years later the Society revived and continued its activities, but we do not hear much of it after the fourth century B.C.

The Pythagorean ethical views were strict and ascetic in nature. They demanded the highest purity of life from the members of the Order. Abstaining from meat was enforced, although this seemed to develop later on. We know that Pythagoras himself didn’t completely avoid eating meat. They prohibited the consumption of beans and wore specific clothing unique to their group. They taught that the body is the prison or tomb of the soul. They believed one should not seek "release" through suicide because "man is the {33} property of God," the property of God. They weren’t politicians in the modern sense, but their actions effectively interfered greatly in politics. It seems that the Pythagoreans tried to impose their rules on the ordinary citizens of Crotona. They aimed to replace the State with their own Order and even took control of the government of Crotona for a brief time. This led to attacks on the Order and the persecution of its members. When the average citizen of Crotona was told not to eat beans and that under no circumstances could he eat his own dog, this was too much to handle. A widespread persecution occurred. The Pythagorean meeting place was burned to the ground, the Society was dismantled, and its members were killed or forced to flee. This happened between 440 and 430 B.C. Some years later, the Society revived and continued its work, but we don’t hear much about it after the fourth century B.C.

It was largely a mystical society. The Pythagoreans developed their own ritual, ceremonial and mysteries. This love of mystery, and their general character as miracle-mongers, largely account for the legends which grew up around the life of Pythagoras himself. Their scientific activities were also considerable. They enforced moral self-control. They cultivated the arts and crafts, gymnastics, music, medicine, and mathematics. The development of mathematics in early Greece was largely the work of the Pythagoreans. Pythagoras is said to have discovered the 47th Proposition of Euclid, and to have sacrificed an ox in honour thereof. And there is good reason to believe that practically the whole of the substance of the First Book of Euclid is the work of Pythagoras.

It was mainly a mystical society. The Pythagoreans created their own rituals, ceremonies, and mysteries. Their fascination with mystery and their tendency towards the miraculous largely explain the legends that formed around the life of Pythagoras himself. They also engaged significantly in scientific activities. They promoted moral self-discipline. They practiced various arts and crafts, gymnastics, music, medicine, and mathematics. The advancement of mathematics in early Greece was mostly attributed to the Pythagoreans. It is said that Pythagoras discovered the 47th Proposition of Euclid and even sacrificed an ox in its honor. There’s good reason to believe that nearly all of the content in the First Book of Euclid is the work of Pythagoras.

Turning now to their philosophical teaching, the first thing that we have to understand is that we cannot speak of the philosophy of Pythagoras, but only of the philosophy of the Pythagoreans. For it is not known what share Pythagoras had in this philosophy or what share was contributed by his successors. Now we recognize objects in the universe by means of their qualities. But the majority of these qualities are not universal in their scope; some things possess some qualities; others possess others. A leaf, for example, is green, but not all things are green. Some things have no colour at all. The same is true of tastes and smells. Some things are sweet; some bitter. But there is one quality in things which is absolutely universal in its scope, which applies to everything in the universe--corporeal or incorporeal. All things are numerable, and can be counted. Moreover, it is impossible to conceive a universe in which number is not to be found. You could easily imagine a universe in which there is no colour, or no sweet taste, or a universe in which nothing possesses weight. But you cannot imagine a universe in which there is no number. This is an inconceivable thought. Upon these grounds we should be justified in concluding that number is an extremely important aspect of things, and forms a fundamental pad of the framework of the world. And it is upon this aspect of things that the Pythagoreans laid emphasis.

Turning now to their philosophical teaching, the first thing we need to understand is that we can’t talk about the philosophy of Pythagoras, but only about the philosophy of the Pythagoreans. It’s unclear how much Pythagoras contributed to this philosophy or what input came from his followers. We recognize objects in the universe by their qualities. However, most of these qualities are not universal; some things have certain qualities while others have different ones. A leaf, for instance, is green, but not everything is green. Some things have no color at all. The same goes for tastes and smells. Some things are sweet; some are bitter. But there is one quality that is absolutely universal, applying to everything in the universe—whether physical or not. All things are numerable and can be counted. Furthermore, it's impossible to imagine a universe without numbers. You could easily visualize a universe without color, or without sweet taste, or one where nothing has weight. But you can’t conceive of a universe where there is no number. That idea is beyond imagination. For these reasons, we could conclude that number is an extremely important aspect of things and forms a fundamental part of the world's framework. And it is this aspect that the Pythagoreans emphasized.

They drew attention to proportion, order, and harmony as the dominant notes of the universe. Now when we examine the ideas of proportion, order, and harmony, we shall see that they are closely connected with number. Proportion, for example, must necessarily {35} be expressible by the relation of one number to another. Similarly order is measurable by numbers. When we say that the ranks of a regiment exhibit order, we mean that they are arranged in such a way that the soldiers stand at certain regular distances from each other, and these distances are measurable by numbers of feet or inches. Lastly, consider the idea of harmony. If, in modern times, we were to say that the universe is a harmonious whole, we should understand that we are merely using a metaphor from music. But the Pythagoreans lived in an age when men were not practised in thought, and they confused cosmical harmony with musical harmony. They thought that the two things were the same. Now musical harmony is founded upon numbers, and the Pythagoreans were the first to discover this. The difference of notes is due to the different numbers of vibrations of the sounding instrument. The musical intervals are likewise based upon numerical proportions. So that since, for the Pythagoreans, the universe is a musical harmony, it follows that the essential character of the universe is number. The study of mathematics confirmed the Pythagoreans in this idea. Arithmetic is the science of numbers, and all other mathematical sciences are ultimately reducible to numbers. For instance, in geometry, angles are measured by the number of degrees.

They highlighted proportion, order, and harmony as the key elements of the universe. When we look at the concepts of proportion, order, and harmony, we see they are closely related to numbers. Proportion, for instance, must be expressible in terms of the relationship between one number and another. Similarly, order can be measured by numbers. When we say that the ranks of a regiment show order, we mean they are arranged so that the soldiers stand at specific regular distances from each other, and these distances can be measured in feet or inches. Finally, think about the idea of harmony. If we were to say today that the universe is a harmonious whole, we would understand it as a metaphor from music. However, the Pythagoreans lived in a time when people were not practiced in abstract thinking, and they confused cosmic harmony with musical harmony, believing they were the same. Musical harmony is based on numbers, and the Pythagoreans were the first to recognize this. The difference in notes comes from the different numbers of vibrations of the sound-producing instrument. Musical intervals are also based on numerical proportions. Therefore, for the Pythagoreans, since the universe is like a musical harmony, it follows that numbers are essential to its character. The study of mathematics reinforced this idea for the Pythagoreans. Arithmetic is the study of numbers, and all other branches of mathematics ultimately relate back to numbers. For example, in geometry, angles are measured in degrees.

Now, as already pointed out, considering all these facts, we might well be justified in concluding that number is a very important aspect of the universe, and is fundamental in it. But the Pythagoreans went much further than this. They drew what seems to us the extraordinary conclusion that the world is made of {36} numbers. At this point, then, we reach the heart of the Pythagorean philosophy. Just as Thales had said that the ultimate reality, the first principle of which things are composed, is water, so now the Pythagoreans teach that the first principle of things is number. Number is the world-ground, the stuff out of which the universe is made.

Now, as already mentioned, considering all these facts, we might reasonably conclude that numbers are a very important aspect of the universe and fundamental to it. But the Pythagoreans took it even further. They came to what seems like an extraordinary conclusion that the world is made of {36} numbers. At this point, we reach the core of Pythagorean philosophy. Just as Thales claimed that the ultimate reality, the first principle of which everything is made, is water, the Pythagoreans assert that the first principle of things is number. Number is the foundation of the world, the substance from which the universe is created.

In the detailed application of this principle to the world of things we have a conglomeration of extraordinary fancies and extravagances. In the first place, all numbers arise out of the unit. This is the prime number, every other number being simply so many units. The unit then is the first in the order of things in the universe. Again, numbers are divided into odd and even. The universe, said the Pythagoreans, is composed of pairs of opposites and contradictories, and the fundamental character of these opposites is that they are composed of the odd and even. The odd and even, moreover, they identified with the limited and the unlimited respectively. How this identification was made seems somewhat doubtful. But it is clearly connected with the theory of bipartition. An even number can be divided by two and therefore it does not set a limit to bipartition. Hence it is unlimited. An odd number cannot be divided by two, and therefore it sets a limit to bipartition. The limited and the unlimited become therefore the ultimate principles of the universe. The Limit is identified with the unit, and this again with the central fire of the universe. The Limit is first formed and proceeds to draw more and more of the unlimited towards itself, and to limit it. Becoming limited, it becomes a definite "something," a thing. So the formation of the {37} world of things proceeds. The Pythagoreans drew up a list of ten opposites of which the universe is composed. They are (1) Limited and unlimited, (2) odd and even, (3) one and many, (4) right and left, (5) masculine and feminine, (6) rest and motion, (7) straight and crooked, (8) light and darkness, (9) good and evil, (10) square and oblong.

In applying this principle to the world around us, we encounter a mix of incredible ideas and excesses. First of all, every number comes from the unit. The unit is the foundation, with every other number just a collection of units. The unit is, therefore, the first in the hierarchy of things in the universe. Additionally, numbers are categorized as odd and even. The Pythagoreans believed the universe is made up of pairs of opposites and contradictions, with the essential nature of these opposites consisting of the odd and even. Moreover, they associated the odd with the limited and the even with the unlimited. However, how they made this connection is a bit unclear. It's evident that it relates to the idea of bipartition. An even number can be divided by two, so it doesn’t impose a limit on bipartition, making it unlimited. In contrast, an odd number can’t be divided by two, which means it places a limit on bipartition. Therefore, the concepts of limited and unlimited become the foundational principles of the universe. The Limit is linked to the unit, which is also connected to the central fire of the universe. The Limit initially forms and then attracts more and more of the unlimited towards itself, imposing limits on it. As it becomes limited, it transforms into a specific "something," an object. Thus, the formation of the {37} world of things unfolds. The Pythagoreans created a list of ten opposites that make up the universe: (1) Limited and unlimited, (2) odd and even, (3) one and many, (4) right and left, (5) masculine and feminine, (6) rest and motion, (7) straight and crooked, (8) light and darkness, (9) good and evil, (10) square and oblong.

With the further development of the number-theory Pythagoreanism becomes entirely arbitrary and without principle. We hear, for example, that 1 is the point, 2 is the line, 3 is the plane, 4 is the solid, 5 physical qualities, 6 animation, 7 intelligence, health, love, wisdom. There is no principle in all this. Identification of the different numbers with different things can only be left to the whim and fancy of the individual. The Pythagoreans disagreed among themselves as to what number is to be assigned to what thing. For example, justice, they said, is that which returns equal for equal. If I do a man an injury, justice ordains that injury should be done to me, thus giving equal for equal. Justice must, therefore, be a number which returns equal for equal. Now the only numbers which do this are square numbers. Four equals two into two, and so returns equal for equal. Four, then, must be justice. But nine is equally the square of three. Hence other Pythagoreans identified justice with nine.

As number theory developed further, Pythagoreanism became completely arbitrary and lacking in principle. For example, they said that 1 represents a point, 2 represents a line, 3 represents a plane, 4 represents a solid, 5 represents physical qualities, 6 represents animation, 7 represents intelligence, health, love, and wisdom. There's no principle behind any of this. The assignment of different numbers to various concepts is entirely up to individual interpretation. The Pythagoreans even disagreed among themselves about what number should correspond to what concept. They argued that justice is something that repays equal for equal. If I harm someone, justice dictates that I should receive equal harm in return, thus balancing the scale. Therefore, justice must be represented by a number that balances equal for equal. The only numbers that do this are square numbers. Four is the product of two times two, so it returns equal for equal. Hence, four must represent justice. However, nine is also a square, being the product of three times three. So, other Pythagoreans identified justice with nine instead.

According to Philolaus, one of the most prominent Pythagoreans, the quality of matter depends upon the number of sides of its smallest particles. Of the five regular solids, three were known to the Pythagoreans. That matter whose smallest particles are regular tetrahedra, said Philolaus, is fire. Similarly earth is composed {38} of cubes, and the universe is identified with the dodecahedron. This idea was developed further by Plato in the "Timaeus," where we find all the five regular solids brought into the theory.

According to Philolaus, a leading figure among the Pythagoreans, the characteristics of matter are determined by the number of sides on its smallest particles. The Pythagoreans were familiar with three of the five regular solids. Philolaus claimed that matter made up of regular tetrahedra is fire. In the same way, earth consists of cubes, and the universe is represented by the dodecahedron. Plato expanded on this concept in the "Timaeus," where he included all five regular solids in his theory.

The central fire, already mentioned as identified with the unit, is a characteristic doctrine of the Pythagoreans. Up to this time it had been believed that the earth is the centre of the universe, and that everything revolves round it. But with the Pythagoreans the earth revolves round the central fire. One feels inclined at once to identify this with the sun. But this is not correct. The sun, like the earth, revolves round the central fire. We do not see the central fire because that side of the earth on which we live is perpetually turned away from it. This involves the theory that the earth revolves round the central fire in the same period that it takes to rotate upon its axis. The Pythagoreans were the first to see that the earth is itself one of the planets, and to shake themselves free from the geocentric hypothesis. Round the central fire, sometimes mystically called "the Hearth of the Universe," revolve ten bodies. First is the "counter-earth," a non-existent body invented by the Pythagoreans, next comes the earth, then the sun, the moon, the five planets, and lastly the heaven of the fixed stars. This curious system might have borne fruit in astronomy. That it did not do so was largely due to the influence of Aristotle, who discountenanced the theory, and insisted that the earth is the centre of the universe. But in the end the Pythagorean view won the day. We know that Copernicus derived the suggestion of his heliocentric hypothesis from the Pythagoreans.

The central fire, previously mentioned as linked to the unit, is a key concept of the Pythagoreans. Until now, people believed that the earth was the center of the universe and that everything revolved around it. However, the Pythagoreans proposed that the earth orbits around the central fire. One might immediately think this refers to the sun, but that's not accurate. The sun, like the earth, also revolves around the central fire. We can’t see the central fire because the side of the earth where we live is always facing away from it. This suggests that the earth orbits the central fire in the same amount of time it takes to spin on its axis. The Pythagoreans were the first to recognize that the earth is one of the planets and to break free from the geocentric model. Around the central fire, sometimes mystically referred to as "the Hearth of the Universe," there are ten bodies that revolve. First is the "counter-earth," a fictional body created by the Pythagoreans, followed by the earth, then the sun, the moon, the five planets, and finally the realm of the fixed stars. This intriguing system could have advanced astronomy. Its failure to do so was largely because of Aristotle's influence, who rejected the theory and maintained that the earth is the center of the universe. Ultimately, however, the Pythagorean perspective prevailed. We know that Copernicus took inspiration for his heliocentric theory from the Pythagoreans.

The Pythagoreans also taught "The Great Year," probably a period of 10,000 years, in which the world comes into being and passes away, going in each such period through the same evolution down to the smallest details.

The Pythagoreans also taught about "The Great Year," which was likely a span of 10,000 years, during which the world is created and eventually disappears, going through the same evolution each time, down to the smallest details.

There is little to be said by way of criticism of the Pythagorean system. It is entirely crude philosophy. The application of the number theory issues in a barren and futile arithmetical mysticism. Hegel's words in this connection are instructive:--

There isn't much to criticize about the Pythagorean system. It's a very basic form of philosophy. The use of number theory leads to an empty and pointless mathematical mysticism. Hegel's comments on this are helpful:--

"We may certainly," he says, "feel ourselves prompted to associate the most general characteristics of thought with the first numbers: saying one is the simple and immediate, two is difference and mediation, and three the unity of both these. Such associations however are purely external; there is nothing in the mere numbers to make them express these definite thoughts. With every step in this method, the more arbitrary grows the association of definite numbers with definite thoughts ... To attach, as do some secret societies of modern times, importance to all sorts of numbers and figures is, to some extent an innocent amusement, but it is also a sign of deficiency of intellectual resource. These numbers, it is said, conceal a profound meaning, and suggest a deal to think about. But the point in philosophy is not what you may think but what you do think; and the genuine air of thought is to be sought in thought itself and not in arbitrarily selected symbols." [Footnote 3]

"We can definitely," he says, "feel inclined to connect the most basic traits of thought with the first numbers: saying one represents simplicity and immediacy, two symbolizes difference and mediation, and three embodies the unity of both. However, these associations are purely external; the numbers themselves don’t inherently convey these specific ideas. With each step in this approach, the connection between specific numbers and specific thoughts becomes more arbitrary... Assigning significance to various numbers and figures, as some modern secret societies do, can be somewhat of an innocent pastime, but it also reflects a lack of intellectual depth. It’s said that these numbers hide profound meanings and offer a lot to ponder. But the key point in philosophy is not about what you think might be true, but rather what you actually do think; the true essence of thought should be found in the thought itself, not in randomly chosen symbols." [Footnote 3]

[Footnote 3: Hegel's Smaller Logic, translated
by Wallace, second edition, page 198.]

[Footnote 3: Hegel's Smaller Logic, translated
by Wallace, second edition, page 198.]

THE ELEATICS

The Eleatics

The Eleatics are so called because the seat of their school was at Elea, a town in South Italy, and Parmenides and Zeno, the two chief representatives of the school, were both citizens of Elea. So far we have been dealing with crude systems of thought in which only the germs of philosophic thinking can be dimly discerned. Now, however, with the Eleatics we step out definitely for the first time upon the platform of philosophy. Eleaticism is the first true philosophy. In it there emerges the first factor of the truth, however poor, meagre, and inadequate. For philosophy is not, as many persons suppose, simply a collection of freak speculations, which we may study in historical order, but at the end of which, God alone knows which we ought to believe. On the contrary, the history of philosophy presents a definite line of evolution. The truth unfolds itself gradually in time.

The Eleatics are named after Elea, a town in southern Italy, where Parmenides and Zeno, the two main figures of the school, were both from. Until now, we've been looking at basic systems of thought that only hint at the beginnings of philosophical thinking. However, with the Eleatics, we clearly step onto the platform of philosophy for the first time. Eleaticism represents the first true philosophy. It introduces the first element of truth, even if it’s limited and insufficient. Philosophy isn’t, as many people think, just a random collection of odd ideas that can be studied in chronological order, leaving us unsure about what to believe. Instead, the history of philosophy shows a clear path of development. The truth gradually unfolds over time.



Xenophanes

Xenophanes

The reputed founder of the Eleatic School was Xenophanes. It is, however, doubtful whether Xenophanes ever went to Elea. Moreover, he belongs more properly {41} to the history of religion than to the history of philosophy. The real creator of the Eleatic School was Parmenides. But Parmenides seized upon certain germs of thought latent in Xenophanes and transmuted them into philosophic principles. We have, therefore, in the first instance, to say something of Xenophanes. He was born about the year 576 B.C., at Colophon in Ionia. His long life was spent in wandering up and down the cities of Hellas, as a poet and minstrel, singing songs at banquets and festivals. Whether, as sometimes stated; he finally settled at Elea is a matter of doubt, but we know definitely that at the advanced age of ninety-two he was still wandering about Greece. His philosophy, such as it is, is expressed in poems. He did not, however, write philosophical poems, but rather elegies and satires upon various subjects, only incidentally expressing his religious views therein. Fragments of these poems have come down to us.

The well-known founder of the Eleatic School was Xenophanes. However, it's uncertain if Xenophanes ever actually went to Elea. Additionally, he is more accurately a figure in the history of religion than in the history of philosophy. The true creator of the Eleatic School was Parmenides. But Parmenides took some of the ideas that were present in Xenophanes’ work and developed them into philosophical principles. Therefore, we first need to say a bit about Xenophanes. He was born around 576 B.C. in Colophon, Ionia. He spent his long life traveling through the cities of Greece as a poet and minstrel, performing songs at banquets and festivals. Whether he eventually settled in Elea, as sometimes stated, is uncertain, but we know for sure that at the age of ninety-two, he was still traveling around Greece. His philosophy, as it is, is conveyed through his poems. However, he didn't write philosophical poems but rather elegies and satires on various topics, only expressing his religious views on the side. Fragments of these poems have survived.

Xenophanes is the originator of the quarrel between philosophy and religion. He attacked the popular religious notions of the Greeks with a view to founding a purer and nobler conception of Deity. Popular Greek religion consisted of a belief in a number of gods who were conceived very much as in the form of human beings. Xenophanes attacks this conception of God as possessing human form. It is absurd, he says, to suppose that the gods wander about from place to place, as represented in the Greek legends. It is absurd to suppose that the gods had a beginning. It is disgraceful to impute to them stories of fraud, adultery, theft and deceit. And Xenophanes inveighs against Homer and Hesiod for disseminating these degrading conceptions {42} of the Deity. He argues, too, against the polytheistic notion of a plurality of gods. That which is divine can only be one. There can only be one best. Therefore, God is to be conceived as one. And this God is comparable to mortals neither in bodily form nor understanding. He is "all eye, all ear, all thought." It is he "who, without trouble, by his thought governs all things." But it would be a mistake to suppose that Xenophanes thought of this God as a being external to the world, governing it from the outside, as a general governs his soldiers. On the contrary, Xenophanes identified God with the world. The world is God, a sentient being, though without organs of sense. Looking out into the wide heavens, he said, "The One is God." [Footnote 4] The thought of Xenophanes is therefore more properly described as pantheism than as monotheism. God is unchangeable, immutable, undivided, unmoved, passionless, undisturbed. Xenophanes appears, thus, rather as a religious reformer than as a philosopher. Nevertheless, inasmuch as he was the first to enunciate the proposition "All is one," he takes his place in philosophy. It was upon this thought that Parmenides built the foundations of the Eleatic philosophy.

Xenophanes is credited with starting the conflict between philosophy and religion. He challenged the common religious beliefs of the Greeks to create a purer and nobler idea of God. The popular Greek religion was centered around multiple gods who were imagined to be very much like humans. Xenophanes criticized this idea of God having a human form. He argued that it's ridiculous to think that the gods wander from place to place, as portrayed in Greek myths. It's absurd to believe that the gods had a beginning. It's shameful to attribute stories of fraud, adultery, theft, and deceit to them. He condemned Homer and Hesiod for spreading these degrading views of the divine. He also opposed the idea of multiple gods, asserting that the divine must be singular. There can only be one best. Therefore, God should be understood as one. This God cannot be compared to humans in either body or intellect. He is "all eye, all ear, all thought." It is he "who, without effort, governs all things by his thought." However, it's a misunderstanding to think that Xenophanes viewed this God as separate from the world, managing it from a distance like a general commands his troops. Instead, Xenophanes equated God with the world. The world itself is God, a sentient being, although without sensory organs. Gazing into the vast heavens, he said, "The One is God." The philosophy of Xenophanes is better described as pantheism than as monotheism. God is unchanging, eternal, indivisible, unmoving, emotionless, and peaceful. Thus, Xenophanes comes across more as a religious reformer than as a philosopher. Nevertheless, since he was the first to express the idea "All is one," he holds a significant place in philosophy. It was on this idea that Parmenides founded Eleatic philosophy.

[Footnote 4: Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book I. chapter v.]

[Footnote 4: Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book I. chapter v.]

Certain other opinions of Xenophanes have been preserved. He observed fossils, and found shells inland, and the forms of fish and sea-weed embedded in the rocks in the quarries of Syracuse and elsewhere. From these he concluded that the earth had risen out of the sea and would again partially sink into it. Then the human race would be destroyed. But the earth would again rise from the sea and the human race would again {43} be renewed. He believed that the sun and stars were burning masses of vapour. The sun, he thought, does not revolve round the earth. It goes on in a straight line, and disappears in the remote distance in the evening. It is not the same sun which rises the next morning. Every day a new sun is formed out of the vapours of the sea. This idea is connected with his general attitude towards the popular religion. His motive was to show that the sun and stars are not divine beings, but like other beings, ephemeral. Xenophanes also ridiculed the Pythagoreans, especially their doctrine of re-incarnation.

Certain other opinions of Xenophanes have been preserved. He observed fossils and found shells inland, along with forms of fish and seaweed embedded in the rocks in the quarries of Syracuse and other places. From these, he concluded that the earth had risen from the sea and would again partially sink into it, leading to the destruction of the human race. However, the earth would rise from the sea again, and humanity would be renewed. He believed that the sun and stars were burning masses of vapor. He thought the sun does not revolve around the earth; it moves in a straight line and disappears in the distance in the evening. It's not the same sun that rises the next morning; every day, a new sun forms from the sea's vapors. This idea is related to his general view on popular religion. His goal was to show that the sun and stars are not divine beings, but rather temporary like everything else. Xenophanes also mocked the Pythagoreans, especially their doctrine of reincarnation.



Parmenides

Parmenides

Parmenides was born about 514 B.C. at Elea. Not much is known of his life. He was in his early youth a Pythagorean, but recanted that philosophy and formulated a philosophy of his own. He was greatly revered in antiquity both for the depth of his intellect, and the sublimity and nobility of his character. Plato refers to him always with reverence. His philosophy is comprised in a philosophic didactic poem which is divided into two parts. The first part expounds his own philosophy and is called "the way of truth." The second part describes the false opinions current in his day and is called "the way of opinion."

Parmenides was born around 514 B.C. in Elea. Not much is known about his life. In his early years, he was a Pythagorean but eventually rejected that philosophy and developed his own. He was highly respected in ancient times for both the depth of his intellect and the greatness and integrity of his character. Plato always speaks of him with respect. His philosophy is expressed in a didactic poem that is divided into two parts. The first part outlines his own philosophy and is called "the way of truth." The second part discusses the false beliefs popular in his time and is called "the way of opinion."

The reflection of Parmenides takes its rise from observation of the transitoriness and changeableness of things. The world, as we know it, is a world of change and mutation. All things arise and pass away. Nothing is permanent, nothing stands. One moment it is, another moment it is not. It is as true to say of {44} anything, that it is not, as that it is. The truth of things cannot lie here, for no knowledge of that which is constantly changing is possible. Hence the thought of Parmenides becomes the effort to find the eternal amid the shifting, the abiding and everlasting amid the change and mutation of things. And there arises in this way the antithesis between Being and not-being. The absolutely real is Being. Not-being is the unreal. Not-being is not at all. And this not-being he identifies with becoming, with the world of shifting and changing things, the world which is known to us by the senses. The world of sense is unreal, illusory, a mere appearance. It is not-being. Only Being truly is. As Thales designated water the one reality, as the Pythagoreans named number, so now for Parmenides the sole reality, the first principle of things, is Being, wholly unmixed with not-being, wholly excludent of all becoming. The character of Being he describes, for the most part, in a series of negatives. There is in it no change, it is absolutely unbecome and imperishable. It has neither beginning nor end, neither arising nor passing away. If Being began, it must have arisen either from Being or from not-being. But for Being to arise out of Being, that is not a beginning, and for Being to arise out of not-being is impossible, since there is then no reason why it should arise later rather than sooner. Being cannot come out of not-being, nor something out of nothing. Ex nihilo nihil fit. This is the fundamental thought of Parmenides. Moreover, we cannot say of Being that it was, that it is, that it will be. There is for it no past, no present, and no future. It is rather eternally and timelessly present. It is undivided and indivisible. For anything to be divided {45} it must be divided by something other than itself. But there is nothing other than Being; there is no not-being. Therefore there is nothing by which Being can be divided. Hence it is indivisible. It is unmoved and undisturbed, for motion and disturbance are forms of becoming, and all becoming is excluded from Being. It is absolutely self-identical. It does not arise from anything other than itself. It does not pass into anything other than itself. It has its whole being in itself. It does not depend upon anything else for its being and reality. It does not pass over into otherness; it remains, steadfast, and abiding in itself. Of positive character Being has nothing. Its sole character is simply its being. It cannot be said that it is this or that; it cannot be said that it has this or that quality, that it is here or there, then or now. It simply is. Its only quality is, so to speak, "isness."

The reflection of Parmenides starts from observing how things are temporary and constantly changing. The world we know is one of change and transformation. Everything comes into existence and fades away. Nothing is permanent, nothing remains. One moment it exists, the next moment it doesn’t. It's equally true to say of {44} anything that it doesn’t exist as it is that it does. The truth of things can’t be found here, because you can’t have knowledge of something that is always changing. Thus, Parmenides' thought aims to find the eternal within the shifting, the unchanging and everlasting within the change and transformation of things. This brings about the contrast between Being and not-being. The absolutely real is Being. Not-being is unreal. Not-being doesn’t exist at all. He equates not-being with becoming and the world of shifting and changing things, the world we know through our senses. The sensory world is unreal, illusory, just an appearance. It is not-being. Only Being truly exists. Just as Thales considered water as the one reality and the Pythagoreans identified number, for Parmenides, the only reality, the fundamental principle of things, is Being, completely free of not-being, entirely excluding all becoming. He mostly describes the nature of Being through negatives. There is no change in it; it is completely uncreated and imperishable. It has no beginning or end, no coming into or going out of existence. If Being began, it must have come from either Being or not-being. But for Being to come from Being, that’s not really a beginning, and for Being to come from not-being is impossible because there would be no reason for it to arise at one time rather than another. Being cannot come from not-being, nor can something come from nothing. Ex nihilo nihil fit. This is Parmenides' central idea. Furthermore, we can’t say of Being that it was, that it is, or that it will be. It has no past, present, or future. Instead, it is eternally and timelessly present. It is whole and indivisible. For anything to be divided {45}, it must be split by something other than itself. But there is nothing besides Being; there is no not-being. Therefore, there is nothing that can divide Being. Hence, it is indivisible. It is unmoved and untroubled because motion and disturbance are forms of becoming, and all becoming is excluded from Being. It is completely self-identical. It doesn’t arise from anything other than itself. It doesn’t transform into anything other than itself. Its entire existence is within itself. It doesn’t rely on anything else for its being and reality. It doesn’t transition into otherness; it remains firm, steady, and consistent in itself. Being has no positive characteristics; its only attribute is simply its existence. It can’t be described as this or that; it can’t be said to have certain qualities, to be here or there, now or then. It simply is. Its only quality is, in a sense, "isness."

But in Parmenides there emerges for the first time a distinction of fundamental importance in philosophy, the distinction between Sense and Reason. The world of falsity and appearance, of becoming, of not-being, this is, says Parmenides, the world which is presented to us by the senses. True and veritable Being is known to us only by reason, by thought. The senses therefore, are, for Parmenides, the sources of all illusion and error. Truth lies only in reason. This is exceedingly important, because this, that truth lies in reason and not in the world of sense, is the fundamental position of idealism.

But in Parmenides, we see for the first time a crucial distinction in philosophy: the difference between Sense and Reason. The world of falsehood and appearances, of change and non-existence, is, according to Parmenides, the world presented to us by our senses. True and genuine Being is known to us only through reason and thought. Therefore, for Parmenides, the senses are the sources of all illusion and error. Truth resides only in reason. This is extremely important because the idea that truth is found in reason and not in the world of sense is the core belief of idealism.

The doctrine of Being, just described, occupies the first part of the poem of Parmenides. The second part is the way of false opinion. But whether Parmenides is here simply giving an account of the false philosophies {46} of his day, (and in doing this there does not seem much point,) or whether he was, with total inconsistency, attempting, in a cosmological theory of his own, to explain the origin of that world of appearance and illusion, whose very being he has, in the first part of the poem, denied--this does not seem to be clear. The theory here propounded, at any rate, is that the sense-world is composed of the two opposites, the hot and the cold, or light and darkness. The more hot there is, the more life, the more reality; the more cold, the more unreality and death.

The doctrine of Being, as described, makes up the first part of Parmenides' poem. The second part discusses the way of false opinion. However, it's unclear whether Parmenides is just outlining the misguided philosophies of his time (which seems somewhat pointless) or if he's inconsistently trying to create his own cosmological theory to explain the origin of that world of appearances and illusions, which he has denied in the first part of the poem. At any rate, the theory he presents is that the sensory world consists of two opposites: hot and cold, or light and darkness. The more heat there is, the more life and reality; the more cold, the more unreality and death.

What position, now, are we to assign to Parmenides in philosophy? How are we to characterize his system? Such writers as Hegel, Erdmann, and Schwegler, have always interpreted his philosophy in an idealistic sense. Professor Burnet, however, takes the opposite view. To quote his own words: "Parmenides is not, as some have said, the father of idealism. On the contrary, all materialism depends upon his view." [Footnote 5] Now if we cannot say whether Parmenides was a materialist or an idealist, we cannot be said to understand much about his philosophy. The question is therefore of cardinal importance. Let us see, in the first place, upon what grounds the materialistic interpretation of Parmenides is based. It is based upon a fact which I have so far not mentioned, leaving it for explanation at this moment. Parmenides said that Being, which is for him the ultimate reality, occupies space, is finite, and is spherical or globe-shaped. Now that which occupies space, and has shape, is matter. The ultimate reality of things, therefore, is conceived by Parmenides as material, and this, of course, is the {47} cardinal thesis of materialism. This interpretation of Parmenides is further emphasized in the disagreement between himself and Melissus, as to whether Being is finite or infinite. Melissus was a younger adherent of the Eleatic School, whose chief interest lies in his views on this question. His philosophical position in general is the same as that of Parmenides. But on this point they differed. Parmenides asserted that Being is globe-shaped, and therefore finite. Now it was an essential part of the doctrine of Parmenides that empty space is non-existent. Empty space is an existent non-existence. This is self-contradictory, and for Parmenides, therefore, empty space is simply not-being. There are, for example, no interstices, or empty spaces between the particles of matter. Being is "the full," that is, full space with no mixture of empty space in it. Now Melissus agreed with Parmenides that there is no such thing as empty space; and he pointed out, that if Being is globe-shaped, it must be bounded on the outside by empty space. And as this is impossible, it cannot be true that Being is globe-shaped, or finite, but must, on the contrary, extend illimitably through space. This makes it quite clear that Parmenides, Melissus, and the Eleatics generally, did regard Being as, in some sense, material.

What position should we assign to Parmenides in philosophy now? How should we describe his system? Thinkers like Hegel, Erdmann, and Schwegler have always interpreted his philosophy in an idealistic way. However, Professor Burnet takes the opposite stance. In his own words: "Parmenides is not, as some have said, the father of idealism. On the contrary, all materialism depends upon his view." [Footnote 5] If we can't determine whether Parmenides was a materialist or an idealist, we can't claim to understand much about his philosophy. This question is therefore crucial. Let's first examine the basis for the materialistic interpretation of Parmenides. It rests on a fact I haven't mentioned yet, which I will explain now. Parmenides stated that Being, which he considers the ultimate reality, occupies space, is finite, and is spherical or globe-shaped. So, that which occupies space and has shape is matter. Thus, Parmenides conceives the ultimate reality of things as material, which is, of course, the {47} central thesis of materialism. This interpretation of Parmenides is further highlighted by the disagreement between him and Melissus about whether Being is finite or infinite. Melissus was a younger follower of the Eleatic School, whose main focus was this question. His philosophical position is generally the same as Parmenides'. However, they disagreed on this issue. Parmenides claimed that Being is globe-shaped, and therefore finite. An essential part of Parmenides' doctrine is that empty space does not exist. Empty space is a contradiction in terms. For Parmenides, empty space is simply not-being. For example, there are no voids or empty spaces between particles of matter. Being is "the full," meaning full space with no mixture of empty space. Melissus agreed with Parmenides that empty space doesn't exist, but he pointed out that if Being is globe-shaped, it must be surrounded by empty space. Since this is impossible, it cannot be true that Being is globe-shaped or finite; instead, it must extend infinitely through space. This clearly shows that Parmenides, Melissus, and the Eleatics in general viewed Being as, in some sense, material.

[Footnote 5: Early Greek Philosophy, chap. iv. § 89.]

[Footnote 5: Early Greek Philosophy, chap. iv. § 89.]

Now, however, let us turn to the other side of the picture. What ground is there for regarding Parmenides as an idealist? In the first place, we may say that his ultimate principle, Being, whatever he may have thought of it, is not in fact material, but is essentially an abstract thought, a concept. Being is not here, it is not there. It is not in any place or time. It is not to be found by the senses. It is to be found only in reason. {48} We form the idea of Being by the process of abstraction. For example, we see this desk. Our entire knowledge of the desk consists in our knowledge of its qualities. It is square, brown, hard, odourless, etc. Now suppose we successively strip off these qualities in thought--its colour, its size, its shape. We shall ultimately be left with nothing at all except its mere being. We can no longer say of it that it is hard, square, etc. We can only say "it is." As Parmenides said, Being is not divisible, movable; it is not here nor there, then nor now. It simply "is." This is the Eleatic notion of Being, and it is a pure concept. It may be compared to such an idea as "whiteness." We cannot see "whiteness." We see white things, but not "whiteness" itself. What, then, is "whiteness"? It is a concept, that is to say, not a particular thing, but a general idea, which we form by abstraction, by considering the quality which all white things have in common, and neglecting the qualities in which they differ. Just so, if we consider the common character of all objects in the universe, and neglect their differences, we shall find that what they all have in common is simply "being." Being then is a general idea, or concept. It is a thought, and not a thing. Parmenides, therefore, actually placed the absolute reality of things in an idea, in a thought, though he may have conceived it in a material and sensuous way. Now the cardinal thesis of idealism is precisely this, that the absolute reality, of which the world is a manifestation, consists in thought, in concepts. Parmenides, on this view, was an idealist.

Now, however, let’s look at the other side of the picture. What basis is there for viewing Parmenides as an idealist? First of all, we can say that his ultimate principle, Being, regardless of how he perceived it, is not material but is essentially an abstract thought or concept. Being isn’t here or there. It’s not located in any place or time. It cannot be found through the senses. It can only be understood through reason. {48} We form the idea of Being through the process of abstraction. For example, we see this desk. Our entire understanding of the desk is based on its qualities. It is square, brown, hard, odorless, etc. Now imagine we progressively remove these qualities in our thoughts—its color, its size, its shape. Eventually, we are left with nothing but its mere existence. We can no longer describe it as hard, square, etc. We can only say, “it is.” As Parmenides pointed out, Being is not divisible or movable; it is not here or there, then or now. It simply “is.” This is the Eleatic concept of Being, and it is a pure concept. It can be compared to an idea like “whiteness.” We cannot see “whiteness.” We see white objects but not “whiteness” itself. So what is “whiteness”? It is a concept, meaning it’s not a specific thing but a general idea formed by recognizing the quality that all white things share, ignoring the unique qualities that differentiate them. Similarly, if we consider the common characteristics of all objects in the universe and overlook their differences, we’ll find that what they all share is simply “being.” Therefore, Being is a general idea or concept. It is a thought, not a tangible thing. Parmenides, thus, actually placed the absolute reality of things in an idea, in a thought, even if he might have conceived it in a material and sensory way. The core thesis of idealism is precisely this: that the absolute reality, of which the world is a manifestation, is composed of thought and concepts. From this perspective, Parmenides was indeed an idealist.

Moreover, Parmenides has clearly made the distinction between sense and reason. True Being is not known to {49} the senses, but only to reason, and this distinction is an essential feature of all idealism. Materialism is precisely the view that reality is to be found in the world of sense. But the proposition of Parmenides is the exact opposite of this, namely, that reality is to be found only in reason. Again, there begins to appear for the first time in Parmenides the distinction between reality and appearance. Parmenides, of course, would not have used these terms, which have been adopted in modern times. But the thought which they express is unmistakably there. This outward world, the world of sense, he proclaims to be illusion and appearance. Reality is something which lies behind, and is invisible to the senses. Now the very essence of materialism is that this material world, this world of sense, is the real world. Idealism is the doctrine that the sense-world is an appearance. How then can Parmenides be called a materialist?

Moreover, Parmenides has clearly distinguished between sense and reason. True Being is not known to {49} the senses, but only to reason, and this distinction is a key aspect of all idealism. Materialism is the belief that reality is found in the world of the senses. But Parmenides' proposition is exactly the opposite: reality is found only in reason. For the first time with Parmenides, a distinction between reality and appearance starts to emerge. He wouldn't have used these terms, which we adopted later, but the idea they express is clearly present. He declares that this outer world, the world of the senses, is an illusion and mere appearance. Reality is something that lies beyond and is invisible to our senses. Yet the core of materialism is that this material world, this world of the senses, is the real world. Idealism maintains that the sensory world is just an appearance. So how can Parmenides be considered a materialist?

How are we to reconcile these two conflicting views of Parmenides? I think the truth is that these two contradictories lie side by side in Parmenides unreconciled, and still mutually contradicting each other. Parmenides himself did not see the contradiction. If we emphasize the one side, then Parmenides was a materialist. If we emphasize the other side, then he is to be interpreted as an idealist. In point of fact, in the history of Greek philosophy, both these sides of Parmenides were successively emphasized. He became the father both of materialism and of idealism. His immediate successors, Empedocles and Democritus, seized upon the materialistic aspect of his thought, and developed it. The essential thought of Parmenides was that Being cannot arise from not-being, and that Being neither {50} arises nor passes away. If we apply this idea to matter we get what in modern times is called the doctrine of the "indestructibility of matter." Matter has no beginning and no end. The apparent arising and passing away of things is simply the aggregation and separation of particles of matter which, in themselves, are indestructible. This is precisely the position of Democritus. And his doctrine, therefore, is a materialistic rendering of the main thought of Parmenides that Being cannot arise from not-being or pass into not-being.

How do we reconcile these two conflicting views of Parmenides? I believe the truth is that these two contradictions exist side by side in Parmenides, unresolved and still contradicting each other. Parmenides himself didn’t recognize the contradiction. If we focus on one side, then Parmenides was a materialist. If we focus on the other side, then he can be seen as an idealist. In the history of Greek philosophy, both aspects of Parmenides were emphasized at different times. He became the father of both materialism and idealism. His immediate successors, Empedocles and Democritus, focused on the materialistic side of his thought and developed it further. The key idea of Parmenides was that Being cannot come from not-being, and that Being neither comes into existence nor disappears. If we apply this idea to matter, we arrive at what is now known as the doctrine of the "indestructibility of matter." Matter has no beginning and no end. The apparent coming into existence and disappearance of things is simply the gathering and separating of particles of matter that are, in themselves, indestructible. This reflects Democritus’s position. Therefore, his doctrine is a materialistic interpretation of Parmenides' main idea that Being cannot arise from not-being or turn into not-being.

It was not till the time of Plato that the idealistic aspect of the Parmenidean doctrine was developed. It was the genius of Plato which seized upon the germs of idealism in Parmenides and developed them. Plato was deeply influenced by Parmenides. His main doctrine was that the reality of the world is to be found in thought, in concepts, in what is called "the Idea." And he identified the Idea with the Being of Parmenides.

It wasn't until the time of Plato that the idealistic side of Parmenides' teachings was fully developed. Plato's genius recognized the seeds of idealism in Parmenides and expanded upon them. Plato was greatly influenced by Parmenides. His main belief was that the true reality of the world is found in thought, in concepts, and in what we call "the Idea." He identified the Idea with the Being of Parmenides.

But still, it may be asked, which is the true view of Parmenides? Which is the historical Parmenides? Was not Plato in interpreting him idealistically reading his own thought into Parmenides? Are not we, if we interpret him as an idealist, reading into him later ideas? In one sense this is perfectly true. It is clear from what Parmenides himself said that he regarded the ultimate reality of things as material. It would be a complete mistake to attribute to him a fully developed and consistent system of idealism. If you had told Parmenides that he was an idealist, he would not have understood you. The distinction between materialism and idealism was not then developed. If you had told him, moreover, that Being is a concept, he would not have understood {51} you, because the theory of concepts was not developed until the time of Socrates and Plato. Now it is the function of historical criticism to insist upon this, to see that later thought is not attributed to Parmenides. But if this is the function of historical scholarship, it is equally the function of philosophic insight to seize upon the germs of a higher thought amid the confused thinking of Parmenides, to see what he was groping for, to see clearly what he saw only vaguely and dimly, to make explicit what in him was merely implicit, to exhibit the true inwardness of his teaching, to separate what is valuable and essential in it from what is worthless and accidental. And I say that in this sense the true and essential meaning of Parmenides is his idealism. I said in the first chapter that philosophy is the movement from sensuous to non-sensuous thought. I said that it is only with the utmost difficulty that this movement occurs. And I said that even the greatest philosophers have sometimes failed herein. In Parmenides we have the first example of this. He began by propounding the truth that Being is the essential reality, and Being, as we saw, is a concept. But Parmenides was a pioneer. He trod upon unbroken ground. He had not behind him, as we have, a long line of idealistic thinkers to guide him. So he could not maintain this first non-sensuous thought. He could not resist the temptation to frame for himself a mental image, a picture, of Being. Now all mental images and pictures are framed out of materials supplied to us by the senses. Hence it comes about that Parmenides pictured Being as a globe-shaped something occupying space. But this is not the truth of Parmenides. This is simply his failure to realise {52} and understand his own principle, and to think his own thought. It is true that his immediate successors, Empedocles and Democritus, seized upon this, and built their philosophies upon it. But in doing so they were building upon the darkness of Parmenides, upon his dimness of vision, upon his inability to grapple with his own idea. It was Plato who built upon the light of Parmenides.

But still, the question remains: what is the true view of Parmenides? What is the historical Parmenides? Was Plato interpreting him idealistically by projecting his own ideas onto Parmenides? Are we, when we interpret him as an idealist, projecting later ideas onto him? In one sense, this is absolutely true. Parmenides made it clear that he saw the ultimate reality of things as material. It would be completely incorrect to claim that he had a fully developed and consistent system of idealism. If you had told Parmenides he was an idealist, he wouldn't have understood you. The distinction between materialism and idealism had not been developed at that time. Furthermore, if you had told him that Being is a concept, he also wouldn’t have grasped the meaning because the theory of concepts didn’t emerge until the era of Socrates and Plato. Now, it's the role of historical criticism to emphasize this, ensuring that later thoughts aren’t mistakenly attributed to Parmenides. However, while historical scholarship has this role, philosophical insight also needs to identify the seeds of higher thought within Parmenides' muddled thinking, to discern what he was reaching for, to clarify what he only saw vaguely, to articulate what was merely implied in his work, and to extract the true essence of his teachings while distinguishing what is valuable and essential from what is insignificant and accidental. In that sense, I argue that the true and essential meaning of Parmenides is his idealism. I mentioned in the first chapter that philosophy involves the transition from sensory to non-sensory thought, noting that this transition happens with great difficulty. Even the greatest philosophers have occasionally struggled with it. Parmenides is our first example of this. He started by stating the truth that Being is the essential reality, and as we noted, Being is a concept. But Parmenides was a pioneer. He walked on untouched ground. Unlike us, he didn’t have a long history of idealistic thinkers to guide him. Therefore, he couldn’t sustain this first non-sensory thought. He couldn’t resist the urge to create a mental image or picture of Being. All mental images and pictures are constructed from materials provided by our senses. This led Parmenides to envision Being as some globe-shaped thing occupying space. But this is not the truth of Parmenides. It's merely his failure to recognize and understand his own principle and to think through his own idea. It's true that his immediate successors, Empedocles and Democritus, picked up on this and built their philosophies around it. However, in doing so, they were constructing their ideas upon the obscurity of Parmenides, relying on his unclear vision and his difficulty in grappling with his own concept. It was Plato who built upon the clarity of Parmenides.


Zeno

Zeno

The third and last important thinker of the Eleatic School is Zeno who, like Parmenides, was a man of Elea. His birth is placed about 489 B.C. He composed a prose treatise in which he developed his philosophy. Zeno's contribution to Eleaticism is, in a sense, entirely negative. He did not add anything positive to the teachings of Parmenides. He supports Parmenides in the doctrine of Being. But it is not the conclusions of Zeno that are novel, it is rather the reasons which he gave for them. In attempting to support the Parmenidean doctrine from a new point of view he developed certain ideas about the ultimate character of space and time which have since been of the utmost importance in philosophy. Parmenides had taught that the world of sense is illusory and false. The essentials of that world are two-- multiplicity and change. True Being is absolutely one; there is in it no plurality or multiplicity. Being, moreover, is absolutely static and unchangeable. There is in it no motion. Multiplicity and motion are the two characteristics of the false world of sense. Against multiplicity and motion, therefore, Zeno directed his {53} arguments, and attempted indirectly to support the conclusions of Parmenides by showing that multiplicity and motion are impossible. He attempted to force multiplicity and motion to refute themselves by showing that, if we assume them as real, contradictory propositions follow from that assumption. Two propositions which contradict each other cannot both be true. Therefore the assumptions from which both follow, namely, multiplicity and motion, cannot be real things.

The third and final key thinker of the Eleatic School is Zeno, who, like Parmenides, came from Elea. He was born around 489 B.C. He wrote a prose work in which he elaborated on his philosophy. Zeno's role in Eleaticism is primarily negative. He didn't add anything new to Parmenides' teachings. Instead, he supported Parmenides’ doctrine of Being. What makes Zeno interesting are not his conclusions, but the reasons he provided for them. By trying to defend the Parmenidean doctrine from a fresh perspective, he developed certain ideas about the true nature of space and time that have become incredibly important in philosophy. Parmenides taught that the sensory world is illusory and false, consisting fundamentally of two elements—multiplicity and change. True Being is completely one; it contains no plurality or multiplicity. Furthermore, Being is entirely static and unchangeable; there is no motion in it. Multiplicity and motion are the two features of the false sensory world. Thus, Zeno directed his {53} arguments against multiplicity and motion, trying to indirectly support Parmenides’ conclusions by demonstrating that these concepts are impossible. He sought to show that if we assume multiplicity and motion are real, they lead to contradictory statements. Two contradictory statements cannot both be true, so the underlying assumptions of multiplicity and motion cannot represent real entities.

Zeno's arguments against multiplicity.

Zeno's arguments against plurality.

(1) If the many is, it must be both infinitely small and infinitely large. The many must be infinitely small. For it is composed of units. This is what we mean by saying that it is many. It is many parts or units. These units must be indivisible. For if they are further divisible, then they are not units. Since they are indivisible they can have no magnitude, for that which has magnitude is divisible. The many, therefore, is composed of units which have no magnitude. But if none of the parts of the many have magnitude, the many as a whole has none. Therefore, the many is infinitely small. But the many must also be infinitely large. For the many has magnitude, and as such, is divisible into parts. These parts still have magnitude, and are therefore further divisible. However far we proceed with the division the parts still have magnitude and are still divisible. Hence the many is divisible ad infinitum. It must therefore be composed of an infinite number of parts, each having magnitude. But the smallest magnitude, multiplied by infinity, becomes an infinite magnitude. Therefore the many is infinitely large. (2) The {54} many must be, in number, both limited and unlimited. It must be limited because it is just as many as it is, no more, no less. It is, therefore, a definite number. But a definite number is a finite or limited number. But the many must be also unlimited in number. For it is infinitely divisible, or composed of an infinite number of parts.

(1) If there are many things, they must be both infinitely small and infinitely large. The many must be infinitely small because it consists of individual units. That's what we mean when we say it is many. It contains many parts or units. These units must be indivisible. If they could be divided further, then they wouldn’t be units. Since they are indivisible, they can't have any size, because anything with size can be divided. Therefore, the many is made up of units that have no size. But if none of the parts of the many have size, then the many as a whole doesn’t either. So, the many is infinitely small. However, the many must also be infinitely large. Since the many has size, it can be divided into parts. These parts still have size, and are therefore further divisible. No matter how far we go with the division, the parts still have size and can still be divided. Thus, the many is divisible ad infinitum. It must be made up of an infinite number of parts, each with size. But the smallest size, multiplied by infinity, results in an infinite size. Therefore, the many is infinitely large. (2) The {54} many must be, in number, both limited and unlimited. It has to be limited because it is exactly as many as it is, no more, no less. Thus, it is a specific number. But a specific number is a finite or limited number. At the same time, the many must also be unlimited in number, as it is infinitely divisible, or made up of an infinite number of parts.

Zeno's arguments against motion.

Zeno's arguments against movement.

(1) In order to travel a distance, a body must first travel half the distance. There remains half left for it still to travel. It must then travel half the remaining distance. There is still a remainder. This progress proceeds infinitely, but there is always a remainder untravelled. Therefore, it is impossible for a body to travel from one point to another. It can never arrive. (2) Achilles and the tortoise run a race. If the tortoise is given a start, Achilles can never catch it up. For, in the first place, he must run to the point from which the tortoise started. When he gets there, the tortoise will have gone to a point further on. Achilles must then run to that point, and finds then that the tortoise has reached a third point. This will go on for ever, the distance between them continually diminishing, but never being wholly wiped out. Achilles will never catch up the tortoise. (3) This is the story of the flying arrow. An object cannot be in two places at the same time. Therefore, at any particular moment in its flight the arrow is in one place and not in two. But to be in one place is to be at rest. Therefore in each and every moment of its flight it is at rest. It is thus at rest throughout. Motion is impossible.

(1) To travel a distance, an object must first cover half that distance. There’s still half left to go. Then it has to travel half of the remaining distance. There’s always some distance left. This process goes on infinitely, but there’s always some left untraveled. So, it’s impossible for an object to move from one point to another. It can never arrive. (2) Achilles and the tortoise are racing. If the tortoise gets a head start, Achilles can never catch up. First, he has to run to the spot where the tortoise began. By the time he gets there, the tortoise will have moved on ahead. Achilles must then run to that new spot and finds that the tortoise has already reached an even further point. This goes on forever, with the gap between them getting smaller but never completely closed. Achilles will never catch the tortoise. (3) This is the tale of the flying arrow. An object can’t occupy two places at once. So, at any specific moment during its flight, the arrow is in one place and not in two. But being in one place means being at rest. Therefore, at every moment of its flight, it is at rest. Thus, it is at rest the whole time. Motion is impossible.

This type of argument is, in modern times, called "antinomy." An antinomy is a proof that, since two contradictory propositions equally follow from a given assumption, that assumption must be false. Zeno is also called by Aristotle the inventor of dialectic. Dialectic originally meant simply discussion, but it has come to be a technical term in philosophy, and is used for that type of reasoning which seeks to develop the truth by making the false refute and contradict itself. The conception of dialectic is especially important in Zeno, Plato, Kant, and Hegel.

This type of argument is, in modern times, called "antinomy." An antinomy is a proof that if two contradictory propositions equally stem from a given assumption, then that assumption must be false. Zeno is also referred to by Aristotle as the inventor of dialectic. Dialectic originally just meant discussion, but it has evolved into a technical term in philosophy, used for the kind of reasoning that seeks to uncover the truth by making the false refute and contradict itself. The concept of dialectic is particularly significant in the works of Zeno, Plato, Kant, and Hegel.

All the arguments which Zeno uses against multiplicity and motion are in reality merely variations of one argument. That argument is as follows. It applies equally to space, to time, or to anything which can be quantitatively measured. For simplicity we will consider it only in its spatial significance. Any quantity of space, say the space enclosed within a circle, must either be composed of ultimate indivisible units, or it must be divisible ad infinitum. If it is composed of indivisible units, these must have magnitude, and we are faced with the contradiction of a magnitude which cannot be divided. If it is divisible ad infinitum, we are faced with the contradiction of supposing that an infinite number of parts can be added up and make a finite sum-total. It is thus a great mistake to suppose that Zeno's stories of Achilles and the tortoise, and of the flying arrow, are merely childish puzzles. On the contrary, Zeno was the first, by means of these stories, to bring to light the essential contradictions which lie in our ideas of space and time, and thus to set an important problem for all subsequent philosophy.

All the arguments Zeno makes against multiplicity and motion are really just variations of one main argument. This argument applies equally to space, time, or anything that can be measured. For simplicity, let’s focus on its spatial meaning. Any amount of space, like the area within a circle, must either be made up of ultimate indivisible units or it must be infinitely divisible. If it’s made of indivisible units, they must have size, leading to the contradiction of having a size that can’t be divided. If it can be divided infinitely, we face the contradiction of claiming that an infinite number of parts can add up to a finite total. Therefore, it’s a big mistake to think that Zeno's tales of Achilles and the tortoise, and the flying arrow, are just silly puzzles. In fact, Zeno was the first to highlight the fundamental contradictions in our understanding of space and time, thereby raising a significant issue for all future philosophy.

All Zeno's arguments are based upon the one argument described above, which may be called the antinomy of infinite divisibility. For example, the story of the flying arrow. At any moment of its flight, says Zeno, it must be in one place, because it cannot be in two places at the same moment. This depends upon the view of time as being infinitely divisible. It is only in an infinitesimal moment, an absolute moment having no duration, that the arrow is at rest. This, however, is not the only antinomy which we find in our conceptions of space and time. Every mathematician is acquainted with the contradictions immanent in our ideas of infinity. For example, the familiar proposition that parallel straight lines meet at infinity, is a contradiction. Again, a decreasing geometrical progression can be added up to infinity, the infinite number of its terms adding up in the sum-total to a finite number. The idea of infinite space itself is a contradiction. You can say of it exactly what Zeno said of the many. There must be in existence as much space as there is, no more. But this means that there must be a definite and limited amount of space. Therefore space is finite. On the other hand, it is impossible to conceive a limit to space. Beyond the limit there must be more space. Therefore space is infinite. Zeno himself gave expression to this antinomy in the form of an argument which I have not so far mentioned. He said that everything which exists is in space. Space itself exists, therefore space must be in space. That space must be in another space and so ad infinitum. This of course is merely a quaint way of saying that to conceive a limit to space is impossible.

All of Zeno's arguments are based on the one argument mentioned earlier, which can be called the contradiction of infinite divisibility. For example, take the story of the flying arrow. Zeno says that at any moment during its flight, it must be in one location, because it can't be in two places at the same time. This relies on the idea of time being infinitely divisible. The arrow is only at rest in an infinitesimal moment, an absolute moment that has no duration. However, this is not the only contradiction we find in our ideas of space and time. Every mathematician is aware of the contradictions inherent in our concepts of infinity. For instance, the well-known claim that parallel straight lines meet at infinity is a contradiction. Additionally, a decreasing geometric series can be summed up to infinity, yet the infinite number of its terms totals a finite number. The idea of infinite space itself is a contradiction. You can say about it exactly what Zeno said about the many. There must exist as much space as there is, no more. But this implies that there has to be a definite and limited amount of space. Therefore, space is finite. On the other hand, it is impossible to imagine a limit to space. Beyond that limit, there must be more space. Therefore, space is infinite. Zeno himself articulated this contradiction with an argument I haven’t mentioned yet. He asserted that everything that exists is in space. Since space itself exists, then space must be in space. That means space must be in another space and so on ad infinitum. This, of course, is just a quirky way of saying that it's impossible to conceive a limit to space.

But to return to the antinomy of infinite divisibility, {57} on which most of Zeno's arguments rest, you will perhaps expect me to say something of the different solutions which have been offered. In the first place, we must not forget Zeno's own solution. He did not propound this contradiction for its own sake, but to support the thesis of Parmenides. His solution is that as multiplicity and motion contain these contradictions, therefore multiplicity and motion cannot be real. Therefore, there is, as Parmenides said, only one Being, with no multiplicity in it, and excludent of all motion and becoming. The solution given by Kant in modern times is essentially similar. According to Kant, these contradictions are immanent in our conceptions of space and time, and since time and space involve these contradictions it follows that they are not real beings, but appearances, mere phenomena. Space and time do not belong to things as they are in themselves, but rather to our way of looking at things. They are forms of our perception. It is our minds which impose space and time upon objects, and not objects which impose space and time upon our minds. Further, Kant drew from these contradictions the conclusion that to comprehend the infinite is beyond the capacity of human reason. He attempted to show that, wherever we try to think the infinite, whether the infinitely large or the infinitely small, we fall into irreconcilable contradictions. Therefore, he concluded that human faculties are incapable of apprehending infinity. As might be expected, many thinkers have attempted to solve the problem by denying one or other side of the contradiction, by saying that one or other side does not follow from the premises, that one is true and the other false. David Hume, for example, {58} denied the infinite divisibility of space and time, and declared that they are composed of indivisible units having magnitude. But the difficulty that it is impossible to conceive of units having magnitude which are yet indivisible is not satisfactorily explained by Hume. And in general, it seems that any solution which is to be satisfactory must somehow make room for both sides of the contradiction. It will not do to deny one side or the other, to say that one is false and the other true. A true solution is only possible by rising above the level of the two antagonistic principles and taking them both up to the level of a higher conception, in which both opposites are reconciled.

But returning to the conflict of infinite divisibility, {57} on which most of Zeno's arguments rely, you might expect me to discuss the various solutions that have been proposed. First, we should remember Zeno's own solution. He didn't present this contradiction just for the fun of it, but to support Parmenides' thesis. His solution is that since multiplicity and motion contain these contradictions, they cannot be real. Therefore, as Parmenides said, there is only one Being, without multiplicity and excluding all motion and change. Kant's modern-day solution is quite similar. According to Kant, these contradictions are inherent in our concepts of space and time, and since time and space involve these contradictions, they are not real beings, but mere appearances or phenomena. Space and time do not belong to things as they are in themselves; instead, they belong to our perspective of things. They are forms of our perception. It is our minds that impose space and time on objects, not the other way around. Furthermore, Kant concluded from these contradictions that comprehending the infinite is beyond human reason. He tried to show that whenever we attempt to think about the infinite, whether it's something infinitely large or infinitely small, we run into irreconcilable contradictions. Thus, he concluded that our faculties cannot grasp infinity. As expected, many thinkers have tried to resolve the issue by denying one side of the contradiction, asserting that one side does not follow from the premises, claiming one is true and the other false. For instance, David Hume {58} denied the infinite divisibility of space and time, stating that they are made up of indivisible units that have magnitude. However, the challenge of imagining units with magnitude that are still indivisible isn't satisfactorily explained by Hume. Generally, it seems that any satisfactory solution must account for both sides of the contradiction. It won't suffice to dismiss one side or the other or to claim that one is false and the other true. A true solution can only be achieved by transcending the conflict between the two opposing principles and integrating them into a higher concept, where both opposites are reconciled.

This was the procedure followed by Hegel in his solution of the problem. Unfortunately his solution cannot be fully understood without some knowledge of his general philosophical principles, on which it wholly depends. I will, however, try to make it as plain as possible. In the first place, Hegel did not go out of his way to solve these antinomies. They appear as mere incidents in the development of his thought. He did not regard them as isolated cases of contradiction which occur in thought, as exceptions to a general rule, which therefore need special explanation. On the contrary, he regarded them, not as exceptions to, but as examples of, the essential character of reason. All thought, all reason, for Hegel, contains immanent contradictions which it first posits and then reconciles in a higher unity, and this particular contradiction of infinite divisibility is reconciled in the higher notion of quantity. The notion of quantity contains two factors, namely the one and the many. Quantity means precisely a many in {59} one, or a one in many. If, for example, we consider a quantity of anything, say a heap of wheat, this is, in the first place, one; it is one whole. Secondly, it is many; for it is composed of many parts. As one it is continuous; as many it is discrete. Now the true notion of quantity is not one, apart from many, nor many apart from one. It is the synthesis of both. It is a many in one. The antinomy we are considering arises from considering one side of the truth in a false abstraction from the other. To conceive unity as not being in itself multiplicity, or multiplicity as not being unity, is a false abstraction. The thought of the one involves the thought of the many, and the thought of the many involves the thought of the one. You cannot have a many without a one, any more than you can have one end of a stick without the other. Now, if we consider anything which is quantitatively measured, such as a straight line, we may consider it, in the first place, as one. In that case it is a continuous indivisible unit. Next we may regard it as many, in which case it falls into parts. Now each of these parts may again be regarded as one, and as such is an indivisible unit; and again each part may be regarded as many, in which case it falls into further parts; and this alternating process may go on for ever. This is the view of the matter which gives rise to the contradictions we have been considering. But it is a false view. It involves the false abstraction of first regarding the many as something that has reality apart from the one, and then regarding the one as something that has reality apart from the many. If you persist in saying that the line is simply one and not many, then there arises the theory of indivisible units. If you {60} persist in saying it is simply many and not one, then it is divisible ad infinitum. But the truth is that it is neither simply many nor simply one; it is a many in one, that is, it is a quantity. Both sides of the contradiction are, therefore, in one sense true, for each is a factor of the truth. But both sides are also false, if and in so far as, each sets itself up as the whole truth.

This was the approach Hegel used to tackle the problem. Unfortunately, his solution can't be fully grasped without some understanding of his overall philosophical principles, which it entirely depends on. However, I’ll do my best to clarify it. First of all, Hegel didn't actively seek to resolve these contradictions. They show up as mere moments in the evolution of his thinking. He didn't see them as isolated instances of contradiction occurring in thought, as exceptions to a general rule that would require special explanation. Instead, he viewed them not as exceptions to, but as illustrations of, the fundamental nature of reason. For Hegel, all thought and reason inherently contain contradictions that they first present and then reconcile in a higher unity, and this specific contradiction of infinite divisibility is resolved in the broader concept of quantity. The notion of quantity includes two elements: the one and the many. Quantity specifically refers to many in one, or one in many. For instance, if we think about a quantity of something, like a pile of wheat, it is, first and foremost, one; it is one complete whole. Secondly, it is many, because it consists of many parts. As one, it is continuous; as many, it is discrete. The true concept of quantity is neither just one, separate from many, nor many, separate from one. It is the combination of both. It is a many in one. The contradiction we’re examining occurs when we consider only one aspect of the truth while ignoring the other. To think of unity as not being multiplicity or of multiplicity as not being unity is a flawed abstraction. The concept of the one includes the concept of the many, and the concept of the many includes the concept of the one. You can't have many without one, just as you can't have one end of a stick without the other. Now, if we look at something that’s quantitatively measured, like a straight line, we can first think of it as one. In that case, it’s a continuous indivisible unit. Next, we might consider it as many, which means it breaks into parts. Each of these parts can also be seen as one, and as such, it's an indivisible unit; and again, each part can be seen as many, which can further break into more parts; and this back-and-forth can continue indefinitely. This perspective gives rise to the contradictions we've been discussing. But it's a mistaken view. It involves the flawed abstraction of initially considering the many as something that exists independently of the one, and then considering the one as something that exists independently of the many. If you insist that the line is simply one and not many, then you end up with the theory of indivisible units. If you persist in arguing that it is simply many and not one, then it is infinitely divisible. But the truth is that it is neither just many nor just one; it is a many in one, which means it is a quantity. Therefore, both sides of the contradiction are, in one sense, true since each is a part of the truth. However, both sides are also false to the extent that each claims to be the whole truth.


Critical Remarks on Eleaticism.

Critical Thoughts on Eleaticism.

The consideration of the meaning of Zeno's doctrine will give us an insight into the essentials of the position of the Eleatics. Zeno said that motion and multiplicity are not real. Now what does this mean? Did Zeno mean to say that when he walked about the streets of Elea, it was not true that he walked about? Did he mean that it was not a fact that he moved from place to place? When I move my arms, did he mean that I am not moving my arms, but that they really remain at rest all the time? If so, we might justly conclude that this philosophy is a mere craze of speculation run mad, or else a joke. But this is not what is meant. The Eleatic position is that though the world of sense, of which multiplicity and motion are essential features, may exist, yet that outward world is not the true Being. They do not deny that the world exists. They do not deny that motion exists or that multiplicity exists. These things no sane man can deny. The existence of motion and multiplicity is, as Hegel says, as sensuously certain as the existence of elephants. Zeno, then, does not deny the existence of the world. What he denies is the truth of existence. What he means is: certainly there is motion and multiplicity; certainly the world is here, is present to our senses, but it is not the true world. It is {61} not reality. It is mere appearance, illusion, an outward show and sham, a hollow mask which hides the real being of things. You may ask what is meant by this distinction between appearance and reality. Is not even an appearance real? It appears. It exists. Even a delusion exists, and is therefore a real thing. So is not the distinction between appearance and reality itself meaningless? Now all this is perfectly true, but it does not comprehend quite what is meant by the distinction. What is meant is that the objects around us have existence, but not self-existence, not self-substantiality. That is to say, their being is not in themselves, their existence is not grounded in themselves but is grounded in another, and flows from that other. They exist, but they are not independent existences. They are rather beings whose being flows into them from another, which itself is self-existent and self-substantial. They are, therefore, mere appearances of that other, which is the reality. Of course the Eleatics did not speak of appearance and reality in these terms. But this is what they were groping for, and dimly saw.

Considering the meaning of Zeno's doctrine gives us insight into the core beliefs of the Eleatics. Zeno argued that motion and multiplicity aren't real. So, what does this mean? Was Zeno suggesting that when he walked around the streets of Elea, it wasn't true that he was walking? Did he mean it wasn't a fact that he moved from one place to another? When I move my arms, did he mean I’m not actually moving them, but that they’re really at rest all the time? If that’s the case, we could rightly think that this philosophy is just a crazy speculation or a joke. But that's not what he means. The Eleatic view is that while the sensory world, which includes motion and multiplicity, may exist, that external world is not the true reality. They don’t deny the existence of the world. They don’t deny that motion exists or that multiplicity exists. No sane person can deny these things. The existence of motion and multiplicity is, as Hegel says, as undeniably real as the existence of elephants. So, Zeno doesn’t deny the existence of the world. What he denies is the truth of existence. What he means is: yes, there is motion and multiplicity; yes, the world is here, is present to our senses, but it is not the true world. It is {61} not reality. It is merely appearance, an illusion, an outward show, a facade that conceals the true nature of things. You might ask what is meant by the distinction between appearance and reality. Is even an appearance not real? It appears. It exists. Even a delusion exists, and is, therefore, a real thing. So, is the distinction between appearance and reality itself meaningless? While that’s true, it doesn’t fully capture what the distinction means. What is meant is that the objects around us have existence but lack self-existence or self-substantiality. In other words, their being is not in themselves; their existence is not founded in themselves but comes from another source. They exist, but they aren’t independent existences. They are more like beings whose existence flows into them from another, which itself is self-existent and self-substantial. Therefore, they are merely appearances of that other, which is the reality. Of course, the Eleatics didn’t express appearance and reality in these specific terms. But this is what they were searching for and dimly understood.

If we now look back upon the road on which we have travelled from the beginning of Greek philosophy, we shall be able to characterize the direction in which we have been moving. The earliest Greek philosophers, the Ionics, propounded the question, "what is the ultimate principle of things?" and answered it by declaring that the first principle of things is matter. The second Greek School, the Pythagoreans, answered the same question by declaring numbers to be the first principle. The third school, the Eleatics, answered the question by asserting that the first principle of things is Being. {62} Now the universe, as we know it, is both quantitative and qualitative. Quantity and quality are characteristics of every sense-object. These are not, indeed, the only characteristics of the world, but they are the only characteristics which have so far come to light. Now the position of the Ionics was that the ultimate reality is both quantitative and qualitative, that is to say, it is matter, for matter is just what has both quantity and quality. The Pythagoreans abstracted from the quality of things. They stripped off the qualitative aspect from things, and were accordingly left with only quantity as ultimate reality. Quantity is the same as number. Hence the Pythagorean position that the world is made of numbers. The Eleatic philosophy, proceeding one step further in the same direction, abstracted from quantity as well as quality. Whereas the Pythagoreans had denied the qualitative aspect of things, leaving themselves only with the quantitative, the Eleatics denied both quantity and quality, for in denying multiplicity they denied quantity. Therefore they are left with the total abstraction of mere Being which has in it neither dividedness (quantity), nor positive character (quality). The rise from the Ionic to the Eleatic philosophy is therefore essentially a rise from sensuous to pure thinking. The Eleatic Being is a pure abstract thought. The position of the Pythagoreans on the other hand is that of semi-sensuous thought. They form the stepping-stone from the Ionics to the Eleatics.

If we look back on the journey we've taken since the start of Greek philosophy, we can see the direction we've been heading. The earliest Greek philosophers, the Ionics, asked, "What is the fundamental principle of everything?" and responded by saying that matter is the first principle. The second group, the Pythagoreans, answered the same question by stating that numbers are the first principle. The third group, the Eleatics, responded by claiming that the first principle of everything is Being. Now, the universe, as we understand it, is both quantitative and qualitative. Quantity and quality are traits of every object we can sense. These aren't the only characteristics of the world, but they are the only ones we've discovered so far. The Ionics believed that ultimate reality is both quantitative and qualitative; in other words, it is matter, which embodies both quantity and quality. The Pythagoreans focused only on quantity. They removed the qualitative aspect of things, leaving them with only quantity as the ultimate reality. Quantity is equivalent to number, which is why the Pythagorean view is that the world consists of numbers. The Eleatic philosophy took this further by removing both quantity and quality. While the Pythagoreans had dismissed the qualitative aspect, leaving only the quantitative, the Eleatics rejected both, as denying multiplicity also means denying quantity. As a result, they arrived at the complete abstraction of pure Being, which contains neither division (quantity) nor distinguishable attributes (quality). The progression from Ionics to Eleatics is essentially a move from sensory experience to pure thought. The Eleatic concept of Being is a purely abstract idea, while the Pythagorean perspective represents a form of semi-sensory thinking. They serve as a bridge between the Ionics and the Eleatics.

Now let us consider what of worth there is in this Eleatic principle, and what its defects are. In the first place, it is necessary for us to understand that the Eleatic philosophy is the first monism. A monistic philosophy {63} is a philosophy which attempts to explain the entire universe from one single principle. The opposite of monism is therefore pluralism, which is that kind of philosophy which seeks to explain the universe from many ultimate and equally underived principles. But more particularly and more frequently we speak of the opposite of monism as being dualism, that is to say, the position that there are two ultimate principles of explanation. If, for example, we say that all the good in the universe arises from one source which is good, and that all the evil arises from another source which is evil, and that these sources of good and evil cannot be subordinated one to the other, and that one does not arise out of the other, but both are co-ordinate and equally primeval and independent, that position would be a dualism. All philosophy, which is worthy of the name, seeks, in some sense, a monistic explanation of the universe, and when we find that a system of philosophy breaks down and fails, then we may nearly always be sure its defect will reveal itself as an unreconciled dualism. Such a philosophy will begin with a monistic principle, and will attempt to derive or deduce the entire universe from it, but somewhere or other it comes across something in the world which it cannot bring under that principle. Then it is left with two equally ultimate existences, neither of which can be derived from the other. Thus it breaks out into dualism.

Now, let’s take a look at what is valuable in this Eleatic principle and what its flaws are. First, we need to understand that Eleatic philosophy represents the first form of monism. A monistic philosophy is one that aims to explain the entire universe based on a single principle. The opposite of monism is pluralism, which seeks to explain the universe through multiple ultimate and equally fundamental principles. More specifically, we often refer to the opposite of monism as dualism, which is the belief that there are two ultimate principles of explanation. For instance, if we say that all the good in the universe comes from one source that is good, and that all the evil comes from another source that is evil—where these sources of good and evil cannot be subordinated to one another and do not arise from each other, but instead are independent and equally fundamental—that view would be dualism. All philosophy that is truly philosophical aims, in some way, for a monistic explanation of the universe. When a philosophical system fails, its flaw usually reveals itself as an unresolved dualism. Such a philosophy might start with a monistic principle and try to explain the entire universe from that, but eventually it encounters aspects of the world that it cannot fit into that principle. It ends up with two equally fundamental existences that cannot be derived from each other, thus falling into dualism.

Now the search for a monistic explanation of things is a universal tendency of human thought. Wherever we look in the world of thought, we find that this monistic tendency appears. I have already said that it appears throughout the history of philosophy. It reveals itself, {64} too, very clearly in the history of religion. Religion begins in polytheism, the belief in many gods. From that it passes on to monotheism, the belief in one God, who is the sole author and creator of the universe. In Hindu thought we find the same thing. Hindu thought is based upon the principle that "All is one." Everything in the world is derived from one ultimate being, Brahman. But not only is this monistic tendency traceable in religion and philosophy; it is also traceable in science. The progress of scientific explanation is essentially a progress towards monism. In the first place, the explanation of isolated facts consists always in assigning causes for them. Suppose there is a strange noise in your room at night. You say it is explained when you find that it is due to the falling of a book or the scuttling of a rat across the floor. The noise is thus explained by assigning a cause for it. But this simply means that you have robbed it of its isolated and exceptional position, and reduced it to the position of an example of a general law. When the water freezes in your jug, you say that the cause of this is the cold. It is an example of the law that whenever the cold reaches a certain degree, then, other things being equal, water solidifies. But to assign causes in this way is not really to explain anything. It does not give any reason for an event happening. You cannot see any reason why water should solidify in the cold. It merely tells us that the event is not exceptional, but is an example of what always happens. It reduces the isolated event to a case of a general law, which "explains," not merely this one event, but possibly millions of events. It is not merely that cold solidifies the water in your jug. {65} It equally solidifies the water in everybody's jug. The same law "explains" all these, and likewise "explains" icebergs and the polar caps on the earth and the planet Mars. In fact scientific explanation means the reduction of millions of facts to one principle. But science does not stop here. It seeks further to explain the laws themselves, and its method is to reduce the many laws to one higher and more general law. A familiar example of this is the explanation of Kepler's laws of the planetary motions. Kepler laid down three such laws. The first was that planets move in elliptical orbits with the sun in one focus. The second was that planets describe equal areas in equal times. The third was a rather more complicated law. Kepler knew these laws from observation, but he could not explain them. They were explained by Newton's discovery of the law of gravitation. Newton proved that Kepler's three laws could be mathematically deduced from the law of gravitation. In that way Kepler's laws were explained, and not only Kepler's laws, but many other astronomical laws and facts. Thus the explanation of the many isolated facts consists in their reduction to the one law, and the explanation of the many laws consists in their reduction to the one more general law. As knowledge advances, the phenomena of the universe come to be explained by fewer and fewer, and wider and wider, general principles. Obviously the ultimate goal would be the explanation of all things by one principle. I do not mean to say that scientific men have this end consciously in view. But the point is that the monistic tendency is there. What is meant by the explanation is the reduction of all things to one principle.

Now, the search for a single explanation of everything is a universal tendency in human thinking. Wherever we look in the realm of thought, we see this tendency for unity. As I've mentioned, it appears throughout the history of philosophy. It also shows up clearly in the history of religion. Religion starts with polytheism, the belief in many gods. From there, it evolves into monotheism, the belief in one God, who is the only creator of the universe. We find the same idea in Hindu thought. Hinduism is based on the principle that "All is one." Everything in the world comes from one ultimate being, Brahman. But this tendency towards unity can be traced not just in religion and philosophy, but also in science. The advancement of scientific explanation is essentially a move toward a unified understanding. In the beginning, explaining isolated facts always involves assigning causes to them. Take, for example, a strange noise in your room at night. It’s explained when you discover it’s just a book falling or a rat scurrying across the floor. The noise is explained by identifying a cause, which means you’ve taken it out of its unique and unusual status and placed it as an example of a general law. When the water in your jug freezes, you say cold is the cause. It’s an instance of the law that whenever the temperature drops to a certain level, and other conditions remain the same, water turns solid. However, assigning causes like this doesn’t really explain anything. It doesn’t offer any reason for why the event happens. You can't see why water should freeze in the cold—it simply tells us that the event isn’t exceptional but is an example of what regularly occurs. It turns an isolated event into a case of a broader law that "explains" not just this one event, but potentially millions of them. It's not just that cold freezes the water in your jug. It also freezes the water in everyone else's jug. The same law "explains" all of these cases, as well as icebergs and the polar caps on Earth and Mars. In reality, scientific explanation means reducing countless facts to one principle. But science doesn’t stop there. It aims to further explain the laws themselves, and its method is to condense many laws into one higher and more general law. A well-known example is Kepler's laws of planetary motion. Kepler established three laws: the first states that planets move in elliptical orbits with the sun at one focus. The second states that planets cover equal areas in equal times. The third is a bit more complex. Kepler identified these laws through observation, but he couldn’t explain them. They were clarified by Newton's discovery of the law of gravitation. Newton demonstrated that Kepler's three laws could be mathematically derived from the law of gravitation. In this way, Kepler's laws were explained, along with many other astronomical laws and facts. So, the explanation of the many isolated facts consists of reducing them to one law, and the explanation of the many laws involves reducing them to one more general law. As knowledge advances, the phenomena of the universe get explained by fewer and broader principles. Clearly, the ultimate goal would be to explain everything by just one principle. I don’t mean to imply that scientists consciously aim for this. The point is that the tendency toward unity exists. What’s meant by explanation is the reduction of everything to one principle.

In philosophy, in religion, and in science, then, we find this monistic tendency of thought. But it might be asked how we know that this universal tendency is right? How do we know that it is not merely a universal error? Is there no logical or philosophical basis for the belief that the ultimate explanation of things must be one? Now this is a subject which takes us far afield from Greek philosophy. The philosophical basis of monism was never thought out till the time of Spinoza. So we cannot go into it at length here. But, quite shortly, the question is--Is there any reason for believing that the ultimate explanation of things must be one? Now if we are to explain the universe, two conditions must be fulfilled. In the first place, the ultimate reality by which we attempt to explain everything must explain all the other things in the world. It must be possible to deduce the whole world from it. Secondly, the first principle must explain itself. It cannot be a principle which itself still requires explanation by something else. If it is itself not self-explanatory, but is an ultimate mystery, then even if we succeed in deducing the universe from it, nothing is thereby explained. This, for example, is precisely the defect of materialism. Even if we suppose it proved that all things, including mind, arise from matter, yet the objection remains that this explains nothing at all, for matter is not a self-explanatory existence. It is an unintelligible mystery. And to reduce the universe to an ultimate mystery is not to explain it. Again; some people think that the world is to be explained by what they call a "first cause." But why should any cause be the first? Why should we stop anywhere in the chain of causes? Every cause is {67} necessarily the effect of a prior cause. The child, who is told that God made the world, and who inquires who, in that case, made God, is asking a highly sensible question. Or suppose, in tracing back the chain of causes, we come upon one which we have reason to say is really the first, is anything explained thereby? Still we are left with an ultimate mystery. Whatever the principle of explanation is, it cannot be a principle of this kind. It must be a principle which explains itself, and does not lead to something further, such as another cause. In other words, it must be a principle which has its whole being in itself, which does not for its completeness refer us to anything beyond itself. It must be something fully comprehended in itself, without reference to anything outside it. That is to say, it must be what we call self-determined or absolute. Now any absolute principle must necessarily be one. Suppose that it were two. Suppose you attempt to explain the world by two principles, X and Y, each of which is ultimate, neither being derived from the other. Then what relation does X bear to Y? We cannot fully comprehend X without knowing its relation to Y. Part of the character and being of X is constituted by its relation to Y. Part of X's character has to be explained by Y. But that is not to be self-explained. It is to be explained by something not itself. Therefore, the ultimate explanation of things must be one.

In philosophy, religion, and science, we see this tendency towards monism in thought. However, we might ask how we know that this universal tendency is correct. How do we know it’s not just a widespread mistake? Is there any logical or philosophical basis for believing that the ultimate explanation of everything must be singular? This topic takes us far away from ancient Greek philosophy. The philosophical foundation of monism wasn’t fully developed until Spinoza's time, so we can't dive into it deeply here. But, briefly, the question is: Is there any reason to believe that the ultimate explanation of everything has to be one? To explain the universe, two conditions must be met. First, the ultimate reality we use to explain everything must account for all other things in the world. It should be possible to derive the entire universe from it. Second, the first principle must explain itself; it can’t be a principle that still needs to be explained by something else. If it’s not self-explanatory and is instead an ultimate mystery, then even if we manage to derive the universe from it, nothing is actually clarified. This is exactly the flaw in materialism. Even if we assume it's been proven that everything, including the mind, comes from matter, the objection still stands that this explains nothing, as matter itself is not a self-explanatory entity. It remains an incomprehensible mystery. Reducing the universe to an ultimate mystery does not provide an explanation. Additionally, some people believe the world can be explained by what they call a "first cause." But why should any cause be considered the first? Why should we stop anywhere in the chain of causes? Every cause is necessarily the effect of a prior cause. The child who hears that God created the world and then asks who created God is asking a perfectly valid question. Or, suppose we trace the chain of causes back to one we can argue is the first—does that really explain anything? We are still left with an ultimate mystery. Whatever the principle of explanation is, it cannot be this kind of principle. It must be a principle that explains itself and doesn’t lead to something else, like another cause. In other words, it must be a principle that has its whole existence within itself, not requiring anything beyond itself for its completeness. It needs to be something fully understood within itself, without referencing anything outside of it. This means it must be what we call self-determined or absolute. Now, any absolute principle has to be singular. Imagine if it were two. If you try to explain the universe using two principles, X and Y, each being ultimate and not derived from one another, what relationship does X have to Y? We can’t fully understand X without knowing how it relates to Y. Part of X’s identity is shaped by its relationship to Y. Part of X’s characteristics needs to reference Y for explanation. But that means it’s not self-explanatory; it’s explained by something other than itself. Therefore, the ultimate explanation of everything must be one.

The Eleatics, then, were perfectly correct in saying that all is one, and that the ultimate principle of the universe, Being, is one. But if we examine the way in which they carried out their monism, we shall see that it broke down in a hopeless dualism. How did they {68} explain the existence of the world? They propounded the principle of Being, as the ultimate reality. How then did they derive the actual world from that principle? The answer is that they neither derived it nor made any attempt to derive it. Instead of deducing the world from their first principle, they simply denied the reality of the world altogether. They attempted to solve the problem by denying the existence of the problem. The world, they said, is simply not-being. It is an illusion. Now certainly it is a great thing to know which is the true world, and which the false, but after all this is not an explanation. To call the world an illusion is not to explain it. If the world is reality, then the problem of philosophy is, how does that reality arise? If the world is illusion, then the problem is, how does that illusion arise? Call it illusion, if you like. But this is not explaining it. It is simply calling it names. This is the defect, too, of Indian philosophy in which the world is said to be Maya--delusion. Hence in the Eleatic philosophy there are two worlds brought face to face, lying side by side of each other, unreconciled--the world of Being, which is the true world, and the world of facts, which is illusion. Although the Eleatics deny the sense-world, and call it illusion, yet of this illusion they cannot rid themselves. In some sense or other, this world is here, is present. It comes back upon our senses, and demands explanation. Call it illusion, but it still stands beside the true world, and demands that it be deduced from that. So that the Eleatics have two principles, the false world and the true world, simply lying side by side, without any connecting link between them, without anything to {69} show how the one arises from the other. It is an utterly irreconcilable dualism.

The Eleatics were right to say that everything is one, and that the ultimate principle of the universe, Being, is singular. But if we look at how they implemented their idea of oneness, we’ll see it fell apart into an unresolvable dualism. How did they explain the existence of the world? They introduced the principle of Being as the ultimate reality. So how did they connect that principle to the actual world? The answer is that they neither connected it nor tried to. Instead of deriving the world from their first principle, they merely denied the reality of the world completely. They attempted to address the issue by denying that the issue even existed. They claimed the world is simply not-being. It’s an illusion. While it’s certainly important to know which is the real world and which is the fake, in the end, this isn’t an explanation. Calling the world an illusion doesn’t explain it. If the world is reality, then the philosophical question is: how does that reality come into being? If the world is an illusion, then the question is: how does that illusion come about? Call it an illusion if you want, but that doesn’t explain it. It’s just labeling it. This is also a flaw in Indian philosophy, where the world is described as Maya—delusion. Therefore, in Eleatic philosophy, there are two worlds placed side by side, unreconciled—the world of Being, which is the true world, and the world of facts, which is an illusion. Even though the Eleatics deny the world we perceive and label it an illusion, they can't escape this illusion. In some sense, this world exists and is present. It returns to our senses and demands explanation. Call it an illusion, but it still exists next to the true world and requires a connection to be drawn from it. Thus, the Eleatics have two principles, a false world and a true world, lying side by side without any link between them, without anything to show how one arises from the other. It’s an utterly irreconcilable dualism.

It is easy to see why the Eleatic philosophy broke down in this dualism. It is due to the barrenness of their first principle itself. Being, they say, has in it no becoming. All principle of motion is expressly excluded from it. Likewise they deny to it any multiplicity. It is simply one, without any many in it. If you expressly exclude multiplicity and becoming from your first principle, then you can never get multiplicity and becoming out of it. You cannot get out of it anything that is not in it. If you say absolutely there is no multiplicity in the Absolute, then it is impossible to explain how multiplicity comes into this world. It is exactly the same in regard to the question of quality. Pure Being is without quality. It is mere "isness." It is an utterly featureless, characterless Being, perfectly empty and abstract. How then can the quality of things issue from it? How can all the riches and variety of the world come out of this emptiness? The Eleatics are like jugglers who try to make you believe that they get rabbits, guinea-pigs, pieces of string, paper, and ribbon, out of an entirely empty top-hat. One can see how utterly barren and empty this principle is, if one translates it into figurative language, that is to say, into the language of religion. The Eleatic principle would correspond to a religion in which we said that "God is," but beyond the fact that He "is," He has absolutely no character. But surely this is a wholly barren and meagre conception of the Deity. In the Christian religion we are accustomed to hear such expressions as, not only that "God is," but that "God is Love," "God is Power," {70} "God is Goodness," "God is Wisdom." Now objection may certainly be taken to these predicates and epithets on the ground that they are merely figurative and anthropomorphic. In fact, they exhibit the tendency to think non-sensuous objects sensuously. These predicates are merely picked up from the finite world and applied haphazard to God, for whom they are entirely inadequate. But at least these expressions teach us, that out of mere emptiness nothing can come; that the world cannot arise out of something which is lower and poorer than itself. Here in the world we find in a certain measure, love, wisdom, excellence, power. These things cannot spring from a source which is so poor that it contains nothing but "isness." The less can arise out of the greater, but not the greater out of the less. We may contrast Eleaticism not only with Christianity, but even with popular modern agnosticism. According to this, the Absolute is unknowable. But what the agnostic means is that human reason is inadequate to grasp the greatness of the ultimate being. But the Eleatic principle is, not that in saying "God is Love, Power, Wisdom," we are saying too little about God, and that our ideas are inadequate to express the fullness of His being, but on the contrary, that they express too high an idea for God, of whom nothing can be said except "He is," because there is absolutely nothing more to say. This conception of God is the conception of an absolutely empty being.

It’s easy to understand why Eleatic philosophy fell apart with this dualism. It stems from the emptiness of their foundational idea. They claim that Being has no becoming in it. Any principle of motion is completely excluded from it. They also deny any form of multiplicity. It is simply one, without anything many in it. If you completely remove multiplicity and becoming from your first principle, you can never derive multiplicity and becoming from it. You can’t get out of it anything that isn’t already in it. If you firmly state that there is no multiplicity in the Absolute, then it’s impossible to explain how multiplicity appears in this world. The same goes for the question of quality. Pure Being has no quality. It is just "isness." It is a featureless, characterless Being, entirely empty and abstract. So how can the qualities of things emerge from it? How can all the richness and variety of the world come from this emptiness? The Eleatics are like magicians trying to convince you that they pull rabbits, guinea pigs, string, paper, and ribbons from a completely empty top hat. One can see how completely barren and void this principle is if you put it into figurative terms, or the language of religion. The Eleatic principle would be like a religion claiming that “God is,” but beyond that fact, He has no characteristics at all. But surely, this is a quite empty and meager idea of the Divine. In Christianity, we often hear phrases like not only that "God is," but also that "God is Love," "God is Power," "God is Goodness," "God is Wisdom." While one might argue that these descriptions are just figurative and anthropomorphic, they do show a tendency to perceive non-sensory objects in a sensory way. These qualities are simply borrowed from the finite world and applied randomly to God, for whom they are entirely inadequate. But at the very least, these phrases teach us that nothing can come from mere emptiness; the world cannot emerge from something that is lower and poorer than itself. Here in the world, we encounter love, wisdom, excellence, and power to some extent. These qualities cannot come from a source that is so impoverished that it consists solely of "isness." The lesser cannot arise from the greater, but the greater can’t arise from the lesser. We can contrast Eleaticism not only with Christianity but also with contemporary popular agnosticism. According to this view, the Absolute is unknowable. However, what the agnostic means is that human reason cannot comprehend the greatness of the ultimate being. But the Eleatic principle is not that by saying "God is Love, Power, Wisdom," we are saying too little about God, and that our ideas fail to express the fullness of His existence, but rather that they express too elevated an idea for God, of whom nothing can be said except "He is," because there’s absolutely nothing more to say. This idea of God is the idea of an entirely empty being.

Monism, I said, is a necessary idea in philosophy. The Absolute must be one. But an utterly abstract monism is impossible. If the Absolute is simply one, wholly excludent of all process and multiplicity, out of such an abstraction the process and multiplicity of the {71} world cannot issue. The Absolute is not simply one, or simply many. It must be a many in one, as correctly set forth in the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. Religion moves from an abstract polytheism (God is many) to an abstract monotheism (God is one; Judaism, Hinduism and Islam). But it does not stop there. It rightly passes on to a concrete monotheism (God is many in one; Christianity). There are two popular misconceptions regarding the doctrine of the Trinity. The first mistake is that of popular rationalism, the second is that of popular theology. Popular rationalism asserts that the doctrine of the Trinity is contrary to reason. Popular theology asserts that it is a mystery which transcends reason. But the truth is that it neither contradicts nor transcends reason. On the contrary, it is in itself the highest manifestation of reason. What is really a mystery, what really contradicts reason, is to suppose that God, the Absolute, is simply one without any multiplicity. This contradiction results in the fatal dualism which broke out in Eleaticism, and has broken out in every other system of thought, such as that of the Hindus or that of Spinoza, which begins with the conception of the Absolute as a pure one, totally exclusive of the many.

Monism, as I mentioned, is an essential concept in philosophy. The Absolute must be unified. However, an entirely abstract monism is unworkable. If the Absolute is merely one, completely excluding all process and diversity, then this kind of abstraction cannot give rise to the processes and diversity of the {71} world. The Absolute is not just one or just many. It has to be a many in one, which is accurately described in the Christian belief in the Trinity. Religion evolves from an abstract polytheism (God is many) to an abstract monotheism (God is one; represented in Judaism, Hinduism, and Islam). But it doesn't stop there. It correctly moves on to a concrete monotheism (God is many in one; as seen in Christianity). There are two popular misunderstandings about the doctrine of the Trinity. The first misconception is from popular rationalism, and the second comes from popular theology. Popular rationalism claims that the doctrine of the Trinity goes against reason. Popular theology claims it is a mystery that goes beyond reason. But the reality is that it neither contradicts nor transcends reason. In fact, it represents the highest expression of reason. What truly is a mystery, what genuinely contradicts reason, is the idea that God, the Absolute, is merely one without any multiplicity. This contradiction leads to the damaging dualism that emerged in Eleaticism and has appeared in every other philosophical system, such as those of the Hindus or Spinoza, which start with the understanding of the Absolute as entirely one, completely excluding the many.

HERACLEITUS

HERACLITUS

Heracleitus was born about 535 B.C., and is believed to have lived to the age of sixty. This places his death at 475 B.C. He was thus subsequent to Xenophanes, contemporary with Parmenides, and older than Zeno. In historical order of time, therefore, he runs parallel to the Eleatics. Heracleitus was a man of Ephesus in Asia Minor. He was an aristocrat, descendant of a noble Ephesian family, and occupied in Ephesus the nominal position of basileus, or King. This, however, merely meant that he was the Chief Priest of the local branch of the Eleusinian mysteries, and this position he resigned in favour of his brother. He appears to have been a man of a somewhat aloof, solitary, and scornful nature. He looked down, not only upon the common herd, but even upon the great men of his own race. He mentions Xenophanes and Pythagoras in terms of obloquy. Homer, he thinks, should be taken out and whipped. Hesiod he considers to be the teacher of the common herd, one with them, "a man," he says, "who does not even know day and night." Upon the common herd of mortals he looks down with infinite scorn. Some of his sayings remind us not a little of Schopenhauer in their pungency and sharpness. "Asses prefer straw to {73} gold." "Dogs bark at everyone they do not know." Many of his sayings, however, are memorable and trenchant epitomes of practical wisdom. "Man's character is his fate." "Physicians who cut, burn, stab and rack the sick, demand a fee for doing it, which they do not deserve to get." From his aloof and aristocratic standpoint he launched forth denunciations against the democracy of Ephesus.

Heraclitus was born around 535 B.C. and is thought to have lived to about the age of sixty, which places his death around 475 B.C. He came after Xenophanes, was a contemporary of Parmenides, and was older than Zeno. In chronological order, he aligns with the Eleatics. Heraclitus was from Ephesus in Asia Minor. He belonged to an aristocratic family and held the nominal title of basileus, or King, in Ephesus. This title mainly indicated that he was the Chief Priest of the local branch of the Eleusinian mysteries, a position he eventually gave up for his brother. He seemed to have had a somewhat distant, solitary, and disdainful personality. He looked down not only on the common people but also on the notable figures of his own background. He referred to Xenophanes and Pythagoras with contempt. He believed Homer deserved to be taken out and punished, and he considered Hesiod to be the voice of the common people, calling him "a man who does not even know day and night." He regarded the general populace with immense scorn. Some of his quotes echo the sharpness and wit of Schopenhauer: "Donkeys prefer straw to gold." "Dogs bark at everyone they don’t recognize." However, many of his sayings are memorable and insightful reflections on practical wisdom. "A person's character is their destiny." "Doctors who cut, burn, stab, and torture the sick charge a fee for their services, which they don’t deserve." From his distant and aristocratic viewpoint, he expressed strong criticism against the democracy of Ephesus.

Heracleitus embodied his philosophical thoughts in a prose treatise, which was well-known at the time of Socrates, but of which only fragments have come down to us. His style soon became proverbial for its difficulty and obscurity, and he gained the nickname of Heracleitus the "Dark," or the "Obscure." Socrates said of his work that what he understood of it was excellent, what not, he believed was equally so, but that the book required a tough swimmer. He has even been accused of intentional obscurity. But there does not seem to be any foundation for this charge. The fact is that if he takes no great trouble to explain his thoughts, neither does he take any trouble to conceal them. He does not write for fools. His attitude appears to be that if his readers understand him, well; if not, so much the worse for his readers. He wastes no time in elaborating and explaining his thought, but embodies it in short, terse, pithy, and pregnant sayings.

Heraclitus expressed his philosophical ideas in a written work that was well-known during Socrates' time, but only fragments have survived. His writing style quickly became famous for being difficult and unclear, earning him the nickname Heraclitus the "Dark" or the "Obscure." Socrates remarked that the parts he understood were excellent, and he believed the parts he didn't understand were just as good, but that the text required a tough reader. He has even been accused of deliberately being unclear. However, there doesn't seem to be any basis for this accusation. The truth is that while he doesn't go out of his way to clarify his thoughts, he also doesn't try to hide them. He doesn't write for the uninformed. His attitude seems to be that if his readers comprehend him, great; if not, that's their loss. He doesn't waste time expanding and explaining his ideas but instead presents them in short, direct, impactful, and powerful statements.

His philosophical principle is the direct antithesis of Eleaticism. The Eleatics had taught that only Being is, and Becoming is not at all. All change, all Becoming is mere illusion. For Heracleitus, on the contrary, only Becoming is, and Being, permanence, identity, these are nothing but illusion. All things sublunary are {74} perpetually changing, passing over into new forms and new shapes. Nothing stands, nothing holds fast, nothing remains what it is. "Into the same river," he says, "we go down, and we do not go down; for into the same river no man can enter twice; ever it flows in and flows out." Not only does he deny all absolute permanence, but even a relative permanence of things is declared to be illusory. We all know that everything has its term, that all things arise and pass away, from the insects who live an hour to the "eternal" hills. Yet we commonly attribute to these things at least a relative permanence, a shorter or longer continuance in the same state. But even this Heracleitus will not allow. Nothing is ever the same, nothing remains identical from one consecutive moment to another. The appearance of relative permanence is an illusion, like that which makes us think that a wave passing over the surface of the water remains all the time the same identical wave. Here, as we know, the water of which the wave is composed changes from moment to moment, only the form remaining the same. Precisely so, for Heracleitus, the permanent appearance of things results from the inflow and outflow in them of equivalent quantities of substance. "All is flux." It is not, for example, the same sun which sets to-day and rises to-morrow. It is a new sun. For the fire of the sun burns itself out and is replenished from the vapours of the sea.

His philosophical principle is the direct opposite of Eleaticism. The Eleatics taught that only Being exists, while Becoming does not exist at all. They believed that all change and all Becoming are mere illusions. In contrast, for Heracleitus, only Becoming exists, and Being, permanence, identity, are nothing but illusions. Everything below the moon is perpetually changing, transitioning into new forms and shapes. Nothing stands still, nothing holds fast, nothing remains what it is. "Into the same river," he states, "we go down, and we do not go down; for into the same river no man can enter twice; it is always flowing in and flowing out." He not only denies all absolute permanence but also claims that even a relative permanence of things is an illusion. We all know that everything has its limits, that all things arise and pass away, from insects that live only an hour to the "eternal" mountains. Yet we often attribute to these things at least a relative permanence, a shorter or longer duration in the same state. But even this Heracleitus rejects. Nothing is ever the same, nothing remains identical from one moment to the next. The appearance of relative permanence is an illusion, similar to how we think that a wave passing over the surface of the water remains the same identical wave throughout. In reality, the water that makes up the wave changes from moment to moment, with only the shape staying the same. Likewise, for Heracleitus, the seemingly permanent appearance of things comes from the inflow and outflow of equivalent amounts of substance. "All is flux." It is not, for instance, the same sun that sets today and rises tomorrow. It is a new sun. The fire of the sun burns out and is replenished by the vapors of the sea.

Not only do things change from moment to moment. Even in one and the same moment they are and are not the same. It is not merely that a thing first is, and then a moment afterwards, is not. It both is and is not at the same time. The at-onceness of "is" and "is not" {75} is the meaning of Becoming. We shall understand this better if we contrast it with the Eleatic principle. The Eleatics described all things under two concepts, Being and not-being. Being has, for them, all truth, all reality. Not-being is wholly false and illusory. For Heracleitus both Being and not-being are equally real. The one is as true as the other. Both are true, for both are identical. Becoming is the identity of Being and not-being. For Becoming has only two forms, namely, the arising of things and their passing away, their beginning and their end, their origination and their decease. Perhaps you may think that this is not correct, that there are other forms of change besides origination and decease. A man is born. That is his origination. He dies. That is his decease. Between his birth and his death there are intermediate changes. He grows larger, grows older, grows wiser or more foolish, his hair turns grey. So also the leaf of a tree does not merely come into being and pass out of being. It changes in shape, form, colour. From light green it becomes dark green, and from dark green, yellow. But there is after all nothing in all this except origination and decease, not of the thing itself, but of its qualities. The change from green to yellow is the decease of green colour, the origination of yellow colour. Origination is the passage of not-being into Being. Decease is the passage of Being into not-being. Becoming, then, has in it only the two factors of Being and not-being, and it means the passing of one into the other. But this passage does not mean, for Heracleitus, that at one moment there is Being, and at the next moment not-being. It means that Being and not-being are in everything at one and the same time. Being is {76} not-being. Being has not-being in it. Take as an example the problem of life and death. Ordinarily we think that death is due to external causes, such as accident or disease. We consider that while life lasts, it is what it is, and remains what it is, namely life, unmixed with death, and that it goes on being life until something comes from outside, as it were, in the shape of external causes, and puts an end to it. You may have read Metchnikoff's book "The Nature of Man." In the course of that book he develops this idea. Death, he says, is always due to external causes. Therefore, if we could remove the causes, we could conquer death. The causes of death are mostly disease and accident, for even old age is disease. There is no reason why science should not advance so far as to eliminate disease and accident from life. In that case life might be made immortal, or at any rate, indefinitely prolonged. Now this is founded upon a confusion of ideas. No doubt death is always due to external causes. Every event in the world is determined, and wholly determined, by causes. The law of causation admits of no exception whatever. Therefore it is perfectly true that in every case of death causes precede it. But, as I explained in the last chapter, [Footnote 6] to give the cause is not to give any reason for an event. Causation is never a principle of explanation of anything. It tells us that the phenomenon A is invariably and unconditionally followed by the phenomenon B, and we call A the cause of B. But this only means that whenever B happens, it happens in a certain regular order and succession of events. But it does not tell us why B happens at all. The reason of a thing is to be {77} distinguished from its cause. The reason why a man dies is not to be found in the causes which bring about his death. The reason rather is that life has the germ of death already in it, that life is already death potentially, that Being has not-being in it. The causation of death is merely the mechanism, by the instrumentality of which, through one set of causes or another, the inevitable end is brought about.

Things change constantly, even within the same moment; they exist and don’t exist at the same time. It’s not just that something exists now and then doesn’t later; it both exists and doesn’t exist simultaneously. The coexistence of "is" and "is not" {75} captures the essence of Becoming. We can better understand this by comparing it to the Eleatic principle. The Eleatics described all things in terms of two ideas: Being and not-being. For them, Being holds all truth and reality, while not-being is entirely false and illusory. However, for Heraclitus, both Being and not-being are equally real; one is as true as the other. Both are true because they are identical. Becoming is the combination of Being and not-being. Becoming consists of two forms: the emergence of things and their disappearance, their beginning and their end, their origination and their passing away. You might argue that this isn’t entirely accurate, and that there are other forms of change besides emergence and disappearance. A person is born, which is his emergence. He dies, which is his passing away. Between birth and death, there are intermediate changes: he grows larger, older, wiser or more foolish, and his hair turns grey. Similarly, a tree leaf doesn’t just appear and vanish; it changes in shape, form, and color. It transitions from light green to dark green, and then from dark green to yellow. However, ultimately, this is still about emergence and passing away, not of the entity itself, but of its qualities. The change from green to yellow signifies the passing away of the green color and the emergence of the yellow color. Emergence is the transition from not-being to Being, while passing away is the transition from Being to not-being. Thus, Becoming solely involves these two elements: Being and not-being, and refers to the transition of one into the other. But for Heraclitus, this transition doesn’t imply that one moment there is Being and the next there is not-being; it signifies that Being and not-being coexist in everything at the same time. Being is {76} not-being. Being contains not-being. Consider the issue of life and death. We typically believe that death arises from external causes, such as accidents or diseases. We think that while life exists, it is purely life, unaffected by death, and continues as life until some external cause intervenes to end it. You may be familiar with Metchnikoff's book "The Nature of Man." Throughout the book, he elaborates on this idea, stating that death is always caused by external factors. He suggests that if we could eliminate those causes, we could overcome death. Most causes of death include disease and accidents, as even old age is considered a disease. There’s no reason we shouldn’t expect science to advance to a point where disease and accidents could be eradicated from life. In that case, life could potentially be made immortal or at least indefinitely prolonged. However, this reasoning reflects a misunderstanding. Certainly, death is due to external causes. Every event in the world is entirely determined by causes. The law of causality has no exceptions. So, it’s accurate to state that in every case of death, causes precede it. But, as I mentioned in the last chapter, [Footnote 6] providing the cause doesn’t explain an event. Causation is not a principle of understanding anything. It simply tells us that phenomenon A is always and unconditionally followed by phenomenon B, and we label A as the cause of B. But this only indicates that whenever B occurs, it happens in a specific sequence of events. It doesn’t explain why B occurs at all. The reason for something should be {77} differentiated from its cause. The reason a person dies isn’t found in the causes leading to his death. Rather, the reason is that life inherently contains the potential for death; that life is, in a sense, already a form of death, that Being contains not-being. The causation of death is simply the mechanism through which, by one set of causes or another, the inevitable conclusion is reached.

[Footnote 6: Page 64.]

[Footnote 6: __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__]

Not only is Being, for Heracleitus, identical with not-being, but everything in the universe has in it its own opposite. Every existent thing is a "harmony of opposite tensions." A harmony contains necessarily two opposite principles which, in spite of their opposition, reveal an underlying unity. That it is by virtue of this principle that everything in the universe exists, is the teaching of Heracleitus. All things contain their own opposites within them. In the struggle and antagonism between hostile principles consists their life, their being, their very existence. At the heart of things is conflict. If there were no conflict in a thing, it would cease to exist. This idea is expressed by Heracleitus in a variety of ways. "Strife," he says, "is the father of all things." "The one, sundering from itself, coalesces with itself, like the harmony of the bow and the lyre." "God is day and night, summer and winter, war and peace, satiety and hunger." "Join together whole and unwhole, congruous and incongruous, accordant and discordant, then comes from one all and from all one." In this sense, too, he censures Homer for having prayed that strife might cease from among gods and men. If such a prayer were granted, the universe itself would pass away.

Not only does Being, for Heraclitus, equate to not-being, but everything in the universe contains its own opposite. Every existing thing is a "harmony of opposite tensions." A harmony necessarily includes two opposing principles that, despite their conflict, reveal an underlying unity. Heraclitus teaches that everything in the universe exists because of this principle. All things hold their own opposites within them. Their life, existence, and being come from the struggle and antagonism between conflicting principles. Conflict lies at the core of everything. Without conflict, a thing would stop existing. Heraclitus expresses this idea in several ways: "Strife is the father of all things." "The one, separating from itself, merges with itself, like the harmony of the bow and the lyre." "God is day and night, summer and winter, war and peace, fullness and hunger." "Join together whole and unwhole, congruent and incongruent, harmonious and discordant, then from one comes all and from all comes one." In this way, he also critiques Homer for wishing that strife might end among gods and humans, arguing that if such a wish were granted, the universe itself would cease to exist.

Side by side with this metaphysic, Heracleitus lays down a theory of physics. All things are composed of fire. "This world," he says, "neither one of the gods nor of the human race has made; but it is, it was, and ever shall be, an eternally living fire." All comes from fire, and to fire all returns. "All things are exchanged for fire and fire for all, as wares for gold and gold for wares." Thus there is only one ultimate kind of matter, fire, and all other forms of matter are merely modifications and variations of fire. It is clear for what reason Heracleitus enunciated this principle. It is an exact physical parallel to the metaphysical principle of Becoming. Fire is the most mutable of the elements. It does not remain the same from one moment to another. It is continually taking up matter in the form of fuel, and giving off equivalent matter in the form of smoke and vapour. The primal fire, according to Heracleitus, transmutes itself into air, air into water, and water into earth. This he calls "the downward path." To it corresponds "the upward path," the transmutation of earth into water, water to air, and air to fire. All transformation takes place in this regular order, and therefore, says Heracleitus, "the upward and the downward path are one."

Alongside this metaphysics, Heraclitus presents a theory of physics. Everything is made of fire. "This world," he says, "was not created by either the gods or humans; it simply is, it was, and will always be, an eternally living fire." Everything originates from fire, and everything ultimately returns to fire. "All things are exchanged for fire, and fire for all, like goods for gold and gold for goods." Thus, there is only one fundamental type of matter, fire, and all other forms of matter are simply modifications and variations of fire. It's clear why Heraclitus stated this principle. It directly parallels the metaphysical principle of Becoming. Fire is the most changeable of the elements. It doesn’t stay the same from one moment to the next. It continuously absorbs matter in the form of fuel and releases equivalent matter as smoke and vapor. The original fire, according to Heraclitus, transforms into air, air into water, and water into earth. He refers to this as "the downward path." Corresponding to it is "the upward path," where earth becomes water, water becomes air, and air becomes fire. All transformations occur in this orderly fashion, and therefore, Heraclitus says, "the upward and the downward path are one."

Fire is further specially identified with life and reason. It is the rational element in things. The more fire there is, the more life, the more movement. The more dark and heavy materials there are, the more death, cold, and not-being. The soul, accordingly, is fire, and like all other fires it continually burns itself out and needs replenishment. This it obtains, through the senses and the breath, from the common life and reason of the {79} world, that is, from the surrounding and all-pervading fire. In this we live and move and have our being. No man has a separate soul of his own. It is merely part of the one universal soul-fire. Hence if communication with this is cut off, man becomes irrational and finally dies. Sleep is the half-way house to death. In sleep the passages of the senses are stopped up, and the outer fire reaches us only through breath. Hence in sleep we become irrational and senseless, turning aside from the common life of the world, each to a private world of his own. Heracleitus taught also the doctrine of periodic world-cycles. The world forms itself out of fire, and by conflagration passes back to the primitive fire.

Fire is closely linked to life and reason. It represents the rational element in everything. The more fire there is, the more life and movement we see. Conversely, the more dark and heavy materials there are, the more we experience death, cold, and nothingness. The soul is like fire; it constantly burns out and needs to be replenished. It gets this replenishment through our senses and breath, drawing from the collective life and reason of the {79} world, or from the surrounding and all-encompassing fire. In this state, we live, move, and exist. No one has a separate soul; it is just a part of the one universal soul-fire. Therefore, if we lose connection with this, we become irrational and eventually die. Sleep is a step toward death. During sleep, our senses are blocked, and we only connect to the outer fire through our breath. This leads to irrational and senseless states, as we turn away from the shared life of the world and retreat into our individual worlds. Heraclitus also taught that the world goes through periodic cycles. The world originates from fire and returns to its original state through conflagration.

In his religious opinions Heracleitus was sceptical. But he does not, like Xenophanes, direct his attacks against the central ideas of religion, and the doctrine of the gods. He attacks mostly the outward observances and forms in which the religious spirit manifests itself. He inveighs against the worship of images, and urges the uselessness of blood sacrifice.

In his religious views, Heracleitus was doubtful. However, unlike Xenophanes, he doesn't directly challenge the core beliefs of religion or the concept of the gods. Instead, he mostly criticizes the external practices and rituals through which religious feelings are expressed. He speaks out against idol worship and argues that blood sacrifices are pointless.

With the Eleatics he distinguishes between sense and reason, and places truth in rational cognition. The illusion of permanence he ascribes to the senses. It is by reason that we rise to the knowledge of the law of Becoming. In the comprehension of this law lies the duty of man, and the only road to happiness. Understanding this, man becomes resigned and contented. He sees that evil is the necessary counterpart of good, and pain the necessary counterpart of pleasure, and that both together are necessary to form the harmony of the world. Good and evil are principles on the struggle {80} between which the very existence of things depends. Evil, too, is necessary, has its place in the world. To see this is to put oneself above pitiful and futile struggles against the supreme law of the universe.

With the Eleatics, he distinguishes between perception and reasoning, placing truth in rational understanding. He attributes the illusion of permanence to the senses. It is through reason that we come to know the law of Becoming. Understanding this law is humanity's duty and the sole path to happiness. By grasping this, a person becomes accepting and at peace. They recognize that evil is the necessary counterpart to good, and pain is the necessary counterpart to pleasure, and that both are essential for the harmony of the world. Good and evil are principles in the struggle {80} upon which the very existence of things relies. Evil is also necessary; it has its place in the world. Realizing this allows one to rise above futile struggles against the ultimate law of the universe.


EMPEDOCLES

EMPEDOCLES

Empedocles was a man of Agrigentum in Sicily. The dates of his birth and death are placed about 495 and 435 B.C. respectively. Like Pythagoras, he possessed a powerful and magnetic personality. Hence all kinds of legends quickly grew up and wove themselves round his life and death. He was credited with the performance of miracles, and romantic stories were circulated about his death. A man of much persuasive eloquence he raised himself to the leadership of the Agrigentine democracy, until he was driven out into exile.

Empedocles was a guy from Agrigentum in Sicily. He was born around 495 B.C. and died around 435 B.C. Similar to Pythagoras, he had a strong and charismatic presence. Because of this, numerous legends quickly formed around his life and death. People said he performed miracles, and romantic tales spread about how he died. A highly persuasive speaker, he rose to lead the Agrigentine democracy until he was exiled.

The philosophy of Empedocles is eclectic in character. Greek philosophy had now developed a variety of conflicting principles, and the task of Empedocles is to reconcile these, and to weld them together in a new system, containing however no new thought of its own. In speaking of Parmenides, I pointed out that his teaching may be interpreted either in an idealistic or a materialistic sense, and that these two aspects of thought lie side by side in Parmenides, and that it is possible to emphasize either the one or the other. Empedocles seizes upon the materialistic side. The essential thought of Parmenides was that Being cannot pass into not-being, nor not-being into Being. Whatever is, remains for ever what it is. {82} If we take that in a purely material context, what it means is that matter has neither beginning nor end, is uncreated and indestructible. And this is the first basic principle of Empedocles. On the other hand, Heracleitus had shown that becoming and change cannot be denied. This is the second basic principle of Empedocles. That there is no absolute becoming, no creation, and utter destruction of things, and yet that things do somehow arise and pass away, this must be explained, these contradictory ideas must be reconciled. Now if we assert that matter is uncreated and indestructible, and yet that things arise and pass away, there is only one way of explaining this. We must suppose that objects, as wholes begin and cease to be, but that the material particles of which they are composed are uncreated and indestructible. This thought now forms the first principle of Empedocles, and of his successors, Anaxagoras, and the Atomists.

The philosophy of Empedocles has a diverse nature. By this time, Greek philosophy had developed a range of conflicting ideas, and Empedocles aimed to reconcile these and combine them into a new system, though it doesn't introduce any original thoughts. When discussing Parmenides, I noted that his teachings can be interpreted in either an idealistic or materialistic way, with both perspectives coexisting in Parmenides, allowing for one to be emphasized over the other. Empedocles focuses on the materialistic aspect. The core idea of Parmenides was that Being cannot transform into not-being, nor can not-being become Being. Whatever exists remains what it is eternally. If we view this in purely material terms, it means that matter has no beginning or end, is uncreated and indestructible. This is the first fundamental principle of Empedocles. On the other hand, Heraclitus demonstrated that change and becoming cannot be ignored. This is the second fundamental principle of Empedocles. While there is no absolute becoming, no true creation or total destruction of things, it still needs to be explained how things come into existence and fade away; these opposing ideas must be reconciled. If we assert that matter is uncreated and indestructible, yet acknowledge that things come into being and pass away, there is only one way to explain this: we must assume that objects as whole entities begin and cease to exist, but the material particles they are made of are uncreated and indestructible. This concept forms the first principle of Empedocles, and also influences his successors, Anaxagoras and the Atomists.

Now the Ionic philosophers had taught that all things are composed of some one ultimate matter. Thales believed it to be water, Anaximenes air. This necessarily involved that the ultimate kind of matter must be capable of transformation into other kinds of matter. If it is water, then water must be capable of turning into brass, wood, iron, air, or whatever other kind of matter exists. And the same thing applies to the air of Anaximenes. Parmenides, however, had taught that whatever is, remains always the same, no change or transformation being possible. Empedocles here too follows Parmenides, and interprets his doctrine in his own way. One kind of matter, he thinks, can never change into another kind of matter; fire never becomes {83} water, nor does earth ever become air. This leads Empedocles at once to a doctrine of elements. The word "elements," indeed, is of later invention, and Empedocles speaks of the elements as "the roots of all." There are four elements, earth, air, fire, and water. Empedocles was therefore the originator of the familiar classification of the four elements. All other kinds of matter are to be explained as mixtures, in various proportions, of these four. Thus all origination and decease, as well as the differential qualities of certain kinds of matter, are now explained by the mixing and unmixing of the four elements. All becoming is simply composition and decomposition.

Now the Ionic philosophers taught that everything is made up of one ultimate substance. Thales thought it was water, while Anaximenes believed it was air. This meant that the ultimate substance must be able to change into other substances. If it’s water, then water must be able to turn into brass, wood, iron, air, or any other form of matter. The same goes for the air that Anaximenes mentioned. However, Parmenides argued that whatever exists always stays the same, and no change or transformation is possible. Empedocles follows Parmenides but interprets his ideas in his own way. He believes that one type of matter can never change into another; fire will never become water, nor will earth ever become air. This leads Empedocles to a theory of elements. The term "elements" was actually coined later, and Empedocles refers to them as "the roots of all." He identifies four elements: earth, air, fire, and water. Thus, Empedocles is credited with the well-known classification of the four elements. All other types of matter are explained as mixtures of these four in different proportions. Therefore, all creation and destruction, along with the different qualities of various types of matter, are now explained through the mixing and unmixing of the four elements. All change is simply a matter of combination and separation.

But the coming together and separation of the elements involves the movement of particles, and to explain this there must exist some moving force. The Ionic philosophers had assumed that matter has the power or force required for movement immanent in itself. The air of Anaximenes, of its own inherent power, transforms itself into other kinds of matter. This doctrine Empedocles rejects. Matter is for him absolutely dead and lifeless, without any principle of motion in itself. There is, therefore, only one remaining possibility. Forces acting upon matter from the outside must be assumed. And as the two essential processes of the world, mixing and unmixing, are opposite in character, so there must be two opposite forces. These he calls by the names Love and Hate, or Harmony and Discord. Though these terms may have an idealistic sound, Empedocles conceives them as entirely physical and material forces. But he identifies the attractions and repulsions of human beings, which we call love and hate, with the universally operating forces of the material world. Human love and {84} hate are but the manifestations in us of the mechanical forces of attraction and repulsion at work in the world at large.

But the coming together and separation of elements involves the movement of particles, and to explain this, there must be some driving force. The Ionic philosophers assumed that matter has the power or force necessary for movement inherent within itself. Anaximenes believed that air can transform into different types of matter through its own inherent power. Empedocles rejects this idea. For him, matter is completely dead and lifeless, lacking any principle of motion within itself. Therefore, one possibility remains: external forces must be acting on matter. As the two fundamental processes of the world—mixing and unmixing—are opposite, there must also be two opposing forces. He names these forces Love and Hate, or Harmony and Discord. Although these terms might sound idealistic, Empedocles views them as entirely physical and material forces. He equates the attractions and repulsions of people, which we call love and hate, with the universally operating forces of the material world. Human love and hate are merely expressions of the mechanical forces of attraction and repulsion that are active in the broader world.

Empedocles taught the doctrine of periodic world-cycles. The world-process is, therefore, properly speaking, circular, and has neither beginning nor end. But in describing this process one must begin somewhere. We will begin, then, with the sphairos (sphere). In the primeval sphere the four elements are completely mixed, and interpenetrate each other completely. Water is not separated off from air, nor air from earth. All are chaotically mixed together. In any portion of the sphere there must be an equal quantity of earth, air, fire and water. The elements are thus in union, and the sole force operative within the sphere is Love or Harmony. Hence the sphere is called a "blessed god." Hate, however, exists all round the outside of the sphere. Hate gradually penetrates from the circumference towards the centre and introduces the process of separation and disunion of the elements. This process continues till, like coming together with like, the elements are wholly separated. All the water is together; all the fire is together, and so on. When this process of disintegration is complete, Hate is supreme and Love is entirely driven out. But Love again begins to penetrate matter, to cause union and mixture of the elements, and finally brings the world back to the state of the original sphere. Then the same process begins again. At what position in this circular movement is our present world to be placed? The answer is that it is neither in the complete union of the sphere, nor is it completely disintegrated. It is half-way between the sphere and the stage of total {85} disintegration. It is proceeding from the former towards the later, and Hate is gradually gaining the upper hand. In the formation of the present world from the sphere the first element to be separated off was air, next fire, then the earth. Water is squeezed out of the earth by the rapidity of its rotation. The sky is composed of two halves. One is of fire, and this is the day. The other is dark matter with masses of fire scattered about in it, and this is the night.

Empedocles taught the idea of recurring world-cycles. So, the process of the world is essentially circular and has no true beginning or end. However, when describing this process, you have to start somewhere. Let’s start with the sphere. In the original sphere, the four elements are fully mixed and completely interwoven. Water isn’t separated from air, nor is air from earth. Everything is chaotically blended together. In any part of the sphere, there must be an equal amount of earth, air, fire, and water. The elements are united, and the only force at work in the sphere is Love or Harmony. Because of this, the sphere is referred to as a "blessed god." However, Hate exists all around the outside of the sphere. Hate gradually moves in from the edge towards the center, bringing about the process of separation and disunion of the elements. This process continues until, like attracts like, and the elements are completely separated. All the water is grouped together; all the fire is grouped together, and so on. When this process of breaking down is finished, Hate reigns supreme and Love is entirely pushed out. But Love starts to penetrate the matter again, causing the elements to unite and mix, ultimately bringing the world back to the state of the original sphere. Then the same process starts over. Where does our current world fit in this circular movement? The answer is that it is neither in the complete unity of the sphere nor is it entirely disintegrated. It’s halfway between the sphere and the stage of total disintegration. It is moving from the former towards the latter, and Hate is gradually gaining the upper hand. In forming the current world from the sphere, the first element that was separated out was air, then fire, followed by earth. Water is pushed out of the earth due to its rapid rotation. The sky is made up of two halves. One half is fire, which represents day. The other half is dark matter with patches of fire scattered throughout, which represents night.

Empedocles believed in the transmigration of souls. He also put forward a theory of sense-perception, the essential of which is that like perceives like. The fire in us perceives external fire, and so with the other elements. Sight is caused by effluences of the fire and water of the eyes meeting similar effluences from external objects.

Empedocles believed in the idea of souls moving from one body to another. He also proposed a theory about how we perceive things, which basically says that similar things recognize each other. The fire inside us notices outside fire, and the same goes for the other elements. We see things when the fire and water in our eyes interact with similar qualities coming from external objects.

THE ATOMISTS

THE ATOMISTS

The founder of the Atomist philosophy was Leucippus. Practically nothing is known of his life. The date of his birth, the date of his death, and his place of residence, are alike unknown, but it is believed that he was a contemporary of Empedocles and Anaxagoras. Democritus was a citizen of Abdera in Thrace. He was a man of the widest learning, as learning was understood in his day. A passion for knowledge and the possession of adequate means for the purpose, determined him to undertake extensive travels in order to acquire the wisdom and knowledge of other nations. He travelled largely in Egypt, also probably in Babylonia. The date of his death is unknown, but he certainly lived to a great age, estimated at from ninety to one hundred years. Exactly what were the respective contributions of Leucippus and Democritus to the Atomist philosophy, is also a matter of doubt. But it is believed that all the essentials of this philosophy were the work of Leucippus, and that Democritus applied and extended them, worked out details, and made the theory famous.

The founder of the Atomist philosophy was Leucippus. Almost nothing is known about his life. The dates of his birth and death, as well as where he lived, are all unknown, but it's thought that he was a contemporary of Empedocles and Anaxagoras. Democritus was from Abdera in Thrace. He was widely knowledgeable for his time. His passion for learning and his means to explore led him to travel extensively to gain the wisdom and knowledge of other cultures. He traveled primarily in Egypt and probably also in Babylonia. The date of his death is unclear, but he definitely lived to be quite old, estimated to be between ninety and one hundred years. Exactly what contributions Leucippus and Democritus made to Atomist philosophy is also uncertain. However, it's believed that Leucippus was responsible for the core ideas of this philosophy, while Democritus developed, elaborated on, and popularized them.

Now we saw that the philosophy of Empedocles was based upon an attempt to reconcile the doctrine of Parmenides with the doctrine of Heracleitus. The {87} fundamental thought of Empedocles was that there is no absolute becoming in the strict sense, no passage of Being into not-being or not-being into Being. Yet the objects of the senses do, in some way, arise and pass away, and the only method by which this is capable of explanation is to suppose that objects, as whole objects, come to be and cease to be, but that the material particles of which they are composed are eternally existent. But the detailed development which Empedocles gave to this principle was by no means satisfactory. In the first place, if we hold that all objects are composed of parts, and that all becoming is due to the mixing and unmixing of pre-existent matter, we must have a theory of particles. And we do hear vaguely of physical particles in the doctrine of Empedocles, but no definition is given of their nature, and no clear conception is formed of their character. Secondly, the moving forces of Empedocles, Love and Hate, are fanciful and mythological. Lastly, though there are in Empedocles traces of the doctrine that the qualities of things depend on the position and arrangement of their particles, this idea is not consistently developed. For Empedocles there are only four ultimate kinds of matter, qualitatively distinguished. The differential qualities of all other kinds of matter must, therefore, be due to the mixing of these four elements. Thus the qualities of the four elements are ultimate and underived, but all other qualities must be founded upon the position and arrangement of particles of the four elements. This is the beginning of the mechanical explanation of quality. But to develop this theory fully and consistently, it should be shown, not merely that some qualities are ultimate and some {88} derived from position and arrangement of particles, but that all quality whatever is founded upon position and arrangement. All becoming is explained by Empedocles as the result of motion of material particles. To bring this mechanical philosophy to its logical conclusion, all qualitativeness of things must be explained in the same way. Hence it was impossible that the philosophy of mechanism and materialism should stand still in the position in which Empedocles left it. It had to advance to the position of Atomism. The Atomists, therefore, maintain the essential position of Empedocles, after eliminating the inconsistencies which we have just noted. The philosophy of Empedocles is therefore to be considered as merely transitional in character.

Now we see that Empedocles’ philosophy was an attempt to combine Parmenides' ideas with those of Heraclitus. The {87} central idea of Empedocles was that there is no absolute becoming in the strict sense—no transition from Being to non-being or from non-being to Being. However, the objects we perceive do somehow come into being and pass away, and the only way to explain this is to assume that objects, as whole entities, come into existence and cease to exist, while the material particles they are made of are eternally present. However, the way Empedocles developed this idea was far from satisfactory. First of all, if we accept that all objects are made up of parts, and that all transformation is due to the mixing and separating of pre-existing matter, we must have a theory of particles. We do hear vague references to physical particles in Empedocles' teachings, but there’s no clear definition of what they are, nor is there a distinct concept of their nature. Secondly, Empedocles' driving forces, Love and Hate, are fanciful and mythological. Lastly, while there are hints in Empedocles' work suggesting that the qualities of things depend on how their particles are arranged, this idea is not developed consistently. According to Empedocles, there are only four fundamental types of matter, each qualitatively different. Thus, the differing qualities of all other types of matter must arise from the mixing of these four elements. So, the qualities of the four elements are basic and not derived, while all other qualities depend on how the particles of these four elements are arranged. This marks the start of the mechanical explanation of quality. To fully and consistently develop this theory, it should be demonstrated not just that some qualities are fundamental and some {88} arise from the arrangement of particles, but that all qualities are based on position and arrangement. Empedocles explains all transformation as resulting from the movement of material particles. To reach a logical conclusion for this mechanical philosophy, all aspects of quality must be explained in the same way. Therefore, it was impossible for the philosophy of mechanism and materialism to stay where Empedocles left it; it had to progress to the idea of Atomism. The Atomists, consequently, hold onto the core ideas of Empedocles while addressing the inconsistencies we just mentioned. Thus, Empedocles' philosophy is to be seen as merely transitional.

First, the Atomists developed the theory of particles. According to Leucippus and Democritus, if matter were divided far enough, we should ultimately come to indivisible units. These indivisible units are called atoms, and atoms are therefore the ultimate constituents of matter. They are infinite in number, and are too small to be perceptible to the senses. Empedocles had assumed four different kinds of matter. But, for the Atomists, there is only one kind. All the atoms are composed of exactly the same kind of matter. With certain exceptions, which I will mention in a moment, they possess no quality. They are entirely non-qualitative, the only differences between them being differences of quantity. They differ in size, some being larger, some smaller. And they likewise differ in shape. Since the ultimate particles of things thus possess no quality, all the actual qualities of objects must be due to the {89} arrangement and position of the atoms. This is the logical development of the tentative mechanism of Empedocles.

First, the Atomists developed the theory of particles. According to Leucippus and Democritus, if matter were divided enough times, we would eventually reach indivisible units. These indivisible units are called atoms, and atoms are therefore the fundamental building blocks of matter. They are infinite in number and too small to be detected by our senses. Empedocles had proposed four different types of matter, but for the Atomists, there is only one type. All atoms are made up of precisely the same kind of matter. With certain exceptions, which I will point out shortly, they have no inherent qualities. They are completely non-qualitative, with the only differences among them being differences in quantity. They vary in size, with some being larger and others smaller. They also differ in shape. Since the basic particles of things have no qualities, all the actual qualities of objects must come from the arrangement and position of the atoms. This is the logical progression of Empedocles' tentative mechanism.

I said that the atoms possess no qualities. They must, however, be admitted to possess the quality of solidity, or impenetrability, since they are defined as being indivisible. Moreover it is a question whether the atoms of Democritus and Leucippus were thought to possess weight, or whether the weight of objects is to be explained, like other qualities, by the position and movement of the atoms. There is no doubt that the Epicureans of a later date considered the atoms to have weight. The Epicureans took over the atomism of Democritus and Leucippus, with few modifications, and made it the basis of their own teaching. They ascribed weight to the atoms, and the only question is whether this was a modification introduced by them, or whether it was part of the original doctrine of Democritus and Leucippus.

I stated that atoms have no qualities. However, we must acknowledge that they do have the quality of solidity, or impenetrability, since they are defined as indivisible. Additionally, it's uncertain whether Democritus and Leucippus believed atoms had weight, or if the weight of objects is explained, like other qualities, by the arrangement and movement of atoms. There’s no doubt that later Epicureans thought atoms did have weight. They adopted the atomism of Democritus and Leucippus, with few changes, as the foundation of their own beliefs. They attributed weight to atoms, and the only question is whether this was a change they made or if it was part of Democritus and Leucippus's original ideas.

The atoms are bounded, and separated off from each other. Therefore, they must be separated by something, and this something can only be empty space. Moreover, since all becoming and all qualitativeness of things are to be explained by the mixing and unmixing of atoms, and since this involves movement of the atoms, for this reason also empty space must be assumed to exist, for nothing can move unless it has empty space to move in. Hence there are two ultimate realities, atoms and empty space. These correspond respectively to the Being and not-being of the Eleatics. But whereas the latter denied any reality to not-being, the Atomists affirm that not-being, that is, empty space, is just as real as being. Not-being also exists. "Being," said {90} Democritus, "is by nothing more real than nothing." The atoms being non-qualitative, they differ in no respect from empty space, except that they are "full." Hence atoms and the void are also called the plenum and the vacuum.

The atoms are bound and separated from each other. So, they must be separated by something, and that something can only be empty space. Also, since all change and all qualities of things come from the mixing and unmixing of atoms, and since this involves the movement of atoms, we must assume that empty space exists, because nothing can move without empty space to move in. Therefore, there are two ultimate realities: atoms and empty space. These correspond to the Being and non-being of the Eleatics. However, while the latter denied any reality to non-being, the Atomists argue that non-being, meaning empty space, is just as real as being. Non-being also exists. "Being," said {90} Democritus, "is not more real than nothing." The atoms are non-qualitative, so they differ from empty space only in that they are "full." Thus, atoms and the void are also referred to as the plenum and the vacuum.

How, now, is the movement of the atoms brought about? Since all becoming is due to the separation and aggregation of atoms, a moving force is required. What is this moving force? This depends upon the question whether atoms have weight. If we assume that they have weight, then the origin of the world, and the motion of atoms, becomes clear. In the system of the Epicureans the original movement of the atoms is due to their weight, which causes them to fall perpetually downwards through infinite space. Of course the Atomists had no true ideas of gravitation, nor did they understand that there is no absolute up and down. The large atoms are heavier than the smaller. The matter of which they are composed is always the same. Therefore, volume for volume, they weigh the same. Their weight is thus proportional to their size, and if one atom is twice as large as another, it will also be twice as heavy. Here the Atomists made another mistake, in supposing that heavier things fall in a vacuum more quickly than light things. They fall, as a matter of fact, with the same speed. But according to the Atomists, the heavier atoms, falling faster, strike against the lighter, and push them to one side and upwards. Through this general concussion of atoms a vortex is formed, in which like atoms come together with like. From the aggregation of atoms worlds are created. As space is infinite and the atoms go on falling eternally, there must have been innumerable worlds of which our world is only one. {91} When the aggregated atoms fall apart again, this particular world will cease to exist. But all this depends upon the theory that the atoms have weight. According to Professor Burnet, however, the weight of atoms is a later addition of the Epicureans. If that is so, it is very difficult to say how the early Atomists, Leucippus and Democritus, explained the original motion. What was their moving force, if it was not weight? If the atoms have no weight, their original movement cannot have been a fall. "It is safest to say," says Professor Burnet, "that it is simply a confused motion this way and that." [Footnote 7] Probably this is a very safe thing to say, because it means nothing in particular. Motion itself cannot be confused. It is only our ideas of motion which can be confused. If this theory is correct, then, we can only say that the Atomists had no definite solution of the problem of the origin of motion and the character of the moving force. They apparently saw no necessity for explanation, which seems unlikely in view of the fact that Empedocles had already seen the necessity of solving the problem, and given a definite, if unsatisfactory, solution, in his theory of Love and Hate. This remark would apply to Democritus, if not to Leucippus.

How is the movement of atoms created? Since all changes are caused by the separation and coming together of atoms, a driving force is needed. What is this driving force? This depends on whether atoms have weight. If we assume they do, then the origin of the universe and the movement of atoms become clearer. In the Epicurean system, the initial movement of atoms is due to their weight, which causes them to fall continuously downward through infinite space. Of course, the Atomists didn't have a real understanding of gravity, nor did they realize that there is no absolute up or down. Larger atoms are heavier than smaller ones. The matter they are made of is always the same. Therefore, volume for volume, they weigh the same. Their weight is proportional to their size, so if one atom is twice as large as another, it will also be twice as heavy. Here the Atomists made another mistake by thinking that heavier things fall faster in a vacuum than lighter things. They actually fall at the same speed. But according to the Atomists, the heavier atoms fall faster, colliding with the lighter ones, pushing them aside and upwards. Through this general collision of atoms, a vortex is formed where similar atoms come together. From this aggregation of atoms, worlds are created. Since space is infinite and the atoms keep falling eternally, there must have been countless worlds, of which our world is just one. {91} When the aggregated atoms disperse, this particular world will cease to exist. But all this relies on the theory that atoms have weight. According to Professor Burnet, however, the concept of atom weight is a later addition by the Epicureans. If that's true, it’s hard to say how the early Atomists, Leucippus and Democritus, explained the original motion. What was their driving force if it wasn't weight? If atoms have no weight, their initial movement couldn't have been a fall. "It is safest to say," says Professor Burnet, "that it is simply a confused motion this way and that." [Footnote 7] This is probably a very safe thing to say because it doesn’t mean much of anything. Motion itself can't be confused; only our understanding of motion can be. If this theory is right, we can only conclude that the Atomists did not have a clear solution to the problem of how motion began and what the driving force was. They seemingly didn’t see the need for an explanation, which seems unlikely given that Empedocles had already recognized this necessity and provided a definite, if unsatisfactory, explanation with his theory of Love and Hate. This observation would apply to Democritus, if not to Leucippus.

[Footnote 7: Early Greek Philosophy, chap. ix. § 179.]

[Footnote 7: Early Greek Philosophy, chap. ix. § 179.]

The Atomists also spoke of all movement being under the force of "necessity." Anaxagoras was at this time teaching that all motion of things is produced by a world-intelligence, or reason. Democritus expressly opposes to this the doctrine of necessity. There is no reason or intelligence in the world. On the contrary, all phenomena and all becoming are completely determined by blind mechanical causes. In this connection there arises {92} among the Atomists a polemic against the popular gods and the popular religion. Belief in gods Democritus explains as being due to fear of great terrestrial and astronomical phenomena, such as volcanoes, earthquakes, comets, and meteors. But somewhat inconsistently with this, Democritus believed that the air is inhabited by beings resembling men, but larger and of longer life, and explained belief in the gods as being due to projection from these of images of themselves composed of atoms which impinge upon human senses, and produce the ideas of gods.

The Atomists also talked about all movement being driven by "necessity." At this time, Anaxagoras was teaching that all motion in the world comes from a universal intelligence or reason. Democritus directly disagrees with this idea of necessity. He argues that there is no reason or intelligence in the world. Instead, all phenomena and changes are entirely dictated by random mechanical causes. In this context, a debate arises among the Atomists against the common gods and popular religion. Democritus explains belief in gods as stemming from fear of significant earthly and astronomical events, like volcanoes, earthquakes, comets, and meteors. However, somewhat inconsistently, Democritus believed that the air is filled with beings that look like humans, but are larger and live longer, and he explained the belief in gods as a projection from these beings, creating images of themselves made of atoms that affect human senses, leading to the concept of gods.

Different kinds of matter must be explained, in any atomic theory, by the shape, size, and position of the atoms of which they are composed. Thus the Atomists taught that fire is composed of smooth round atoms. The soul is also composed of smooth round atoms, and is an exceptionally pure and refined fire. At death the soul atoms are scattered, and hence there is, of course, no question of a future life. Democritus also put forward a theory of perception, according to which objects project into space images of themselves composed of atoms. These images strike against the senses. Like atoms are perceived by like. Thought is true when the soul is equable in temperature. The sensible qualities of things, such as smell, taste, colour, do not exist in the things themselves, but merely express the manner in which they affect our senses, and are therefore relative to us. A number of the ethical maxims of Democritus have come down to us. But they are not based in any way upon the Atomic theory, and cannot be deduced from it. Hence they have no scientific foundation but are merely detached sayings, epitomizing the experience {93} and worldly wisdom of Democritus. That one should enjoy oneself as much and vex oneself as little as possible seems to have been his principal idea. This, however, is not to be interpreted in any low, degraded, or sensual way. On the contrary, Democritus says that the happiness of man does not depend on material possessions, but upon the state of the soul. He praises equanimity and cheerfulness, and these are best attained, he thinks, by moderation and simplicity.

Different types of matter must be explained, in any atomic theory, by the shape, size, and position of the atoms they consist of. The Atomists taught that fire is made up of smooth round atoms. The soul is also made of smooth round atoms and is an exceptionally pure and refined form of fire. At death, the soul atoms are scattered, so there’s no question of an afterlife. Democritus also proposed a theory of perception, claiming that objects send out images of themselves made of atoms into space. These images interact with the senses. Similar atoms are recognized by similar senses. Thought is accurate when the soul is balanced in temperature. The sensory qualities of things, like smell, taste, and color, don’t exist in the objects themselves; they only express how those objects affect our senses and are therefore relative to us. Several ethical principles of Democritus have come down to us. However, they aren’t based on the Atomic theory and can’t be derived from it. Therefore, they lack a scientific foundation and are merely isolated sayings that summarize the experiences and worldly wisdom of Democritus. His main idea seems to be that one should enjoy life as much as possible and worry as little as possible. This shouldn’t be interpreted in a low, degrading, or sensual way. On the contrary, Democritus argues that human happiness doesn’t depend on material possessions but on the state of the soul. He values calmness and happiness, which he believes can be best achieved through moderation and simplicity.


ANAXAGORAS

ANAXAGORAS

Anaxagoras was born at Clazomenae in Asia Minor about 500 B.C. He was a man of noble family, and possessed considerable property. He neglected his property in the search for knowledge and in the pursuit of science and philosophy. Leaving his home at Clazomenae, he settled down in Athens. We have not heard so far anything of Athens in the history of Greek Philosophy. It was Anaxagoras who transplanted philosophy to Athens, which from his time forward became the chief centre of Greek thought. At Athens, Anaxagoras came into contact with all the famous men of the time. He was an intimate friend of Pericles, the statesman, and of Euripides, the poet. But his friendship with Pericles cost him dear. There was a strong political faction opposed to Pericles. So far as we know Anaxagoras never meddled in politics, but he was a friend of the statesman Pericles, and that was quite enough. The enemies of Pericles determined to teach Anaxagoras a lesson, and a charge of atheism and blasphemy was accordingly brought against him. The particulars of the charge were that Anaxagoras said that the sun was a red-hot stone, and that the moon was made of earth. This was quite true, as that is exactly what Anaxagoras did say of the sun and the moon. But the Greeks {95} regarded the heavenly bodies as gods; even Plato and Aristotle thought that the stars were divine beings. To call the sun a red-hot stone, and to say that the moon was made of earth, was therefore blasphemy according to Greek ideas. Anaxagoras was charged, tried, and condemned. The details of the trial, and of what followed, are not known with accuracy. But it appears that Anaxagoras escaped, probably with the help of Pericles, and from Athens went back to his native country in Asia Minor. He settled at Lampsacus, and died there at the age of 72. He was the author of a treatise in which he wrote down his philosophical ideas. This treatise was well-known at the time of Socrates, but only fragments now remain.

Anaxagoras was born in Clazomenae, Asia Minor, around 500 B.C. He came from a noble family and owned significant property. However, he neglected his wealth in his quest for knowledge and his pursuit of science and philosophy. After leaving Clazomenae, he moved to Athens. Until then, Athens hadn't played a notable role in the history of Greek philosophy. Anaxagoras was the one who introduced philosophy to Athens, which then became the main hub of Greek thought. In Athens, Anaxagoras interacted with all the famous figures of the time. He was close friends with the statesman Pericles and the poet Euripides. However, his friendship with Pericles came at a cost. There was a strong political faction that opposed Pericles. As far as we know, Anaxagoras never got involved in politics, but being friends with Pericles was enough. Pericles' enemies decided to teach Anaxagoras a lesson, resulting in charges of atheism and blasphemy against him. The accusation was that Anaxagoras claimed the sun was a red-hot stone and the moon was made of earth. This was indeed true, as that was exactly what Anaxagoras said about the sun and the moon. However, the Greeks {95} viewed heavenly bodies as gods; even Plato and Aristotle believed that the stars were divine beings. Thus, calling the sun a red-hot stone and claiming the moon was made of earth was considered blasphemous by Greek standards. Anaxagoras was charged, put on trial, and convicted. The specifics of the trial and what happened afterward are not accurately known. It seems that Anaxagoras managed to escape, likely with the help of Pericles, and returned to his homeland in Asia Minor. He settled in Lampsacus and died there at the age of 72. He wrote a treatise where he outlined his philosophical ideas. This treatise was well-known during the time of Socrates, but only fragments of it remain today.

The foundation of the philosophy of Anaxagoras is the same as that of Empedocles and the Atomists. He denied any absolute becoming in the strict sense of the passing of being into not-being and not-being into being. Matter is uncreated and indestructible, and all becoming must be accounted for by the mixing and unmixing of its component parts. This principle Anaxagoras himself expressed with great clearness, in a fragment of his treatise which has come down to us. "The Greeks," he says, "erroneously assume origination and destruction, for nothing originates and nothing is destroyed. All is only mixed and unmixed out of pre-existent things, and it were more correct to call the one process composition and the other process decomposition."

The foundation of Anaxagoras's philosophy is similar to that of Empedocles and the Atomists. He rejected the idea of absolute change in the strict sense of something becoming something else or disappearing altogether. Matter is neither created nor destroyed; all changes can be explained by the mixing and unmixing of its components. Anaxagoras expressed this principle clearly in a fragment of his work that has survived. "The Greeks," he says, "wrongly believe in origin and destruction, for nothing comes into being and nothing is destroyed. Everything is just mixed and unmixed from pre-existing things, and it would be more accurate to refer to one process as composition and the other as decomposition."

The Atomists had assumed the ultimate constituents of things to be atoms composed of the same kind of matter. Empedocles had believed in four ultimate and underived kinds of matter. With neither of these does Anaxagoras agree. For him, all the different kinds of {96} matter are equally ultimate and underived, that is to say, such things as gold, bone, hair, earth, water, wood, etc., are ultimate kinds of matter, which do not arise from anything else, and do not pass over into one another. He also disagrees with the conception of the Atomists that if matter is divided far enough, ultimate and indivisible particles will be reached. According to Anaxagoras matter is infinitely divisible. In the beginning all these kinds of matter were mixed together in a chaotic mass. The mass stretches infinitely throughout space. The different kinds of matter wholly intermingle and interpenetrate each other. The process of world-formation is brought about by the unmixing of the conglomeration of all kinds of matter, and the bringing together of like matter with like. Thus the gold particles separating out of the mass come together, and form gold; the wood particles come together and form wood, and so on. But as matter is infinitely divisible and the original mixing of the elements was complete, they were, so to speak, mixed to an infinite extent. Therefore the process of unmixing would take infinite time, is now going on, and will always go on. Even in the purest element there is still a certain admixture of particles of other kinds of matter. There is no such thing as pure gold. Gold is merely matter in which the gold particles predominate.

The Atomists believed that everything is made up of atoms that are all the same type of matter. Empedocles thought there were four basic types of matter. Anaxagoras disagrees with both ideas. To him, all different types of matter, like gold, bone, hair, earth, water, wood, etc., are equally basic and not derived from anything else. They don’t transform into each other. He also rejects the Atomists' idea that if you keep dividing matter, you'll eventually get to ultimate indivisible particles. Anaxagoras claims that matter can be divided infinitely. At the start, all these types of matter were mixed together in a chaotic mass that stretches infinitely in space. The different kinds of matter fully intermingle and penetrate each other. The formation of the world happens through the separation of this mixture into like matter. So, gold particles split from the mass and come together to form gold, wood particles join to create wood, and so on. But since matter can be divided infinitely and the initial mixing of elements was complete, they were mixed to an infinite degree. Because of this, the process of separating them will take infinite time; it's happening now and will keep happening. Even in the purest element, there's still some mix of particles from other kinds of matter. There’s no such thing as pure gold. Gold is simply matter where the gold particles are dominant.

As with Empedocles and the Atomists, a moving force is required to explain the world-process of unmixing. What, in the philosophy of Anaxagoras, is this force? Now up to the present point the philosophy of Anaxagoras does not rise above the previous philosophies of Empedocles and the Atomists. On the contrary, in clearness {97} and logical consistency, it falls considerably below the teaching of the latter. But it is just here, on the question of the moving force, that Anaxagoras becomes for the first time wholly original, and introduces a principle peculiar to himself, a principle, moreover, which is entirely new in philosophy. Empedocles had taken as his moving forces, Love and Hate, mythical and fanciful on the one hand, and yet purely physical on the other. The forces of the Atomists were also completely material. But Anaxagoras conceives the moving force as wholly non-physical and incorporeal. It is called Nous, that is, mind or intelligence. It is intelligence which produces the movement in things which brings about the formation of the world. What was it, now, which led Anaxagoras to the doctrine of a world-governing intelligence? It seems that he was struck with the apparent design, order, beauty and harmony of the universe. These things, he thought, could not be accounted for by blind forces. The world is apparently a rationally governed world. It moves towards definite ends. Nature shows plentiful examples of the adaptation of means to ends. There appears to be plan and purpose in the world. The Atomists had assumed nothing but matter and physical force. How can design, order, harmony and beauty be brought about by blind forces acting upon chaotic matter? Blind forces acting upon a chaos would produce motion and change. But the change would be meaningless and purposeless. They could not produce a rationally ordered cosmos. One chaos would succeed another chaos ad infinitum. That alone which can produce law and order is intelligence. There must therefore be a world-controlling Nous.

Like Empedocles and the Atomists, a driving force is needed to explain the process of separation in the world. What, then, is this force in Anaxagoras' philosophy? Up to this point, Anaxagoras' philosophy doesn't surpass the earlier ideas of Empedocles and the Atomists. In fact, in terms of clarity and logical consistency, it falls short of the latter's teachings. However, it is precisely in the discussion of the moving force where Anaxagoras becomes truly original, introducing a principle unique to him that is completely new in philosophy. Empedocles identified Love and Hate as his moving forces, which were both mythical and fanciful on one hand, yet purely physical on the other. The Atomists also viewed their forces as entirely material. In contrast, Anaxagoras envisions the moving force as completely non-physical and incorporeal. He calls it Nous, which means mind or intelligence. It is this intelligence that drives movement in things and leads to the formation of the world. What led Anaxagoras to develop the idea of a world-governing intelligence? It seems he was impressed by the evident design, order, beauty, and harmony of the universe. He believed these aspects could not simply be explained by blind forces. The world appears to be ordered rationally. It moves toward specific goals. Nature provides numerous examples of means being well-suited to ends. There seems to be a plan and purpose in the world. The Atomists considered nothing but matter and physical force. How can design, order, harmony, and beauty arise from blind forces acting on chaotic matter? Blind forces acting on chaos would result in motion and change, but that change would be meaningless and without purpose. They couldn't create a rationally ordered cosmos. One chaos would simply follow another endlessly. Only intelligence can produce law and order. Thus, there must be a controlling Nous.

What is the character of the Nous, according to Anaxagoras? Is it, in the first place, really conceived as purely non-material and incorporeal? Aristotle, who was in a position to know more of the matter than any modern scholar, clearly implies in his criticism that the Nous of Anaxagoras is an incorporeal principle, and he has been followed in this by the majority of the best modern writers, such as Zeller and Erdmann. But the opposite view has been maintained, by Grote, for example, and more recently by Professor Burnet, who thinks that Anaxagoras conceived the Nous as a material and physical force. [Footnote 8] As the matter is of fundamental importance, I will mention the chief arguments upon which Professor Burnet rests his case. In the first place Anaxagoras described the Nous as the "thinnest and purest of all things." He also said that it was "unmixed," that it had in it no mixture of anything besides itself. Professor Burnet argues that such words as "thin" and "unmixed" would be meaningless in connection with an incorporeal principle. Only material things can properly be described as thin, pure, and unmixed. Secondly, Professor Burnet thinks that it is quite certain that the Nous occupies space, for Anaxagoras speaks of greater and smaller portions of it. Greater and smaller are spatial relations. Hence the Nous occupies space, and that which occupies space is material. But surely these are very inconclusive arguments. In the first place as regards the use of the words "thin" and "unmixed." It is true that these terms express primarily physical qualities. But, as I pointed out in {99} the first chapter, almost all words by which we seek to express incorporeal ideas have originally a physical signification. And if Anaxagoras is to be called a materialist because he described the Nous as thin, then we must also plead guilty to materialism if we say that the thought of Plato is "luminous," or that the mind of Aristotle is "clear." The fact is that all philosophy labours under the difficulty of having to express non-sensuous thought in language which has been evolved for the purpose of expressing sensuous ideas. There is no philosophy in the world, even up to the present day, in which expressions could not be found in plenty which are based upon the use of physical analogies to express entirely non-physical ideas. Then as regards the Nous occupying space, it is not true that greater and smaller are necessarily spatial relations. They are also qualitative relations of degree. I say that the mind of Plato is greater than the mind of Callias. Am I to be called a materialist? Am I to be supposed to mean that Plato's mind occupies more space than that of Callias? And it is certainly in this way that Anaxagoras uses the terms. "All Nous," he says, "is alike, both the greater and the smaller." He means thereby that the world-forming mind (the greater) is identical in character with the mind of man (the smaller). For Anaxagoras it is the one Nous which animates all living beings, men, animals, and even plants. These different orders of beings are animated by the same Nous but in different degrees, that of man being the greatest. But this does not mean that the Nous in man occupies more space than the Nous in a plant. But even if Anaxagoras did conceive the Nous as spatial, it does not follow that he {100} regarded it as material. The doctrine of the non-spatiality of mind is a modern doctrine, never fully developed till the time of Descartes. And to say that Anaxagoras did not realize that mind is non-spatial is merely to say that he lived before the time of Descartes. No doubt it would follow from this that the incorporeality of mind is vaguely and indistinctly conceived by Anaxagoras, that the antithesis between matter and mind is not so sharply drawn by him as it is by us. But still the antithesis is conceived, and therefore it is correct to say that the Nous of Anaxagoras is an incorporeal principle. The whole point of this introduction of the Nous into the philosophy of Anaxagoras is because he could not explain the design and order of the universe on a purely physical basis.

What is the nature of the Nous according to Anaxagoras? Is it, first of all, really considered as completely non-material and incorporeal? Aristotle, who knew more about this than any modern scholar, clearly suggests in his critique that Anaxagoras's Nous is an incorporeal principle, and many top modern writers, like Zeller and Erdmann, agree with him. However, the opposite view has been presented by Grote, for instance, and more recently by Professor Burnet, who believes that Anaxagoras saw the Nous as a material and physical force. [Footnote 8] Since this issue is fundamental, I will outline the main arguments that Professor Burnet uses to support his claim. First, Anaxagoras described the Nous as the "thinnest and purest of all things." He also stated that it was "unmixed," meaning it contained no mixture of anything other than itself. Professor Burnet argues that terms like "thin" and "unmixed" would be meaningless if applied to an incorporeal principle. Only material things can be accurately described as thin, pure, and unmixed. Secondly, Professor Burnet believes it is quite certain that the Nous occupies space, since Anaxagoras refers to larger and smaller portions of it. Larger and smaller indicate spatial relationships. Thus, the Nous occupies space, and anything that occupies space is material. However, these arguments are quite unconvincing. First of all, regarding the use of "thin" and "unmixed," while these words primarily express physical qualities, as I pointed out in {99} the first chapter, almost all terms we use to convey incorporeal ideas originally have a physical meaning. If Anaxagoras is labeled a materialist because he described the Nous as thin, then we must also be accused of materialism if we say that Plato’s thought is "luminous," or that Aristotle’s mind is "clear." The truth is that all philosophy struggles with the challenge of expressing non-sensory thoughts using language developed for sensory ideas. There is no philosophy, even today, without many expressions based on physical analogies to convey entirely non-physical concepts. As far as the Nous occupying space is concerned, it's not true that greater and smaller are necessarily spatial relationships. They can also signify qualitative degrees. For example, I might say that Plato's mind is greater than Callias's. Should I be considered a materialist? Am I suggesting that Plato's mind takes up more space than Callias's? Certainly, this is how Anaxagoras uses the terms. "All Nous," he states, "is alike, both the greater and the smaller." He means that the world-forming mind (the greater) is identical in nature to the mind of man (the smaller). For Anaxagoras, it is one Nous that animates all living beings, including humans, animals, and even plants. These different categories of beings are animated by the same Nous but at different levels, with humans having the greatest degree. However, this doesn’t mean that the Nous in humans occupies more space than the Nous in a plant. Even if Anaxagoras thought of the Nous as spatial, it doesn’t imply that he regarded it as material. The idea that mind is non-spatial is a modern concept, not fully developed until Descartes’s time. Saying Anaxagoras didn’t realize that mind is non-spatial simply points out that he lived before Descartes. It’s likely that he had a vague and indistinct understanding of the incorporeality of mind, and the distinction between matter and mind isn’t as clearly defined for him as it is for us. But he still conceives of this distinction, so it's accurate to say that Anaxagoras's Nous is an incorporeal principle. The main point of introducing the Nous into Anaxagoras's philosophy is that he couldn’t explain the design and order of the universe solely through a physical framework.

[Footnote 8: Early Greek Philosophy, chap. vi. § 132.]

[Footnote 8: Early Greek Philosophy, chap. vi. § 132.]

The next characteristic of Nous is that it is to be thought of as essentially the ground of motion. It is because he cannot in any other way explain purposive motion that Anaxagoras introduces mind into his otherwise materialistic system. Mind plays the part of the moving force which explains the world-process of unmixing. As the ground of motion, the Nous is itself unmoved; for if there were any motion in it we should have to seek for the ground of this motion in something else outside it. That which is the cause of all motion, cannot itself be moved. Next, the Nous is absolutely pure and unmixed with anything else. It exists apart, by itself, wholly in itself, and for itself. In contrast to matter, it is uncompounded and simple. It is this which gives it omnipotence, complete power over everything, because there is no mixture of matter in it to limit it, to clog and hinder its activities. We moderns are {101} inclined to ask the question whether the Nous is personal. Is it, for example, a personal being like the God of the Christians? This is a question which it is almost impossible to answer. Anaxagoras certainly never considered it. According to Zeller, the Greeks had an imperfect and undeveloped conception of personality. Even in Plato we find the same difficulty. The antithesis between God as a personal and as an impersonal being, is a wholly modern idea. No Greek ever discussed it.

The next characteristic of Nous is that it should be seen as essentially the foundation of motion. Anaxagoras introduces mind into his otherwise materialistic system because he can't explain purposeful motion in any other way. Mind serves as the moving force that explains the world's process of unmixing. As the foundation of motion, the Nous is itself unmoved; if there were any motion in it, we would have to find the cause of that motion in something else outside of it. What causes all motion cannot itself be moved. Additionally, the Nous is completely pure and not mixed with anything else. It exists alone, entirely in itself, and for itself. Unlike matter, it is uncompounded and simple. This purity gives it omnipotence and complete control over everything, because there is no mixture of matter within it that would limit or hinder its activities. We modern thinkers are {101} inclined to ask whether the Nous is personal. Is it, for example, a personal being like the God of the Christians? This is a question that is almost impossible to answer. Anaxagoras certainly never considered it. According to Zeller, the Greeks had an incomplete and underdeveloped idea of personality. Even in Plato, we see the same challenge. The contrast between God as a personal being and as an impersonal one is a completely modern concept. No Greek ever debated it.

To come now to the question of the activity of the Nous and its function in the philosophy of Anaxagoras, we must note that it is essentially a world-forming, and not a world-creating, intelligence. The Nous and matter exist side by side from eternity. It does not create matter, but only arranges it. "All things were together," says Anaxagoras, "infinitely numerous, infinitely little; then came the Nous and set them in order." In this Anaxagoras showed a sound logical sense. He based his idea of the existence of Nous upon the design which exhibits itself in the world. In modern times the existence of design in the world has been made the foundation of an argument for the existence of God, which is known as the teleological argument. The word teleology means the view of things as adapting means towards purposive ends. To see intelligent design in the universe is to view the universe teleologically. And the teleological argument for the existence of God asserts that, as there is evidence of purpose in nature, this must be due to an intelligent cause. But, as a matter of fact, taken by itself, teleology cannot possibly be made the basis of an argument for the existence of a world-creating intelligence, but only for the existence of a world-designing {102} intelligence. If you find in the desert the ruins of ancient cities and temples, you are entitled to conclude therefrom, that there existed a mind which designed these cities and buildings, and which arranged matter in that purposive way, but you are not entitled to conclude that the mind which designed the cities also created the matter out of which they were made. Anaxagoras was, therefore, in that sense quite right. Teleology is not evidence of a world-creating mind, and if we are to prove that, we must have recourse to other lines of reasoning.

To address the question of the Nous's activity and its role in Anaxagoras's philosophy, we should note that it is fundamentally an intelligence that shapes the world, not one that creates it. The Nous and matter have existed together for all time. It does not create matter; it simply arranges it. "All things were together," Anaxagoras says, "infinitely numerous, infinitely small; then came the Nous and organized them." In this, Anaxagoras displayed sound reasoning. He based his idea of the Nous's existence on the design evident in the world. In modern times, the existence of design in the universe has been the basis for an argument for God's existence known as the teleological argument. Teleology refers to seeing things as means toward purposeful ends. To recognize intelligent design in the universe is to view the universe teleologically. The teleological argument claims that because there is evidence of purpose in nature, it must be due to an intelligent cause. However, taken on its own, teleology cannot support a claim for a world-creating intelligence, only for a world-designing intelligence. If you discover the ruins of ancient cities and temples in the desert, you can conclude that there was a mind that designed these cities and arranged matter in that purposeful way, but you cannot conclude that this mind also created the matter from which they were made. Anaxagoras was, therefore, right in that respect. Teleology does not prove a world-creating mind, and if we want to establish that, we need to look to other lines of reasoning.

In the beginning, then, there was a chaotic mixture of different kinds of matter. The Nous produced a vortex at one point in the middle of this mass. This vortex spread itself outwards in the mass of matter, like rings caused by the fall of a stone in water. It goes on for ever and continually draws more and more matter out of the infinite mass into itself. The movement, therefore, is never-ending. It causes like kinds of matter to come together with like, gold to gold, wood to wood, water to water, and so on. It is to be noted, therefore, that the action of the Nous is apparently confined to the first movement. It acts only at the one central point, and every subsequent movement is caused by the vortex itself, which draws in more and more of the surrounding matter into itself. First are separated out the warm, dry, and light particles, and these form the aether or upper air. Next come the cold, moist, dark, and dense particles which form the lower air. Rotation takes the latter towards the centre, and out of this the earth is formed. The earth, as with Anaximenes, is a flat disc, borne upon the air. The heavenly bodies consist of {103} masses of stone which have been torn from the earth by the force of its rotation, and being projected outwards become incandescent through the rapidity of their movement. The moon is made of earth and reflects the light of the sun. Anaxagoras was thus the first to give the true cause of the moon's light. He was also the first to discover the true theory of eclipses, since he taught that the solar eclipse is due to the intervention of the moon between the sun and the earth, and that lunar eclipses arise from the shadow of the earth falling upon the moon. He believed that there are other worlds besides our own with their own suns and moons. These worlds are inhabited. The sun, according to Anaxagoras, is many times as large as the Peloponnese. The origin of life upon the earth is accounted for by germs which existed in the atmosphere, and which were brought down into the terrestrial slime by rain water, and there fructified. Anaxagoras's theory of perception is the opposite of the theories of Empedocles and the Atomists. Perception takes place by unlike matter meeting unlike.

In the beginning, there was a chaotic mix of different types of matter. The Nous created a vortex at one central point within this mass. This vortex spread outward like ripples from a stone dropped in water. It continues indefinitely, pulling in more and more matter from the infinite mass around it. The movement is therefore never-ending. It causes similar kinds of matter to group together—gold with gold, wood with wood, water with water, and so on. It's important to note that the action of the Nous seems to be limited to this initial movement. It only acts at that one central point, and all subsequent movements are caused by the vortex itself, which continues to draw in more of the surrounding matter. First, the warm, dry, and light particles are separated out, forming the aether or upper air. Next come the cold, moist, dark, and dense particles that create the lower air. Rotation pulls the latter towards the center, resulting in the formation of the earth. The earth, like Anaximenes described, is a flat disc resting on air. The heavenly bodies are made of {103} stone masses that were ripped from the earth by the force of its rotation, and as they were thrown outwards, they became incandescent due to their rapid movement. The moon is made of earth and reflects the sun's light. Anaxagoras was the first to explain the true reason for the moon's light. He also discovered the correct theory of eclipses, explaining that a solar eclipse happens when the moon passes between the sun and the earth, and lunar eclipses occur when the earth's shadow falls on the moon. He believed there are other worlds besides ours, each with its own suns and moons. These worlds are inhabited. According to Anaxagoras, the sun is many times larger than the Peloponnese. The origin of life on earth comes from germs that existed in the atmosphere, which were brought down into the muddy ground by rain, where they flourished. Anaxagoras's theory of perception contrasts with those of Empedocles and the Atomists. Perception occurs when unlike matters interact with one another.

Anaxagoras owes his importance in the history of philosophy to the theory of the Nous. This was the first time that a definite distinction had been made between the corporeal and incorporeal. Anaxagoras is the last philosopher of the first period of Greek philosophy. In the second chapter, [Footnote 9] I observed that this first period is characterized by the fact that in it the Greek mind looks only outward upon the external world. It attempts to explain the operations of nature. It had not yet learned to look inward upon itself. But the transition to the introspective study of mind is found in the Nous of {104} Anaxagoras. Mind is now brought to the fore as a problem for philosophy. To find reason, intelligence, mind, in all things, in the State, in the individual, in external nature, this is the characteristic of the second period of Greek philosophy. To have formulated the antithesis between mind and matter is the most important work of Anaxagoras.

Anaxagoras is significant in the history of philosophy because of his theory of the Nous. This was the first time a clear distinction was made between the physical and the non-physical. Anaxagoras represents the last philosopher of the first phase of Greek philosophy. In the second chapter, [Footnote 9] I noted that this initial period is defined by the Greek mind's focus solely on the external world. It attempts to explain nature's actions. It had not yet learned to reflect inwardly on itself. However, the shift to examining the mind from within begins with Anaxagoras's Nous. The concept of mind now becomes a central issue for philosophy. The search for reason, intelligence, and mind in everything—from the State to individuals to the natural world—characterizes the second phase of Greek philosophy. The formulation of the distinction between mind and matter is Anaxagoras's most significant contribution.

[Footnote 9: Pages 23-4.]

[Footnote 9: __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.]

Secondly, it is to the credit of Anaxagoras that he was the first to introduce the idea of teleology into philosophy. The system of the Atomists formed the logical completion of the mechanical theory of the world. The theory of mechanism seeks to explain all things by causes. But, as we saw, causation can explain nothing. The mechanism of the world shows us by what means events are brought about, but it does not explain why they are brought about at all. That can only be explained by showing the reason for things, by exhibiting all process as a means towards rational ends. To look to the beginning (cause) of things for their explanation is the theory of mechanism. To look to their ends for explanation of them is teleology. Anaxagoras was the first to have dimly seen this. And for this reason Aristotle praises him, and, contrasting him with the mechanists, Leucippus and Democritus, says that he appears like "a sober man among vain babblers." The new principle which he thus introduced into philosophy was developed, and formed the central idea of Plato and Aristotle. To have realized the twin antitheses of matter and mind, of mechanism and teleology, is the glory of Anaxagoras.

Secondly, it's important to recognize that Anaxagoras was the first to bring the concept of teleology into philosophy. The Atomists' system represented the logical conclusion of the mechanical view of the world. The mechanical theory aims to explain everything through causes. However, as we've observed, causation cannot truly explain anything. The mechanics of the world reveal how events occur, but they don't clarify why they occur in the first place. That can only be understood by demonstrating the reasons for things, by showing that processes serve as means to rational ends. Looking at the beginning (cause) of things for their explanation is the mechanistic viewpoint. In contrast, seeking their ends for understanding is teleology. Anaxagoras was the first to vaguely grasp this concept. For this reason, Aristotle commends him, noting that he seems "like a sober man among vain babblers," especially when compared to mechanists like Leucippus and Democritus. The new principle he introduced into philosophy was further developed and became central to the ideas of Plato and Aristotle. Anaxagoras's achievement in recognizing the dual oppositions of matter and mind, and mechanism and teleology, is a significant legacy.

But it is just here, in the development of these two ideas, that the defects of his system make their appearance. Firstly, he so separated matter and mind that {105} his philosophy ends in sheer dualism. He assumes the Nous and matter as existing from the beginning, side by side, as equally ultimate and underived principles. A monistic materialism would have derived the Nous from matter, and a monistic idealism would have derived matter from the Nous. But Anaxagoras does neither. Each is left, in his theory, an inexplicable ultimate mystery. His philosophy is, therefore, an irreconcilable dualism.

But it's right here, in the development of these two ideas, that the flaws in his system become clear. First, he separates mind and matter so much that his philosophy ends up as pure dualism. He treats the Nous and matter as existing from the start, side by side, as equally fundamental and undebatable principles. A monistic materialism would have derived the Nous from matter, and a monistic idealism would have derived matter from the Nous. But Anaxagoras does neither. In his theory, each remains an inexplicable ultimate mystery. Therefore, his philosophy is an unresolvable dualism.

Secondly, his teleology turns out in the end to be only a new theory of mechanism. The only reason which induces him to introduce the Nous into the world, is because he cannot otherwise explain the origin of movement. It is only the first movement of things, the formation of the vortex, which he explains by mind. All subsequent process is explained by the action of the vortex itself, which draws the surrounding matter into itself. The Nous is thus nothing but another piece of mechanism to account for the first impulse to motion. He regards the Nous simply as a first cause, and thus the characteristic of all mechanism, to look back to first causes, to the beginning, rather than to the end of things for their explanation, appears here. Aristotle, as usual, puts the matter in a nutshell. "Anaxagoras," he says, "uses mind as a deus ex machina to account for the formation of the world, and whenever he is at a loss to explain why anything necessarily is, he drags it in by force. But in other cases he assigns as a cause for things anything else in preference to mind." [Footnote 10]

Secondly, his teleology ultimately turns out to be just another theory of mechanism. The only reason he brings the Nous into the picture is that he can't explain the origin of movement any other way. He only explains the initial movement of things—the formation of the vortex—through the mind. All subsequent processes are explained by the action of the vortex itself, which pulls in the surrounding matter. The Nous, therefore, is just another mechanical concept to explain the first push toward motion. He views the Nous merely as a first cause, demonstrating a typical characteristic of mechanism: looking to first causes and beginnings for explanation rather than to the ends of things. Aristotle, as usual, sums it up perfectly. "Anaxagoras," he says, "uses mind as a deus ex machina to explain the formation of the world, and whenever he struggles to clarify why something is necessary, he forcefully brings it in. But in other situations, he prefers to attribute causes to anything other than mind." [Footnote 10]

[Footnote 10; Aristotle, Metaphysics, book i, chap. iv.]

[Footnote 10; Aristotle, Metaphysics, book i, chap. iv.]


THE SOPHISTS

THE SOPHISTS

The first period of Greek philosophy closes with Anaxagoras. His doctrine of the world-forming intelligence introduced a new principle into philosophy, the principle of the antithesis between corporeal matter and incorporeal mind, and therefore, by implication, the antithesis between nature and man. And if the first period of philosophy has for its problem the origin of the world, and the explanation of the being and becoming of nature, the second period of philosophy opens, in the Sophists, with the problem of the position of man in the universe. The teaching of the earlier philosophers was exclusively cosmological, that of the Sophists exclusively humanistic. Later in this second period, these two modes of thought come together and fructify one another. The problem of the mind and the problem of nature are subordinated as factors of the great, universal, all-embracing, world-systems of Plato and Aristotle.

The first period of Greek philosophy ends with Anaxagoras. His idea of a world-forming intelligence brought a new concept into philosophy, highlighting the contrast between physical matter and non-physical mind, and thus, by extension, the contrast between nature and humanity. While the first period of philosophy focused on the origin of the world and explained the existence and change of nature, the second period, represented by the Sophists, shifts to the question of humanity's place in the universe. The earlier philosophers were mainly concerned with cosmology, whereas the Sophists focused entirely on humanism. Later in this second period, these two approaches start to merge and enrich each other. The issues of mind and nature become secondary to the comprehensive, universal systems of thought developed by Plato and Aristotle.

It is not possible to understand the activities and teaching of the Sophists without some knowledge of the religious, political, and social conditions of the time. After long struggles between the people and the nobles, democracy had almost everywhere triumphed. But in Greece democracy did not mean what we now mean by {107} that word. It did not mean representative institutions, government by the people through their elected deputies. Ancient Greece was never a single nation under a single government. Every city, almost every hamlet, was an independent State, governed only by its own laws. Some of these States were so small that they comprised merely a handful of citizens. All were so small that all the citizens could meet together in one place, and themselves in person enact the laws and transact public business. There was no necessity for representation. Consequently in Greece every citizen was himself a politician and a legislator. In these circumstances, partisan feeling ran to extravagant lengths. Men forgot the interests of the State in the interests of party, and this ended in men forgetting the interests of their party in their own interests. Greed, ambition, grabbing, selfishness, unrestricted egotism, unbridled avarice, became the dominant notes of the political life of the time.

It’s impossible to understand the activities and teachings of the Sophists without knowing about the religious, political, and social conditions of that time. After long struggles between the people and the nobles, democracy had nearly triumphed everywhere. But in Greece, democracy didn’t mean what we think of when we hear that word today. It didn’t mean having representative institutions or a government run by the people through their elected officials. Ancient Greece was never a unified nation under one government. Every city, almost every village, was an independent state, governed only by its own laws. Some of these states were so small that they consisted of just a handful of citizens. All were so small that all citizens could gather in one place to create laws and conduct public business themselves. There was no need for representation. As a result, every citizen was also a politician and a legislator. In this environment, partisan feelings became extremely intense. People prioritized party interests over the interests of the state, and this eventually led them to forget about party interests in favor of their own. Greed, ambition, self-serving behavior, unrestricted egotism, and unbridled avarice dominated the political life of that time.

Hand in hand with the rise of democracy went the decay of religion. Belief in the gods was almost everywhere discredited. This was partly due to the moral worthlessness of the Greek religion itself. Any action, however scandalous or disgraceful, could be justified by the examples of the gods themselves as related by the poets and mythologers of Greece. But, in greater measure, the collapse of religion was due to that advance of science and philosophy which we have been considering in these lectures. The universal tendency of that philosophy was to find natural causes for what had hitherto been ascribed to the action of the divine powers, and this could not but have an undermining effect upon popular {108} belief. Nearly all the philosophers had been secretly, and many of them openly, antagonistic to the people's religion. The attack was begun by Xenophanes; Heracleitus carried it on; and lastly Democritus had attempted to explain belief in the gods as being caused by fear of gigantic terrestrial and astronomical phenomena. No educated man any longer believed in divination, auguries, and miracles. A wave of rationalism and scepticism passed over the Greek people. The age became one of negative, critical, and destructive thought. Democracy had undermined the old aristocratic institutions of the State, and science had undermined religious orthodoxy. With the downfall of these two pillars of things established, all else went too. All morality, all custom, all authority, all tradition, were criticised and rejected. What was regarded with awe and pious veneration by their fore-fathers the modern Greeks now looked upon as fit subjects for jest and mockery. Every restraint of custom, law, or morality, was resented as an unwarrantable restriction upon the natural impulses of man. What alone remained when these were thrust aside were the lust, avarice, and self-will of the individual.

As democracy rose, religion declined. Belief in the gods became widely discredited. This was partly because the Greek religion lacked moral value. Any action, no matter how scandalous, could be justified by the behavior of the gods as described by poets and storytellers. However, the main reason for the decline of religion was the advancement of science and philosophy we’ve been discussing in these lectures. The main trend of that philosophy was to find natural explanations for what had previously been attributed to divine powers, which inevitably weakened popular belief. Almost all philosophers were secretly, and many openly, opposed to the people's religion. The challenge began with Xenophanes; Heraclitus continued it, and finally Democritus tried to explain belief in gods as a product of fear of enormous earthly and astronomical events. No educated person believed in divination, omens, or miracles anymore. A wave of rationalism and skepticism swept over the Greek populace. This era became one of negative, critical, and destructive thinking. Democracy eroded the traditional aristocratic structures of the State, and science challenged religious beliefs. With the collapse of these two foundational pillars, everything else fell apart. Morality, customs, authority, and tradition were all scrutinized and dismissed. What had inspired awe and reverence in their ancestors, modern Greeks viewed as subjects for laughter and derision. Every constraint from custom, law, or morality was seen as an unjust limitation on natural human impulses. What remained when these were cast aside were just personal desires, greed, and self-interest.

The teaching of the Sophists was merely a translation into theoretical propositions of these practical tendencies of the period. The Sophists were the children of their time, and the interpreters of their age. Their philosophical teachings were simply the crystallization of the impulses which governed the life of the people into abstract principles and maxims.

The teachings of the Sophists were just a theoretical interpretation of the practical trends of their time. The Sophists were products of their era, acting as the voice of their generation. Their philosophical ideas were simply a way to refine the motivations driving people's lives into abstract concepts and principles.

Who and what were the Sophists? In the first place, they were not a school of philosophers. They are not to be compared, for example, with the Pythagoreans or {109} Eleatics. They had not, as a school has, any system of philosophy held in common by them all. None of them constructed systems of thought. They had in common only certain loose tendencies of thought. Nor were they, as we understand the members of a school to be, in any close personal association with one another. They were a professional class rather than a school, and as such they were scattered over Greece, and nourished among themselves the usual professional rivalries. They were professional teachers and educators. The rise of the Sophists was due to the growing demand for popular education, which was partly a genuine demand for light and knowledge, but was mostly a desire for such spurious learning as would lead to worldly, and especially political, success. The triumph of democracy had brought it about that political careers were now open to the masses who had hitherto been wholly shut out from them. Any man could rise to the highest positions in the State, if he were endowed with cleverness, ready speech, whereby to sway the passions of the mob, and a sufficient equipment in the way of education. Hence the demand arose for such an education as would enable the ordinary man to carve out a political career for himself. It was this demand which the Sophists undertook to satisfy. They wandered about Greece from place to place, they gave lectures, they took pupils, they entered into disputations. For these services they exacted large fees. They were the first in Greece to take fees for the teaching of wisdom. There was nothing disgraceful in this in itself, but it had never been customary. The wise men of Greece had never accepted any payment for their wisdom. Socrates, who never accepted any payment, {110} but gave his wisdom freely to all who sought it, somewhat proudly contrasted himself with the Sophists in this respect.

Who were the Sophists? First of all, they weren't a school of philosophers. They can't be compared to groups like the Pythagoreans or the Eleatics. They didn't share a common philosophical system like a formal school would. None of them developed structured philosophies. What they had in common were only some vague tendencies of thought. They also weren't closely connected personally like members of a typical school. They were more of a professional class than a school, scattered across Greece, and had the usual rivalries among professionals. They were teachers and educators by profession. The rise of the Sophists came from the increasing demand for popular education, which was partly a genuine need for knowledge but mostly a desire for superficial learning that would lead to worldly and especially political success. The success of democracy had opened up political careers to the masses who had previously been excluded. Any man could achieve high positions in the State if he had cleverness, eloquence to sway the crowd, and enough education. This created a demand for education that would help ordinary people build political careers for themselves. The Sophists aimed to meet this demand. They traveled around Greece, delivering lectures, teaching students, and engaging in debates. For their services, they charged high fees. They were the first in Greece to charge for teaching wisdom. There was nothing inherently wrong with this, but it was unusual. The wise men of Greece had never accepted payment for their insights. Socrates, who never charged for his teachings and freely shared his wisdom with anyone who asked, somewhat proudly contrasted himself with the Sophists in this regard.

The Sophists were not, technically speaking, philosophers. They did not specialise in the problems of philosophy. Their tendencies were purely practical. They taught any subject whatever for the teaching of which there was a popular demand. For example, Protagoras undertook to impart to his pupils the principles of success as a politician or as a private citizen. Gorgias taught rhetoric and politics, Prodicus grammar and etymology, Hippias history, mathematics and physics. In consequence of this practical tendency of the Sophists we hear of no attempts among them to solve the problem of the origin of nature, or the character of the ultimate reality. The Sophists have been described as teachers of virtue, and the description is correct, provided that the word virtue is understood in its Greek sense, which did not restrict it to morality alone. For the Greeks, it meant the capacity of a person successfully to perform his functions in the State. Thus the virtue of a mechanic is to understand machinery, the virtue of a physician to cure the sick, the virtue of a horse trainer the ability to train horses. The Sophists undertook to train men to virtue in this sense, to make them successful citizens and members of the State.

The Sophists weren't really philosophers in the true sense. They didn't focus on philosophical problems. Their approach was very practical. They taught just about any subject that was in demand. For instance, Protagoras aimed to teach his students how to succeed as politicians or private citizens. Gorgias taught rhetoric and politics, Prodicus focused on grammar and etymology, and Hippias covered history, math, and physics. Because of this practical focus, we don't hear about any efforts from the Sophists to tackle questions about the origins of nature or the nature of ultimate reality. They've been described as teachers of virtue, and this is accurate, as long as we understand "virtue" in its Greek context, which wasn't limited to just morality. For the Greeks, it referred to a person's ability to effectively perform their roles in society. So, the virtue of a mechanic is knowing how to work with machinery, the virtue of a doctor is being able to heal the sick, and the virtue of a horse trainer is having the skills to train horses. The Sophists aimed to train people in this sense of virtue, to help them become successful citizens and members of society.

But the most popular career for a Greek of ability at the time was the political, which offered the attraction of high positions in the State. And for this career what was above all necessary was eloquence, or if that were unattainable, at least ready speech, the ability to argue, to meet every point as it arose, if not with sound {111} reasoning, then with quick repartee. Hence the Sophists very largely concentrated their energies upon the teaching of rhetoric. In itself this was good. They were the first to direct attention to the science of rhetoric, of which they may be considered the founders. But their rhetoric also had its bad side, which indeed, soon became its only side. The aims of the young politicians whom they trained were, not to seek out the truth for its own sake, but merely to persuade the multitude of whatever they wished them to believe. Consequently the Sophists, like lawyers, not caring for the truth of the matter, undertook to provide a stock of arguments on any subject, or to prove any proposition. They boasted of their ability to make the worse appear the better reason, to prove that black is white. Some of them, like Gorgias, asserted that it was not necessary to have any knowledge of a subject to give satisfactory replies as regards it. And Gorgias ostentatiously undertook to answer any question on any subject instantly and without consideration. To attain these ends mere quibbling, and the scoring of verbal points, were employed. Hence our word "sophistry." The Sophists, in this way, endeavoured to entangle, entrap, and confuse their opponents, and even, if this were not possible, to beat them down by mere violence and noise. They sought also to dazzle by means of strange or flowery metaphors, by unusual figures of speech, by epigrams and paradoxes, and in general by being clever and smart, rather than earnest and truthful. When a man is young he is often dazzled by brilliance and cleverness, by paradox and epigram, but as he grows older he learns to discount these things and to care chiefly for the substance and {112} truth of what is said. And the Greeks were a young people. They loved clever sayings. And this it is which accounts for the toleration which they extended even to the most patent absurdities of the Sophists. The modern question whether a man has ceased beating his wife is not more childish than many of the rhetorical devices of the Sophists, and is indeed characteristic of the methods of the more extravagant among them.

But the most popular career for a talented Greek at the time was politics, which offered the appeal of high positions in the government. To succeed in this field, what was most important was eloquence, or at least the ability to speak well and argue effectively, responding to every point as it arose, whether with sound reasoning or quick replies. As a result, the Sophists largely focused their efforts on teaching rhetoric. This was beneficial in itself. They were the first to draw attention to the science of rhetoric, of which they could be seen as the founders. However, their rhetoric also had its downsides, which soon became its defining feature. The young politicians they trained aimed not to uncover the truth for its own sake, but simply to convince the masses of whatever they wanted them to believe. Consequently, the Sophists, like lawyers, disregarded the truth of the matter and set out to provide a stock of arguments on any topic or to support any claim. They prided themselves on their ability to make the weaker argument seem stronger, to prove that black is white. Some, like Gorgias, claimed it was unnecessary to have any knowledge of a topic to give satisfactory answers about it. Gorgias boldly claimed he could answer any question on any subject instantly and without thought. To achieve these goals, they relied on mere wordplay and scoring verbal points. Hence our term "sophistry." The Sophists aimed to ensnare, confuse, and entrap their opponents, and if that failed, to overwhelm them with sheer noise and aggression. They also sought to impress with elaborate or flowery metaphors, unusual figures of speech, epigrams, and paradoxes, generally being clever and witty rather than serious or genuine. When someone is young, they are often captivated by brilliance and cleverness, by paradox and epigram, but as they grow older, they learn to look past these and focus more on the substance and truth of what is being said. The Greeks were a youthful society. They enjoyed clever sayings. This helps explain the tolerance they extended even to the most obvious absurdities of the Sophists. The modern question of whether a man has stopped beating his wife is no more childish than many of the rhetorical tricks of the Sophists and is, in fact, typical of the methods of the more extreme among them.

The earliest known Sophist is Protagoras. He was born at Abdera, about 480 B.C. He wandered up and down Greece, and settled for some time at Athens. At Athens, however, he was charged with impiety and atheism. This was on account of a book written by him on the subject of the gods, which began with the words, "As for the gods, I am unable to say whether they exist or whether they do not exist." The book was publicly burnt, and Protagoras had to fly from Athens. He fled to Sicily, but was drowned on the way about the year 410 B.C.

The earliest known Sophist is Protagoras. He was born in Abdera around 480 B.C. He traveled all over Greece and spent some time in Athens. However, while in Athens, he was accused of impiety and atheism. This was because of a book he wrote about the gods, which started with the words, "As for the gods, I can’t say if they exist or don’t exist." The book was publicly burned, and Protagoras had to escape from Athens. He fled to Sicily but drowned on the way around 410 B.C.

Protagoras was the author of the famous saying, "Man is the measure of all things; of what is, that it is; of what is not, that it is not." Now this saying puts in a nutshell, so to speak, the whole teaching of Protagoras. And, indeed, it contains in germ the entire thought of the Sophists. It is well, therefore, that we should fully understand exactly what it means. The earlier Greek philosophers had made a clear distinction between sense and thought, between perception and reason, and had believed that the truth is to be found, not by the senses, but by reason. The Eleatics had been the first to emphasize this distinction. The ultimate reality of {113} things, they said, is pure Being, which is known only through reason; it is the senses which delude us with a show of becoming. Heracleitus had likewise affirmed that the truth, which was, for him, the law of becoming, is known by thought, and that it is the senses which delude us with a show of permanence. Even Democritus believed that true being, that is, material atoms, are so small that the senses cannot perceive them, and only reason is aware of their existence. Now the teaching of Protagoras really rests fundamentally upon the denying and confusing of this distinction. If we are to see this, we must first of all understand that reason is the universal, sensation the particular, element in man. In the first place, reason is communicable, sensation incommunicable. My sensations and feelings are personal to myself, and cannot be imparted to other people. For example, no one can communicate the sensation of redness to a colour-blind man, who has not already experienced it. But a thought, or rational idea, can be communicated to any rational being. Now suppose the question is whether the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal. We may approach the problem in two ways. We may appeal either to the senses or to reason. If we appeal to the senses, one man will come forward and say that to him the angles look equal. Another man will say that one angle looks bigger than the other, and so on. But if, like Euclid, we appeal to reason, then it can be proved that the two angles are equal, and there is no room left for mere personal impressions, because reason is a law universally valid and binding upon all men. My sensations are private and peculiar to myself. They bind no one but myself. My {114} impressions about the triangle are not a law to anyone except myself. But my reason I share with all other rational beings. It is not a law for me merely, but for all. It is one and the same reason in me and in other men. Reason, therefore, is the universal, sensation the particular, element in man. Now it is practically this distinction that Protagoras denied. Man, he said, is the measure of all things. By man he did not mean mankind at large. He meant the individual man. And by measure of all things he meant the standard of the truth of all things. Each individual man is the standard of what is true to himself. There is no truth except the sensations and impressions of each man. What seems true to me is true for me. What seems true to you is true for you.

Protagoras was the author of the well-known saying, "Man is the measure of all things; of what is, that it is; of what is not, that it is not." This saying encapsulates the essence of Protagoras's entire teaching and, in fact, it contains the core idea of the Sophists. It’s important that we understand exactly what it means. Earlier Greek philosophers distinguished clearly between sense and thought, between perception and reason, believing that truth is found not through the senses but through reason. The Eleatics were the first to emphasize this distinction, stating that the ultimate reality of things is pure Being, known only through reason; the senses deceive us with an illusion of change. Heraclitus also claimed that truth, for him the law of change, is known through thought, and that the senses mislead us into believing in permanence. Even Democritus suggested that true being, namely material atoms, are so tiny that the senses can't perceive them, and only reason can acknowledge their existence. Protagoras's teaching fundamentally rests on denying and confusing this distinction. To grasp this, we must first recognize that reason is universal, while sensation is particular to each individual. Reason is communicable, whereas sensation is not. My sensations and feelings are unique to me and cannot be shared with others. For example, no one can convey the sensation of redness to a color-blind person who has never experienced it. However, a thought or rational idea can be shared with any rational being. Consider the question of whether the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal. We can approach this in two ways: through the senses or through reason. If we rely on the senses, one person might say the angles look equal, while another might think one angle appears larger. In contrast, if we appeal to reason, as Euclid did, we can prove that the two angles are equal, leaving no room for mere personal impressions because reason is a universally valid law that applies to everyone. My sensations are private and particular to me; they don’t bind anyone else. My impressions about the triangle aren’t a law for anyone but myself. However, my reason is shared with all rational beings. It isn’t just a law for me but for everyone. It is the same reason in me and in others. Thus, reason is the universal element in humanity, while sensation is the particular element. Protagoras practically denied this distinction. He stated that man is the measure of all things. By "man," he meant the individual, not mankind as a whole. When he said "measure of all things," he referred to the standard of truth for each individual. Each person is the standard for what is true for themselves. There is no truth beyond the sensations and impressions of each individual. What seems true to me is true for me, and what seems true to you is true for you.

We commonly distinguish between subjective impressions and objective truth. The words subjective and objective are constantly recurring throughout the history of philosophy, and as this is the first time I use them, I will explain them here. In every act of thought there must necessarily be two terms. I am now looking at this desk and thinking of this desk. There is the "I" which thinks, and there is the desk which is thought. "I" am the subject of the thought, the desk is the object of the thought. In general, the subject is that which thinks, and the object is that which is thought. Subjective is that which appertains to the subject, and objective is that which appertains to the object. So the meaning of the distinction between subjective impressions and the objective truth is clear. My personal impression may be that the earth is flat, but the objective truth is that the {115} earth is round. Travelling through a desert, I may be subject to a mirage, and think that there is water in front of me. That is my subjective impression. The objective truth is that there is nothing but sand. The objective truth is something which has an existence of its own, independent of me. It does not matter what I think, or what you think, what I want, or what you want; the truth is what it is. We must conform ourselves to the truth. Truth will not conform itself to our personal inclinations, wishes, or impressions. The teaching of Protagoras practically amounted to a denial of this. What it meant was that there is no objective truth, no truth independent of the individual subject. Whatever seems to the individual true is true for that individual. Thus truth is identified with subjective sensations and impressions.

We often distinguish between personal feelings and facts. The terms subjective and objective appear frequently in the history of philosophy, and since it’s the first time I'm using them here, I'll clarify. In every thought process, there are always two components. Right now, I'm looking at this desk and thinking about it. There's the "I" that thinks, and there's the desk that is being thought about. "I" am the subject of the thought, while the desk is the object. Generally, the subject is the one that thinks, and the object is what is being thought about. Subjective refers to what relates to the subject, and objective refers to what relates to the object. Thus, the distinction between personal impressions and objective truth is clear. My personal impression might be that the earth is flat, but the objective truth is that the earth is round. While traveling through a desert, I might experience a mirage and believe there's water in front of me. That’s my subjective impression. The objective truth is that there’s nothing but sand. Objective truth exists independently of me. It doesn't matter what I think, or what you think, what I want, or what you want; the truth is what it is. We need to align ourselves with the truth. The truth won't bend to our personal preferences, desires, or impressions. Protagoras' teachings essentially denied this. He suggested that there’s no objective truth, no truth that exists outside of the individual subject. Whatever an individual perceives as true is true for that person. In this way, truth becomes tied to personal sensations and impressions.

To deny the distinction between objective truth and subjective impression is the same as to deny the distinction between reason and sense. To my senses the earth seems flat. It looks flat to the eye. It is only through reason that I know the objective truth that the world is round. Reason, therefore, is the only possible standard of objective truth. If you deny the rational element its proper part, it follows that you will be left a helpless prey to diverse personal impressions. The impressions yielded by the senses differ in different people. One man sees a thing in one way, another sees it in another. If, therefore, what seems to me true is true for me, and what seems to you true is true for you, and if our impressions differ, it will follow that two contradictory propositions must both be true. Protagoras clearly understood this, {116} and did not flinch from the conclusion. He taught that all opinions are true, that error is impossible, and that, whatever proposition is put forward, it is always possible to oppose to it a contradictory proposition with equally good arguments and with equal truth. In reality, the result of this procedure is to rob the distinction between truth and falsehood of all meaning. It makes no difference whether we say that all opinions are true, or whether we say that all are false. The words truth and falsehood, in such context, have no meaning. To say that whatever I feel is the truth for me means only that what I feel I feel. To call this "truth for me," adds nothing to the meaning.

To deny the difference between objective truth and subjective perception is the same as denying the difference between reason and senses. To my senses, the earth seems flat. It looks flat to the eye. It’s only through reason that I know the objective truth that the world is round. So, reason is the only real standard for objective truth. If you ignore the rational part of understanding, you’ll end up being at the mercy of various personal impressions. The impressions given by the senses vary from person to person. One person sees something one way, while another sees it differently. If what seems true to me is true for me, and what seems true to you is true for you, and if our impressions differ, then two contradictory statements could both be considered true. Protagoras clearly got this, {116} and didn’t shy away from the conclusion. He taught that all opinions are valid, that error doesn’t exist, and that for any statement, it’s always possible to come up with a contradictory statement backed by equally good arguments and equal truth. In reality, this approach strips away any meaning from the difference between truth and falsehood. It doesn’t matter whether we say that all opinions are true or that all are false. In this context, the words truth and falsehood hold no significance. To say that whatever I feel is the truth for me simply means that what I feel, I feel. Calling this “truth for me” adds nothing to the meaning.

Protagoras seems to have been led to these doctrines partly by observing the different accounts of the same object which the sense-organs yield to different people, and even to the same person at different times. If knowledge depends upon these impressions, the truth about the object cannot be ascertained. He was also influenced by the teaching of Heracleitus. Heracleitus had taught that all permanence is illusion. Everything is a perpetual becoming; all things flow. What is at this moment, at the next moment is not. Even at one and the same moment, Heracleitus believed, a thing is and is not. If it is true to say that it is, it is equally true that it is not. And this is, in effect, the teaching of Protagoras.

Protagoras seems to have come to these beliefs in part by noticing the different perceptions of the same object that various people have, and even how the same person sees it differently at different times. If knowledge relies on these impressions, then the true nature of the object can't be determined. He was also influenced by the ideas of Heracleitus. Heracleitus taught that all permanence is an illusion. Everything is constantly changing; all things are in flux. What exists at this moment won’t exist the next. Even at the same moment, Heracleitus believed a thing can both be and not be. If it’s true to say that something is, it’s equally true to say that it isn’t. And this is essentially what Protagoras teaches.

The Protagorean philosophy thus amounts to a declaration that knowledge is impossible. If there is no objective truth, there cannot be any knowledge of it. The impossibility of knowledge is also the standpoint of Gorgias. The title of his book is characteristic of {117} the Sophistical love of paradox. It was called "On Nature, or the non-existent." In this book he attempted to prove three propositions, (1) that nothing exists: (2) that if anything exists, it cannot be known: (3) that if it can be known, the knowledge of it cannot be communicated.

The Protagorean philosophy basically states that knowledge is impossible. If there's no objective truth, then we can't truly know anything. This view on the impossibility of knowledge is also held by Gorgias. The title of his book reflects the Sophistical love of paradox. It was called "On Nature, or the Non-Existent." In this book, he tried to prove three points: (1) that nothing exists; (2) that if anything does exist, we can't know it; (3) that if we can know it, we can't communicate that knowledge.

For proof of the first proposition, "nothing exists," Gorgias attached himself to the school of the Eleatics, especially to Zeno. Zeno had taught that in all multiplicity and motion, that is to say, in all existence, there are irreconcilable contradictions. Zeno was in no sense a sceptic. He did not seek for contradictions in things for the sake of the contradictions, but in order to support the positive thesis of Parmenides, that only being is, and that becoming is not at all. Zeno, therefore, is to be regarded as a constructive, and not merely as a destructive, thinker. But it is obvious that by emphasizing only the negative element in his philosophy, it is possible to use his antinomies as powerful weapons in the cause of scepticism and nihilism. And it was in this way that Gorgias made use of the dialectic of Zeno. Since all existence is self-contradictory, it follows that nothing exists. He also made use of the famous argument of Parmenides regarding the origin of being. If anything is, said Gorgias, it must have had a beginning. Its being must have arisen either from being, or from not-being. If it arose from being, there is no beginning. If it arose from not-being, this is impossible, since something cannot arise out of nothing. Therefore nothing exists.

To support his first claim, "nothing exists," Gorgias aligned himself with the Eleatic school, particularly Zeno. Zeno taught that in all multiplicity and motion, or in all existence, there are irreconcilable contradictions. Zeno was not a skeptic. He didn’t look for contradictions just for the sake of it, but to back up Parmenides' positive thesis that only being truly exists and that becoming does not exist at all. Therefore, Zeno should be seen as a constructive, not just a destructive thinker. However, by focusing solely on the negative aspects of his philosophy, his paradoxes can be wielded as strong arguments for skepticism and nihilism. Gorgias utilized Zeno's dialectic in this way. Since all existence is self-contradictory, it follows that nothing exists. He also referenced Parmenides' famous argument about the origin of being. Gorgias stated that if anything exists, it must have had a beginning. Its existence must have come from either being or not-being. If it came from being, then there’s no beginning. If it came from not-being, that's impossible because something can’t come from nothing. Therefore, nothing exists.

The second proposition of Gorgias, that if anything exists it cannot be known, is part and parcel of the whole Sophistic tendency of thought, which identifies knowledge {118} with sense-perception, and ignores the rational element. Since sense-impressions differ in different people, and even in the same person, the object as it is in itself cannot be known. The third proposition follows from the same identification of knowledge with sensation, since sensation is what cannot be communicated.

The second proposition of Gorgias, that if anything exists it can't be known, is central to the entire Sophistic way of thinking, which equates knowledge {118} with sensory experience and overlooks the rational aspect. Since sensory impressions vary among different people, and even within the same person, the object as it is in itself can't be comprehended. The third proposition comes from the same equation of knowledge with sensation, since sensation is something that can't be shared.

The later Sophists went much further than Protagoras and Gorgias. It was their work to apply the teaching of Protagoras to the spheres of politics and morals. If there is no objective truth, and if what seems true to each individual is for him the truth, so also, there can be no objective moral code, and what seems right to each man is right for him. If we are to have anything worth calling morality, it is clear that it must be a law for all, and not merely a law for some. It must be valid for, and binding upon, all men. It must, therefore, be founded upon that which is universal in man, that is to say, his reason. To found it upon sense-impressions and feelings is to found it upon shifting quicksands. My feelings and sensations are binding upon no man but myself, and therefore a universally valid law cannot be founded upon them. Yet the Sophists identified morality with the feelings of the individual. Whatever I think right is right for me. Whatever you think right is right for you. Whatever each man, in his irrational self-will, chooses to do, that is, for him, legitimate. These conclusions were drawn by Polus, Thrasymachus, and Critias.

The later Sophists went much further than Protagoras and Gorgias. Their goal was to apply Protagoras's teachings to politics and morality. If there’s no objective truth, and what seems true to each individual is their truth, then there can’t be an objective moral code either; what feels right to each person is right for them. If we want to have anything that can be called morality, it must be a law for everyone, not just for some. It needs to be valid for and binding on all people. Therefore, it must be based on something universal in humans, which is their reason. Basing it on senses and feelings is like building on unstable ground. My feelings and sensations only apply to me, so a universally valid law can’t be based on them. However, the Sophists equated morality with individual feelings. Whatever I think is right is right for me. Whatever you think is right is right for you. Whatever each person chooses to do in their irrational self-will is legitimate for them. Polus, Thrasymachus, and Critias drew these conclusions.

Now if there is, in this way, no such thing as objective right, it follows that the laws of the State can be founded upon nothing except force, custom, and convention. We often speak of just laws, and good laws. But to speak in that way involves the existence of an objective {119} standard of goodness and justice, with which we can compare the law, and see whether it agrees with that standard or not. To the Sophists, who denied any such standard, it was mere nonsense to speak of just and good laws. No law is in itself good or just, because there is no such thing as goodness or justice. Or if they used such a word as justice, they defined it as meaning the right of the stronger; or the right of the majority. Polus and Thrasymachus, consequently, drew the conclusion that the laws of the State were inventions of the weak, who were cunning enough, by means of this stratagem, to control the strong, and rob them of the natural fruits of their strength. The law of force is the only law which nature recognizes. If a man, therefore, is powerful enough to defy the law with impunity, he has a perfect right to do so. The Sophists were thus the first, but not the last, to preach the doctrine that might is right. And, in similar vein, Critias explained popular belief in the gods as the invention of some crafty statesman for controlling the mob through fear.

Now, if there’s no such thing as objective right, it follows that the laws of the State are based solely on force, customs, and conventions. We often talk about just laws and good laws. But using those terms implies the existence of an objective {119} standard of goodness and justice, which we can use to compare the law and see if it aligns with that standard. For the Sophists, who denied any such standard, talking about just and good laws was nonsense. No law is inherently good or just because goodness and justice don’t exist. If they used a term like justice, they defined it as the right of the stronger or the right of the majority. Polus and Thrasymachus concluded that the laws of the State were creations of the weak, who cleverly controlled the strong through this tactic and deprived them of the natural benefits of their strength. The only law recognized by nature is the law of force. Therefore, if someone is powerful enough to ignore the law without facing consequences, they have every right to do so. The Sophists were the first, but not the last, to advocate the idea that might makes right. Similarly, Critias explained the common belief in gods as the invention of some clever politician to control the masses through fear.

Now it is obvious that the whole tendency of this sophistical teaching is destructive and anti-social. It is destructive of religion, of morality, of the foundations of the State, and of all established institutions. And we can now see that the doctrines of the Sophists were, in fact, simply the crystallization into abstract thought of the practical tendencies of the age. The people in practice, the Sophists in theory, decried and trod under foot the restrictions of law, authority, and custom, leaving nothing but the deification of the individual in his crude self-will and egotism. It was in fact an age of "aufklärung," which means enlightenment or {120} illumination. Such periods of illumination, it seems, recur periodically in the history of thought, and in the history of civilization. This is the first, but not the last, such period with which the history of philosophy deals. This is the Greek illumination. Such periods present certain characteristic features. They follow, as a rule, upon an era of constructive thought. In the present instance the Greek illumination followed closely upon the heels of the great development of science and philosophy from Thales to Anaxagoras. In such a constructive period the great thinkers bring to birth new principles, which, in the course of time, filter down to the masses of the people and cause popular, if shallow, science, and a wide-spread culture. Popular education becomes a feature of the time. The new ideas, fermenting among the people, break up old prejudices and established ideas, and thus thought, at first constructive, becomes, among the masses, destructive in character. Hence the popular thought, in a period of enlightenment, issues in denial, scepticism, and disbelief. It is merely negative in its activities and results. Authority, tradition, and custom are wholly or partially destroyed. And since authority, tradition, and custom are the cement of the social structure, there results a general dissolution of that structure into its component individuals. All emphasis is now laid on the individual. Thought becomes egocentric. Individualism is the dominant note. Extreme subjectivity is the principle of the age. All these features make their appearance in the Greek aufklärung. The Sophistical doctrine that the truth is what I think, the good what I choose to do, is the extreme application of the subjective and egocentric principles.

Now it’s clear that the whole point of this misleading teaching is harmful and goes against society. It undermines religion, morality, the foundations of the State, and all established institutions. We can see now that the ideas of the Sophists were just a way of turning the practical tendencies of the time into abstract concepts. People in practice, and Sophists in theory, denounced and disregarded the limits of law, authority, and tradition, leaving only the notion of individualism in its raw form of self-will and egotism. It was truly an age of "aufklärung," which means enlightenment or {120} illumination. Such periods of enlightenment seem to arise periodically in the history of thought and civilization. This is the first, but not the last, such phase that philosophy addresses. This is the Greek enlightenment. These periods have certain typical features. They usually follow a time of constructive thought. In this case, the Greek enlightenment closely followed the significant advancements in science and philosophy from Thales to Anaxagoras. During such a constructive period, great thinkers introduce new principles, which, over time, reach the masses and create popular, if superficial, science and widespread culture. Popular education becomes a hallmark of the era. The new ideas, brewing among the people, break down old prejudices and established beliefs, which leads to initially constructive thought becoming destructive among the masses. Thus, popular thought during an enlightening period results in denial, skepticism, and disbelief. It is simply negative in its actions and outcomes. Authority, tradition, and custom are completely or partially dismantled. Since authority, tradition, and custom are the glue of social structure, this leads to a general breakdown of that structure into its individual parts. Now, all focus is on the individual. Thought becomes self-centered. Individualism takes center stage. Extreme subjectivity is the hallmark of the era. All these characteristics emerge in the Greek aufklärung. The Sophistical idea that the truth is what I think and the good is what I choose to do is the extreme expression of these subjective and egocentric principles.

The early eighteenth century in England and France was likewise a period of enlightenment, and the era from which we are now, perhaps, just emerging, bears many of the characteristics of aufklärung. It is sceptical and destructive. All established institutions, marriage, the family, the state, the law, come in for much destructive criticism. It followed immediately upon the close of a great period of constructive thought, the scientific development of the nineteenth century. And lastly, the age has produced its own Protagorean philosophy, which it calls pragmatism. If pragmatism is not egocentric, it is at least anthropocentric. Truth is no longer thought of as an objective reality, to which mankind must conform. On the contrary, the truth must conform itself to mankind. Whatever it is useful to believe, whatever belief "works" in practice, is declared to be true. But since what "works" in one age and country does not "work" in another, since what it is useful to believe to-day will be useless to-morrow, it follows that there is no objective truth independent of mankind at all. Truth is not now defined as dependent on the sensations of man, as it was with Protagoras, but as dependent on the volition of man. In either case it is not the universal in man, his reason, which is made the basis of truth and morals, but the subjective, individual, particular element in him.

The early eighteenth century in England and France was also a time of enlightenment, and the era we are currently in, perhaps, is just starting to emerge from that. It shares many traits with aufklärung. It is critical and deconstructive. All established institutions—marriage, family, state, and law—face significant criticism. This came right after a long period of innovative thinking during the scientific advancements of the nineteenth century. Lastly, this age has produced its own version of Protagorean philosophy, which we now call pragmatism. If pragmatism is not egocentric, it is at least centered on human concerns. Truth is no longer seen as an objective reality that humanity must adhere to. Instead, truth must adapt to humanity. Whatever beliefs are useful, or whatever beliefs "work" in practice, are deemed true. But since what "works" in one era and place might not "work" elsewhere, and what is useful to believe today may be pointless tomorrow, it leads to the conclusion that there is no objective truth that exists independently of humanity. Truth is now viewed as dependent on human will, rather than the sensations of humans, as it was with Protagoras. In either case, it’s not the universal aspects of humanity, like reason, that form the basis for truth and morals, but rather the subjective, individual, and particular elements of a person.

We must not forget the many merits of the Sophists. Individually, they were often estimable men. Nothing is known against the character of Protagoras, and Prodicus was proverbial for his wisdom and the genuine probity and uprightness of his principles. Moreover the Sophists contributed much to the advance of learning. {122} They were the first to direct attention to the study of words, sentences, style, prosody, and rhythm. They were the founders of the science of rhetoric. They spread education and culture far and wide in Greece, they gave a great impulse to the study of ethical ideas, which made possible the teaching of Socrates, and they stirred up a ferment of ideas without which the great period of Plato and Aristotle could never have seen the light. But, from the philosophical point of view, their merit is for the first time to have brought into general recognition the right of the subject. For there is, after all, much reason in these attacks made by the Sophists upon authority, upon established things, upon tradition, custom and dogma. Man, as a rational being, ought not to be tyrannized over by authority, dogma, and tradition. He cannot be subjected, thus violently, to the imposition of beliefs from an external source. No man has the right to say to me, "you shall think this," or "you shall think that." I, as a rational being, have the right to use my reason, and judge for myself. If a man would convince me, he must not appeal to force, but to reason. In doing so, he is not imposing his opinions externally upon me; he is educing his opinions from the internal sources of my own thought; he is showing me that his opinions are in reality my own opinions, if I only knew it. But the mistake of the Sophists was that, in thus recognizing the right of the subject, they wholly ignored and forgot the right of the object. For the truth has objective existence, and is what it is, whether I think it or not. Their mistake was that though they rightly saw that for truth and morality to be valid for me, they must be assented to by, and developed out of, {123} me myself, not imposed from the outside, yet they laid the emphasis on my merely accidental and particular characteristics, my impulses, feelings, and sensations, and made these the source of truth and morality, instead of emphasizing as the source of truth and right the universal part of me, my reason. "Man is the measure of all things"; certainly, but man as a rational being, not man as a bundle of particular sensations, subjective impressions, impulses, irrational prejudices, self-will, mere eccentricities, oddities, foibles, and fancies.

We shouldn't overlook the many strengths of the Sophists. On an individual level, they were often commendable people. Nothing negative is known about Protagoras, and Prodicus was famous for his wisdom and the genuine integrity of his principles. Additionally, the Sophists made significant contributions to the advancement of knowledge. {122} They were the first to focus on the study of words, sentences, style, prosody, and rhythm. They were the founders of the field of rhetoric. They spread education and culture throughout Greece, significantly boosting the study of ethical ideas, which enabled Socrates to teach, and they sparked a wave of ideas that made the great era of Plato and Aristotle possible. However, from a philosophical perspective, their main contribution was bringing into general awareness the right of the subject. There is, after all, considerable validity to the critiques the Sophists made against authority, established norms, tradition, custom, and dogma. A person, as a rational being, should not be dominated by authority, dogma, or tradition. They cannot be forcefully subjected to beliefs imposed from an outside source. No one has the right to dictate to me, "you must think this," or "you must think that." As a rational being, I have the right to think for myself and use my judgment. If someone wants to persuade me, they should appeal to reason, not force. In doing so, they are not externally imposing their beliefs on me; they are drawing out their beliefs from my own inner thoughts; they are demonstrating that their views are actually my views, if only I recognized it. However, the Sophists' mistake was that, in acknowledging the right of the subject, they completely overlooked the right of the object. Truth has an objective existence and is what it is, regardless of whether I believe it or not. Their error was that, while they correctly recognized that for truth and morality to hold value for me, they must be accepted by and arise from {123} myself, not forced from the outside, they focused too much on my individual and specific traits, my impulses, feelings, and sensations, making these the foundation of truth and morality instead of emphasizing the universal part of me—my reason—as the source of truth and right. "Man is the measure of all things"; certainly, but man as a rational being, not man as a collection of individual sensations, subjective impressions, impulses, irrational biases, self-will, mere eccentricities, oddities, quirks, and whims.

Good examples of the right and wrong principles of the Sophists are to be found in modern Protestantism and modern democracy. Protestantism, it is often said, is founded upon the right of private judgment, and this is simply the right of the subject, the right of the individual to exercise his own reason. But if this is interpreted to mean that each individual is entitled to set up his mere whims and fancies as the law in religious matters, then we have the bad sort of Protestantism. Again, democracy is simply political protestantism, and democratic ideas are the direct offspring of the protestant Reformation. The democratic principle is that no rational being can be asked to obey a law to which his own reason has not assented. But the law must be founded upon reason, upon the universal in man. I, as an individual, as a mere ego, have no rights whatever. It is only as a rational being, as a potentially universal being, as a member of the commonwealth of reason, that I have any rights, that I can claim to legislate for myself and others. But if each individual's capricious self-will, his mere whims and fancies, are erected into a law, then democracy turns into anarchism and bolshevism.

Good examples of the right and wrong principles of the Sophists can be found in modern Protestantism and modern democracy. Protestantism is often said to be based on the right of private judgment, which is simply the right of individuals to use their own reason. However, if this is taken to mean that every person can establish their own whims and fancies as the law in religious matters, then we end up with the negative side of Protestantism. Similarly, democracy is essentially political Protestantism, and democratic ideas directly stem from the Protestant Reformation. The democratic principle holds that no rational being should be asked to obey a law that their own reason hasn’t agreed to. But the law must be rooted in reason, in what is universal to humanity. As an individual, as just a person, I have no rights at all. It’s only as a rational being, a potentially universal being, part of the community of reason, that I have any rights or can claim to legislate for myself and others. If each person's unpredictable self-will, their mere whims and fancies, are turned into law, then democracy devolves into anarchism and bolshevism.

It is a great mistake to suppose that the doctrines of the Sophists are merely antiquated ideas, dead and fossilized thoughts, of interest only to historians, but of no importance to us. On the contrary, modern popular thought positively reeks with the ideas and tendencies of the Sophists. It is often said that a man ought to have strong convictions, and some people even go so far as to say that it does not much matter what a man believes, so long as what he believes he believes strongly and firmly. Now certainly it is quite true that a man with strong convictions is more interesting than a man without any opinions. The former is at least a force in the world, while the latter is colourless and ineffectual. But to put exclusive emphasis on the mere fact of having convictions is wrong. After all, the final test of worth must be whether the man's convictions are true or false. There must be an objective standard of truth, and to forget this, to talk of the mere fact of having strong opinions as in itself a merit, is to fall into the error of the Sophists.

It's a big mistake to think that the ideas of the Sophists are just outdated concepts, irrelevant thoughts that only historians care about. In reality, modern popular beliefs are heavily influenced by Sophist ideas and tendencies. People often say that someone should have strong beliefs, and some even argue that it doesn’t really matter what someone believes, as long as they believe it strongly and firmly. While it's true that a person with strong beliefs is more engaging than someone without any opinions, the former is at least a driving force in the world, while the latter is bland and ineffective. However, focusing solely on the fact of having convictions is misguided. Ultimately, the true measure of value must be whether those beliefs are true or false. There needs to be an objective standard of truth, and to overlook this—considering just the act of holding strong opinions as valuable in itself—is to fall into the error of the Sophists.

Another common saying is that everyone has a right to his own opinions. This is quite true, and it merely expresses the right of the subject to use his own reason. But it is sometimes interpreted in a different way. If a man holds a totally irrational opinion, and if every weapon is beaten out of his hands, if he is driven from every position he takes up--so that there is nothing left for him to do, except to admit that he is wrong, such a man will sometimes take refuge in the saying, that, after all, argue as you may, he has a right to his own opinion. But we cannot allow the claim. No man has a right to wrong opinions. There cannot be any right {125} in wrong opinions. You have no right to an opinion unless it is founded upon that which is universal in man, his reason. You cannot claim this right on behalf of your subjective impressions, and irrational whims. To do so is to make the mistake of the Sophists.

Another common saying is that everyone has the right to their own opinions. This is true and simply expresses a person's right to use their own reasoning. However, it’s sometimes interpreted differently. If someone has a completely irrational opinion and all their arguments are taken away, leaving them no choice but to admit they are wrong, that person might cling to the idea that, regardless of the arguments, they still have the right to their own opinion. But we cannot accept that claim. No one has the right to hold wrong opinions. There can't be any right {125} in wrong opinions. You don’t have the right to an opinion unless it's based on universal human reasoning. You can't claim this right based on your subjective impressions or irrational whims. To do so is to make the same mistake as the Sophists.

The tendencies of the more shallow type of modern rationalism exhibit a similar Sophistical thought. It is pointed out that moral ideas vary very much in different countries and ages, that in Japan, for example, prostitution is condoned, and that in ancient Egypt incest was not condemned. Now it is important to know these facts. They should serve as a warning to us against dogmatic narrow-mindedness in moral matters. But some people draw from these facts the conclusion that there is no universally valid and objectively real moral law. The conclusion does not follow from the premises, and the conclusion is false. People's opinions differ, not only on moral questions, but upon every subject under the sun. Because men, a few hundred years ago, believed that the earth was flat, whereas now we believe it is round, it does not follow that it has in reality no shape at all, that there is no objective truth in the matter. And because men's opinions differ, in different ages and countries, as to what the true moral law is, it does not follow that there is no objective moral law.

The tendencies of the shallower kind of modern rationalism show a similar Sophistical way of thinking. It's noted that moral ideas vary greatly in different countries and eras; for instance, in Japan, prostitution is accepted, and in ancient Egypt, incest was not viewed as wrong. It's important to recognize these facts. They should serve as a reminder against dogmatic narrow-mindedness in moral issues. However, some people take these facts to mean that there is no universally valid and objectively real moral law. This conclusion doesn't logically follow from the premises, and it is incorrect. People's opinions vary not only on moral questions but on every topic imaginable. Just because people a few hundred years ago believed the earth was flat, while we now know it is round, doesn't mean that the earth has no shape at all or that there is no objective truth in the matter. Likewise, the fact that people's views differ over time and across cultures about what the true moral law is doesn't mean there is no objective moral law.

We will take as our last example the current talk about the importance of developing one's personality. A man, it is said, should "be himself," and the expression of his own individuality must be his leading idea. Now certainly it is good to be oneself in the sense that it is hypocritical to pretend to be what one is not. Moreover, it is no doubt true that each man has certain special {126} gifts, which he ought to develop, so that all, in their diverse ways, may contribute as much as possible to the spiritual and material wealth of the world. But this ideal of individuality often leads to false developments, as we see in the spheres of art and of education. Such a man as Oscar Wilde, whose personality is essentially evil, defends his artistic principles on the ground that he must needs express his personality, that art is nothing but such personal expression, and that it is subject to no standard save the individuality of the artist. Some writers on education, among them Mr. Bernard Shaw, who has many points in common with the Sophists, tell us that to attempt to mould the character of a child by discipline, is to sin against its personality, and that the child should be allowed to develop its individuality unchecked in its own way. But against this we have to protest that to make the cultivation of individuality an end in itself, and to put exclusive emphasis on this, is wrong. The cultivation of an individuality is not in itself a good thing; it is not a good thing if the individuality be a worthless one. If a child exhibits savage or selfish tendencies, it must be subjected to discipline, and it is ridiculous to make a fetish of its personality to such an extent as to allow it to develop as it likes. In a similar way, the ideal of individuality is often interpreted to mean that the cultivation of the mere eccentricities and oddities of the individual is something good. But the personal peculiarities of a man are just what is worthless about him. That alone which entitles him to the sacred rights of a "person" is his rational and universal nature.

We will take as our last example the current talk about the importance of developing one's personality. It is said that a person should "be themselves," and expressing their own individuality should be their main goal. It is definitely good to be genuine, as pretending to be someone you’re not is hypocritical. Additionally, each person has unique gifts that they should nurture so that everyone, in their own way, can contribute to the spiritual and material growth of the world. However, this ideal of individuality often leads to misguided developments, particularly in art and education. For instance, Oscar Wilde, whose personality is fundamentally flawed, argues that he must express his personality through his art, claiming that art is solely about personal expression and should adhere only to the artist's individuality. Some writers on education, including Mr. Bernard Shaw, who shares many views with the Sophists, tell us that trying to shape a child's character through discipline is a violation of their personality, and that children should be allowed to develop their individuality freely. However, we must argue against this idea that prioritizes individuality for its own sake. Focusing exclusively on cultivating individuality is problematic; it isn't beneficial if that individuality lacks value. If a child shows aggressive or selfish behavior, they need discipline, and it's absurd to idolize their personality to the point where they can develop without limits. Similarly, the ideal of individuality is often misunderstood to mean that fostering a person's quirks and oddities is praiseworthy. However, a person’s personal peculiarities are often what makes them less valuable. What truly grants someone the rights of a "person" is their rational and universal nature.


SOCRATES

SOCRATES

Amid the destruction of all ideals of truth and morality, which was brought about by the Sophists, there appeared in Athens the figure of Socrates, who was destined to restore order out of chaos, and to introduce sanity into the disordered intellectual life of the time. Socrates was born about 470 B.C. in Athens. His father was a sculptor, his mother a midwife. Very little is known of his early years and education, except that he took up his father's occupation as a sculptor. In later years some statues used to be shown at the Acropolis in Athens, which were said to be the work of Socrates. But comparatively early in life he deserted his profession in order to devote himself to what he considered his mission in life, philosophy. He spent his entire life in Athens, never departing from it, save for short periods on three occasions, when he served in military expeditions in the Athenian army. For from twenty to thirty years he laboured at his philosophical mission in Athens, until, in his seventieth year, he was charged with denying the national gods, introducing new gods of his own, and corrupting the Athenian youth. On these charges he was condemned to death and executed.

Amid the destruction of all ideals of truth and morality caused by the Sophists, Socrates emerged in Athens, destined to restore order out of chaos and bring sanity to the chaotic intellectual life of the time. Socrates was born around 470 B.C. in Athens. His father was a sculptor, and his mother was a midwife. Very little is known about his early years and education, except that he followed in his father's footsteps as a sculptor. Later in life, some statues displayed at the Acropolis in Athens were said to be made by Socrates. But relatively early on, he abandoned his profession to dedicate himself to what he believed was his life's mission: philosophy. He spent his entire life in Athens, only leaving for short periods on three occasions when he served in military campaigns for the Athenian army. For about twenty to thirty years, he worked on his philosophical mission in Athens until, in his seventieth year, he faced charges of denying the national gods, introducing new gods of his own, and corrupting the youth of Athens. He was found guilty on these charges and executed.

The personal appearance of Socrates was grotesque. He was short, thick-set, and ugly. As he grew older he became bald; his nose was broad, flat, and turned up; he walked with a peculiar gait, and had a trick of rolling his eyes. His clothes were old and poor. He cared little or nothing for external appearances.

The way Socrates looked was quite unusual. He was short, stocky, and not handsome. As he got older, he went bald; his nose was wide, flat, and turned up; he had a unique way of walking and a habit of rolling his eyes. His clothes were worn and shabby. He didn’t care much about how he looked on the outside.

Socrates believed that he was guided in all his actions by a supernatural voice, which he called his "daemon." This voice, he thought, gave him premonitions of the good or evil consequences of his proposed actions, and nothing would induce him to disobey its injunctions. Socrates constructed no philosophy, that is to say, no system of philosophy. He was the author of philosophical tendencies, and of a philosophic method. He never committed his opinions to writing. His method of philosophizing was purely conversational. It was his habit to go down every day to the market place in Athens, or to any other spot where people gathered, and there to engage in conversation with anyone who was ready to talk to him about the deep problems of life and death. Rich or poor, young or old, friend or stranger, whoever came, and would attend, could listen freely to the talk of Socrates. He took no fees, as the Sophists did, and remained always a poor man. He did not, like the Sophists, deliver long speeches, tirades, and monologues. He never monopolised the conversation, and frequently it was the other party who did most of the talking, Socrates only interposing questions and comments, and yet remaining always master of the conversation, and directing it into fruitful channels. The conversation proceeded chiefly by the method of question and answer, Socrates by acute questions educing, bringing to birth, {129} the thoughts of his partner, correcting, refuting, or developing them.

Socrates believed he was guided in all his actions by a supernatural voice that he called his "daemon." He thought this voice gave him insights into the good or bad consequences of his planned actions, and nothing could make him ignore its instructions. Socrates didn’t create a formal philosophy or a system of philosophy. Instead, he was the source of philosophical ideas and a philosophical method. He never wrote down his opinions. His way of doing philosophy was entirely conversational. Every day, he would go to the marketplace in Athens or any other place where people gathered and talk with anyone willing to discuss the deep issues of life and death. Whether rich or poor, young or old, friend or stranger, anyone who showed up had the chance to listen to Socrates. He didn’t charge any fees like the Sophists and always remained poor. Unlike the Sophists, he didn’t give long speeches or rants. He never dominated the conversation, often letting the other person do most of the talking, while he would ask questions and make comments, all the while guiding the conversation in productive directions. The discussions mainly happened through a question-and-answer format, where Socrates would use sharp questions to draw out his partner’s thoughts, correcting, challenging, or building on them.

In carrying on this daily work, Socrates undoubtedly regarded himself as engaged upon a mission in some way supernaturally imposed upon him by God. Of the origin of this mission we have an account in the "Apology" of Plato, who puts into the mouth of Socrates the following words:--"Chairephon .... made a pilgrimage to Delphi and had the audacity to ask this question from the oracle .... He actually asked if there was any man wiser than I. And the priestess answered, No .... When I heard the answer, I asked myself: What can the god mean? what can he be hinting? For certainly I have never thought myself wise in anything, great or small. What can he mean then, when he asserts that I am the wisest of men? He cannot lie, of course: that would be impossible for him. And for a long while I was at a loss to think what he could mean. At last, after much thought, I started on some such course as this. I betook myself to one of the men who seemed wise, thinking that there, if anywhere, I should refute the utterance, and could say to the oracle: 'This man is wiser than I, and you said I was the wisest.' Now when I looked into the man--there is no need to give his name--it was one of our citizens, men of Athens, with whom I had an experience of this kind--when we talked together I thought, 'This man seems wise to many men, and above all to himself, but he is not so'; and then I tried to show that he thought he was wise, but he was not. Then he got angry with me and so did many who heard us, but I went away and thought to myself, 'Well, at any rate I am wiser than this man: probably neither of {130} us knows anything of beauty or of good, but he thinks he knows something when he knows nothing, and I, if I know nothing, at least never suppose that I do. So it looks as though I really were a little wiser than he, just in so far as I do not imagine myself to know things about which I know nothing at all.' After that I went to another man who seemed to be wiser still, and I had exactly the same experience, and then he got angry with me too, and so did many more. Thus I went round them all, one after the other, aware of what was happening and sorry for it, and afraid that they were getting to hate me."

In doing this daily work, Socrates definitely saw himself as on a mission that he believed was somehow imposed upon him by God. We have a description of this mission in Plato's "Apology," where Socrates says: "Chairephon... went to Delphi and boldly asked the oracle... He actually asked if there was anyone wiser than me. And the priestess answered, No... When I heard this, I asked myself: What could the god mean? What could he be hinting at? Because I’ve never thought of myself as wise in anything, big or small. What does he mean then when he claims I’m the wisest of men? He can't be lying, of course; that's impossible for him. For a long time, I was puzzled about what he could mean. Eventually, after much thought, I decided to go talk to one of the men who seemed wise, believing that there I could disprove the oracle and say to it: ‘This man is wiser than I, and you said I was the wisest.’ When I examined the man—there's no need to say his name—he was one of our citizens, an Athenian, and I had this experience with him. When we talked, I thought, ‘This man seems wise to many people, especially to himself, but he isn’t,’ and I tried to show him that he thought he was wise when he really wasn’t. He got mad at me, and so did many others who were listening, but I left thinking, ‘Well, at least I’m wiser than this guy: probably neither of us knows anything about beauty or good, but he thinks he knows something when he knows nothing, and I, if I know nothing, at least never pretend that I do. So it seems I am indeed a little wiser than he, solely because I don’t assume I know things about which I know nothing at all.’ After that, I went to another man who seemed even wiser, and I had the exact same experience with him too, and he got angry with me as well, along with many others. So I went around to them all, one after the other, aware of what was happening and feeling sorry for it, and worried that they were starting to hate me."

In this passage we can see, too, the supposed origin of another peculiar Socratic feature, the Socratic "irony." In any discussion, Socrates would, as a rule, profess himself to be totally ignorant of the matter in hand, and only anxious to learn the wisdom possessed by his interlocutor. This professed ignorance was not affectation. He was genuinely impressed with the notion that not only he, but all other men, live for the most part in ignorance of the things that are the most important to be known, the nature of goodness, beauty, and truth. He believed that the self-styled knowledge of the wise was, for the most part, nothing but pretentious ignorance. Nevertheless, he used this profession of ignorance as a weapon of offence, and it became in his hands a powerful rhetorical instrument, which he used with specially telling effect against those who, puffed up with their own importance and wisdom, pretended to knowledge which they did not possess. Such hollow pretence of knowledge met with uncompromising exposure at the hands of Socrates. With such persons he would open the {131} conversation with a confession of his own ignorance and an expression of his desire to learn the wisdom, which, he knew, they possessed. In their eagerness to show off their knowledge, they would, perhaps, rush into the breach with some very positive assertion. Socrates would express himself as delighted with this, but would add that there were one or two things about it which he did not fully understand, and he would proceed, with a few dexterous questions, to expose the hollowness, the shallowness, or the ignorance of the answers.

In this passage, we can also see the supposed origin of another distinctive Socratic trait, the Socratic "irony." During discussions, Socrates would generally claim to be completely clueless about the topic at hand and only eager to learn from his conversation partner's wisdom. This claim of ignorance wasn't just a show. He truly believed that not only he, but everyone else, mostly lives in ignorance of the most important things to know, like the nature of goodness, beauty, and truth. He thought that the supposed knowledge of the wise was mostly just pretentious ignorance. However, he used this declaration of ignorance as a tool and turned it into a powerful rhetorical device, especially effective against those who, inflated by their own self-importance and wisdom, pretended to have knowledge they didn't actually possess. Such empty pretense of knowledge was ruthlessly exposed by Socrates. With these individuals, he would begin the {131} conversation by admitting his own ignorance and expressing his desire to learn the wisdom he knew they had. In their eagerness to showcase their knowledge, they might rush in with some strong claims. Socrates would show his delight in this but would also mention that there were a couple of things he didn’t fully understand, and then he would skillfully ask questions to reveal the emptiness, shallowness, or ignorance of their responses.

It was chiefly the young men of Athens who gathered round Socrates, who was for them a centre of intellectual activity and a fountain of inspiration. It was this fact which afterwards formed the basis of the charge that he "corrupted the youth." He was a man of the noblest character and of the simplest life. Accepting no fees, he acquired no wealth. Poor, caring nothing for worldly goods, wholly independent of the ordinary needs and desires of men, he devoted himself exclusively to the acquisition of that which, in his eyes, alone had value, wisdom and virtue. He was endowed with the utmost powers of physical endurance and moral strength. When he served with the army in the Peloponnesian war, he astonished his fellow-soldiers by his bravery, and his cheerful endurance of every hardship. On two occasions, at considerable risk to himself, he saved the lives of his companions. At the battle of Delium it is said that Socrates was the only man who kept his head in the rout of the Athenians. He was an excellent companion, and though simple in his habits, and independent of all material pleasures, never made a fetish of this independence, nor allowed it to degenerate into a harsh asceticism, {132} Thus, he needed no wine, but yet, if occasion called for it, he not only drank, but could drink more than any other man without turning a hair. In the "Banquet" of Plato, Socrates is depicted sitting all night long drinking and talking philosophy with his friends. One by one the guests succumbed, leaving only Socrates and two others, and at last, as the dawn broke, these two also fell asleep. But Socrates got up, washed himself, and went down to the market place to begin his daily work.

It was primarily the young men of Athens who gathered around Socrates, who was a center of intellectual activity and a source of inspiration for them. This later formed the basis of the accusation that he "corrupted the youth." He was a man of the highest character and the simplest lifestyle. Not accepting any fees, he gained no wealth. Poor and indifferent to material possessions, completely independent of the usual needs and desires of people, he focused entirely on acquiring what he believed to be the only things of real value: wisdom and virtue. He was blessed with incredible physical endurance and moral strength. When he served in the army during the Peloponnesian War, he impressed his fellow soldiers with his bravery and his cheerful ability to endure hardships. On two occasions, putting himself at considerable risk, he saved the lives of his comrades. At the battle of Delium, it is said that Socrates was the only one who kept his cool during the retreat of the Athenians. He was a great friend, and while simple in his habits and independent of material pleasures, he never made a big deal out of this independence nor let it turn into a strict asceticism, {132} While he didn’t need wine, if the situation called for it, he not only drank but could drink more than anyone else without flinching. In Plato's "Banquet," Socrates is depicted as sitting all night drinking and discussing philosophy with his friends. One by one, the guests gave in to sleep, leaving only Socrates and two others, who eventually also fell asleep as dawn broke. But Socrates got up, cleaned himself up, and went to the marketplace to start his daily work.

In his seventieth year he was tried on three charges: (1) for denying the national gods, (2) for setting up new gods of his own, (3) for corrupting the youth. All these charges were entirely baseless. The first might well have been brought against almost any of the earlier Greek thinkers with some justice. Most of them disbelieved in the national religion; many of them openly denied the existence of the gods. Socrates, almost alone, had refrained from any such attitude. On the contrary, he always enjoined veneration towards the gods, and urged his hearers, in whatever city they might be, to honour the gods according to the custom of that city. According to Xenophon, however, he distinguished between the many gods and the one creator of the universe, who controls, guides, and guards over the lives of men. The second charge appears to have been based upon the claim of Socrates to be guided by a supernatural inner voice, but whatever we may think of this claim, it can hardly constitute good ground for a charge of introducing new gods. The third charge, that of corrupting the youth, was equally baseless, though the fact that Alcibiades, who had been a favourite pupil of Socrates, afterwards turned traitor to Athens, and {133} led, moreover, a dissolute and unprincipled life, no doubt prejudiced the philosopher in the eyes of the Athenians. But Socrates was not responsible for the misdeeds of Alcibiades, and his general influence upon the Athenian youth was the very opposite of corrupting.

In his seventieth year, he was tried on three charges: (1) for denying the national gods, (2) for creating new gods of his own, and (3) for corrupting the youth. All these charges were completely unfounded. The first could have reasonably been made against almost any earlier Greek thinker. Most of them doubted the national religion; many openly rejected the existence of the gods. Socrates, almost uniquely, maintained a different stance. Instead, he consistently promoted respect for the gods and encouraged his listeners, no matter where they were, to honor the gods according to their city's traditions. However, according to Xenophon, he made a distinction between the many gods and the singular creator of the universe, who controls, guides, and watches over human lives. The second charge seems to have stemmed from Socrates claiming to be guided by a supernatural inner voice, but regardless of what we think of this claim, it hardly justifies a charge of introducing new gods. The third charge, that he corrupted the youth, was similarly unfounded, although the fact that Alcibiades, a former favorite pupil of Socrates, later betrayed Athens and led a reckless and immoral life likely biased the Athenians against the philosopher. However, Socrates was not accountable for Alcibiades' wrongdoings, and his overall impact on the Athenian youth was actually the exact opposite of corrupting.

What then were the real reasons for these accusations? In the first place, there is no doubt that Socrates had made many personal enemies. In his daily disputations he had not spared even the most powerful men in Athens, but had ruthlessly laid bare the ignorance of those who pretended to be wise. There is, however, no reason to believe that the three men who actually laid the charges, Melitus, Lycon, and Anytus, did so out of any personal animosity. But they were men of straw, put forward by more powerful persons who remained behind the scenes. In the second place, Socrates had rendered himself obnoxious to the Athenian democracy. He was no aristocrat in feeling, nor was he a supporter of the vested interests and privileges of the few. But he could not accommodate himself to the mob-rule which then went by the name of democracy. The government of the State, he believed, should be in the hands of the wise, the just, and the good, those competent and trained to govern, and these are necessarily the few. He himself had taken no part in the political life of the time, preferring to guide by his influence and advice the young men on whom some day the duties of the State would devolve. On two occasions only did he take an active part in politics, and on both occasions his conduct gave great offence. Both these incidents are recounted in a passage in Plato's "Apology," which I will quote. The {134} first incident refers to the aftermath of the battle of Arginusae. The Athenian fleet had gained a victory here, but lost twenty-five ships of war, and the whole of the crews of these ships were drowned. This was attributed to the carelessness of the generals, and there was great indignation in Athens, upon their return whither the generals were put upon their trial. According to the law of Athens each accused had to be given a separate trial, but in their eagerness to have the generals condemned, the judges in this instance decided to try them all in a body. "You know, men of Athens," says Socrates in the "Apology," "that I have never held any other office in the State, but I did serve on the Council. And it happened that my tribe, Antiochis, had the Presidency at the time you decided to try the ten generals who had not taken up the dead after the fight at sea. You decided to try them in one body, contrary to law, as you all felt afterwards. On that occasion I was the only one of the Presidents who opposed you, and told you not to break the law; and I gave my vote against you; and when the orators were ready to impeach and arrest me, and you encouraged them and hooted me, I thought then that I ought to take all the risks on the side of law and justice, rather than side with you, when your decisions were unjust, through fear of imprisonment or death. That was while the city was still under the democracy. When the oligarchy came into power, the Thirty, in their turn, summoned me with four others to the Rotunda, and commanded us to fetch Leon of Salamis from that island, in order to put him to death: the sort of commands they often gave to many others, anxious as they were to incriminate all they could. And on that occasion {135} I showed not by words only, that for death, to put it bluntly, I did not care one straw--but I did care, and to the full, about doing what was wicked and unjust. I was not terrified then into doing wrong by that government in all its power; when we left the Rotunda, the other four went off to Salamis and brought Leon back, but I went home. And probably I should have been put to death for it, if the government had not been overthrown soon afterwards."

What were the real reasons behind these accusations? First of all, it’s clear that Socrates made many personal enemies. In his daily debates, he didn't hold back from challenging even the most powerful men in Athens, exposing the ignorance of those who claimed to be wise. However, there’s no reason to believe that the three men who actually brought the charges—Melitus, Lycon, and Anytus—did so out of personal hatred. They were merely frontmen for more influential figures who stayed in the background. Secondly, Socrates had become a thorn in the side of the Athenian democracy. He wasn’t an aristocrat in mindset nor was he supportive of the interests and privileges of the elite. However, he couldn’t go along with the mob rule that was called democracy at the time. He believed that the government should be run by the wise, just, and good—those who are competent and trained to lead, which naturally are the few. He himself had not engaged in the political life of the day, choosing instead to influence and advise the young men who would someday take on the responsibilities of governing. He only took an active role in politics twice, and both times his actions caused great offense. These events are detailed in Plato's "Apology," which I will quote. The {134} first incident refers to the aftermath of the battle of Arginusae. The Athenian fleet achieved a victory but lost twenty-five warships, and all the crews of those ships drowned. This was blamed on the generals’ negligence, leading to widespread outrage in Athens upon their return, and the generals were put on trial. According to Athenian law, each accused was supposed to have a separate trial, but in their eagerness to have the generals convicted, the judges decided to try them all together. "You know, men of Athens," Socrates says in the "Apology," "that I have never held any other office in the State, but I did serve on the Council. At the time you decided to try the ten generals who failed to recover the dead after the sea battle, my tribe, Antiochis, was in the presidency. You chose to try them all at once, which was against the law, as you all felt later. On that occasion, I was the only president who opposed you, telling you not to break the law; I voted against you. When the speakers moved to accuse and arrest me, while you cheered them on and heckled me, I thought that I should risk everything on the side of law and justice rather than side with you when your decisions were unjust, out of fear of imprisonment or death. This was when the city was still a democracy. When the oligarchy took over, the Thirty called me and four others to the Rotunda and ordered us to bring Leon of Salamis from the island to execute him—this was the kind of order they often gave to others, eager as they were to implicate as many as possible. On that occasion {135} I showed not just through words, but in action, that I didn’t care in the slightest about death—but I did care deeply about doing something wrong and unjust. I wasn’t intimidated into doing wrong by that government in all its power; when we left the Rotunda, the other four went to Salamis and brought Leon back, but I went home. I probably would have been executed for that if the government hadn’t fallen soon after."

But there was a third, and greater reason, for the condemnation of Socrates. These charges were brought against him because the popular mind confused him with the Sophists. This was entirely absurd, because Socrates in no respect resembled the Sophists, either in the manner of his life or in the tendency of his thought, which was wholly anti-sophistical. But that such a confusion did exist in the popular mind is clearly proved by "The Clouds" of Aristophanes. Aristophanes was a reactionary in thought and politics, and, hating the Sophists as the representatives of modernism, he lampooned them in his comedy, "The Clouds." Socrates appears in the play as the central character, and the chief of the Sophists. This was entirely unjust, but it affords evidence of the fact that Socrates was commonly mistaken for a Sophist by the Athenians. Aristophanes would not have ventured to introduce such a delusion into his play, had his audience not shared in it. Now at this time a wave of reaction was passing over Athens, and there was great indignation against the Sophists, who were rightly supposed to be overturning all ideals of truth and goodness. Socrates fell a victim to the anger of the populace against the Sophists.

But there was a third, and more significant reason, for the condemnation of Socrates. The charges against him arose because the public mistakenly associated him with the Sophists. This was completely ridiculous, because Socrates was not at all like the Sophists, either in how he lived or in his thinking, which was completely opposed to Sophistry. However, the existence of this confusion in the public's mind is clearly demonstrated by Aristophanes' "The Clouds." Aristophanes was reactionary in both thought and politics, and he despised the Sophists as symbols of modernism, so he ridiculed them in his comedy, "The Clouds." Socrates is depicted in the play as the main character and the leader of the Sophists. This portrayal was entirely unjust, but it shows that the Athenians commonly mistook Socrates for a Sophist. Aristophanes wouldn’t have included such a misconception in his play if his audience hadn’t shared it. At this time, a wave of backlash was sweeping through Athens, and there was widespread anger toward the Sophists, who were rightly seen as undermining all ideals of truth and goodness. Socrates became a scapegoat for the public's fury against the Sophists.

At the trial Socrates conducted himself with dignity and confidence. It was usual in those days for an accused person to weep and lament, to flatter the judges, to seek indulgence by grovelling and fawning, to appeal for pity by parading his wife and children in the court. Socrates refused to do any of these things, considering them unmanly. His "defence" was, indeed, not so much a defence of himself as an arraignment of his judges, the people of Athens, for their corruption and vice. This attitude of Socrates certainly brought about his condemnation. There is every reason to believe that if he had adopted a grovelling, even a conciliatory tone, he would have been acquitted. As it was, he was found guilty by a bare majority. The law enacted that, when the charge was proved, those who had brought the accusation should first propose the penalty which they thought fitting; then the accused himself should propose an alternative penalty. It was for the judges to decide which of the two should be inflicted. The accusers of Socrates proposed the death-penalty. Here again Socrates might have escaped by proposing at once some petty punishment. This would have satisfied the people, who were only anxious to score off the troublesome philosopher and pedant. But Socrates proudly affirmed that, as he was guilty of no crime, he deserved no punishment. To propose a penalty would be to admit his guilt. Far from being a guilty person, he considered himself in the light of a public benefactor, and as such, if he were to get his deserts, he proposed that he should be publicly honoured by being given a seat at the President's table. Nevertheless, as the law forced him to propose a penalty, he would, without prejudice to his {137} plea of innocence, suggest a fine of thirty minas. This conduct so exasperated the judges that he was now condemned to death by a large majority, about eighty of those who had previously voted for his acquittal now voting for his execution.

At the trial, Socrates carried himself with dignity and confidence. Back then, it was common for an accused person to cry and lament, to flatter the judges, to seek leniency by groveling and fawning, and to appeal for pity by bringing their family into the courtroom. Socrates refused to do any of these things, viewing them as unmanly. His "defense" was not so much about defending himself as it was about accusing his judges, the people of Athens, for their corruption and vice. This stance undoubtedly led to his condemnation. There’s every reason to believe that if he had taken a more submissive or conciliatory approach, he might have been acquitted. Instead, he was found guilty by a narrow margin. The law stated that once the charge was proven, the accusers would first suggest a penalty they deemed appropriate; then the accused would propose an alternative punishment. It was up to the judges to decide which penalty would be imposed. Socrates' accusers suggested the death penalty. Again, Socrates could have escaped by immediately proposing a minor punishment. This would have satisfied the public, who just wanted to get back at the bothersome philosopher and know-it-all. But Socrates proudly asserted that since he had committed no crime, he deserved no punishment. To propose a penalty would imply his guilt. Rather than seeing himself as guilty, he viewed himself as a public benefactor, and as such, he proposed that he should be publicly honored with a seat at the President's table. Nevertheless, since the law required him to propose a penalty, he would suggest a fine of thirty minas, without compromising his {137} plea of innocence. This behavior so angered the judges that he was ultimately condemned to death by a large majority, with about eighty of those who had previously voted for his acquittal now voting for his execution.

Thirty days elapsed before he was executed, and these days were spent in prison. His friends, who had free access to him, urged him to escape. These things were possible in Athens. Anaxagoras had apparently escaped with the help of Pericles. A little silver in the hands of the jailguards would probably have settled the matter. Socrates could fly to Thessaly, where the law could not reach him, as Anaxagoras had fled to Ionia. But Socrates steadily refused, saying that to flee from death was cowardly, and that one ought to obey the laws. The law had decreed his death, and he must obey. After thirty days, therefore, the poison cup was brought to him, and he drank it without flinching. Here is Plato's account of the death of Socrates, which I quote from the "Phaedo." In detail it cannot be considered historical, but we may well believe that the main incidents as well as the picture it gives us of the bearing and demeanour of the philosopher in his last moments, are accurate representations of the facts.

Thirty days passed before he was executed, and he spent those days in prison. His friends, who could visit him freely, encouraged him to escape. Such things were possible in Athens. Anaxagoras had apparently escaped with Pericles' help. A little cash in the hands of the jailers would likely have done the trick. Socrates could have fled to Thessaly, where the law couldn’t pursue him, just as Anaxagoras had fled to Ionia. But Socrates consistently refused, stating that running away from death was cowardly and that one should obey the laws. The law had sentenced him to death, and he had to abide by it. After thirty days, the poison cup was brought to him, and he drank it without hesitation. Here is Plato's account of Socrates' death, which I quote from the "Phaedo." While it can't be fully regarded as historical, we can reasonably believe that the main events and the depiction of the philosopher's demeanor during his final moments are accurate representations of the facts.

"He rose and went into a chamber to bathe, and Crito followed him, but he directed us to wait for him. We waited, therefore, conversing among ourselves about what had been said, and considering it again, and sometimes speaking about our calamity, how severe it would be to us, sincerely thinking that, like those who are deprived of a father, we should pass the rest of our lives as orphans. When he had bathed and his {138} children were brought to him, for he had two little sons and one grown up, and the women belonging to his family were come, having conversed with them in the presence of Crito, and given them such injunctions as he wished, he directed the women and children to go away, and then returned to us. And it was now near sunset; for he spent a considerable time within. But when he came from bathing he sat down and did not speak much afterwards: then the officer of the Eleven came in and standing near him said, 'Socrates, I shall not have to find that fault with you that I do with the others, that they are angry with me, and curse me, when, by order of the archons, I bid them drink the poison. But you, on all other occasions during the time you have been here, I have found to be the most noble, meek and excellent man of all that ever came into this place; and, therefore, I am now well convinced that you will not be angry with me. Now, then, for you know what I came to announce to you, farewell, and endeavour to bear what is inevitable as easily as possible.' And at the same time, bursting into tears, he turned away and withdrew. And Socrates, looking after him, said, 'And thou too, farewell, we will do as you direct.' At the same time, turning to us he said 'How courteous the man is; during the whole time I have been here he has visited me, and conversed with me sometimes, and proved the worthiest of men; and how generously he weeps for me. But come, Crito, let us obey him and let some one bring the poison, if it is ready pounded, but if not let the man pound it.'

He got up and went to a room to take a bath, and Crito followed him, but he told us to wait for him. So we waited, talking among ourselves about what had been said, thinking it over again, and sometimes discussing our situation, how tough it would be for us, genuinely believing that, like those who lose a father, we would spend the rest of our lives feeling like orphans. After he had bathed, his {138} children were brought to him; he had two young sons and one older son, and the women from his family had come too. After speaking with them in front of Crito and giving them the instructions he wanted, he told the women and children to leave before returning to us. It was now close to sunset because he had spent a good amount of time inside. When he came out from bathing, he sat down and didn’t speak much afterward. Then the officer of the Eleven came in and stood by him, saying, "Socrates, I won’t have to deal with you like I do with the others, who get angry at me and curse me when I order them to drink the poison. But you, throughout your time here, I have found to be the noblest, gentlest, and most admirable person to ever come here; so I’m sure you won't be mad at me. Now, you know why I’m here, so goodbye, and try to accept what’s inevitable as easily as you can." As he said this, he started to cry, turned away, and left. Socrates, watching him go, said, "Goodbye to you too, we will follow your instructions." Then, turning to us, he remarked, "How kind he is; during my whole time here, he has visited me and chatted with me, proving to be such a good man; how heartfelt his tears are for me. But come, Crito, let’s listen to him and have someone bring the poison, if it’s already prepared; if not, let the man prepare it."

"Then Crito said, 'But I think, Socrates, that the sun is still on the mountains, and has not yet set. Besides, {139} I know that others have drunk the poison very late, after it had been announced to them, and have supped and drunk freely, and some even have enjoyed the objects of their love. Do not hasten them, for there is yet time.'

"Then Crito said, 'But I think, Socrates, that the sun is still on the mountains and hasn't set yet. Besides, {139} I know that others have taken the poison very late, after it was announced to them, and have had dinner and drank freely, and some even enjoyed the company of their loved ones. Don't rush them; there’s still time.'"

"Upon this Socrates replied, 'These men whom you mention, Crito, do these things with good reason, for they think they shall gain by so doing, and I too with good reason, shall not do so; for I think I shall gain nothing by drinking a little later, except to become ridiculous to myself, in being so fond of life, and sparing of it when none any longer remains. Go then,' he said, 'obey, and do not resist.'

"Then Socrates replied, 'The people you’re talking about, Crito, have their reasons for acting this way because they believe they’ll benefit from it. I also have my reasons for not acting this way; I think I won’t gain anything by waiting a little longer to drink, except making a fool of myself by being so attached to life yet holding back when there’s hardly any time left. So go ahead,' he said, 'just do what you need to do and don’t resist.'"

"Crito having heard this, nodded to the boy that stood near. And the boy having gone out, and stayed for some time, came, bringing with him the man that was to administer the poison, who brought it ready pounded in a cup. And Socrates, on seeing the man, said, 'Well, my good friend, as you are skilled in these matters, what must I do?' 'Nothing else,' he replied, 'than when you have drunk it walk about, until there is a heaviness in your legs, then lie down; thus it will do its purpose.' And at the same time he held out the cup to Socrates. And he having received it very cheerfully, Echecrates, neither trembling, nor changing at all in colour or countenance, but, as he was wont, looking steadfastly at the man, said, 'what say you of this potion, with respect to making a libation to anyone, is it lawful or not?' 'We only pound so much, Socrates,' he said, 'as we think sufficient to drink.' 'I understand you,' he said, 'but it is certainly both lawful and right to pray to the gods that my departure hence thither may be happy; which therefore I pray, and so {140} may it be.' And as he said this he drank it off readily and calmly. Thus far, most of us were with difficulty able to restrain ourselves from weeping, but when we saw him drinking, and having finished the draught, we could do so no longer; but in spite of myself the tears came in full torrent, so that, covering my face, I wept for myself, for I did not weep for him, but for my own fortune, in being deprived of such a friend. But Crito, even before me, when he could not restrain his tears, had risen up. But Apollodorus even before this had not ceased weeping, and then, bursting into an agony of grief, weeping and lamenting, he pierced the heart of everyone present, except Socrates himself. But he said. 'What are you doing, my admirable friends? I indeed, for this reason chiefly, sent away the women, that they might not commit any folly of this kind. For I have heard that it is right to die with good omens. Be quiet, therefore, and bear up.'

Crito, having heard this, signaled to the boy standing nearby. The boy went out, and after a while, returned with the person who was to give the poison, which was already prepared in a cup. When Socrates saw the man, he said, "Well, my good friend, since you know about this, what should I do?" "Nothing else," he replied, "but after you drink it, walk around until your legs feel heavy, then lie down; that's how it will work." At the same time, he held out the cup to Socrates. Socrates took it cheerfully, without trembling or changing color or expression, but looking steadily at the man, he asked, "What do you think about this potion in terms of making a libation to anyone, is it allowed or not?" "We only prepare as much as we think is enough to drink," he said. "I understand," Socrates replied, "but it is definitely both allowed and right to pray to the gods for my journey to be a happy one; so I do pray, and may it be so." As he said this, he calmly drank it all down. Up to this point, most of us could barely hold back our tears, but when we saw him drink and finish the potion, we lost control; I couldn't help but cry, not for him but for myself, for losing such a friend. Crito, even before me, stood up when he could no longer hold back his tears. Apollodorus, even before this, had been weeping continuously, and then, overwhelmed with grief, he cried out in despair, affecting everyone present except Socrates himself. Socrates then said, "What are you doing, my wonderful friends? I specifically sent away the women for this reason, so they wouldn’t act foolishly. I've heard that it's best to die with good omens. So please be calm and hold up."

"When we heard this we were ashamed, and restrained our tears. But he, having walked about, when he said that his legs were growing heavy, lay down on his back; for the man so directed him. And at the same time he who gave him the poison, taking hold of him, after a short interval examined his feet and legs; and then having pressed his foot hard, he asked if he felt it; he said that he did not. And after this he pressed his thighs; and thus going higher he showed us that he was growing cold and stiff. Then Socrates touched himself, and said that when the poison reached his heart he should then depart. But now the parts around the lower belly were almost cold; when uncovering himself, for he had been covered over, he said; and they were his {141} last words. 'Crito, we owe a cock to AEsculapius; pay it, therefore, and do not neglect it.' 'It shall be done,' said Crito, 'but consider whether you have anything else to say.'

"When we heard this, we felt ashamed and held back our tears. But he, after walking around a bit, said that his legs were getting heavy and lay down on his back, as the man directed him to do. At the same time, the one who gave him the poison held him, and after a short moment, checked his feet and legs. He pressed his foot hard and asked if he could feel it; he said he couldn't. After that, he pressed his thighs, and as he went higher, he showed us that he was getting cold and stiff. Then Socrates touched himself and said that when the poison reached his heart, he would depart. But now the areas around his lower belly were almost cold; as he uncovered himself—since he had been covered—he said, and those were his {141} last words. 'Crito, we owe a cock to AEsculapius; pay it, then, and don't forget.' 'It will be done,' Crito replied, 'but think about whether you have anything else to say.'"

"To this question he gave no reply; but shortly after he gave a convulsive movement, and the man covered him, and his eyes were fixed, and Crito, perceiving it, closed his mouth and eyes.

"To this question, he didn't respond; but shortly after, he had a sudden convulsive movement, and the man covered him, his eyes were wide open, and Crito, noticing this, closed his mouth and eyes."

"This, Echecrates, was the end of our friend, a man, as we may say, the best of all of his time that we have known, and moreover, the most wise and just."

"This, Echecrates, was the end of our friend, a man, as we could say, the best of all of his time that we have known, and also the wisest and most just."

Our knowledge of the teaching of Socrates is derived chiefly from two sources, Plato and Xenophon, for the peculiarities of each of whom allowances must be made. Plato in his dialogues makes Socrates the mouthpiece of his own teaching, consequently the majority of the tenets to which Socrates is made to give expression are purely Platonic doctrines of which the historical Socrates could never even have dreamed. It might, therefore, seem at first sight that there is no possibility of ascertaining from Plato's dialogues any trustworthy account of the ideas of Socrates. But on closer inspection this does not turn out to be correct, because the earlier dialogues of Plato were written before he had developed his own philosophy, and when he was, to all intents and purposes, simply a disciple of Socrates, bent only upon giving the best expression to the Socratic doctrine. Even in these Socratic dialogues, however, we have what is no doubt an idealized portrait of Socrates. Plato makes no pretence of being merely a biographer or historian. The incidents and conversation, although they are no doubt frequently founded upon facts, are, in the {142} main, imaginary. All we can say is that they contain the gist and substance of the philosophy of Socrates. The other source, Xenophon, also has his peculiarities. If Plato was an idealizing philosopher, Xenophon was a prosaic and matter of fact man of affairs. He was a plain, honest soldier. He had no great insight into any philosophy, Socratic or otherwise. He was not attached to Socrates primarily as a philosopher, but as an admirer of his character and personality. If Plato puts the teaching of Socrates too high, Xenophon puts it too low. But, in spite of this, Xenophon's Memorabilia contains a mass of valuable information both about the life and the philosophical ideas of Socrates.

Our understanding of Socrates' teachings mainly comes from two sources, Plato and Xenophon, each of whom has their own quirks that we must consider. Plato, in his dialogues, largely presents Socrates as a voice for his own teachings, meaning many of the ideas Socrates expresses are actually Plato's own thoughts, which the historical Socrates could never have imagined. So, it might initially seem that we can't find any reliable insight into Socrates' ideas from Plato's dialogues. However, upon closer examination, this isn't entirely true, because Plato's earlier dialogues were written before he fully developed his own philosophy and when he was mainly just a follower of Socrates, focused on accurately representing Socratic teachings. Even in these dialogues, though, we see an idealized version of Socrates. Plato doesn't claim to be just a biographer or historian. The events and conversations, while often based on real occurrences, are mostly invented. All we can conclude is that they capture the essence of Socratic philosophy. The other source, Xenophon, has his own unique style. While Plato is an idealizing philosopher, Xenophon is a straightforward, practical person. He was a simple, honest soldier with limited understanding of philosophy, Socratic or otherwise. His connection to Socrates was more about admiring his character than anything philosophical. If Plato elevates Socrates’ teachings too much, Xenophon lowers them too much. Yet, despite this, Xenophon's *Memorabilia* provides a wealth of valuable information about Socrates' life and philosophical ideas.

The Socratic teaching is essentially ethical in character. In this alone did Socrates bear any resemblance to the Sophists. It was the Sophists who had introduced into Greek philosophy the problem of man, and of the duties of man. And to these problems Socrates also turns his exclusive attention. He brushes aside all questions as to the origin of the world, or the nature of the ultimate reality, of which we have heard so much in the philosophies of the earlier thinkers. Socrates openly deprecated such speculations and considered all such knowledge comparatively worthless as against ethical knowledge, the knowledge of man. Mathematics, physics, and astronomy, he thought, were not valuable forms of knowledge. He said that he never went for walks outside the city, because there is nothing to be learnt from fields and trees.

The Socratic teaching is fundamentally ethical. This is the only way Socrates resembled the Sophists. It was the Sophists who brought the issues of humanity and human responsibilities into Greek philosophy. Socrates also focused exclusively on these problems. He dismissed questions about the origin of the world or the nature of ultimate reality, which were prevalent in the philosophies of earlier thinkers. Socrates openly criticized such speculations and believed that this kind of knowledge was comparatively worthless compared to ethical knowledge, the knowledge of humanity. He thought mathematics, physics, and astronomy were not valuable types of knowledge. He mentioned that he never walked outside the city because there’s nothing to be learned from fields and trees.

Nevertheless the ethical teaching of Socrates was founded upon a theory of knowledge, which is quite simple, but extremely important. The Sophists had founded knowledge upon perception, with the result {143} that all objective standards of truth had been destroyed. It was the work of Socrates to found knowledge upon reason, and thereby to restore to truth its objectivity. Briefly, the theory of Socrates may be summarized by saying that he taught that all knowledge is knowledge through concepts. What is a concept? When we are directly conscious of the presence of any particular thing, a man, a tree, a house, or a star, such consciousness is called perception. When, shutting our eyes, we frame a mental picture of such an object, such consciousness is called an image or representation. Such mental images are, like perceptions, always ideas of particular individual objects. But besides these ideas of individual objects, whether through sense-perception or imagination, we have also general ideas, that is to say, not ideas of any particular thing, but ideas of whole classes of things. If I say "Socrates is mortal," I am thinking of the individual, Socrates. But if I say "Man is mortal," I am thinking, not of any particular man, but of the class of men in general. Such an idea is called a general idea, or a concept. All class-names, such as man, tree, house, river, animal, horse, being, which stand, not for one thing, but for a multitude of things, represent concepts. We form these general ideas by including in them all the qualities which the whole class of objects has in common, and excluding from them all the qualities in which they differ, that is to say, the qualities which some of the objects possess, but others do not. For example, I cannot include the quality whiteness in my general idea of horses, because, though some horses are white, others are not. But I can include the quality vertebrate because all horses agree in being vertebrate. Thus a {144} concept is formed by bringing together the ideas in which all the members of a class of objects agree with one another, and neglecting the ideas in which they differ.

Nevertheless, Socrates' ethical teaching was based on a theory of knowledge that is quite simple but extremely important. The Sophists based knowledge on perception, which led to the destruction of all objective standards of truth. Socrates aimed to base knowledge on reason, thereby restoring objectivity to truth. In short, Socrates taught that all knowledge is knowledge through concepts. What is a concept? When we are directly aware of the presence of a specific thing—a person, a tree, a house, or a star—such awareness is called perception. When we close our eyes and create a mental picture of such an object, that awareness is called an image or representation. These mental images, like perceptions, are always ideas of particular individual objects. However, along with ideas of individual objects, whether from sense perception or imagination, we also have general ideas. These aren't ideas of any specific thing, but of entire classes of things. If I say, "Socrates is mortal," I'm referring to the individual, Socrates. But if I say, "Man is mortal," I’m thinking not of any specific man but of the class of men in general. This idea is called a general idea, or a concept. All class names, like man, tree, house, river, animal, horse, and being, which represent not one thing but many things, are concepts. We form these general ideas by including all the qualities that the entire class of objects shares and excluding the qualities in which they differ—those qualities that some objects have but others do not. For example, I cannot include the quality of whiteness in my general idea of horses, because while some horses are white, others are not. However, I can include the quality of being vertebrate because all horses share that characteristic. Thus, a {144} concept is formed by bringing together the ideas that all members of a class of objects have in common while ignoring the ideas where they differ.

Now reason is the faculty of concepts. This may not, at first sight, be obvious. Reason, it might be objected, is the faculty of arguing, of drawing conclusions from premises. But a little consideration will show us that, though this is so, yet all reasoning is employed upon concepts. All reasoning is either deductive or inductive. Induction consists in the formulation of general principles from particular cases. A general principle is always a statement made, not about a particular thing, but about a whole class of things, that is, about a concept. Concepts are formed inductively by comparing numerous examples of a class. Deductive reasoning is always the opposite process of applying general principles to particular cases. If we argue that Socrates must be mortal because all men are so, the question is whether Socrates is a man, that is to say, whether the concept, man, is properly applied to the particular object called Socrates. Thus inductive reasoning is concerned with the formation of concepts, deductive reasoning with the application of them.

Now, reasoning is the ability to work with concepts. This might not be immediately clear. One might argue that reasoning is about making arguments and drawing conclusions from premises. However, if we think about it for a moment, we’ll realize that all reasoning is based on concepts. Reasoning can be either deductive or inductive. Induction involves creating general principles from specific cases. A general principle is always a statement about a whole category of things, not just one specific thing; in other words, it relates to a concept. Concepts are formed inductively by comparing many examples within a category. Deductive reasoning, on the other hand, involves applying general principles to specific cases. For instance, if we argue that Socrates must be mortal because all men are mortal, the key question is whether Socrates is a man—meaning whether the concept of "man" applies correctly to the specific individual known as Socrates. Therefore, inductive reasoning focuses on forming concepts, while deductive reasoning is about applying them.

Socrates, in placing all knowledge in concepts, was thus making reason the organ of knowledge. This was in direct opposition to the principle of the Sophists, who placed all knowledge in sense-perception. Now since reason is the universal element in man, it follows that Socrates, in identifying knowledge with concepts, was restoring the belief in an objective truth, valid for all men, and binding upon all men, and was destroying the Sophistic teaching that the truth is whatever each {145} individual chooses to think it is. We shall see this more clearly if we reflect that a concept is the same thing as a definition. If we wish to define any word, for example, the word man, we must include in our definition only the qualities which all men have in common. We cannot, for example, define man as a white-skinned animal, because all men are not white-skinned. Similarly we cannot include "English-speaking" in our definition, because, though some men speak English, others do not. But we might include such a quality as "two-legged," because "two-legged" is a quality common to all human beings, except mere aberrations and distortions of the normal type. Thus a definition is formed in the same way as a concept, namely, by including the common qualities of a class of objects, and excluding the qualities in which the members of the class differ. A definition, in fact, is merely the expression of a concept in words. Now by the process of fixing definitions we obtain objective standards of truth. If, for example, we fix the definition of a triangle, then we can compare any geometrical figure with it, and say whether it is a triangle or not. It is no longer open to anyone to declare that whatever he chooses to call a triangle is a triangle. Similarly, if we fix upon a definition of the word man, we can then compare any object with that definition, and say whether it is a man or not. Again, if we can decide what the proper concept of virtue is, then the question whether any particular act is virtuous can only be decided by comparing that act with the concept, and seeing if they agree. The Sophist can no longer say, "whatever seems to me right, is right for me. Whatever I choose to do is virtuous for me." His act must be judged, not by {146} his subjective impressions, but by the concept or definition, which is thus an objective standard of truth, independent of the individual. This, then, was the theory of knowledge propounded by Socrates. Knowledge, he said, is not the same thing as the sensations of the individual, which would mean that each individual can name as the truth whatever he pleases. Knowledge means knowledge of things as they objectively are, independently of the individual, and such knowledge is knowledge of the concepts of things. Therefore the philosophizing of Socrates consisted almost exclusively in trying to frame proper concepts. He went about enquiring, "What is virtue?" "What is prudence?" "What is temperance?"--meaning thereby "what are the true concepts or definitions of these things?" In this way he attempted to find a basis for believing in an objectively real truth and an objectively real moral law.

Socrates believed that all knowledge came from concepts, making reason the means of knowledge. This directly opposed the Sophists, who believed knowledge was based on sense perception. Since reason is a universal trait in humans, Socrates’ view of knowledge as concepts aimed to restore faith in an objective truth that applies to everyone, countering the Sophistic idea that truth is whatever each person thinks. We can see this more clearly by remembering that a concept is essentially the same as a definition. When we define a word, like "man," we must include only the traits that all men share. For example, we can't define man as a white-skinned being, because not all men are white-skinned. Similarly, we can't include "English-speaking" since some people speak English and others don’t. However, we can include "two-legged" because that quality is common to all humans, barring any rare exceptions. Therefore, a definition is created like a concept, by including shared qualities of a group while excluding differing traits. A definition is simply a verbal expression of a concept. By establishing definitions, we create objective standards of truth. For instance, if we define a triangle, we can then compare any geometric figure to that definition and determine if it is a triangle. No one can just claim that whatever they choose to call a triangle is one. Likewise, if we establish a definition of "man," we can compare any entity to that definition to see if it qualifies as a man. Furthermore, if we define what virtue is, we can determine if a specific act is virtuous by comparing that act to the concept of virtue. The Sophist can no longer assert, "Whatever seems right to me is right for me. Whatever I do is virtuous for me." Their actions must be evaluated against the objective standard of the concept or definition, not based on personal feelings. This was Socrates' theory of knowledge. He argued that knowledge isn't just the individual’s sensations, which would allow anyone to name their own truth. Knowledge is about understanding things as they objectively are, regardless of the individual. This understanding comes from knowing the concepts of things. Thus, Socrates primarily focused on developing accurate concepts, asking questions like, “What is virtue?” “What is prudence?” “What is temperance?”—which meant "What are the correct concepts or definitions of these things?" Through this process, he sought a foundation for believing in an objectively real truth and a universally valid moral law.

His method of forming concepts was by induction. He would take common examples of actions which are universally admitted to be prudent, and would attempt to find the quality which they all have in common, and by virtue of which they are all classed together, and so form the concept of prudence. Then he would bring up fresh examples, and see whether they agreed with the concept so formed. If not, the concept might have to be corrected in the light of the new examples.

His way of forming concepts was through induction. He would take common examples of actions that everyone agrees are wise and try to identify the quality they all share that categorizes them together, thus creating the concept of wisdom. Then he would introduce new examples and check if they matched the concept he had formed. If they didn't, he might need to adjust the concept based on the new examples.

But the Socratic theory of knowledge was not a theory put forward for its own sake, but for practical ends. Socrates always made theory subservient to practice. He wanted to know what the concept of virtue is, only in order to practise virtue in life. And this brings us to the central point of the ethical teaching of Socrates, {147} which was the identification of virtue with knowledge. Socrates believed that a man cannot act rightly, unless he first knows what is right, unless, in fact, he knows the concept of right. Moral action is thus founded upon knowledge, and must spring from it. But not only did Socrates think that if a man has not knowledge, he cannot do right. He also put forward the much more doubtful assertion that if a man possesses knowledge, he cannot do wrong. All wrong-doing arises from ignorance. If a man only knows what is right, he must and will infallibly do what is right. All men seek the good, but men differ as to what the good is. "No man," said Socrates, "intentionally does wrong." He does wrong, because he does not know the true concept of right, and being ignorant, thinks that what he is doing is good. "If a man intentionally does wrong," said Socrates again, "he is better than a man who does so unintentionally." For the former has in him the essential condition of goodness, knowledge of what goodness is, but the latter, lacking that knowledge, is hopeless.

But the Socratic theory of knowledge wasn’t just a theory for its own sake; it had practical purposes. Socrates always prioritized practice over theory. He wanted to understand the concept of virtue only to apply it in life. This brings us to the key point of Socrates' ethical teaching, {147}, which was the idea that virtue is tied to knowledge. Socrates believed that a person can’t act rightly unless they first know what is right, and truly understand the concept of right. Moral action is grounded in knowledge and must come from it. However, Socrates didn’t just think that a person without knowledge can’t do what’s right. He also made the more controversial claim that if someone has knowledge, they can’t do wrong. All wrongdoing comes from ignorance. If someone knows what’s right, they must and will undeniably do what’s right. Everyone seeks what’s good, but people have different ideas about what that is. "No one," Socrates said, "intentionally does wrong." People do wrong because they don’t understand the true concept of right and, being unaware, believe what they’re doing is good. "If someone intentionally does wrong," Socrates said again, "they are better than someone who does so unintentionally." The former has within them the essential condition of goodness, which is knowledge of what goodness is, but the latter, lacking that knowledge, is lost.

Aristotle, in commenting upon this whole doctrine, observed that Socrates had ignored or forgotten the irrational parts of the soul. Socrates imagined that everybody's actions are governed solely by reason, and that therefore if only they reasoned aright, they must do right. He forgot that the majority of men's actions are governed by passions and emotions, "the irrational parts of the soul." Aristotle's criticism of Socrates is unanswerable. All experience shows that men do deliberately do wrong, that, knowing well what is right, they nevertheless do wrong. But it is easy to see why Socrates made this mistake; he was arguing only from {148} his own case. Socrates really does appear to have been above human weakness. He was not guided by passions, but by reason, and it followed as the night follows the day, that if Socrates knew what was right, he did it. He was unable to understand how men, knowing the right, could yet do the wrong. If they are vicious, he thought, it must be because they do not know what is right. The criticism of Aristotle is thus justified. Yet for all that, the theory of Socrates is not to be too quickly brushed aside. There is more truth in it than appears at first sight. We say that a man believes one thing and does another. Yet it is a matter of question what a man really believes, and what is the test of his belief. Men go to church every Sunday, and there repeat formulas and prayers, of which the main idea is that all earthly riches are worthless in comparison with spiritual treasures. Such men, if asked, might tell us that they believe this to be true. They believe that they believe it. And yet in actual life, perhaps, they seek only for earthly riches, and behave as if they thought these the supreme good. What do such men really believe? Do they believe as they speak, or as they act? Is it not at least arguable that they are really pursuing what they believe to be good, and that, if they were genuinely convinced of the superiority of spiritual treasures, they would seek them, and not material riches? This at least is what Socrates thought. All men seek the good, but the many do not know what the good is. There is certainly truth in this in many cases, though in others there can be no doubt that men do deliberately what they know to be evil.

Aristotle, in his commentary on this entire doctrine, noted that Socrates overlooked or forgot the irrational parts of the soul. Socrates believed that everyone's actions are driven entirely by reason, and if only they reasoned correctly, they would act rightly. He failed to consider that most people's actions are influenced by passions and emotions, "the irrational parts of the soul." Aristotle's critique of Socrates is compelling. All experience shows that people can knowingly do wrong; even when they are aware of what is right, they still choose to do wrong. It’s easy to see why Socrates made this mistake; he was only considering his own perspective. Socrates truly seemed to be above human frailty. He was not swayed by passions, but by reason, and it naturally followed that if Socrates knew what was right, he would do it. He couldn't grasp how individuals, aware of the right path, could still go astray. He assumed that if people were immoral, it must be because they were unaware of what was right. Therefore, Aristotle's criticism stands. Nevertheless, Socrates' theory shouldn't be dismissed too quickly. There's more truth in it than initially meets the eye. We often say that a person believes one thing yet does another. However, it's debatable what a person genuinely believes and how we can test that belief. People attend church every Sunday, reciting formulas and prayers that emphasize how earthly wealth pales in comparison to spiritual treasures. If you asked them, they might say they believe this to be true. They believe they believe it. Yet, in real life, they might actually be chasing only earthly wealth, acting as if they consider it the highest good. So, what do these people really believe? Do they believe what they say, or what they do? Isn’t it at least arguable that they are genuinely pursuing what they think is good, and that if they were truly convinced of the superiority of spiritual treasures, they would seek those instead of material wealth? This is what Socrates believed. Everyone seeks the good, but many don’t understand what the good actually is. This holds true in many situations, although in others, there’s no doubt that people intentionally choose to do what they know is wrong.

There are two other characteristic Socratic propositions {149} which flow from the same general idea, that virtue is identical with knowledge. The first is, that virtue can be taught. We do not ordinarily think that virtue can be taught like arithmetic. We think that virtue depends upon a number of factors, prominent among which are the inborn disposition of a man, heredity, environment, modified to some extent by education, practice, and habit. The consequence is that a man's character does not change very much as he grows older. By constant practice, by continual self-control, a man may, to some extent, make himself better, but on the whole, what he is he remains. The leopard, we say, does not change his spots. But as, for Socrates, the sole condition of virtue is knowledge, and as knowledge is just what can be imparted by teaching, it followed that virtue must be teachable. The only difficulty is to find the teacher, to find some one who knows the concept of virtue. What the concept of virtue is--that is, thought Socrates, the precious piece of knowledge, which no philosopher has ever discovered, and which, if it were only discovered, could at once be imparted by teaching, whereupon men would at once become virtuous.

There are two other key Socratic ideas {149} that come from the same general thought: virtue is the same as knowledge. The first idea is that virtue can be taught. Typically, we don’t think of virtue as something that can be taught like math. We believe that virtue depends on several factors, mainly a person’s natural disposition, genetics, and environment, all influenced to some degree by education, practice, and habits. As a result, a person’s character doesn’t change much as they get older. Through constant practice and self-control, a person may improve themselves to some extent, but overall, they remain who they are. We say the leopard doesn’t change its spots. However, for Socrates, the only requirement for virtue is knowledge, and since knowledge can be taught, it follows that virtue can be taught as well. The real challenge is finding someone to teach it, a person who understands the essence of virtue. What this essence of virtue is—Socrates believed this to be the valuable knowledge that no philosopher has ever found, and if it could be discovered, it could be taught right away, allowing people to become virtuous immediately.

The other Socraticism is that "virtue is one." We talk of many virtues, temperance, prudence, foresight, benevolence, kindness, etc. Socrates believed that all these particular virtues flowed from the one source, knowledge. Therefore knowledge itself, that is to say, wisdom, is the sole virtue, and this includes all the others.

The other idea from Socratic philosophy is that "virtue is one." We refer to many virtues—like temperance, prudence, foresight, benevolence, kindness, and so on. Socrates believed that all these specific virtues come from a single source: knowledge. So, knowledge, or wisdom, is the only virtue, encompassing all the others.

This completes the exposition of the positive teaching of Socrates. It only remains for us to consider what position Socrates holds in the history of thought. There are two sides of the Socratic teaching. In the first {150} place, there is the doctrine of knowledge, that all knowledge is through concepts. This is the scientific side of the philosophy of Socrates. Secondly, there is his ethical teaching. Now the essential and important side of Socrates is undoubtedly the scientific theory of concepts. It is this which gives him his position in the history of philosophy. His ethical ideas, suggestive as they were, were yet all tainted with the fallacy that men are governed only by reason. Hence they have exercised no great influence on the history of thought. But the theory of concepts worked a revolution in philosophy. Upon a development of it is founded the whole of Plato's philosophy, and, through Plato, the philosophy of Aristotle, and, indeed, all subsequent idealism. The immediate effect of this theory, however, was the destruction of the teaching of the Sophists. The Sophists taught the doctrine that truth is sense-perception, and as the perceptions of different individuals differ in regard to the same object, it followed that truth became a matter of taste with the individual. This undermined all belief in truth as an objective reality, and, by similar reasoning, faith in the objectivity of the moral law was also destroyed. The essential position of Socrates is that of a restorer of faith. His greatness lay in the fact that he saw that the only way to combat the disastrous results of the Sophistic teaching was to refute the fundamental assumption from which all that teaching flowed, the assumption, namely, that knowledge is perception. Against this, therefore, Socrates opposed the doctrine that knowledge is through concepts. To base knowledge upon concepts is to base it upon the universality of reason, and therefore to restore it from the {151} position of a subjective seeming to that of an objective reality.

This wraps up the explanation of Socrates' positive teachings. Now we need to look at his role in the history of thought. There are two aspects of Socratic teaching. First, there’s the idea that all knowledge comes from concepts. This represents the scientific side of Socrates' philosophy. Second, there’s his moral teachings. The crucial and significant aspect of Socrates is undoubtedly the scientific theory of concepts, which establishes his place in the history of philosophy. Although his ethical ideas were thought-provoking, they were flawed by the belief that people are only guided by reason. As a result, they haven't had a significant impact on the evolution of thought. However, the theory of concepts sparked a revolution in philosophy. It laid the groundwork for all of Plato's philosophy, and through Plato, it influenced Aristotle's philosophy—and really, all later forms of idealism. The immediate consequence of this theory, though, was the downfall of Sophist teachings. The Sophists argued that truth is based on sense perception, and since different individuals perceive the same object differently, truth became a matter of personal opinion. This eroded belief in truth as an objective reality, and by similar logic, it also undermined faith in the objectivity of moral law. Socrates' key role was to restore faith. His greatness came from recognizing that the only way to counteract the damaging effects of Sophist teachings was to challenge the fundamental assumption that all knowledge is perception. In contrast, Socrates argued that knowledge comes from concepts. Grounding knowledge in concepts means grounding it in the universality of reason, thereby restoring it from a subjective illusion to an objective reality.

But though Socrates is thus a restorer of faith, we must not imagine that his thought is therefore a mere retrogression to the intellectual condition of pre-Sophistic times. It was, on the contrary, an advance beyond the Sophists. We have here, in fact, an example of what is the normal development of all thought, whether in the individual or the race. The movement of thought exhibits three stages. The first stage is positive belief, not founded upon reason; it is merely conventional belief. At the second stage thought becomes destructive and sceptical. It denies what was affirmed in the previous stage. The third stage is the restoration of positive belief now founded upon the concept, upon reason, and not merely upon custom. Before the time of the Sophists, men took it for granted that truth and goodness are objective realities; nobody specially affirmed it, because nobody denied it. It seemed obvious. It was, thus, not believed on rational grounds, but through custom and habit. This, the first stage of thought, we may call the era of simple faith. When the Sophists came upon the scene, they brought reason and thought to bear upon what had hitherto been accepted as a matter of course, namely law, custom, and authority. The first encroachment of reason upon simple faith is always destructive, and hence the Sophists undermined all ideals of goodness and truth. Socrates is the restorer of these ideals, but with him they are no longer the ideals of simple faith; they are the ideals of reason. They are based upon reason. Socrates substituted comprehending belief for unintelligent assent. We may contrast him, in this {152} respect, with Aristophanes. Aristophanes, the conservative, the believer in the "good old times," saw, as clearly as Socrates, the disastrous effects worked by the Sophists upon public morals. But the remedy he proposed was a violent return to the "good old times." Since it was thought which worked these ill effects, thought must be suppressed. We must go back to simple faith. But simple faith, once destroyed by thought, never returns either to the individual, or to the race. This can no more happen than a man can again become a child. There is only one remedy for the ills of thought, and that is, more thought. If thought, in its first inroads, leads, as it always does, to scepticism and denial, the only course is, not to suppress thought, but to found faith upon it. This was the method of Socrates, and it is the method, too, of all great spirits. They are not frightened of shadows. They have faith in reason. If reason leads them into the darkness, they do not scuttle back in fright. They advance till the light comes again. They are false teachers who counsel us to give no heed to the promptings of reason, if reason brings doubt into our beliefs. Thought cannot be thus suppressed. Reason has rights upon us as rational beings. We cannot go back. We must go on, and make our beliefs rational. We must found them upon the concept, as Socrates did. Socrates did not deny the principle of the Sophists that all institutions, all ideals, all existing and established things must justify themselves before the tribunal of reason. He accepted this without question. He took up the challenge of thought, and won the battle of reason in his day.

But even though Socrates is a restorer of faith, we shouldn't think that his ideas simply take us back to the intellectual state of pre-Sophistic times. Instead, it was a step forward beyond the Sophists. This situation actually illustrates the normal evolution of all thought, whether in an individual or society. The movement of thought goes through three stages. The first stage is positive belief, which isn’t based on reason; it’s merely conventional belief. In the second stage, thought becomes destructive and skeptical. It refutes what was accepted in the previous stage. The third stage is the restoration of positive belief, now based on concepts and reason, rather than just tradition. Before the Sophists, people assumed that truth and goodness were objective realities; no one specifically asserted it because no one denied it. It seemed obvious. Thus, it wasn’t believed for rational reasons, but rather through tradition and habit. We can call this first stage of thought the era of simple faith. When the Sophists appeared, they applied reason and thought to things that were previously taken for granted, like law, customs, and authority. The initial impact of reason on simple faith is always destructive, so the Sophists eroded all ideals of goodness and truth. Socrates restored these ideals, but for him, they were no longer just the ideals of simple faith; they became the ideals of reason. They were based on reason. Socrates replaced blind belief with informed understanding. We can contrast him in this respect with Aristophanes. Aristophanes, the conservative who believed in the "good old days," clearly recognized the damaging effects that the Sophists had on public morals, just like Socrates. However, the solution he proposed was a drastic return to the "good old days." Since it was thought that caused these negative effects, he believed that thought needed to be suppressed. We should return to simple faith. But once simple faith has been dismantled by thought, it doesn't come back to either individuals or society. Just like a person can't become a child again. The only solution for the problems caused by thought is more thought. If thought initially leads, as it always does, to skepticism and denial, the only path is not to suppress thought but to base faith on it. This was Socrates' approach, and it is also the approach of all great thinkers. They aren’t afraid of shadows. They trust in reason. If reason takes them into darkness, they don’t retreat in fear. They move forward until the light returns. Those who tell us to ignore reason when it introduces doubt into our beliefs are false teachers. Thought cannot be suppressed like that. Reason has rights over us as rational beings. We can’t go back. We must move forward and make our beliefs rational. We need to base them on concepts, just like Socrates did. Socrates didn’t reject the Sophists’ principle that all institutions, ideals, and established things must justify themselves through reason. He accepted this challenge without hesitation. He embraced the challenge of thought and triumphed in the battle for reason in his time.

The Sophists brought to light the principle of subjectivity, the principle that the truth must be my truth, {153} and the right my right. They must be the products of my own thinking, not standards forcibly imposed upon me from without. But the mistake of the Sophists was to imagine that the truth must be mine, merely in my capacity as a percipient creature of sense, which means that I have a private truth of my own. Socrates corrected this by admitting that the truth must be my truth, but mine in my capacity as a rational being, which means, since reason is the universal, that it is not my private truth, but universal truth which is shared by and valid for all rational beings. Truth is thus established as being not mere subjective appearance, but objective reality, independent of the sensations, whims, and self-will of the individual. The whole period of Socrates and the Sophists is full of instruction. Its essential lesson is that to deny the supremacy of reason, to set up any other process of consciousness above reason, must inevitably end in scepticism and the denial of the objectivity of truth and morality. Many theosophists and others, at the present day, teach the doctrine of what they call "intuition." The supreme kind of religious knowledge, they think, is to be reached by intuition, which is conceived as something higher than reason. But this is simply to make the mistake of Protagoras over again. It is true that this so-called intuition is not merely sense-perception, as was the case with Protagoras. It is, however, a form of immediate spiritual perception. It is immediate apprehension of the object as being present to me, as having thereness. It is therefore of the nature of perception. It is spiritual and super-sensuous, as opposed to material and sensuous, perception. But it makes no difference at all whether perception is sensuous {154} or super-sensuous. To place the truth in any sort of perception is, in principle, to do as Protagoras did, to yield oneself up a helpless prey to the subjective impressions of the individual. I intuit one thing; another man intuits the opposite. What I intuit must be true for me, what he intuits true for him. For we have denied reason, we have placed it below intuition, and have thereby discarded that which alone can subject the varying impressions of each individual to the rule of a universal and objective standard. The logical conclusion is that, since each man's intuition is true for him, there is no such thing as an objective truth. Nor can there be such a thing, in these circumstances, as an objective goodness. Thus the theory must end in total scepticism and darkness. The fact that theosophists do not, as a matter of fact, draw these sceptical conclusions, simply means that they are not as clear-headed and logical as Protagoras was.

The Sophists highlighted the idea of subjectivity, the belief that truth must be my truth, {153} and the right my right. These truths need to come from my own reasoning, not standards that are forced on me from the outside. However, the Sophists erred in thinking that truth must be my own simply because I am a sensory being, which implies that I have a personal truth. Socrates corrected this by acknowledging that the truth must be my truth, but not just as an individual, rather as a rational being. This means that, because reason is universal, my truth is not a private one but a universal truth that is valid for all rational beings. Therefore, truth is established as something more than subjective appearance; it is an objective reality, independent of personal sensations, whims, and individual will. The entire period of Socrates and the Sophists offers valuable lessons. The main takeaway is that rejecting the supremacy of reason and elevating any other mode of consciousness above it inevitably leads to skepticism and the denial of objective truth and morality. Nowadays, many theosophists and others promote the idea of what they call "intuition." They believe that the highest form of religious knowledge comes through intuition, seen as something greater than reason. Yet, this simply repeats Protagoras's mistake. While this so-called intuition is not just sense-perception as with Protagoras, it still constitutes a form of immediate spiritual perception. It refers to the direct awareness of something as present to me, having thereness. Thus, it is still a type of perception. It is spiritual and beyond the senses, in contrast to material and sensory perception. However, it doesn't matter if perception is sensory {154} or super-sensory. To position truth in any form of perception is, in principle, to do exactly what Protagoras did, surrendering oneself to the subjective impressions of individuals. I may intuit one thing; someone else may intuit the opposite. What I intuit is true for me, and what he intuits is true for him. By denying reason and placing it beneath intuition, we discard the only thing that can align the differing impressions of individuals with a universal and objective standard. The logical result is that if each person's intuition is true for them, then there is no such thing as an objective truth. Under these circumstances, there cannot be objective goodness either. Therefore, this theory ends in complete skepticism and confusion. The fact that theosophists do not reach these skeptical conclusions simply indicates that they are not as clear and logical as Protagoras was.


THE SEMI-SOCRATICS

THE SEMI-SOCRATICS

Upon the death of Socrates there ensued a phenomenon which is not infrequent in the history of thought. A great and many-sided personality combines in himself many conflicting tendencies and ideas. Let us take an example, not, however, from the sphere of intellect, but from the sphere of practical life. We often say that it is difficult to reconcile mercy and justice. Among the many small personalities, one man follows only the ideal of mercy, and as his mercy has not in it the stern stuff of justice, it degenerates into mawkishness and sentimental humanitarianism. Another man follows only the ideal of justice, forgetting mercy, and he becomes harsh and unsympathetic. It takes a greater man, a larger personality, harmoniously to combine the two. And as it is in the sphere of practical life, so it is in the arena of thought and philosophy. A great thinker is not he who seizes upon a single aspect of the truth, and pushes that to its extreme limit, but the man who combines, in one many-sided system, all the varying and conflicting sides of truth. By emphasizing one thought, by being obsessed by a single idea and pushing it to its logical conclusion, regardless of the other aspects of the truth, one may indeed achieve a considerable local and {156} temporary reputation; because such a procedure often leads to striking paradoxes, to strange and seemingly uncommon conclusions. The reputations of such men as Nietzsche, Bernard Shaw, Oscar Wilde, are made chiefly in this way. But upon the death of a great all-embracing personality, just because his thought is a combination of so many divergent truths, we often find that it splits up into its component parts, each of which gives rise to a one-sided school of thought. The disciples, being smaller men, are not able to grasp the great man's thought in its wholeness and many-sidedness. Each disciple seizes upon that portion of his master's teaching which has most in common with his own temperament, and proceeds to erect this one incomplete idea into a philosophy, treating the part as if it were the whole. This is exactly what happened after the death of Socrates. Only one man among his disciples was able to grasp the whole of his teaching, and understand the whole of his personality, and that was Plato. Among the lesser men who were the followers and personal friends of Socrates, there were three who founded schools of philosophy, each partial and one-sided, but each claiming to be the exponent of the true Socraticism. Antisthenes founded the Cynic school, Aristippus the Cyrenaic, and Euclid the Megaric.

After Socrates died, something happened that isn't uncommon in the history of ideas. A great and complex personality often embodies many conflicting tendencies and ideas. Let’s look at an example, not from the realm of thought, but from everyday life. We often say that it's tough to balance mercy and justice. Among many smaller personalities, one person focuses solely on mercy, and because their mercy lacks the firmness of justice, it turns into excessive sentimentality and shallow humanitarianism. Another individual concentrates only on justice, ignoring mercy, and becomes harsh and uncaring. It takes a greater individual, a more comprehensive personality, to harmoniously blend the two. Just as this applies to practical life, it also applies to thought and philosophy. A great thinker isn’t someone who only focuses on one aspect of the truth and takes it to its furthest extreme, but rather, it's someone who integrates all the different and conflicting sides of truth into a unified system. By emphasizing one idea, becoming fixated on a single thought, and pushing it to its logical extreme while ignoring other truths, a person can gain significant, though often temporary, recognition; such an approach frequently leads to striking paradoxes and unusual conclusions. The reputations of individuals like Nietzsche, Bernard Shaw, and Oscar Wilde often emerge this way. However, after a great all-encompassing personality dies, because their thought combines so many divergent truths, we often see it fragment into its individual parts, each giving rise to a narrow school of thought. The followers, being lesser thinkers, cannot grasp the totality and depth of the great thinker’s ideas. Each disciple picks the part of their teacher’s teachings that aligns most closely with their own temperament and then builds this one incomplete idea into a philosophy, treating the part as if it were the whole. This is precisely what occurred after Socrates' death. Only one of his disciples truly understood the entirety of his teachings and his full personality—that was Plato. Among the lesser men who were followers and close friends of Socrates, three established philosophical schools, each one-sided and incomplete, yet each claiming to represent true Socraticism. Antisthenes founded the Cynic school, Aristippus the Cyrenaic, and Euclid the Megaric.

Now, of the two aspects of the Socratic philosophy, the theory of concepts, and the ethical theory, it is easy for us, looking back upon history, to see which it was that influenced the history of thought most, and which, therefore, was the most important. But the men of his own time could not see this. What they fastened upon was the obvious aspect of Socrates, his ethics, and above all the ethical teaching which was expressed, not so {157} much in abstract ideas, as in the life and personality of the master. Both this life and this teaching might be summed up in the thought that virtue is the sole end of life, that, as against virtue, all else in the world, comfort, riches, learning, is comparatively worthless. It is this, then, that virtue is the sole end of life, which forms the point of agreement between all the three semi-Socratic schools. We have now to see upon what points they diverge from one another.

Now, of the two aspects of Socratic philosophy, the theory of concepts and the ethical theory, it's easy for us to look back at history and see which one had the greatest influence on the history of thought and was therefore the most significant. However, the people in his time couldn’t see this. What they focused on was the more apparent aspect of Socrates—his ethics—and especially the ethical teachings that were conveyed not so much in abstract ideas, but through the life and personality of the master. Both his life and teachings could be summarized in the belief that virtue is the ultimate goal of life, and that everything else in the world—comfort, wealth, knowledge—pales in comparison to virtue. This belief that virtue is the ultimate goal of life forms the common ground between all three semi-Socratic schools. Now, we need to examine the points at which they diverge from one another.

If virtue is the sole end of life, what precisely is virtue? Socrates had given no clear answer to this question. The only definition he had given was that virtue is knowledge, but upon examination it turns out that this is not a definition at all. Virtue is knowledge, but knowledge of what? It is not knowledge of astronomy, of mathematics, or of physics. It is ethical knowledge, that is to say, knowledge of virtue. To define virtue as the knowledge of virtue is to think in a circle, and gets us no further in the enquiry what virtue is. But Socrates, as a matter of fact, did not think in a circle. He did not mean that virtue is knowledge, although his doctrine is often, somewhat misleadingly, stated in that form. What he meant was--quite a different thing--that virtue depends upon knowledge. It is the first condition of virtue. The principle, accurately stated, is, not that virtue is the knowledge of virtue, which is thinking in a circle, but that virtue depends upon the knowledge of virtue, which is quite straight thinking. Only if you know what virtue is can you be virtuous. Hence we have not here any definition of virtue, or any attempt to define it. We are still left with the question, "what is virtue?" unanswered.

If virtue is the ultimate goal of life, what exactly is virtue? Socrates didn’t provide a clear answer to this question. The only definition he offered was that virtue is knowledge, but when we look closer, it turns out that this isn’t really a definition. Virtue is knowledge, but knowledge of what? It’s not about astronomy, mathematics, or physics. It’s ethical knowledge, which means understanding virtue. Defining virtue as the knowledge of virtue is circular reasoning and doesn’t help us progress in understanding what virtue actually is. However, Socrates didn’t engage in circular reasoning. He didn't mean to say that virtue is knowledge, even though his beliefs are often inaccurately summarized that way. What he actually meant was something quite different: that virtue depends upon knowledge. Knowledge is the fundamental requirement for virtue. The principle should be stated accurately: virtue is not the knowledge of virtue (which is circular thinking) but rather that virtue depends on the knowledge of virtue (which is clear thinking). Only by knowing what virtue is can you be virtuous. So we still don't have a definition of virtue or any attempt to define it. The question, "what is virtue?" remains unanswered.

No doubt this was due in part to the unmethodical and unsystematic manner in which Socrates developed his thought, and this, in its turn, was due to his conversational style of philosophizing. For it is not possible to develop systematic thinking in the course of casual conversations. But in part, too, it was due to the very universality of the man's genius. He was broad enough to realize that it is not possible to tie down virtue in any single narrow formula, which shall serve as a practical receipt for action in all the infinitely various circumstances of life. So that, in spite of the fact that his whole principle lay in the method of definitions, Socrates, in fact, left his followers without any definition of the supreme concept of his philosophy, virtue. It was upon this point, therefore, that the followers of Socrates disagreed. They all agreed that virtue is the sole end of life, but they developed different ideas as to what sort of life is in fact virtuous.

No doubt this was partly due to the unstructured and unsystematic way Socrates developed his ideas, which was a result of his conversational approach to philosophy. It’s not possible to create systematic thinking during casual chats. But it was also because of the remarkable breadth of his genius. He was wise enough to understand that you can’t define virtue with a single, narrow formula that would apply to all the countless situations in life. So, even though his entire philosophy centered on definitions, Socrates actually left his followers without a clear definition of the central concept of his philosophy, virtue. This was the point where Socrates’ followers disagreed. They all agreed that virtue is the ultimate goal of life, but they each had different views on what type of life is genuinely virtuous.


The Cynics.

The Cynics.

Antisthenes, the founder of the Cynic School, repeated the familiar propositions that virtue is founded upon knowledge, is teachable, and is one. But what aroused the admiration of Antisthenes was not Socrates, the man of intellect, the man of science, the philosopher, but Socrates, the man of independent character, who followed his own notions of right with complete indifference to the opinions of others. This independence was in fact merely a by-product of the Socratic life. Socrates had been independent of all earthly goods and possessions, caring neither for riches nor for applause, only because his heart was set upon a greater treasure, the acquisition of wisdom. Mere independence and indifference to the {159} opinions of others were not for him ends in themselves. He did not make fetishes of them. But the Cynics interpreted his teaching to mean that the independence of earthly pleasures and possessions is in itself the end and object of life. This, in fact, was their definition of virtue, complete renunciation of everything that, for ordinary men, makes life worth living, absolute asceticism, and rigorous self-mortification. Socrates, again, thinking that the only knowledge of supreme value is ethical knowledge, had exhibited a tendency to disparage other kinds of knowledge. This trait the Cynics exaggerated into a contempt for all art and learning so great as frequently to amount to ignorance and boorishness. "Virtue is sufficient for happiness," said Antisthenes, "and for virtue nothing is requisite but the strength of a Socrates; it is a matter of action, and does not require many words, or much learning." The Cynic ideal of virtue is thus purely negative; it is the absence of all desire, freedom from all wants, complete independence of all possessions. Many of them refused to own houses or any dwelling place, and wandered about as vagrants and beggars. Diogenes, for the same reason, lived in a tub. Socrates, following single-heartedly what he knew to be good, cared nothing what the vulgar said. But this indifference to the opinion of others was, like his independence of possessions, not an end in itself. He did not interpret it to mean that he was wantonly to offend public opinion. But the Cynics, to show their indifference, flouted public opinion, and gave frequent and disgusting exhibitions of indecency.

Antisthenes, the founder of the Cynic School, repeated the familiar ideas that virtue is based on knowledge, can be taught, and is unified. However, what impressed Antisthenes was not Socrates, the intellectual and philosopher, but Socrates, the person with strong character who followed his own sense of right without caring about what others thought. This independence was actually a natural result of the Socratic way of life. Socrates was detached from worldly goods and possessions, indifferent to wealth or fame, because he valued a greater treasure: the pursuit of wisdom. For him, mere independence and indifference to others' opinions were not ends in themselves. He didn’t idolize them. But the Cynics interpreted his teachings as if the rejection of earthly pleasures and possessions was the ultimate goal in life. This became their definition of virtue: total renunciation of everything that most people find meaningful, extreme asceticism, and harsh self-denial. Socrates believed that the only knowledge that truly matters is ethical knowledge, and he tended to undervalue other types of knowledge. The Cynics distorted this tendency into a disdain for all forms of art and learning, often resulting in ignorance and rudeness. "Virtue is enough for happiness," said Antisthenes, "and the only thing needed for virtue is the strength of a Socrates; it’s about action, requiring neither lengthy words nor extensive knowledge." The Cynic ideal of virtue is therefore purely negative; it's the absence of desire, freedom from wants, and complete independence from possessions. Many of them refused to own houses or any place to live and instead roamed as vagrants and beggars. Diogenes, for example, lived in a tub for the same reason. Socrates, focused solely on what he believed to be good, didn’t care about the opinions of common people. However, his indifference to what others thought was not a goal in itself; he didn’t see it as a reason to deliberately offend public opinion. In contrast, the Cynics flaunted their indifference by disregarding public opinion and often displayed indecency in an outrageous manner.

Virtue, for the Cynics, is alone good. Vice is the only evil. Nothing else in the world is either good or bad. {160} Everything else is "indifferent." Property, pleasure, wealth, freedom, comfort, even life itself, are not to be regarded as goods. Poverty, misery, illness, slavery, and death itself, are not to be regarded as evils. It is no better to be a freeman than a slave, for if the slave have virtue, he is in himself free, and a born ruler. Suicide is not a crime, and a man may destroy his life, not however to escape from misery and pain (for these are not ills), but to show that for him life is indifferent. And as the line between virtue and vice is absolutely definite, so is the distinction between the wise man and the fool. All men are divided into these two classes. There is no middle term between them. Virtue being one and indivisible, either a man possesses it whole or does not possess it at all. In the former case he is a wise man, in the latter case a fool. The wise man possesses all virtue, all knowledge, all wisdom, all happiness, all perfection. The fool possesses all evil, all misery, all imperfection.

For the Cynics, virtue is the only true good. Vice is the only real evil. Everything else in the world is neither good nor bad. {160} Everything else is "indifferent." Things like property, pleasure, wealth, freedom, comfort, and even life itself should not be seen as goods. Poverty, suffering, illness, slavery, and even death should not be regarded as evils. Being free is no better than being a slave, because if a slave has virtue, he is internally free and a natural leader. Suicide is not a crime, and a person can end his life, not to escape from suffering and pain (since those are not true ills), but to demonstrate that life is indifferent to him. Just as the line between virtue and vice is completely clear, so too is the distinction between the wise person and the fool. Everyone falls into one of these two categories. There is no middle ground. Virtue is one and indivisible; a person either has it fully or not at all. In the first case, he is a wise person; in the second case, he is a fool. The wise person has all virtue, all knowledge, all wisdom, all happiness, and all perfection. The fool has all vice, all misery, and all imperfection.


The Cyrenaics.

The Cyrenaics.

For the Cyrenaics, too, virtue is, at least formally, the sole object of life. It is only formally, however, because they give to virtue a definition which robbed it of all meaning. Socrates had not infrequently recommended virtue on account of the advantages which it brings. Virtue, he said, is the sole path to happiness, and he had not refrained from holding out happiness as a motive for virtue. This did not mean, however, that he did not recognize a man's duty to do the right for its own sake, and not for the sake of the advantage it brings. "Honesty," we say, "is the best policy," {161} but we do not mean thereby to deny that it is the duty of men to be honest even if it is not, in some particular case, the best policy. Socrates, however, had not been very clear upon these points, and had been unable to find any definite basis for morality, other than that of happiness. It was this side of his teaching which Aristippus now pressed to its logical conclusions, regardless of all other claims. Doubtless virtue is the sole end of life, but the sole end of virtue is one's own advantage, that is to say, pleasure. One may as well say at once that the sole end of life is pleasure.

For the Cyrenaics, virtue is, at least in theory, the only goal of life. However, it's only in theory because they define virtue in a way that takes away its real meaning. Socrates often promoted virtue because of the benefits it brings. He stated that virtue is the only path to happiness, and he didn't hesitate to present happiness as a reason to be virtuous. This didn’t mean he didn’t understand that a person should do the right thing for its own sake, not just for the benefits it may provide. We say, "Honesty is the best policy," {161} but we don’t intend to imply that people shouldn’t be honest even if it’s not the best policy in a particular case. However, Socrates wasn’t very clear on these matters and couldn’t establish any solid foundation for morality other than happiness. This aspect of his teachings is what Aristippus highlighted and took to its logical extremes, ignoring all other considerations. Certainly, virtue is the only purpose of life, but the only purpose of virtue is personal gain, which means pleasure. One might as well say that the only purpose of life is pleasure.

The influence of Protagoras and the Sophists also played its part in moulding the thought of Aristippus. Protagoras had denied the objectivity of truth, and the later Sophists had applied the same theory to morals. Each man is a law unto himself. There is no moral code binding upon the individual against his own wishes. Aristippus combined this with his doctrine of pleasure. Pleasure being the sole end of life, no moral law externally imposed can invalidate its absolute claims. Nothing is wicked, nothing evil, provided only it satisfies the individual's thirst for pleasure.

The impact of Protagoras and the Sophists also influenced Aristippus's thinking. Protagoras rejected the idea of objective truth, and later Sophists extended this idea to morals. Each person creates their own rules. There's no moral code that binds someone if it goes against their desires. Aristippus merged this with his belief in pleasure. Since pleasure is the ultimate goal of life, no external moral law can undermine its absolute importance. Nothing is wrong or evil as long as it satisfies a person's desire for pleasure.

Whether such a philosophy will lead, in practice, to the complete degradation of its devotees, depends chiefly upon what sort of pleasure they have in mind. If refined and intellectual pleasures are meant, there is no reason why a comparatively good life should not result. If bodily pleasures are intended, the results are not likely to be noble. The Cyrenaics by no means wholly ignored the pleasures of the mind, but they pointed out that feelings of bodily pleasure are more potent and intense, and it was upon these, therefore, that they chiefly {162} concentrated their attention. Nevertheless they were saved from the lowest abysses of sensuality and bestiality by their doctrine that, in the pursuit of pleasure, the wise man must exercise prudence. Completely unrestrained pursuit of pleasure leads in fact to pain and disaster. Pain is that which has to be avoided. Therefore the wise man will remain always master of himself, will control his desires, and postpone a more urgent to a less urgent desire, if thereby in the end more pleasure and less pain will accrue to him. The Cyrenaic ideal of the wise man is the man of the world, bent indeed solely upon pleasure, restrained by no superstitious scruples, yet pursuing his end with prudence, foresight, and intelligence. Such principles would, of course, admit of various interpretations, according to the temperament of the individual. We may notice two examples. Anniceris, the Cyrenaic, believed indeed that pleasure is the sole end, but set such store upon the pleasures that arise from friendship and family affection, that he admitted that the wise man should be ready to sacrifice himself for his friends or family--a gleam of light in the moral darkness. Hegesias, a pessimist, considered that positive enjoyment is impossible of attainment. In practice the sole end of life which can be realized is the avoidance of pain.

Whether this philosophy leads to the complete downfall of its followers really depends on what kind of pleasure they have in mind. If they’re thinking about sophisticated and intellectual pleasures, there’s no reason a reasonably good life can’t come from that. However, if they’re focused on physical pleasures, the outcomes are unlikely to be admirable. The Cyrenaics didn’t completely ignore mental pleasures, but they highlighted that physical pleasures are stronger and more intense, which is why they mostly concentrated on those. Still, they avoided the lowest depths of hedonism and animalistic behavior by teaching that the wise person must exercise caution in the pursuit of pleasure. An unrestrained chase after pleasure can actually lead to pain and disaster. Pain is what should be avoided. Therefore, the wise person keeps control of themselves, manages their desires, and prioritizes the less urgent over the more urgent desires if it means ultimately gaining more pleasure and less pain. The Cyrenaic ideal of the wise person is someone who is focused solely on pleasure, unbound by superstitious fears, yet approaches their goal with caution, foresight, and intelligence. Naturally, these principles can be interpreted differently based on a person's temperament. For instance, Anniceris, a Cyrenaic thinker, believed pleasure is the only goal but valued the pleasures that come from friendship and family so highly that he argued the wise person should be willing to sacrifice themselves for loved ones—a spark of light in moral darkness. On the other hand, Hegesias, a pessimist, thought that real enjoyment is unattainable. He argued that the only achievable goal in life is avoiding pain.


The Megarics.

The Megaricks.

Euclid of Megara was the founder of this school. His principle was a combination of Socraticism with Eleaticism. Virtue is knowledge, but knowledge of what? It is here that the Eleatic influence became visible. With Parmenides, the Megarics believed in the One Absolute Being. All multiplicity, all motion, are illusory. {163} the world of sense has in it no true reality. Only Being is. If virtue is knowledge, therefore, it can only be the knowledge of this Being. If the essential concept of Socrates was the Good and the essential concept of Parmenides Being, Euclid now combined the two. The Good is identified with Being. Being, the One, God, the Good, divinity, are merely different names for one and the same thing. Becoming, the many, Evil, are the names of its opposite, not-being, Multiplicity is thus identified with evil, and both are declared illusory. Evil has no real existence. The Good alone truly is. The various virtues, as benevolence, temperance, prudence, are merely different names for the one virtue, knowledge of Being.

Euclid of Megara was the founder of this school. His principle was a mix of Socratic thinking and Eleatic philosophy. Virtue is knowledge, but knowledge of what? This is where the Eleatic influence became clear. Like Parmenides, the Megarics believed in the One Absolute Being. All diversity and movement are just illusions. The world of senses has no true reality. Only Being exists. If virtue is knowledge, then it can only be the knowledge of this Being. If Socrates' essential concept was the Good and Parmenides' was Being, Euclid combined the two. The Good is equated with Being. Being, the One, God, the Good, divinity, are just different names for the same thing. Becoming, the many, Evil, are names for its opposite, not-being. Multiplicity is therefore linked to evil, and both are considered illusory. Evil has no real existence. The Good alone truly exists. The various virtues, like benevolence, temperance, and prudence, are simply different names for the one virtue, which is the knowledge of Being.

Zeno, the Eleatic, had shown that multiplicity and motion are not only unreal but even impossible, since they are self-contradictory. The Megarics appropriated this idea, together with the dialectic of Zeno, and concluded that since not-being is impossible, Being includes all possibility. Whatever is possible is also actual. There is no such thing as a possible something, which yet does not exist.

Zeno, the Eleatic, demonstrated that multiplicity and motion are not just unreal but actually impossible, because they are self-contradictory. The Megarics took this idea, along with Zeno's dialectic, and concluded that since non-existence is impossible, Being encompasses all possibility. Anything that is possible is also actual. There’s no such thing as something that is possible but doesn’t exist.

As the Cynics found virtue in renunciation and negative independence, the Cyrenaics in the hedonistic pursuit of pleasure, so the Megarics find it in the life of philosophic contemplation, the knowledge of Being.

As the Cynics discovered virtue in giving up things and being self-sufficient, and the Cyrenaics found it in the pursuit of pleasure, the Megarics find it in a life of philosophical contemplation and understanding the nature of existence.


PLATO

PLATO

None of the predecessors of Plato had constructed a system of philosophy. What they had produced, and in great abundance, were isolated philosophical ideas, theories, hints, and suggestions. Plato was the first person in the history of the world to produce a great all-embracing system of philosophy, which has its ramifications in all departments of thought and reality. In doing this, Plato laid all previous thought under contribution. He gathered the entire harvest of Greek philosophy. All that was best in the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, Heracleitus, and Socrates, reappears, transfigured in the system of Plato. But it is not to be imagined, on this account, that Plato was a mere eclectic, or a plagiarist, who took the best thoughts of others, and worked them into some sort of a patch-work philosophy of his own. He was, on the contrary, in the highest degree an original thinker. But like all great systems of thought, that of Plato grows out of the thought of previous thinkers. He does indeed appropriate the ideas of Heracleitus, Parmenides, and Socrates. But he does not leave them as he finds them. He takes them as the germs of a new development. They are the foundations, below ground, upon which he builds the palace of philosophy. In his hands, all previous thought becomes {165} transfigured under the light of a new and original principle.

None of Plato's predecessors had created a system of philosophy. What they produced, in abundance, were isolated philosophical ideas, theories, hints, and suggestions. Plato was the first person in history to develop a comprehensive system of philosophy that touches on all areas of thought and reality. In doing this, Plato built upon all previous ideas. He gathered the entire body of Greek philosophy. All that was best in the Pythagoreans, the Eleatics, Heraclitus, and Socrates is transformed in Plato's system. However, it shouldn't be assumed that Plato was simply an eclectic or a plagiarist who took the best ideas of others to create a patchwork philosophy. On the contrary, he was an extremely original thinker. Like all great philosophical systems, Plato's work emerges from the ideas of earlier thinkers. He does take the ideas of Heraclitus, Parmenides, and Socrates, but he doesn’t leave them as he found them. He uses them as the seeds for a new development. They are the foundations, underground, upon which he constructs the palace of philosophy. In his hands, all previous thought becomes {165} transformed under the light of a new and original principle.


1. Life and Writings.

Life and Works.

The exact date of the birth of Plato is a matter of doubt. But the date usually given, 429-7 B.C. cannot be far wrong. He came of an aristocratic Athenian family, and was possessed of sufficient wealth to enable him to command that leisure which was essential for a life devoted to philosophy. His youth coincided with the most disastrous period of Athenian history. After a bitter struggle, which lasted over a quarter of a century, the Peloponnesian war ended in the complete downfall of Athens as a political power. And the internal affairs of the State were in no less confusion than the external. Here, as elsewhere, a triumphant democracy had developed into mob-rule. Then at the close of the Peloponnesian war, the aristocratic party again came into power with the Thirty Tyrants, among whom were some of Plato's own relatives. But the aristocratic party, so far from improving affairs, plunged at once into a reign of bloodshed, terror, and oppression. These facts have an important bearing upon the history of Plato's life. If he ever possessed any desire to adopt a political career, the actual condition of Athenian affairs must have quenched it. An aristocrat, both in thought and by birth, he could not accommodate himself to the rule of the mob. And if he ever imagined that the return of the aristocracy to power would improve matters, he must have been bitterly disillusioned by the proceedings of the Thirty Tyrants. Disgusted alike with the democracy and the aristocracy he seems to have retired into seclusion. He never once, throughout his long life, appeared as a {166} speaker in the popular assembly. He regarded the Athenian constitution as past help.

The exact date of Plato's birth is unclear. However, the commonly accepted date, 429-7 B.C., is likely accurate. He came from a wealthy aristocratic Athenian family, which allowed him the leisure necessary for a life dedicated to philosophy. His youth coincided with a very turbulent time in Athenian history. After a harsh struggle that lasted more than 25 years, the Peloponnesian War ended with Athens completely losing its political power. The state’s internal situation was just as chaotic as its external one. There, as in other places, a victorious democracy turned into mob rule. After the Peloponnesian War ended, the aristocratic faction regained control with the Thirty Tyrants, some of whom were related to Plato. However, instead of improving conditions, this aristocratic group quickly descended into a period of violence, fear, and oppression. These events significantly impacted Plato's life. If he ever wanted to pursue a political career, the state of Athens must have killed that ambition. As both an aristocrat by birth and thought, he couldn't adapt to mob rule. And if he thought the return of the aristocracy would bring positive change, the actions of the Thirty Tyrants likely disillusioned him. Disenchanted with both democracy and aristocracy, he seemingly chose to withdraw into solitude. Throughout his long life, he never appeared as a public speaker in the assembly. He believed the Athenian constitution was beyond saving.

Not much is known of the philosopher's youth. He composed poems. He was given the best education that an Athenian citizen of those days could obtain. His teacher, Cratylus, was a follower of Heracleitus, and Plato no doubt learned from him the doctrines of that philosopher. It is improbable that he allowed himself to remain unacquainted with the disputations of the Sophists, many of whom were his own contemporaries. He probably read the book of Anaxagoras, which was easily obtainable in Athens at the time. But on all these points we have no certain information. What we do know is that the decisive event in his youth, and indeed in his life, was his association with Socrates.

Not much is known about the philosopher's early years. He wrote poems. He received the best education available to an Athenian citizen of that time. His teacher, Cratylus, was a follower of Heracleitus, and Plato likely learned the teachings of that philosopher from him. It's unlikely that he didn't engage with the debates of the Sophists, many of whom were his contemporaries. He probably read Anaxagoras's book, which was easily accessible in Athens then. However, we have no definite information on all these points. What we do know is that the key event in his youth, and indeed in his life, was his relationship with Socrates.

For the last eight years of the life of Socrates, Plato was his friend and his faithful disciple. The teaching and personality of the master constituted the supreme intellectual impulse of his life, and the inspiration of his entire thought. And the devotion and esteem which he felt for Socrates, so far from waning as the years went by, seem, on the contrary, to have grown continually stronger. For it is precisely in the latest dialogues of his long life that some of the most charming and admiring portraits of Socrates are to be found. Socrates became for him the pattern and exemplar of the true philosopher.

For the last eight years of Socrates' life, Plato was his friend and devoted student. Socrates' teachings and personality were the greatest intellectual inspiration for Plato, influencing all his thoughts. Far from diminishing over time, Plato's respect and admiration for Socrates seemed to grow stronger. In fact, it’s in the later dialogues of his life that we find some of the most beautiful and admiring depictions of Socrates. Socrates became the model and example of what a true philosopher should be for Plato.

After the death of Socrates a second period opens in the life of Plato, the period of his travels. He migrated first to Megara, where his friend and fellow-disciple Euclid was then founding the Megaric school. The Megaric philosophy was a combination of the thought of Socrates with that of the Eleatics. And it was no doubt here, at {167} Megara, under the influence of Euclid, that Plato formed his deeper acquaintance with the teaching of Parmenides, which exercised an all-important influence upon his own philosophy. From Megara he travelled to Cyrene, Egypt, Italy, and Sicily. In Italy he came in contact with the Pythagoreans. And to the effects of this journey may be attributed the strong Pythagorean elements which permeate his thought.

After the death of Socrates, a new chapter began in Plato's life: the period of his travels. He first went to Megara, where his friend and fellow student Euclid was starting the Megaric school. The Megaric philosophy blended Socratic ideas with those of the Eleatics. It was likely here, in Megara, influenced by Euclid, that Plato gained a deeper understanding of Parmenides' teachings, which significantly impacted his own philosophy. From Megara, he traveled to Cyrene, Egypt, Italy, and Sicily. In Italy, he encountered the Pythagoreans. The influence of this journey is evident in the strong Pythagorean elements that permeate his ideas.

In Sicily he attended the court of Dionysius the Elder, tyrant of Syracuse. But here his conduct seems to have given grave offence. Dionysius was so angered by his moralizings and philosophical diatribes that he put Plato up to auction in the slave market. Plato narrowly escaped the fate of slavery, but was ransomed by Anniceris, the Cyrenaic. He then returned to Athens, his travels having occupied a period of about ten years.

In Sicily, he went to the court of Dionysius the Elder, the tyrant of Syracuse. However, his behavior apparently caused serious offense. Dionysius became so upset by his moral lectures and philosophical rants that he put Plato up for sale in the slave market. Plato narrowly avoided the fate of slavery, as he was bought back by Anniceris, the Cyrenaic. He then returned to Athens, after spending around ten years traveling.

With the return of Plato to Athens we enter upon the third and last period of his life. With the exception of two journeys to be mentioned shortly, he never again left Athens. He now appeared for the first time as a professional teacher and philosopher. He chose for the scene of his activities a gymnasium, called the Academy. Here he gradually collected round him a circle of pupils and disciples. For the rest of his life, a period of about forty years, he occupied himself in literary activity, and in the management of the school which he had founded. His manner of life was in strong contrast to that of Socrates. Only in one respect did he resemble his master. He took no fees for his teaching. Otherwise the lives of the two great men bear no resemblance to each other. Socrates had gone out into the highways and byways in search of wisdom. He had wrangled in {168} the market-place with all comers. Plato withdrew himself into the seclusion of a school, protected from the hubbub of the world by a ring of faithful disciples. It was not to be expected that a man of Plato's refinement, culture, and aristocratic feelings, should appreciate, as Socrates, the man of the people, had done, the rough-and-tumble life of the Athenian market-place. Nor was it desirable for the advancement of philosophy that it should be so. The Socratic philosophy had suffered from the Socratic manner of life. It was unmethodical and inchoate. Systematic thought is not born of disputes at the street corner. For the development of a great world-system, such as that of Plato, laborious study and quiet seclusion were essential.

With Plato's return to Athens, we enter the third and final phase of his life. Aside from two upcoming trips, he never left Athens again. He now emerged as a professional teacher and philosopher for the first time. He chose a gymnasium called the Academy as the setting for his work. Here, he gradually gathered a group of students and followers around him. For the next forty years, he focused on writing and managing the school he founded. His lifestyle was very different from Socrates’. The only similarity was that he didn’t charge fees for his teaching. Otherwise, the lives of these two great men were quite different. Socrates wandered through the streets seeking wisdom, engaging in debates in the market with anyone who would talk. Plato, on the other hand, chose to withdraw into the quiet of a school, shielded from the noise of the world by a circle of loyal followers. It was unlikely that a man of Plato's refinement, culture, and aristocratic sensibilities would appreciate—like Socrates, the man of the people—the rough-and-tumble life of the Athenian marketplace. Nor was it beneficial for philosophy's progress for it to be so. The Socratic philosophy had suffered because of Socrates' lifestyle; it was chaotic and unstructured. Systematic thought doesn’t arise from arguments at street corners. For the development of a significant world system, like Plato’s, careful study and peaceful solitude were crucial.

This period of Plato's mastership was broken only by two journeys to Sicily, both undertaken with political objects. Plato knew well that the perfect State, as depicted in his "Republic," was not capable of realization in the Greece of his own time. Nevertheless, he took his political philosophy very seriously. Though the perfect republic was an unattainable ideal, yet, he thought, any real reform of the State must at least proceed in the direction of that ideal. One of the essential principles of the "Republic" was that the rulers must also be philosophers. Not till philosopher and ruler were combined in one and the same person could the State be governed upon true principles. Now, in the year 368 B.C., Dionysius the Elder died, and Dionysius the younger became tyrant of Syracuse. Dionysius despatched an invitation to Plato to attend his court and give him the benefit of his advice. Here was an opportunity to experiment. Plato could train and educate a {169} philosopher-king. He accepted the invitation. But the expedition ended disastrously. Dionysius received him with enthusiasm, and interested himself in the philosophical discourses of his teacher. But he was young, impetuous, hot-headed, and without genuine philosophic bent. His first interest gave place to weariness and irritation. Plato left Syracuse a disappointed man; and returned to Athens. Nevertheless, after the lapse of a few years, Dionysius again invited him to Syracuse, and again he accepted the invitation. But the second journey ended in disaster like the first, and Plato was even in danger of his life, but was rescued by the intervention of the Pythagoreans. He returned to Athens in his seventieth year, and lived till his death in the seclusion of his school, never again attempting to intervene in practical politics.

This time when Plato was in charge was only interrupted by two trips to Sicily, both aimed at political goals. Plato understood that the ideal State he described in his "Republic" couldn't be achieved in the Greece of his era. Still, he took his political philosophy seriously. Even though the perfect republic was an unattainable dream, he believed that any real reform of the State should at least move in that direction. One key idea from the "Republic" was that rulers should also be philosophers. Only when a philosopher and a ruler were the same person could the State be governed based on true principles. In 368 B.C., Dionysius the Elder died, and Dionysius the Younger became the tyrant of Syracuse. Dionysius sent an invitation to Plato to join his court and offer him advice. This was a chance to put theory into practice. Plato could train and educate a philosopher-king. He accepted the invitation. However, the trip ended badly. Dionysius welcomed him enthusiastically and showed interest in his philosophical discussions, but he was young, impulsive, hot-headed, and lacked a genuine philosophical mindset. His initial interest quickly turned to boredom and frustration. Plato left Syracuse feeling disappointed and returned to Athens. Yet, a few years later, Dionysius invited him back to Syracuse, and once again he accepted. But the second trip ended in disaster just like the first, and Plato was even in danger of losing his life, only to be saved by the Pythagoreans. He went back to Athens in his seventieth year and lived the rest of his life in the quiet of his school, never again trying to get involved in practical politics.

For more than another decade he dwelt and taught in Athens. His life was serene, quiet, and happy. He died peacefully at the age of eighty-two.

For over another decade, he lived and taught in Athens. His life was calm, peaceful, and happy. He passed away peacefully at the age of eighty-two.

Plato's writings take the form of dialogues. In the majority of these, the chief part is taken by Socrates, into whose mouth Plato puts the exposition of his own philosophy. In a few, as for example the "Parmenides," other speakers enunciate the Platonic teaching, but even in these Socrates always plays an important rôle. Plato was not only a philosopher, but a consummate literary artist. The dialogues are genuinely dramatic, enlivened by incident, humour, and life-like characterization. Not only is the portrait of Socrates drawn with loving affection, but even the minor characters are flesh and blood.

Plato's writings are in the form of dialogues. In most of these, Socrates takes the lead, serving as the mouthpiece for Plato's own philosophy. In a few, like the "Parmenides," other characters express the Platonic ideas, but Socrates still plays a significant role. Plato wasn't just a philosopher; he was also an exceptional literary artist. The dialogues are genuinely dramatic, filled with incidents, humor, and realistic character portrayals. The depiction of Socrates is done with deep affection, and even the minor characters feel real and relatable.

A most important element of Plato's style is his use of myths. He does not always explain his meaning in {170} the form of direct scientific exposition. He frequently teaches by allegories, fables, and stories, all of which may be included under the one general appellation of Platonic myths. These are often of great literary beauty, but in spite of this they involve grave disadvantages. Plato slips so easily from scientific exposition into myth, that it is often no easy matter to decide whether his statements are meant literally or allegorically. Moreover, the myths usually signify a defect in his thought itself. The fact is that the combination of poet and philosopher in one man is an exceedingly dangerous combination. I have explained before that the object of philosophy is, not merely to feel the truth, as the poet and mystic feel it, but intellectually to comprehend it, not merely to give us a series of pictures and metaphors, but a reasoned explanation of things upon scientific principles. When a man, who is at once a poet and a philosopher, cannot rationally explain a thing, it is a terrible temptation to him to substitute poetic metaphors for the explanation which is lacking. We saw, for example, that the writers of the Upanishads, who believed that the whole world issues forth from the one, absolute, imperishable, being, which they called Brahman, being unable to explain why the One thus differentiates itself into the many, took refuge in metaphors. As the sparks from the substantial fire, so, they say, do all finite beings issue forth from the One. But this explains nothing, and the aim of the philosopher is not thus vaguely to feel, but rationally to understand. Now this is not merely my view of the functions of philosophy. It is emphatically Plato's own view. In fact Plato was the originator of it. He is perpetually insisting that {171} nothing save full rational comprehension deserves the names of knowledge and philosophy. No writer has ever used such contemptuous language as Plato used of the mere mystic and poet, who says wise and beautiful things, without in the least understanding why they are wise and beautiful. No man has formed such a low estimate of the functions of the poet and mystic. Plato is, in theory at least, the prince of rationalists and intellectualists. In practice, however, he must be convicted of the very fault he so severely censured in others. This, in fact, is the explanation of most of the Platonic myths. Wherever Plato is unable to explain anything, he covers up the gap in his system with a myth. This is particularly noticeable, for example, in the "Timaeus." Plato having, in other dialogues, developed his theory of the nature of the ultimate reality, arrives, in the "Timaeus," at the problem how the actual world is to be explained from that ultimate reality. At this point, as we shall see, Plato's system breaks down. His account of the absolute reality is defective, and in consequence, it affords no principle whereby the actual universe can be explained. In the "Timaeus," therefore, instead of a reasoned explanation, he gives us a series of wholly fanciful myths about the origin of the world. Wherever we find myths in Plato's dialogues, we may suspect that we have arrived at one of the weak points of the system.

A key aspect of Plato's style is his use of myths. He doesn't always explain his ideas in a straightforward scientific way. He often teaches through allegories, fables, and stories, all of which can be grouped together as Platonic myths. These can be quite beautiful in a literary sense, but they come with significant drawbacks. Plato slides so easily from scientific explanation into myth that it's often hard to tell whether his statements should be taken literally or as allegory. Additionally, the myths usually highlight a flaw in his own reasoning. The reality is that combining the roles of poet and philosopher in one person can be very risky. I've previously explained that the goal of philosophy is not just to experience the truth, like a poet or mystic does, but to comprehend it intellectually, providing not only a sequence of images and metaphors but also a logical explanation based on scientific principles. When someone is both a poet and a philosopher and struggles to explain something rationally, there's a strong temptation to replace the missing explanation with poetic metaphors. For instance, we observed that the authors of the Upanishads, who believed that everything in the world comes from the one, absolute, eternal being they called Brahman, when unable to clarify why the One differentiates into the many, resorted to metaphors. They likened finite beings to sparks coming from a substantial fire. But this explains nothing, and the philosopher's aim is not to feel vaguely but to understand rationally. This perspective on philosophy isn't just mine; it's definitely Plato's own view. In fact, he was the originator of this idea. He repeatedly asserts that nothing less than complete rational understanding deserves to be called knowledge and philosophy. No other writer has ever used such dismissive language as Plato did toward the mere mystics and poets who say wise and beautiful things without understanding why they are wise and beautiful. No one has held such a low opinion of the roles of poets and mystics. Theoretically, at least, Plato is the leading rationalist and intellectualist. However, in practice, he can be found guilty of the very flaw he harshly criticizes in others. This is essentially the explanation for many of the Platonic myths. Whenever Plato can’t explain something, he fills the gap in his argument with a myth. This is particularly evident, for example, in the "Timaeus." Having developed his theory of ultimate reality in earlier dialogues, when he arrives at the question of how the actual world can be explained based on that ultimate reality in the "Timaeus," as we’ll see, his system falters. His description of absolute reality is inadequate, and as a result, it provides no principle for explaining the actual universe. Therefore, in the "Timaeus," instead of a logical explanation, he offers a series of entirely fanciful myths about the world's origin. Wherever we encounter myths in Plato's dialogues, we might suspect we’ve hit one of the system's weak points.

If we are to study Plato intelligently, it is essential that we should cease to regard the dialogues as if they were all produced en bloc from a single phase of their author's mind. His literary activity extended over a period of not less than fifty years. During that time, he did not stand still. His thought, and his mode of {172} expression, were constantly developing. If we are to understand Plato, we must obtain some clue to enable us to trace this development. And this means that we must know something of the order in which the dialogues were written. Unfortunately, however, they have not come down to us dated and numbered. It is a matter of scholarship and criticism to deduce the period at which any dialogue was written from internal evidences. Many minor points are still undecided, as well as a few questions of importance, such as the date of the "Phaedrus," [Footnote 11] which some critics place quite early and some very late in Plato's life. Neglecting these points, however, we may say in general that unanimity has been reached, and that we now know enough to be able to trace the main lines of development.

If we want to study Plato intelligently, it's crucial that we stop viewing the dialogues as if they all came from a single moment in the author's mind. His literary work spanned at least fifty years. During that time, he didn't remain stagnant. His thoughts and how he expressed them were constantly evolving. To truly understand Plato, we need to find some way to track this development. That means we have to be aware of the order in which the dialogues were written. Unfortunately, they haven't been preserved with dates and numbers. It's up to scholars and critics to figure out when any dialogue was written based on internal evidence. Many minor points are still unresolved, along with a few significant questions, like the date of the "Phaedrus," which some critics argue was written quite early and others very late in Plato's life. However, setting aside these details, we can generally say that there's a consensus, and we now know enough to trace the main lines of development.

[Footnote 11: The same remark applies to the "Symposium," the "Republic," and the "Theaetetus."]

[Footnote 11: The same point applies to the "Symposium," the "Republic," and the "Theaetetus."]

The dialogues fall into three main groups, which correspond roughly to the three periods of Plato's life. Those of the earliest group were written about the time of the death of Socrates, and before the author's journey to Megara. Some of them may have been written before the death of Socrates. This group includes the "Hippias Minor," the "Lysis," the "Charmides," the "Laches," the "Euthyphro," the "Apology," the "Crito," and the "Protagoras." The "Protagoras" is the longest, the most complex in thought, and the most developed. It is probably the latest, and forms the bridge to the second group.

The dialogues are divided into three main groups, which roughly correspond to the three periods of Plato's life. The earliest group was written around the time of Socrates’ death and before the author traveled to Megara. Some of these may have been written even before Socrates died. This group includes the "Hippias Minor," the "Lysis," the "Charmides," the "Laches," the "Euthyphro," the "Apology," the "Crito," and the "Protagoras." The "Protagoras" is the longest, most complex in thought, and most developed. It’s likely the latest of this group and serves as a bridge to the second group.

All these early dialogues are short and simple, and are still, as regards their thought, entirely under the influence of Socrates. Plato has not as yet developed {173} any philosophy of his own. He propounds the philosophy of Socrates almost unaltered. Even so, however, he is no mere plagiarist. There are throughout these dialogues evidences of freshness and originality, but these qualities exhibit themselves rather in the literary form than in the philosophical substance. We find here all the familiar Socratic propositions, that virtue is knowledge, is one, is teachable; that all men seek the good, but that men differ as to what the good is; that a man who does wrong deliberately is better than a man who does it unintentionally; and so on. Moreover, just as Socrates had occupied himself in attempting to fix the concepts of the virtues, asking "what is prudence?", "what is temperance?", and the like, so in many of these dialogues Plato pursues similar inquiries. The "Lysis" discusses the concept of friendship, the "Charmides" of temperance, the "Laches" of bravery. On the whole, the philosophical substance of these early writings is thin and meagre. There is a preponderance of incident and much biographical detail regarding Socrates. There is more art than matter. Consequently, from a purely literary point of view, these are among the most charming of Plato's dialogues, and many of them, such as the "Apology" and the "Crito," are especially popular with those who care for Plato rather as an artist than as a philosopher.

All these early dialogues are short and straightforward, and in terms of their ideas, they're still completely influenced by Socrates. Plato hasn't yet developed any philosophy of his own. He presents Socrates' philosophy almost unchanged. Even so, he isn’t just copying. Throughout these dialogues, there are signs of freshness and originality, but these qualities show more in the writing style than in the philosophical content. We see all the familiar Socratic ideas: that virtue is knowledge, is one, and can be taught; that everyone seeks the good, but people disagree on what the good is; and that someone who does wrong intentionally is better than someone who does it accidentally, and so on. Moreover, just as Socrates asked questions to clarify the concepts of virtues—like "What is prudence?" and "What is temperance?"—many of these dialogues have Plato exploring similar questions. The "Lysis" examines friendship, the "Charmides" looks at temperance, and the "Laches" considers bravery. Overall, the philosophical content in these early writings is thin and lacking substance. There's a lot of action and many biographical details about Socrates. There’s more style than substance. As a result, from a purely literary perspective, these are some of the most delightful of Plato's dialogues, and many, like the "Apology" and the "Crito," are particularly loved by those who appreciate Plato more as an artist than as a philosopher.

The second group of dialogues is generally connected with the period of Plato's travels. In addition to the influence of Socrates, we have now the influence of the Eleatics, which naturally connects these dialogues with the period of the philosopher's sojourn at Megara. But it is in these dialogues, too, that Plato for the first time {174} develops his own special philosophical thesis. This is in fact his great constructive period. The central and governing principle of his philosophy is the theory of Ideas. All else hinges on this, and is dominated by this. In a sense, his whole philosophy is nothing but the theory of Ideas and what depends upon it. It is in this second period that the theory of Ideas is founded and developed, and its relationship to the Eleatic philosophy of Being discussed. We have here the spectacle of Plato's most original thoughts in the pangs of childbirth. He is now at grips with the central problems of philosophy. He is intent upon the thought itself, and cares little for the ornaments of style. He is struggling to find expression for ideas newly-formed in his mind, of which he is not yet completely master, and which he cannot manipulate with ease. Consequently, the literary graces of the first period recede into the background. There is little incident, and no humour. There is nothing but close reasoning, hard and laborious discussion.

The second group of dialogues is typically associated with the time of Plato's travels. Along with the influence of Socrates, we also see the impact of the Eleatics, which naturally links these dialogues to the period of the philosopher's stay in Megara. However, it is in these dialogues that Plato first develops his own distinctive philosophical thesis. This marks his significant constructive period. The core principle of his philosophy is the theory of Ideas. Everything else is based on this and is shaped by it. Essentially, his entire philosophy revolves around the theory of Ideas and its implications. In this second period, the theory of Ideas is established and expanded upon, alongside a discussion of its connection to the Eleatic philosophy of Being. Here, we witness Plato's most original ideas being formed in what feels like a struggle for birth. He is now grappling with the central issues of philosophy. He focuses on the ideas themselves and pays little attention to stylistic embellishments. He is attempting to articulate concepts that are newly developed in his mind, which he hasn’t fully mastered yet and cannot manipulate easily. As a result, the literary elegance of the first period takes a back seat. There is little action, and no humor. There is only rigorous reasoning and intense, laborious discussion.

The twin dialogues, "Gorgias" and "Theaetetus" are probably the earliest of this group. They result in nothing very definite, and are chiefly negative in character. Plato is here engaged merely in a preparatory clearing of the ground. The "Gorgias" discusses and refutes the Sophistic identification of virtue and pleasure, and attempts to show, as against it, that the good must be something objectively existent, and independent of the pleasure of the individual. The "Theaetetus," similarly, shows that truth is not, as the Sophists thought, merely the subjective impression of the individual, but is something objectively true in itself. The other {175} dialogues of the group are the "Sophist," the "Statesman," and the "Parmenides." The "Sophist" discusses Being and not-being, and their relationship to the theory of Ideas. The "Parmenides" inquires whether the absolute reality is to be regarded, in the manner of the Eleatics, as an abstract One. It gives us, therefore, Plato's conception of the relation of his own philosophy to Eleaticism.

The twin dialogues, "Gorgias" and "Theaetetus," are likely the earliest of this group. They don't lead to any definitive conclusions and are mostly negative in nature. Plato is simply doing some groundwork here. The "Gorgias" examines and refutes the Sophistic link between virtue and pleasure, trying to argue that the good must be something that exists objectively and is independent of individual pleasure. The "Theaetetus," similarly, shows that truth is not just the subjective impression of the individual, as the Sophists claimed, but is something that is objectively true in itself. The other {175} dialogues in this group are the "Sophist," the "Statesman," and the "Parmenides." The "Sophist" talks about Being and non-being, and their connection to the theory of Ideas. The "Parmenides" questions whether absolute reality should be viewed, like the Eleatics did, as an abstract One. It thus provides Plato's perspective on how his philosophy relates to Eleaticism.

The dialogues of the third group are the work of Plato's maturity. He has now completely mastered his thought, and turns it with ease in all directions. Hence the style returns to the lucidity and purity of the first period. If the first period was marked chiefly by literary grace, the second by depth of thought, the third period combines both. The perfect substance is now moulded in the perfect form. But a peculiarity of all the dialogues of this period is that they take it for granted that the theory of Ideas is already established and familiar to the reader. They proceed to apply it to all departments of thought. The second period was concerned with the formulation and proof of the theory of Ideas, the third period undertakes its systematic application. Thus the "Symposium," which has for its subject the metaphysic of love, attempts to connect man's feeling for beauty with the intellectual knowledge of the Ideas. The "Philebus" applies the theory of Ideas to the sphere of ethics, the "Timaeus" to the sphere of physics, and the "Republic" to the sphere of politics. The "Phaedo" founds the doctrine of the immortality of the soul upon the theory of Ideas. The "Phaedrus" is probably to be grouped with the "Symposium." The beauty, grace, and lucidity of the style, and the fact that it assumes throughout that {176} the theory of Ideas is a thing established, lead us to the belief that it belongs to the period of Plato's maturity. Zeller's theory that it was written at the beginning of the second period, and is then offered to the reader as a sort of sweetmeat to induce him to enter upon the laborious task of reading the "Sophist," the "Statesman," and the "Parmenides," seems to be far-fetched and unnecessary. [Footnote 12]

The dialogues of the third group reflect Plato's mature work. He fully understands his ideas now and can express them effortlessly in various ways. As a result, the style returns to the clarity and simplicity of his early work. If the first period was mostly about literary elegance, and the second focused on deep thinking, the third combines both. The complete content is now shaped into a perfect form. However, a key feature of all the dialogues from this era is that they assume the theory of Ideas is already known and accepted by the reader. They move forward to apply it across different fields of thought. The second period dealt with defining and proving the theory of Ideas, while the third period focuses on systematically applying it. For instance, the "Symposium," which explores the philosophy of love, tries to connect our feelings for beauty with an intellectual understanding of Ideas. The "Philebus" applies the theory to ethics, the "Timaeus" to physics, and the "Republic" to politics. The "Phaedo" establishes the idea of the soul's immortality based on the theory of Ideas. The "Phaedrus" is likely grouped with the "Symposium." The beauty, elegance, and clarity of the writing, combined with the assumption that the theory of Ideas is well-established, suggest that it belongs to Plato's mature period. Zeller's theory that it was written at the start of the second period and is presented as a kind of incentive to encourage readers to tackle the challenging "Sophist," "Statesman," and "Parmenides," feels far-fetched and unnecessary. [Footnote 12]

[Footnote 12: Zeller's Plato and the Older Academy, chap. iii.]

[Footnote 12: Zeller's Plato and the Older Academy, chap. iii.]

If the second is the great constructive period of Plato's life, the third may be described as his systematic and synthetic period. Every part of his philosophy is here linked up with every other part. All the details of the system are seen to flow from the one central principle of his thought, the theory of Ideas. Every sphere of knowledge and being is in turn exhibited in the light of that principle, is permeated and penetrated by it.

If the second stage was the significant creative phase of Plato's life, the third can be described as his organized and comprehensive phase. Every aspect of his philosophy is connected to every other aspect. All the details of the system are seen to emerge from the single central idea of his thought, the theory of Ideas. Each area of knowledge and existence is presented through the lens of that idea, infused and influenced by it.

The plan for expounding Plato which first suggests itself is to go through the dialogues, one by one, and extract the doctrine of each successively. But this suggestion has to be given up as soon as it is mentioned. For although the philosophy of Plato is in itself a systematic and coherent body of thought, he did not express it in a systematic way. On the contrary, he scatters his ideas in all directions. He throws them out at random in any order. What logically comes first often appears last. It may be found at the end of a dialogue, and the next step in reasoning may make its appearance at the beginning, or even in a totally different dialogue. If, therefore, we are to get any connected view of the system, we must abandon Plato's own order of exposition, and piece the thought together for ourselves. We must begin {177} with what logically comes first, wherever we may find it, and proceed with the exposition in the same manner.

The best way to explain Plato seems to be to go through his dialogues one by one and pull out the ideas from each one in order. However, this idea has to be abandoned as soon as it’s suggested. Even though Plato's philosophy is a systematic and coherent set of ideas, he didn’t present it that way. Instead, he spreads his thoughts everywhere. He presents them randomly and out of order. What should come first often shows up last. It can be found at the end of a dialogue, while the next logical step could appear at the beginning or even in a completely different dialogue. So, if we want to understand the system as a whole, we need to ignore Plato's original order and assemble the ideas ourselves. We should start {177} with what logically comes first, no matter where we find it, and continue explaining in that same way.

A similar difficulty attends the question of the division of Plato's philosophy. He himself has given us no single and certain principle of division. But the principle usually adopted divides his philosophy into Dialectic, Physics, and Ethics. Dialectic, or the theory of Ideas, is Plato's doctrine of the nature of the absolute reality. Physics is the theory of phenomenal existence in space and time, and includes therefore the doctrine of the soul and its migrations, since these are happenings in time. Ethics includes politics, the theory of the duty of man as a citizen, as well as the ethics of the individual. Certain portions of the system, the doctrine of Eros, for example, do not fall very naturally into any of these divisions. But, on the other hand, though some dialogues are mixed as to their subject matter, others, and those the most important, fall almost exclusively into one or other division. For example, the "Timaeus," the "Phaedo," and the "Phaedrus," are physical. The "Philebus," the "Gorgias," and the "Republic," are ethical. The "Theaetetus," the "Sophist," and the "Parmenides," are dialectical.

A similar challenge comes with dividing Plato's philosophy. He hasn't provided us with a clear principle for this division. However, the commonly accepted approach breaks his philosophy into three parts: Dialectic, Physics, and Ethics. Dialectic, or the theory of Ideas, is Plato's understanding of absolute reality. Physics deals with how things exist in space and time, which also includes the concept of the soul and its journeys since these events occur over time. Ethics covers politics, focusing on the responsibilities of individuals as citizens, along with personal ethics. Some elements of his system, like the doctrine of Eros, don't neatly fit into these categories. On the flip side, while some dialogues mix subjects, many of the crucial ones clearly belong to one category or another. For instance, "Timaeus," "Phaedo," and "Phaedrus" are physical. "Philebus," "Gorgias," and "Republic" are ethical. "Theaetetus," "Sophist," and "Parmenides" are dialectical.


2. The Theory of Knowledge.

2. Knowledge Theory.

The theory of Ideas is itself based upon the theory of knowledge. What is knowledge? What is truth? Plato opens the discussion by telling us first what knowledge and truth are not. His object here is the refutation of false theories. These must be disposed of to clear the ground preparatory to positive exposition. The first such false theory which he attacks is that knowledge {178} is perception. To refute this is the main object of the "Theaetetus." His arguments may be summarized as follows:--

The theory of Ideas is built on the theory of knowledge. What is knowledge? What is truth? Plato starts the discussion by explaining what knowledge and truth are not. His aim here is to disprove false theories. These must be addressed to prepare the way for a clear and positive explanation. The first false theory he tackles is that knowledge {178} is perception. Refuting this is the main goal of the "Theaetetus." His arguments can be summarized as follows:--

(1) That knowledge is perception is the theory of Protagoras and the Sophists, and we have seen to what results it leads. What it amounts to is that what appears to each individual true is true for that individual. But this is at any rate false in its application to our judgment of future events. The frequent mistakes which men make about the future show this. It may appear to me that I shall be Chief Justice next year. But instead of that, I find myself, perhaps, in prison. In general, what appears to each individual to be the truth about the future frequently does not turn out so in the event.

(1) The idea that knowledge is based on perception is the view of Protagoras and the Sophists, and we've seen the consequences of this belief. Essentially, it means that whatever seems true to each person is true for that person. However, this perspective is clearly flawed when it comes to our predictions about the future. The frequent errors people make regarding what’s to come highlight this issue. I might believe that I will be Chief Justice next year, but instead, I might find myself in prison. Overall, what each individual thinks is true about the future often doesn’t align with what actually happens.

(2) Perception yields contradictory impressions. The same object appears large when near, small when removed to a distance. Compared with some things it is light, with others heavy. In one light it is white, in another green, and in the dark it has no colour at all. Looked at from one angle this piece of paper seems square, from another it appears to be a rhombus. Which of all these impressions is true? To know which is true, we must be able to exercise a choice among these varying impressions, to prefer one to another, to discriminate, to accept this and reject that. But if knowledge is perception, then we have no right to give one perception preference over another. For all perceptions are knowledge. All are true.

(2) Perception creates conflicting impressions. The same object looks large up close but small from a distance. It feels light compared to some things and heavy compared to others. Under one light, it appears white; under another, green, and in the dark, it has no color at all. Viewed from one angle, this piece of paper seems square; from another, it looks like a rhombus. Which of these impressions is accurate? To figure out which is true, we need to be able to choose among these different impressions, favor one over another, distinguish, accept this one and reject that one. But if knowledge is based on perception, then we can't favor one perception over another. All perceptions are knowledge. All are true.

(3) This doctrine renders all teaching, all discussion, proof, or disproof, impossible. Since all perceptions are equally true, the child's perceptions must be just as much the truth as those of his teachers. His teachers, {179} therefore, can teach him nothing. As to discussion and proof, the very fact that two people dispute about anything implies that they believe in the existence of an objective truth. Their impressions, if they contradict each other, cannot both be true. For if so, there is nothing to dispute about. Thus all proof and refutation are rendered futile by the theory of Protagoras.

(3) This idea makes teaching, discussion, proof, or disproof impossible. Since all perceptions are equally valid, a child's perceptions are just as true as those of their teachers. Therefore, teachers can’t teach them anything. Regarding discussion and proof, the fact that two people argue about something means they believe an objective truth exists. If their impressions contradict each other, they can't both be true. If that were the case, there would be nothing to argue about. So, everything related to proof and refutation becomes pointless under Protagoras’ theory.

(4) If perception is truth, man is the measure of all things, in his character as a percipient being. But since animals are also percipient beings, the lowest brute must be, equally with man, the measure of all things.

(4) If what we perceive is true, then humans are the standard for everything, based on our ability to perceive. However, since animals can also perceive, even the simplest creature must, just like humans, be considered a standard for all things.

(5) The theory of Protagoras contradicts itself. For Protagoras admits that what appears to me true is true. If, therefore, it appears to me true that the doctrine of Protagoras is false, Protagoras himself must admit that it is false.

(5) Protagoras's theory is self-contradictory. He acknowledges that what seems true to me is true. So, if it seems true to me that Protagoras's doctrine is false, then Protagoras himself has to accept that it's false.

(6) It destroys the objectivity of truth, and renders the distinction between truth and falsehood wholly meaningless. The same thing is true and false at the same time, true for you and false for me. Hence it makes no difference at all whether we say that a proposition is true, or whether we say that it is false. Both statements mean the same thing, that is to say, neither of them means anything. To say that whatever I perceive is true for me merely gives a new name to my perception, but does not add any value to it.

(6) It destroys the objectivity of truth and makes the distinction between truth and falsehood completely meaningless. The same thing can be true and false at the same time, true for you and false for me. So it doesn’t matter at all whether we say a statement is true or false. Both claims mean the same thing; in other words, neither means anything. Saying that whatever I perceive is true for me just gives a new label to my perception but doesn’t add any value to it.

(7) In all perception there are elements which are not contributed by the senses. Suppose I say, "This piece of paper is white." This, we might think, is a pure judgment of perception. Nothing is stated except what I perceive by means of my senses. But on consideration it turns out that this is not correct. First of all I must {180} think "this piece of paper." Why do I call it paper? My doing so means that I have classified it. I have mentally compared it with other pieces of paper, and decided that it is of a class with them. My thought, then, involves comparison and classification. The object is a compound sensation of whiteness, squareness, etc. I can only recognise it as a piece of paper by identifying these sensations, which I have now, with sensations received from other similar objects in the past. And not only must I recognize the sameness of the sensations, but I must recognize their difference from other sensations. I must not confound the sensations I receive from paper with those which I receive from a piece of wood. Both identities and differences of sensations must be known before I can say "this piece of paper." The same is true when I go on to say that it "is white." This is only possible by classifying it with other white objects, and differentiating it from objects of other colours. But the senses themselves cannot perform these acts of comparison and contrast. Each sensation is, so to speak, an isolated dot. It cannot go beyond itself to compare itself with others. This operation must be performed by my mind, which acts as a co-ordinating central authority, receiving the isolated sensations, combining, comparing, and contrasting them. This is particularly noticeable in cases where we compare sensations of one sense with those of another. Feeling a ball with my fingers, I say it feels round. Looking at it with my eyes, I say it looks round. But the feel is quite a different sensation from the look. Yet I use the same word, "round," to describe both. And this shows that I have identified the two sensations. This {181} cannot be done by the senses themselves. For my eyes cannot feel, and my fingers cannot see. It must be the mind itself, standing above the senses, which performs the identification. Thus the ideas of identity and difference are not yielded to me by my senses. The intellect itself introduces them into things. Yet they are involved in all knowledge, for they are involved even in the simplest acts of knowledge, such as the proposition, "This is white." Knowledge, therefore, cannot consist simply of sense-impressions, as Protagoras thought, for even the simplest propositions contain more than sensation.

(7) In every perception, there are aspects that the senses don't provide. If I say, "This piece of paper is white," we might think this is a straightforward judgment based solely on perception. It seems like I'm only stating what I sense through my senses. However, upon reflection, that assumption is incorrect. First, I have to think "this piece of paper." Why do I call it paper? By doing so, I'm classifying it. I’ve mentally compared it to other pieces of paper and decided that it belongs in that category. My thought, then, involves comparison and classification. The object is actually a combination of sensations like whiteness, squareness, and so on. I can only recognize it as a piece of paper by connecting these sensations to those I’ve experienced from similar objects before. I have to recognize both the similarities and the differences between sensations. I must not confuse the sensations I get from paper with those I receive from a piece of wood. I need to be aware of both the identities and the differences of sensations before I can say, "this piece of paper." The same goes when I say it "is white." This can only happen by classifying it among other white objects and distinguishing it from things of different colors. But the senses themselves can't perform these comparisons and contrasts. Each sensation is like an isolated dot; it can’t reach beyond itself to compare with others. This process must be done by my mind, which acts as a central authority that receives the isolated sensations and combines, compares, and contrasts them. This becomes especially clear when we compare sensations from different senses. When I feel a ball with my fingers, I say it feels round. When I look at it with my eyes, I say it looks round. Yet the feeling and the sight are two different sensations. Still, I use the same word, "round," to describe both. This shows that I have connected the two sensations. This {181} can't be achieved by the senses alone. My eyes can’t feel, and my fingers can’t see. It has to be my mind, which stands above the senses, that makes the identification. Thus, the ideas of identity and difference aren't something my senses provide. The intellect introduces them into our understanding of things. Yet they are part of all knowledge because they are involved even in the simplest acts of knowing, like the statement, "This is white." Therefore, knowledge cannot simply be made up of sense impressions, as Protagoras believed, because even the simplest propositions include more than just sensation.

If knowledge is not the same as perception, neither is it, on the other hand, the same as opinion. That knowledge is opinion is the second false theory that Plato seeks to refute. Wrong opinion is clearly not knowledge. But even right opinion cannot be called knowledge. If I say, without any grounds for the statement, that there will be a thunderstorm next Easter Sunday, it may chance that my statement turns out to be correct. But it cannot be said that, in making this blind guess, I had any knowledge, although, as it turned out, I had right opinion. Right opinion may also be grounded, not on mere guess-work, but on something which, though better, is still not true understanding. We often feel intuitively, or instinctively, that something is true, though we cannot give any definite grounds for our belief. The belief may be quite correct, but it is not, according to Plato, knowledge. It is only right opinion. To possess knowledge, one must not only know that a thing is so, but why it is so. One must know the reasons. Knowledge must be full and complete understanding, rational comprehension, and not mere instinctive belief. {182} It must be grounded on reason, and not on faith. Right opinion may be produced by persuasion and sophistry, by the arts of the orator and rhetorician. Knowledge can only be produced by reason. Right opinion may equally be removed by the false arts of rhetoric, and is therefore unstable and uncertain. But true knowledge cannot be thus shaken. He who truly knows and understands cannot be robbed of his knowledge by the glamour of words. Opinion, lastly, may be true or false. Knowledge can only be true.

If knowledge isn't the same as perception, it also isn't the same as opinion. The idea that knowledge is just opinion is the second misconception that Plato aims to challenge. A wrong opinion is clearly not knowledge. However, even a correct opinion can't be considered knowledge. For example, if I say, without any evidence, that there will be a thunderstorm next Easter Sunday, it might turn out that I'm right. But I can't say I had any knowledge when I made that random guess, even though I had a correct opinion. A correct opinion could also be based not on just guessing but on something that, while better than a guess, still lacks true understanding. We often have a gut feeling that something is true even if we can't provide solid reasons for our belief. The belief might be right, but according to Plato, it's still not knowledge—it's just a correct opinion. To truly have knowledge, you need to know not just that something is true, but also why it's true. You need to understand the reasons. Knowledge has to be a complete and thorough understanding, rooted in rational thought, not just a gut feeling. It must be based on reason, not faith. Correct opinions can arise from persuasion and tricks of language, from the skills of speakers and writers. Knowledge can only come from reason. A correct opinion can also be swayed by misleading rhetoric, making it unstable and uncertain. But true knowledge can't be easily shaken. Someone who genuinely knows and understands can't be deprived of that knowledge by clever words. Finally, opinion can be true or false, but knowledge can only be true.

These false theories being refuted, we can now pass to the positive side of the theory of knowledge. If knowledge is neither perception nor opinion, what is it? Plato adopts, without alteration, the Socratic doctrine that all knowledge is knowledge through concepts. This, as I explained in the lecture on Socrates, gets rid of the objectionable results of the Sophistic identification of knowledge with perception. A concept, being the same thing as a definition, is something fixed and permanent, not liable to mutation according to the subjective impressions of the individual. It gives us objective truth. This also agrees with Plato's view of opinion. Knowledge is not opinion, founded on instinct or intuition. Knowledge is founded on reason. This is the same as saying that it is founded upon concepts, since reason is the faculty of concepts.

With these false theories dismissed, we can now move on to the positive aspects of the theory of knowledge. If knowledge isn’t perception or opinion, then what is it? Plato accepts, without changes, the Socratic idea that all knowledge comes from concepts. As I explained in the lecture on Socrates, this eliminates the problematic results of the Sophists' equation of knowledge with perception. A concept, being identical to a definition, is something fixed and enduring, not subject to change based on individual subjective impressions. It provides us with objective truth. This also aligns with Plato's understanding of opinion. Knowledge isn’t opinion based on instinct or intuition. Knowledge is based on reason. This is equivalent to saying that it is based on concepts, since reason is the faculty of concepts.

But if Plato, in answering the question, "What is knowledge?" follows implicitly the teaching of Socrates, he yet builds upon this teaching a new and wholly un-Socratic metaphysic of his own. The Socratic theory of knowledge he now converts into a theory of the nature of reality. This is the subject-matter of Dialectic.

But if Plato, in answering the question, "What is knowledge?" implicitly follows Socrates' teachings, he still develops a new and completely non-Socratic metaphysics of his own. He transforms the Socratic theory of knowledge into a theory about the nature of reality. This is the focus of Dialectic.


3. Dialectic, or the Theory of Ideas.

3. Dialectic, or the Theory of Ideas.

The concept had been for Socrates merely a rule of thought. Definitions, like guide-rails, keep thought upon the straight path; we compare any act with the definition of virtue in order to ascertain whether it is virtuous. But what was for Socrates merely regulative of thought, Plato now transforms into a metaphysical substance. His theory of Ideas is the theory of the objectivity of concepts. That the concept is not merely an idea in the mind, but something which has a reality of its own, outside and independent of the mind--this is the essence of the philosophy of Plato.

The idea was just a guideline for Socrates. Definitions, like guardrails, keep our thinking on track; we measure any action against the definition of virtue to decide if it’s virtuous. But what was simply a guideline for Socrates, Plato changes into a fundamental reality. His theory of Ideas proposes that concepts are objective. The concept isn't just an idea in our heads; it has its own reality, existing independently of our minds—this is the core of Plato's philosophy.

How did Plato arrive at this doctrine? It is founded upon the view that truth means the correspondence of one's ideas with the facts of existence. If I see a lake of water, and if there really is such a lake, then my idea is true. But if there is no lake, then my idea is false. It is an hallucination. Truth, according to this view, means that the thought in my mind is a copy of something outside my mind. Falsehood consists in having an idea which is not a copy of anything which really exists. Knowledge, of course, means knowledge of the truth. And when I say that a thought in my mind is knowledge, I must therefore mean that this thought is a copy of something that exists. But we have already seen that knowledge is the knowledge of concepts. And if a concept is true knowledge, it can only be true in virtue of the fact that it corresponds to an objective reality. There must, therefore, be general ideas or concepts, outside my mind. It were a contradiction to suppose, on the one hand, that the concept is true knowledge, and on the other, that it corresponds to nothing external {184} to us. This would be like saying that my idea of the lake of water is a true idea, but that no such lake really exists. The concept in my mind must be a copy of the concept outside it.

How did Plato come to this idea? It’s based on the belief that truth means the alignment of our thoughts with the reality of existence. If I see a lake of water, and there really is a lake, then my idea is true. But if there’s no lake, then my idea is false. It’s just an illusion. Truth, according to this belief, means that the thought in my mind reflects something outside of it. Falsehood is having an idea that doesn’t reflect anything that actually exists. Knowledge, of course, is understanding the truth. So, when I say that a thought in my mind is knowledge, I mean that this thought reflects something that exists. However, we’ve already noted that knowledge involves understanding concepts. If a concept is true knowledge, it can only be true because it corresponds to an objective reality. Therefore, there must be general ideas or concepts beyond my mind. It would be contradictory to say that a concept is true knowledge while also claiming that it doesn’t correspond to anything external to us. This would be like claiming my idea of the lake of water is a true idea, but no such lake actually exists. The concept in my mind must be a reflection of the concept outside of it.

Now if knowledge by concepts is true, our experiences through sensation must be false. Our senses make us aware of many individual horses. Our intellect gives us the concept of the horse in general. If the latter is the sole truth, the former must be false. And this can only mean that the objects of sensation have no true reality. What has reality is the concept; what has no reality is the individual thing which is perceived by the senses. This and that particular horse have no true being. Reality belongs only to the idea of the horse in general.

If knowledge through concepts is accurate, then our experiences through sensation must be incorrect. Our senses make us aware of many individual horses. Our mind provides the concept of a horse as a whole. If the concept is the only truth, then the individual horses must be false. This means that the objects of our senses lack real existence. What is real is the concept; what has no reality is the individual thing that we perceive with our senses. This particular horse and that one do not have true existence. Reality belongs only to the idea of a horse in general.

Let us approach this theory from a somewhat different direction. Suppose I ask you the question, "What is beauty?" You point to a rose, and say, "Here is beauty." And you say the same of a woman's face, a piece of woodland scenery, and a clear moonlight night. But I answer that this is not what I want to know. I did not ask what things are beautiful, but what is beauty. I did not ask for many things, but for one thing, namely, beauty. If beauty is a rose, it cannot be moonlight, because a rose and moonlight are quite different things. By beauty we mean, not many things, but one. This is proved by the fact that we use only one word for it. And what I want to know is what this one beauty is, which is distinct from all beautiful objects. Perhaps you will say that there is no such thing as beauty apart from beautiful objects, and that, though we use one word, yet this is only a manner of {185} speech, and that there are in reality many beauties, each residing in a beautiful object. In that case, I observe that, though the many beauties are all different, yet, since you use the one word to describe them all, you evidently think that they are similar to each other. How do you know that they are similar? Your eyes cannot inform you of this similarity, because it involves comparison, and we have already seen that comparison is an act of the mind, and not of the senses. You must therefore have an idea of beauty in your mind, with which you compare the various beautiful objects and so recognise them as all resembling your idea of beauty, and therefore as resembling each other. So that there is at any rate an idea of one beauty in your mind. Either this idea corresponds to something outside you, or it does not. In the latter case, your idea of beauty is a mere invention, a figment of your own brain. If so, then, in judging external objects by your subjective idea, and in making it the standard of whether they are beautiful or not, you are back again at the position of the Sophists. You are making yourself and the fancies of your individual brain the standard of external truth. Therefore, the only alternative is to believe that there is not only an idea of beauty in your mind, but that there is such a thing as the one beauty itself, of which your idea is a copy. This beauty exists outside the mind, and it is something distinct from all beautiful objects.

Let’s look at this theory from a different angle. Imagine I ask you, “What is beauty?” You might point to a rose and say, “This is beauty.” You could say the same about a woman’s face, a forest scene, or a clear moonlit night. But I respond that this isn’t what I’m trying to understand. I didn’t ask what things are beautiful; I asked what beauty is. I’m not looking for many things, but for one thing: beauty. If beauty is a rose, it can’t also be moonlight, since a rose and moonlight are entirely different. When we talk about beauty, we mean one thing, not many. This is shown by the fact that we have just one word for it. What I want to understand is what this singular beauty is, separate from all beautiful objects. You might argue that beauty doesn’t exist apart from beautiful objects and that, even though we use a single word, this is just a way of speaking, with many beauties, each found in a beautiful object. In that case, I notice that even though those many beauties are different, since you use the same word to describe them all, it seems you think they are similar. How do you know they are similar? Your eyes can’t tell you that similarity, because it requires comparison, and we’ve already established that comparison is a mental act, not something your senses do. Therefore, you must have an idea of beauty in your mind that you use to compare the different beautiful objects and thus recognize them as all relating to your concept of beauty, and consequently, to each other. So, there’s at least an idea of one beauty in your mind. Either this idea aligns with something external, or it doesn’t. If it doesn’t, then your idea of beauty is just a fabrication, a product of your imagination. If that’s the case, by judging external objects through your subjective idea and making it the benchmark for whether they’re beautiful, you revert back to the view of the Sophists. You’re using your own standards and individual imagination as the measure of external truth. Thus, the only other possibility is to accept that not only is there an idea of beauty in your mind, but that there is also such a thing as one true beauty, of which your idea is just a reflection. This beauty exists outside your mind and is something distinct from all beautiful objects.

What has been said of beauty may equally be said of justice, or of goodness, or of whiteness, or of heaviness. There are many just acts, but only one justice, since we use one word for it. This justice must be a real thing, distinct from all particular just acts. Our ideas of justice {186} are copies of it. So also there are many white objects, but also the one whiteness.

What is true for beauty can also be true for justice, goodness, whiteness, or heaviness. There are many just actions, but there is only one justice because we use a single word for it. This justice must be a real concept, separate from all specific just actions. Our ideas of justice {186} are representations of it. Likewise, there are many white objects, but there is still just one whiteness.

Of the above examples, several are very exalted moral ideas, such as beauty, justice, and goodness. But the case of whiteness will serve to show that the theory attributes reality not only to exalted ideas, but to others also. In fact, we might quite well substitute evil for goodness, and all the same arguments would apply. Or we might take a corporeal object such as the horse, and ask what "horse" means. It does not mean the many individual horses, for since one word is used it must mean one thing, which is related to individual horses, just as whiteness is related to individual white things. It means the universal horse, the idea of the horse in general, and this, just as much as goodness or beauty, must be something objectively real.

Of the examples mentioned above, several represent very high moral concepts, like beauty, justice, and goodness. However, the example of whiteness shows that the theory assigns reality not only to high ideals but to other concepts as well. In fact, we could easily replace goodness with evil, and the same arguments would hold true. Or we could consider a physical object like a horse and ask what "horse" means. It doesn’t refer to the many individual horses since a single word is used; it must represent one concept that relates to individual horses, just as whiteness relates to individual white objects. It signifies the universal horse, the general idea of a horse, and this, just like goodness or beauty, must be something that is objectively real.

Now beauty, justice, goodness, whiteness, the horse in general, are all concepts. The idea of beauty is formed by including what is common to all beautiful objects, and excluding those points in which they differ. And this, as we have seen, is just what is meant by a concept. Plato's theory, therefore, is that concepts are objective realities. And he gives to these objective concepts the technical name Ideas. This is his answer to the chief question of philosophy, namely, what, amid all the appearances and unrealities of things, is that absolute and ultimate reality, from which all else is to be explained? It consists, for Plato, in Ideas.

Now beauty, justice, goodness, and concepts like "the horse" are all ideas. The idea of beauty is created by identifying what is shared among all beautiful objects while excluding the differences between them. As we have observed, this is essentially what a concept is. Plato’s theory, therefore, asserts that concepts are objective realities. He refers to these objective concepts as Ideas. This is his response to the central question of philosophy: amidst all the appearances and illusions of things, what is the absolute and ultimate reality from which everything else can be explained? For Plato, that reality is composed of Ideas.

Let us see next what the characteristics of the Ideas are. In the first place, they are substances. Substance is a technical term in philosophy, but its philosophical meaning is merely a more consistent development of its {187} popular meaning. In common talk, we generally apply the word substance to material things such as iron, brass, wood, or water. And we say that these substances possess qualities. For example, hardness and shininess are qualities of the substance iron. The qualities cannot exist apart from the substances. They do not exist on their own account, but are dependent on the substance. The shininess cannot exist by itself. There must be a shiny something. But, according to popular ideas, though the qualities are not independent of the substance, the substance is independent of the qualities. The qualities derive their reality from the substance. But the substance has reality in itself. The philosophical use of the term substance is simply a more consistent application of this idea. Substance means, for the philosopher, that which has its whole being in itself, whose reality does not flow into it from anything else, but which is the source of its own reality. It is self-caused, and self-determined. It is the ground of other things, but itself has no ground except itself. For example, if we believe the popular Christian idea that God created the world, but is Himself an ultimate and uncreated being, then, since the world depends for its existence upon God, but God's existence depends only upon Himself, God is a substance and the world is not. In this sense the word is correctly used in the Creed where it speaks of God as "three persons, but one substance." Again, if, with the Idealists, we think that mind is a self-existent reality, and that matter owes its existence to mind, then in that case matter is not substance, but mind is. In this technical sense the Ideas are substances. They are absolute and ultimate realities. {188} Their whole being is in themselves. They depend on nothing, but all things depend on them. They are the first principles of the universe.

Let’s explore the characteristics of Ideas next. First off, they are substances. "Substance" is a technical term in philosophy, but its philosophical meaning is simply a more coherent version of its common meaning. In everyday language, we usually refer to material things like iron, brass, wood, or water as substances. We say that these substances have qualities. For instance, hardness and shininess are qualities of iron. These qualities can't exist separately from the substances; they don't exist on their own but rely on the substance for their existence. Shininess can't exist by itself; there has to be something shiny. However, according to popular beliefs, even though the qualities aren't independent of the substance, the substance is independent of the qualities. The qualities get their reality from the substance, but the substance has reality in itself. In philosophy, the term "substance" just means something that has its entire being within itself, whose reality doesn't depend on anything else, but is the source of its own reality. It is self-causing and self-determining. It is the foundation of other things but has no foundation besides itself. For example, if we accept the common Christian belief that God created the world but is Himself an ultimate and uncreated being, then, since the world relies on God for its existence while God's existence relies solely on Himself, God is a substance but the world is not. In this sense, the term is correctly used in the Creed when it describes God as "three persons, but one substance." Similarly, if we, like the Idealists, believe that the mind is a self-existent reality and that matter gets its existence from the mind, then in that scenario, matter isn't a substance, but mind is. In this technical sense, Ideas are substances. They are absolute and ultimate realities. Their entire being is in themselves. They depend on nothing, while everything depends on them. They are the first principles of the universe.

Secondly, the Ideas are universal. An Idea is not any particular thing. The Idea of the horse is not this or that horse. It is the general concept of all horses. It is the universal horse. For this reason the Ideas are, in modern times, often called "universals."

Secondly, Ideas are universal. An Idea is not any specific thing. The Idea of a horse is not this or that horse. It is the general concept of all horses. It is the universal horse. For this reason, Ideas are often referred to as "universals" in modern times.

Thirdly, the Ideas are not things, but thoughts. There is no such thing as the horse-in-general. If there were, we should be able to find it somewhere, and it would then be a particular thing instead of a universal. But in saying that the Ideas are thoughts, there are two mistakes to be carefully avoided. The first is to suppose that they are the thoughts of a person, that they are your thoughts or my thoughts. The second is to suppose that they are thoughts in the mind of God. Both these views are wrong. It would be absurd to suppose that our thoughts can be the cause of the universe. Our concepts are indeed copies of the Ideas, but to confuse them with the Ideas themselves is, for Plato, as absurd as to confuse our idea of a mountain with the mountain itself. Nor are they the thoughts of God. They are indeed sometimes spoken of as the "Ideas in the divine mind." But this is only a figurative expression. We can, if we like, talk of the sum of all the Ideas as constituting the "divine mind." But this means nothing in particular, and is only a poetical phrase. Both these mistakes are due to the fact that we find it difficult to conceive of thoughts without a thinker. This, however, is just what Plato meant. They are not subjective ideas, that is, the ideas in a particular and existent {189} mind. They are objective Ideas, thoughts which have reality on their own account, independently of any mind.

Thirdly, Ideas aren’t objects, but thoughts. There’s no such thing as a horse-in-general. If there were, we’d be able to find it somewhere, and it would then be a specific thing instead of a universal concept. However, when we say that Ideas are thoughts, there are two mistakes we need to avoid. The first is assuming that they are the thoughts of a person, like your thoughts or my thoughts. The second is thinking that they are thoughts in the mind of God. Both of these views are incorrect. It would be ridiculous to think that our thoughts could cause the universe. Our concepts are indeed copies of the Ideas, but confusing them with the Ideas themselves is, for Plato, as silly as confusing our idea of a mountain with the mountain itself. They aren’t the thoughts of God either. They are sometimes referred to as the "Ideas in the divine mind," but that’s just a figurative expression. We can talk about the totality of all the Ideas as the "divine mind" if we want, but that doesn’t signify anything specific; it’s merely a poetic phrase. Both of these misconceptions arise because we find it hard to imagine thoughts without a thinker. However, this is precisely what Plato meant. They aren’t subjective ideas, which means they aren’t ideas in a specific and existing {189} mind. They are objective Ideas, thoughts that have their own reality, independent of any mind.

Fourthly, each Idea is a unity. It is the one amid the many. The Idea of man is one, although individual men are many. There cannot be more than one Idea for each class of objects. If there were several Ideas of justice, we should have to seek for the common element among them, and this common element would itself constitute the one Idea of justice.

Fourthly, each Idea is a unity. It's the one among the many. The Idea of man is singular, even though there are many individual men. There can only be one Idea for each class of objects. If there were multiple Ideas of justice, we would need to find the common element among them, and this common element would itself form the one Idea of justice.

Fifthly, the Ideas are immutable and imperishable. A concept is the same as a definition. And the whole point in a definition is that it should always be the same. The object of a definition is to compare individual things with it, and to see whether they agree with it or not. But if the definition of a triangle differed from day to day, it would be useless, since we could never say whether any particular figure were a triangle or not, just as the standard yard in the Tower of London would be useless if it changed in length, and were twice as long to-day as it was yesterday. A definition is thus something absolutely permanent, and a definition is only the expression in words of the nature of an Idea. Consequently the Ideas cannot change. The many beautiful objects arise and pass away, but the one Beauty neither begins nor ends. It is eternal, unchangeable, and imperishable. The many beautiful things are but the fleeting expressions of the one eternal beauty. The definition of man would remain the same, even if all men were destroyed. The Idea of man is eternal, and remains untouched by the birth, old age, decay, and death, of individual men.

Fifth, the Ideas are unchanging and everlasting. A concept is basically a definition. The whole point of a definition is that it should always remain the same. A definition serves to compare individual things with it to see if they match or not. But if the definition of a triangle changed every day, it would be useless, since we could never determine whether a specific figure is a triangle or not, just like the standard yard at the Tower of London would be pointless if its length varied and was twice as long today as it was yesterday. A definition is, therefore, something completely permanent, and it is just the verbal expression of the nature of an Idea. As a result, the Ideas cannot change. Many beautiful objects come and go, but true Beauty is constant; it neither begins nor ends. It is eternal, unchangeable, and indestructible. The various beautiful things are merely temporary expressions of the one eternal beauty. The definition of man would stay the same, even if all humanity were wiped out. The Idea of man is eternal and remains unaffected by the birth, aging, decay, and death of individual people.

Sixthly, the Ideas are the Essences of all things. The definition gives us what is essential to a thing. If we {190} define man as a rational animal, this means that reason is of the essence of man. The fact that this man has a turned-up nose, and that man red hair, are accidental facts, not essential to their humanity. We do not include them in the definition of man.

Sixthly, ideas represent the essence of all things. The definition reveals what is essential to a thing. If we define man as a rational animal, this means that reasoning is essential to being human. The fact that one man has a turned-up nose and another has red hair are just accidental traits, not essential to their humanity. We don’t include these traits in the definition of man.

Seventhly, each Idea is, in its own kind, an absolute perfection, and its perfection is the same as its reality. The perfect man is the one universal type-man, that is, the Idea of man, and all individual men deviate more or less from this perfect type. In so far as they fall short of it, they are imperfect and unreal.

Seventh, every Idea is, in its own way, a complete perfection, and its perfection is its reality. The perfect man represents the universal ideal of man, meaning the Idea of man, and every individual man deviates to some extent from this perfect standard. To the degree that they fall short, they are imperfect and not real.

Eighthly, the Ideas are outside space and time. That they are outside space is obvious. If they were in space, they would have to be in some particular place. We ought to be able to find them somewhere. A telescope or microscope might reveal them. And this would mean that they are individual and particular things, and not universals at all. They are also outside time. For they are unchangeable and eternal; and this does not mean that they are the same at all times. If that were so, their immutability would be a matter of experience, and not of reason. We should, so to speak, have to look at them from time to time to see that they had not really changed. But their immutability is not a matter of experience, but is known to thought. It is not merely that they are always the same in time, but that time is irrelevant to them. They are timeless. In the "Timaeus" eternity is distinguished from infinite time. The latter is described as a mere copy of eternity.

Eighthly, the Ideas exist outside of space and time. It’s clear that they are outside space. If they were in space, they would have to be located somewhere specific. We should be able to find them in a particular place. A telescope or microscope might uncover them. This would suggest that they are individual and specific things, rather than universals. They are also outside of time because they are unchangeable and eternal; this doesn’t mean they are the same at all times. If that were the case, their unchanging nature would rely on observation rather than reason. We would, so to speak, need to check on them periodically to see if they had truly changed. However, their unchangeability is a matter of understanding, not experience. It’s not just that they always remain the same over time, but that time doesn’t apply to them at all. They are timeless. In the "Timaeus," eternity is distinguished from infinite time, with the latter described as merely a copy of eternity.

Ninthly, the Ideas are rational, that is to say, they are apprehended through reason. The finding of the common element in the manifold is the work of inductive {191} reason, and through this alone is knowledge of the Ideas possible. This should be noted by those persons who imagine that Plato was some sort of benevolent mystic. The imperishable One, the absolute reality, is apprehended, not by intuition, or in any kind of mystic ecstasy, but only by rational cognition and laborious thought.

Ninth, the Ideas are rational, meaning they are understood through reason. Identifying the common element in the diversity is the task of inductive {191} reasoning, and knowledge of the Ideas is only possible through this. This is important for those who think of Plato as some kind of kind mystic. The eternal One, the absolute reality, is grasped not through intuition or any mystical experience, but solely through rational understanding and diligent thought.

Lastly, towards the end of his life, Plato identified the Ideas with the Pythagorean numbers. We know this from Aristotle, but it is not mentioned in the dialogues of Plato himself. It appears to have been a theory adopted in old age, and set forth in the lectures which Aristotle attended. It is a retrograde step, and tends to degrade the great and lucid idealism of Plato into a mathematical mysticism. In this, as in other respects, the influence of the Pythagoreans upon Plato was harmful.

Lastly, towards the end of his life, Plato linked the Ideas with the Pythagorean numbers. We know this from Aristotle, but it isn’t mentioned in Plato's own dialogues. It seems to have been a theory he adopted in his old age and presented in the lectures that Aristotle attended. This is a backward step and tends to lower the great and clear idealism of Plato into a kind of mathematical mysticism. In this way, as in other respects, the influence of the Pythagoreans on Plato was detrimental.

It results from this whole theory of Ideas that there are two sources of human experience, sense-perception and reason. Sense-perception has for its object the world of sense; reason has for its object the Ideas. The world of sense has all the opposite characteristics to the Ideas. The Ideas are absolute reality, absolute Being. Objects of sense are absolute unreality, not-being, except in so far as the Ideas are in them. Whatever reality they have they owe to the Ideas. There is in Plato's system a principle of absolute not-being which we shall consider when we come to deal with his Physics. Objects of sense participate both in the Ideas and in this not-being. They are, therefore, half way between Being and not-being. They are half real. Ideas, again, are universal; things of sense are always particular and individual. The Idea is one, the sense-object is always {192} a multiplicity. Ideas are outside space and time, things of sense are both temporal and spatial. The Idea is eternal and immutable; sense-objects are changeable and in perpetual flux.

It follows from this entire theory of Ideas that there are two sources of human experience: sensory perception and reason. Sensory perception focuses on the sensory world, while reason focuses on the Ideas. The sensory world has characteristics that are in direct contrast to the Ideas. The Ideas represent absolute reality and absolute existence. Sensory objects are absolutely unreal, or non-existent, except to the extent that the Ideas are present in them. Any reality they possess is due to the Ideas. In Plato's system, there's a principle of absolute non-being that we will discuss when we address his Physics. Sensory objects participate in both the Ideas and this non-being, making them halfway between existence and non-existence. They are partially real. Ideas, on the other hand, are universal; sensory things are always specific and individual. The Idea is singular, while the sensory object is always a {192} plurality. Ideas exist outside of space and time, while sensory objects are both temporal and spatial. The Idea is eternal and unchanging; sensory objects are variable and in constant motion.

As regards the last point, Plato adopts the view of Heracleitus that there is an absolute Becoming, and he identifies it with the world of sense, which contains nothing stable and permanent, but is a constant flow. The Idea always is, and never becomes; the thing of sense always becomes, and never is. It is for this reason that, in the opinion of Plato, no knowledge of the world of sense is possible, for one can have no knowledge of that which changes from moment to moment. Knowledge is only possible if its subject stands fixed before the mind, is permanent and changeless. The only knowledge, then, is knowledge of the Ideas.

Regarding the last point, Plato agrees with Heraclitus that there is a constant state of becoming, which he connects to the sensory world, where nothing is stable or permanent, but everything is in constant flux. The Idea always exists and never changes; the sensory object is always changing and never truly exists. This is why, according to Plato, we can't truly know the sensory world, as we can't have knowledge of things that change every moment. Knowledge is only possible if its subject is fixed in the mind, permanent, and unchanging. Therefore, the only true knowledge is knowledge of the Ideas.

This may seem, at first sight, a very singular doctrine. That there can be no knowledge of sense-objects would, it might seem to us moderns, involve the denial that modern physical science, with all its exactitude and accumulated knowledge, is knowledge at all. And surely, though all earthly things arise and pass away, many of them last long enough to admit of knowledge. Surely the mountains are sufficiently permanent to allow us to know something of them. They have relative, though not absolute, permanence. This criticism is partly justified. Plato did underestimate the value of physical knowledge. But for the most part, the criticism is a misunderstanding. By the world of sense Plato means bare sensation with no rational element in it. Now physical science has not such crude sensation for its object. Its objects are rationalized sensations. {193} If, in Plato's manner, we think only of pure sensation, then it is true that it is nothing but a constant flux without stability; and knowledge of it is impossible. The mountains are comparatively permanent. But our sensation of the mountains is perpetually changing. Every change of light, every cloud that passes over the sun, changes the colours and the shades. Every time we move from one situation to another, the mountain appears a different shape. The permanence of the mountain itself is due to the fact that all these varying sensations are identified as sensations of one and the same object. The idea of identity is involved here, and it is, as it were, a thread upon which these fleeting sensations are strung. But the idea of identity cannot be obtained from the senses. It is introduced into things by reason. Hence knowledge of this permanent mountain is only possible through the exercise of reason. In Plato's language, all we can know of the mountain is the Ideas in which it participates. To revert to a previous example, even the knowledge "this paper is white" involves the activity of intellect, and is impossible through sensation alone. Bare sensation is a flow, of which no knowledge is possible.

This might initially seem like a very unusual idea. The claim that we can't know anything about sensory objects might suggest to us today that modern physical science, with all its precision and accumulated knowledge, isn't really knowledge at all. And surely, even though all earthly things come and go, many of them last long enough for us to gain knowledge about them. The mountains are definitely stable enough for us to understand something about them. They have a relative, though not absolute, permanence. This criticism has some merit. Plato did underestimate the importance of physical knowledge. However, most of the criticism is based on a misunderstanding. When Plato refers to the world of senses, he means pure sensation without any rational element. But physical science doesn't focus on such crude sensations. Its subjects are rationalized sensations. {193} If we think solely in terms of pure sensation, then it's true that it's just a constant change without stability, and knowing it is impossible. The mountains are relatively stable. But our perception of the mountains is always changing. Every change in light, every cloud that moves across the sun, alters the colors and the shades. Each time we change our position, the mountain looks like a different shape. The mountain’s permanence comes from the fact that all these different sensations are recognized as sensations of one and the same object. The idea of identity plays a role here, acting like a thread that connects these fleeting sensations. But we can't derive the idea of identity from our senses. It's something we bring to things through reason. Therefore, knowledge of this permanent mountain is only possible by using reason. In Plato's terms, all we can know about the mountain are the Ideas it embodies. To revisit a previous example, even the knowledge "this paper is white" requires intellectual involvement and can't be attained through sensation alone. Pure sensation is a flow, from which no knowledge can be gained.

Aristotle observes that Plato's theory of Ideas has three sources, the teachings of the Eleatics, of Heracleitus, and of Socrates. From Heracleitus, Plato took the notion of a sphere of Becoming, and it appears in his system as the world of sense. From the Eleatics he took the idea of a sphere of absolute Being. From Socrates he took the doctrine of concepts, and proceeded to identify the Eleatic Being with the Socratic concepts. This gives him his theory of Ideas.

Aristotle notes that Plato's theory of Ideas comes from three sources: the teachings of the Eleatics, Heraclitus, and Socrates. From Heraclitus, Plato adopted the idea of a realm of Becoming, which he integrated into his system as the world of sensory experience. From the Eleatics, he borrowed the concept of a realm of absolute Being. From Socrates, he took the theory of concepts and went on to equate the Eleatic Being with the Socratic concepts. This forms the basis of his theory of Ideas.

Sense objects, so far as they are knowable, that is so far as they are more than bare sensations, are so only because the Idea resides in them. And this yields the clue to Plato's teaching regarding the relation of sense objects to the Ideas. The Ideas are, in the first place the cause, that is to say, the ground (not the mechanical cause) of sense-objects. The Ideas are the absolute reality by which individual things must be explained. The being of things flows into them from the Ideas. They are "copies," "imitations," of the Ideas. In so far as they resemble the Idea, they are real; in so far as they differ from it, they are unreal. In general, sense objects are, in Plato's opinion, only very dim, poor and imperfect copies of the Ideas. They are mere shadows, and half-realities. Another expression frequently used by Plato to express this relationship is that of "participation." Things participate in the Ideas. White objects participate in the one whiteness, beautiful objects, in the one beauty. In this way beauty itself is the cause or explanation of beautiful objects, and so of all other Ideas. The Ideas are thus both transcendent and immanent; immanent in so far as they reside in the things of sense, transcendent inasmuch as they have a reality of their own apart from the objects of sense which participate in them. The Idea of man would still be real even if all men were destroyed, and it was real before any man existed, if there ever was such a time. For the Ideas, being timeless, cannot be real now and not then.

Sense objects, as far as we can know them—meaning, as long as they’re more than just bare sensations—are only that way because the Idea exists within them. This gives us insight into Plato's teaching about how sense objects relate to the Ideas. The Ideas are primarily the cause, or the reason (not in a mechanical sense), behind sense objects. The Ideas represent absolute reality, which is how we must understand individual things. The essence of things comes from the Ideas. They are "copies" or "imitations" of the Ideas. To the extent that they resemble the Idea, they are real; to the extent that they differ, they are unreal. Overall, in Plato’s view, sense objects are just very faint, poor, and imperfect copies of the Ideas. They are mere shadows and partial realities. Another term often used by Plato to describe this relationship is "participation." Things participate in the Ideas. White objects share in the concept of whiteness, beautiful objects share in the concept of beauty. Thus, beauty itself explains beautiful objects and all other Ideas. The Ideas are both transcendent and immanent; they are immanent in that they exist within the sense objects, and transcendent because they have their own reality separate from the sense objects that participate in them. The Idea of man would still be real even if all men were gone, and it existed before any man was born, if that time ever existed. The Ideas, being timeless, cannot be real at one time and not at another.

Of what kinds of things are there Ideas? That there are moral Ideas, such as Justice, Goodness, and Beauty, Ideas of corporeal things, such as horse, man, tree, star, river, and Ideas of qualities, such as whiteness, heaviness, {195} sweetness, we have already seen. But there are Ideas not only of natural corporeal objects, but likewise of manufactured articles; there are Ideas of beds, tables, clothes. And there are Ideas not only of exalted moral entities, such as Beauty and Justice. There are also the Ideal Ugliness, and the Ideal Injustice. There are even Ideas of the positively nauseating, such as hair, filth, and dirt. This is asserted in the "Parmenides." In that dialogue Plato's teaching is put into the mouth of Parmenides. He questions the young Socrates whether there are Ideas of hair, filth, and dirt. Socrates denies that there can be Ideas of such base things. But Parmenides corrects him, and tells him that, when he has attained the highest philosophy, he will no longer despise such things. Moreover, these Ideas of base things are just as much perfection in their kind as Beauty and Goodness are in theirs. In general, the principle is that there must be an Idea wherever a concept can be formed; that is, wherever there is a class of many things called by one name.

What types of things have Ideas? We’ve already seen that there are moral Ideas, like Justice, Goodness, and Beauty, Ideas of physical things, like horse, man, tree, star, river, and Ideas of qualities, like whiteness, heaviness, {195} sweetness. But there are Ideas not only of natural physical objects, but also of manufactured items; there are Ideas of beds, tables, and clothes. Additionally, there are Ideas not only of high moral concepts like Beauty and Justice, but also of Ideal Ugliness and Ideal Injustice. There are even Ideas of things that are truly disgusting, like hair, filth, and dirt. This is noted in the "Parmenides." In that dialogue, Plato's ideas are expressed through Parmenides, who asks the young Socrates whether there are Ideas of hair, filth, and dirt. Socrates argues that there can’t be Ideas of such lowly things. However, Parmenides corrects him, stating that when he reaches the highest level of philosophy, he will no longer look down on such things. Furthermore, these Ideas of lowly things are just as much perfection in their own way as Beauty and Goodness are in theirs. In general, the principle is that there must be an Idea wherever a concept can be formed; that is, wherever there is a group of many things referred to by one name.

We saw, in treating of the Eleatics, that for them the absolute Being contained no not-being, and the absolute One no multiplicity. And it was just because they denied all not-being and multiplicity of the absolute reality that they were unable to explain the world of existence, and were forced to deny it altogether. The same problem arises for Plato. Is Being absolutely excludent of not-being? Is the Absolute an abstract One, utterly exclusive of the many? Is his philosophy a pure monism? Is it a pluralism? Or is it a combination of the two? These questions are discussed in the "Sophist" and the "Parmenides."

We observed in our discussion about the Eleatics that, for them, absolute Being has no non-being, and the absolute One has no multiplicity. Their denial of all non-being and multiplicity in absolute reality left them unable to explain the world of existence, leading them to deny it entirely. The same issue comes up for Plato. Is Being completely free of non-being? Is the Absolute a purely abstract One, totally separate from the many? Is his philosophy simply monism? Is it pluralism? Or is it a mix of both? These questions are explored in the "Sophist" and the "Parmenides."

Plato investigates the relations of the One and the many, Being and not-being, quite in the abstract. He decides the principles involved, and leaves it to the reader to apply them to the theory of Ideas. Whether the Absolute is one or many, Being or not-being, can be decided independently of any particular theory of the nature of the Absolute, and therefore independently of Plato's own theory, which was that the Absolute consists of Ideas. Plato does not accept the Eleatic abstraction. The One cannot be simply one, for every unity must necessarily be a multiplicity. The many and the One are correlative ideas which involve each other. Neither is thinkable without the other. A One which is not many is as absurd an abstraction as a whole which has no parts. For the One can only be defined as that which is not many, and the many can only be defined as the not-one. The One is unthinkable except as standing out against a background of the many. The idea of the One therefore involves the idea of the many, and cannot be thought without it. Moreover, an abstract One is unthinkable and unknowable, because all thought and knowledge consist in applying predicates to subjects, and all predication involves the duality of its subject.

Plato explores the relationship between the One and the many, Being and not-being, in a very abstract manner. He outlines the principles involved and lets the reader apply them to the theory of Ideas. Whether the Absolute is one or many, Being or not-being, can be determined without relying on any specific theory about the nature of the Absolute, including Plato's own theory that the Absolute consists of Ideas. Plato rejects the Eleatic abstraction. The One cannot just be one, since every unity must inherently include a multiplicity. The many and the One are related concepts that depend on each other. Neither can be understood without the other. A One that is not many is as nonsensical an abstraction as a whole without parts. The One can only be defined as what is not many, and the many can only be defined as the not-one. The One is unthinkable unless it contrasts with a background of the many. Thus, the idea of the One inherently includes the idea of the many and cannot be conceived without it. Furthermore, an abstract One is unthinkable and unknowable, because all thought and knowledge come from applying predicates to subjects, and all predication involves the duality of its subject.

Consider the simplest affirmation that can be made about the One, namely, "The One is." Here we have two things, "the One," and "is," that is to say, being. The proposition means that the One is Being. Hence the One is two. Firstly, it is itself, "One." Secondly, it is "Being," and the proposition affirms that these two things are one. Similarly with any other predicate we apply to the One. Whatever we say of it involves its duality. Thus we find that all systems of thought which {197} postulate an abstract unity as ultimate reality, such as Eleaticism, Hinduism, and the system of Spinoza, attempt to avoid the difficulty by saying nothing positive about the One. They apply to it only negative predicates, which tell us not what it is, but what it is not. Thus the Hindus speak of Brahman as formless, immutable, imperishable, unmoved, uncreated. But this, of course, is a futile expedient. In the first place, even a negative predicate involves the duality of the subject. And, in the second place, a negative predicate is always, by implication, a positive one. You cannot have a negative without a positive. To deny one thing is to affirm its opposite. To deny motion of the One, by calling it the unmoved, is to affirm rest of it. Thus a One which is not also a many is unthinkable. Similarly, the idea of the many is inconceivable without the idea of the One. For the many is many ones. Hence the One and the many cannot be separated in the Eleatic manner. Every unity must be a unity of the many. And every many is ipso facto a unity, since we think the many in one idea, and, if we did not, we should not even know that it is a many. The Absolute must therefore be neither an abstract One, nor an abstract many. It must be a many in one.

Consider the simplest statement that can be made about the One, specifically, "The One is." Here we have two elements: "the One" and "is," which refers to being. This statement implies that the One is Being. So, the One consists of two aspects. First, it is itself, "One." Second, it is "Being," and this statement confirms that these two aspects are unified. The same applies to any other description we give to the One. Whatever we say about it reflects its dual nature. Therefore, we find that all philosophical systems that {197} propose an abstract unity as the ultimate reality, like Eleaticism, Hinduism, and Spinoza's philosophy, try to sidestep this issue by not making any positive statements about the One. They only use negative descriptions, which tell us what it is not, rather than what it is. For instance, the Hindus refer to Brahman as formless, immutable, imperishable, unmoved, uncreated. However, this approach is ultimately ineffective. First of all, even a negative description involves the duality of the subject. Secondly, a negative description always implies a positive one. You can't have a negative without a positive. To deny one thing is to affirm its opposite. Denying motion of the One by calling it the unmoved is to affirm that it is at rest. Therefore, a One that is not also a many is unimaginable. Likewise, the concept of the many can't exist without the concept of the One, as the many consists of multiple ones. Thus, the One and the many cannot be separated in the Eleatic way. Every unity must be a unity of the many. And every many is ipso facto a unity, since we understand the many as one concept, and without that, we wouldn't even recognize it as many. Therefore, the Absolute must be neither an abstract One nor an abstract many. It must be a many in one.

Similarly, Being cannot totally exclude not-being. They are, just as much as the One and the many, correlatives, which mutually involve each other. The being of anything is the not-being of its opposite. The being of light is the not-being of darkness. All being, therefore, has not-being in it.

Similarly, Being can’t completely eliminate not-being. They are, just like the One and the many, interconnected concepts that depend on each other. The existence of anything is the absence of its opposite. The existence of light is the absence of darkness. Therefore, all being contains not-being within it.

Let us apply these principles to the theory of Ideas. The absolute reality, the world of Ideas, is many, since {198} there are many Ideas, but it is one, because the Ideas are not isolated units, but members of a single organized system. There is, in fact, a hierarchy of Ideas. Just as the one Idea presides over many individual things of which it is the common element, so one higher Idea presides over many lower Ideas, and is the common element in them. And over this higher Idea, together with many others, a still higher Idea will rule. For example, the Ideas of whiteness, redness, blueness, are all subsumed under the one Idea of colour. The Ideas of sweetness and bitterness come under the one Idea of taste. But the Ideas of colour and taste themselves stand under the still higher Idea of quality. In this way, the Ideas form, as it were, a pyramid, and to this pyramid there must be an apex. There must be one highest Idea, which is supreme over all the others. This Idea will be the one final and absolutely real Being which is the ultimate ground, of itself, of the other Ideas, and of the entire universe. This Idea is, Plato tells us, the Idea of the Good. We have seen that the world of Ideas is many, and we now see that it is one. For it is one single system culminating in one supreme Idea, which is the highest expression of its unity. Moreover, each separate Idea is, in the same way, a many in one. It is one in regard to itself. That is to say, if we ignore its relations to other Ideas, it is, in itself, single. But as it has also many relations to other Ideas, it is, in this way, a multiplicity.

Let’s apply these principles to the theory of Ideas. The absolute reality, the world of Ideas, is many because there are many Ideas, but it is also one because the Ideas are not isolated units; they are part of a single organized system. In fact, there is a hierarchy of Ideas. Just as one Idea governs many individual things of which it is the common element, one higher Idea governs many lower Ideas and is the common element among them. And above this higher Idea, along with others, a still higher Idea will rule. For example, the Ideas of whiteness, redness, and blueness are all included under the one Idea of color. The Ideas of sweetness and bitterness fall under the one Idea of taste. But the Ideas of color and taste themselves fall under the even higher Idea of quality. In this way, the Ideas form a pyramid, and there has to be a peak. There must be one highest Idea that is supreme over all the others. This Idea will be the one final and absolutely real Being, which is the ultimate basis of itself, the other Ideas, and the whole universe. This Idea is, as Plato tells us, the Idea of the Good. We have seen that the world of Ideas is many, and now we see that it is one. For it is one single system culminating in one supreme Idea, which is the highest expression of its unity. Furthermore, each individual Idea is, in the same way, many in one. It is one regarding itself. In other words, if we ignore its relationships to other Ideas, it is single in itself. But because it has many relationships to other Ideas, it is, in this way, a multiplicity.

Every Idea is likewise a Being which contains not-being. For each Idea combines with some Ideas and not with others. Thus the Idea of corporeal body combines both with the Idea of rest and that of motion. {199} But the Ideas of rest and motion will not combine with each other. The Idea of rest, therefore, is Being in regard to itself, not-being in regard to the Idea of motion, for the being of rest is the not-being of motion. All Ideas are Being in regard to themselves, and not-being in regard to all those other Ideas with which they do not combine.

Every Idea is also a Being that includes not-being. Each Idea connects with some Ideas and not with others. For example, the Idea of a physical body connects with both the Idea of rest and the Idea of motion. {199} However, the Ideas of rest and motion do not connect with each other. Therefore, the Idea of rest is Being in relation to itself and not-being in relation to the Idea of motion, since the existence of rest means the non-existence of motion. All Ideas are Being in relation to themselves and not-being in relation to all the other Ideas they do not connect with.

In this way there arises a science of Ideas which is called dialectic. This word is sometimes used as identical with the phrase, "theory of Ideas." But it is also used, in a narrower sense, to mean the science which has to do with the knowledge of which Ideas will combine and which not. Dialectic is the correct joining and disjoining of Ideas. It is the knowledge of the relations of all the Ideas to each other.

In this way, a science of Ideas emerges, known as dialectic. This term is sometimes used interchangeably with the phrase "theory of Ideas." However, it can also refer more specifically to the study of which Ideas can combine and which cannot. Dialectic is the accurate connection and separation of Ideas. It involves understanding the relationships between all the Ideas.

The attainment of this knowledge is, in Plato's opinion, the chief problem of philosophy. To know all the Ideas, each in itself and in its relations to other Ideas, is the supreme task. This involves two steps. The first is the formation of concepts. Its object is to know each Idea separately, and its procedure is by inductive reason to find the common element in which the many individual objects participate. The second step consists in the knowledge of the inter-relation of Ideas, and involves the two processes of classification and division. Classification and division both have for their object to arrange the lower Ideas under the proper higher Ideas, but they do this in opposite ways. One may begin with the lower Ideas, such as redness, whiteness, etc., and range them under their higher Idea, that of colour. This is classification. Or one may begin with the higher Idea, colour, and divide it into the lower Ideas, red, white, {200} etc. Classification proceeds from below upwards. Division proceeds from above downwards. Most of the examples of division which Plato gives are divisions by dichotomy. We may either divide colour straight away into red, blue, white, etc.; or we may divide each class into two sub-classes. Thus colour will be divided into red and not-red, not-red into white and not-white, not-white into blue and not-blue, and so on. This latter process is division by dichotomy, and Plato prefers it because, though it is tedious, it is very exhaustive and systematic.

The achievement of this knowledge is, in Plato's view, the main issue in philosophy. To understand all the Ideas, each on its own and in relation to other Ideas, is the ultimate goal. This involves two steps. The first is creating concepts. Its purpose is to understand each Idea individually, and the method is to use inductive reasoning to identify the common factor that many individual objects share. The second step is understanding how Ideas relate to one another, which includes classification and division. Both classification and division aim to organize the lower Ideas under the appropriate higher Ideas, but they do this in opposite ways. One can start with the lower Ideas, like redness and whiteness, and group them under their higher Idea, which is color. This is classification. Alternatively, one can start with the higher Idea, color, and break it down into the lower Ideas, like red, white, {200}, etc. Classification moves from the bottom up. Division moves from the top down. Most of the division examples Plato provides are through dichotomy. We might divide color directly into red, blue, white, and so on; or we could split each category into two subcategories. So, color could be divided into red and not-red, not-red into white and not-white, not-white into blue and not-blue, and so on. This latter approach is division by dichotomy, and Plato prefers it because, while it can be tedious, it is very thorough and systematic.

Plato's actual performance of the supreme task of dialectic, the classification and arrangement of all Ideas, is not great. He has made no attempt to complete it. All he has done is to give us numerous examples. And this is, in reality, all that can be expected, for the number of Ideas is obviously infinite, and therefore the task of arranging them cannot be completed. There is, however, one important defect in the dialectic, which Plato ought certainly to have remedied. The supreme Idea, he tells us, is the Good. This, as being the ultimate reality, is the ground of all other Ideas. Plato ought therefore to have derived all other Ideas from it, but this he has not done. He merely asserts, in a more or less dogmatic way, that the Idea of the Good is the highest, but does nothing to connect it with the other Ideas. It is easy to see, however, why he made this assertion. It is, in fact, a necessary logical outcome of his system. For every Idea is perfection in its kind. All the Ideas have perfection in common. And just as the one beauty is the Idea which presides over all beautiful things, so the one perfection must be the supreme Idea which presides {201} over all the perfect Ideas. The supreme Idea, therefore, must be perfection itself, that is to say, the Idea of the Good. On the other hand it might, with equal force, be argued that since all the Ideas are substances, therefore the highest Idea is the Idea of substance. All that can be said is that Plato has left these matters in obscurity, and has merely asserted that the highest Idea is the Good.

Plato's actual execution of the ultimate task of dialectic, which is the classification and organization of all Ideas, isn't impressive. He hasn't tried to finish it. All he's provided are numerous examples. And really, that’s all we can expect, since the number of Ideas is clearly infinite, so the task of arranging them can never be fully achieved. However, there is one significant flaw in the dialectic that Plato definitely should have addressed. He tells us that the supreme Idea is the Good. This, being the ultimate reality, serves as the foundation for all other Ideas. Therefore, Plato should have derived all other Ideas from it, but he didn’t. He just states, in a somewhat dogmatic manner, that the Idea of the Good is the highest, without establishing any connection to the other Ideas. It's easy to understand why he made this claim. It’s actually a necessary logical consequence of his system. Every Idea represents perfection in its category. All Ideas share perfection. Just as the singular beauty is the Idea that oversees all beautiful things, the singular perfection must be the supreme Idea that oversees all the perfect Ideas. Hence, the supreme Idea must be perfection itself, which means the Idea of the Good. On the flip side, one could also argue, just as strongly, that since all Ideas are substances, the highest Idea should be the Idea of substance. Ultimately, it's clear that Plato has left these issues vague and simply claimed that the highest Idea is the Good.

Consideration of the Idea of the Good leads us naturally to enquire how far Plato's system is teleological in character. A little consideration will show that it is out and out teleological. We can see this both by studying the many lower Ideas, and the one supreme Idea. Each Idea is perfection of its kind. And each Idea is the ground of the existence of the individual objects which come under it. Thus the explanation of white objects is the perfect whiteness, of beautiful objects the perfect beauty. Or we may take as our example the Idea of the State which Plato describes in the "Republic." The ordinary view is that Plato was describing a State which was the invention of his own fancy, and is therefore to be regarded as entirely unreal. This is completely to misunderstand Plato. So far was he from thinking the ideal State unreal, that he regarded it, on the contrary, as the only real State. All existent States, such as the Athenian or the Spartan, are unreal in so far as they differ from the ideal State. And moreover, this one reality, the ideal State, is the ground of the existence of all actual States. They owe their existence to its reality. Their existence can only be explained by it. Now since the ideal State is not yet reached in fact, but is the perfect State towards which all actual States tend, it is clear that we have here {202} a teleological principle. The real explanation of the State is not to be found in its beginnings in history, in an original contract, or in biological necessities, but in its end, the final or perfect State. Or, if we prefer to put it so; the true beginning is the end. The end must be in the beginning, potentially and ideally, otherwise it could never begin: It is the same with all other things. Man is explained by the ideal man, the perfect man; white things by the perfect whiteness, and so on. Everything is explained by its end, and not by its beginning. Things are not explained by mechanical causes, but by reasons.

Thinking about the Idea of the Good naturally leads us to explore how Plato's system is fundamentally teleological. A bit of reflection will reveal that it is entirely teleological. We can see this by looking at both the many lower Ideas and the one supreme Idea. Each Idea represents perfection in its own category. Each Idea is the basis for the existence of the individual objects that fall under it. For example, the explanation for white objects is their perfect whiteness, and for beautiful objects, it is perfect beauty. We can also consider the Idea of the State that Plato describes in the "Republic." The common view is that Plato was outlining a State that was purely a product of his imagination and therefore should be seen as completely fictional. This completely misinterprets Plato. He was far from believing that the ideal State was unrealistic; in fact, he saw it as the only real State. All existing States, like the Athenian or the Spartan, are considered unreal as long as they differ from the ideal State. Moreover, this one reality, the ideal State, is the source for the existence of all actual States. They derive their existence from its reality. Their existence can only be understood through it. Since the ideal State hasn't yet been achieved in reality but is the perfect State that all actual States strive toward, it is clear that we have here {202} a teleological principle. The true explanation of the State isn't found in its historical origins, in an original contract, or in biological necessities, but in its goal—the final or perfect State. Or, if we want to express it differently: the true beginning is the end. The end must be present in the beginning, potentially and ideally; otherwise, it could never originate. This is true for everything else as well. A man is defined by the ideal man, the perfect man; white things by perfect whiteness, and so forth. Everything is explained by its end, not by its beginning. Things aren't explained by mechanical causes, but by reasons.

And the teleology of Plato culminates in the Idea of the Good. That Idea is the final explanation of all other Ideas, and of the entire universe. And to place the final ground of all things in perfection itself means that the universe arises out of that perfect end towards which all things move.

And Plato's teleology reaches its peak in the Idea of the Good. This Idea serves as the ultimate explanation for all other Ideas and the whole universe. Placing the ultimate foundation of everything in perfection itself means that the universe emerges from that perfect goal toward which everything is directed.

Another matter which requires elucidation here is the place which the conception of God holds in Plato's system. He frequently uses the word God both in the singular and the plural, and seems to slip with remarkable ease from the monotheistic to the polytheistic manner of speaking. In addition to the many gods, we have frequent reference to the one supreme Creator, controller, and ruler of the world, who is further conceived as a Being providentially watching over the lives of men. But in what relation does this supreme God stand to the Ideas, and especially to the Idea of the Good? If God is separate from the highest Idea, then, as Zeller points out, [Footnote 13] only three relations are possible, all of which are {203} equally objectionable. Firstly, God may be the cause or ground of the Idea of the Good. But this destroys the substantiality of the Idea, and indeed, destroys Plato's whole system. The very essence of his philosophy is that the Idea is the ultimate reality, which is self-existent, and owes its being to nothing else. But this theory makes it a mere creature of God, dependent on Him for its existence. Secondly, God may owe His being to the Idea. The Idea may be the ground of God's existence as it is the ground of all else in the universe. But this theory does violence to the idea of God, turning Him into a mere derivative existence, and, in fact, into an appearance. Thirdly, God and the Idea may be co-ordinate in the system as equally primordial independent ultimate realities. But this means that Plato has given two mutually inconsistent accounts of the ultimate reality, or, if not, that his system is a hopeless dualism. As none of these theories can be maintained, it must be supposed that God is identical with the Idea of the Good, and we find certain expressions in the "Philebus" which seem clearly to assert this. But in that case God is not a personal God at all, since the Idea is not a person. The word God, if used in this way, is merely a figurative term for the Idea. And this is the most probable theory, if we reflect that there is in fact no room for a personal God in a system which places all reality in the Idea, and that to introduce such a conception threatens to break up the whole system. Plato probably found it useful to take the popular conceptions about the personality of God or the gods and use them, in mythical fashion, to express his Ideas. Those parts of Plato which speak of God, and the governance of God, {204} are to be interpreted on the same principles as the other Platonic myths.

Another issue that needs clarification here is the role of the concept of God in Plato's system. He often uses the word God in both singular and plural forms, and he seems to shift effortlessly between monotheistic and polytheistic language. Along with many gods, he frequently refers to one supreme Creator, who controls and rules the world and is also seen as a Being that watches over human lives. But what is the relationship between this supreme God and the Ideas, especially the Idea of the Good? If God is separate from the highest Idea, then, as Zeller points out, [Footnote 13] only three relationships are possible, all of which are equally problematic. First, God might be the cause or foundation of the Idea of the Good. However, this undermines the substance of the Idea and, indeed, dismantles Plato's entire system. The core of his philosophy is that the Idea is the ultimate reality, which is self-existent and does not depend on anything else. But this theory makes it merely a creation of God, relying on Him for its existence. Second, God could derive His existence from the Idea, with the Idea serving as the basis for God's existence just like it is for everything else in the universe. But this diminishes the concept of God, reducing Him to a mere derivative existence, essentially making Him an illusion. Third, God and the Idea could be seen as equal, independent ultimate realities within the system. But this implies that Plato has given two conflicting accounts of ultimate reality, or, if not, that his system falls into hopeless dualism. Since none of these theories can hold up, we must conclude that God is identical to the Idea of the Good, and we encounter phrases in the "Philebus" that seem to clearly support this. However, in this case, God is not a personal God at all, since the Idea is not a person. The term God, in this usage, merely serves as a figurative reference to the Idea. This is the most likely theory, especially if we consider that there is actually no space for a personal God in a system that places all reality in the Idea, and introducing such a concept risks disrupting the entire system. Plato likely found it useful to take popular ideas about the personality of God or gods and use them mythologically to express his Ideas. The sections of Plato that discuss God and God's governance should be interpreted using the same principles applied to other Platonic myths.

[Footnote 13: Plato and the Older Academy, chap. vi.]

[Footnote 13: Plato and the Older Academy, chap. vi.]

Before closing our discussion of dialectic, it may be well to consider what place it occupies in the life of man, and what importance is attached to it. Here Plato's answer is emphatic. Dialectic is the crown of knowledge, and knowledge is the crown of life. All other spiritual activities have value only in so far as they lead up to the knowledge of the Idea. All other subjects of intellectual study are merely preparatory to the study of philosophy. The special sciences have no value in themselves, but they have value inasmuch as their definitions and classifications form a preparation for the knowledge of Ideas. Mathematics is important because it is a stepping-stone from the world of sense to the Ideas. Its objects, namely, numbers and geometrical figures, resemble the Ideas in so far as they are immutable, and they resemble sense-objects in so far as they are in space or time. In the educational curriculum of Plato, philosophy comes last. Not everyone may study it. And none may study it till he has been through all the preparatory stages of education, which form a rigorous discipline of the mind before it finally enters upon dialectic. Thus all knowledge ends in dialectic, and that life has not attained its end which falls short of philosophy.

Before wrapping up our discussion on dialectic, it makes sense to reflect on its role in human life and its significance. Plato's response is clear: Dialectic is the pinnacle of knowledge, and knowledge is the essence of life. All other intellectual pursuits only hold value if they contribute to understanding the Idea. Other subjects of study are merely stepping stones toward philosophy. The specialized sciences don't hold inherent value; instead, they are valuable because their definitions and classifications prepare us for grasping Ideas. Mathematics is significant because it bridges the gap between the sensory world and the Ideas. Its subjects, like numbers and geometric shapes, are like Ideas in that they are unchanging, but they also relate to sensory objects as they exist in space and time. In Plato's educational framework, philosophy is taught last. It's not something everyone can pursue, and no one should study it until they have completed all prior educational stages, which rigorously train the mind before it finally engages with dialectic. Thus, all knowledge culminates in dialectic, and a life that hasn't reached philosophy hasn't fulfilled its purpose.

Perhaps the most striking illustration of the subordination of all spiritual activities to philosophy is to be found in the doctrine of Eros, or Love. The phrase "platonic love" is on the lips of many, but, as a rule, something very different from Plato's own doctrine is meant. According to him, love is always concerned with beauty, and his teaching on the subject is expounded {205} chiefly in the "Symposium," He believed that before birth the soul dwelt disembodied in the pure contemplation of the world of Ideas. Sinking down into a body, becoming immersed in the world of sense, it forgets the Ideas. The sight of a beautiful object reminds it of that one Idea of beauty of which the object is a copy. This accounts for the mystic rapture, the emotion, the joy, with which we greet the sight of the beautiful. Since Plato had expressly declared that there are Ideas of the ugly as well as of the beautiful, that there are Ideas, for example, of hair, filth, and dirt, and since these Ideas are just as divine and perfect as the Idea of the beautiful, we ought, on this theory, to greet the ugly, the filthy, and the nauseating, with a ravishment of joy similar to that which we experience in the presence of beauty. Why this is not the case Plato omitted to explain. However, having learned to love the one beautiful object, the soul passes on to the love of others. Then it perceives that it is the same beauty which reveals itself in all these. It passes from the love of beautiful forms to the love of beautiful souls, and from that to the love of beautiful sciences. It ceases to be attached to the many objects, as such, that is to say, to the sensuous envelopes of the Idea of beauty. Love passes into the knowledge of the Idea of beauty itself, and from this to the knowledge of the world of Ideas in general. It passes in fact into philosophy.

Perhaps the most striking example of how all spiritual activities are subordinate to philosophy is found in the concept of Eros, or Love. The term "platonic love" is often used, but usually, it refers to something very different from what Plato actually meant. According to him, love is always connected to beauty, and his teachings on this topic are mainly explained in the "Symposium." He believed that before birth, the soul existed without a body, engaging solely in the pure contemplation of the world of Ideas. When it enters a body and becomes immersed in the sensory world, it forgets those Ideas. Seeing a beautiful object triggers a memory of the one Idea of beauty that the object reflects. This explains the mystical joy and emotion we feel when we see something beautiful. Since Plato clearly stated that there are Ideas of the ugly as well as of the beautiful—like Ideas of hair, filth, and dirt—and that these Ideas are just as divine and perfect as the Idea of beauty, according to his theory, we should react to the ugly, the filthy, and the disgusting with the same joy we feel in the presence of beauty. However, Plato did not explain why this is not the case. Once the soul learns to love one beautiful object, it moves on to love other objects. Then it realizes that the same beauty is present in all of them. It transitions from loving beautiful forms to loving beautiful souls, and from there to loving beautiful sciences. It stops being attached to the many objects themselves, the sensory forms of the Idea of beauty. Love evolves into the understanding of the Idea of beauty itself, and from that to the understanding of the world of Ideas as a whole. It actually turns into philosophy.

In this development there are two points which we cannot fail to note. In the first place, emotional love is explained as being simply the blind groping of reason towards the Idea. It is reason which has not yet recognized itself as such. It appears, therefore, in the {206} guise of feeling. Secondly, the later progress of the soul's love is simply the gradual recognition of itself by reason. When the soul perceives that the beauty in all objects is the same, that it is the common element amid the many, this is nothing but the process of inductive reasoning. And this development ends at last in the complete rational cognition of the world of Ideas, in a word, philosophy. Love is but an instinctive reason. The animal has no feeling of the beautiful, just because it has no reason. Love of the beautiful is founded upon the nature of man, not as a percipient or feeling being, but as a rational being. And it must end in the complete recognition of reason by itself, not in the feeling and intuition, but in the rational comprehension, of the Idea.

In this development, there are two important points we should note. First, emotional love is described as the blind search of reason for the Idea. It’s reason that hasn’t yet recognized itself as such. So, it comes across in the form of feelings. Second, the later evolution of the soul's love is just the gradual self-recognition of reason. When the soul sees that the beauty in all things is the same, that it’s the common thread among the many, this is simply the process of inductive reasoning. Ultimately, this evolution leads to a complete rational understanding of the world of Ideas—in other words, philosophy. Love is just an instinctive form of reason. Animals don’t experience beauty because they lack reason. The love of beauty is rooted in human nature, not as a perceiving or feeling being, but as a rational being. It must culminate in a full recognition of reason by itself, not through feelings and intuition, but through a rational understanding of the Idea.

One can imagine what Plato's answer would be to the sort of vulgarians and philistines who want to know what the use of philosophy is, and in what way it is "practical." To answer such a question is for Plato impossible, because the question itself is illegitimate. For a thing to have a use involves that it is a means towards an end. Fire has use, because it may be made a means towards the cooking of food. Money is useful, because it is a means to the acquisition of goods. That which is an end in itself, and not a means towards any further end, cannot possibly have any use. To suggest that philosophy ought to have use is, therefore, to put the cart before the horse, to invert the whole scale of values. It suggests that philosophy is a means towards some further end, instead of being the absolute end to which all other things are means. Philosophy is not for anything. Everything else is for it. And, if this seems an exaggerated or unpractical view, we may at least {207} remember that this is the view taken by the religious consciousness of man. Religion makes the supreme end of life the knowledge of, and communion with, God. God is for religion what the Idea is for philosophy. God is a figurative name for the Idea. To place the end of life in the knowledge of the Absolute, or the Idea, is therefore the teaching both of philosophy and religion.

One can imagine what Plato would say to those who are merely interested in the practical use of philosophy. For him, answering such a question is impossible, as the question itself is misguided. For something to have a use, it has to be a means to an end. Fire is useful because it can be used to cook food. Money is useful because it's a way to acquire goods. Something that is an end in itself, and not just a means to an additional end, can't really be considered useful. Suggesting that philosophy should have practical use reverses the fundamental values. It implies that philosophy is a means to achieve another goal, rather than being the ultimate goal itself to which all other things serve as means. Philosophy doesn't exist for anything else; everything else exists for it. If this view seems extreme or impractical, we can at least remember that this is how the religious consciousness of humanity sees it. Religion considers knowing and connecting with God as the highest purpose of life. God is to religion what the Idea is to philosophy. God is a symbolic representation of the Idea. Thus, placing the purpose of life in understanding the Absolute or the Idea is the teaching of both philosophy and religion.


4. Physics, or the Theory of Existence.

4. Physics, or the Science of Being.

Dialectic is the theory of reality, physics the theory of existence, dialectic of that which lies behind things as their ground, physics of the things which are thus grounded. That is to say, physics is concerned with phenomena and appearances, things which exist in space and time, as opposed to the timeless and non-spatial Ideas. Things of this kind are both corporeal and incorporeal. Physics falls therefore into two parts, the doctrine of the outward corporeality, the world, with its incorporeal essence, the World-Soul, and the doctrine of the incorporeal soul of man.

Dialectic is the theory of reality, while physics is the theory of existence. Dialectic looks at what lies behind things as their foundation, whereas physics focuses on the things that are built on that foundation. In other words, physics deals with phenomena and appearances—things that exist in space and time—unlike the timeless and non-spatial Ideas. These things can be both physical and non-physical. Therefore, physics can be divided into two parts: the study of the physical world and its non-physical essence, the World-Soul, and the study of the non-physical soul of humans.


(a) The Doctrine of the World.

(a) The Doctrine of the World.

If, in the dialectic, Plato has given an account of the nature of the first principle and ground of all things, the problem now arises of explaining how the actual universe of things arises out of that ground, how it is derived from the first principle. In other words, the Ideas being the absolute reality, how does the world of sense, and, in general, the existent universe, arise out of the Ideas? Faced with this problem, the system of Plato broke down. The things of sense are, we are told, "copies" or "imitations" of the Ideas. {208} They "participate" in the Ideas. So far, so good. But why should there be any copies of the Ideas? Why should the Ideas give rise to copies of themselves, and how is the production of these copies effected? To these questions Plato has no answer, and he therefore has recourse to the use of myths. Poetic description here takes the place of scientific explanation.

If Plato has explained the nature of the first principle and the foundation of everything in his dialectic, the next question is how the actual universe comes from that foundation, how it originates from the first principle. In other words, if the Ideas represent absolute reality, how does the sensory world, and the universe in general, emerge from the Ideas? Confronted with this issue, Plato's system falters. We're told that sensory things are "copies" or "imitations" of the Ideas. {208} They "participate" in the Ideas. That makes sense so far. But why should there be any copies of the Ideas? Why would the Ideas create copies of themselves, and how do these copies come into being? Plato doesn't have answers to these questions, so he turns to myths. In this case, poetic description replaces scientific explanation.

This poetic description of the origin of the world is to be found in the "Timaeus." We have seen that the Ideas are absolute Being, and that things of sense are half real and half unreal. They are partly real because they participate in Being. They are partly unreal because they participate in not-being. There must be, therefore, a principle of absolute not-being. This, in Plato's opinion, is matter. Things of sense are copies of the Ideas fashioned out of, or stamped upon, matter. But Plato does not understand by matter what we, in modern times, understand by it. Matter, in our sense, is always some particular kind of matter. It is brass, or wood, or iron, or stone. It is matter which has determinate character and quality. But the possession of specific character means that it is matter with the copy of Ideas already stamped upon it. Since iron exists in great quantities in the world, and there is a common element in all the various pieces of iron, by virtue of which all are classed together, there must be a concept of iron. There is, therefore, an Idea of iron in the world of Ideas. And the iron which we find in the earth must be matter which is already formed into a copy of this Idea. It participates in the Idea of iron. The same remarks apply to any other particular kind of matter. In fact, all form, all the specific characters and {209} features of matter, as we know it, are due to the operation of the Ideas. Hence matter as it is in itself, before the image of the Ideas is stamped upon it, must be absolutely without quality, featureless, formless. But to be absolutely without any quality is to be simply nothing at all. This matter is, therefore, as Plato says, absolute not-being. Zeller conjectures, probably rightly, that what Plato meant was simply empty space. [Footnote 14] Empty space is an existent not-being, and it is totally indeterminate and formless. It accords with this view that Plato adopted the Pythagorean tenet that the differential qualities of material substances are due to their smallest particles being regular geometrical figures limited out of the unlimited, that is, out of space. Thus earth is composed of cubes. That is to say, empty space when bound into cubes (the limiting of the unlimited) becomes earth. The smallest particles of fire are tetrahedra, of air octahedra, of water icosahedra.

This poetic description of the origin of the world is found in the "Timaeus." We’ve seen that Ideas are absolute Being, while sensory objects are partially real and partially unreal. They are partly real because they participate in Being, and partly unreal because they take part in non-being. Therefore, there must be a principle of absolute non-being. In Plato's view, this is matter. Sensory objects are copies of the Ideas shaped from, or impressed upon, matter. However, Plato doesn’t understand matter in the same way we do today. Matter, as we see it, is always a specific type of material—like brass, wood, iron, or stone. It is matter with defined characteristics and qualities. The specific characteristics imply that it’s matter that has already had the copy of Ideas impressed upon it. Since iron exists in large quantities in the world, and there is a common element among all different pieces of iron that allows them to be categorized together, there must be a concept of iron. Hence, there is an Idea of iron in the world of Ideas. The iron found in the earth must be matter that has already taken the shape of this Idea. It participates in the Idea of iron. The same applies to any other specific kind of matter. In fact, all forms, all specific characteristics and features of matter as we know it, result from the operation of the Ideas. Thus, matter in its pure form—before the image of Ideas is stamped on it—must be completely without quality, featureless, and formless. But to be completely without any quality is to be nothing at all. This matter is, therefore, as Plato describes, absolute non-being. Zeller speculates—probably correctly—that what Plato meant was simply empty space. Empty space is an existent non-being, completely indeterminate and formless. According to this view, Plato adopted the Pythagorean belief that the different qualities of materials are due to their smallest particles being regular geometric shapes formed from the unlimited, that is, from space. Thus, earth is made up of cubes. In other words, empty space, when shaped into cubes (the limitation of the unlimited), becomes earth. The smallest particles of fire are tetrahedra, those of air octahedra, and those of water icosahedra.

[Footnote 14: Plato and the Older Academy, chap. vii. ]

[Footnote 14: Plato and the Older Academy, chap. vii. ]

We have, then, on the one hand, the world of Ideas, on the other, matter, an absolutely formless, chaotic, mass. By impressing the images of the Ideas upon this mass, "things" arise, that is to say, the specific objects of sense. They thus participate both in Being and in not-being. But how is this mixing of Being and not-being brought about? How do the Ideas come to have their images stamped upon matter? It is at this point that we enter upon the region of myth. Up to this point Plato is certainly to be taken literally. He of course believed in the reality of the world of Ideas, and he no doubt also believed in his principle of matter. And he thought that the objects of sense are to be {210} explained as copies of the Ideas impressed upon matter. But now, with the problem how this copying is brought about, Plato leaves the method of scientific explanation behind. If the Ideas are the absolute ground of all things, then the copying process must be done by the Ideas themselves. They must themselves be made the principles for the production of things. But this is, for Plato, impossible. For production involves change. If the Ideas produce things out of themselves, the Ideas must in the process undergo change. But Plato has declared them to be absolutely unchangeable, and to be thus immutable is to be sterile. Hence the Ideas have within themselves no principle for the production of things, and the scientific explanation of things by this means becomes impossible. Hence there is nothing for it but to have recourse to myth. Plato can only imagine that things are produced by a world-former, or designer, who, like a human artist, fashions the plastic matter into images of the Ideas.

We have, then, on one side, the world of Ideas, and on the other, matter, which is an entirely formless, chaotic mass. By impressing the images of the Ideas onto this mass, "things" come into existence, meaning the specific objects we can perceive. They thus have a role in both Being and not-being. But how does this blending of Being and not-being happen? How do the Ideas get their images imprinted on matter? This is where we step into the realm of myth. Up to this point, Plato should be taken literally. He certainly believed in the reality of the world of Ideas, and he also believed in his concept of matter. He thought that the objects we perceive are explained as copies of the Ideas impressed upon matter. However, with the question of how this copying occurs, Plato moves away from scientific explanation. If the Ideas are the absolute foundation of all things, then the process of copying must be done by the Ideas themselves. They would need to be the principles for creating things. But for Plato, this is impossible. Production involves change. If the Ideas produce things from themselves, they must change in the process. But Plato has stated that they are absolutely unchangeable, and to be unchangeable is to be sterile. Therefore, the Ideas have no principle within themselves for producing things, making a scientific explanation of things in this way impossible. As a result, Plato has no choice but to turn to myth. He can only imagine that things are created by a world-maker or designer who, like a human artist, shapes the formless matter into representations of the Ideas.

God, the Creator, the world-designer, finds beside him, on the one hand, the Ideas, on the other, formless matter. First, he creates the World-Soul. This is incorporeal, but occupies space. He spreads it out like a huge net in empty space. He bisects it, and bends the two halves into an inner and an outer circle, these circles being destined to become the spheres of the planets and the stars respectively. He takes matter and binds it into the four elements, and these elements he builds into the empty framework of the World-Soul. When this is done, the creation of the universe is complete. The rest of the "Timaeus" is occupied with the details of Plato's ideas of astronomy and physical {211} science. These are mostly worthless and tedious, and we need not pursue them here. But we may mention that Plato, of course, regarded the earth as the centre of the world. The stars, which are divine beings, revolve around it. They necessarily move in circles, because the circle is the perfect figure. The stars, being divine, are governed solely by reason, and their movement must therefore be circular, because a circular motion is the motion of reason.

God, the Creator, the designer of the world, has next to him, on one side, the Ideas, and on the other, formless matter. First, he creates the World-Soul. This is immaterial but occupies space. He spreads it out like a giant net in empty space. He divides it into two halves and bends those halves into an inner and an outer circle, which are meant to become the spheres for the planets and the stars respectively. He takes matter and shapes it into the four elements, which he constructs within the empty framework of the World-Soul. Once this is done, the creation of the universe is complete. The rest of the "Timaeus" focuses on Plato's ideas about astronomy and physical science. These details are mostly trivial and tedious, and we need not delve into them here. However, we should note that Plato saw the earth as the center of the universe. The stars, which are divine beings, circle around it. They must move in circles because the circle is the perfect shape. The stars, being divine, are governed only by reason, so their movement must be circular since circular motion is the motion of reason.

The above account of the origin of the world is merely myth, and Plato knows that it is myth. What he apparently did believe in, however, was the existence of the World-Soul, and a few words upon this subject are necessary. The soul, in Plato's system, is the mediator between the world of Ideas and the world of sense. Like the former, it is incorporeal and immortal. Like the latter, it occupies space. Plato thought that there must be a soul in the world to account for the rational behaviour of things, and to explain motion. The reason which governs and directs the world dwells in the World-Soul. And the World-Soul is the cause of motion in the outer universe, just as the human soul is the cause of the motions of the human body. The cosmos is a living being.

The description of the world's origin above is just a myth, and Plato understands that it is a myth. However, he genuinely believed in the existence of the World-Soul, so it's important to discuss that a bit. In Plato's philosophy, the soul acts as a link between the realm of Ideas and the physical world. Like the realm of Ideas, it is non-physical and eternal. Like the physical world, it takes up space. Plato believed there had to be a soul in the universe to explain why things behave rationally and to account for motion. The reason that governs and guides the universe resides in the World-Soul. The World-Soul initiates movement in the outer universe, just as the human soul is responsible for the movements of the human body. The cosmos is a living being.


(b) The Doctrine of the Human Soul.

(b) The Doctrine of the Human Soul.

The human soul is similar in kind to the World-Soul. It is the cause of the body's movements, and in it the human reason dwells. It has affinities both with the world of Ideas and the world of sense. It is divided into two parts, of which one part is again subdivided into two. The highest part is reason, which is {212} that part of the soul which apprehends the Ideas. It is simple and indivisible. Now all destruction of things means the sundering of their parts. But the rational part of the soul, being simple, has no parts. Therefore it is indestructible and immortal. The irrational part of the soul is mortal, and is subdivided into a noble and an ignoble half. To the noble half belong courage, love of honour, and in general the nobler emotions. To the ignoble portion belong the sensuous appetites. The noble half has a certain affinity with reason, in that it has an instinct for what is noble and great. Nevertheless, this is mere instinct, and is not rational. The seat of reason is the head, of the noble half of the lower soul, the breast, of the ignoble half, the lower part of the body. Man alone possesses the three parts of the soul. Animals possess the two lower parts, plants only the appetitive soul. What distinguishes man from the lower orders of creation is thus that he alone possesses reason.

The human soul is similar to the World-Soul. It causes the body's movements, and it's where human reason resides. It has connections to both the world of Ideas and the world of senses. It's divided into two main parts, one of which is further split into two. The highest part is reason, which is {212} that aspect of the soul that understands the Ideas. It is simple and indivisible. Destruction of things refers to the separation of their parts. However, the rational part of the soul, being simple, contains no parts. Therefore, it is indestructible and immortal. The irrational part of the soul is mortal and is divided into a noble half and an ignoble half. The noble half includes courage, love of honor, and generally the more admirable emotions. The ignoble half consists of base desires. The noble half has a connection to reason, as it has an instinct for what is noble and great. However, this is just instinct and not rational thought. The seat of reason is in the head, the noble part of the lower soul is in the chest, and the ignoble part is in the lower body. Only humans have all three parts of the soul. Animals have the two lower parts, and plants only have the appetitive soul. What sets humans apart from lower forms of life is that they alone possess reason.

Plato connects the doctrine of the immortality of the rational soul with the theory of Ideas by means of the doctrines of recollection and transmigration. According to the former doctrine, all knowledge is recollection of what was experienced by the soul in its disembodied state before birth. It must carefully be noted, however, that the word knowledge is here used in the special and restricted sense of Plato. Not everything that we should call knowledge is recollection. The sensuous element in my perception that this paper is white is not recollection, since, as being merely sensuous, it is not, in Plato's opinion, to be called knowledge. Here, as elsewhere, he confines the term {213} to rational knowledge, that is to say, knowledge of the Ideas, though it is doubtful whether he is wholly consistent with himself in the matter, especially in regard to mathematical knowledge. It must also be noted that this doctrine has nothing in common with the Oriental doctrine of the memory of our past lives upon the earth. An example of this is found in the Buddhist Jàtakas, where the Buddha relates from memory many things that happened to him in the body in his previous births. Plato's doctrine is quite different. It refers only to recollection of the experiences of the soul in its disembodied state in the world of Ideas.

Plato links the idea of the immortality of the rational soul with the theory of Ideas through the concepts of recollection and transmigration. According to the first concept, all knowledge is simply recalling what the soul experienced while it was disembodied before birth. However, it's important to note that the term knowledge is used here in a specific and limited way by Plato. Not everything we would consider knowledge qualifies as recollection. The sensory aspect of my perception that this paper is white isn't recollection, because, according to Plato, it is merely sensory and should not be called knowledge. Here, as in other cases, he limits the term {213} to rational knowledge, meaning knowledge of the Ideas, though it's uncertain whether he is entirely consistent on this, particularly regarding mathematical knowledge. It's also crucial to recognize that this doctrine has nothing in common with the Eastern belief in the memory of our past lives on earth. An example of this can be found in the Buddhist Jàtakas, where the Buddha recounts from memory many events that occurred to him in his previous incarnations. Plato's doctrine is quite distinct. It only pertains to the recollection of the experiences of the soul in its disembodied state in the realm of Ideas.

The reasons assigned by Plato for believing in this doctrine may be reduced to two. Firstly, knowledge of the Ideas cannot be derived from the senses, because the Idea is never pure in its sensuous manifestation, but always mixed. The one beauty, for example, is only found in experience mixed with the ugly. The second reason is more striking. And, if the doctrine of recollection is itself fantastic, this, the chief reason upon which Plato bases it, is interesting and important. He pointed out that mathematical knowledge seems to be innate in the mind. It is neither imparted to us by instruction, nor is it gained from experience. Plato, in fact, came within an ace of discovering what, in modern times, is called the distinction between necessary and contingent knowledge, a distinction which was made by Kant the basis of most far-reaching developments in philosophy. The character of necessity attaches to rational knowledge, but not to sensuous. To explain this distinction, we may take as our example of rational knowledge such a proposition as that two {214} and two make four. This does not mean merely that, as a matter of fact, every two objects and every other two objects, with which we have tried the experiment, make four. It is not merely a fact, it is a necessity. It is not merely that two and two do make four, but that they must make four. It is inconceivable that they should not. We have not got to go and see whether, in each new case, they do so. We know beforehand that they will, because they must. It is quite otherwise with such a proposition as, "gold is yellow." There is no necessity about it. It is merely a fact. For all anybody can see to the contrary it might just as well be blue. There is nothing inconceivable about its being blue, as there is about two and two making five. Of course, that gold is yellow is no doubt a mechanical necessity, that is, it is determined by causes, and in that sense could not be otherwise. But it is not a logical necessity. It is not a logical contradiction to imagine blue gold, as it would be to imagine two and two making five. Any other proposition in mathematics possesses the same necessity. That the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal is a necessary proposition. It could not be otherwise without contradiction. Its opposite is unthinkable. But that Socrates is standing is not a necessary truth. He might just as well be sitting.

The reasons Plato gives for believing in this idea can be boiled down to two points. First, knowledge of the Forms can’t come from our senses because the Form is never pure in its sensory form but always mixed. For example, perfect beauty can only be found in experiences that include both beauty and ugliness. The second reason is even more compelling. Even if the idea of recollection seems a bit far-fetched, the main reason Plato uses to support it is both interesting and significant. He noted that mathematical knowledge appears to be innate to the mind. It’s not something we learn from teaching, nor do we gain it from experience. In fact, Plato was very close to identifying what we now call the distinction between necessary and contingent knowledge—a distinction that Kant later used as the foundation for major developments in philosophy. Rational knowledge has a sense of necessity, while sensory knowledge does not. To illustrate this distinction, consider a proposition such as "two plus two equals four." This doesn’t simply mean that, in every instance we’ve tested, two objects combined with another two make four. It’s not simply a fact; it’s a necessity. It’s not just that two plus two equals four, but that they must equal four. It’s unimaginable that they wouldn’t. We don’t need to check each time to see if it holds; we know in advance that it will because it’s necessary. This is different from a statement like "gold is yellow." There’s no necessity there. It’s just a fact. As far as anyone can tell, it could just as easily be blue. There’s nothing inconceivable about gold being blue, unlike the impossibility of two plus two equaling five. Of course, saying that gold is yellow is a mechanical necessity—it’s determined by causes and in that sense, it couldn’t be otherwise. But it’s not a logical necessity. It’s not a logical contradiction to imagine blue gold, unlike imagining two plus two making five. The same necessity applies to any other mathematical statement. The proposition that the angles at the base of an isosceles triangle are equal is a necessary truth. It couldn’t be otherwise without leading to a contradiction. Its opposite is unthinkable. But saying that Socrates is standing is not a necessary truth; he could just as easily be sitting.

Since a mathematical proposition is necessarily true, its truth is known without verification by experience. Having proved the proposition about the isosceles triangle, we do not go about measuring the angles of triangular objects to make sure there is no exception. We know it without any experience at all. And if we {215} were sufficiently clever, we might even evolve mathematical knowledge out of the resources of our own minds, without its being told us by any teacher. That Caesar was stabbed by Brutus is a fact which no amount of cleverness could ever reveal to me. This information I can only get by being told it. But that the base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal I could discover by merely thinking about it. The proposition about Brutus is not a necessary proposition. It might be otherwise. And therefore I must be told whether it is true or not. But the proposition about the isosceles triangle is necessary, and therefore I can see that it must be true without being told.

Since a mathematical statement is always true, we know it's true without needing to verify it through experience. Once we've proven the statement about the isosceles triangle, we don’t need to measure the angles of triangular objects to check for exceptions. We understand it without any experience at all. And if we {215} were smart enough, we could potentially develop mathematical knowledge just from our own thinking, without needing a teacher to tell us. The fact that Caesar was stabbed by Brutus is something that no amount of cleverness could reveal to me. I can only learn that from being informed. However, the fact that the base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal is something I could figure out just by thinking about it. The statement about Brutus isn’t necessary; it could be different. So, I need to be told whether it’s true or not. But the statement about the isosceles triangle is necessary, which means I can realize it must be true without being told.

Now Plato did not clearly make this distinction between necessary and non-necessary knowledge. But what he did perceive was that mathematical knowledge can be known without either experience or instruction. Kant afterwards gave a less fantastic explanation of these facts. But Plato concluded that such knowledge must be already present in the mind at birth. It must be recollected from a previous existence. It might be answered that, though this kind of knowledge is not gained from the experience of the senses, it may be gained from teaching. It may be imparted by another mind. We have to teach children mathematics, which we should not have to do if it were already in their minds. But Plato's answer is that when the teacher explains a geometrical theorem to the child, directly the child understands what is meant, he assents. He sees it for himself. But if the teacher explains that Lisbon is on the Tagus, the child cannot see that this is true for himself. He must either believe the word {216} of the teacher, or he must go and see. In this case, therefore, the knowledge is really imparted from one mind to another. The teacher transfers to the child knowledge which the child does not possess. But the mathematical theorem is already present in the child's mind, and the process of teaching merely consists in making him see what he already potentially knows. He has only to look into his own mind to find it. This is what we mean by saying that the child sees it for himself.

Now, Plato didn’t clearly differentiate between necessary and unnecessary knowledge. However, he understood that mathematical knowledge can exist without experience or direct instruction. Kant later provided a more straightforward explanation of these facts. Plato concluded that this kind of knowledge must already be in the mind at birth and should be recollected from a previous existence. One might argue that even though this type of knowledge doesn't come from sensory experience, it can come from teaching. It can be passed from one mind to another. We need to teach children math, which wouldn’t be necessary if that knowledge were already in their minds. But Plato’s response is that when a teacher explains a geometric theorem to a child, as soon as the child understands the explanation, he agrees with it. He sees it for himself. However, if the teacher explains that Lisbon is on the Tagus, the child can’t immediately see that this is true for himself. He must either believe the teacher’s word or go see for himself. In this case, the knowledge is actually transferred from one mind to another. The teacher gives the child knowledge the child doesn’t possess. But the mathematical theorem is already present in the child’s mind, and teaching simply involves helping him see what he already potentially knows. He just needs to look into his own mind to find it. That’s what we mean when we say that the child sees it for himself.

In the "Meno" Plato attempts to give an experimental proof of the doctrine of recollection. Socrates is represented as talking to a slave-boy, who admittedly has no education in mathematics, and barely knows what a square is. By dint of skilful questioning Socrates elicits from the boy's mind a theorem about the properties of the square. The point of the argument is that Socrates tells him nothing at all. He imparts no information. He only asks questions. The boy's knowledge of the theorem, therefore, is not due to the teaching of Socrates, nor is it due to experience. It can only be recollection. But if knowledge is recollection, it may be asked, why is it that we do not remember at once? Why is the tedious process of education in mathematics necessary? Because the soul, descending from the world of Ideas into the body, has its knowledge dulled and almost blotted out by its immersion in the sensuous. It has forgotten, or it has only the dimmest and faintest recollection. It has to be reminded, and it takes a great effort to bring the half-lost ideas back to the mind. This process of being reminded is education.

In the "Meno," Plato tries to provide an experimental proof of the idea of recollection. Socrates is shown talking to a slave boy who, by his own admission, has no education in math and barely knows what a square is. Through skillful questioning, Socrates helps the boy recall a theorem about the properties of a square. The key point of the argument is that Socrates doesn’t tell him anything; he shares no information. He only asks questions. Therefore, the boy's knowledge of the theorem doesn’t come from Socrates teaching him, nor from experience. It can only be recollection. But if knowledge is recollection, one might wonder why we don't remember everything immediately. Why is the long process of math education needed? Because the soul, descending from the world of Ideas into the body, has its knowledge dulled and almost erased by its immersion in the sensory world. It has forgotten or retains only the faintest recollection. It needs to be reminded, and it requires significant effort to bring those half-forgotten ideas back to mind. This process of being reminded is what education is all about.

With this, of course, is connected the doctrine of {217} transmigration, which Plato took, no doubt, from the Pythagoreans. Most of the details of Plato's doctrine of transmigration are mere myth. Plato does not mean them seriously, as is shown by the fact that he gives quite different and inconsistent accounts of these details in different dialogues. What, in all probability, he did believe, however, may be summarized as follows. The soul is pre-existent as well as immortal. Its natural home is the world of Ideas, where at first it existed, without a body, in the pure and blissful contemplation of Ideas. But because it has affinities with the world of sense, it sinks down into a body. After death, if a man has lived a good life, and especially if he has cultivated the knowledge of Ideas, philosophy, the soul returns to its blissful abode in the world of Ideas, till, after a long period it again returns to earth in a body. Those who do evil suffer after death severe penalties, and are then reincarnated in the body of some being lower than themselves. A man may become a woman. Men may even, if their lives have been utterly sensual, pass into the bodies of animals.

This connects to the idea of {217} transmigration, which Plato likely borrowed from the Pythagoreans. Most of the specifics of Plato's idea about transmigration are purely mythical. He doesn't take them seriously, as shown by the fact that he offers different and inconsistent descriptions of these specifics in various dialogues. What he probably did believe can be summarized like this: the soul exists before birth and is immortal. Its natural home is the world of Ideas, where it initially existed without a body, in pure and joyful contemplation of Ideas. However, due to its connections with the sensory world, it descends into a body. After death, if a person has lived a good life, especially if they've pursued knowledge of Ideas and philosophy, the soul returns to its joyful home in the world of Ideas until, after a long time, it returns to earth in another body. Those who do wrong face severe punishments after death and are then reincarnated in a lower form than they had. A man can become a woman. In cases of extreme sensuality, men can even reincarnate as animals.


5. Ethics

5. Ethics

(a) The Ethics of the Individual

(a) The Ethics of the Individual

Just as Plato's theory of knowledge begins with a negative portion, designed to refute false theories of what truth is, so does his theory of morals begin with a negative portion, intended to refute false theories of what virtue is. These two negative departments of Plato's philosophy correspond in every way. As he was then engaged in showing that knowledge is not perception, as Protagoras thought, so he now urges that {218} virtue is not the same as pleasure. And as knowledge is not mere right opinion, neither is virtue mere right action. The propositions that knowledge is perception, and that virtue is pleasure, are indeed only the same principle applied to different spheres of thought. For the Sophists whatever appeared true to the individual was true for that individual. This is the same as saying that knowledge is perception. For the Sophists, again, whatever appeared right to the individual was right for that individual. This is the same as saying that it is right for each man to do whatever he pleases. Virtue is defined as the pleasure of the individual. This consequence of the Sophistic principles was drawn both by many of the Sophists themselves, and later by the Cyrenaics.

Just as Plato's theory of knowledge starts with a critique aimed at disproving false notions of truth, his theory of morals also begins with a similar critique to challenge incorrect ideas about virtue. These two negative aspects of Plato's philosophy align perfectly. Just as he demonstrated that knowledge isn't just perception, as Protagoras believed, he now asserts that virtue isn't the same as pleasure. And just as knowledge isn't simply the right opinion, virtue isn't simply the right action. The claims that knowledge is perception and that virtue is pleasure are essentially the same idea applied in different contexts. According to the Sophists, whatever seems true to an individual is true for that individual. This means that knowledge is perception. Similarly, the Sophists believed that whatever seems right to an individual is right for that individual, implying that it's acceptable for each person to do as they wish. Virtue is defined as the individual's pleasure. This outcome of the Sophistic ideas was recognized by many Sophists themselves and later by the Cyrenaics.

As these two propositions are thus in fact only one principle, what Plato has said in refutation of the former provides also his refutation of the latter. The theory that virtue is pleasure has the same destructive influence upon morals as the theory that knowledge is perception had upon truth. We may thus shortly summarize Plato's arguments.

As these two ideas are really just one principle, what Plato said against the first also counters the second. The idea that virtue equals pleasure has the same damaging effect on morals as the idea that knowledge is just perception had on truth. We can therefore briefly summarize Plato's arguments.

(1) As the Sophistic theory of truth destroys the objectivity of truth, so the doctrine that virtue is the pleasure of the individual destroys the objectivity of the good. Nothing is good in itself. Things are only good for me or for you. There results an absolute moral relativity, in which the idea of an objective standard of goodness totally disappears.

(1) Just like the Sophistic theory of truth undermines the idea of objective truth, the belief that virtue is about individual pleasure undermines the idea of objective goodness. Nothing is intrinsically good. Things are only good for me or for you. This leads to complete moral relativity, where the notion of an objective standard for goodness vanishes completely.

(2) This theory destroys the distinction between good and evil. Since the good is whatever the individual pleases, and since the pleasure of one individual is the {219} displeasure of another, the same thing is both good and evil at the same time, good for one person and evil for another. Good and evil are therefore not distinct. They are the same.

(2) This theory eliminates the difference between good and evil. Since what's considered good is whatever the individual desires, and one person's pleasure often results in another person's displeasure, the same thing can be both good and evil simultaneously—good for one person and evil for another. Therefore, good and evil are not separate; they are the same.

(3) Pleasure is the satisfaction of our desires. Desires are merely feelings. This theory, therefore, founds morality upon feeling. But an objective morality cannot be founded upon what is peculiar to individuals. If the moral code is to be a law binding upon all men, it can only be founded upon that which is common to all men, the universal reason.

(3) Pleasure is the fulfillment of our desires. Desires are just feelings. This theory, therefore, bases morality on feeling. But an objective morality can't be built on what is unique to individuals. If the moral code is to be a law that applies to everyone, it can only be founded on what is common to all people, universal reason.

(4) The end of moral activity must fall within, and not outside, the moral act itself. Morality must have an intrinsic, not a merely extrinsic, value. We must not do right for the sake of something else. We must do right because it is right, and thus make virtue an end in itself. But the Sophistic theory places the end of morality outside morality. We are to do right, not for its own sake, but for the sake of pleasure. Morality is thus not an end in itself, but merely a means towards a further end.

(4) The purpose of moral actions should be found within the act itself, not outside of it. Morality needs to have inherent value, not just external value. We shouldn’t do the right thing just for the sake of something else. We should do the right thing because it’s the right thing to do, making virtue an end in itself. However, the Sophistic theory places the purpose of morality outside of morality. We’re supposed to do the right thing, not for its own sake, but for the sake of achieving pleasure. Therefore, morality becomes just a means to an additional end, not an end in itself.

Virtue, therefore, is not pleasure, any more than knowledge is perception. Likewise, just as knowledge is not right opinion, so virtue is not right action. Right opinion may be held upon wrong grounds, and right action may be performed on wrong grounds. For true virtue we must not only know what is right, but why it is right. True virtue is thus right action proceeding from a rational comprehension of true values. Hence there arises in Plato's philosophy a distinction between philosophic virtue and customary virtue. Philosophic virtue is founded upon reason, and understands the {220} principle on which it acts. It is, in fact, action governed by principles. Customary virtue is right action proceeding from any other grounds, such as custom, habit, tradition, good impulses, benevolent feelings, instinctive goodness. Men do right merely because other people do it, because it is customary, and they do it without understanding the reasons for it. This is the virtue of the ordinary honest citizen, the "respectable" person. It is the virtue of bees and ants, who act as if rationally, but without any understanding of what they are doing. And Plato observes--no doubt with an intentional spice of humour--that such people may in the next life find themselves born as bees and ants. Plato denies philosophic virtue not only to the masses of men, but even to the best statesmen and politicians of Greece.

Virtue, then, isn’t just about pleasure, just like knowledge isn’t just perception. Similarly, just as knowledge isn’t merely the same as right opinion, virtue isn’t just about right action. Right opinion can be held for the wrong reasons, and right action can occur for the wrong reasons. To achieve true virtue, we need to understand not only what is right but also why it’s right. True virtue, therefore, is right action that comes from a rational understanding of true values. This leads to a distinction in Plato's philosophy between philosophical virtue and customary virtue. Philosophical virtue is based on reason and understands the principle behind its actions. Essentially, it’s about acting according to principles. Customary virtue, on the other hand, involves right actions taken for other reasons, like customs, habits, traditions, good impulses, kind feelings, or instinctive goodness. People often do the right thing just because others do it, adhering to what’s customary, and they do this without grasping the reasons behind their actions. This represents the virtue of the average honest citizen, the “respectable” person. It’s the virtue displayed by bees and ants, which may seem rational, but they lack any real understanding of their actions. Plato humorously suggests that such people might find themselves reincarnated as bees and ants in the next life. He claims that philosophical virtue is not only absent from the masses but also from even the best statesmen and politicians in Greece.

As true virtue is virtue which knows at what it is aiming, the knowledge of the nature of the highest aim becomes the chief question of ethics. What is the end of moral activity? Now we have just seen that that end must fall within, and not outside, the moral act. The end of goodness is the good. What, then, is the good? What is the supreme good, the summum bonum?

As genuine virtue is virtue that understands its purpose, understanding the nature of the highest goal becomes the main question of ethics. What is the purpose of moral actions? We've just established that this purpose must be found within the moral act itself, not outside of it. The goal of goodness is the good. So, what is the good? What is the ultimate good, the summum bonum?

A note of warning is necessary before we enter upon the details of this problem. Plato frequently speaks of all moral activity aiming at, and ending in, happiness. With modern phrases ringing in our ears, we might easily suppose this to mean that Plato is a utilitarian. The utilitarianism of Bentham and Mill is distinguished by the fact that it places the end of morality in happiness. Yet Plato was not a utilitarian, and would unhesitatingly have condemned the theory of Mill. He {221} would have found it identical in principle with the Sophistic doctrine that pleasure is the end of virtue. The only difference is that, whereas the Sophists identified virtue with the pleasure of the individual, Mill makes it the pleasure of the community. That act is right which leads to "the greatest happiness of the greatest number." In practice, of course, this makes a tremendous difference. But the principle is equally objectionable because, like the Sophistic theory, it founds morality upon mere feeling, instead of upon reason, and because it places the end of morality outside morality itself. Yet the formula of Mill, that the end of morals is happiness, seems the same as Plato's formula. What is the difference?

A warning is needed before we dive into the details of this issue. Plato often talks about all moral actions aiming for, and resulting in, happiness. With modern terminology in mind, we might easily assume that Plato is a utilitarian. The utilitarianism of Bentham and Mill is characterized by the idea that the goal of morality is happiness. However, Plato was not a utilitarian and would have readily condemned Mill's theory. He would have seen it as fundamentally the same as the Sophistic belief that pleasure is the ultimate goal of virtue. The only difference is that, while the Sophists associated virtue with individual pleasure, Mill ties it to the pleasure of the community. An action is considered right if it leads to "the greatest happiness for the greatest number." In practice, this makes a significant difference. But the principle is equally problematic because, like the Sophistic belief, it bases morality on mere feelings instead of reason and places the goal of morality outside of morality itself. Yet Mill's idea that the aim of morals is happiness seems to match Plato's view. So, what’s the difference?

The fact is that what Mill calls happiness Plato would have called pleasure. Pleasure is the satisfaction of one's desires, whether they are noble or ignoble. Then what is happiness? It can only be defined as the general harmonious well-being of life. Only that man is happy whose soul is in the state it ought to be in, only in fact the just, the good, and the moral man. Happiness has nothing to do with pleasure. If you could conceive an absolutely just and upright man, who was yet weighed down with every possible misery and disaster, in whose life pleasure had no part, such a man would still be absolutely happy. Happiness is, therefore, in Plato, merely another name for the summum bonum. In saying that the summum bonum is happiness, Plato is not telling us anything about it. He is merely giving it a new name. And we are still left to enquire: what is the summum bonum? what is happiness?

The fact is that what Mill refers to as happiness, Plato would have called pleasure. Pleasure is the fulfillment of one's desires, whether they're high-minded or base. So, what is happiness? It can only be defined as a general harmonious well-being in life. Only a person is happy whose soul is in the state it should be, specifically the just, the good, and the moral person. Happiness has nothing to do with pleasure. If you could imagine a completely just and upright person who was burdened with every possible misery and disaster, whose life had no pleasure, that person would still be absolutely happy. Therefore, for Plato, happiness is just another term for the summum bonum. When he says that the summum bonum is happiness, Plato isn't revealing anything new about it. He's just giving it a different name. And we are still left to ask: what is the summum bonum? What is happiness?

Plato's answer, as indeed his whole ethics, is but {222} an application of the theory of Ideas. But here we can distinguish two different and, to some extent, inconsistent strains of thought, which exist side by side in Plato, and perpetually struggle for the mastery. Both views depend upon the theory of Ideas. In the first place, the Idea, in Plato's philosophy, is the sole reality. The object of sense is unreal, and merely clogs and dims the soul's vision of the Ideas. Matter is that which obstructs the free activity of the Idea. Sense-objects hide the Idea from our view. Therefore the world of sense is wholly evil. True virtue must consist in flying from the world of sense, in retiring from the affairs of the world, and even from the beauty of the senses, into the calm of philosophic contemplation. And if this were all, philosophy, the knowledge of the Ideas, would be the sole constituent of the summum bonum. But it is possible to regard sense-objects in another light. They are, after all, copies of the Ideas. They are therefore a manifestation and revelation of the ideal world. Hence Plato is compelled by this thought to allow a certain value to the world of sense, its affairs, and its beauty.

Plato's answer, and indeed his entire ethics, is essentially {222} an application of the theory of Ideas. However, we can identify two distinct, and somewhat conflicting, lines of thought that exist side by side in Plato and continuously compete for dominance. Both perspectives rely on the theory of Ideas. Firstly, in Plato's philosophy, the Idea is the only true reality. The objects we sense are not real and simply obstruct and obscure the soul's perception of the Ideas. Matter hinders the unimpeded expression of the Idea. Sense-objects conceal the Idea from our sight. Consequently, the world of senses is entirely negative. True virtue must involve escaping the sensory world, withdrawing from worldly affairs, and even from sensory beauty, into the tranquility of philosophical contemplation. If this were the complete picture, then philosophy, the understanding of the Ideas, would be the only element of the summum bonum. However, it is also possible to view sense-objects differently. They are, after all, reflections of the Ideas. They represent a manifestation and revelation of the ideal world. Therefore, Plato is compelled by this idea to acknowledge a certain value in the sensory world, its matters, and its beauty.

The result of this inconsistency is, at any rate, that Plato remains broad and human. He does not, on the one hand, preach a purely selfish retirement into philosophy, or a narrow ascetic ideal. He does not, on the other hand, adopt a low utilitarian view of life, allowing value only to that which is "practical." He remains true to the Greek ideal of life as a harmonious play of all the faculties, in which no one part of man is over-developed at the expense of the others.

The outcome of this inconsistency is that Plato stays expansive and relatable. He neither advocates for a completely self-centered withdrawal into philosophy nor a limited ascetic ideal. Conversely, he doesn’t embrace a shallow utilitarian perspective on life that only values what is "practical." He stays committed to the Greek ideal of life as a balanced expression of all the faculties, where no part of an individual is overly developed to the detriment of the others.

The result is that Plato's summum bonum is not a single {223} end. It is a compound consisting of four parts. First, and chief of all, is the knowledge of the Ideas as they are in themselves, philosophy. Secondly, the contemplation of the Ideas as they reveal themselves in the world of sense, the love and appreciation of all that is beautiful, ordered, and harmonious. Thirdly, the cultivation of the special sciences and arts. And fourthly, indulgence in pure, refined, and innocent pleasures of the senses, excluding, of course, whatever is base and evil.

The result is that Plato's summum bonum is not a single end. It consists of four parts. First and foremost is the knowledge of the Ideas as they exist in themselves, which is philosophy. Second is the contemplation of the Ideas as they appear in the sensory world, including the love and appreciation of everything that is beautiful, organized, and harmonious. Third is the pursuit of the specific sciences and arts. And fourth is enjoying pure, refined, and innocent pleasures of the senses, while of course avoiding anything that is base and evil.

Plato had also a specific doctrine of virtue. As already stated, he distinguished between philosophic and customary virtue, and attached absolute value only to the former. He does not, however, deny a relative value to customary virtue, inasmuch as it is a means towards true virtue. Plato saw that man cannot rise at one bound to the pinnacles of rational virtue. He must needs pass through the preparatory stage of customary virtue. In the man in whom reason is not yet awakened, good habits and customs must be implanted, in order that, when reason comes, it may find the ground ready prepared.

Plato had a distinct view on virtue. As mentioned earlier, he differentiated between philosophical and conventional virtue, giving absolute importance only to the former. However, he acknowledged that conventional virtue has relative value since it serves as a stepping stone to true virtue. Plato understood that a person cannot jump straight to the heights of rational virtue. They must first go through the foundational stage of conventional virtue. For someone whose reason has not yet developed, good habits and customs should be established so that when reason does awaken, it finds a well-prepared foundation.

Socrates had taught that virtue is one. And Plato in his earlier writings adopted this view. But later on he came to see that every faculty of man has its place and its function, and the due performance of its function is a virtue. He did not, however, surrender the unity of virtue altogether, but believed that its unity is compatible with its plurality. There are four cardinal virtues. Three of these correspond to the three parts of the soul, and the fourth is the unity of the others. The virtue of reason is wisdom, of the noble half of {224} the mortal soul courage, of the ignoble appetites, temperance or self-control, in which the passions allow themselves to be governed by reason. The fourth virtue, justice, arises from the others. Justice means proportion and harmony, and accrues to the soul when all three parts perform their functions and co-operate with each other.

Socrates taught that virtue is one. Plato, in his earlier writings, accepted this idea. However, he later recognized that each part of a person has its own role and function, and fulfilling that function is a virtue. He didn't entirely abandon the idea of the unity of virtue, but he believed that this unity can coexist with its diversity. There are four key virtues. Three of these relate to the three parts of the soul, while the fourth encompasses the unity of the others. The virtue of reason is wisdom, the virtuous aspect of the mortal soul is courage, and the base desires reflect temperance or self-control, where passions are guided by reason. The fourth virtue, justice, comes from the others. Justice represents balance and harmony, and it manifests in the soul when all three parts perform their roles and work together.

Following Zeller, we may add to this account of the virtues some of Plato's views upon the details of life. And first, his opinion of women and marriage. Here Plato does not rise above the level of ordinary Greek morals. He has nothing specially original to say, but reflects the opinions of his age. Women he regards as essentially inferior to men. Moreover, the modern view of woman as the complement of man, as possessing those special virtues of womanliness, which a man lacks, is quite alien to Plato. The difference between men and women is, in his view, not one of kind but only of degree. The only specific difference between the sexes is the physical difference. Spiritually they are quite the same, except that woman is inferior. Hence Plato would not exclude women from the same education which man receives. He would educate them in exactly the same way, but this involves the imposition upon them of the same burdens. Even military duties are not outside the sphere of women.

Following Zeller, we can add to this discussion of virtues some of Plato's views on everyday life. First, there's his perspective on women and marriage. Here, Plato doesn’t elevate his ideas beyond the standard Greek morals of his time. He doesn't have anything particularly original to say and instead mirrors the attitudes of his era. He sees women as essentially inferior to men. Furthermore, the modern belief that women complement men, possessing unique feminine virtues that men lack, is completely foreign to Plato. In his opinion, the difference between men and women isn't a matter of kind but rather of degree. The only distinct difference between the sexes is physical. Spiritually, they are essentially the same, except that women are inferior. Therefore, Plato wouldn’t deny women the same education that men receive. He would educate them in the same manner, but this would require placing the same burdens on them. Even military responsibilities are within women's capabilities.

His views of marriage flow from the same principle. Since woman is not the complement of man, she is in no special sense fitted to be his companion. Hence the ideal of spiritual companionship is absent from Plato's view of marriage, the sole object of which, in his opinion, is the propagation of children. The natural companion {225} of a man is not a woman, but another man. The ideal of friendship, therefore, takes the place of the spiritual ideal of marriage in Plato and, indeed, among the ancients generally.

His views on marriage come from the same principle. Since a woman is not the complement of a man, she isn't specially suited to be his partner. As a result, the ideal of spiritual companionship is missing from Plato's perspective on marriage, which he believes is solely for the purpose of having children. The natural companion {225} of a man is not a woman, but another man. Therefore, the ideal of friendship replaces the spiritual ideal of marriage in Plato's view and, indeed, among the ancients in general.

Slavery is not denounced by Plato. He takes no trouble to justify it, because he thinks it so obviously right that it needs no justification. All that can be said to his credit is that he demands humane and just, though firm and unsentimental, treatment of slaves.

Slavery isn't criticized by Plato. He doesn’t bother to justify it because he believes it's so clearly right that it doesn’t require justification. The only thing that can be said in his favor is that he insists on humane and just, although firm and unsentimental, treatment of slaves.

If in these respects Plato never transcends the Greek view of life, in one matter at least he does so. The common view of his time was that one ought to do good to one's friends and evil to one's enemies. This Plato expressly repudiates. It can never be good, he thinks, to do evil. One should rather do good to one's enemies, and so convert them into friends. To return good for evil is no less a Platonic than a Christian maxim.

If in these respects Plato never goes beyond the Greek perspective on life, he does break new ground in one area. The common belief during his time was that people should do good for their friends and bad for their enemies. Plato clearly rejects this idea. He believes it can never be right to do evil. Instead, we should do good for our enemies and turn them into friends. Returning good for evil is a principle that is just as much a part of Plato's philosophy as it is of Christian teachings.


(b) The State.

(i) The State.


We pass from the ethics of individual life to the ethics of the community. Plato's "Republic" is not an attempt to paint an imaginary and unreal perfection. Its object is to found politics on the theory of Ideas by depicting the Idea of the State. This State is, therefore, not unreal, but the only real State, and its reality is the ground of the existence of all actually existent States.

We transition from personal ethics to community ethics. Plato's "Republic" doesn't try to illustrate a made-up or unrealistic perfection. Its purpose is to base politics on the theory of Ideas by showing the Idea of the State. This State is not fictional; it is the only true State, and its reality is the basis for the existence of all actual States.

We can trace here, too, the same two strains of thought as we found in considering the ethics of the individual. On the one hand, since the Idea alone is real, the existent world a mere illusion, the service of the {226} State cannot be the ideal life for a rational being. Complete retirement from the world into the sphere of Ideas is a far nobler end, and the aims of the ordinary politician are, in comparison, worthless baubles. Though only the philosopher is competent to rule, yet he will not undertake the business of the State, except under compulsion. In the political States, as they exist in the world, the philosopher dwells with his body, but his soul is a stranger, ignorant of their standards, unmoved by their ambitions. But the opposite strain of thought is uppermost when we are told that it is, after all, only in the State, only in his capacity as a citizen and a social being that the individual can attain perfection. It is only possible to reconcile these views in one way. If the ideals of the State and of philosophy seem inconsistent, they must be brought together by adapting the State to philosophy. We must have a State founded upon philosophy and reason. Then only can the philosopher dwell in it with his soul as well as with his body. Then only can either the individual or the State reach perfection. To found the State upon reason is the keynote of Plato's politics.

We can identify the same two lines of thought here as we did when looking at individual ethics. On one hand, since the Idea is the only true reality and the physical world is just an illusion, serving the {226} State can't be the ultimate goal for a rational person. Retreating completely from the world into the realm of Ideas is a far more noble pursuit, making the goals of ordinary politicians seem insignificant. Although only a philosopher is qualified to lead, he won't engage in state affairs unless absolutely necessary. In the political states as they exist today, the philosopher may inhabit them physically, but his soul is an outsider, unaware of their values and unaffected by their ambitions. However, a different perspective emerges when we consider that it is, ultimately, only within the State, in his role as a citizen and social being, that an individual can find true perfection. The only way to reconcile these views is by aligning the State with philosophy. We need a State that is grounded in philosophy and reason. Only then can the philosopher exist fully within it, both in body and soul. Only then can either the individual or the State achieve true perfection. Building the State on reason is the central theme of Plato's politics.

And this gives us, too, the clue to the problem, what is the end of the State? Why should there be a State at all? This does not mean, how has the State arisen in history? We are not in search of the cause, but of the reason, or end, of the State. The end of all life is wisdom, virtue, and knowledge. The unassisted individual cannot reach these ends. It is only by the State that they can be brought down from heaven to earth. The end of the State is thus the virtue and happiness (not pleasure) of the citizens. And since this is only possible {227} through education, the State's primary function is educational.

And this gives us a clue to the problem: what is the purpose of the State? Why should there even be a State? This isn’t about how the State came about in history; we’re not looking for the cause but the reason or purpose of the State. The ultimate goals of life are wisdom, virtue, and knowledge. An individual on their own can't achieve these goals. It's only through the State that these ideals can be brought from the realm of the ideal into reality. Therefore, the purpose of the State is the virtue and happiness (not just pleasure) of its citizens. Since this can only be achieved {227} through education, the primary role of the State is educational.

Since the State is to be founded upon reason, its laws must be rational, and rational laws can only be made by rational men, philosophers. The rulers must be philosophers. And since the philosophers are few, we must have an aristocracy, not of birth, or of wealth, but of intellect. The first operative principle of the State is reason, the second is force. For it is not to be expected that the irrational masses will willingly submit to rational laws. They must be compelled. And since the work of the world must go on, the third operative principle will be labour. Plato believed in the principle of division of labour. Only he can excel at any occupation whose life is devoted to it. Hence to the three operative principles correspond three classes, castes, or professions. Reason is embodied in the philosopher-rulers, force in the warriors, labour in the masses. This division of the functions of the State is based upon the threefold division of the soul. To the rational soul correspond the philosopher-rulers, to the nobler half of the mortal soul the warriors, to the appetitive soul the masses. Consequently the four cardinal virtues belong to the State through the functioning of the three classes. The virtue of the philosopher-rulers is wisdom, of the warriors courage, of the masses, temperance. The harmonious co-operation of all three produces justice.

Since the State is based on reason, its laws must be rational, and rational laws can only be created by rational people, specifically philosophers. The leaders need to be philosophers. And since there aren't many philosophers, we should have an aristocracy not based on birth or wealth, but on intellect. The first guiding principle of the State is reason, the second is force. It can’t be expected that the irrational masses will willingly follow rational laws; they must be compelled. As the work of the world must continue, the third guiding principle will be labor. Plato believed in the principle of division of labor. Only someone who dedicates their life to a specific occupation can truly excel at it. Thus, these three guiding principles correspond to three classes, castes, or professions. Reason is represented by the philosopher-rulers, force by the warriors, and labor by the masses. This division of the functions of the State aligns with the threefold division of the soul. The rational soul corresponds to the philosopher-rulers, the nobler part of the mortal soul corresponds to the warriors, and the appetitive soul corresponds to the masses. Therefore, the four cardinal virtues are integrated into the State through the functioning of these three classes. The virtue of the philosopher-rulers is wisdom, the warriors embody courage, and the masses represent temperance. The harmonious collaboration of all three results in justice.

The rulers must not cease to be philosophers. Most of their time must be spent in the study of the Ideas, philosophy, and only a portion in the affairs of government. This is rendered possible by the system of taking turns. Those who are not at any particular time {228} engaged upon government retire into thought. The duty of the warriors is the protection of the State, both against its external enemies, and against the irrational impulses of the masses of its own citizens. Normally, the latter will be their chief duty, the enforcement of the decrees of the philosopher-rulers upon the masses. The masses will engage themselves in trade, commerce, and agriculture. Both the other ranks are prohibited from soiling their fingers with trade or agriculture, upon which Plato, as a Greek aristocrat, looked down with unbounded contempt. To what rank a citizen belongs is not determined by birth, nor by individual choice. No individual can choose his own profession. This will be determined by the officers of the State, who will base their decision, however, upon the disposition and capabilities of the individual. As they have also to decide the numbers required for each rank, the magistrates also control the birth of children. Parents cannot have children when they wish. The sanction of the State is required.

The rulers must continue to be philosophers. They should spend most of their time studying the Ideas and philosophy, with only a small portion dedicated to government affairs. This is made possible through a system of taking turns. Those who aren't actively engaged in government at that time retreat into contemplation. The warriors' responsibility is to protect the State, both from external enemies and from the irrational impulses of its own citizens. Typically, the latter will be their primary duty—to enforce the philosopher-rulers' decisions on the masses. The general population will be involved in trade, commerce, and agriculture. The other classes are not allowed to get involved in trade or agriculture, which Plato, as a Greek aristocrat, viewed with disdain. A citizen's rank is not determined by birth or personal choice. No one can choose their own profession; this will be decided by the State officials, who will consider the individual's disposition and abilities. As they also determine how many individuals are needed for each rank, the magistrates manage population control. Parents cannot have children whenever they want; they need the State's approval.

Since the end of the State is the virtue of the citizens, this involves the destruction of whatever is evil and the encouragement of whatever is good. To compass the destruction of evil, the children of bad parents, or offspring not sanctioned by the State, will be destroyed. Weak and sickly children will also not be allowed to live. The positive encouragement of good involves the education of the citizens by the State. Children from their earliest years do not belong to their parents, but to the State. They are, therefore, at once removed from the custody of their parents, and transferred to State nurseries. Since the parents are to have no {229} property nor interest in them, stringent means are adopted to see that, after removal to the public nurseries, parents shall never again be able to recognize their own children. All the details of the educational curriculum are decreed by the State. Poetry, for example, is only allowed in an emasculated form. Of the three kinds, epic, dramatic, and lyric, the two former are banished from the State altogether, because, in the base example of the immorality of the gods, which they depict, they are powerful instruments in the propagation of evil. Only lyric poetry is allowed, and that under strict supervision. The subject, the form, even the metre, will be prescribed by the proper authorities. Poetry is not recognized as valuable in itself, but only as an educative moral influence. All poems, therefore, must strictly inculcate virtue.

Since the goal of the State is the virtue of its citizens, this requires eliminating anything evil and promoting what is good. To eliminate evil, the children of bad parents, or those not approved by the State, will be discarded. Weak and sickly children will also be condemned to death. Promoting good involves the education of citizens by the State. From an early age, children don’t belong to their parents but to the State. Therefore, they are immediately taken from their parents' care and placed in State-run nurseries. Since parents will have no ownership or interest in them, strict measures are taken to ensure that once children are moved to public nurseries, their parents will never recognize them again. The State dictates all aspects of the educational curriculum. Poetry, for example, is only permitted in a sanitized form. Of the three types—epic, dramatic, and lyric—the first two are completely banned, as their depiction of the gods' immorality serves as a powerful means of spreading evil. Only lyric poetry is permitted, and even that is subject to strict oversight. The topic, structure, and even the meter will be dictated by the appropriate authorities. Poetry is not seen as valuable in itself but only as a moral educational tool. Therefore, all poems must promote virtue.

It is, in Plato's opinion, intolerable that the individual should have any interest apart from the interests of the State. Private interests clash with those of the community, and must therefore be abolished. The individual can possess no property either in material things, or in the members of his family. This involves the community of goods, community of wives, and the State ownership of children from their birth.

In Plato's view, it's unacceptable for individuals to have interests that differ from those of the State. Personal interests conflict with the community's interests and should therefore be eliminated. Individuals cannot own property, whether it's material possessions or family members. This means shared resources, communal relationships, and the State's ownership of children from birth.


6. Views upon Art.

6. Perspectives on Art.

In modern times aesthetics is recognized as a separate division of philosophy. This was not the case in Plato's time, and yet his opinions upon art cannot be fitted into either dialectic, physics, or ethics. On the other hand, they cannot be ignored, and there is nothing for it, therefore, but to treat them as a sort of appendix {230} to his philosophy. Plato has no systematic theory of art, but only scattered opinions, the most important of which will now be mentioned.

In today's world, aesthetics is seen as a distinct branch of philosophy. This wasn't true in Plato's time, yet his views on art don't align neatly with dialectic, physics, or ethics. However, they can't be overlooked, so we have no choice but to consider them as a kind of appendix {230} to his philosophy. Plato doesn't offer a systematic theory of art; instead, he shares scattered opinions, the most significant of which will now be discussed.

Most modern theories of art are based upon the view that art is an end in itself, that the beautiful has, as such, absolute value, and not value merely as a means to some further end. Upon such a view, art is recognized as autonomous within its own sphere, governed only by its own laws, judged only by its own standards. It cannot be judged, as Tolstoi would have us believe, by the standard of morals. The beautiful is not a means to the good. They may be indeed, ultimately identical, but their identity cannot be recognized till their difference has been admitted. Nor can one be subordinated to the other.

Most modern theories of art hold that art exists for its own sake, meaning that beauty has inherent value and isn’t just valuable as a means to achieve something else. From this perspective, art is seen as independent within its own realm, governed solely by its own rules and evaluated by its own criteria. It shouldn’t be judged, as Tolstoi would suggest, by moral standards. Beauty isn’t just a path to goodness. While they might ultimately be the same, you can’t see that similarity until you acknowledge their differences. Nor can one be placed above the other.

Now this view of art finds no place at all in Plato's thought. Art is, for him, absolutely subservient both to morals and to philosophy. That it subserves morality we see from the "Republic," where only that poetry is allowed which inculcates virtue, and only because it inculcates virtue. It is no sufficient justification of a poem to plead that it is beautiful. Beautiful or not, if it does not subserve the ends of morality, it is forbidden. Hence too the preposterous notion that its exercise is to be controlled, even in details, by the State. That this would mean the utter destruction of art either did not occur to Plato, or if it did, did not deter him. If poetry cannot exist under the yoke of morality, it must not be allowed to exist at all. That art is merely a means to philosophy is even more evident. The end of all education is the knowledge of the Ideas, and every other subject, science, mathematics, art, is introduced into the {231} educational curriculum solely as a preparation for that end. They have no value in themselves. This is obvious from the teaching of the "Republic," and it is even more evident in the "Symposium," where the love of beautiful objects is made to end, not in itself, but in philosophy.

Now, this perspective on art has no place in Plato's thinking. For him, art is completely subordinate to morals and philosophy. We see its moral purpose in the "Republic," where only poetry that promotes virtue is permitted, and only because it promotes virtue. It's not sufficient for a poem to claim it's beautiful. Whether it's pretty or not, if it doesn't support moral goals, it’s banned. This leads to the absurd idea that the State should control it, even in detail. Plato either didn’t realize that this would completely destroy art, or if he did, it didn’t stop him. If poetry can’t exist under the constraints of morality, then it shouldn’t exist at all. It's even clearer that art is just a means to philosophy. The ultimate goal of education is to understand the Ideas, and every other subject—science, math, art—is included in the {231} curriculum only as preparation for that goal. They have no intrinsic value. This is clear from the teaching in the "Republic," and it's even more apparent in the "Symposium," where the love of beautiful things is supposed to lead, not to itself, but to philosophy.

Plato's low estimate of art appears also in his theory of art as imitation, and his contemptuous references to the nature of artistic genius. As to the first, art is, to him, only imitation. It is the copy of an object of the senses, and this again is only a copy of an Idea. Hence a work of art is only a copy of a copy. Plato did not recognise the creativeness of art. This view is certainly false. If the aims of art were merely to imitate, a photograph would be the best picture, since it is the most accurate copy of its object. What Plato failed to see was that the artist does not copy his object, but idealizes it. And this means that he does not see the object simply as an object, but as the revelation of an Idea. He does not see the phenomenon with the eyes of other men, but penetrates the sensuous envelope and exhibits the Idea shining through the veils of sense.

Plato's low opinion of art is also evident in his theory of art as imitation and his dismissive comments about artistic genius. To him, art is merely imitation. It’s just a copy of something we can sense, which itself is only a copy of an Idea. Therefore, a work of art is just a copy of a copy. Plato did not recognize the creativity involved in art. This perspective is definitely misguided. If art's only purpose was to imitate, then a photograph would be the best representation because it provides the most accurate copy of its subject. What Plato overlooked was that the artist doesn't just copy their subject; they idealize it. This means that they don't view the subject purely as an object but as the expression of an Idea. They don't perceive the phenomenon the way others do; instead, they go beyond the surface and reveal the Idea shining through the layers of sensory experience.

The second point is Plato's estimate of artistic genius. The artist does not work by reason, but by inspiration. He does not, or he should not, create the beautiful by means of rules, or by the application of principles. It is only after the work of art is created that the critic discovers rules in it. This does not mean that the discovery of rules is false, but that the artist follows them unconsciously and instinctively. If, for example, we believe Aristotle's dictum that the object of tragedy {232} is to purge the heart by terror and pity, we do not mean that the tragedian deliberately sets out to accomplish that end. He does so without knowing or intending it. And this kind of instinctive impulse we call the inspiration of the artist. Now Plato fully recognizes these facts. But far from considering inspiration something exalted, he thinks it, on the contrary, comparatively low and contemptible, just because it is not rational. He calls it "divine madness," divine indeed, because the artist produces beautiful things, but madness because he himself does not know how or why he has done it. The poet says very wise and beautiful things, but he does not know why they are wise and beautiful. He merely feels, and does not understand anything. His inspiration, therefore, is not on the level of knowledge, but only of right opinion, which knows what is true, but does not know why.

The second point is Plato's view on artistic genius. The artist doesn't create through reason, but rather through inspiration. They shouldn't, or don’t need to, produce beauty by following rules or applying principles. It’s only after the artwork is completed that critics can identify rules within it. This doesn’t mean that the discovery of these rules is incorrect; rather, the artist follows them unconsciously and instinctively. For instance, if we accept Aristotle's claim that the purpose of tragedy {232} is to cleanse the heart through fear and pity, we don’t imply that the playwright intentionally aims for that outcome. They achieve it without realizing or planning for it. This instinctual drive is what we refer to as the artist’s inspiration. Plato acknowledges these truths. However, instead of viewing inspiration as something lofty, he sees it as relatively low and contemptible, precisely because it’s not based on reason. He refers to it as "divine madness," divine because the artist creates beautiful things, but madness since they have no awareness of how or why it happens. The poet expresses very wise and beautiful ideas, but they don’t grasp why those ideas are wise and beautiful. They simply feel it, without understanding anything. Consequently, their inspiration is not grounded in knowledge, but merely in correct opinion, which recognizes what is true but lacks awareness of why it is true.

Plato's views of art are thus not satisfactory. He is doubtless right in placing inspiration below reason, and art below philosophy. They do stand to each other in the relation of higher and lower. Not that such a question can be decided by mere personal preferences. The usual discussions whether art or philosophy is better, whether emotion or reason is higher, are pointless and insipid, because the disputants merely exalt their personal peculiarities. The man of artistic temperament naturally prefers art, and says it is the highest. The philosopher exalts philosophy above art, merely because it is his pet hobby. This kind of discussion is futile. The matter must be decided upon some principle. And the principle is quite clear. Both art and philosophy have the same object, the {233} apprehension of the Absolute, or the Idea. Philosophy apprehends it as it is in itself, that is to say, as thought. Art apprehends it in a merely sensuous form. Philosophy apprehends it in its truth, art in a comparatively untrue way. Philosophy, therefore, is the higher. But while any true philosophy of art must recognize this, it must not interpret it to mean that art is to be made merely a means towards philosophy. It must somehow find room for the recognition of the truth that art is an end in itself, and it is in this that Plato fails.

Plato's views on art are not satisfactory. He is undoubtedly correct in ranking inspiration below reason, and art below philosophy. They relate to each other as higher and lower. However, this question can't be settled by personal preferences alone. The typical debates about whether art or philosophy is superior, or whether emotion or reason is higher, are pointless and bland, as the participants simply elevate their own biases. An artist naturally favors art and claims it is the highest form, while a philosopher prioritizes philosophy over art simply because it is their main interest. Such discussions are fruitless. The issue should be resolved based on some principle. And the principle is quite clear. Both art and philosophy aim for the {233} understanding of the Absolute, or the Idea. Philosophy understands it as it exists in itself, meaning as thought. Art, on the other hand, grasps it only in a sensory form. Philosophy comprehends it in its truth, while art does so in a somewhat less true manner. Therefore, philosophy is the higher discipline. However, any true philosophy of art must recognize this without suggesting that art exists solely as a tool for philosophy. It must also acknowledge that art is valuable in its own right, which is where Plato falls short.

Aristotle, who had no spark of artistic capacity in his composition, whose own writings are the severest of scientific treatises, did far greater justice to art than Plato, and propounded a far more satisfactory theory. Plato, himself a great artist, is utterly unjust to art. Paradoxical as it may appear, the very reason why Aristotle could be just to art was that he was no artist. Being solely a philosopher, his own writings are scientific and inartistic. This enables him to recognize art as a separate sphere, and therefore as having its own rights. Plato could not keep the two separate. His dialogues are both works of art and of philosophy. We have seen already that this fact exercised an evil influence on his philosophy, since it made him substitute poetic myths for scientific explanation. Now we see that it exercised an equally evil influence on his views of art. As a philosopher-artist his own practice is to use literary art solely as a means towards the expression of philosophical ideas. And this colours his whole view of art. It is, to him, nothing but a means towards philosophy. And this is the tap-root of his entire view of the subject.

Aristotle, who had no talent for artistic composition and whose writings are strictly scientific, did a much better job of understanding art than Plato did and developed a much more satisfying theory. Despite being a talented artist himself, Plato is completely unfair to art. Surprisingly, the very reason Aristotle was able to appreciate art was that he wasn’t an artist. As a pure philosopher, his own writings are scientific and lacking in artistic qualities. This allows him to see art as its own separate area, which gives it its own rights. Plato couldn’t keep the two separate. His dialogues are both artistic works and philosophical texts. We’ve already seen that this blended approach negatively impacted his philosophy, as it led him to replace scientific explanations with poetic myths. Now we can see that it also harmed his views on art. As a philosopher-artist, he primarily uses literary art as a way to express philosophical ideas. This shapes his entire perspective on art. To him, it is merely a tool for philosophy. This is the fundamental issue with his entire approach to the subject.


7. Critical Estimate of Plato's Philosophy,

7. Critical Evaluation of Plato's Philosophy,

If we are to form a just estimate of the value of Plato's philosophy, we must not fritter away our criticism on the minor points, the external details, the mere outworks of the system. We must get at the heart and governing centre of it all. Amid the mass of thought which Plato has developed, in all departments of speculation, that which stands out as the central thesis of the whole system is the theory of Ideas. All else is but deduction from this. His physics, his ethics, his politics, his views upon art, all flow from this one governing theory. It is here then that we must look, alike for the merits and the defects of Plato's system.

To truly understand the value of Plato's philosophy, we shouldn't waste our criticism on minor issues, the superficial details, or the outer layers of his system. We need to get to the core and central idea of it all. Among the vast amount of thought that Plato has explored across various fields, the main concept that stands out as the heart of his entire system is the theory of Ideas. Everything else is a deduction from this. His views on physics, ethics, politics, and art all stem from this one central theory. So, this is where we need to focus, both for the strengths and weaknesses of Plato's system.

The theory of Ideas is not a something sprung suddenly upon the world out of Plato's brain. It has its roots in the past. It is, as Aristotle showed, the outcome of Eleatic, Heracleitean, and Socratic determinations. Fundamentally, however, it grows out of the distinction between sense and reason, which had been the common property of Greek thinkers since the time of Parmenides. Parmenides was the first to emphasize this distinction, and to teach that the truth is to be found by reason, the world of sense being illusory. Heracleitus, and even Democritus, were pronounced adherents of reason, as against sense. The crisis came with the Sophists, who attempted to obliterate the distinction altogether, and to find all knowledge in sensation, thus calling forth the opposition of Socrates and Plato. As against them Socrates pointed out that all knowledge is through concepts, reason: and Plato added to this that the concept is not a mere rule of thought but a metaphysical reality. This was the substance of the theory of Ideas. {235} Every philosophy which makes a systematic attempt to solve the riddle of the universe necessarily begins with a theory of the nature of that absolute and ultimate reality from which the universe is derived. This absolute reality we will call simply the Absolute. Plato's theory is that the Absolute consists of concepts. To say that the Absolute is reason, is thought, is concepts, is the universal--these are merely four different expressions of the same theory. Now this proposition, that the Absolute is reason, is the fundamental thesis of all idealism. Since Plato's time there have been several great idealistic systems of philosophy. That the Absolute is reason is the central teaching of them all. Plato, therefore, is the founder and initiator of all idealism. It is this that gives him his great place in the history of philosophy. That the Absolute is universal thought, this is what Plato has contributed to the philosophical speculation of the world. This is his crowning merit.

The theory of Ideas didn't just pop up out of nowhere from Plato's mind; it has deep roots in history. As Aristotle showed, it comes from the ideas of the Eleatics, Heraclitus, and Socrates. At its core, it emerges from the distinction between the senses and reason, a concept that Greek thinkers have shared since Parmenides' time. Parmenides was the first to stress this difference and to teach that truth is discovered through reason, while the sensory world is an illusion. Heraclitus, and even Democritus, were strong supporters of reason over sense. The turning point came with the Sophists, who tried to erase this distinction completely and argued that all knowledge comes from sensation, igniting a response from Socrates and Plato. In opposition to them, Socrates pointed out that all knowledge arises through concepts and reason, while Plato expanded on this by stating that the concept is not just a mental framework but a metaphysical reality. This formed the basis of the theory of Ideas. {235} Every philosophy that systematically tries to unravel the mysteries of the universe starts with a theory about the nature of the absolute and ultimate reality from which everything else comes. We'll simply call this absolute reality the Absolute. Plato's theory suggests that the Absolute consists of concepts. Saying that the Absolute is reason, thought, concepts, or the universal—these are just four different ways of expressing the same idea. Now, this claim that the Absolute is reason is the fundamental premise of all forms of idealism. Since Plato's time, there have been several major idealistic philosophies, all centered around the idea that the Absolute is reason. Therefore, Plato is the originator and pioneer of all idealism, which is what secures his significant place in the history of philosophy. The concept that the Absolute is universal thought is Plato's main contribution to global philosophical thought, and this is his greatest achievement.

But we must go somewhat more into details. We must see how far he applied this principle successfully to the unravelment of the great problems of philosophy. In lecturing upon the Eleatics, I said that any successful philosophy must satisfy at least two conditions. It must give such an account of the Absolute, that the Absolute is shown as capable of explaining the world. It must be possible to deduce the actual world of facts from the first principle. Secondly, not only must this first principle explain the world; it must also explain itself. It must be really ultimate, that is, we must not, in order to understand it, have to refer to anything beyond and outside it. If we have to do so then our ultimate is not an ultimate at all; our first principle {236} is not first. That thing by means of which we explain it must itself be the ultimate reality. And besides being ultimate, our principle must be wholly intelligible. It must not be a mere ultimate mystery; for to reduce the whole world to an ultimate mystery is clearly not to explain it. Our first principle must, in a word, be self-explanatory. Let us apply this two-fold test to Plato's system. Let us see, firstly, whether the principle of Ideas explains the world, and secondly, whether it explains itself.

But we need to dive a bit deeper. We have to see how effectively he used this principle to tackle the big questions in philosophy. When I lectured on the Eleatics, I mentioned that any solid philosophy must meet at least two conditions. It has to provide an explanation of the Absolute in a way that shows it can account for the world. The actual world of facts needs to be able to be derived from the first principle. Secondly, this first principle not only has to explain the world; it also has to explain itself. It has to be genuinely ultimate, meaning we shouldn't need to reference anything beyond or outside of it to understand it. If we do, then what we've called ultimate isn’t really ultimate at all; our first principle {236} isn’t first. The means by which we explain it must itself be the ultimate reality. In addition to being ultimate, our principle must be completely understandable. It can’t just be a mysterious ultimate; simplifying the entire world to a mystery doesn't explain it. In short, our first principle must be self-explanatory. Let’s put this two-part test to Plato's system. First, let’s determine whether the principle of Ideas explains the world, and second, whether it explains itself.

Does it explain the world? Is the actual existence of things, horses, trees, stars, men, explained by it? What, in the first place, is the relation between things and the Ideas? Things, says Plato, are "copies," or "imitations" of the Ideas. They "participate" in the Ideas. The Ideas are "archetypal" of things. Now all these phrases are mere poetic metaphors. They do not really tell us how things are related to Ideas. But suppose we ignore this, and assume, for the sake of argument, that we understand what is meant by "participation" and that things are, in the literal sense, "copies" of Ideas. The question still remains, why do such copies exist, how do they arise? Now, if this problem is to be solved, it is not enough to show, merely as a fact, that, by some mysterious act, copies of Ideas come into existence. There must be a reason for it, and this reason it is the business of philosophy to explain. This reason, too, must exist in the nature of the Ideas themselves, and not outside them. There must be, in the very nature of the Ideas, some inner necessity which forces them to reproduce themselves in things. This is what we {237} mean by saying that the Ideas are a sufficient explanation of the existence of things. But there is in Plato's Ideas no such necessity. The Ideas are defined as being the sole reality. They have already all reality in themselves. They are self-sufficient. They lack nothing. It is not necessary for them further to realize their being in the concrete manifestation of things, because they, as wholly real, need no realization. Why, then, should they not remain for ever simply as they are? Why should they go out of themselves into things? Why should they not remain in themselves and by themselves? Why should they need to reproduce themselves in objects? There are, we know, white objects in the universe. Their existence, we are told, is explained by the Idea of whiteness? But why should the Idea of whiteness produce white things? It is itself the perfect whiteness. Why should it stir itself? Why should it not remain by itself, apart, sterile, in the world of Ideas, for all eternity? We cannot see. There is in the Ideas no necessity urging them towards reproduction of themselves, and this means that they possess no principle for the explanation of things.

Does it explain the world? Does the actual existence of things—like horses, trees, stars, and people—get explained by it? What is the relationship between things and Ideas? Plato says that things are "copies" or "imitations" of the Ideas. They "participate" in the Ideas. The Ideas are "archetypal" of things. But all these phrases are just poetic metaphors. They don't really clarify how things relate to Ideas. However, let's put that aside and assume, for the sake of argument, that we understand what "participation" means and that things are, in a literal sense, "copies" of Ideas. The question still stands: why do such copies exist, and how do they come to be? If we're going to solve this problem, it’s not enough to simply point out that, through some mysterious process, copies of Ideas come into being. There must be a reason for this, and it’s the role of philosophy to explain that reason. This reason must also stem from the nature of the Ideas themselves, not from anything outside of them. There has to be some inherent necessity in the Ideas that compels them to reproduce themselves in things. This is what we mean when we say that the Ideas provide a sufficient explanation for the existence of things. But in Plato's Ideas, there is no such necessity. The Ideas are defined as the only reality. They possess all reality within themselves. They are self-sufficient and lack nothing. They don’t need to further manifest their existence in the concrete form of things because they are already fully real and don’t require realization. So, why would they not simply remain as they are for all eternity? Why would they need to extend themselves into things? Why not stay within themselves and exist solely by themselves? Why would they need to reproduce in objects? We know that white objects exist in the universe. Their existence is said to be explained by the Idea of whiteness. But why should the Idea of whiteness create white things? It is itself the perfect whiteness. Why should it engage with anything? Why not remain by itself, separate and unproductive, in the world of Ideas for eternity? We can’t see the necessity. There is no drive within the Ideas pushing them to reproduce themselves, which means they lack a principle for explaining things.

Nevertheless Plato has to make some attempt to meet the difficulty. And as the Ideas are themselves impotent to produce things, Plato, unable to solve the problem by reason, attempts to solve it by violence. He drags in the notion of God from nowhere in particular, and uses him as a deus ex machina. God fashions matter into the images of Ideas. The very fact that Plato is forced to introduce a creator shows that, in the Ideas themselves, there is no ground of explanation. Things ought to be explained by the Ideas themselves, {238} but as they are incapable of explaining anything, God is called upon to do their work for them. Thus Plato, faced with the problem of existence, practically deserts his theory of Ideas, and falls back upon a crude theism. Or if we say that the term God is not to be taken literally, and that Plato uses it merely as a figurative term for the Idea of Good, then this saves Plato from the charge of introducing a theism altogether inconsistent with his philosophy, but it brings us back to the old difficulty. For in this case, the existence of things must be explained by means of the Idea of the Good. But this Idea is just as impotent as the other Ideas.

Nevertheless, Plato has to make some effort to address the issue. Since the Ideas themselves are unable to produce things, Plato, unable to resolve the problem through reasoning, tries to solve it through force. He introduces the concept of God from nowhere specific and uses Him as a deus ex machina. God shapes matter into the images of Ideas. The very fact that Plato is compelled to bring in a creator indicates that, within the Ideas themselves, there is no basis for explanation. Things should be explained by the Ideas themselves, {238} but since they cannot explain anything, God is called upon to do their work for them. Thus, faced with the issue of existence, Plato almost abandons his theory of Ideas and resorts to a simple form of theism. Or if we say that the term God should not be taken literally, and that Plato uses it merely as a figurative term for the Idea of Good, then this protects Plato from the accusation of introducing a theism that is completely inconsistent with his philosophy, but it brings us back to the original problem. In this case, the existence of things must be explained through the Idea of the Good. But this Idea is just as ineffective as the other Ideas.

In this connection, too, the dualism of Plato's system becomes evident. If everything is grounded in the one ultimate reality, the Ideas, then the entire universe must be clasped together in a system, all parts of which flow out of the Ideas. If there exists in the universe anything which stands aloof from this system, remains isolated, and cannot be reduced to a manifestation of the Ideas, then the philosophy has failed to explain the world, and we have before us a confessed dualism. Now not only has Plato to drag in God for the explanation of things, he has also to drag in matter. God takes matter and forms it into copies of the Ideas. But what is this matter, and where does it spring from? Clearly, if the sole reality is the Ideas, matter, like all else, must be grounded in the Ideas. But this is not the case in Plato's system. Matter appears as a principle quite independent of the Ideas. As its being is self-derived and original, it must be itself a substance. But this is just what Plato denies, calling it absolute {239} not-being. Yet since it has not its source in the Ideas or in anything outside itself, we must say that though Plato calls it absolute not-being, it is in fact an absolute being. The Ideas and matter stand face to face in Plato's system neither derived from the other, equally ultimate co-ordinate, absolute realities. This is sheer dualism.

In this regard, the dualism in Plato's system becomes clear. If everything is rooted in one ultimate reality, the Ideas, then the entire universe must be interconnected in a system where all parts come from the Ideas. If there’s anything in the universe that is separate from this system, remains isolated, and can't be considered a reflection of the Ideas, then Plato's philosophy fails to explain the world, and we encounter a clear dualism. Now, not only does Plato have to introduce God to explain things, but he also has to include matter. God takes matter and shapes it into copies of the Ideas. But what exactly is this matter, and where does it come from? Clearly, if the only reality is the Ideas, then matter, like everything else, must be rooted in the Ideas. But this isn't true in Plato's system. Matter appears as a principle that's quite independent of the Ideas. Since its existence is self-derived and original, it must be a substance itself. However, this is exactly what Plato denies, calling it absolute {239} not-being. Yet since it doesn’t originate from the Ideas or from anything outside itself, we have to conclude that although Plato refers to it as absolute not-being, it is, in fact, an absolute being. The Ideas and matter stand opposite each other in Plato's system, neither derived from the other, equally ultimate, coordinate, absolute realities. This is pure dualism.

The source of this dualism is to be found in the absolute separation which Plato makes between sense and reason. He places the world of sense on one side, the world of reason on the other, as things radically different and opposed. Hence it is impossible for him ever to bridge the gulf that he has himself created between them. We may expect the dualism of a philosophy which builds upon such premises to break out at numerous points in the system. And so indeed it does. It exhibits itself as the dualism of Ideas and matter, of the sense-world and the thought-world, of body and soul. Not, of course, that it is not quite right to recognize the distinction between sense and reason. Any genuine philosophy must recognize that. And no doubt too it is right to place truth and reality on the side of reason rather than sense. But although sense and reason are distinct, they must also be identical. They must be divergent streams flowing from one source. And this means that a philosophy which considers the absolute reality to be reason must exhibit sense as a lower form of reason. Because Plato fails to see the identity of sense and reason, as well as their difference, his philosophy becomes a continual fruitless effort to overreach the dualism thus generated.

The root of this dualism lies in the complete separation that Plato makes between the sensory world and the rational world. He puts the sensory world on one side and the rational world on the other, viewing them as fundamentally different and opposing. As a result, he can never truly bridge the gap he has created between them. We can expect the dualism in a philosophy based on such ideas to manifest in many areas of the system. And indeed, it does. It shows up as the dualism between Ideas and matter, between the sensory world and the world of thought, between body and soul. Of course, it’s entirely valid to recognize the distinction between sense and reason. Any genuine philosophy must do so. Clearly, it is also right to align truth and reality with reason rather than with sense. However, although sense and reason are distinct, they must also be identical. They should be like two diverging streams flowing from the same source. This means that a philosophy that views absolute reality as reason must portray sense as a lower form of reason. Because Plato fails to see both the identity and the difference between sense and reason, his philosophy becomes a continuous, unsuccessful struggle to overcome the dualism it has created.

Thus the answer to our first question, whether the theory of Ideas explains the world of things, must be {240} answered in the negative. Let us pass on to the second test. Is the principle of Ideas a self-explanatory principle? Such a principle must be understood purely out of itself. It must not be a principle, like that of the materialist, which merely reduces the whole universe to an ultimate mysterious fact. For even if it be shown that the reason of everything is matter, it is still open to us to ask what the reason of matter is. We cannot see any reason why matter should exist. It is a mere fact, which dogmatically forces itself upon our consciousness without giving any reason for itself. Our principle must be such that we cannot ask a further reason of it. It must be its own reason, and so in itself satisfy the demand for a final explanation. Now there is only one such principle in the world, namely, reason itself. You can ask the reason of everything else in the world. You can ask the reason of the sun, the moon, stars, the soul, God, or the devil. But you cannot ask the reason of reason, because reason is its own reason. Let us put the same thought in another way. When we demand the explanation of anything, what do we mean by explanation? What is it we want? Do we not mean that the thing appears to us irrational, and we want it shown that it is rational? When this is done, we say it is explained. Think, for example, of what is called the problem of evil. People often talk of it as the problem of the "origin of evil," as if what we want to know is, how evil began. But even if we knew this, it would not explain anything. Suppose that evil began because someone ate an apple. Does this make the matter any clearer? Do we feel that all our difficulties about the existence of evil are solved? No. This is {241} not what we want to know. The difficulty is that evil appears to us something irrational. The problem can only be solved by showing us that somehow, in spite of appearances, it is rational that evil should exist. Show us this, and evil is explained. Explanation of a thing, then, means showing that the thing is rational. Now we can ask that everything else in the world should be shown to be rational. But we cannot demand that the philosopher shall show that reason is rational. This is absurd. Reason is what is already absolutely rational. It is what explains itself. It is its own reason. It is a self-explanatory principle. This, then, must be the principle of which we are in search. The Absolute, we said, must be a self-explanatory principle, and there is only one such, namely, reason. The Absolute, therefore, is reason.

So the answer to our first question, whether the theory of Ideas explains the world of things, must be answered with a no. Let’s move on to the second question. Is the principle of Ideas self-explanatory? Such a principle should be understood entirely on its own. It shouldn’t be like the materialist principle that just reduces everything to a final mysterious fact. Because even if we prove that everything comes from matter, we can still ask what explains matter itself. We can’t see any reason why matter exists. It’s just a fact that imposes itself on our awareness without justifying its existence. Our principle has to be one that doesn’t require further justification. It must be its own reason and thus satisfy the need for a final explanation. Now, there’s only one such principle in the world—reason itself. You can ask why everything else exists—like the sun, the moon, the stars, the soul, God, or the devil. But you can’t ask why reason exists, because reason is its own explanation. Let’s phrase this differently. When we ask for an explanation of something, what do we actually mean? What are we looking for? Don’t we want to show that what seems irrational is actually rational? Once we do this, we consider it explained. Take the so-called problem of evil, for example. People often refer to it as the problem of the "origin of evil," as if we want to know how evil started. But even if we knew that, it wouldn’t explain anything. Suppose evil started because someone ate an apple. Does that clarify things? Do we feel our concerns about the existence of evil are resolved? No. That’s not what we’re trying to understand. The real issue is that evil seems inherently irrational. The problem can only be solved by demonstrating that, against appearances, there’s actually a reason for evil’s existence. Show us that, and then we can consider it explained. So, to explain something means to show that it makes sense. We can ask for everything else in the world to be demonstrated as rational, but we can’t demand the philosopher show that reason itself is rational. That’s absurd. Reason is already completely rational. It explains itself. It is its own reason. It is a self-explanatory principle. Therefore, this must be the principle we are looking for. The Absolute, as we said, has to be a self-explanatory principle, and there is only one such principle—reason. Therefore, the Absolute is reason.

It was the greatness and glory of Plato to have seen this, and thereby to have become the founder of all true philosophy. For to say that the Absolute is concepts is the same as saying it is reason. It might seem, then, that Plato has satisfied the second canon of criticism. He takes as first principle a self-explanatory reality. But we cannot quite so quickly jump to this conclusion. After all, the mere word reason is not a key which will unlock to us the doors of the universe. Something more is necessary than the mere word. We must, in fact, be told what reason is. Now there are two senses in which we might ask the question, what reason is, one of which is legitimate, the other illegitimate. It is illegitimate to ask what reason is, in the sense of asking that it shall be explained to us in terms of something else, which is not reason. This would be {242} to give up our belief that reason is its own reason. It would be to seek the reason of reason in something which is not reason. It would be to admit that reason, in itself, is not rational. And this is absurd. But it is legitimate to ask, what reason is, meaning thereby, what is the content of reason. The content of reason, we have seen, is concepts. But what concepts? How are we to know whether any particular concept is part of the system of reason or not? Only, it is evident, by ascertaining whether it is a rational concept. If a concept is wholly rational, then it is a part of reason. If not, not. What we need, then, is a detailed account of all the concepts which reason contains, and a proof that each of these concepts is really rational. It is obvious that only in this way can we make a satisfactory beginning in philosophy. Before we can show that reason explains, that is, rationalizes the world, we must surely first show that reason itself is rational, or rather, to be more accurate, that our conception of reason is rational. There must not be any mere inexplicable facts, any mysteries, any dark places, in our notion of reason. It must be penetrated through and through by the light of reason. It must be absolutely transparent, crystalline. How can we hope to explain the world, if our very first principle itself contains irrationalities?

It was Plato's greatness and glory to have recognized this, making him the founder of all true philosophy. To say that the Absolute is concepts is the same as saying it is reason. It might seem that Plato has met the second standard of criticism. He takes a self-evident reality as his first principle. However, we can’t jump to this conclusion so quickly. After all, the mere word reason isn’t a key that will open the doors of the universe for us. We need something more than just the word itself. We actually need to be told what reason is. Now, there are two ways we can ask what reason is, one of which is valid and the other is not. It's not valid to ask what reason is in the sense of wanting it explained in terms of something else that isn’t reason. This would mean abandoning our belief that reason is self-justifying. It would imply looking for the reason of reason in something that isn't reason. That would suggest that reason itself is not rational, which is absurd. But it's valid to ask what reason is, meaning, what is the content of reason. The content of reason, as we have seen, is concepts. But what concepts? How do we determine whether a particular concept is part of the system of reason or not? Obviously, we can do this by figuring out whether it is a rational concept. If a concept is entirely rational, then it is part of reason. If it isn’t, then it isn’t. What we need, then, is a detailed account of all the concepts that reason includes, and proof that each of these concepts is genuinely rational. Clearly, this is the only way we can effectively start in philosophy. Before we can demonstrate that reason explains, that is, rationalizes the world, we must first establish that reason itself is rational, or more precisely, that our understanding of reason is rational. There shouldn’t be any inexplicable facts, mysteries, or dark areas in our concept of reason. It must be completely illuminated by the light of reason. It must be entirely clear and transparent. How can we hope to explain the world if our very first principle contains irrational elements?

Each concept then must prove itself rational. And this means that it must be a necessary concept. A necessary proposition, we saw, is one, such as that two and two equal four, the opposite of which is unthinkable. So for Plato's Ideas to be really necessary it ought to be logically impossible for us to deny their {243} reality. It ought to be impossible to think the world at all without these concepts. To attempt to deny them ought to be shown to be self-contradictory. They ought to be so necessarily involved in reason that thought without them becomes impossible. Clearly this is the same as saying that the Ideas must not be mere ultimate inexplicable facts. Of such a fact we assert merely that it is so, but we cannot see any reason for it. To see a reason for it is the same as seeing its necessity, seeing not merely that it is so, but that it must be so.

Each concept must prove itself to be rational. This means it has to be a necessary concept. A necessary proposition, as we discussed, is one like the statement that two plus two equals four, the opposite of which is unthinkable. So for Plato's Ideas to truly be necessary, it should be logically impossible for us to deny their {243} reality. It should be impossible to imagine the world at all without these concepts. Trying to deny them should be shown to be self-contradictory. They should be so inherently part of reason that thinking without them becomes impossible. Clearly, this is the same as saying that the Ideas cannot just be mere ultimate inexplicable facts. With such a fact, we simply state that it is true, but we can't see any reason for it. To see a reason for it is the same as recognizing its necessity, understanding not just that it is true, but that it must be true.

Now Plato's Ideas are not of this necessary kind. There is, we are told, an Idea of whiteness. But why should there be such an Idea? It is a mere fact. It is not a necessity. We can think the world quite well without the Idea of whiteness. The world, so far as we can see, could get on perfectly well without either white objects or the Idea of whiteness. To deny its reality leads to no self-contradictions. Put it in another way. There are certainly white objects in the world. We demand that these, among other things, be explained. Plato tells us, by way of explanation, that there are white objects because there is an Idea of whiteness. But in that case why is there an Idea of whiteness? We cannot see. There is no reason. There is no necessity in this. The same thing applies to all the other Ideas. They are not rational concepts. They are not a part of the system of reason.

Now, Plato's Ideas aren't necessary in this way. There's, apparently, an Idea of whiteness. But why should there be such an Idea? It’s just a fact. It’s not essential. We can understand the world just fine without the Idea of whiteness. The world, as far as we can tell, could function perfectly well without white objects or the Idea of whiteness. Denying its reality doesn’t lead to any contradictions. In other words, there are definitely white objects in the world. We ask for explanations regarding these, among other things. Plato explains that white objects exist because there’s an Idea of whiteness. But then, why is there an Idea of whiteness? We can’t see it. There’s no reason. There’s no necessity in this. The same goes for all the other Ideas. They aren’t rational concepts. They’re not part of the system of reason.

But at this point, perhaps, a glimmer of hope dawns upon us. We ask the reason for these Ideas. Has not Plato asserted that the ultimate reason and ground of all the lower Ideas will be found in the supreme Idea of {244} the Good? Now if this is so, it means that the lower Ideas must find their necessity in the highest Idea. If we could see that the Idea of the Good necessarily involves the other Ideas, then these other Ideas would be really explained. In other words, we ought to be able to deduce all the other Ideas from this one Idea. It ought to be possible to show that, granted the Idea of the Good, all the other Ideas necessarily follow, that to assume the Good and deny the other Ideas would be self-contradictory and unthinkable. There are examples in Plato of the kind of deduction we require. For example, in the "Parmenides" he showed that the Idea of the one necessarily involves the Idea of the many, and vice versa. You cannot think the one without also thinking the many. This means that the many is deduced from the one, and the one from the many. Just in the same way, we ought to be able to deduce the Idea of whiteness from the Idea of the Good. But this is clearly not possible. You may analyse the Good as long as you like, you may turn it in every conceivable direction, but you cannot get whiteness out of it. The two Ideas do not involve each other. They are thinkable apart. It is quite possible to think the Good without thinking whiteness. And it is the same with all the other Ideas. None of them can be deduced from the Good.

But at this point, maybe a glimmer of hope starts to shine on us. We ask why these Ideas exist. Hasn't Plato claimed that the ultimate reason for all the lower Ideas can be found in the supreme Idea of {244} the Good? If that's true, it means that the lower Ideas must find their necessity in the highest Idea. If we could see that the Idea of the Good necessarily includes the other Ideas, then these other Ideas would be truly explained. In other words, we should be able to deduce all the other Ideas from this one Idea. It should be possible to demonstrate that, given the Idea of the Good, all the other Ideas necessarily follow, and that to assume the Good while denying the other Ideas would be self-contradictory and unthinkable. There are examples in Plato of the kind of deduction we need. For instance, in the "Parmenides," he showed that the Idea of the one necessarily includes the Idea of the many, and vice versa. You can't think of the one without also thinking of the many. This means that the many is derived from the one, and the one from the many. Similarly, we should be able to deduce the Idea of whiteness from the Idea of the Good. But this is clearly not possible. You can analyze the Good as much as you want, you can examine it from every angle, but you can't derive whiteness from it. The two Ideas do not depend on each other. They can be thought of independently. It's entirely possible to think of the Good without thinking of whiteness. The same goes for all the other Ideas. None of them can be deduced from the Good.

And the reason of this is very obvious. Just as the lower Ideas contain only what is common among the things of a class, and exclude their differences, so the higher Ideas include what is common to the Ideas that come under them, but exclude what is not common. For example, the Idea of colour contains what white, blue, red, and green, have in common. But all colours {245} have not whiteness in common. Green, for example, is not white. Hence the Idea of colour excludes the Idea of whiteness, and it likewise excludes all the Ideas of the other particular colours. So too the highest Idea of all contains only what all the Ideas agree in, but all the rest falls outside it. Thus the Idea of whiteness is perfect in its kind. And as all Ideas are likewise perfect, the highest Idea is that in which they all agree, namely, perfection itself. But this means that the perfection of the Idea of whiteness is contained in the supreme Idea, but its specific character in which it differs from other Ideas is excluded. Its specific character is just its whiteness. Thus the perfection of whiteness is contained in the Good, but its whiteness is not. Consequently it is impossible to deduce whiteness from the Good, because the Good does not contain whiteness. You cannot get out of it what is not in it. When Plato deduced the many from the one, he did so only by showing that the One contains the many. He cannot deduce whiteness from goodness, because goodness does not contain whiteness.

And the reason for this is pretty clear. Just like lower Ideas include only what is common among the things in a class and leave out their differences, higher Ideas encompass what is shared among the Ideas that fall under them but exclude what is not common. For example, the Idea of color includes what white, blue, red, and green have in common. But all colors do not share whiteness. Green, for instance, is not white. Therefore, the Idea of color excludes the Idea of whiteness, and it also excludes all the Ideas of the other specific colors. Similarly, the highest Idea of all includes only what all Ideas agree on, while everything else falls outside it. So, the Idea of whiteness is perfect in its own right. And since all Ideas are also perfect, the highest Idea is the one they all agree on, which is perfection itself. This means that the perfection of the Idea of whiteness is part of the supreme Idea, but its unique characteristics that set it apart from other Ideas are excluded. Its unique characteristic is simply its whiteness. Therefore, the perfection of whiteness is included in the Good, but its whiteness is not. As a result, it is impossible to derive whiteness from the Good because the Good does not encompass whiteness. You cannot extract what isn’t there. When Plato derived the many from the one, he did it by demonstrating that the One contains the many. He cannot derive whiteness from goodness, because goodness does not contain whiteness.

The lower Ideas thus have not the character of necessity. They are mere facts. And the hope that we shall find their necessity in the supreme Idea fails. But suppose we waive this. Suppose we grant that there must be an Idea of whiteness, because there is an Idea of the Good. Then why is there an Idea of the Good? What is the necessity of that? We cannot see any necessity in it. What we said of the other Ideas applies with equal force to the highest Idea. The Good may be a necessary Idea, but Plato has not shown it.

The lower Ideas don’t have to be necessary. They’re just facts. The expectation that we’ll discover their necessity in the highest Idea doesn’t hold up. But let’s put that aside for a moment. Let’s say we accept that there has to be an Idea of whiteness because there’s an Idea of the Good. Then why is there an Idea of the Good? What makes that necessary? We can’t find any necessity in it. What we said about the other Ideas is just as true for the highest Idea. The Good might be a necessary Idea, but Plato hasn’t proven it.

Thus, though Plato named reason as the Absolute, {246} and though reason is a self-explanatory principle, his account of the detailed content of reason is so unsatisfactory that none of the concepts which he includes in it are really shown to be rational. His philosophy breaks down upon the second test as it did upon the first. He has neither explained the world from the Ideas, nor has he made the Ideas explain themselves.

Thus, even though Plato referred to reason as the Absolute, {246} and even though reason is a principle that explains itself, his explanation of the detailed content of reason is so lacking that none of the concepts he includes really demonstrate rationality. His philosophy fails upon the second test just like it did on the first. He neither explained the world through the Ideas nor made the Ideas self-explanatory.

There is one other defect in Plato's system which is of capital importance. There runs throughout it a confusion between the notions of reality and existence. To distinguish between existence and reality is an essential feature of all idealism. Even if we go back to the dim idealism of the Eleatics, we shall see this. Zeno, we saw, denied motion, multiplicity, and the world of sense. But he did not deny the existence of the world. That is an impossibility. Even if the world is delusion, the delusion exists. What he denied was the reality of existence. But if reality is not existence, what is it? It is Being, replied the Eleatics. But Being does not exist. Whatever exists is this or that particular sort of being. Being itself is not anywhere to be found. Thus the Eleatics first denied that existence is reality, and then that reality exists. They did not themselves draw this conclusion, but it is involved in their whole position.

There’s another major flaw in Plato’s system that’s really important. Throughout it, there’s a mix-up between the concepts of reality and existence. Being able to tell the difference between existence and reality is a key aspect of all forms of idealism. Even if we look back at the early idealism of the Eleatics, we can see this. Zeno denied motion, diversity, and the sensory world. However, he didn’t deny that the world exists. That’s impossible. Even if the world is an illusion, the illusion itself exists. What he denied was the reality of existence. But if reality isn’t the same as existence, then what is it? It’s Being, the Eleatics would say. But Being doesn’t actually exist. Anything that exists is a specific type of being. Being itself can’t be found anywhere. So, the Eleatics first rejected the idea that existence is reality, and then suggested that reality doesn’t exist. They didn’t explicitly reach this conclusion, but it’s implied in their entire argument.

With a fully developed idealism, like Plato's, this ought to be still clearer. And, in a sense, it is. The individual horse is not real. But it certainly exists. The universal horse is real. But it does not exist. But, upon this last point, Plato wavered and fell. He cannot resist the temptation to think of the absolute reality as existing. And consequently the Ideas are {247} not merely thought as the real universal in the world, but as having a separate existence in a world of their own. Plato must have realised what is, in truth, involved in his whole position, that the absolute reality has no existence. For he tells us that it is the universal, and not any particular individual thing. But everything that exists is an individual thing. Again, he tells us that the Idea is outside time. But whatever exists must exist at some time. Here then this central idealistic thought seems well fixed in Plato's mind. But when he goes on to speak of recollection and reincarnation, when he tells us that the soul before birth dwelt apart in the world of Ideas, to which after death it may hope to return, it is clear that Plato has forgotten his own philosophy, that he is now thinking of the Ideas as individual existences in a world of their own. This is a world of Ideas having a separate existence and place of its own. It is not this world. It is a world beyond. Thus the Platonic philosophy which began on a high level of idealistic thinking, proclaiming the sole reality of the universal, ends by turning the universal itself into nothing but an existent particular. It is the old old story of trying to form mental pictures of that which no picture is adequate to comprehend. Since all pictures are formed out of sensuous materials, and since we can form no picture of anything that is not an individual thing, to form a picture of the universal necessarily means thinking of it as just what it is not, an individual. So Plato commits the greatest sin that can be ascribed to a philosopher. He treats thought as a thing.

With a fully developed idealism, like Plato's, this should be even clearer. And, in a way, it is. The individual horse is not real. But it definitely exists. The universal horse is real. But it doesn’t exist. However, on this last point, Plato wavered and stumbled. He couldn’t resist the pull to think of absolute reality as existing. As a result, the Ideas are {247} not just thought of as the real universal in the world, but as having a separate existence in their own realm. Plato must have realized what is, in fact, at stake in his entire position: that absolute reality has no existence. He tells us that it is the universal, not any specific individual thing. But everything that exists is an individual thing. Again, he tells us that the Idea is outside of time. But anything that exists must exist at some point in time. Here, then, this central idealistic thought seems well entrenched in Plato's mind. But when he continues to discuss recollection and reincarnation, when he tells us that the soul before birth lived separately in the world of Ideas, to which it may hope to return after death, it’s clear that Plato has forgotten his own philosophy; he is now thinking of the Ideas as individual existences in their own world. This is a world of Ideas having a separate existence and place of its own. It is not this world. It is a world beyond. Thus, the Platonic philosophy that began with a high level of idealistic thinking, proclaiming the sole reality of the universal, ultimately turns the universal itself into nothing more than an existing particular. It’s the old, old story of trying to create mental images of what no image can adequately capture. Since all images are made from sensory materials, and since we can create no image of anything that isn’t an individual thing, to visualize the universal necessarily means thinking of it as precisely what it isn’t: an individual. So Plato commits the greatest sin that can be attributed to a philosopher. He treats thought as if it were a tangible thing.

To sum up. Plato is the great founder of idealism, the initiator of all subsequent truths in philosophy. {248} But, as always with pioneers, his idealism is crude. It cannot explain the world; it cannot explain itself. It cannot even keep true to its own principles, because, having for the first time in history definitely enunciated the truth that reality is the universal, it straightway forgets its own creed and plunges back into a particularism which regards the Ideas as existent individuals. It was these defects which Aristotle set himself to rectify in a purer idealism, shorn of Plato's impurities.

To sum up, Plato is the great founder of idealism, the initiator of all subsequent truths in philosophy. {248} But, as with any pioneers, his idealism is basic. It can't explain the world; it can't explain itself. It can't even stay true to its own principles because, for the first time in history, he clearly stated that reality is universal, but then he quickly forgets his own beliefs and slips back into a narrow view that sees the Ideas as existing individuals. It was these flaws that Aristotle aimed to correct with a purer form of idealism, free from Plato's impurities.


ARISTOTLE

ARISTOTLE

1. Life, Writings, and general character of his Work.

1. Life, Writings, and overall character of his Work.

Aristotle was born in 384 B.C. at Stagirus, a Grecian colony and seaport on the coast of Thrace. His father Nichomachus was court physician to King Amyntas of Macedonia, and from this began Aristotle's long association with the Macedonian Court, which considerably influenced his life and destinies. While he was still a boy his father died, and he was sent by his guardian, Proxenus, to Athens, the intellectual centre of the world, to complete his education. He was then aged seventeen. He joined the Academy and studied under Plato, attending the latter's lectures for a period of twenty years. In subsequent times, Aristotle's detractors, anxious to vilify his character, accused him of "ingratitude" to his master, Plato. It was said that Plato's old age had been embittered by dissensions in the school caused by the factious spirit of Aristotle. That there is no ground for attaching any blame to Aristotle for the troubles of Plato, which either did not exist or have been grossly exaggerated, is evident both from the facts within our knowledge and from the reference to Plato in Aristotle's works. It is not likely that, had Aristotle rendered himself genuinely objectionable, he could have remained for twenty years in {250} the Academy, and only left it upon the death of Plato. Moreover, although Aristotle in his works attacks the teaching of Plato with unsparing vigour, there is nowhere to be found in these attacks any suggestion of acrimony or personal rancour. On the contrary, he refers to himself as the friend of Plato, but a greater friend of the truth. The fact, in all probability, is that a man of such independent and original mind as Aristotle did not accord to Plato the kind of blind adoration and hero-worship which he may have received from the inferior intellects in the school. As is so often the case with young men of marked ability, the brilliant student may have suffered from the impatience and self-assertion of youth. There was certainly nothing worse.

Aristotle was born in 384 B.C. in Stagirus, a Greek colony and seaport on the coast of Thrace. His father, Nichomachus, was the court physician to King Amyntas of Macedonia, which started Aristotle's long connection with the Macedonian Court, significantly impacting his life and future. When he was still a boy, his father passed away, and his guardian, Proxenus, sent him to Athens, the intellectual hub of the world, to finish his education. He was seventeen at the time. He joined the Academy and studied under Plato, attending his lectures for twenty years. Later on, some of Aristotle's critics, eager to tarnish his reputation, accused him of being "ungrateful" to Plato. They claimed that Plato’s later years were made difficult by disputes in the school due to Aristotle's contentious nature. However, there is no basis for blaming Aristotle for Plato's issues, which either didn't exist or were greatly exaggerated, as indicated by the facts we know and Aristotle’s references to Plato in his works. It’s unlikely that if Aristotle had truly been objectionable, he could have stayed at the Academy for twenty years, leaving only after Plato's death. Furthermore, although Aristotle criticizes Plato's teachings in his works without holding back, there’s no sign of bitterness or personal hatred in these criticisms. Instead, he refers to himself as a friend of Plato but a greater friend of the truth. The reality is probably that a man as independent and original as Aristotle didn't show the kind of blind devotion and hero-worship that lesser minds in the school might have had for Plato. As is often true of young people with exceptional talent, this brilliant student may have struggled with the impatience and assertiveness that come with youth. There was certainly nothing worse.

While at the Academy Aristotle exhibited an unflagging spirit and unwearied zeal in the pursuit of knowledge in all its forms, a spirit which gave rise to nick-names and anecdotes, which probably contained as much truth, or as little, as most of the anecdotes which gather round remarkable characters. One of these stories was that he used a mechanical contrivance to wake him up whenever sleep threatened to put an end to his hours of study.

While at the Academy, Aristotle showed an unwavering spirit and tireless enthusiasm for learning in every form, a passion that led to nicknames and stories that were probably as true, or as false, as many tales about notable figures. One of these stories claimed that he used a mechanical device to wake him up whenever sleep tried to interrupt his study time.

In 347 B.C. Plato died, and his nephew Speusippus was chosen as head of the Academy. Aristotle left Athens with his fellow-student Xenocrates, and together they repaired to the court of Hermeias, King of Atarneus, in Asia Minor. Hermeias, a man of low origin, but of high instincts and advanced education, had himself attended the lectures of Plato, and received the two young philosophers as welcome guests. Aristotle stayed three years at Atarneus, and, while there, married {251} Pythias, the niece of the King. In later life he was married a second time to one Herpyllis, who bore him a son, Nichomachus. At the end of three years Hermeias fell a victim to the treachery of the Persians, and Aristotle went to Mytilene. Here he remained for several years till he received an invitation from Philip of Macedonia to become the tutor of the young Alexander, afterwards conqueror of the world, then aged thirteen. Aristotle obeyed the summons, and for about five years superintended the education of Alexander. Both Philip and Alexander appear to have paid Aristotle high honour, and there were stories that he was supplied by the Macedonian court, not only with funds for the prosecution of learning, but even with thousands of slaves for the collection of specimens. These stories are probably false and certainly exaggerated. But there is no doubt that, in his scientific and philosophical enquiries, he was backed by the influence of the court, and could even perhaps have looked to that quarter for supplies, had it ever been necessary.

In 347 B.C., Plato died, and his nephew Speusippus was appointed as the head of the Academy. Aristotle left Athens with his classmate Xenocrates, and they traveled to the court of Hermeias, the King of Atarneus in Asia Minor. Hermeias came from humble beginnings but had strong instincts and an advanced education. He had himself attended Plato's lectures and welcomed the two young philosophers as guests. Aristotle stayed in Atarneus for three years, and during that time, he married Pythias, the King's niece. Later in life, he married again, to a woman named Herpyllis, with whom he had a son named Nichomachus. After three years, Hermeias was betrayed by the Persians, and Aristotle moved to Mytilene. He remained there for several years until he received an invitation from Philip of Macedonia to tutor the young Alexander, who would later conquer the world and was then just thirteen years old. Aristotle accepted the invitation and spent about five years overseeing Alexander's education. Both Philip and Alexander seemed to have held Aristotle in high regard, and there were rumors that he was supported by the Macedonian court not just with funds for his studies but even with thousands of slaves to help gather specimens. These rumors are likely exaggerated, but there’s no doubt that in his scientific and philosophical pursuits, he had the court’s backing and could have sought resources from them if necessary.

Upon the death of Philip, Alexander succeeded to the kingship. The period of his studies was now over, and he began to make preparations for his subsequent conquests. Aristotle's work being finished, he returned to Athens, which he had not visited since the death of Plato. He found the Platonic school flourishing under Xenocrates, and Platonism the dominant philosophy of Athens. He thereupon set up his own school at a place called the Lyceum. It was in connection with this that his followers became known, in after years, as the "peripatetics," a name which arose from Aristotle's habit of walking about as he discoursed. The period of {252} his residence in Athens lasted thirteen years, during which time he was occupied in the leadership of his school and in literary labours. This appears to have been the most fruitful period of his life. There is no doubt that all his most important writings were composed at this time. But at the end of this period his fortunes changed.

Upon Philip's death, Alexander became king. His time studying was over, and he started preparing for his future conquests. After finishing his work with Aristotle, he returned to Athens, which he hadn't seen since Plato died. He found the Platonic school thriving under Xenocrates, with Platonism as the leading philosophy in Athens. So, he established his own school at a place called the Lyceum. It’s from this that his followers later became known as the "peripatetics," a name that came from Aristotle's habit of walking around while he taught. Alexander lived in Athens for thirteen years, during which he led his school and worked on literary projects. This seems to have been the most productive time of his life. There's no doubt that all his most significant writings were completed during this period. However, by the end of this time, his fortunes changed.

In B.C. 323 Alexander the Great died suddenly at Babylon in the midst of his triumphs. The Athenian Government was in the hands of a pro-Macedonian party. Upon the death of Alexander this party was overthrown, and a general reaction occurred against everything Macedonian. Alexander had been regarded in Greece much as Napoleon was regarded in Europe a century ago. He had insulted the free Greek cities. He had even sacked the city of Thebes. The whole of Greece lived in perpetual terror of invasion. Now that this fear was removed by his death, there was a general outburst of feeling against Macedonia. An anti-Macedonian party came into power. Now Aristotle had always been regarded as a representative and protege of the Macedonian court, although, as a matter of fact, he had recently fallen out of favour with the autocratic Alexander. A charge of impiety was trumped up against him. To escape prosecution he fled to Chalcis in Euboea, in order that, as he said, "the Athenians might not have another opportunity of sinning against philosophy as they had already done in the person of Socrates." He perhaps intended to return to Athens as soon as the storm had blown over. But in the first year of his residence at Chalcis he was overtaken by a sudden illness, and died at the age of sixty-three, in B.C. 322.

In 323 B.C., Alexander the Great died unexpectedly in Babylon while at the height of his successes. The Athenian Government was controlled by a pro-Macedonian faction. After Alexander's death, this faction was toppled, leading to a widespread backlash against anything associated with Macedonia. In Greece, Alexander had been viewed similarly to how Napoleon was seen in Europe a century later. He had disrespected the independent Greek cities and even destroyed Thebes. Greece had lived in constant fear of invasion, but with his death, that fear dissipated, sparking a collective rise against Macedonia. An anti-Macedonian faction took control. Aristotle had always been seen as a supporter and representative of the Macedonian court, although he had recently fallen out of favor with the authoritarian Alexander. A false charge of impiety was brought against him. To avoid prosecution, he fled to Chalcis in Euboea, stating that he wanted to prevent the Athenians from having "another chance to wrong philosophy as they had done with Socrates." He likely planned to return to Athens once things calmed down. However, in the first year of his time in Chalcis, he was struck by a sudden illness and passed away at the age of sixty-three in 322 B.C.

Aristotle is said to have composed some four hundred books. Our astonishment at this productivity diminishes somewhat when we remember that what is here called a "book" is much the same as what we should call a chapter in a modern treatise. More than three-quarters of these writings have been lost. But, by good fortune, what remains to us is undoubtedly by far the most important part, and we have preserved in it a fairly complete account of the whole Aristotelian system in all its departments. Nearly all the writings, however, have come down to us in a mutilated state. This is especially the case with the "Metaphysics." This treatise is unfinished, and it was probably left unfinished by its author at his death. But apart from this, several of the books of the "Metaphysics" are undoubtedly spurious. Others apparently come in the wrong order. We end one book in the middle of a discussion, and when we begin the next we find ourselves in the middle of an entirely different subject. There are frequent repetitions, and parts of it read as if they were mere lecture notes. There are many interpolations. The same characteristics are to be observed in Aristotle's other writings, though in a less degree. It seems probable that they were not intended, in their present state, for publication. Final revision and finishing touches are lacking. In spite of these defects, the writings are voluminous and clear enough to enable us to trace out the whole of the main positions of Aristotle's thought.

Aristotle is said to have written around four hundred books. Our surprise at this output lessens a bit when we remember that what we now call a "book" is similar to what we would consider a chapter in a modern work. More than three-quarters of these writings have been lost. However, luckily, what we do have is undoubtedly the most significant portion, and it provides us with a fairly complete overview of the entire Aristotelian system across its various fields. Almost all of the writings, though, have come down to us in a damaged state. This is especially true for the "Metaphysics." This work is unfinished and was likely left incomplete by Aristotle at his death. Additionally, several of the books in the "Metaphysics" are definitely not authentic. Others seem to be out of order. We often end one book in the middle of a discussion, and when we start the next, we find ourselves in the middle of a completely different topic. There are frequent repetitions, and some sections read like mere lecture notes. There are many additions that weren't originally part of the text. The same issues can be seen in Aristotle's other writings, although to a lesser extent. It seems likely that they were not meant, in their current form, for publication. They lack final revisions and finishing touches. Despite these flaws, the writings are extensive and clear enough for us to understand the main ideas of Aristotle's thought.

We saw, in the case of Plato, that, as his literary activity lasted over a period of half a century, during which his philosophy was in constant development, it became important to trace this development in the {254} order of his Dialogues. The same thing is not true in the case of Aristotle. The whole of his writings, or rather those that have come down to us, seem to have been written during his last thirteen years, while he was at Athens, that is to say, after he had passed his fiftieth year. His system was then complete, mature, and fully developed. The question of the order in which they were written has no great importance. The result of critical investigations, however, is to show that he probably began with the various works upon logic, composed next the treatises upon physical science, next the ethical and political books, and lastly the "Metaphysics," which he left unfinished.

We observed, in Plato's case, that since his literary work spanned over fifty years, during which his philosophy evolved continuously, it became crucial to track this evolution in the {254} order of his Dialogues. This isn't the case with Aristotle. Most of his writings, or at least the ones we have, seem to have been produced during his last thirteen years in Athens, meaning after he turned fifty. By then, his system was complete, mature, and fully developed. The order in which they were written isn’t particularly important. Critical investigations suggest that he likely started with various works on logic, followed by treatises on physical science, then the ethical and political books, and finally the "Metaphysics," which he left unfinished.

It must not be forgotten that Aristotle was not only a philosopher in the modern restricted sense of that term. He was a man of universal learning. There is no branch of knowledge which did not receive his attention, and upon which he was not the greatest expert of his time, except perhaps mathematics. So far was he from being only an abstract philosopher, that his natural tastes seem to have lain rather in the field of physical science than of abstract thought. But his design seems to have been to work over the entire field of knowledge, thoroughly to overhaul the sciences already in existence, rejecting what seemed false in the work of his predecessors, and invariably adding to the residue valuable developments and suggestions of his own. Where there was no science already in existence, his plan involved the foundation of new sciences wherever necessary, and he thus became the founder of at least two sciences, Logic and Zoology. He thus attained to a pre-eminence in all branches {255} of knowledge which would be impossible for a single man in modern times. His works include treatises upon Logic and Metaphysics, upon Ethics, Politics, and Art. He wrote a treatise upon the principles of Rhetoric, another upon Astronomy, under the title "On the Heavens," another upon Meteorology. Several of his treatises deal with the biology of animal life, in which he was intensely interested. They include books entitled "On the Parts of Animals," "On the Movements of Animals," "On the Origin of Animals," as well as his great treatise, "Researches on Animals," which contains an enormous mass of facts collected from every possible source. It is true that a large proportion of these facts have turned out to be fictions, but this was inevitable in the infancy of science. It has been calculated that Aristotle shows himself acquainted with about five hundred different species of living beings, though they are not, of course, classified by him in the modern way. With these books upon animals he founded the science of Zoology, for no one before his day had made any special study of the subject.

We shouldn't forget that Aristotle was more than just a philosopher in the modern sense of the word. He was a person with a broad range of knowledge. There wasn't a field of study that he didn't explore, and he was considered one of the top experts of his time, except maybe in mathematics. Far from being just an abstract thinker, his natural interests seemed to lean more toward the physical sciences than abstract theories. His goal appeared to be to cover the entire spectrum of knowledge, thoroughly reviewing the existing sciences, discarding what he deemed false in earlier works, and consistently contributing valuable insights and developments of his own. When there was no existing science in a particular area, he aimed to create new sciences as needed, making him the founder of at least two disciplines: Logic and Zoology. He achieved a level of expertise across various fields of knowledge that would be impossible for a single individual today. His writings include treatises on Logic and Metaphysics, Ethics, Politics, and Art. He also wrote a treatise on the principles of Rhetoric, another on Astronomy titled "On the Heavens," and one on Meteorology. Several of his treatises focus on the biology of animals, which he was deeply interested in. These include books titled "On the Parts of Animals," "On the Movements of Animals," "On the Origin of Animals," and his significant work "Researches on Animals," which contains a vast collection of facts gathered from numerous sources. It's true that many of these facts turned out to be incorrect, but that was expected in the early stages of science. It's estimated that Aristotle was familiar with about five hundred different species of living beings, although he didn't classify them in the way we do today. Through his works on animals, he established the science of Zoology, as no one had seriously studied this subject before him.

It has been said that everyone has either an Aristotelian or a Platonic type of mind. As this implies that Aristotle and Plato are opposites, it is considerably less than a half truth. No genuine understanding of Aristotle can endorse the opinion that his philosophical system was the opposite of Plato's. It would be truer to say that Aristotle was the greatest of all Platonists, since his system is still founded upon the Idea, and is an attempt to found an idealism free from the defects of Plato's system. It is in fact a development of Platonism. What is the cause then of the popular notion that {256} Aristotle was the opposite of Plato? Now the fact is that they were opposites in many important respects. But there was a fundamental agreement between them which lies deeper than the differences. The differences are largely superficial, the agreement is deep-seated. Hence it is the differences that are most obvious, and it was the differences, too, which were most obvious to Aristotle himself. The popular opinion arises largely from the fact that Aristotle never loses an opportunity of attacking the Platonic theory of Ideas. He is continually at pains to emphasize the difference between himself and Plato, but says nothing of the agreement. But no man is a judge of his own deeper relations to his predecessors and contemporaries. It is only in after years, when the hubbub of controversy has settled down into the silence of the past, that the historian can see the true perspective, and can penetrate the relations of each great man to the time in which he lived. Plato was the founder of idealism, and his idealism was in many respects crude and untenable. It was the special mission of Aristotle to clear away these crudities, and so develop Platonism into a tenable philosophy. And it was natural that he should emphasize the crudities, which he had to fight so hard to overcome, rather than that substratum of truth which Plato had already developed, and which therefore required no special treatment at his hands. It was the differences between himself and his predecessor which were most obvious to him, and it was inevitable that he should adopt a thoroughly polemical attitude towards his master.

It has been said that everyone has either an Aristotelian or a Platonic way of thinking. While this suggests that Aristotle and Plato are opposites, it's not entirely true. No real understanding of Aristotle supports the idea that his philosophy was the opposite of Plato's. It's more accurate to say that Aristotle was the greatest Platonist because his system is still based on the Idea and attempts to create an idealism that avoids the flaws of Plato's system. In fact, it is a development of Platonism. So what leads to the common belief that {256} Aristotle was the opposite of Plato? The truth is they were opposites in many significant ways. However, there was a fundamental agreement between them that runs deeper than their differences. The differences are mostly superficial, while the agreement is profound. That's why the differences are the most noticeable, and they stood out to Aristotle himself. The popular opinion largely arises from the fact that Aristotle frequently criticized the Platonic theory of Ideas. He consistently emphasizes the differences between himself and Plato but doesn't mention their agreements. However, no one can fully judge their own deeper connections with their predecessors and contemporaries. It's only later, once the noise of controversy has settled into the silence of history, that historians can see the true context and understand each great individual's relationship to the era they lived in. Plato was the founder of idealism, and his version of it was crude and unsustainable in many ways. It was Aristotle's specific mission to address these crude aspects and develop Platonism into a viable philosophy. Naturally, he focused on those issues, which he fought so hard to overcome, rather than on the foundational truths that Plato had already established, which didn't require his particular attention. The differences between him and his predecessor were most apparent to him, and it was inevitable for him to take a strongly critical stance toward his mentor.

But if the agreement was more deep-seated than the differences, and lay in the recognition of the Idea as the {257} absolute foundation of the world, the differences were none the less very striking. In the first place, Aristotle loved facts. What he wanted was always definite scientific knowledge. Plato, on the other hand, had no love of facts and no gift for physical enquiries. And what disgusted Aristotle about the system of Plato was the contempt which it poured upon the world of sense. To depreciate objects of sense, and to proclaim the knowledge of them valueless, was a fundamental characteristic of all Plato's thinking. But the world of sense is the world of facts, and Aristotle was deeply interested in facts. No matter in what branch of knowledge, any fact was received by Aristotle with enthusiasm. To Plato it appeared of no interest what the habits of some obscure animal might be. That alone which should be pursued is the knowledge of the Idea. And he went so far as to deny that knowledge of the sense-world could properly be described as knowledge at all. But the habits of animals appeared to Aristotle a matter worthy of investigation for its own sake. Francis Bacon in his "Novum Organum" has many contemptuous references to Aristotle. And the gist of them all is that Aristotle had no regard for facts, but theorized a priori out of his head, and that instead of patiently investigating the facts of nature, he decided, upon so-called "rational" grounds, what nature ought to do, and squared the facts with his theories.

But if the agreement was deeper than the differences, and was based on the recognition of the Idea as the {257} absolute foundation of the world, the differences were still very noticeable. First, Aristotle loved facts. He always sought definite scientific knowledge. Plato, on the other hand, had no interest in facts and was not skilled in physical inquiries. What disgusted Aristotle about Plato's system was the disdain it showed for the sensory world. To belittle the objects of sense and claim that knowledge of them is worthless was a key aspect of all Plato's thinking. But the sensory world is the world of facts, and Aristotle was very interested in facts. No matter the field of knowledge, Aristotle welcomed any fact with enthusiasm. To Plato, the habits of some obscure animal were of no interest. What should be pursued is the knowledge of the Idea. He even went so far as to deny that knowledge of the sensory world could really be called knowledge at all. But the habits of animals seemed to Aristotle a subject worthy of investigation for its own sake. Francis Bacon in his "Novum Organum" makes many dismissive references to Aristotle. The essence of them all is that Aristotle paid little attention to facts, instead theorizing a priori from his own mind, and rather than patiently investigating the facts of nature, he decided—based on so-called "rational" grounds—what nature should do, and fit the facts to his theories.

It was natural for Bacon to be unjust to him. He, with the other thinkers of his time, was engaged upon an uphill fight against scholasticism, then dominant, which claimed to represent the true teaching of Aristotle. And it was true that the schoolmen theorized a priori, {258} and ignored facts, or, what was worse, appealed to the writings of Aristotle to decide questions of fact which should have been decided by an appeal to nature. And Bacon not unnaturally confounded Aristotle with these modern Aristotelians, and attributed to him the faults that were really theirs. But no man was ever keener on facts than Aristotle as is proved by his treatises upon animals, which contain evidences of astonishing patience and laborious work in the collection of facts. It is true, however, that even in the domain of facts, Aristotle, like all the ancients, was guilty of introducing a priori reasonings when they were quite out of place. Thus he does not scruple to argue that the stars must move in circles because the circle is the perfect figure. And numerous similar instances could be quoted. But it was inevitable that, with science in its swaddling clothes, without the aid of any instruments, or of any body of previously ascertained truths, Aristotle should fall into these snares. He well understood the fundamental necessity of all natural sciences for a laborious investigation of facts, but, when this was impossible, he used the only means in his power, his reason.

It was only natural for Bacon to be unfair to him. Along with other thinkers of his time, he was fighting a tough battle against scholasticism, which was dominant then and claimed to represent the true teachings of Aristotle. It was true that the schoolmen theorized without considering the facts, and even worse, they referred to Aristotle's writings to settle factual questions that should have been answered through observation of nature. Bacon understandably confused Aristotle with these modern Aristotelians and blamed him for their faults. However, no one was more focused on facts than Aristotle, as evidenced by his writings on animals, which show remarkable patience and thoroughness in fact collection. It is true, though, that even in the realm of facts, Aristotle, like all the ancients, sometimes introduced a priori reasoning when it was inappropriate. For example, he argued that the stars must move in circles because the circle is the perfect shape. Many similar examples could be cited. But it was unavoidable that, with science in its infancy, without any instruments or a body of established truths, Aristotle would fall into these traps. He understood well that all natural sciences required a diligent investigation of facts, but when that wasn't possible, he relied on the only tool he had at his disposal: his reasoning.

Secondly, in spite of Plato's rationalism, he had allowed to myths and poetry a large share in the development of his thoughts, and had even exhibited a distinct tendency towards mysticism. Here again what Aristotle wanted was definite knowledge. It pained him to see poetic metaphors substituted for rational explanation. And this accounts for the third main difference between Plato and Aristotle, the marked contrast in their prose styles. Plato was a master-artist in words. Aristotle cared nothing for the ornaments and beauties of style. {259} He harshly excludes them from his work. What alone he is intent upon is the meaning, the truth that the words express. He is too much in earnest with philosophy to lose himself in a haze of beautiful words, or to be put off with metaphors instead of reasons. His style is even harsh, abrupt, and ugly. But what it loses in beauty it gains in clearness of conception. For every thought or shade of thought which it is desired to express there is an accurate term. If no term in common use will express the thought, Aristotle coins one. Hence he is one of the greatest terminologists that ever lived. He adapted or invented an enormous number of terms. He may be not unjustly regarded as the founder of philosophical language, as the inventor of a vocabulary of technical terms. Many of the terms used to this day to express man's most abstract thoughts, were invented or introduced by Aristotle. It must not be supposed that Aristotle wrote in a rigidly scientific style because he had no aesthetic sense. The very contrary is the case. His treatise on art shows him by far the best critic of the ancient world, and in his appreciation and estimation of the beautiful he far excels Plato. But he saw that art and science have each their own sphere, and that it is fatal to confuse the two. Nothing is so damaging to art as to be made the mere vehicle of reasoning. Nothing is so damaging to philosophy as to allow itself to be governed by poetry. If we want beauty, we must follow the path of art. But if we desire truth, we must stick close to reason.

Secondly, despite Plato's focus on rational thinking, he allowed myths and poetry to play a significant role in shaping his ideas, even leaning toward mysticism. Aristotle, on the other hand, sought clear knowledge. It frustrated him to see poetic metaphors replace logical explanations. This leads to the third major difference between Plato and Aristotle: their distinct prose styles. Plato was a master wordsmith. Aristotle had little interest in the embellishments and elegance of style. {259} He outright rejected them in his work. His main focus is on meaning, the truth that the words convey. He is too serious about philosophy to get lost in a swirl of beautiful language or to settle for metaphors instead of solid reasoning. His style is often harsh, abrupt, and unattractive. But what it lacks in beauty, it makes up for in clarity of thought. For every idea or nuance he wants to express, there’s a precise term. If there isn't a commonly used term that fits, Aristotle creates one. That’s why he’s considered one of the greatest terminologists ever. He adapted or invented a vast array of terms. He can rightly be seen as the founder of philosophical language, the creator of a vocabulary of technical terms. Many of the terms we still use today to express abstract thoughts were either invented or popularized by Aristotle. It's important to note that Aristotle didn't write in a strictly scientific style because he lacked an appreciation for beauty. On the contrary, his treatise on art demonstrates that he was the best critic of the ancient world, and in recognizing and valuing beauty, he surpasses Plato. However, he understood that art and science each have their own domains, and confusing the two is detrimental. Nothing harms art more than turning it into just a means of reasoning. Nothing hurts philosophy more than being influenced by poetry. If we seek beauty, we should pursue art. But if we desire truth, we must adhere closely to reason.

Aristotle's system falls most easily into the fivefold division of logic, metaphysics, physics, ethics, and aesthetics.

Aristotle's system can be easily divided into five categories: logic, metaphysics, physics, ethics, and aesthetics.

2. Logic.

Logic.

Not much need be said under this head, because whoever knows the common logic of the text-books knows the logic of Aristotle. Of the two branches of reasoning, deductive and inductive, Aristotle clearly recognizes the latter. And many of his observations upon induction are acute and penetrating. But he has not reduced induction to a science. He has not laid bare the fundamental canons of inductive thought. This was a work not performed until comparatively modern times. His name therefore is more especially associated with deductive logic, of which he was the founder. He not only founded the science, but practically completed it. What we now know as "formal logic," what is to this day contained in all text-books, taught in all schools and universities, is, in all its essentials, nothing more than the logic of Aristotle. His writings upon the subject include the treatment of the well-known laws of thought, the doctrine of the ten categories, the five predicables, the doctrines of terms, of propositions, of syllogisms, and of the reduction of the other figures to the first figure of the syllogism. And these heads might well form the list of contents of a modern work on formal logic. In only two respects has any advance been made upon Aristotle by subsequent logicians. The fourth figure of the syllogism is not recognized by Aristotle; and he dealt only with categorical syllogisms, and does not treat conditional syllogisms. But whether or not the fourth figure of the syllogism has any value is still a matter open to dispute. And though the doctrine of conditional syllogisms is important, it is not essential, because all conditional syllogisms can be reduced to categorical {261} syllogisms. The categorical syllogism is the fundamental type of reasoning, to which every other form of deduction can be reduced. As for the rest of the huge treatises on formal logic which some moderns have produced, the supposed additions are nothing but wearisome, endless, useless, nauseating, academic distinctions and refinements, which are much better forgotten than remembered. Aristotle's logic contains therefore all that is essential to the subject. The only ground on which it can be attacked is its wholly empirical procedure. But that is another story. As a collection, arrangement, and analysis of the facts of reason, it is to all intents and purposes finality achieved at one stroke.

Not much needs to be said here, because anyone familiar with basic logic from textbooks understands Aristotle's logic. He clearly acknowledges both deductive and inductive reasoning, although he has not established induction as a formal science. He hasn’t clarified the fundamental principles of inductive thought, a task that wasn’t accomplished until much later. His name is primarily associated with deductive logic, of which he was the originator. He not only created the field but also nearly concluded it. What we recognize today as "formal logic," which is included in all textbooks and taught in schools and universities, is essentially Aristotle's logic. His writings cover well-known laws of thought, the doctrine of the ten categories, the five predicables, and the concepts of terms, propositions, syllogisms, and the reduction of other figures to the first figure of the syllogism. These topics could easily serve as a table of contents for a modern book on formal logic. There have only been two significant advancements made by later logicians beyond Aristotle. He does not acknowledge the fourth figure of the syllogism, and he only explored categorical syllogisms, omitting conditional ones. However, whether the fourth figure holds any value is still debated. While the concept of conditional syllogisms is important, it’s not crucial since all conditional syllogisms can be simplified to categorical syllogisms. The categorical syllogism is the fundamental form of reasoning from which all other forms of deduction can be derived. As for the extensive treatises on formal logic produced by some modern thinkers, their so-called additions are merely tedious, endless, unnecessary, and irritating academic distinctions and nuances that are better forgotten than remembered. Aristotle's logic encompasses all the essential elements of the subject. The only criticism it faces is its entirely empirical approach. But that's another topic. As a comprehensive collection, organization, and analysis of reasoning facts, it can be considered a conclusive achievement.


3. Metaphysics.

3. Philosophy of existence.

The treatise now known as the "Metaphysics" of Aristotle did not originally bear that name. Aristotle's name for this subject is "first philosophy," by which he means the knowledge of the first, highest, or most general principles of the universe. All other branches of knowledge are subordinate to this science, not because they are inferior in value, but because they are lower in logical sequence as dealing with principles less universal in their scope. Thus all the special sciences deal with one or another particular sphere of being, but the "first philosophy" has for its subject being as such, "being so far forth as it is being." It studies, not the characteristics of this or that kind of being, but the principles which are equally true of all being. The laws of Zoology apply only to animals, but the principles of the "first philosophy" apply to everything. The name "metaphysics" came into use only half a century B.C., when {262} Andronicus published a complete edition of Aristotle's known works. In this edition the treatise on "first philosophy" was placed after the "physics," and "metaphysics" signifies simply "after physics." The derivation of the word thus appears to be merely accidental and adventitious. Whether it was also in any way intended to signify that the subject is "beyond physics," that is, deals with what transcends physical existence, seems doubtful.

The work now called "Metaphysics" by Aristotle didn’t originally have that title. Aristotle referred to this topic as "first philosophy," meaning the understanding of the first, highest, or most general principles of the universe. All other fields of knowledge are secondary to this science, not because they are less valuable, but because they are lower in logical order as they address principles that are less universal in nature. Thus, all the specialized sciences focus on specific areas of existence, while "first philosophy" studies existence itself, "being as such." It examines not the traits of individual types of being, but the principles that apply to all beings. The laws of Zoology only concern animals, but the principles of "first philosophy" apply universally. The term "metaphysics" came into use only about fifty years B.C. when {262} Andronicus published a complete edition of Aristotle's known works. In this edition, the treatise on "first philosophy" was placed after "physics," so "metaphysics" literally means "after physics." This derivation seems to be simply coincidental. Whether it was also meant to suggest that the subject is "beyond physics," meaning it deals with what surpasses physical existence, remains uncertain.

Aristotle's metaphysical theory grows naturally out of his polemic against Plato's theory of Ideas, because his own system was in effect simply an attempt to overcome the defects which he found in Plato. The main heads of this polemic are the following:--

Aristotle's metaphysical theory develops directly from his criticism of Plato's theory of Ideas, as his own system was essentially an effort to address the flaws he perceived in Plato's work. The main points of this critique are the following:--

(1) Plato's Ideas do not explain the existence of things. To explain why the world is here is after all the main problem of philosophy, and Plato's theory fails to do this. Even admitting that, say, the Idea of whiteness exists, we cannot see how it produces white objects.

(1) Plato's Ideas don't explain why things exist. Figuring out why the world is here is really the main issue in philosophy, and Plato's theory doesn't address this. Even if we accept that, for example, the Idea of whiteness exists, we still can't understand how it creates white objects.

(2) Plato has not explained the relation of Ideas to things. Things, we are told, are "copies" of Ideas, and "participate" in them. But how are we to understand this "participation"? In using such phrases, says Aristotle, Plato is giving no real account of the relationship, but is merely "uttering poetic metaphors."

(2) Plato hasn’t clarified how Ideas relate to things. We’re told that things are "copies" of Ideas and "participate" in them. But how are we supposed to understand this "participation"? Aristotle argues that by using these phrases, Plato isn’t providing a genuine explanation of the relationship; he’s just "speaking in poetic metaphors."

(3) Even if the existence of things is explained by the Ideas, their motion is not. Suppose that the Idea of whiteness produces white things, the Idea of beauty beautiful things, and so on, yet, since the Ideas themselves are immutable and motionless, so will be the world which is their copy. Thus the universe would be {263} absolutely static, like Coleridge's "painted ship upon a painted ocean." But the world, on the contrary, is a world of change, motion, life, becoming. Plato makes no attempt to explain the unceasing becoming of things. Even if the Idea of whiteness explains white objects, yet why do these objects arise, develop, decay, and cease to exist? To explain this there must be some principle of motion in the Ideas themselves. But there is not. They are immovable and lifeless.

(3) Even if the existence of things is explained by the Ideas, their motion isn’t. Let’s say the Idea of whiteness creates white things, the Idea of beauty produces beautiful things, and so on. However, since the Ideas themselves are unchanging and motionless, the world, which is their copy, would also be completely static, like Coleridge's "painted ship upon a painted ocean." But the world, on the other hand, is one of change, motion, life, and becoming. Plato doesn’t try to explain the constant change of things. Even if the Idea of whiteness accounts for white objects, why do these objects emerge, grow, decay, and eventually cease to exist? To explain this, there must be some principle of motion within the Ideas themselves. But there isn’t. They are unmoving and lifeless.

(4) The world consists of a multitude of things, and it is the business of philosophy to explain why they exist. By way of explanation Plato merely assumes the existence of another multitude of things, the Ideas. But the only effect of this is to double the number of things to be explained. How does it help thus to duplicate everything? And Aristotle likens Plato to a man who, being unable to count with a small number, fancies that, if he doubles the number, he will find it easier to count.

(4) The world is made up of many things, and it's philosophy's job to explain why they exist. Plato tries to explain this by assuming there’s another set of things, the Ideas. But all this does is double the number of things that need explaining. How does just repeating everything help? Aristotle compares Plato to someone who can't count with a small number and thinks that if he doubles it, it will be easier to count.

(5) The Ideas are supposed to be non-sensuous, but they are, in fact, sensuous. Plato thought that a non-sensuous principle must be sought in order to explain the world of sense. But not being able to find any such principle, he merely took the objects of sense over again and called them non-sensuous. But there is, in fact, no difference between the horse and the Idea of the horse, between the man and the Idea of the man, except a useless and meaningless "in-itself" or "in-general" attached to each object of sense to make it appear something different. The Ideas are nothing but hypostatized things of sense, and Aristotle likens them to the anthropomorphic gods of the popular religion. "As {264} these," he says, "are nothing but deified men, so the Ideas are nothing but eternalized things of nature." Things are said to be copies of Ideas, but in fact the Ideas are only copies of things.

(5) The Ideas are supposed to be non-sensory, but they actually are sensory. Plato believed that a non-sensory principle needed to be found to explain the sensory world. However, since he couldn’t discover such a principle, he just took sensory objects again and labeled them non-sensory. In reality, there’s no difference between a horse and the Idea of a horse, or between a man and the Idea of a man, other than a pointless and meaningless "in-itself" or "in-general" attached to each sensory object to make it seem different. The Ideas are simply abstracted sensory things, and Aristotle compares them to the human-like gods of popular religion. "Just as these," he says, "are nothing but glorified humans, the Ideas are just eternalized natural things." Things are said to be copies of Ideas, but in reality, the Ideas are just copies of things.

(6) Next comes the argument of the "third man," so called by Aristotle from the illustration by which he explained it. Ideas are assumed in order to explain what is common to many objects. Wherever there is a common element there must be an Idea. Thus there is a common element in all men, and therefore there is an Idea of man. But there is also an element common to the individual man and to the Idea of man. There must, therefore, be a further Idea, the "third man," to explain this. And between this further Idea and the individual man there must be yet another Idea to explain what they have in common, and so on ad infinitum.

(6) Next comes the argument of the "third man," a term coined by Aristotle based on the illustration he used to explain it. Ideas are assumed to explain what is shared among many objects. Whenever there is a shared element, there must be an Idea. For instance, there is a common trait in all humans, so there is an Idea of man. However, there's also a trait that is common to the individual man and the Idea of man. Therefore, there must be another Idea, the "third man," to explain this. And between this additional Idea and the individual man, there must be yet another Idea to clarify what they have in common, and this continues ad infinitum.

(7) But by far the most important of all Aristotle's objections to the ideal theory, and that which, to all intents and purposes, sums up all the others, is that it assumes that Ideas are the essences of things, and yet places those essences outside the things themselves. The essence of a thing must be in it, and not outside it. But Plato separated Ideas from things, and placed the Ideas away somewhere in a mysterious world of their own. The Idea, as the universal, can only exist in the particular. Possibly the reality in all horses is the universal horse, but the universal horse is not something that exists by itself and independently of individual horses. Hence Plato was led into the absurdity of talking as if, besides the individual horses we know, there is somewhere another individual called the horse-in-general, or as if besides white objects there is a thing called {265} whiteness. And this is in fact the supreme self-contradiction of the theory of Ideas, that it begins by saying that the universal is real, and the particular unreal, but ends by degrading the universal again into a particular. This is the same thing as saying that Plato's mistake lay in first (rightly) seeing that existence is not reality, but then (wrongly) going on to imagine that the reality is an existence.

(7) But the biggest issue with Aristotle's objections to the ideal theory, which basically sums up all the others, is that it assumes that Ideas are the essences of things, yet places those essences outside of the things themselves. The essence of a thing must be within it, not outside it. However, Plato separated Ideas from things and put the Ideas in some mysterious realm of their own. The Idea, as the universal, can only exist in the particular. It might be that the essence of all horses is the universal horse, but the universal horse isn’t something that exists on its own, independent of individual horses. This led Plato to the absurdity of suggesting that, in addition to the individual horses we see, there’s another individual called the horse-in-general, or that alongside white objects, there’s a thing called _{265}_ whiteness. And this is really the main contradiction of the theory of Ideas: it starts by claiming that the universal is real and the particular unreal, but then reduces the universal back to being a particular. This is the same as saying that Plato's mistake was in first (correctly) recognizing that existence isn’t reality, but then (incorrectly) assuming that reality is a type of existence.

Out of this last objection grows Aristotle's own philosophy, the fundamental principle of which is that the universal is indeed the absolute reality, but that it is a universal which exists only in the particular. What is reality? What is substance? This is the first question for the metaphysician. Now substance is what has an independent existence of its own; it is that whose being does not flow into it from any source outside itself. Consequently, substance is what is never a predicate; it is that to which all predicates are applied. Thus in the proposition, "Gold is heavy," gold is the subject, or substance, and "heavy" is its predicate. The heaviness is dependent for its existence on the gold, and it is therefore the latter, and not the former, that is the substance.

Out of this final objection comes Aristotle's own philosophy, which fundamentally holds that the universal is indeed the absolute reality, but it is a universal that only exists in the particular. What is reality? What is substance? This is the first question for the metaphysician. Substance is what has independent existence; it is something whose being does not come from any source outside itself. Therefore, substance is never a predicate; it is what all predicates apply to. In the statement "Gold is heavy," gold is the subject or substance, and "heavy" is its predicate. The heaviness depends on the existence of gold, which means it's gold, not heavy, that is the substance.

Now, keeping this in mind, are universals, as Plato asserts, substances? No; because the universal is merely a common predicate which attaches to many objects of a class. Thus the concept of man is merely what is common to all men. It is the same thing as the predicate "humanness." But humanness cannot exist apart from human beings, any more than heaviness apart from the heavy object. Universals, then, are not substances. But neither are particulars substances. For there is no such thing as that which is absolutely {266} particular and isolated. If humanness does not exist apart from men, neither do men exist apart from humanness. Take away from a man what he has in common with other men, and what he has in common with other objects, and you will find that, having stripped him of all his qualities, there is absolutely nothing left. We say gold is heavy, yellow, malleable, etc. Now the heaviness, the yellowness, and the other qualities, cannot exist apart from the gold. But it is equally true that the gold cannot exist apart from its qualities. Strip off all its qualities in thought, and then ask yourself what the gold itself is apart from its qualities. You will find that your mind is a total blank. In taking away the qualities you have taken away the gold itself. The gold can only be thought through its qualities. It only exists through its qualities. The gold, therefore, just as much depends on the qualities for its existence as the qualities depend upon the gold. Hence neither of them, considered apart from the other, is substance. But the qualities are the universal element in the gold, the gold without the qualities is the absolutely particular and isolated. For, first, the yellowness is a quality which this gold has in common with that gold, and is therefore a universal, and so with all the qualities. Even if a particular piece of gold has a quality possessed by no other gold, it is yet possessed by some other object in the universe, or it would be unknowable. Every quality is consequently a universal. Secondly, the gold without its qualities is the absolutely particular. For, being stripped of all qualities, it is stripped of whatever it has in common with other things; it is stripped of whatever universality it has, and it remains an absolute particular. Hence the {267} universal is not substance, nor is the particular. For neither of them can exist without the other. Substance must be a compound of the two; it must be the universal in the particular. And this means that that alone which is substance is the individual object, for example, the gold with all its qualities attached to it.

Now, with this in mind, are universals, as Plato claims, substances? No; because a universal is just a common characteristic that applies to many objects within a category. So, the idea of "man" is simply what all men share. It's the same as the term "humanness." But humanness can't exist without human beings, just like heaviness can't exist without a heavy object. Therefore, universals are not substances. But particulars aren't substances either. There's no such thing as something that is completely {266} particular and isolated. If humanness doesn't exist apart from humans, then humans also don't exist apart from humanness. Take away what a man shares with other men, and what he shares with other objects, and you'll find that, after removing all his traits, there's absolutely nothing left. We say gold is heavy, yellow, malleable, etc. Now, heaviness, yellowness, and other qualities cannot exist without the gold. But it's also true that the gold can't exist without its qualities. If you mentally strip away all its qualities, and then ask yourself what the gold itself is without its qualities, you'll find that your mind is completely blank. By removing the qualities, you've taken away the gold itself. Gold can only be understood through its qualities. It only exists through its qualities. Therefore, gold depends on its qualities for existence just as much as the qualities depend on the gold. So neither can be considered substance when looked at separately. However, the qualities are the universal aspect of the gold; without the qualities, gold is completely particular and isolated. First, yellowness is a characteristic that this gold shares with that gold, and is therefore a universal, as are all the qualities. Even if a specific piece of gold has a quality that no other gold has, it still must have some other object's quality, or else it wouldn't be knowable. Consequently, every quality is a universal. Secondly, gold without its qualities is the absolutely particular. Because, when stripped of all qualities, it loses everything it shares with other things; it loses all universality and remains an absolute particular. Thus, {267} the universal is not substance, nor is the particular. Neither can exist without the other. Substance must be a combination of the two; it must be the universal within the particular. This means that the only thing that is truly substance is the individual object, for example, gold with all its qualities attached.

It is usually believed that Aristotle contradicted himself in as much as he first states, as above, that the individual object, the compound of universal and particular, is substance, but later on allows a superior reality to the universal, or "form" as he calls it, and in effect teaches, like Plato, that the universal is what alone is absolutely real, that is, that the universal is substance. I do not agree that there is any real inconsistency in Aristotle. Or rather, the inconsistency is one of words and not of thought. It must be remembered that, whenever Aristotle says that the individual, and not the universal, is substance, he is thinking of Plato. What he means to deny is that the universal can exist on its own account, as Plato thought. Nevertheless he agrees with Plato that the universal is the real. When he says that the universal is not substance he means, as against Plato, that it is not existent. What alone exists is the individual thing, the compound of universal and particular. When he says, or implies, that the universal is substance, he means that, though it is not existent, it is real. His words are contradictory, but his meaning is not. He has not expressed himself as clearly as he should; that is all.

Many people think that Aristotle contradicted himself because he first claims, as mentioned earlier, that the individual object, which is a mix of universal and particular, is substance. However, later on, he allows for a higher reality to the universal, or "form," as he refers to it, effectively teaching, like Plato, that the universal is the only thing that is absolutely real, meaning that the universal is substance. I don't believe there is any real inconsistency in Aristotle. Rather, the inconsistency is in the wording, not in the ideas. It's important to remember that whenever Aristotle argues that the individual, not the universal, is substance, he is considering Plato's viewpoint. What he aims to deny is the idea that the universal can exist independently, as Plato believed. Nevertheless, he agrees with Plato that the universal is real. When he claims that the universal is not substance, he means, in contrast to Plato, that it doesn't exist. What truly exists is the individual thing, the blend of universal and particular. When he states, or implies, that the universal is substance, he means that, even though it doesn't exist, it is real. His statements may seem contradictory, but his meaning is not. He simply hasn't expressed himself as clearly as he should have; that's all.

The further development of Aristotle's metaphysics depends upon his doctrine of causation. By causation here, however, is meant a very much wider conception {268} than what is understood by that term in modern times. I have in previous lectures attempted to make clear the distinction between causes and reasons. The cause of a thing does not give any reason for it, and therefore does not explain it. The cause is merely the mechanism by which a reason produces its consequence. Death is caused by accident or disease, but these causes explain nothing as to why death should be in the world at all. Now if we accept this distinction, we may say that Aristotle's conception of causation includes both what we have called causes and reasons. Whatever is necessary, whether facts or principles, whether causes or reasons, fully to understand the existence of a thing, or the happening of an event, is included in the Aristotelian notion of causation.

The further development of Aristotle's metaphysics relies on his theory of causation. However, when we talk about causation here, we're referring to a much broader concept {268} than what the term means today. In previous lectures, I’ve tried to clarify the difference between causes and reasons. The cause of something doesn’t provide a reason for it, and thus doesn’t explain it. The cause is simply the mechanism through which a reason leads to its outcome. Death might be caused by an accident or a disease, but these causes don’t explain why death exists in the world at all. If we accept this distinction, we can say that Aristotle's idea of causation includes both what we call causes and reasons. Anything necessary—whether facts or principles, whether causes or reasons—to fully understand the existence of something or the occurrence of an event is included in Aristotle's notion of causation.

Taking causation in this wide sense, Aristotle finds that there are four kinds of causes, the material, the efficient, the formal, and the final cause. These are not alternative causes; it is not meant that, to explain anything, one or other of the four must be present. In every case of the existence or production of a thing all four causes operate simultaneously. Moreover the same four causes are to be found both in human and in cosmic production, in the making of manufactured articles by man and in the production of things by nature. They are more clearly and easily seen, however, in human production, from which sphere, therefore, we select our example. The material cause of a thing is the matter of which it is composed. It is the raw material which becomes the thing. For example, in the making of a bronze statue of Hermes, the bronze is the material cause of the statue. This example might lead one to suppose {269} that Aristotle means by material cause what we call matter, physical substance, such as brass, iron, or wood. As we shall see later, this is not necessarily the case, though it is so in the present instance. The efficient cause is always defined by Aristotle as the cause of motion. It is the energy or moving force required to bring about change. It must be remembered that by motion Aristotle means not merely change of place but change of any sort. The alteration of a leaf from green to yellow is just as much motion, in his sense, as the falling of a stone. The efficient cause, then, is the cause of all change. In the example taken, what causes the bronze to become a statue, what produces this change, is the sculptor. He is, therefore, the efficient cause of the statue. The formal cause Aristotle defines as the substance and essence of the thing. Now the essence of a thing is given in its definition. But the definition is the explication of the concept. Therefore the formal cause is the concept, or, as Plato would call it, the Idea of the thing. Plato's Ideas thus reappear in Aristotle as formal causes. The final cause is the end, purpose, or aim, towards which the movement is directed. When a statue is being produced, the end of this activity, what the sculptor aims at, is the completed statue itself. And the final cause of a thing in general is the thing itself, the completed being of the object.

Taking causation in this broad sense, Aristotle identifies four types of causes: material, efficient, formal, and final causes. These aren't alternative causes; it's not necessary for one or another of the four to be present to explain anything. In every instance of a thing's existence or creation, all four causes are at work simultaneously. Furthermore, these same four causes can be found in both human and natural processes, whether it’s about how people make manufactured items or how nature produces things. However, they are more clearly observed in human creation, which is why we use that as our example. The material cause of a thing is the matter it’s made from. It’s the raw material that becomes the item. For instance, in creating a bronze statue of Hermes, the bronze is the material cause of the statue. This example might suggest {269} that Aristotle refers to material cause in the way we understand matter, as physical substance like brass, iron, or wood. As we’ll see later, this isn’t always the case, though it is true in this situation. The efficient cause is always described by Aristotle as the cause of motion. It’s the energy or driving force needed to create change. It’s important to note that by motion, Aristotle means not just change of location, but any type of change. The transformation of a leaf from green to yellow is just as much motion, in his view, as the falling of a stone. So, the efficient cause is what brings about all change. In this example, what causes the bronze to turn into a statue, what creates this change, is the sculptor. He is, therefore, the efficient cause of the statue. The formal cause is what Aristotle defines as the substance and essence of the thing. The essence of a thing is defined by its definition. Thus, the formal cause corresponds to the concept, or, as Plato would term it, the Idea of the thing. Plato’s Ideas thus reappear in Aristotle as formal causes. The final cause is the end, purpose, or goal that directs the movement. When a statue is being created, the goal of this activity, what the sculptor is aiming for, is the finished statue itself. Therefore, the final cause of a thing in general is the thing itself, the completed object.

We can see at once how much wider this conception of causation is than the modern conception. If we take Mill's definition of a cause as the best expression of modern scientific ideas, we find that he defines a cause as the "invariable and unconditional antecedent of a phenomenon." This cuts out final causes at once. For {270} the final cause is the end, and is not an antecedent in time. It also does not include formal causes. For we do not now think of the concept of a thing as being part of its cause. This leaves us with only material and efficient causes, and these correspond roughly to the modern notions of matter and energy. Even the efficient causes of Aristotle, however, appear on further consideration, to be excluded from the modern idea of causation. For, though the efficient cause is the energy which produces motion, modern science regards it as purely mechanical energy, whereas Aristotle thinks of it, as we shall see, as an ideal force, operating not from the beginning but from the end. But it must not be supposed that, in saying that the modern idea of causation excludes formal and final causes, we mean that Aristotle is wrong in adding them, or that the modern idea is better than Aristotle's. It is not a question of better and worse at all. Modern science does not in any way deny the reality of formal and final causes. It merely considers them to be outside its sphere. It is no business of science whether they exist or not. As knowledge advances, differentiation and division of labour occur. Science takes as its province mechanical causes, and leaves formal and final causes to the philosopher to explicate. Thus, for example, formal causes are not considered by science because they are not, in the modern sense, causes at all. They are what we have called reasons. If we are to explain the existence of an object in the universe it may be necessary to introduce formal causes, concepts, to show why the thing exists, to show in fact its reasons. But science makes no attempt to explain the existence of objects. It takes their {271} existence for granted, and seeks to trace their history and their relations to each other. Therefore it does not require formal causes. It seeks to work out the mechanical view of the universe, and therefore considers only mechanical causes. But Aristotle's theory, as being philosophy rather than science, includes both the principles of mechanism and teleology.

We can immediately see how much broader this idea of causation is compared to the modern view. If we consider Mill's definition of a cause as the best expression of contemporary scientific thought, he defines a cause as the "invariable and unconditional antecedent of a phenomenon." This definition dismisses final causes right away. For {270}, the final cause is the goal and isn't a time-based antecedent. It also doesn't include formal causes, as we no longer see the concept of a thing as part of its cause. This leaves us with just material and efficient causes, which roughly align with modern concepts of matter and energy. However, even Aristotle's efficient causes, upon deeper consideration, seem to be left out of the modern idea of causation. While the efficient cause is the energy that generates motion, modern science views it purely as mechanical energy, whereas Aristotle perceives it, as we will explore, as an ideal force operating not from the beginning but from the end. But we shouldn't assume that by stating the modern idea of causation excludes formal and final causes, we imply that Aristotle is incorrect for including them, or that the modern concept is superior to Aristotle's. It's not a matter of better or worse. Modern science does not deny the existence of formal and final causes; it simply considers them outside its domain. Science does not concern itself with whether they exist or not. As knowledge progresses, we see increased specialization and division of labor. Science focuses on mechanical causes and leaves formal and final causes for philosophers to explain. For example, formal causes aren't addressed by science because they don't fit the modern definition of causes at all. They are what we refer to as reasons. If we're trying to explain why an object exists in the universe, it may be necessary to introduce formal causes or concepts to clarify the reasons behind its existence. However, science does not attempt to explain the existence of objects; it accepts their {271} existence as a given and seeks to trace their history and relationships with one another. Consequently, it does not require formal causes. It aims to develop a mechanical understanding of the universe, thus focusing solely on mechanical causes. Aristotle's theory, being philosophical rather than scientific, encompasses both the principles of mechanism and teleology.

It was not Aristotle's habit to propound his theories as if they were something absolutely new, sprung for the first time out of his own brain. In attacking any problem, his custom was to begin by enumerating current and past opinions, to criticise them, to reject what was valueless in them, to retain the residue of truth, and to add to it his own suggestions and original ideas. The resultant of this process was his own theory, which he thus represented, not as absolutely new, but as a development of the views of his predecessors. This course he follows also in the present instance. The first book of the "Metaphysics" is a history of all previous philosophy, from Thales to Plato, undertaken with the object of investigating how far the four causes had been recognized by his predecessors. The material cause, he says, had been recognized from the first. The Ionics believed in this and no other cause. They sought to explain everything by matter, though they differed among themselves as to the nature of the material cause, Thales describing it as water, Anaximenes as air. Later philosophers also gave different accounts of it, Heracleitus thinking it was fire, Empedocles the four elements, Anaxagoras an indefinite number of kinds of matter. But the point is that they all recognized the necessity for a material cause of some sort to explain the universe.

It wasn't Aristotle's style to present his theories as if they were completely new, created entirely in his mind for the first time. When tackling any issue, he typically started by listing existing opinions—both past and present—critiquing them, dismissing what was useless, keeping the bits of truth, and adding his own insights and original thoughts. The outcome of this process was his own theory, which he framed not as something wholly new, but as an evolution of his predecessors' ideas. He follows the same approach in this case. The first book of the "Metaphysics" is a history of all previous philosophy, from Thales to Plato, with the aim of examining how well the four causes were recognized by earlier thinkers. He states that the material cause has been acknowledged from the very beginning. The Ionics believed only in this cause, seeking to explain everything through matter, even though they disagreed about the nature of the material cause—Thales identified it as water, while Anaximenes identified it as air. Later philosophers also offered different interpretations: Heraclitus thought it was fire, Empedocles named the four elements, and Anaxagoras suggested an indefinite number of types of matter. The key point is that they all acknowledged the need for some type of material cause to explain the universe.

The earliest thinkers, then, the Ionics, assumed only this one cause. But as thought advanced, says Aristotle, and other philosophers came upon the scene, "the thing itself guided them." It was seen that a second cause was necessary to explain the motion and becoming of things. For matter itself does not produce its motion. Wood is not the cause of its becoming a bed, nor is brass the cause of its becoming a statue. Hence arose the idea of the efficient cause. The Eleatics did not recognize it, for they denied motion, and for them, therefore, no cause of motion could be assumed. But Parmenides, Aristotle thinks, wavered on this point, somehow allowing vaguely the existence of a second cause, which he denominated the hot and the cold. The reference is, of course, to the second part of the poem of Parmenides. Other philosophers clearly assumed an efficient cause, for they thought that one element, for example, fire, is more active, that is, more productive of motion, than others. Empedocles certainly attained to the idea of an efficient cause, for he named as moving forces, harmony and discord, love and hate. Anaxagoras also, used Nous as a moving force.

The earliest thinkers, the Ionics, considered only one cause. But as ideas developed, Aristotle and other philosophers noted that "the thing itself guided them." It became clear that a second cause was needed to explain the motion and transformation of things. Matter itself doesn’t produce its motion. Wood doesn’t cause itself to become a bed, nor does brass cause itself to become a statue. This led to the concept of the efficient cause. The Eleatics didn’t acknowledge it because they denied motion, so they couldn’t assume a cause of motion. However, Aristotle thinks Parmenides hesitated on this issue, vaguely allowing for the existence of a second cause, which he referred to as the hot and the cold. This refers to the second part of Parmenides’ poem. Other philosophers clearly accepted an efficient cause since they believed that some elements, like fire, are more active or productive of motion than others. Empedocles certainly recognized the idea of an efficient cause, identifying moving forces as harmony and discord, love and hate. Anaxagoras also used Nous as a moving force.

Formal causes had, perhaps, been recognized by the Pythagoreans, for numbers are forms. But they straightway degraded the formal cause to the level of a material cause by declaring that number is the stuff or matter of which things are made. Plato alone clearly saw the necessity for the formal cause, for formal causes are, as we have seen, the same as Plato's Ideas. But Plato's philosophy contains only two of the four causes, namely the material and the formal, for Plato made all things out of matter and the Ideas. Since the Ideas have in them {273} no principle of motion, Plato's system contains no efficient cause. As for final causes, Plato had indeed the vague idea that everything is for the sake of the Good, but he makes no use of this conception and does not develop it. Final causes were introduced into philosophy by Anaxagoras, whose doctrine of the world forming mind was assumed to explain the design and purpose which the universe exhibits. But as his system developed he forgot about this, and used the Nous merely as a piece of mechanism to explain motion, thus letting it sink into nothing more than an efficient cause.

Formal causes were probably acknowledged by the Pythagoreans since numbers are forms. However, they quickly lowered the importance of the formal cause by claiming that number is the substance or material from which things are created. Plato alone recognized the need for the formal cause, as these formal causes align with his Ideas. But Plato's philosophy only includes two of the four causes: the material and the formal, because he constructed everything using matter and the Ideas. Since the Ideas have no principle of motion within them, his system lacks an efficient cause. Regarding final causes, Plato had a vague notion that everything exists for the sake of the Good, but he doesn't utilize or expand on this idea. Final causes were brought into philosophy by Anaxagoras, whose concept of a world-forming mind was meant to clarify the design and purpose present in the universe. However, as his system evolved, he moved away from this idea and treated the Nous merely as a mechanism to explain motion, reducing it to nothing more than an efficient cause.

In the result, Aristotle finds that all four causes have been recognized in greater or lesser degrees by his predecessors, and this, in his opinion, greatly reinforces his own doctrine. But whereas material and efficient causes have been clearly understood, his predecessors had only vaguely foreshadowed and dimly perceived the value of formal and final causes.

As a result, Aristotle discovers that all four causes have been acknowledged to varying extents by those who came before him, and he believes this greatly supports his own theory. However, while material and efficient causes have been clearly grasped, his predecessors had only vaguely hinted at and faintly recognized the importance of formal and final causes.

The next step in Aristotle's metaphysics is to reduce these four principles to two, which he calls matter and form. This reduction takes place by showing that formal cause, efficient cause, and final cause, all melt into the single conception of form. In the first place, the formal cause and the final cause are the same. For the formal cause is the essence, the concept, the Idea, of the thing. Now the final cause, or the end, is simply the realisation of the Idea of the thing in actuality. What the thing aims at is the definite expression of its form. It thus aims at its form. Its end, final cause, is thus the same as its formal cause. Secondly, the efficient cause is the same as the final cause. For the efficient cause is the cause of becoming. The final cause is the end of {274} the becoming, it is what it becomes. And, in Aristotle's opinion, what causes the becoming is just that it aims at the end. The striving of all things is towards the end, and exists because of the end. The end is thus itself the cause of becoming or motion. That is to say, the final cause is the real efficient cause. We may see this better by an example. The end or final cause of the acorn is the oak. And it is the oak which is the cause of the acorn's growth, which consists essentially in a movement by which the acorn is drawn towards its end, the oak. We may see this even more definitely in the case of human productions, because here the striving towards an end is conscious, whereas in nature it is unconscious or instinctive. The efficient cause of the statue is the sculptor. It is he that moves the brass. But what moves the sculptor, and causes him to act upon the brass, is the idea of the completed statue in his mind. The idea of the end, the final cause, is thus the real ultimate cause of the movement. Only, in the case of human production, the idea of the end is actually present in the sculptor's mind as a motive. In nature there is no mind in which the end is conscious of itself, but nevertheless nature moves towards the end, and the end is the cause of the movement. Thus the three causes named all melt into a single notion, which Aristotle calls the form of the thing. And this leaves only the material cause unreduced to any other. So we are left with the single antithesis of matter and form.

The next step in Aristotle's metaphysics is to simplify these four principles into two, which he refers to as matter and form. This simplification happens by demonstrating that formal cause, efficient cause, and final cause all merge into the single idea of form. First, the formal cause and the final cause are the same. The formal cause represents the essence, concept, or Idea of a thing. The final cause, or the goal, is simply the realization of that Idea in reality. What a thing strives for is the specific expression of its form. Therefore, it aims at its form. Its goal, the final cause, is the same as its formal cause. Second, the efficient cause is identical to the final cause. The efficient cause is the reason for becoming, while the final cause is the end result of that becoming; it is what it turns into. According to Aristotle, what drives the process of becoming is that it aims for the end. Everything aims toward the end and exists because of it. Thus, the end itself is the cause of becoming or motion. In other words, the final cause is the true efficient cause. This is clearer with an example. The end or final cause of an acorn is the oak tree. The oak is what causes the acorn to grow, which fundamentally consists of a movement that draws the acorn toward its end, the oak. This is even more apparent in human creations, where the aim for an end is conscious, while in nature it is unconscious or instinctual. The efficient cause of a statue is the sculptor, who moves the bronze. However, what drives the sculptor and prompts him to work on the bronze is the idea of the completed statue in his mind. Thus, the idea of the end, the final cause, is the actual ultimate cause of the action. In human production, the idea of the end is present in the sculptor's mind as motivation. In nature, there isn't a mind that consciously understands the end, yet nature still moves toward it, and the end remains the cause of that motion. Consequently, the three causes blend into a single concept, which Aristotle calls the form of the thing. This leaves only the material cause distinct from the others. So we are left with the simple opposition of matter and form.

Now as matter and form are the fundamental categories of Aristotle's philosophy, by means of which he seeks to explain the entire universe, it is essential that we should thoroughly understand their characteristics. {275} First of all, matter and form are inseparable. We think of them as separate in order to understand them clearly. And this is quite right, because they are opposite principles, and therefore they are separable in thought. But they are never separable in fact. There is no such thing as form without matter, or matter without form. Every existent thing, that is, every individual object, is a compound of matter and form. We may compare them in this respect to the material and the shape of a thing, though we must be careful not to think that form is merely shape. Geometry considers shapes as if they existed by themselves. But, in fact, we know that there are no such things as squares, circles, and triangles. There are only square objects, circular objects, etc. And as there are no shapes without objects, so there are no objects without shapes. We talk of things being "shapeless," but this only means that their shape is irregular or unusual. Some shape an object must have. Yet, though shape and matter are inseparable in fact, they are opposite principles, and are separable in thought. Geometry is quite right to treat shapes as if they existed by themselves, but it is nevertheless dealing with mere abstractions. Just in the same way, matter and form are never apart, and to think of form by itself or matter by itself is a mere abstraction. No such thing exists. In fact, to imagine that forms can exist by themselves was just the mistake of which, as we have seen, Aristotle accuses Plato. For the form is the Idea, and Plato imagined that Ideas exist in a world of their own.

Now, since matter and form are the basic concepts in Aristotle's philosophy that he uses to explain the entire universe, it’s important for us to really grasp their characteristics. {275} First, matter and form are inseparable. We consider them separately to understand them better. This approach is valid because they are opposing principles, which means we can separate them in our minds, but they can never exist apart in reality. There's no such thing as form without matter or matter without form. Every existing thing—every individual object—is a combination of matter and form. We can think of them as similar to the material and shape of an object, though we need to be cautious not to reduce form to just shape. Geometry looks at shapes as if they exist independently, but in reality, we know that squares, circles, and triangles don’t actually exist on their own. There are only square objects, circular objects, and so on. Just as shapes cannot exist without objects, objects cannot exist without shapes. We often describe things as "shapeless," but that simply means their shape is irregular or unusual. An object must have some sort of shape. Although shape and matter are inseparable in reality, they are opposing principles that we can think of separately. Geometry is correct in treating shapes as if they exist on their own, but it's still addressing mere abstractions. Similarly, matter and form are never apart, and to think of form alone or matter alone is just an abstraction—no such thing actually exists. Imagining that forms can exist independently was exactly the error Aristotle points out in Plato. For form is the Idea, and Plato believed that Ideas existed in a separate world of their own.

From this, too, we can see that the form is the universal, the matter the particular. For the form is the Idea, and the Idea is the universal. To say that form and {276} matter cannot exist apart is thus the same as saying that the universal only exists in the particular, which, as we have seen, is the fundamental note of Aristotle's philosophy. But if we thus identify matter with the particular element in things, we must be careful that we do not confuse the particular with the individual. We often use these two words as practically synonymous, and there is no harm in this, but here we must be careful to separate them. For every individual is, according to Aristotle, a compound of matter and form, of the particular and the universal. And when we say that matter is the particular, we mean, not that it is such a compound, but that it is the absolutely particular which has no universal in it. But the absolutely particular and isolated does not exist. A piece of gold, for instance, only exists by virtue of its properties, yellowness, heaviness, etc., and these qualities are just what it has in common with other things. So that the particular, as such, has no existence, but this is only the same as saying, what we have already said, that matter has no existence apart from form.

From this, we can see that form is the universal, while matter is the specific. The form represents the Idea, and the Idea embodies the universal. To claim that form and matter cannot exist separately is equivalent to saying that the universal only exists within the specific, which, as we've mentioned, is a key point in Aristotle's philosophy. However, if we define matter as the specific aspect of things, we need to be careful not to confuse the specific with the individual. We often treat these two terms as interchangeable, and that’s usually fine, but here we should distinguish between them. According to Aristotle, every individual is a combination of matter and form, of the specific and the universal. When we say that matter is the specific, we don't mean that it's such a combination, but rather that it is the completely specific that has no universal aspect. Yet, the totally specific and isolated does not exist. For example, a piece of gold only exists because of its properties—like yellowness and heaviness—and these qualities are what it shares with other objects. Therefore, the specific, in itself, doesn't exist, which is just another way of saying that matter doesn't exist without form.

A very natural mistake would be to suppose that by matter Aristotle meant the same as we do, namely, physical substance, such as wood or iron, and that by form he meant simply shape. Now although there is a kinship in the ideas, these two pairs of ideas are far from identical. Let us begin with matter. Our ordinary idea of matter as physical substance is an absolute conception. That is to say, a thing which we call material is absolutely, once and for all, matter. It is not material from one point of view, and immaterial from another. In every possible relation it is, and {277} remains, matter. Nor does it in process of time cease to be matter. Brass never becomes anything but matter. No doubt there are in nature changes of one sort of matter into another, for example, radium into helium. And for all we know, brass may become lead. But even so, it does not cease to be matter. But Aristotle's conception of matter is a relative conception. Matter and form are fluid. They flow into one another. The same thing, from one point of view, is matter, from another, form. In all change, matter is that which becomes, that upon which the change is wrought. That is form towards which the change operates. What becomes is matter. What it becomes is form. Thus wood is matter if considered in relation to the bed. For it is what becomes the bed. But wood is form if considered in relation to the growing plant. For it is what the plant becomes. The oak is the form of the acorn, but it is the matter of the oak furniture.

A common mistake would be to think that when Aristotle talked about matter, he meant the same thing we do—physical substances like wood or iron—and that by form he just meant shape. Although there is some connection between these ideas, they are not the same. Let's start with matter. Our usual understanding of matter as physical substance is a fixed idea. This means that something we call material is always, once and for all, matter. It isn’t material from one angle and immaterial from another. In every situation, it is, and always will be, matter. Nor does it stop being matter over time. Brass will always be just matter. Sure, nature can change one type of matter into another, like radium turning into helium. And for all we know, brass might become lead. But even then, it doesn’t stop being matter. However, Aristotle’s idea of matter is more relative. Matter and form are interconnected. They transition into each other. The same thing can be matter from one perspective and form from another. In any transformation, matter is what changes, while form is what the change aims for. What changes is matter. What it changes into is form. For example, wood is considered matter when you think of it as part of a bed because it transforms into the bed. But wood is considered form when you think of it as part of a growing plant because it represents what the plant becomes. The oak is the form of the acorn, but it is the matter of the oak furniture.

That matter and form are relative terms shows, too, that the form cannot be merely the shape. For what is form in one aspect is matter in another. But shape is never anything but shape. No doubt the shape is part of the form, for the form in fact includes all the qualities of the thing. But the shape is quite an unimportant part of the form. For form includes organization, the relation of part to part, and the subordination of all parts to the whole. The form is the sum of the internal and external relations, the ideal framework, so to speak, into which the thing is moulded. Form also includes function. For it includes the final cause. Now the function of a thing is just what the thing is for. And what it is for is the same as its end, or final cause. {278} Therefore function is included in form. For example, the function of a hand, its power of gripping, is part of its form. And therefore, if it loses its function by being cut off from the arm, it likewise loses its form. Even the dead hand, of course, has some form, for every individual object is a compound of matter and form. But it has lost the highest part of its form, and relatively to the living hand it is mere matter, although, relatively to the flesh and bones of which it is composed, it is still form. Clearly, then, form is not merely shape. For the hand cut off does not lose its shape.

That matter and form are relative terms also shows that form can't just be about shape. What is form in one sense can be matter in another. But shape is always just shape. Of course, shape is part of the form because form actually includes all the qualities of the thing. However, shape is a relatively unimportant part of the form. Form includes organization, the relationships between parts, and how all parts fit into the whole. Form is the total of both internal and external relationships, the ideal framework, so to speak, that shapes the thing. Form also covers function because it includes the final purpose. The function of a thing is simply what it is meant for. And what it is meant for is the same as its end or final cause. Therefore, function is included in form. For instance, the function of a hand, its ability to grip, is part of its form. So if a hand loses its function by being cut off from the arm, it also loses its form. Even a dead hand still has some form, since every single object is a mix of matter and form. But it has lost the highest part of its form, and compared to a living hand, it is just matter, although in relation to the flesh and bones it’s made of, it is still considered form. Clearly, then, form is not just about shape. The severed hand does not lose its shape.

The form includes all the qualities of the thing. The matter is what has the qualities. For the qualities are all universals. A piece of gold is yellow, and this means simply that it has this in common with other pieces of gold, and other yellow objects. To say that anything has a quality is immediately to place it in a class. And what the class has in common is a universal. A thing without qualities cannot exist, nor qualities without a thing. And this is the same as saying that form and matter cannot exist separately.

The form includes all the qualities of an object. The matter is what possesses these qualities. Qualities are all universal. A piece of gold is yellow, which simply means it shares this characteristic with other pieces of gold and other yellow objects. To say that something has a quality immediately puts it in a category. What the category shares in common is a universal. An object without qualities cannot exist, nor can qualities exist without an object. This is the same as saying that form and matter cannot exist independently.

The matter, then, is the absolutely formless. It is the substratum which underlies everything. It has, in itself, no character. It is absolutely featureless, indefinite, without any quality. Whatever gives a thing definiteness, character, quality, whatever makes it a this or that, is its form. Consequently, there are no differences within matter. One thing can only differ from another by having different qualities. And as matter has no qualities, it has no difference. And this in itself shows that the Aristotelian notion of matter is not the same as our notion of physical substance. For, according {279} to our modern usage, one kind of matter differs from another, as brass from iron. But this is a difference of quality, and for Aristotle all quality is part of the form. So in his view the difference of brass from iron is not a difference of matter, but a difference of form. Consequently, matter may become anything, according to the form impressed upon it. It is thus the possibility of everything, though it is actually nothing. It only becomes something by the acquisition of form. And this leads directly to a most important Aristotelian antithesis, that between potentiality and actuality. Potentiality is the same as matter, actuality as form. For matter is potentially everything. It may become everything. It is not actually anything. It is a mere potentiality, or capacity of becoming something. But whatever gives it definiteness as a this or that, whatever makes it an actual thing, is its form. Thus the actuality of a thing is simply its form.

The matter, then, is completely formless. It is the foundation that underlies everything. It has no inherent character. It is entirely featureless, vague, and lacks any quality. Anything that gives something its definiteness, character, or quality—anything that makes it a specific thing—is its form. Therefore, there are no differences within matter. One thing can only differ from another by having different qualities. Since matter has no qualities, it has no differences. This clearly shows that Aristotle's idea of matter is not the same as our modern understanding of physical substance. According to our modern usage, one type of matter differs from another, like brass differs from iron. But that difference is based on quality, and for Aristotle, all quality is part of form. So, in his view, the distinction between brass and iron is not a difference in matter but a difference in form. Consequently, matter can become anything, depending on the form imposed on it. It represents the potential for everything, even though it is essentially nothing. It only becomes something by acquiring form. This leads us to a key Aristotelian contrast between potentiality and actuality. Potentiality is equivalent to matter, while actuality is equivalent to form. Matter is potentially everything; it can become anything. It is not actually anything. It is merely a potentiality, or the capacity to become something. But whatever gives it definiteness as this or that, whatever makes it an actual thing, is its form. Thus, the actuality of a thing is simply its form.

Aristotle claims, by means of the antithesis of potentiality and actuality, to have solved the ancient problem of becoming, a riddle, propounded by the Eleatics, which had never ceased to trouble Greek thinkers. How is becoming possible? For being to pass into being is not becoming, for it involves no change, and for not-being to pass into being is impossible, since something cannot come out of nothing. For Aristotle, the sharp line drawn between not-being and being does not exist. For these absolute terms he substitutes the relative terms potentiality and actuality, which shade off into each other. Potentiality in his philosophy takes the place of not-being in previous systems. It solves the riddle because it is not an absolute not-being. It is {280} not-being inasmuch as it is actually nothing, but it is being because it is potential being. Becoming, therefore, does not involve the impossible leap from nothing to something. It involves the transition from potential to actual being. All change, all motion, is thus the passage of potentiality into actuality, of matter into form.

Aristotle argues that through the contrast between potentiality and actuality, he has managed to resolve the age-old dilemma of becoming, a puzzle posed by the Eleatics that has constantly puzzled Greek philosophers. How can becoming happen? For something to change from being to being isn’t actually becoming, since it doesn’t entail any change, and for non-being to become being is impossible because something can’t emerge from nothing. For Aristotle, there’s no clear-cut distinction between non-being and being. Instead of these absolute terms, he uses the relative concepts of potentiality and actuality, which gradually transition into one another. Potentiality in his philosophy replaces non-being from earlier theories. It addresses the puzzle because it isn’t an absolute form of non-being. It is {280} non-being to the extent that it is actually nothing, but it is also being because it represents potential being. Thus, becoming doesn’t require the impossible jump from nothing to something. It involves the shift from potential to actual being. All change and motion represent the transformation of potentiality into actuality, of matter into form.

Since matter is in itself nothing, a bare unrealised capacity, while form is actuality, the completed and perfected being, it follows that form is something higher than matter. But matter is what becomes form. In order of time, therefore, matter is earlier, form later. But in order of thought, and in reality, it is otherwise. For when we say that matter is the potentiality of what it is to become, this implies that what it is to become is already present in it ideally and potentially, though not actually. The end, therefore, is already present in the beginning. The oak is in the acorn, ideally, otherwise the oak could never come out of it. And since all becoming is towards the end, and would not take place but for the end, the end is the operative principle and true cause of becoming. Motion is produced not by a mechanical propulsive force, pushing from behind, so to speak, but by an ideal attractive force, drawing the thing towards its end, as a piece of iron is drawn to the magnet. It is the end itself which exerts this force. And, therefore, the end must be present at the beginning, for if it were not present it could exert no force. Nay, more. It is not only present in the beginning, it is anterior to it. For the end is the cause of the motion, and the cause is logically prior to its consequence. The end, or the principle of form, is thus the absolute first in thought and reality, though it may be the last in time. If, then, {281} we ask what, for Aristotle, is that ultimate reality, that first principle, from which the entire universe flows, the answer is, the end, the principle of form. And as form is the universal, the Idea, we see that his fundamental thesis is the same as Plato's. It is the one thesis of all idealism, namely, that thought, the universal, reason, is the absolute being, the foundation of the world. Where he differs from Plato is in denying that form has any existence apart from the matter in which it exhibits itself.

Since matter is essentially nothing, just an unrealized potential, while form is actuality, the complete and perfected existence, it follows that form is superior to matter. However, matter becomes form. So, in the order of time, matter comes first and form comes later. But in terms of thought and reality, it's the other way around. When we say that matter is the potential of what it will become, we imply that what it will become is already ideally and potentially present within it, even if not actually. The end is already included in the beginning. The oak tree is contained in the acorn ideally; otherwise, the oak could never emerge from it. Since all becoming moves towards the end and wouldn't happen without it, the end is the driving principle and true cause of becoming. Motion is created not by a mechanical force pushing from behind, but by an ideal attractive force pulling the thing towards its end, like how a piece of iron is drawn to a magnet. It is the end itself that exerts this force. Therefore, the end must be present at the beginning; if it weren't, it couldn’t exert any force. Furthermore, it is not only present at the beginning but also comes before it. The end is the cause of the motion, and the cause logically precedes its effect. The end, or the principle of form, is thus the absolute first in thought and reality, although it may be the last in time. So, if we ask what that ultimate reality or first principle is for Aristotle, from which the entire universe originates, the answer is the end, the principle of form. And since form represents the universal, the Idea, we can see that his fundamental thesis aligns with Plato's. It is the common thesis of all idealism, which asserts that thought, the universal, reason, is the absolute being, the foundation of the world. Where he parts ways with Plato is in claiming that form doesn't exist independently of the matter in which it manifests.

Now all this may strike the unsophisticated as very strange. That the absolute being whence the universe flows should be described as that which lies at the end of the development of the universe, and that philosophy should proceed to justify this by asserting that the end is really prior to the beginning, this is so far removed from the common man's mode of thought, that it may appear mere paradox. It is, however, neither strange nor paradoxical. It is essentially sound and true, and it seems strange to the ordinary man only because it penetrates so much deeper into things than he can. This thought is, in fact, essential to a developed idealism, and till it is grasped no advance can be made in philosophy. Whether it is understood is, indeed, a good test of whether a man has any talent for philosophy or not. The fact is that all philosophies of this sort regard time as unreal, as an appearance. This being so, the relation of the absolute being, or God, to the world cannot be a relation of time at all. The common man's idea is that, if there is a first principle or God at all, He must have existed before the world began, and then, somehow, perhaps billions of years ago, something happened as a {282} result of which the world came into being. The Absolute is thus conceived as the cause, the world as the effect, and the cause always precedes its effect in time. Or if, on the other hand, we think that the world never had a beginning, the ordinary man's thought would lead him to believe that, in that case, it is no longer necessary to assume a first principle at all. But if time is a mere appearance, this whole way of looking at things must be wrong. God is not related to the world as cause to effect. It is not a relation of time at all. It is a logical relation. God is rather the logical premise, of which the world is the conclusion, so that, God granted, the world follows necessarily, just as, the premises granted, the conclusion follows. This is the reason why, in discussing Plato, we said that it must be possible to deduce the world from his first principle. If the Absolute were merely the cause of the world in time, it would not explain the world, for, as I have so often pointed out, causes explain nothing. But if the world be deducible from the Absolute, the world is explained, a reason, not a cause, is given for it, just as the premises constitute the reason for the conclusion. Now the conclusion of a syllogism follows from the premises, that is, the premises come first, the conclusion second. But the premise only comes first in thought, not in time. It is a logical succession, not a time-succession. Just in the same way, the Absolute, or in Aristotle's language, the form, is logically first, but is not first in order of time. And though it is the end, it is in thought the absolute beginning, and is thus the foundation of the world, the first principle from which the world flows. The objection may be, taken that if the relation of the {283} Absolute to the world is not a time-relation, then it can no more be the end than the beginning. This objection is, as we shall see, a misunderstanding of Aristotle's philosophy. Although things in time strive towards the end, yet the absolute end is not in time at all, or, in other words, the end is never reached. Its relation to the world as end is just as much a logical, and not a time-relation, as its relation to the world as beginning or absolute prius. As far as time is concerned, the universe is without beginning or end.

Now all this may seem very strange to those who aren't used to it. The idea that the ultimate source of the universe should be seen as something that appears at the end of the universe's development, and that philosophy tries to justify this by stating that the end actually comes before the beginning, is so far removed from how most people think that it might just seem like a paradox. However, it's neither strange nor paradoxical. It is fundamentally sound and true, and it only appears strange to the average person because it delves much deeper into reality than they can. This idea is, in fact, crucial to a more developed idealism, and until it's understood, progress in philosophy is impossible. Whether someone gets this concept is a good indicator of their ability to engage with philosophy. The reality is that all philosophies of this nature view time as an illusion or mere appearance. Given this, the connection between the ultimate being, or God, and the world cannot be a temporal one at all. The average person's idea is that if there is a first principle or God at all, He must have existed before the world began, and then, somehow, possibly billions of years ago, something happened as a {282} result of which the world came into existence. The Absolute is thus seen as the cause, while the world is the effect, and typically, the cause precedes its effect in time. Alternatively, if we think that the world never had a beginning, the ordinary person might conclude that in that case, there's no need to posit a first principle at all. But if time is just an illusion, then this whole perspective must be flawed. God is not related to the world as cause to effect. It isn’t a temporal relation at all. It is a logical relation. God is more like the logical premise from which the world is the conclusion, such that, if God exists, the world necessarily follows, just as the conclusion follows from the premises granted. This is why, when discussing Plato, we stated that it should be possible to deduce the world from his first principle. If the Absolute were only the cause of the world in time, it wouldn't properly explain the world, because, as I’ve often noted, causes do not explain anything. But if the world can be deduced from the Absolute, then the world is explained, providing a reason, not a cause for it, just as the premises serve as justification for the conclusion. In a syllogism, the conclusion follows from the premises—meaning the premises come first, and the conclusion comes second. But the premise comes first only in thought, not in time. It is a logical sequence, not a sequential order in time. Similarly, the Absolute, or as Aristotle might say, the form, is logically first, but not first in a temporal sense. And while it is the end, in thought, it serves as the absolute beginning, making it the foundation of the world, the first principle from which everything flows. One might argue that if the relation of the {283} Absolute to the world isn’t temporal, then it can’t be viewed as either the end or the beginning. However, this objection, as we will see, misunderstands Aristotle's philosophy. Although things in time aim towards the end, the absolute end is not within time at all—in other words, the end is never truly reached. Its relationship to the world as an end is just as much a logical relation, not a temporal one, as its relationship to the world as a beginning or absolute first principle. In terms of time, the universe has neither beginning nor end.

As the world-process is a continual elevation of matter into higher and higher forms, there results the conception that the universe exhibits a continuous scale of being. That is higher in the scale in which form predominates, that lower in which matter outweighs form. At the bottom of the scale will be absolutely formless matter, at the top, absolutely matterless form. Both these extremes, however, are abstractions. Neither of them exists, because matter and form cannot be separated. Whatever exists comes somewhere between the two, and the universe thus exhibits a process of continuous gradations. Motion and change are produced by the effort to pass from the lower to the higher under the attractive force of the end.

As the world evolves, it continuously transforms matter into higher and more complex forms, leading to the idea that the universe shows a continuous range of existence. The higher end of this range is the realm where form dominates, while the lower end is where matter predominates. At the bottom, we find completely formless matter, and at the top, entirely matterless form. However, both of these extremes are just concepts; neither actually exists since matter and form cannot be separated. Everything that exists falls somewhere in between, and the universe therefore shows a process of ongoing gradations. Movement and change happen because of the drive to move from the lower to the higher under the pull of the ultimate goal.

That which comes at the top of the scale, absolute form, is called by Aristotle, God. And the definitions of God's character follow from this as a matter of course. First, since form is actuality, God alone is absolutely actual. He alone is real. All existent things are more or less unreal. The higher in the scale are the more real, as possessing more form. The scale of being is thus also a scale of reality, shading off through infinite gradations {284} from the absolutely real, God, to the absolutely unreal, formless matter. Secondly, since the principle of form contains the formal, the final, and the efficient causes, God is all these. As formal cause, He is the Idea. He is essentially thought, reason. As final cause, He is the absolute end. He is that to which all beings strive. Each being has no doubt its own end in itself. But as absolute end, God includes all lower ends. And as the end of each thing is the completed perfection of the thing, so, as absolute end, God is absolute perfection. Lastly, as efficient cause, God is the ultimate cause of all motion and becoming. He is the first mover. As such, He is Himself unmoved. That the first mover should be itself unmoved is a necessary consequence of Aristotle's conception of it as end and form. For motion is the transition of a thing towards its end. The absolute end can have no end beyond it, and therefore cannot be moved. Likewise motion is the passage of matter into form. Absolute form cannot pass into any higher form, and is therefore unmoved. But the argument which Aristotle himself more frequently uses to establish the immovability of the first mover is that, unless we so conceive it, no cause of motion appears. The moving object is moved perhaps by another moving object. The motion of the latter demands a further cause. If this further cause is itself moving, we must again ask for the cause of its motion. If this process goes on for ever, then motion is unexplained, and no real cause of it has been shown. The real and ultimate cause must therefore be unmoved.

What ranks at the top of the scale, absolute form, is referred to by Aristotle as God. The definitions of God's nature follow from this naturally. First, since form represents actuality, God is the only one who is absolutely actual. He alone is real. Everything else that exists is, to some extent, unreal. The higher something is on the scale, the more real it is, as it possesses more form. Thus, the scale of being is also a scale of reality, gradually shifting {284} from the absolutely real, God, to the absolutely unreal, formless matter. Secondly, since the principle of form includes the formal, final, and efficient causes, God embodies all these roles. As the formal cause, He is the Idea. He is essentially thought and reason. As the final cause, He represents the absolute end. He is what all beings aim toward. Each being undoubtedly has its own purpose in itself. But as the absolute end, God encompasses all lower ends. And just as the end of each thing is its complete perfection, God, as absolute end, is absolute perfection. Lastly, as the efficient cause, God is the ultimate source of all motion and becoming. He is the first mover. As such, He is Himself unmoved. The necessity for the first mover to be unmoved stems from Aristotle's view of it as both end and form. Motion is the process by which a thing reaches its end. The absolute end cannot have any end beyond it, and thus cannot be moved. Similarly, motion is the transition of matter into form. Absolute form cannot transition into any higher form and is therefore unmoved. However, the argument that Aristotle often uses to demonstrate the immovability of the first mover is that, unless we conceive of it this way, no cause of motion seems to exist. The moving object is perhaps moved by another moving object. The motion of the latter requires another cause. If this next cause is also in motion, we must again ask for the reason behind its motion. If this process continues indefinitely, then motion remains unexplained, and no genuine cause has been identified. Thus, the real and ultimate cause must be unmoved.

This last argument sounds as if Aristotle is now thinking in terms of mechanism. It sounds as if he meant that {285} the first mover is something at the beginning of time, which, so to speak, gave things a push to start them off. This is not what Aristotle means. For the true efficient cause is the final cause. And God is the first mover only in His character as absolute end. As far as time is concerned, neither the universe, nor the motion in it, ever had any beginning. Every mechanical cause has its cause in turn, and so ad infinitum. God is not a first cause, in our sense, that is, a first mechanical cause which existed before the world, and created it. He is a teleological cause working from the end. But as such, He is logically prior to all beginning, and so is the first mover. And just as the universe has no beginning in time, so it has no end in time. It will go on for ever. Its end is absolute form, but this can never be reached, because if it were, this would mean that absolute form would exist, whereas we have seen that form cannot exist apart from matter.

This last argument suggests that Aristotle is thinking in terms of mechanism. It seems like he meant that the first mover is something at the start of time that, so to speak, gave things a push to get them going. However, that’s not what Aristotle means. The true efficient cause is the final cause. God is the first mover only in His role as the ultimate end. In terms of time, neither the universe nor the motion within it ever had a beginning. Every mechanical cause has a cause of its own, and so it goes on endlessly. God is not a first cause in our understanding, meaning a first mechanical cause that existed before the world and created it. He is a teleological cause working from the end. But in that sense, He is logically prior to any beginning, making Him the first mover. Just as the universe has no beginning in time, it also has no end in time. It will continue forever. Its end is absolute form, but this can never be attained, because if it were, that would mean absolute form exists, whereas we have seen that form cannot exist without matter.

God is thought. But the thought of what? As absolute form, he is not the form of matter, but the form of form. His matter, so to speak, is form. Form, as the universal, is thought. And this gives us Aristotle's famous definition of God as "the thought of thought." He thinks only his own self. He is at once the subject and the object of his thought. As mortal men think material things, as I now think the paper on which I write, so God thinks thought. In more modern terms, he is self-consciousness, the absolute subject-object. That God should think anything other than thought is inconceivable, because the end of all other thought is outside the thought itself. If I think this paper, the end of my thought, the paper, is outside me. But the thought of {286} God, as the absolute end, cannot have any end outside itself. Were God to think anything else than thought, he would be determined by that which is not himself. By way of further expression of the same idea, Aristotle passes into figurative language. God, he says, lives in eternal blessedness, and his blessedness consists in the everlasting contemplation of his own perfection.

God is thought. But thought of what? As the absolute form, he isn't the form of matter but the form of form. His essence, if you will, is form. Form, as the universal, is thought. This leads us to Aristotle's famous definition of God as "the thought of thought." He thinks only of himself. He is both the subject and the object of his thought. Just as mortal men think about material things—like I’m thinking about the paper I’m writing on—God thinks thought. To put it in more modern terms, he is self-consciousness, the absolute subject-object. It’s inconceivable for God to think anything other than thought because the conclusion of all other thoughts is outside the thought itself. If I think about this paper, the end of my thought, the paper, is outside of me. But the thought of God, as the absolute end, can’t have any conclusion outside of itself. If God were to think anything other than thought, he would be influenced by something that isn’t himself. To express the same idea in another way, Aristotle uses figurative language. He says God exists in eternal blessedness, and his blessedness comes from the continual contemplation of his own perfection.

A modern will naturally ask whether Aristotle's God is personal. It does not do to be very dogmatic upon the point. Aristotle, like Plato, never discusses the question. No Greek ever did. It is a modern question. What we have to do, then, is to take the evidence on both sides. The case for personality is that the language Aristotle uses implies it. The very word God, used instead of the Absolute, or form, conveys the idea of personality. And when he goes on to speak of God living in eternal blessedness, these words, if taken literally, can mean nothing except that God is a conscious person. If we say that this language is merely figurative, it may be replied that Aristotle on principle objects to figurative language, that he frequently censures Plato for using it, that what he demands and sets out to supply is exact, literal, scientific terminology, and that he is not likely to have broken his own canons of philosophic expression by using merely poetical phrases.

A modern person would naturally wonder whether Aristotle's God is personal. It’s not wise to be overly certain about this. Aristotle, like Plato, never addresses the issue. No Greek ever did. It’s a contemporary question. So, what we need to do is examine the evidence on both sides. The argument for personality is that the language Aristotle uses suggests it. The very term God, as opposed to the Absolute or form, implies the concept of personality. And when he talks about God living in eternal happiness, those words, if taken literally, can only mean that God is a conscious person. If we argue that this language is just figurative, one could respond that Aristotle fundamentally opposes figurative language, that he often criticizes Plato for using it, that what he strives for and intends to provide is accurate, literal, scientific terminology, and that he is unlikely to have violated his own standards of philosophical expression by using purely poetic phrases.

To see the other side of the case, we must first ask what personality means. Now without entering into an intricate discussion of this most elusive idea, we may answer that personality at any rate implies an individual and existent consciousness. But, in the first place, God is absolute form, and form is the universal. What is universal, with no particular in it, cannot be an individual. {287} God, therefore, cannot be individual. Secondly, form without matter cannot exist. And as God is form without matter, he cannot be called existent, though he is absolutely real. God, therefore, is neither existent nor individual. And this means that he is not a person. To degrade the real to the level of the existent, to convert the universal into the individual, is exactly the fault for which Aristotle blames Plato. It is exactly the fault which it was the whole object of his philosophy to remedy. If he thought that God is a person, he committed the same fault himself in an aggravated form.

To understand the other side of the argument, we need to start by asking what personality really means. Without diving into a complicated debate about this tricky concept, we can say that personality implies an individual and existent consciousness. However, first of all, God is absolute form, and form is universal. What is universal, without any specifics, cannot be an individual. {287} Therefore, God cannot be individual. Secondly, form cannot exist without matter. And since God is form without matter, he cannot be considered existent, even though he is absolutely real. So, God is neither existent nor individual, which means he is not a person. To lower the real to the level of the existent, to turn the universal into the individual, is precisely the error for which Aristotle criticizes Plato. It is the very mistake Aristotle aimed to correct with his philosophy. If he believed that God is a person, he made the same error in an even more serious way.

We have, then, two hypotheses, both of which involve that Aristotle was guilty of some inconsistency. If God is not a person, then Aristotle's language is figurative, and his use of such language is inconsistent with his rooted objection to its use. This, however, is, after all, merely an inconsistency of language, and not of thought. It does not mean that Aristotle really contradicted himself. It merely means that, though he set himself to express his philosophy in technical scientific terms, and to exclude figurative language, yet he found himself compelled in a few passages to make use of it. There are some metaphysical ideas so abstract, so abstruse, that it is almost impossible to express them at all without the use of figures of speech. Language was made by common men for common purposes, and this fact often forces the philosopher to use terms which he knows only figure forth his meaning without accurately expressing it. Perhaps every philosophy in the world finds itself sometimes under this necessity, and, if Aristotle did so, and was thereby technically inconsistent with himself, it is no wonder, and involves no serious blame upon him.

We have two hypotheses, both suggesting that Aristotle was inconsistent in some way. If God isn't a person, then Aristotle's language is metaphorical, which contradicts his strong objection to using such language. However, this is just a language inconsistency, not a thought inconsistency. It doesn't mean Aristotle truly contradicted himself. It simply shows that while he aimed to express his philosophy in precise scientific terms and avoid figurative language, he ended up using it in a few instances. Some metaphysical ideas are so abstract and complex that it's nearly impossible to convey them without metaphors. Language was created by everyday people for practical use, and this often forces philosophers to use terms that only partially capture their intended meaning. Almost every philosophy encounters this challenge at times, and if Aristotle did as well, leading to a technical inconsistency, it's understandable and doesn't reflect badly on him.

But the other hypothesis, that God is a person, means that Aristotle committed a contradiction, not merely in words, but in thought, and not merely as regards some unimportant detail, but as regards the central thesis of his system. It means that he stultified himself by making his conception of God absolutely contradict the essentials of his system. For what is the whole of Aristotle's philosophy, put in a nutshell? It is that the Absolute is the universal, but that the universal does not exist apart from the particular. Plato supplied the thought of the first clause of the sentence. Aristotle added the last clause, and it is the essential of his philosophy. To assert that God, the absolute form, exists as an individual, is flatly to contradict this. It is not likely that Aristotle should have contradicted himself in so vital a matter, and in a manner which simply means that his system falls to the ground like a house of cards.

But the other idea, that God is a person, suggests that Aristotle contradicted himself not just in words, but in his thinking, and not just about some minor detail, but about the main point of his philosophy. It means he undermined himself by creating a view of God that completely goes against the fundamentals of his system. So what is Aristotle's philosophy, in a nutshell? It's that the Absolute is the universal, but the universal doesn’t exist separately from the particular. Plato provided the concept for the first part of that statement. Aristotle added the second part, and that is the core of his philosophy. To claim that God, the absolute form, exists as an individual directly contradicts this. It seems unlikely that Aristotle would contradict himself on such a crucial issue in a way that would make his entire system collapse like a house of cards.

My conclusion, then, is that it was not Aristotle's intention that what he calls God should be regarded as a person. God is thought, but not subjective thought. He is not thought existent in a mind, but objective thought, real on its own account, apart from any mind which thinks it, like Plato's Ideas. But Plato's mistake was to suppose that because thought is real and objective, it must exist. Aristotle avoids this error. The absolute thought is the absolutely real. But it does not exist. With the concept of God the metaphysics of Aristotle closes.

My conclusion is that Aristotle didn’t intend for what he calls God to be seen as a person. God is thought, but not personal thought. He is not thought that exists within a mind, but rather objective thought, real on its own, independent of any mind thinking it, similar to Plato's Ideas. However, Plato's mistake was assuming that because thought is real and objective, it must exist. Aristotle avoids this error. The absolute thought is absolutely real, but it doesn’t exist. With the concept of God, Aristotle’s metaphysics comes to an end.


4. Physics, or the Philosophy of Nature.

4. Physics, or the Study of Nature.

The existent universe is a scale of being lying between the two extremes of formless matter and matterless form. But this must not be merely asserted, as a general {289} principle. It must be carried out in detail. The passage of matter into form must be shown in its various stages in the world of nature. To do this is the object of Aristotle's Physics, or philosophy of nature.

The existing universe is a spectrum of existence between the two extremes of shapeless matter and form without substance. But this shouldn’t just be stated as a general principle. It needs to be demonstrated in detail. The transformation of matter into form must be illustrated in its different stages in the natural world. This is the purpose of Aristotle's Physics, or philosophy of nature.

If nature is to be understood, we must keep in mind certain general points of view. In the first place, since form includes end, the entire world-process, as passage of matter into form, is essentially movement towards ends. Everything in nature has its end and function. Nothing is purposeless. Nature seeks everywhere to attain the best possible. Everywhere we find evidences of design and of rational plan. Aristotle's philosophy of nature is essentially teleological. This does not, however, exclude the principle of mechanism, and to investigate mechanical causes is part of the duty of science. But mechanical causes turn out in the end to be teleological, because the true efficient cause is the final cause.

If we want to understand nature, we need to keep certain general viewpoints in mind. First, since form includes purpose, the entire process of the world, as the transformation of matter into form, is essentially a movement toward goals. Everything in nature has a purpose and a role. Nothing is without purpose. Nature aims to achieve the best possible outcome everywhere. We can find evidence of design and rational planning all around us. Aristotle's philosophy of nature is fundamentally about purpose. However, this doesn't dismiss the principle of mechanism, and investigating mechanical causes is an important part of science. But ultimately, mechanical causes are really about purpose because the true cause behind everything is the final cause.

But if nothing in nature is aimless or useless, this is not to be interpreted in a narrow anthropocentric spirit. It does not mean that everything exists for the use of man, that the sun was created to give him light by day, the moon by night, and that plants and animals exist only for his food. It is true that, in a certain sense, everything else sublunary is for man. For man is the highest in the scale of beings in this terrestrial sphere, and therefore as the higher end, he includes all lower ends. But this does not exclude the fact that lower beings have each its own end. They exist for themselves and not for us.

But if nothing in nature is aimless or useless, that doesn't mean we should see it from a narrow human-centered perspective. It doesn't imply that everything exists for human use, that the sun was created to provide daylight, the moon for night, or that plants and animals exist solely for our food. It’s true that, in some sense, everything beneath the moon is for humans. Since humans are at the top of the hierarchy of beings in this world, we encompass all the lower purposes. However, this doesn’t negate the fact that lower beings have their own purposes. They exist for themselves, not for us.

Another mistake which we must avoid is to suppose that the design in nature means that nature is conscious of her designs, or, on the other hand, that there is any {290} existent consciousness outside the world which governs and controls it. The latter supposition is excluded by the fact that God is not an existent conscious person, the former by its own inherent absurdity. The only being upon this earth who is conscious of his ends is man. Such animals as bees and ants appear to work rationally, and their activities are clearly governed by design. But it is not to be supposed that they are reasoning beings. They attain their ends instinctively. And when we come to inorganic matter, we find that even here its movements are purposive, but no one could suppose them deliberate and conscious. These manifold activities of lower nature are indeed the work of reason, but not of an existent or self-conscious reason. And this means that instinct, and even mechanical forces such as gravitation are, in their essence, reason. It is not that they are created by reason, but that they are reason, exhibiting itself in lower forms. In commenting upon Plato's dualism of sense and reason, I remarked that any true philosophy, though recognizing the distinction between sense and reason, must yet find room for their identity, and must show that sense is but a lower form of reason. This idea Aristotle thoroughly understood, and sought to show, not merely that sense is reason, but even that the activities of inorganic matter, such as gravitation, are so. In the result, nature, though working through reason, is not conscious of the fact, does so blindly and instinctively, and is compared to a creative artist, who forms beautiful objects by instinct, or, as we should say, by inspiration, without setting before his mind the end to be attained or the rules to be observed in order to attain it.

Another mistake we must avoid is thinking that the design in nature means that nature is aware of its designs, or, conversely, that there is some consciousness outside of the world that governs and controls it. The latter idea is ruled out by the fact that God is not an existing conscious person, while the former is inherently absurd. The only being on this earth that is conscious of its goals is humans. Creatures like bees and ants appear to work rationally, and their actions are clearly guided by design. But we shouldn't assume that they are reasoning beings. They achieve their goals instinctively. When it comes to inorganic matter, we find that even its movements are purposeful, but no one could think they are deliberate and conscious. These various activities of lower nature are indeed the result of reason, but not of an existing or self-conscious reason. This means that instinct, and even mechanical forces like gravity, are essentially reason. It's not that they are created by reason, but that they are reason itself, manifesting in simpler forms. While discussing Plato's dualism of sense and reason, I pointed out that any true philosophy, although acknowledging the distinction between sense and reason, must also recognize their identity and must show that sense is just a lower form of reason. Aristotle fully grasped this idea and aimed to demonstrate that not only is sense reason, but even the activities of inorganic matter, such as gravity, are also reason. As a result, nature, while operating through reason, is not aware of it; it does so blindly and instinctively, and is likened to a creative artist who produces beautiful works by instinct, or, as we might say, by inspiration, without consciously considering the end goal or the rules to follow to achieve it.

In the process of nature, it is always form which impels, matter which retards and obstructs. The entire world-movement is the effort of form to mould matter, but, just because matter has in itself a power of resistance, this effort does not always succeed. This is the reason why form cannot exist without matter, because it can never wholly overcome the clogging activity of matter, and therefore matter can never be wholly moulded into form. And this explains, too, the occasional occurrence in nature of freaks, monstrosities, abortions, and unnatural births. In these the form has failed to mould the matter. Nature has failed to attain her ends. Science, therefore, should study the normal and natural rather than the abnormal and monstrous. For it is in the normal that the ends of nature are to be seen, and through them alone nature can be understood. Aristotle is fond of using the words "natural" and "unnatural," but he uses them always with this special meaning. That is natural which attains its end, that in which the form successfully masters the matter.

In nature, it's always form that drives and matter that slows things down and blocks progress. The whole movement of the world is the effort of form trying to shape matter, but since matter has a built-in resistance, this effort doesn't always work out. That's why form can't exist without matter; it can never completely overcome the hindering force of matter, so matter can never be entirely shaped by form. This also explains why we sometimes see abnormalities, deformities, and unusual births in nature. These happen when form fails to shape matter. Nature doesn't reach its goals in these cases. Therefore, science should focus on the normal and natural instead of the abnormal and monstrous. It's in the normal that we can see nature's goals, and only through them can we truly understand nature. Aristotle often uses the terms "natural" and "unnatural," but he always gives them this specific meaning. What is natural is that which achieves its purpose, where form successfully controls matter.

No doctrine of physics can ignore the fundamental notions of motion, space, and time. Aristotle, therefore, finds it necessary to consider these. Motion is the passage of matter into form, and it is of four kinds. The first is motion which affects the substance of a thing, origination and decease. Secondly, change of quality. Thirdly, change of quantity, increase and decrease. Fourthly, locomotion, change of place. Of these, the last is the most fundamental and important.

No theory of physics can overlook the basic ideas of motion, space, and time. Aristotle, therefore, feels it's important to think about these. Motion is the transformation of matter into form, and it comes in four types. The first is motion that changes the substance of something, like coming into existence and dying. The second is changing quality. The third is changing quantity, which means increasing or decreasing. The fourth is locomotion, or changing place. Among these, the last is the most essential and significant.

Aristotle rejects the definition of space as the void. Empty space is an impossibility. Hence, too, he disagrees with the view of Plato and the Pythagoreans that {292} the elements are composed of geometrical figures. And connected with this is his repudiation of the mechanical hypothesis that all quality is founded upon quantity, or upon composition and decomposition. Quality has a real existence of its own. He rejects, also, the view that space is a physical thing. If this were true, there would be two bodies occupying the same place at the same time, namely the object and the space it fills. Hence there is nothing for it but to conceive space as limit. Space is, therefore, defined as the limit of the surrounding body towards what is surrounded. As we shall see later, in another connexion, Aristotle did not regard space as infinite.

Aristotle rejects the idea that space is just a void. Empty space is impossible. For this reason, he also disagrees with Plato and the Pythagoreans who believe that the elements are made up of geometric figures. Additionally, he dismisses the mechanical theory that all qualities are based on quantities or on the processes of combining and breaking down. Quality exists independently. He also rejects the notion that space is a physical object. If that were true, there would be two bodies in the same place at the same time: the object and the space it occupies. Therefore, we must understand space as a boundary. Space is, thus, defined as the boundary of the surrounding body in relation to what is being surrounded. As we will explore later in another context, Aristotle did not see space as infinite.

Time is defined as the measure of motion in regard to what is earlier and later. It thus depends for its existence upon motion. If there were no change in the universe, there would be no time. And since it is the measuring or counting of motion, it also depends for its existence upon a counting mind. If there were no mind to count, there could be no time. This presents difficulties to us, if we conceive that there was a time when conscious beings did not exist. But this difficulty is non-existent for Aristotle, who believed that men and animals have existed from all eternity. The essentials of time, therefore, are two: change and consciousness. Time is the succession of thoughts. If we object that the definition is bad because succession already involves time, there is doubtless no answer possible.

Time is understood as the measurement of motion in relation to what happens first and what happens next. It relies on motion for its existence. Without change in the universe, there would be no time. Since time is about measuring or counting motion, it also depends on the presence of a mind to count. If there were no mind to keep track, time could not exist. This creates challenges for us if we think there was a time when conscious beings weren't around. However, this problem doesn’t exist for Aristotle, who believed that humans and animals have always existed. Thus, the key elements of time are twofold: change and consciousness. Time is essentially the flow of thoughts. If we argue that this definition is flawed because succession already implies time, there's likely no way to effectively respond.

As to the infinite divisibility of space and time, and the riddles proposed thereupon by Zeno, Aristotle is of opinion that space and time are potentially divisible {293} ad infinitum, but are not actually so divided. There is nothing to prevent us from going on for ever with the process of division, but space and time are not given in experience as infinitely divided.

Regarding the infinite divisibility of space and time, and the puzzles Zeno brought up about it, Aristotle believes that space and time can be divided theoretically ad infinitum, but they aren’t actually divided that way. There’s nothing stopping us from endlessly dividing them, but in experience, space and time are not seen as infinitely divided.

After these preliminaries, we can pass on to consider the main subject of physics, the scale of being. We should notice, in the first place, that it is also a scale of values. What is higher in the scale of being is of more worth, because the principle of form is more advanced in it. It constitutes also a theory of development, a philosophy of evolution. The lower develops into the higher. It does not, however, so develop in time. That the lower form passes in due time into a higher form is a discovery of modern times. Such a conception was impossible for Aristotle. For him, genus and species are eternal. They have neither beginning nor end. Individual men are born and die, but the species man never dies, and has always existed upon the earth. The same is true of plants and animals. And since man has always existed, he cannot have evolved in time from a lower being. There is no room here for Darwinism. In what sense, then, is this a theory of development or evolution? The process involved is not a time-process, it is a logical process, and the development is a logical development. The lower always contains the higher potentially. The man is in the ape ideally. The higher, again, contains the lower actually. The man is all that the ape is, and more also. What is merely implicit in the lower form is explicit in the higher. The form which is dimly seen struggling to light in the lower, has realized itself in the higher. The higher is the same thing as the lower, but it is the same thing in a more {294} evolved state. The higher presupposes the lower and rests upon it as foundation. The higher is the form of which the lower is the matter. It actually is what the lower is struggling to become. Hence the entire universe is one continuous chain. It is a process; not a time-process, but an eternal process. The one ultimate reality, God, reason, absolute form, eternally exhibits itself in every stage of its development. All the stages, therefore, must exist for ever side by side.

After these preliminaries, we can move on to discuss the main topic of physics, the scale of being. First, we should note that it also represents a scale of values. The higher something is on the scale of being, the more valuable it is because its form is more advanced. This also represents a theory of development, a philosophy of evolution. The lower evolves into the higher. However, this evolution doesn’t happen over time. The idea that a lower form transitions into a higher form over time is a modern discovery. This idea would have been impossible for Aristotle, who believed that genera and species are eternal and have no beginning or end. Individual humans are born and die, but the species of humans never dies and has always existed on Earth. The same holds true for plants and animals. Because humanity has always existed, it couldn’t have evolved from a lower being. There’s no space here for Darwinism. So, in what sense is this a theory of development or evolution? The process involved isn’t a process of time; it’s a logical process, and the development is a logical development. The lower always contains the higher in potential. The human exists in the ape ideally. The higher also contains the lower in reality. A human embodies everything the ape is, plus more. What is only implicit in the lower form becomes explicit in the higher. The form that is vaguely seen struggling to emerge in the lower has realized itself in the higher. The higher is essentially the same as the lower but exists in a more evolved state. The higher assumes the existence of the lower and is built upon it as a foundation. The higher represents what the lower is striving to become. Therefore, the entire universe is one continuous chain. It is a process; not a process of time, but an eternal process. The one ultimate reality, God, reason, absolute form, constantly reveals itself at every stage of its development. Thus, all stages must exist forever side by side.

Now the form of a thing is its organization. Hence to be higher in the scale means to be more organized. The first distinction, therefore, with which nature presents us is between the organic and the inorganic. Aristotle was the discoverer of the idea of organism, as he was also the inventor of the word. At the bottom of the scale of being, therefore, is inorganic matter. Inorganic matter is the nearest existent thing to absolutely formless matter, which, of course, does not exist. In the inorganic world matter preponderates to such an extent as almost to overwhelm form, and we can only expect to see the universal exhibiting itself in it in a vague and dim way. What, then, is its form? And this is the same as asking what its function, end, or essential activity is. The end of inorganic matter is merely external to it. Form has not truly entered into it at all, and remains outside it. Hence the activity of inorganic matter can only be to move in space towards its external end. This is the explanation of what we, in modern times, call gravitation. But, according to Aristotle, every element has its peculiar and natural motion; its end is conceived merely spatially, and its activity is to move towards its "proper place," and, having thus reached its end, it rests. The natural {295} movement of fire is up. We may call this a principle of levitation, as opposed to gravitation. Aristotle has been the subject of cheap criticism on account of his frequent use of the words "natural" and "unnatural." [Footnote 15] It is said that he was satisfied to explain the operations of nature by simply labelling them "natural." If you ask a quite uneducated person why heavy bodies fall, he may quite possibly reply, "Oh! naturally they fall." This simply means that the man has never thought about the matter at all, and thinks whatever is absolutely familiar to him is "natural" and needs no explanation. It is like the feminine argument that a thing is so, "because it is." It is assumed that Aristotle was guilty of a like futility. This is not the case. His use of the word "natural" does not indicate lack of thought. There is a thought, an idea, here. No doubt he was quite wrong in many of his facts. Thus there is no such principle as levitation in the universe. But there is a principle of gravitation, and when he explains this by saying it is "natural" for earth to move downwards, he means, not that the fact is familiar, but that the principle of form, or the world-reason, can only exhibit itself here so dimly as to give rise to a comparatively aimless and purposeless movement in a straight line. Not absolutely purposeless, however, because nothing in the world is such, and the purpose here is simply the movement of matter towards its end. This may or may not be a true explanation of gravity. But has anybody since ever explained it better?

Now the shape of something is its organization. So to be higher on the scale means to be more organized. The first distinction that nature shows us is between the organic and the inorganic. Aristotle discovered the concept of organism, and he also invented the term. At the bottom of the being scale is inorganic matter. Inorganic matter is the closest thing to completely formless matter, which, of course, doesn’t exist. In the inorganic world, matter dominates to such a degree that it almost overshadows form, and we can only expect to see the universal express itself in a vague and unclear way. So, what is its form? This is the same as asking what its function, purpose, or essential activity is. The purpose of inorganic matter is merely external to it. Form hasn’t truly entered into it at all and remains outside it. Thus, the activity of inorganic matter can only be to move in space towards its external purpose. This explains what we, in modern times, call gravitation. But, according to Aristotle, every element has its unique and natural motion; its purpose is conceived merely in spatial terms, and its activity is to move towards its "proper place," and once it reaches its purpose, it comes to rest. The natural {295} movement of fire is upwards. We might call this a principle of levitation, as opposed to gravitation. Aristotle has faced criticism for frequently using the terms "natural" and "unnatural." [Footnote 15] It’s said that he was content to explain nature’s operations by simply labeling them "natural." If you ask a completely uneducated person why heavy objects fall, they might very well say, "Oh! naturally they fall." This just means the person has never really thought about it and assumes whatever is completely familiar to them is "natural" and doesn’t need explaining. It’s like the feminine argument that something is the case, "because it is." It’s assumed that Aristotle was guilty of similar emptiness. This isn’t true. His use of the word "natural" doesn’t indicate a lack of thought. There’s a thought, an idea, here. He might have been wrong about many of his facts. There’s no principle of levitation in the universe. But there is a principle of gravitation, and when he explains this by saying it is "natural" for the earth to move downwards, he doesn’t mean that the fact is familiar but that the principle of form, or world-reason, can only show itself here so faintly that it results in a relatively aimless and purposeless movement in a straight line. Not absolutely purposeless, though, because nothing in the world is entirely purposeless, and the purpose here is simply the movement of matter towards its end. This may or may not be a true explanation of gravity. But has anyone since explained it any better?

[Footnote 15: See, e.g. Sir Alexander Grant's Aristotle in the Ancient Classics for English Readers Series (Blackwood), pages 119-121.]

[Footnote 15: See, for example, Sir Alexander Grant's Aristotle in the Ancient Classics for English Readers Series (Blackwood), pages 119-121.]

This gives us, too, the clue to the distinction between {296} the inorganic and the organic. If inorganic matter is what has its end outside itself, organic matter will be what has its end within itself. This is the essential character of an organism, that its end is internal to it. It is an inward self-developing principle. Its function, therefore, can only be the actualisation, the self-realization of this inward end. Whereas, therefore, inorganic matter has no activity except spatial movement, organic matter has for its activity growth, and this growth is not the mere mechanical addition of extraneous matter, as we add a pound of tea to a pound of tea. It is true growth from within. It is the making outward of what is inward. It is the making explicit of what is implicit. It is the making actual of what is potential in the embryo organism.

This also gives us a clue to the difference between {296} the inorganic and the organic. If inorganic matter has its purpose outside itself, then organic matter has its purpose within itself. This is the essential nature of an organism: its purpose is internal. It operates on an inward self-developing principle. Therefore, its function can only be the actualization, the self-realization of this inward purpose. While inorganic matter has no activity beyond spatial movement, organic matter's activity is growth, and this growth isn’t just the mechanical addition of outside material, like adding a pound of tea to another pound of tea. It’s genuine growth from within. It involves bringing forth what is inside. It’s about making explicit what is implicit. It’s the actualization of what is potential in the developing organism.

The lowest in the scale of being is thus inorganic matter, and above it comes organic matter, in which the principle of form becomes real and definite as the inward organization of the thing. This inward organization is the life, or what we call the soul, of the organism. Even the human soul is nothing but the organization of the body. It stands to the body in the relation of form to matter. With organism, then, we reach the idea of living soul. But this living soul will itself have lower and higher grades of being, the higher being a higher realization of the principle of form. As the essential of organism is self-realization, this will express itself first as self-preservation. Self-preservation means first the preservation of the individual, and this gives the function of nutrition. Secondly, it means preservation of the species, and this gives the function of propagation. The lowest grade in the organic kingdom will, therefore, be {297} those organisms whose sole functions are to nourish themselves, grow, and propagate their kind. These are plants. And we may sum up this by saying that plants possess the nutritive soul. Aristotle intended to write a treatise upon plants, which intention, however, he never carried out. All that we have from him on plants is scattered references in his other books. Had the promised treatise been forthcoming, we cannot doubt what its plan would have been. Aristotle would have shown, as he did in the case of animals, that there are higher and lower grades of organism within the plant kingdom, and he would have attempted to trace the development in detail through all the then known species of plants.

The lowest level of existence is inorganic matter, followed by organic matter, where the principle of form becomes clear and specific as the internal organization of the entity. This internal organization is the life, or what we refer to as the soul, of the organism. Even the human soul is simply the organization of the body. It relates to the body in the same way that form relates to matter. With organisms, we encounter the concept of a living soul. However, this living soul will have both lower and higher levels of existence, with the higher levels representing a more advanced realization of the principle of form. Since the essence of an organism is self-realization, this begins with self-preservation. Self-preservation first refers to protecting the individual, which involves nutrition. Secondly, it refers to the preservation of the species, leading to the function of reproduction. Thus, the lowest level in the organic kingdom consists of those organisms whose only functions are to nourish themselves, grow, and reproduce. These are plants. We can summarize this by saying that plants have a nutritive soul. Aristotle intended to write a treatise on plants, but he never completed it. All we have from him regarding plants are scattered mentions in his other works. If the promised treatise had been completed, we can be sure of its structure. Aristotle would have shown, as he did with animals, that there are higher and lower grades of organisms within the plant kingdom, and he would have sought to detail the development across all the known plant species at the time.

Next above plants in the scale of being come animals. Since the higher always contains the lower, but exhibits a further realization of form peculiar to itself, animals share with plants the functions of nutrition and propagation. What is peculiar to them, the point in which they rise above plants, is the possession of sensation. Sense-perception is therefore the special function of animals, and they possess, therefore, the nutritive and the sensitive souls. With sensation come pleasure and pain, for pleasure is a pleasant sensation, and pain the opposite. Hence arises the impulse to seek the pleasant and avoid the painful. This can only be achieved by the power of movement. Most animals, accordingly, have the power of locomotion, which is not possessed by plants, because they do not require it, since they are not sensitive to pleasure and pain. In his books upon animals Aristotle attempts to carry out the principle of development in detail, showing what are the higher, and what the lower, animal organisms. This he connects with the {298} methods of propagation employed by different animals. Sex-generation is the mark of a higher organism than parthenogenesis.

Next above plants in the hierarchy of life come animals. Since the higher always includes the lower but expresses a more advanced form unique to itself, animals share with plants the functions of nourishment and reproduction. What sets them apart, the factor that elevates them above plants, is the ability to feel. Sensory perception is therefore the main function of animals, meaning they possess both nutritive and sensitive souls. With the ability to feel comes pleasure and pain; pleasure is a positive sensation, while pain is its opposite. This creates the drive to seek out what feels good and avoid what feels bad. To do this, movement is necessary. Most animals, therefore, can move, which plants cannot do because they don't need to, as they do not experience pleasure and pain. In his writings on animals, Aristotle strives to elaborate on the idea of development in detail, illustrating which animal forms are higher and which are lower. He connects this with the {298} methods of reproduction used by various animals. Sexual reproduction indicates a higher organism than parthenogenesis.

The scale of being proceeds from animals to man. The human organism, of course, contains the principles of all lower organisms. Man nourishes himself, grows, propagates his kind, moves about, and is endowed with sense-perception. But he must have in addition his own special function, which constitutes his advance beyond the animals. This is reason. Reason is the essential, the proper end and activity of man. His soul is nutritive, sensitive, and rational. In man, therefore, the world-reason which could only appear in inorganic matter as gravitation and levitation, in plants as nutrition, in animals as sensation, appears at last in its own proper form, as what it essentially is, reason. The world-reason, so long struggling towards the light, has reached it, has become actual, has become existent, in man. The world-process has attained its proximate end.

The hierarchy of life goes from animals to humans. The human body contains the characteristics of all lower life forms. Humans eat, grow, reproduce, move, and have sensory perceptions. However, they also have a unique function that sets them apart from animals. That function is reason. Reason is fundamental, the true purpose and activity of humans. A person's soul has three aspects: nutritive, sensitive, and rational. Therefore, in humans, the universal reason that manifested in non-living matter as gravity and levitation, in plants as nourishment, and in animals as sensations finally appears in its true form: reason. The universal reason, which has been striving for recognition, has now achieved it, becoming real and existing in humans. The process of existence has reached its near-end.

Within human consciousness there are lower and higher grades, and Aristotle has taken great pains to trace these from the bottom to the top. These stages of consciousness are what are ordinarily called "faculties." But Aristotle notes that it is nonsense to talk, as Plato did, of the "parts" of the soul. The soul, being a single indivisible being, has no parts. They are different aspects of the activity of one and the same being; different stages of its development. They can no more be separated than the convex and concave aspects of a curve. The lowest faculty, if we must use that word, is sense-perception. Now what we perceive in a thing is its qualities. Perception tells us that a piece of gold is {299} heavy, yellow, etc. The underlying substratum which supports the qualities cannot be perceived. This means that the matter is unknowable, the form knowable, for the qualities are part of the form. Sense-perception, therefore, takes place when the object stamps its form upon the soul. This is important for what it implies rather than what it states. It shows the thoroughly idealistic trend of Aristotle's thought. For if the form is what is knowable in a thing, the more form there is, the more knowable it will be. Absolute form, God, will be the absolutely knowable. That the Absolute is what alone is completely knowable, intelligible, and comprehensible, and the finite and material comparatively unknowable, is a point of view essential to idealism, and stands in marked contrast to the popular idea of rationalism that the Absolute is unknowable, and matter knowable. For idealism, the Absolute is reason, thought. What can be more thoroughly intelligible than reason? What can thought understand, if not thought? This, of course, is not stated by Aristotle. But it is implied in his theory of sense-perception.

Within human consciousness, there are lower and higher levels, and Aristotle has gone to great lengths to identify these from the bottom to the top. These stages of consciousness are what we usually call "faculties." However, Aristotle points out that it's nonsense to refer to the "parts" of the soul, as Plato did. The soul, being a single indivisible entity, has no parts. They are different aspects of the activity of one and the same entity; different stages of its development. They cannot be separated any more than the convex and concave sides of a curve. The lowest faculty, if we must use that term, is sense perception. Now, what we perceive in an object are its qualities. Perception tells us that a piece of gold is {299} heavy, yellow, etc. The underlying substance that supports the qualities cannot be perceived. This means that the matter is unknowable, while the form is knowable, as the qualities are part of the form. Sense perception, therefore, occurs when the object impresses its form onto the soul. This is significant for what it implies rather than what it explicitly states. It reflects the deeply idealistic nature of Aristotle's thought. If the form is what can be known in something, then the more form there is, the more knowable it will be. Absolute form, or God, will be the completely knowable. The view that the Absolute is the only thing that is fully knowable, intelligible, and comprehensible, while the finite and material are relatively unknowable, is essential to idealism, and contrasts sharply with the popular view of rationalism that the Absolute is unknowable, and matter is knowable. For idealism, the Absolute is reason, thought. What could be more intelligible than reason? What can thought understand, if not thought itself? This is, of course, not directly stated by Aristotle, but it is implied in his theory of sense perception.

Next in the scale above the senses comes the common sense. This has nothing to do with what we understand by that phrase in every-day language. It means the central sensation-ganglion in which isolated sensations meet, are combined, and form a unity of experience. We saw, in considering Plato, that the simplest kind of knowledge, such as, "this paper is white," involves, not only isolated sensations, but their comparison and contrast. Bare sensations would not even make objects. For every object is a combined bundle of sensations. What thus combines the various sensations, and in {300} particular those received from different sense-organs, what compares and contrasts them, and turns them from a blind medley of phantasms into a definite experience, a single cosmos, is the common sense. Its organ is the heart.

Next in the hierarchy above the senses is common sense. This isn’t what we typically mean by that term in everyday conversation. It refers to the central sensation center where isolated sensations come together, combine, and create a unified experience. As we noted while discussing Plato, the simplest kind of knowledge, like “this paper is white,” involves not just isolated sensations but also their comparison and contrast. Bare sensations wouldn’t even constitute objects. Every object is a combined collection of sensations. What combines these various sensations, especially those from different sense organs, and what compares and contrasts them, transforming them from a chaotic mix of impressions into a clear experience, a single ordered reality, is common sense. Its organ is the heart.

Above the common sense is the faculty of imagination. By this Aristotle means, not the creative imagination of the artist, but the power, which everyone possesses, of forming mental images and pictures. This is due to the excitation in the sense-organ continuing after the object has ceased to affect it.

Above common sense is the ability to imagine. By this, Aristotle means not the artist's creative imagination, but the capacity that everyone has to form mental images and pictures. This happens because the stimulation in the sense organs continues even after the object is no longer affecting them.

The next faculty is memory. This is the same as imagination, except that there is combined with the image a recognition of it as a copy of a past sense-impression.

The next faculty is memory. This is similar to imagination, except that it includes a recognition of the image as a copy of a past sensory experience.

Recollection, again, is higher than memory. Memory images drift purposelessly through the mind. Recollection is the deliberate evoking of memory-images.

Recollection, once more, is greater than memory. Memory images float aimlessly through the mind. Recollection is the intentional bringing up of memory images.

From recollection we pass to the specifically human faculty of reason. But reason itself has two grades. The lower is called passive reason, the higher active reason. The mind has the power of thought before it actually thinks. This latent capacity is passive reason. The mind is here like a smooth piece of wax which has the power to receive writing, but has not received it. The positive activity of thought itself is active reason. The comparison with wax must not mislead us into supposing that the soul only receives its impressions from sensation. It is pure thought which writes upon the wax.

From memory, we move to the distinctly human ability of reason. But reason comes in two levels. The lower level is known as passive reason, while the higher level is active reason. The mind has the ability to think even before it actually engages in thought. This dormant ability is what we call passive reason. The mind here is like a smooth piece of wax that can take on writing but hasn’t yet done so. The actual process of thinking is active reason. The comparison to wax shouldn't mislead us into thinking that the soul only gets its impressions from sensory experiences. It is pure thought that inscribes upon the wax.

Now the sum of the faculties in general we call the soul. And the soul, we saw, is simply the organization {301} or form, of the body. As form is inseparable from matter, the soul cannot exist without the body. It is the function of the body. It is to the body what sight is to the eye. And in the same sense Aristotle denies the doctrine of Pythagoras and Plato that the soul reincarnates itself in new bodies, particularly in the bodies of animals. What is the function of one thing cannot become the function of another. Exactly what the soul is to the body the music of the flute is to the flute itself. It is the form of which the flute is the matter. It is, to speak metaphorically, the soul of the flute. And you might as well talk, says Aristotle, of the art of flute-playing becoming reincarnate in the blacksmith's anvil, as of the soul passing into another body. This would seem also to preclude any doctrine of immortality. For the function perishes with the thing. We shall return to that point in a moment. But we may note, meanwhile, that Aristotle's theory of the soul is not only a great advance upon Plato's, but is a great advance upon popular thinking of the present day. The ordinary view of the soul, which was Plato's view, is that the soul is a sort of thing. No doubt it is non-material and supersensuous. But still it is a thing; it can be put into a body and taken out of it, as wine can be put into or taken out of a bottle. The connection between body and soul is thus purely mechanical. They are attached to each other by no necessary bond, but rather by force. They have, in their own natures, no connexion with each other, and it is difficult to see why the soul ever entered a body, if it is in its nature something quite separate. But Aristotle's view is that the soul, as form of the body, is not separable from it. You cannot have {302} a soul without a body. The connection between them is not mechanical, but organic. The soul is not a thing which comes into the body and goes out of it. It is not a thing at all. It is a function.

Now the total set of faculties in general is what we call the soul. And the soul, as we observed, is simply the organization {301} or form of the body. Just as form cannot be separated from matter, the soul cannot exist without the body. It acts as a function of the body. It is to the body what sight is to the eye. In the same way, Aristotle rejects the beliefs of Pythagoras and Plato that the soul can reincarnate in new bodies, particularly in the bodies of animals. What one thing does cannot become the function of another. Just as the soul relates to the body, the music of the flute relates to the flute itself. It is the form that the flute takes. To put it metaphorically, it is the soul of the flute. And Aristotle argues that talking about the art of flute-playing taking on new life in a blacksmith's anvil is as nonsensical as saying the soul moves into another body. This perspective also seems to rule out any idea of immortality because the function dies with the thing. We will revisit that point shortly. However, it's worth mentioning that Aristotle's theory of the soul represents not only a significant improvement over Plato's, but it also advances beyond the common understanding of today. The typical view of the soul, which mirrors Plato's perspective, is that the soul is some kind of entity. While it's certainly non-material and beyond sensory perception, it is still seen as an object that can be placed in or removed from a body, much like wine can be poured into or out of a bottle. This implies a purely mechanical connection between body and soul. They are bonded by force, not by any essential link. In their core nature, they have no relation to each other, making it hard to understand why a soul would enter a body if it is inherently something completely separate. Conversely, Aristotle believes that the soul, as the form of the body, is inseparable from it. You can't have {302} a soul without a body. The relationship between them is not mechanical but organic. The soul is not something that comes into the body and leaves it. It is not a thing at all. It is a function.

But to this doctrine Aristotle makes an exception in favour of the active reason. All the lower faculties perish with the body, including the passive reason. Active reason is imperishable and eternal. It has neither beginning nor end. It comes into the body from without, and departs from it at death. God being absolute reason, man's reason comes from God, and returns to him, after the body ceases to function. But before we hail this as a doctrine of personal immortality, we had best reflect. All the lower faculties perish at death, and this includes memory. Now memory is an essential of personality. Without memory our experiences would be a succession of isolated sensations, with no connecting link. What connects my last with my present experience is that my last experience was "mine." To be mine it must be remembered. Memory is the string upon which isolated experiences are strung together, and which makes them into that unity I call myself, my personality. If memory perishes, there can be no personal life. And it must be remembered that Aristotle does not mean merely that, in that future life--if we persist in calling it such--the memory of this life is obliterated. He means that in the future life itself reason has no memory of itself from moment to moment. We cannot be dogmatic about what Aristotle himself thought. He seems to avoid the question. He probably shrank from disturbing popular beliefs on the subject. We have, at any rate, no definite pronouncement from {303} him. All we can say is that his doctrine does not provide the material for belief in personal immortality. It expressly removes the material in that it denies the persistence of memory. Moreover, if Aristotle really thought that reason is a thing, which goes in and out of the body, an exception, in the literal sense, to his general doctrine of soul, all we can say is that he undergoes a sudden drop in the philosophic scale. Having propounded so advanced a theory, he sinks back to the crude view of Plato. And as this is not likely, the most probable explanation is that he is here speaking figuratively, perhaps with the intention of propitiating the religious and avoiding any rude disturbance of popular belief. If so, the statements that active reason is immortal, comes from God, and returns to God, mean simply that the world-reason is eternal, and that man's reason is the actualization of this eternal reason, and in that sense "comes from God" and returns to Him. We may add, too, that since God, though real, is not to be regarded as an existent individual, our return to Him cannot be thought as a continuation of individual existence. Personal immortality is inconsistent with the fundamentals of Aristotle's system. We ought not to suppose that he contradicted himself in this way. Yet if Aristotle used language which seems to imply personal immortality, this is neither meaningless nor dishonest. It is as true for him as for others that the soul is eternal. But eternal does not mean everlasting in time. It means timeless. And reason, even our reason, is timeless. The soul has eternity in it. It is "eternity in an hour." And it is this which puts the difference between man and the brutes.

But Aristotle makes an exception to this idea for active reason. All the lower faculties die with the body, including passive reason. Active reason is imperishable and eternal; it has no beginning or end. It enters the body from outside and leaves at death. Since God is absolute reason, human reason comes from God and returns to Him once the body stops functioning. However, before we consider this a doctrine of personal immortality, we should think it over. All the lower faculties die at death, including memory. And memory is essential to personality. Without memory, our experiences would just be a series of unrelated sensations with no connection. What ties my last experience to my current one is that my previous experience was "mine." For it to be mine, I have to remember it. Memory is the thread that weaves together isolated experiences, creating the unity I call my identity, my personality. If memory dies, there can't be any personal life. It’s important to note that Aristotle doesn’t just mean that the memory of this life is lost in some future existence—if we still want to call it that. He means that in that future state, reason has no memory of itself from moment to moment. We can’t be sure what Aristotle personally believed; he seems to sidestep the issue and likely avoided challenging popular beliefs. In any case, we don’t have a clear statement from him. What we can infer is that his doctrine doesn’t support the belief in personal immortality. It explicitly removes the basis for that belief by denying the continuity of memory. Furthermore, if Aristotle actually thought of reason as something that enters and exits the body, as a literal exception to his overall theory of the soul, that would be a significant fall in his philosophical standing. After presenting such an advanced theory, he would regress to the primitive view of Plato. Since that seems unlikely, a more plausible interpretation is that he is speaking metaphorically, possibly to appease religious views and avoid upsetting popular beliefs. If that’s the case, when he says that active reason is immortal, comes from God, and returns to God, he simply means that universal reason is eternal and that human reason is the manifestation of this eternal reason, which in that sense "comes from God" and returns to Him. We should also note that since God, although real, shouldn’t be considered a personal individual, our return to Him can’t be seen as a continuation of individual existence. Personal immortality doesn’t align with the core principles of Aristotle’s philosophy. We shouldn’t assume he contradicted himself in this manner. Yet if he used language that hints at personal immortality, it’s neither meaningless nor dishonest. It’s just as true for him as for anyone else that the soul is eternal. But eternal doesn’t mean everlasting in time; it means timeless. Our reason, including our own reason, is timeless. The soul contains eternity within it; it is "eternity in an hour." And this is what distinguishes humans from animals.

We have traced the scale of being from inorganic matter, through plants and animals, to man. What then? What is the next step? Or does the scale stop there? Now there is a sort of break in Aristotle's system at this point, which has led many to say that man is the top of the scale. The rest of Aristotle's physics deal with what is outside our earth, such as the stars and planets. And they deal with them quite as if they were a different subject, having little or nothing to do with the terrestrial scale of being which we have been considering. But here we must not forget two facts. The first is that Aristotle's writings have come down to us mutilated, and in many cases unfinished. The second is that Aristotle had a curious habit of writing separate monographs on different parts of his system, and omitting to point out any connexion between them, although such a connexion undoubtedly exists.

We have followed the progression of existence from lifeless matter, through plants and animals, to humans. So, what's next? Is this where the progression ends? At this point, there's a kind of gap in Aristotle's system, which has led many to claim that humans are at the top of the hierarchy. The rest of Aristotle's physics focuses on what’s beyond our planet, like the stars and planets. He treats these as if they’re a separate topic, not really connected to the earthly hierarchy we've been discussing. However, we must keep in mind two important facts. First, Aristotle's writings have come to us incomplete and in many cases unfinished. Second, Aristotle had a peculiar tendency to write separate essays on various parts of his system without indicating any connection between them, although such a connection definitely exists.

Now although Aristotle himself does not say it, there are several good reasons for thinking that the true interpretation of his meaning is that the scale of being does not stop at man, that there is no gap in the chain here, but that it proceeds from man through planets and stars--which Aristotle, like Plato, regarded as divine beings--right up to God himself. In the first place, this is required by the logic of his system. The scale has formless matter at the bottom and matterless form at the top. It should proceed direct from one to the other. It is essential to his philosophy that the universe is a single continuous chain. There is no place for such a hiatus between man and the higher beings. Secondly, it is not as if terrestrial life formed a scale, and celestial beings were all on a par, having among themselves no {305} scale of higher and lower. This is not the case. The heavenly bodies have grades among themselves. The higher are related to the lower as form to matter. Thus stars are higher than planets. So that if we suppose that evolution stops at man, what we have is a gap in the middle, a scale below it, and a scale above it. It is like a bridge over a sheet of water, the two ends of which are intact, but which is broken down in the middle. The natural completion of this scheme involves the filling up of the gap. Thirdly, we have another very important piece of evidence. With his valuable idea of evolution Aristotle combined another very curious, and no doubt, absurd, theory. This was that in the scale of the universe the lowest existence is to be found in the middle, the highest at the periphery, and that in general the higher is always outside the lower, so that the spatial universe is a system of concentric spheres, the outer sphere being related to the inner sphere as higher to lower, as form to matter. At the centre of the spherical universe is our earth. Earth, as the lowest element, is in the middle. Then comes a layer of water, then of air, then of fire. Among the heavenly bodies there are fifty-six spheres. The stars are outside the planets and are therefore higher beings. And in conformity with this scheme, the supreme being, God, is outside the outermost sphere. Now it is obvious that, in this scheme, the passage from the centre of the earth to the stars forms a spatial continuity, and it is impossible to resist the conclusion that it also forms a logical continuity, that is, that there is no break in the chain of evolution.

Although Aristotle himself doesn't state it explicitly, there are several strong reasons to believe that the true interpretation of his meaning indicates that the scale of being doesn’t stop at humanity. There’s no gap in that chain; it continues from humans through planets and stars—which Aristotle, like Plato, considered divine beings—right up to God himself. Firstly, this is required by the logic of his system. The scale starts with formless matter at the bottom and matterless form at the top. It should flow directly from one to the other. It’s essential to his philosophy that the universe is a single, continuous chain. There's no room for a break between humans and higher beings. Secondly, it’s not like terrestrial life forms a scale while celestial beings are all equal, lacking a hierarchy among them. That’s not the case. The heavenly bodies have their own levels. The higher are related to the lower as form is to matter. Thus, stars are higher than planets. So, if we assume that evolution stops at humans, we end up with a gap in the middle, a scale below it, and a scale above it. It’s like a bridge over a body of water, with both ends intact but a break in the middle. The natural completion of this structure involves filling that gap. Thirdly, we have another significant piece of evidence. Along with his valuable idea of evolution, Aristotle combined another peculiar, and arguably absurd, theory. This was that in the scale of the universe, the lowest existence is found in the center, the highest at the edges, and generally, the higher is always outside the lower, making the spatial universe a system of concentric spheres. The outer sphere relates to the inner sphere as higher to lower, as form to matter. At the center of this spherical universe lies our Earth. Earth, as the lowest element, is at the center. Then comes a layer of water, followed by air, and then fire. Among the celestial bodies, there are fifty-six spheres. The stars are outside the planets, thus occupying a higher status. In accordance with this structure, the supreme being, God, resides outside the outermost sphere. It’s evident that, within this framework, the transition from the center of the Earth to the stars creates a spatial continuity, and it’s impossible to deny that it also creates a logical continuity, meaning there’s no break in the evolutionary chain.

Noting that this is not what Aristotle in so many words says, but that it is our interpretation of his {306} intention, which is almost certainly correct, we conclude that man is not the top of the scale. Next to him come the heavenly bodies. The planets include the sun and the moon, which, revolve round the earth in a direction opposite to that of the stars. Next in the scale come the stars. We need not go into details of the fifty-six spheres. The stars and planets are divine beings. But this is only a comparative term. Man, as the possessor of reason, is also divine, but the heavenly bodies infinitely more so. And this means that they are more rational than man, and so higher in the scale. They live an absolutely blessed and perfect life. They are immortal and eternal, because they are the supreme self-realization of the eternal reason. It is only upon this earth that death and corruption occur, a circumstance which has no doubt emphasized that view of Aristotle's philosophy which holds the gap between man and the stars to be a real one. The heavenly bodies are not composed of the four elements, but of a fifth, a quintessence, which is called ether. Like all elements it must have its natural motion. And as it is the finest and most perfect, its motion must be perfect. And it must be an eternal motion, because the stars are eternal beings. It cannot be motion in a straight line, because that never comes to an end, and so is never perfect. Circular motion alone is perfect. And it is eternal because its end and its beginning are one. Hence the natural motion of ether is circular, and the stars move in perfect circles.

Noting that this is not exactly what Aristotle says, but rather our interpretation of his {306} intention, which is probably correct, we conclude that humans are not at the top of the scale. Next to us are the heavenly bodies. The planets, including the sun and the moon, revolve around the earth in a direction opposite to the stars. Next on the scale are the stars. We don’t need to get into the details of the fifty-six spheres. The stars and planets are divine beings, but this is just a comparative term. Humans, being rational, are also divine, but the heavenly bodies are infinitely more so. This means they are more rational than humans and thus higher on the scale. They exist in a completely blessed and perfect life. They are immortal and eternal because they represent the ultimate realization of eternal reason. Only on this earth do death and decay occur, which likely emphasizes Aristotle's view that the gap between man and the stars is a real one. The heavenly bodies are not made up of the four elements but of a fifth, a quintessence known as ether. Like all elements, it must have its natural motion. Being the finest and most perfect, its motion must also be perfect. It must be an eternal motion since the stars are eternal beings. It cannot be linear motion because that never ends, and therefore is never perfect. Only circular motion is perfect. It is eternal because its beginning and end are the same. Thus, the natural motion of ether is circular, and the stars move in perfect circles.

Leaving the stars behind, we reach the summit of the long ladder from matter to form. This is the absolute form, God. As formless matter is not an existent thing, nor is matterless form. God, therefore, is not in the {307} world of space and time at all. But it is one of the curiosities of thought that Aristotle nevertheless gives him a place outside the outermost sphere. What is outside the sphere is, therefore, not space. All space and time are inside this globular universe. Space is therefore finite. And God must be outside the outermost sphere because he is the highest being, and the higher always comes outside the lower.

Leaving the stars behind, we reach the peak of the long ladder from matter to form. This is the absolute form, God. Just as formless matter isn't a real thing, matterless form isn't either. So, God isn't part of the {307} world of space and time at all. However, it's curious that Aristotle still gives Him a place outside the outermost sphere. What lies outside the sphere is not space. All space and time exist within this spherical universe. Therefore, space is finite. God must be outside the outermost sphere because He is the highest being, and the higher always exists outside the lower.

We have now described the entire scale of evolution. Looking back upon it, we can see its inner significance. The Absolute is reason, matterless form. Everything in the world, therefore, is, in its essence, reason. If we wish to know the essential nature even of this clod of earth, the answer is that it is reason, although this view is not consistently developed by Aristotle, since he allows that matter is a separate principle which cannot be reduced to form. The whole universal process of things is nothing but the struggle of reason to express itself, to actualize itself, to become existent in the world. This it definitely does, for the first time proximately in man, and completely in the stars. It can only express itself in lower beings as sensation (animals), as nutrition (plants), or as gravitation and its opposite (inorganic matter).

We have now described the entire spectrum of evolution. Looking back at it, we can see its deeper meaning. The Absolute is reason, a form without matter. Therefore, everything in the world is, at its core, reason. If we want to understand the essential nature of even this lump of earth, the answer is that it is reason, even though Aristotle doesn’t fully develop this idea, as he believes that matter is a separate principle that can't be reduced to form. The whole universal process of things is nothing but the struggle of reason to express itself, to make itself real, to exist in the world. It accomplishes this for the first time, in a direct way, in humans, and fully in the stars. It can only express itself in lower beings as sensation (in animals), as nourishment (in plants), or as gravity and its opposite (inorganic matter).

The value of Aristotle's theory of evolution is immense. It is not the details that signify. The application of the principle in the world of matter and life could not be carried out satisfactorily in the then state of physical science. It could not be carried out with perfection even now. Omniscience alone could give finality to such a scheme. But it is the principle itself which matters. And that it is one of the most valuable conceptions in {308} philosophy will perhaps be more evident if we compare it, firstly, with modern scientific theories of evolution and secondly, with certain aspects of Hindu pantheism.

The value of Aristotle's theory of evolution is huge. It's not the specifics that are important. The application of the principle in the physical and biological world couldn't be done well at the time due to the state of physical science. It still can't be done perfectly today. Only complete knowledge could finalize such a concept. But what's important is the principle itself. It’s one of the most valuable ideas in {308} philosophy, which will likely become more obvious when we compare it, first, with modern scientific theories of evolution and second, with some aspects of Hindu pantheism.

What has Aristotle in common with such a writer a Herbert Spencer? According to Spencer, evolution is a movement from the indefinite, incoherent, and homogeneous, to the definite, coherent, and heterogeneous. Aristotle has all this, though his words are different. He calls it a movement from matter to form. Form he describes as whatever gives definiteness to a thing. Matter is the indefinite substrate, form gives it definiteness. Hence for him too the higher being is more definite because it has more form. That matter is the homogeneous, form the heterogeneous, follows from this. We saw that there are in matter itself no differences, because there are no qualities. And this is the same as saying it is homogeneous. Heterogeneity, that is, differentiation, is introduced by form. Coherence is the same thing as organization. Aristotle has himself defined the form of a thing as its organization. For him, as for Spencer, the higher being is simply that which is more organized. Every theory of evolution depends fundamentally upon the idea of organism. Aristotle invented the idea and the word. Spencer carried it no further, though the more advanced physical knowledge of his day enabled him to illustrate it more copiously.

What does Aristotle have in common with a writer like Herbert Spencer? According to Spencer, evolution involves a shift from the vague, chaotic, and uniform to the clear, structured, and diverse. Aristotle expresses this idea differently but covers the same ground. He describes it as a transition from matter to form. He defines form as anything that gives clarity to a thing. Matter is the vague base, while form provides it with clarity. So for him too, a higher being is more defined because it has more form. This means that matter is uniform while form introduces diversity. We observed that matter itself has no differences because it lacks qualities, which is the same as saying it is uniform. Diversity, or differentiation, is brought about by form. Coherence is synonymous with organization. Aristotle himself defined the form of a thing as its organization. For both him and Spencer, a higher being is simply one that is more organized. Every theory of evolution fundamentally relies on the concept of the organism. Aristotle came up with both the idea and the term. Spencer didn’t develop it further, but the advanced physical knowledge of his time allowed him to illustrate it more thoroughly.

But of course the great difference between Aristotle and the moderns, is that the former did not guess, what the latter have discovered, namely that evolution is not only a logical development, but is a fact in time. Aristotle knew what was meant by the higher and lower organism as well as Darwin, but he did not know, that the latter {309} actually turns into the former in the course of years. But this, though the most obvious, is not really the most important difference between Spencer and Aristotle. The real difference is that Aristotle penetrated far more deeply into the philosophy of evolution than modern science does; that, in fact, modern science has no philosophy of evolution at all. For the fundamental problem here is, if we speak of higher and lower beings, what rational ground have we for calling them higher and lower? That the lower passes in time into the higher is no doubt a very interesting fact to discover, but it dwindles into insignificance beside the problem just indicated, because, on the solution of that problem it depends whether the universe is to be regarded as futile, meaningless, and irrational, or whether we are to see in it order, plan, and purpose. Is Spencer's doctrine a theory of development at all? Or is it not rather simply a theory of change? Something resembling an ape becomes a man. Is there development here, that is, is it a movement from something really lower to something really higher? Or is it merely change from one indifferent thing to another? Is there improvement, or only difference? In the latter case, it makes not the slightest difference whether the ape becomes man, or man becomes an ape. The one is as good as the other. In either case, it is merely a change from Tweedledum to Tweedledee. The change is meaningless, and has no significance.

But of course, the big difference between Aristotle and modern thinkers is that Aristotle didn’t guess what they’ve discovered: that evolution is not just a logical development but also a real event over time. Aristotle understood the concept of higher and lower organisms just as well as Darwin did, but he didn’t realize that the latter {309} actually evolves into the former over the years. However, even though this is quite obvious, it’s not the most important difference between Spencer and Aristotle. The real difference is that Aristotle had a much deeper understanding of the philosophy of evolution than modern science does; in fact, modern science lacks any real philosophy of evolution. The fundamental issue here is, when we talk about higher and lower beings, what rational basis do we have for calling them higher and lower? While it's certainly interesting that the lower can evolve into the higher over time, this pales in comparison to the problem mentioned earlier, because the answer to that problem determines whether we view the universe as pointless, meaningless, and irrational, or whether we see it as orderly, purposeful, and meaningful. Is Spencer's theory even a theory of development? Or is it just a theory of change? Something akin to an ape becomes a man. Is there real development here, meaning a progression from something genuinely lower to something genuinely higher? Or is it merely a shift from one indifferent state to another? Is there actually an improvement, or just a difference? If it’s the latter, it doesn’t matter at all whether the ape evolves into a man or the man devolves into an ape. Both are equally valid. In either case, it’s simply a transition from Tweedledum to Tweedledee. The change is meaningless and holds no significance.

The modern doctrine of evolution can only render the world more intelligible, can only develop into a philosophy of evolution, by showing that there is evolution and not merely change, and this it can only do by {310} giving a rational basis for the belief that some forms of existence are higher than others. To put the matter bluntly, why is a man higher than a horse, or a horse than a sponge? Answer that, and you have a philosophy of evolution. Fail to answer it, and you have none. Now the man in the street will say that man is higher than the horse, because he not merely eats grass, but thinks, deliberates, possesses art, science, religion, morality. Ask him why these things are higher than eating grass, and he has no answer. From him, then, we turn to Spencer, and there we find a sort of answer. Man is higher because he is more organized. But why is it better to be more organized? Science, as such, has no answer. If pressed in this way, science may of course turn round and say: "there is in the reality of things no higher and no lower; what I mean by higher and lower is simply more and less organized; higher and lower are mere metaphors; they are the human way of looking at things; we naturally call higher what is nearest ourselves; but from the absolute point of view there is no higher and lower." But this is to reduce the universe to a madhouse. It means that there is no purpose, no reason, in anything that happens. The universe, in this case, is irrational. No explanation of it is possible. Philosophy is futile, and not only philosophy, but morality and everything else. If there is really no higher and lower, there is no better and no worse. It is just as good to be a murderer as to be a saint. Evil is the same as good. Instead of striving to be saints, statesmen, philosophers, we may as well go and play marbles, because all these values of higher and lower are mere delusions, "the human way of looking at things."

The modern idea of evolution can only make the world clearer and develop into a philosophy of evolution by proving that there is evolution and not just change. It can only do this by {310} providing a logical reason to believe that some forms of existence are superior to others. To be straightforward, why is a human being considered higher than a horse, or a horse higher than a sponge? If you can answer that, you have a philosophy of evolution. If you can't, then you have none. The average person might say that humans are higher than horses because we don't just eat grass; we think, deliberate, and have art, science, religion, and morality. But if you ask why these things are better than eating grass, they have no answer. So, we turn to Spencer, where we find a sort of answer. Humans are higher because they are more organized. But why is it better to be more organized? Science itself doesn't really have an answer. If pressed on this, science might retort that “in the reality of things, there’s no higher or lower; when I say higher or lower, I simply mean more or less organized; higher and lower are just metaphors; they represent the human perspective; we naturally refer to what is closest to us as higher; but from an absolute perspective, there’s no higher or lower.” But this reasoning reduces the universe to chaos, suggesting there is no purpose or reason in anything that occurs. In this view, the universe is irrational, and no explanation for it is possible. Philosophy becomes pointless, and so do morality and everything else. If there’s truly no higher and lower, then there’s no better or worse. Being a murderer is just as acceptable as being a saint. Evil is the same as good. Instead of aiming to be saints, statesmen, or philosophers, we might as well just play marbles, because all these values of higher and lower are mere illusions, "the human way of looking at things."

Spencer then has no answer to the question why it is better to be more organized. So we turn at last to Aristotle. He has an answer. He sees that it is meaningless to talk of development, advance, higher and lower, except in relation to an end. There is no such thing as advance unless it is an advance towards something. A body moving purposelessly in a straight line through infinite space does not advance. It might as well be here as a mile hence. In either case it is no nearer to anything. But if it is moving towards a definite point, we can call this advance. Every mile it moves it gets nearer to its end. So, if we are to have a philosophy of evolution, it must be teleological. If nature is not advancing towards an end, there is no nearer and further, no higher and lower, no development. What then is the end? It is the actualization of reason, says Aristotle. The primal being is eternal reason, but this is not existent. It must come to exist. It first enunciates itself vaguely as gravitation. But this is far off from its end, which is the existence of reason, as such, in the world. It comes nearer in plants and animals. It is proximately reached in man, for man is the existent reason. But there is no question of the universe coming to a stop, when it reaches its end--(the usual objection to teleology). For the absolute end, absolute form, can never be reached. The higher is thus the more rational, the lower the less rational. Now if we try to go on asking, "why is it better to be more rational?" we find we cannot ask such a question. The word "why" means that we want a reason. And our question is absurd because we are asking a reason for reason. Why is it better to be rational means simply, "how is reason rational." To {312} doubt it is a self-contradiction. Or, to put the same thing in another way, reason is the Absolute. And to ask why it is better to be rational is to demand that the ultimate should be expressed in terms of something beyond it. Hence modern science has no philosophy of evolution, whereas Aristotle has. [Footnote 16]

Spencer doesn't have an answer to why being more organized is better. So, let's consider Aristotle. He provides an answer. He argues that it's pointless to discuss development, progress, or concepts of higher and lower without referring to a purpose. There’s no real progress unless it's progress toward something. A body moving aimlessly in a straight line through infinite space doesn't actually advance. It could be here or a mile away; in either situation, it's not closer to anything. However, if it's heading toward a specific destination, we can call that progress. Every mile it travels brings it closer to its goal. Therefore, if we want a philosophy of evolution, it must be teleological. If nature isn't progressing toward an end, there’s no concept of moving closer or further away, no higher or lower, no development. So, what is the end? It’s the realization of reason, according to Aristotle. The primal being is eternal reason, but it doesn’t exist yet. It needs to come into existence. It first expresses itself vaguely as gravitation. But that’s far from its ultimate goal, which is the existence of reason in the world. It gets closer in plants and animals. It’s directly achieved in humans, who embody reason. However, the universe won’t come to a halt once it reaches its end—this is the common objection to teleology. The absolute end, or absolute form, can never fully be attained. The higher corresponds to more rationality, and the lower to less rationality. Now, if we continue to ask, "why is it better to be more rational?" we find that the question doesn't make sense. The term "why" implies we want a reason. Our question is absurd because we’re seeking a reason for reason. Asking why it’s better to be rational essentially asks, "how is reason rational." To doubt this is self-contradictory. Alternatively, reason is the Absolute, and asking why it's better to be rational requires expressing the ultimate in terms of something beyond it. As a result, modern science lacks a philosophy of evolution, while Aristotle provides one. [Footnote 16]

[Footnote 16: See H. S. Macran's Hegel's Doctrine of Formal Logic (Clarendon Press), Introduction, section on the Conception of Evolution, to which I am much indebted in the above paragraphs.]

[Footnote 16: See H. S. Macran's Hegel's Doctrine of Formal Logic (Clarendon Press), Introduction, section on the Conception of Evolution, to which I am much indebted in the above paragraphs.]

The main idea of pantheism is that everything is God. The clod of earth is divine because it is a manifestation of Deity. Now this idea is all very well, and is in fact essential to philosophy. We find it in Aristotle himself, since the entire world is, for him, the actualization of reason, and reason is God. But this is also a very dangerous idea, if not supplemented by a rationally grounded scale of values. No doubt everything is, in a sense, God. But if we leave it at this, it would follow that, since everything is equally divine, there is no higher and lower. If the clod of earth, like the saintliest man, is God, and there is no more to say of the matter, then how is the saint higher than the clod of earth? Why should one ever struggle towards higher things, when in reality all are equally high? Why avoid evil, when evil is as much a manifestation of God as good? Mere pantheism must necessarily end in this calamitous view. And these deplorable effects explain the fact that Hinduism, with all its high thinking, finds room for the worship of cows and snakes, and, with all its undoubted moral elevation, yet allows into its fold the grossest abominations. Both these features are due to the pantheistic placing of all things on a par as equally {313} divine. Not of course that Hinduism has not a sort of doctrine of evolution, a belief in a higher and lower. As everyone knows, it admits the belief that in successive incarnations the soul may mount higher and higher till it perhaps rejoins the common source of all things. There is probably no race of man so savage that it does not instinctively feel that there is a higher and lower, a better and worse, in things. But the point is that, although Hinduism has its scale of values, and its doctrine of development, it has no rational foundation for these, and though it has the idea of higher and lower, yet, because this is without foundation, it lets it slip, it never grips the idea, and so easily slides into the view that all is equally divine. The thought that all is God, and the thought that there are higher and lower beings, are, on the surface, opposed and inconsistent theories. Yet both are necessary, and it is the business of philosophy to find a reconciliation. This Aristotle does, but Hinduism fails to do. It asserts both, but fails to bring them to unity. Now it asserts one view, and again at another time it asserts the other. And this, of course, is connected with the general defect of oriental thinking, its vagueness. Everything is seen, but seen in a haze, in which all things appear one, in which shapes flow into another, in which nothing has an outline, in which even vital distinctions are obliterated. Hence it is that, though oriental thought contains, in one way or another, practically all philosophical ideas, it grips none, and can hold nothing fast. It seizes its object, but its flabby grasp relaxes and slips off. Hinduism, like modern science, has its doctrine of evolution. But it has no philosophy of evolution.

The main idea of pantheism is that everything is God. A piece of dirt is divine because it reflects the divine. This idea is valid and is actually crucial to philosophy. We can see it in Aristotle, who believed the entire world is the actualization of reason, and that reason is God. However, this idea is also very dangerous if it's not supported by a rational scale of values. Everything may be, in a sense, God, but if we stop there, it would imply that since everything is equally divine, there is no higher or lower. If a piece of dirt is just as much God as a saintly person, and there's nothing more to that, then how can we say one is better than the other? Why strive for higher goals when, in reality, everything is equally important? Why avoid evil when evil is just as much a part of God as good is? Simply embracing pantheism could lead to this troubling viewpoint. These unfortunate outcomes explain why Hinduism, with all its profound thinking, allows for the worship of cows and snakes and, despite its undeniable moral values, still incorporates some of the most appalling practices. Both of these aspects stem from a pantheistic view that places everything on the same level as equally ____ divine. It's important to note, though, that Hinduism does have a sort of doctrine of evolution, acknowledging a higher and lower. Everyone knows it includes the belief that through successive incarnations, the soul can rise higher and higher until it might reunite with the ultimate source of all things. There’s probably no human group so primitive that it doesn't instinctively sense a hierarchy of better and worse in the world. The issue is that while Hinduism does acknowledge a scale of values and has a concept of development, it lacks a rational foundation for these ideas. Even though it recognizes higher and lower, without a solid foundation, it tends to lose sight of the idea and easily slides into the belief that all is equally divine. The concept that all is God and the notion that there are higher and lower beings seem like fundamentally opposed theories. Yet both are necessary, and philosophy’s task is to reconcile them. Aristotle achieves this, but Hinduism does not. It claims both perspectives but fails to unify them. At one moment it emphasizes one viewpoint, and at another, it promotes the opposite. This inconsistency is linked to the general issue of eastern thought, which often lacks clarity. Everything is perceived, but seen through a fog where all things appear as one, shapes blur into each other, and vital distinctions vanish. Thus, while eastern thought includes nearly all philosophical ideas in one form or another, it doesn’t truly grasp any; it holds onto nothing firmly. It captures its subject, but then its weak grip slips away. Hinduism, like modern science, has a doctrine of evolution, but it doesn't offer a philosophy of evolution.


5. Ethics.

5. Ethics.

(a) The Individual.

(a) The Person.

A strong note of practical moderation pervades the ethics of Aristotle. While Plato's ethical teaching transcended the ordinary limits of human life, and so lost itself in ideal Utopias, Aristotle, on the other hand, sits down to make practical suggestions: He wishes to enquire what the good is, but by this he means, not some ideal good impossible of attainment upon this earth, but rather that good which, in all the circumstances in which men find themselves, ought to be realizable. The ethical theories of Plato and Aristotle are thus characteristic of the two men. Plato despised the world of sense, and sought to soar altogether beyond the common life of the senses. Aristotle, with his love of facts and of the concrete, keeps close within the bounds of actual human experience.

A strong sense of practical moderation runs through Aristotle's ethics. While Plato's ethical teachings went beyond the ordinary limits of human life and got lost in ideal Utopias, Aristotle aims to provide practical suggestions. He wants to explore what the good is, but he means not some ideal good that cannot be achieved on this earth, but rather the good that, in all the situations people find themselves in, should be attainable. The ethical theories of Plato and Aristotle reflect their distinct personalities. Plato looked down on the sensory world and aimed to rise above the ordinary life of the senses. In contrast, Aristotle, with his appreciation for facts and the concrete, stays grounded within the reality of human experience.

The first question for ethics is the nature of the summum bonum. We desire one thing for the sake of a second, we desire that for the sake of a third. But if this series of means and ends goes on ad infinitum, then all desire and all action are futile and purposeless. There must be some one thing which we desire, not for the sake of anything else, but on its own account. What is this end in itself, this summum bonum, at which all human activity ultimately aims. Everybody, says Aristotle, is agreed about the name of this end. It is happiness. What all men seek, what is the motive of all their actions, that which they desire for the sake of itself and nothing beyond, is happiness. But though all agree as to the name, beyond that there is no agreement. Philosophers, {315} no less than the vulgar, differ as to what this word happiness means. Some say it is a life of pleasure. Others say it consists in the renunciation of pleasures. Some recommend one life, some another.

The first question for ethics is what the summum bonum is. We want one thing for the sake of another, and we want that for the sake of a third. But if this endless chain of means and ends continues ad infinitum, then all desire and action are meaningless and pointless. There must be something we want, not for the sake of anything else, but for its own sake. What is this end in itself, this summum bonum, that all human activity ultimately aims for? Everyone, says Aristotle, agrees on the name of this end. It is happiness. What everyone seeks, what motivates all their actions, what they desire for its own sake and nothing beyond, is happiness. However, while everyone agrees on the name, there is no consensus beyond that. Philosophers, {315} no less than the general public, disagree on what this word happiness really means. Some say it's a life of pleasure. Others say it's about giving up pleasures. Some advocate one way of life, while others recommend another.

We must repeat here the warning which was found necessary in the case of Plato, who also called the summum bonum happiness. Aristotle's doctrine is no more to be confused with modern utilitarianism than is Plato's. Moral activity is usually accompanied by a subjective feeling of enjoyment. In modern times the word happiness connotes the feeling of enjoyment. But for the Greeks it was the moral activity which the word signified. For Aristotle an action is not good because it yields enjoyment. On the contrary, it yields enjoyment because it is good. The utilitarian doctrine is that the enjoyment is the ground of the moral value. But, for Aristotle, the enjoyment is the consequence of the moral value. Hence when he tells us that the highest good is happiness, he is giving us no information regarding its nature, but merely applying a new name to it. We have still to enquire what the nature of the good is. As he himself says, everyone agrees upon the name, but the real question is what this name connotes.

We need to reiterate the warning that was deemed necessary in the case of Plato, who also referred to the summum bonum as happiness. Aristotle's teachings should not be mixed up with modern utilitarianism any more than Plato's teachings. Moral actions are typically accompanied by a subjective feeling of enjoyment. Nowadays, the word happiness is associated with that feeling of enjoyment. However, for the Greeks, it represented the moral action itself. For Aristotle, an action isn't good simply because it brings enjoyment; rather, it brings enjoyment because it is good. The utilitarian view holds that enjoyment is the basis of moral value. But for Aristotle, enjoyment is the result of that moral value. Therefore, when he says that the highest good is happiness, he's not informing us about its nature but merely giving it a new label. We still need to determine what the nature of the good actually is. As he himself notes, everyone agrees on the name, but the real question is what this name implies.

Aristotle's solution of this problem follows from the general principles of his philosophy. We have seen that, throughout nature, every being has its proper end, and the attainment of this end is its special function. Hence the good for each being must be the adequate performance of its special function. The good for man will not consist in the pleasure of the senses. Sensation is the special function of animals, but not of man. Man's special function is reason. Hence the proper {316} activity of reason is the summum bonum, the good for man. Morality consists in the life of reason. But what precisely that means we have still to see.

Aristotle's solution to this problem comes from the basic principles of his philosophy. We've seen that in nature, every being has its proper purpose, and achieving this purpose is its unique function. Therefore, the good for each being is to adequately perform its specific function. For humans, the good isn't found in sensory pleasure. Sensation is the main function of animals, but not of humans. The unique function of humans is reason. Thus, the proper {316} activity of reason is the summum bonum, the good for humans. Morality is about living a life guided by reason. But we still need to clarify what that really means.

Man is not only a reasoning animal. As the higher being, he contains within himself the faculties of the lower beings also. Like plants he is appetitive, like animals, sensitive. The passions and appetites are an organic part of his nature. Hence virtue will be of two kinds. The highest virtues will be found in the life of reason, and the life of thought, philosophy. These intellectual virtues are called by Aristotle dianoetic. Secondly, the ethical virtues proper will consist in the submission of the passions and appetites to the control of reason. The dianoetic virtues are the higher, because in them man's special function alone is in operation, and also because the thinking man most resembles God, whose life is a life of pure thought.

Humans are not just thinking creatures. As superior beings, we also possess the abilities of lesser beings. Like plants, we have desires, and like animals, we are sensitive. Our passions and urges are an essential part of who we are. Therefore, there are two types of virtue. The highest virtues come from a life guided by reason and thought, which is philosophy. Aristotle refers to these intellectual virtues as dianoetic. Secondly, the ethical virtues involve regulating our passions and desires under the guidance of reason. The dianoetic virtues are considered higher because they engage our unique human function, and because the thoughtful person is most like God, whose existence is purely centered on thought.

Happiness, therefore, consists in the combination of dianoetic and ethical virtues. They alone are of absolute value to man. Yet, though he places happiness in virtue, Aristotle, in his broad and practical way, does not overlook the fact that external goods and circumstances have a profound influence upon happiness, and cannot be ignored, as the Cynics attempted to ignore them. Not that Aristotle regards externals as having any value in themselves. What alone is good in itself, is an end in itself, is virtue. But external goods help a man in his quest of virtue. Poverty, sickness, and misfortune, on the other hand, hinder his efforts. Therefore, though externals are not goods in themselves, they may be a means towards the good. Hence they are not to be despised and rejected. Riches, friends, health, {317} good fortune, are not happiness. But they are negative conditions of it. With them happiness is within our grasp. Without them its attainment is difficult. They will be valued accordingly.

Happiness, then, is found in the mix of intellectual and moral virtues. These are the only things that truly matter to people. However, even though happiness is linked to virtue, Aristotle realistically acknowledges that external factors and circumstances significantly affect happiness, and they shouldn’t be dismissed like the Cynics tried to do. Aristotle doesn’t see external things as having value on their own. What is truly good in itself, what is an end in itself, is virtue. But external goods assist a person in pursuing virtue. Conversely, poverty, illness, and bad luck make that pursuit harder. So, while external factors aren’t good in and of themselves, they can be a means to achieve goodness. Therefore, they shouldn’t be looked down upon or dismissed. Wealth, friendships, health, {317} good fortune aren’t happiness, but they are necessary conditions for it. With them, happiness is within reach. Without them, achieving it is tough. They will be valued accordingly.

Aristotle says little in detail of the dianoetic virtues. And we may turn at once to the main subject of his moral system, the ethical virtues. These consist in the governance of the passions by reason. Socrates was wrong in supposing that virtue is purely intellectual, that nothing save knowledge is needed for it, and that if a man thinks right he must needs do right. He forgot the existence of the passions, which are not easily controlled. A man may reason perfectly, his reason may point him to the right path, but his passions may get the upper hand and lead him out of it. How then is reason to gain control over the appetites? Only by practice. It is only by continual effort, by the constant exercise of self-control, that the unruly passions can be tamed. Once brought under the yoke, their control becomes habit. Aristotle lays the utmost emphasis on the importance of habit in morality. It is only by cultivating good habits that a man becomes good.

Aristotle doesn’t go into much detail about the dianoetic virtues. So, let's focus on the main part of his moral system: the ethical virtues. These are about controlling our emotions through reason. Socrates was mistaken in thinking virtue is just about intellect, that knowledge alone is enough, and that if someone thinks the right way, they must act the right way. He overlooked the fact that emotions can be tough to manage. A person can reason perfectly and know the right path, but their emotions might take over and lead them astray. So, how does reason manage our desires? Only through practice. It takes consistent effort and ongoing self-control to tame our wild emotions. Once they are brought under control, managing them becomes a habit. Aristotle emphasizes how crucial habit is in morality. By developing good habits, a person becomes good.

Now if virtue consists in the control of the appetites by reason, it thus contains two constituents, reason and appetite. Both must be present. There must be passions, if they are to be controlled. Hence the ascetic ideal of rooting out the passions altogether is fundamentally wrong. It overlooks the fact that the higher form does not exclude the lower--that were contrary to the conception of evolution--it includes and transcends it. It forgets that the passions are an organic part of man, and that to destroy them is to do injury to his {318} nature by destroying one of its essential members. The passions and appetites are, in fact, the matter of virtue, reason its form, and the mistake of asceticism is that it destroys the matter of virtue, and supposes that the form can subsist by itself. Virtue means that the appetites must be brought under control, not that they must be eradicated. Hence there are two extremes to be avoided. It is extreme, on the one hand, to attempt to uproot the passions; and it is extreme, on the other, to allow them to run riot. Virtue means moderation. It consists in hitting the happy mean as regards the passions, in not allowing them to get the upper hand of reason, and yet in not being quite passionless and apathetic. From this follows the famous Aristotelian doctrine of virtue as the mean between two extremes. Every virtue lies between two vices, which are the excess and defect of appetite respectively.

Now, if virtue is about controlling our desires with reason, it involves two key elements: reason and desire. Both are necessary. There has to be passion for it to be controlled. So, the ascetic idea of completely eliminating passions is basically wrong. It misses the point that a higher form of life doesn’t exclude the lower; that would go against the idea of evolution—it includes and goes beyond it. It overlooks that passions are a natural part of being human, and destroying them harms our true nature by taking away something essential. Passions and desires are actually the substance of virtue, while reason provides its structure, and the error of asceticism is that it removes the substance of virtue and assumes the structure can exist on its own. Virtue means controlling desires, not wiping them out completely. Therefore, there are two extremes to avoid. On one hand, it’s extreme to try to eliminate passions; on the other, it’s extreme to let them run wild. Virtue is about moderation. It’s about finding a balance with our passions, keeping them in check without becoming completely devoid of feeling or indifferent. This leads to the well-known Aristotelian idea that virtue is the middle ground between two extremes. Every virtue lies between two vices, which are the excess and deficiency of desire, respectively.

What is the criterion here? Who is to judge? How are we to know what is the proper mean in any matter? Mathematical analogies will not help us. It is not a case of drawing a straight line from one extreme to the other, and finding the middle point by bisection. And Aristotle refuses to lay down any rule of thumb in the matter. There is no golden rule by virtue of which we can tell where the proper mean is. It all depends on circumstances, and on the person involved. What is the proper mean in one case is not the proper mean in another. What is moderate for one man is immoderate for his neighbour. Hence the matter must be left to the good judgment of the individual. A sort of fine tact, good sense, is required to know the mean, which Aristotle calls "insight." This insight is both the cause and the {319} effect of virtue. It is the cause, because he who has it knows what he ought to do. It is the effect, because it is only developed by practice. Virtue renders virtue easy. Each time a man, by use of his insight, rightly decides upon the mean, it becomes easier for him to discriminate next time.

What’s the standard here? Who gets to decide? How can we figure out what the right balance is in any situation? Mathematical comparisons won’t help us. It's not just about drawing a straight line from one extreme to another and finding the midpoint. Aristotle doesn’t provide any simple rule for this. There isn’t a universal guideline that tells us where the right balance is. It all depends on the circumstances and the person involved. What’s considered balanced in one situation may not be in another. What feels moderate for one person could seem excessive to someone else. Therefore, it must be left to each individual's judgment. You need a certain sensitivity and common sense to understand the balance, which Aristotle refers to as "insight." This insight both causes and results from virtue. It’s a cause because a person with it knows what they should do. It’s an effect because it only develops through practice. Virtue makes it easier to act virtuously. Each time a person uses their insight to make the right choice about balance, it becomes easier for them to make that decision next time.

Aristotle attempts no systematic classification of the virtues, as Plato had done. This sort of schematism is contrary to the practical character of his thought. He sees that life is far too complex to be treated in this way. The proper mean is different in every different case, and therefore there are as many virtues as there are circumstances in life. His list of virtues, therefore, is not intended to be exhaustive. It is merely illustrative. Though the number of virtues is infinite, there are certain well-recognized kinds of good action, which are of such constant importance in life that they have received names. By the example of some of these virtues Aristotle illustrates his doctrine of the mean. For instance, courage is the mean between cowardice and rashness. That is to say, cowardice is the defect of boldness, rashness the excess, courage the reasonable medium. Munificence is the mean between pettiness and vulgar profusion, good temper between spiritlessness and irascibility, politeness between rudeness and obsequiousness, modesty between shamelessness and bashfulness, temperance between insensibility and intemperance.

Aristotle doesn't try to create a systematic classification of virtues like Plato did. This kind of categorization goes against the practical nature of his thinking. He understands that life is way too complicated to be simplified in that way. The right balance varies in every situation, so there are as many virtues as there are circumstances in life. His list of virtues isn't meant to be complete; it's just illustrative. While the number of virtues is infinite, there are certain types of good actions that are so consistently important in life that they have names. Through examples of some of these virtues, Aristotle explains his idea of the mean. For example, courage falls between cowardice and rashness. In other words, cowardice is a lack of boldness, rashness is too much boldness, and courage is the sensible middle ground. Munificence is the balance between pettiness and excessive generosity, good temper between being too spiritless and too irritable, politeness between rudeness and excessive flattery, modesty between being shameless and overly bashful, and temperance between insensitivity and overindulgence.

Justice hardly comes into the scheme; it is rather a virtue of the State than of the individual, and it has been thought by some that the book devoted to it in the "Ethics" has been misplaced. Justice is of two kinds, distributive and corrective. Its fundamental idea {320} is the assignment of advantages and disadvantages according to merit. Distributive justice assigns honours and rewards according to the worth of the individuals involved. Corrective justice has to do with punishment. If a man improperly obtains an advantage, things must be equalized by the imposition on him of a corresponding disadvantage. Justice, however, is a general principle, and no general principle is equal to the complexity of life. Special cases cannot be foreseen, The necessary adjustment of human relations arising from this cause is equity.

Justice rarely fits into the picture; it's more of a quality of the State than of the individual, and some believe that the section in the "Ethics" focused on it is misplaced. There are two types of justice: distributive and corrective. The main idea is the allocation of benefits and burdens based on merit. Distributive justice gives honors and rewards based on the value of the individuals involved. Corrective justice deals with punishment. If someone improperly gains an advantage, that needs to be balanced out by imposing a corresponding disadvantage on them. However, justice is a broad principle, and no broad principle can fully capture the complexity of life. Special cases can't always be predicted. The necessary adjustments in human relations that come from this complexity is equity.

Aristotle is a pronounced supporter of the freedom of the will. He censures Socrates because the latter's theory of virtue practically amounts to a denial of freedom. According to Socrates, whoever thinks right must necessarily do right. But this is equivalent to denying a man's power to choose evil. And if he cannot choose evil, he cannot choose good. For the right-thinking man does not do right voluntarily, but necessarily. Aristotle believed, on the contrary, that man has the choice of good and evil. The doctrine of Socrates makes all actions involuntary. But in Aristotle's opinion only actions performed under forcible compulsion are involuntary. Aristotle did not, however, consider the special difficulties in the theory of free will which in modern times have made it one of the most thorny of all philosophical problems. Hence his treatment of the subject is not of great value to us.

Aristotle is a strong advocate for free will. He criticizes Socrates because Socrates' theory of virtue essentially denies the concept of freedom. According to Socrates, if someone thinks correctly, they must inevitably act correctly. But this suggests that a person cannot choose to do wrong. If they can't choose wrong, they can't choose right either. A person who thinks correctly does right not out of choice, but out of necessity. Aristotle, on the other hand, believed that individuals have the ability to choose between good and evil. Socrates' view makes all actions involuntary. However, Aristotle contended that only actions performed under coercion are involuntary. Nonetheless, Aristotle did not address the specific challenges related to the theory of free will that have made it one of the most complicated philosophical issues in modern times. Therefore, his perspective on the subject isn't very useful to us.


(b) The State.

The State

Politics is not a separate subject from Ethics. It is merely another division of the same subject. And {321} this, not merely because politics is the ethics of the State as against the individual, but because the morality of the individual really finds its end in the State, and is impossible without it. Aristotle agrees with Plato that the object of the State is the virtue and happiness of the citizens, which are impossible except in the State. For man is a political animal by nature, as is proved by his possession of speech, which would be useless to any save a social being. And the phrase "by nature" means the same here as elsewhere in Aristotle. It means that the State is the end of the individual, and that activity in the State is part of man's essential function. The State, in fact, is the form, the individual, the matter. The State provides both an education in virtue and the necessary opportunities for its exercise. Without it man would not be man at all. He would be a savage animal.

Politics isn't a separate subject from Ethics. It's just another branch of the same topic. And {321} this, not only because politics is the ethics of the State in contrast to the individual, but also because an individual's morality truly culminates in the State and cannot exist without it. Aristotle agrees with Plato that the purpose of the State is the virtue and happiness of its citizens, which can only be achieved within the State. After all, man is a political animal by nature, as demonstrated by his ability to speak, which would be pointless for anyone who isn't social. The phrase "by nature" means the same here as it does elsewhere in Aristotle's work. It signifies that the State is the ultimate goal of the individual, and participating in the State is a fundamental aspect of human nature. The State is essentially the structure, while the individual is the substance. The State offers both education in virtue and the necessary chances to practice it. Without the State, a person wouldn't truly be human; they would be a wild animal.

The historical origin of the State Aristotle finds in the family. At first there is the individual. The individual gets himself a mate, and the family arises. The family, in Aristotle's opinion, includes the slaves: for, like Plato, he sees no wrong in the institution of slavery. A number of families, joining together, develop into a village community, and a number of village communities into a polis (city), or State. Beyond the city, of course, the Greek idea of the State did not extend.

The historical origin of the State, according to Aristotle, begins with the family. First, there’s the individual. The individual finds a partner, and then the family is formed. In Aristotle’s view, the family also includes slaves because, like Plato, he sees nothing wrong with slavery. Several families come together to form a village community, and multiple village communities evolve into a polis (city) or State. Beyond the city, however, the Greek concept of the State doesn’t extend.

Such then is the historical origin of the State. But it is of capital importance to understand that, in Aristotle's opinion, this question of historical origin has nothing on earth to do with the far more important question what the State essentially is. It is no mere mechanical aggregate of families and village communities, {322} The nature of the State is not explained in this way. For though the family is prior to the State in order of time, the State is prior to the family and to the individual in order of thought, and in reality. For the State is the end, and the end is always prior to that of which it is the end. The state as form is prior to the family as matter, and in the same way the family is prior to the individual. And as the explanation of things is only possible by teleology, it is the end which explains the beginning, it is the State which explains the family, and not vice versa.

This is the historical origin of the State. However, it's crucial to understand that, according to Aristotle, this question of historical origin is irrelevant compared to the much more important question of what the State fundamentally is. It’s not just a simple collection of families and village communities, {322} The nature of the State can’t be explained this way. Although the family comes before the State in terms of time, the State is conceptually and actually prior to the family and the individual. The State is the ultimate goal, and the goal always precedes what it aims at. The State as a form is prior to the family as a substance, and similarly, the family is prior to the individual. Since understanding things is only possible through their purpose, it’s the end that explains the beginning; it’s the State that explains the family, not the other way around.

The true nature of the State, therefore, is not that it is a mechanical sum of individuals, as a heap of sand is the sum of its grains. The State is a real organism, and the connexion of part to part is not mechanical, but organic. The State has a life of its own. And its members also have their own lives, which are included in the higher life of the State. All the parts of an organism are themselves organisms. And as the distinction between organic and inorganic is that the former has its end in itself, while the latter has its end external to it, this means that the State is an end in itself, that the individual is an end in himself, and that the former end includes the latter. Or we may express the same thought otherwise by saying that, in the State, both the whole and the parts are to be regarded as real, both having their own lives and, in their character as ends, their own rights. Consequently, there are two kinds of views of the nature of the State, which are, according to Aristotle, fundamentally erroneous. The first is the kind of view which depends upon asserting the reality of the parts, but denying the reality of the whole, or, what is the same {323} thing, allowing that the individual is an end in himself, but denying that the State as a whole is such an end or has a separate life of its own. The second kind of false view is of the opposite kind, and consists in allowing reality only to the whole State, and denying the reality of its parts, the individuals. The opinions that the State is merely a mechanical aggregate of individuals, that it is formed by the combination of individuals or families for the sake of mutual protection and benefit, and that it exists only for these purposes, are examples of the first kind. Such views subordinate the State to the individual. The State is treated as an external contrivance for securing the life, the property, or the convenience of the individual. The State exists solely for the sake of the individual, and is not in itself an end. The individual alone is real, the State unreal, because it is only a collection of individuals. These views forget that the State is an organism, and they forget all that this implies. Aristotle would have condemned, on these grounds, the social contract theory so popular in the eighteenth century, and likewise the view of modern individualism that the State exists solely to ensure that the liberty of the individual is curtailed only by the right of other individuals to the same liberty. The opposite kind of false view is illustrated by the ideal State of Plato. As the views we have just discussed deny the reality of the whole, Plato's view, on the contrary, denies the reality of the parts. For him the individual is nothing, the State everything. The individual is absolutely sacrificed to the State. He exists only for the State, and thus Plato makes the mistake of setting up the State as sole end and denying that the {324} individual is an end in himself. Plato imagined that the State is a homogeneous unity, in which its parts totally disappear. But the true view is that the State, as an organism, is a unity which contains heterogeneity. It is coherent, yet heterogeneous. And Plato makes the same mistake in his view of the family as in his view of the individual. The family, Aristotle thinks, is, like the individual, a real part of the social whole. It is an organism within an organism. As such, it is an end in itself, has absolute rights, and cannot be obliterated. But Plato expressly proposed to abolish the family in favour of the State, and by suggesting community of wives and the education of children in State nurseries from the year of their birth, struck a deadly blow at an essential part of the State organization. Aristotle thus supports the institution of family, not on sentimental, but upon philosophic grounds.

The true nature of the State isn't just that it's a mechanical collection of individuals, like a pile of sand made up of grains. The State is a living organism, and the connection between its parts is not mechanical, but organic. The State has its own life. Its members also have their own lives, which are part of the broader life of the State. All parts of an organism are themselves organisms. The difference between organic and inorganic is that the former has its purpose within itself, while the latter has its purpose outside of itself. This means that the State is a purpose in itself, the individual is a purpose in himself, and the former purpose includes the latter. We could express this idea differently by saying that, in the State, both the whole and the parts are real, each having their own lives and their own rights as ends in themselves. Thus, there are two fundamentally incorrect perspectives on the nature of the State, which Aristotle would have criticized. The first perspective asserts the reality of the parts but denies the reality of the whole, or, equivalently, acknowledges that the individual is an end in himself but denies that the State as a whole is such an end or has its own life. The second incorrect perspective takes the opposite stance, recognizing only the whole State's reality and denying the reality of its parts—the individuals. Views that consider the State merely a mechanical sum of individuals, formed by the combination of individuals or families for mutual protection and benefit, and that assert it exists solely for those purposes, are examples of the first perspective. Such views subordinate the State to the individual, treating it as an external mechanism to secure an individual's life, property, or convenience. Here, the State exists only for the individual and is not an end in itself. The individual is the only real entity, while the State is unreal because it is just a collection of individuals. These views overlook that the State is an organism and all that this entails. Aristotle would have rejected, on these grounds, the social contract theory that became popular in the eighteenth century, as well as the modern individualistic view that the State exists solely to ensure that the individual’s freedom is limited only by the rights of others to the same freedom. The opposite false perspective is exemplified by Plato's ideal State. While the previously discussed views deny the reality of the whole, Plato's perspective denies the reality of the parts. For him, the individual is nothing, while the State is everything. The individual is completely sacrificed to the State. He exists only for the State, which is why Plato mistakenly elevates the State as the sole purpose and denies that the individual is an end in himself. Plato envisioned the State as a uniform entity in which its parts completely vanish. However, the true perspective is that the State, as an organism, is a unity that includes diversity. It is cohesive yet diverse. Plato makes the same error in his view of the family as he does in his view of the individual. According to Aristotle, the family is, like the individual, a real component of the social whole. It is an organism within an organism. As such, it is an end in itself, has absolute rights, and cannot be erased. However, Plato explicitly proposed abolishing the family in favor of the State, and by suggesting shared wives and state-run nurseries for children from birth, he delivered a serious blow to a vital part of the State's structure. Aristotle thus defends the institution of the family, not for sentimental reasons, but for philosophical ones.

Aristotle gives no exhaustive classification of different kinds of State, because forms of government may be as various as the circumstances which give rise to them. His classification is intended to include only outstanding types. He finds that there are six such types, of which three are good. The other three are bad, because they are corruptions of the good types. These are (1) Monarchy, the rule of one man by virtue of his being so superior in wisdom to all his fellows that he naturally rules them. The corruption of Monarchy is (2) Tyranny, the rule of one man founded not on wisdom and capacity, but upon force. The second good form is (3) Aristocracy, the rule of the wiser and better few, of which the corrupt form is (4) Oligarchy, the rule of the rich and powerful few. (5) Constitutional Republic or Timocracy arises {325} where all the citizens are of fairly equal capacity, i.e., where no stand-out individual or class exists, so that all or most take a share in the government. The corresponding corrupt form is (6) Democracy, which, though it is the rule of the many, is more especially characterized as being the rule of the poor.

Aristotle doesn't provide a complete classification of different types of states, because forms of government can be as diverse as the situations that create them. His classification aims to include only the main types. He identifies six such types, three of which are good. The other three are bad because they are deviations from the good types. These are (1) Monarchy, where one person rules due to their superiority in wisdom compared to everyone else. The corruption of Monarchy is (2) Tyranny, where one person rules not based on wisdom and ability, but through force. The second good form is (3) Aristocracy, which is the rule of a knowledgeable and virtuous few, while the corrupted form is (4) Oligarchy, the rule of the wealthy and powerful few. (5) Constitutional Republic or Timocracy emerges {325} where all citizens have relatively equal ability, meaning there is no outstanding individual or class, allowing everyone or most to participate in government. The related corrupt form is (6) Democracy, which, while it represents the rule of the many, is particularly marked by being the rule of the poor.

Unlike Plato, Aristotle depicts no ideal State. No single State, he thinks, is in itself the best. Everything must depend upon the circumstances. What is the best State in one age and county will not be the best in another. Moreover, it is useless to discuss Utopian constitutions. What alone interests the sane and balanced mind of Aristotle is the kind of constitution which we may hope actually to realize. Of the three good forms of government he considers that monarchy is theoretically the best. The rule of a single perfectly wise and just man would be better than any other. But it has to be given up as impracticable, because such perfect individuals do not exist. And it is only among primitive peoples that we find the hero, the man whose moral stature so completely exalts him above his fellows that he rules as a matter of course. The next best State is aristocracy. And last, in Aristotle's opinion, comes constitutional republic, which is, however, perhaps the State best suited to the special needs and level of development of the Greek city-states.

Unlike Plato, Aristotle doesn't describe an ideal State. He believes that no single State is the best in itself. Everything depends on the specific circumstances. What is the best State in one era and country won't necessarily be the best in another. Additionally, discussing perfect, Utopian governments is pointless. What truly matters to the rational and balanced mind of Aristotle is the type of government we can realistically hope to achieve. Out of the three good forms of government, he argues that monarchy is theoretically the best. The rule of a single, perfectly wise and just person would be better than any other system. However, this idea is impractical because such perfect individuals don't actually exist. The only time we see a hero, a person whose moral uprightness elevates him above others to the point of natural leadership, is among primitive societies. The next best form of governance is aristocracy. Lastly, in Aristotle's view, the constitutional republic comes in third, which may be the system best suited to fit the unique needs and level of development of the Greek city-states.


6. Aesthetics, or the Theory of Art.

6. Aesthetics, or the Theory of Art.

Plato had no systematic philosophy of Art, and his views had to be collected from scattered references. Aristotle likewise has scarcely a system, though his opinions are more connected, and though he devoted a special tretise, the "Poetics", to the subject. And this {326} book, which has come down to us in a fragmentary condition, deals exclusively with poetry, and even in poetry only the drama is considered in detail. What we have from Aristotle on the subject of aesthetics may be divided roughly into two classes, firstly, reflections on the nature and significance of art in general, and, secondly, a more detailed application of these principles to the art of poetry. We shall deal with these two classes of opinions in that order.

Plato didn't have a systematic philosophy of Art, and his views need to be pieced together from various references. Similarly, Aristotle hardly has a system, though his ideas are more organized, and he dedicated a special treatise, the "Poetics," to the topic. And this {326} book, which has come down to us in a fragmented state, focuses solely on poetry, and even within poetry, it only examines drama in detail. What we have from Aristotle regarding aesthetics can be roughly divided into two categories: first, reflections on the nature and significance of art in general, and second, a more detailed application of these principles to the art of poetry. We will discuss these two categories of opinions in that order.

In order to know what art is, we must first know what it is not. It must be distinguished from kindred activities. And firstly, it is distinguished from morality in that morality is concerned with action, art with production. Morality consists in the activity itself, art in that which the activity produces. Hence the state of mind of the actor, his motives, feelings, etc., are important in morality, for they are part of the act itself. But they are not important in art, the only essential being that the work of art should turn out well, however it has been produced. Secondly, art is distinguished from the activity of nature, which it in many respects resembles. Organic beings reproduce their own kind, and, in the fact that it is concerned with production, generation resembles art. But in generation, the living being produces only itself. The plant produces a plant, man begets man. But the artist produces something quite other than himself, a poem, a picture, a statue.

To understand what art is, we first need to recognize what it is not. It has to be separated from similar activities. First, it is different from morality because morality focuses on actions, while art focuses on creation. Morality is about the act itself, and art is about what that act produces. Therefore, the mindset of the person performing the act, their motives, feelings, and so on, matter in morality since they are part of the act. However, they don’t matter in art; the only crucial factor is that the artwork turns out well, no matter how it was made. Second, art is different from natural activities, even though they are similar in many ways. Living beings reproduce their own kind, and in the aspect of production, reproduction is similar to art. But in reproduction, a living being only creates itself. A plant produces another plant; a man begets another man. In contrast, an artist creates something entirely different from themselves—like a poem, a painting, or a sculpture.

Art is of two kinds, according as it aims at completing the work of nature, or at creating something new, an imaginary world of its own which is a copy of the real world. In the former case, we get such arts as that of {327} medicine. Where nature has failed to produce a healthy body, the physician helps nature out, and completes the work that she has begun. In the latter case, we get what are, in modern times, called the fine arts. These Aristotle calls the imitative arts. We saw that Plato regarded all art as imitative, and that such a view is essentially unsatisfactory. Now Aristotle uses the same word, which he perhaps borrowed from Plato, but his meaning is not the same as Plato's, nor does he fall into the same mistakes. That in calling art imitative he has not in mind the thought that it has for its aim merely the faithful copying of natural objects is proved by the fact that he mentions music as the most imitative of the arts, whereas music is, in fact, in this sense, the least imitative of all. The painter may conceivably be regarded as imitating trees, rivers, or men, but the musician for the most part produces what is unlike anything in nature. What Aristotle means is that the artist copies, not the sensuous object, but what Plato would call the Idea. Art is thus not, in Plato's contemptuous phrase, a copy of a copy. It is a copy of the original. Its object is not this or that particular thing, but the universal which manifests itself in the particular. Art idealizes nature, that is, sees the Idea in it. It regards the individual thing, not as an individual, but in its universal aspects, as the fleeting embodiment of an eternal thought. Hence it is that the sculptor depicts not the individual man, but rather the type-man, the perfection of his kind. Hence too, in modern times, the portrait painter is not concerned to paint a faithful image of his model, but takes the model merely as a suggestion, and seizes upon that essential and eternal {328} essence, that ideal thought, or universal, which he sees shining through the sensuous materials in which it is imprisoned. His task is to free it from this imprisonment. The common man sees only the particular object. The artist sees the universal in the particular. Every individual thing is a compound of matter and form, of particular and universal. The function of art is to exhibit the universal in it.

Art comes in two types: one aims to complete what nature has started, and the other seeks to create something new, an imaginary world that reflects the real one. In the first case, we have fields like medicine. When nature fails to create a healthy body, the doctor steps in to assist and finish what nature began. In the second case, we encounter what we now call the fine arts. Aristotle refers to these as imitative arts. While Plato saw all art as imitative and that view is ultimately flawed, Aristotle uses the same term, which he may have taken from Plato, but he means something different and avoids Plato's errors. Aristotle's idea of imitation doesn’t solely focus on accurately replicating natural objects, as shown by his mention of music as the most imitative of the arts, even though music is actually the least imitative. A painter might be seen as replicating trees, rivers, or people, but a musician often produces sounds that don’t resemble anything in nature. What Aristotle suggests is that the artist doesn't replicate the physical object, but rather what Plato would call the Idea. Art is not, as Plato dismissively claimed, a copy of a copy; it's a reflection of the original. Its focus isn't on any specific object but on the universal that is expressed through the specific. Art idealizes nature, finding the Idea within it. It looks at individual things, not as mere individuals, but in their universal aspects, as the temporary embodiment of an eternal thought. This is why a sculptor represents not just any man, but the ideal type of man, the perfect example of his kind. Likewise, in modern times, portrait painters are not focused on creating an exact likeness of their subject but instead use the subject as inspiration, capturing the essential and timeless essence, that ideal thought or universal, shining through the physical materials that contain it. Their aim is to liberate this essence from its confines. The average person sees only the specific object, while the artist perceives the universal within the specific. Every individual item is a mixture of matter and form, particular and universal. The role of art is to reveal that universal within it.

Hence poetry is truer, more philosophical, than history. For history deals only with the particular as the particular. It tells us only of the fact, of what has happened. Its truth is mere correctness, accuracy. It has not in it, as art has, the living and eternal truth. It does not deal with the Idea. It yields us only the knowledge of something that, having happened, having gone by, is finished. Its object is transient and perishable. It concerns only the endless iteration of meaningless events. But the object of art is that inner essence of objects and events, which perishes not, and of which the objects and events are the mere external drapery. If therefore we would arrange philosophy, art, and history, in order of their essential nobility and truth, we should place philosophy first, because its object is the universal as it is in itself, the pure universal. We should place art second, because its object is the universal in the particular, and history last, because it deals only with the particular as such. Yet because each thing in the world has its own proper function, and errs if it seeks to perform the functions of something else, hence, in Aristotle's opinion, art must not attempt to emulate philosophy. It must not deal with the abstract universal. The poet must not use his verses as a vehicle of abstract thought. His proper {329} sphere is the universal as it manifests itself in the particular, not the universal as it is in itself. Aristotle, for this reason, censures didactic poetry. Such a poem as that of Empedocles, who unfolded his philosophical system in metre, is not, in fact, poetry at all. It is versified philosophy. Art is thus lower than philosophy. The absolute reality, the inner essence of the world, is thought, reason, the universal. To contemplate this reality is the object alike of philosophy and of art. But art sees the Absolute not in its final truth, but wrapped up in a sensuous drapery. Philosophy sees the Absolute as it is in itself, in its own nature, in its full truth; it sees it as what it essentially is, thought. Philosophy, therefore, is the perfect truth. But this does not mean that art is to be superseded and done away with. Because philosophy is higher than art, it does not follow that a man should suppress the artist in himself in order to rise to philosophy. For an essential thought of the Aristotelian philosophy is that, in the scale of beings, even the lower form is an end in itself, and has absolute rights. The higher activities presuppose the lower, and rest upon them. The higher includes the lower, and the lower, as an organic part of its being, cannot be eradicated without injury to the whole. To suppress art in favour of philosophy would be a mistake precisely parallel to the moral error of asceticism. In treating of Aristotle's ethics we saw that, although the activity of reason is held in highest esteem, the attempt to uproot the passions was censured as erroneous. So here, though philosophy is the crown of man's spiritual activity, art has its rights, and is an absolute end in itself, a point which Plato failed to see. In the human organism, the head is the {330} chief of the members. But one does not cut off the hand because it is not the head.

So, poetry is more truthful and philosophical than history. History only focuses on the specific as just that. It tells us about the facts, about what happened. Its truth is just correctness and accuracy. It doesn't have, like art does, the living and eternal truth. It doesn't engage with the Idea. It only gives us knowledge of something that has happened, has passed, and is over. Its subject is temporary and fleeting. It concerns itself with the endless repetition of meaningless events. But art focuses on the inner essence of objects and events, which doesn’t perish, while the objects and events are merely their external appearance. If we were to organize philosophy, art, and history by their essential nobility and truth, we would place philosophy first because its subject is the universal as it is in itself, the pure universal. Art would come second because its subject is the universal in the particular, and history last because it only deals with the particular as such. However, since each thing in the world has its own function and goes wrong if it tries to take on another's role, Aristotle believed art should not try to imitate philosophy. It shouldn’t deal with the abstract universal. The poet shouldn’t use their verses to express abstract thought. Their proper {329} sphere is the universal as it appears in the particular, not the universal as it exists in itself. For this reason, Aristotle criticizes didactic poetry. A poem like that of Empedocles, who expressed his philosophical system in verse, is really not poetry at all; it's just poetry about philosophy. Art is, therefore, lower than philosophy. The ultimate reality, the inner essence of the world, is thought, reason, the universal. Both philosophy and art aim to contemplate this reality. But art perceives the Absolute not in its ultimate truth, but wrapped in sensory details. Philosophy sees the Absolute as it is, in its own nature, in its full truth; it sees it as what it truly is—thought. Thus, philosophy represents perfect truth. However, this doesn’t mean that art should be dismissed. Just because philosophy is superior to art doesn’t mean one should suppress their inner artist to pursue philosophy. A key idea of Aristotelian philosophy is that in the hierarchy of existence, even the lower forms are valid in themselves and have their own rights. Higher activities rely on the lower forms and are built upon them. The higher includes the lower, and the lower, as an integral part of its being, cannot be removed without harming the whole. To suppress art for the sake of philosophy would be a mistake similar to the moral error of asceticism. As we discussed in Aristotle's ethics, while the activity of reason is highly valued, the attempt to eliminate passions was criticized as wrong. So here, even though philosophy is the peak of human spiritual activity, art has its own rights and is a valid end in itself, a point Plato overlooked. In the human body, the head is the {330} leader of the parts. But you don’t cut off the hand just because it isn’t the head.

Coming now to Aristotle's special treatment of the art of poetry, we may note that he concentrates his attention almost exclusively upon the drama. It does not matter whether the plot of a drama is historical or fictitious. For the object of art, the exhibition of the universal, is just as well attained in an imaginary as in a real series of events. Its aim is not correctness, but truth, not facts, but the Idea. Drama is of two kinds, tragedy and comedy. Tragedy exhibits the nobler specimens of humanity, comedy the worse. This remark should be carefully understood. It does not mean that the hero of a tragedy is necessarily a good man in the ordinary sense. He may even be a wicked man. But the point is that, in some sense, he must be a great personality. He cannot be an insignificant person. He cannot be a nonentity. Be he good or bad, he must be conceived in the grand manner. Milton's Satan is not good, but he is great, and would be a fit subject for a tragedy. The soundness of Aristotle's thought here is very noteworthy. What is mean and sordid can never form the basis of tragedy. Modern newspapers have done their best to debauch this word tragedy. Some wretched noteless human being is crushed to death by a train, and the newspapers head their paragraph "Fearful Tragedy at Peckham Rye." Now such an incident may be sad, it may be dreadful, it may be horrible, but it is not tragic. Tragedy no doubt deals with suffering. But there is nothing great and ennobling about this suffering, and tragedy is concerned with the sufferings of greatness. In the same way, Aristotle does not mean that the comic {331} hero is necessarily a wicked man, but that he is, on the whole, a poor creature, an insignificant being. He may be very worthy, but there is something low and ignoble about him which makes us laugh.

Focusing now on Aristotle's specific view of poetry, it's clear that he mainly emphasizes drama. It doesn’t matter if a drama's plot is based on real events or is entirely fictional. The purpose of art, which is to show the universal, can be achieved through both imaginary and real events. Its goal is not accuracy, but truth; not facts, but the Idea. Drama comes in two forms: tragedy and comedy. Tragedy showcases the nobler aspects of humanity, while comedy highlights the less admirable qualities. This point should be well understood. It doesn't mean that a tragic hero has to be a good person in the usual sense; he could even be a bad person. What matters is that he must be a significant character in some way. He can't be someone unremarkable or inconsequential. Whether good or bad, he needs to be portrayed in a grand way. Milton's Satan isn't good, but he is formidable and would be appropriate for a tragedy. Aristotle's insight on this is quite significant. The trivial and sordid can never serve as the foundation for tragedy. Modern newspapers have tried their best to misuse the term tragedy. When some unfortunate person dies in an accident involving a train, the headlines might read "Fearful Tragedy at Peckham Rye." While such an incident can be sad, dreadful, or horrifying, it isn’t tragic. Tragedy certainly involves suffering, but it’s not just any suffering; it’s the suffering tied to greatness. Similarly, Aristotle doesn’t claim that a comedic hero has to be a bad person, but rather that he is generally a pitiful figure, an insignificant character. He may have redeeming qualities, but there’s something low and unworthy about him that makes us laugh.

Tragedy brings about a purification of the soul through pity and terror. Mean, sordid, or dreadful things do not ennoble us. But the representation of truly great and tragic sufferings arouses in the beholder pity and terror which purge his spirit, and render it serene and pure. This is the thought of a great and penetrating critic. The theory of certain scholars, based upon etymological grounds, that it means that the soul is purged, not through, but of pity and terror, that by means of a diarrhoea of these unpleasant emotions we get rid of them and are left happy, is the thought of men whose scholarship may be great, but whose understanding of art is limited. Such a theory would reduce Aristotle's great and illuminating criticism to the meaningless babble of a philistine.

Tragedy purifies the soul through feelings of pity and fear. Mean, dirty, or terrible things don’t elevate us. However, the portrayal of truly great and tragic suffering evokes pity and fear in the viewer, cleansing their spirit and making it calm and pure. This is the insight of a profound critic. The theory of some scholars, based on word origins, suggesting that it means the soul is cleansed, not through, but of pity and fear—arguing that we rid ourselves of these unpleasant emotions through an outpouring of them and end up happy—is the perspective of individuals with extensive knowledge, but limited understanding of art. Such a theory would trivialize Aristotle's significant and enlightening critique into the meaningless chatter of a dilettante.


7. Critical Estimate of Aristotle's Philosophy.

7. A Critical Assessment of Aristotle's Philosophy.

It is not necessary to spend so much time upon criticising Aristotle as we spent upon doing the same for Plato, and that for two reasons. In the first place, Plato with his obvious greatness abounded in defects which had to be pointed out, whereas we have but little adverse criticism for Aristotle. Secondly, Aristotle's main defect is a dualism almost identical with that of Plato, and what has been said of the one need only be shortly applied to the other.

It’s not necessary to spend as much time criticizing Aristotle as we did critiquing Plato, for two reasons. First, Plato had many obvious strengths but also notable flaws that needed addressing, while we have very few criticisms to make about Aristotle. Second, Aristotle’s main flaw is a dualism that’s almost the same as Plato’s, so what has been said about one can be briefly applied to the other.

At bottom Aristotle's philosophy is the same as Plato's, with some of the main defects and crudities removed. Plato was the founder of the philosophy of the Idea. {332} But in his hands, idealism was clogged with unessentials, and overgrown with excrescences. His crude theory of the soul as a thing mechanically forced in and out of the body, his doctrines of reincarnation and recollection, the belief that this thing the soul can travel to some place far away where it will see those things the Ideas, and above all, what is the root of all these, the confusion between reality and existence, with its consequent degradation of the universal to a mere particular--these were the unessentials with which Plato connected his essential idealism. To take the pure theory of Ideas--albeit not under that name--to purge it of these encumbrances and to cast them upon the rubbish heap, to cleanse Plato's gold of its dross, this was the task of Aristotle. Thought, the universal, the Idea, form--call it what you will--this is the ultimate reality, the foundation of the world, the absolute prius of all things. So thought both Plato and Aristotle. But whereas Plato began to draw mental pictures of the universal, to imagine that it existed apart in a world of its own, and so might be experienced by the vision of the wandering soul, Aristotle saw that this was to treat thought as if it were a thing, to turn it into a mere particular again. He saw that the universal, though it is the real, has no existence in a world of its own, but only in this world, only as a formative principle of particular things. This is the key-note of his philosophy. Aristotle registers, therefore, an enormous advance upon Plato. His system is the perfected and completed Greek idealism. It is the highest point reached in the philosophy of Greece. The flower of all previous thought, the essence and pure distillation of the Greek philosophic spirit, the gathering {333} up of all that is good in his predecessors and the rejection of all that is faulty and worthless--such is the philosophy of Aristotle. It was not possible for the Greek spirit to advance further. Further development could be only decay. And so, in fact, it turned out to be.

At its core, Aristotle's philosophy is similar to Plato's, with many of the major flaws and rough edges removed. Plato was the originator of the philosophy of Ideas. {332} However, his version of idealism was burdened by unnecessary details and complexities. His simplistic view of the soul as a mechanism pushed in and out of the body, his ideas about reincarnation and recollection, the belief that this thing called the soul can travel to a distant place to perceive those things known as Ideas, and above all, the confusion between reality and existence, which downgraded the universal to just a particular—these were the unnecessary elements that Plato tied to his essential idealism. The challenge for Aristotle was to take the pure theory of Ideas—not necessarily under that name—remove these burdens, and discard them as trash, purifying Plato's gold from its impurities. Thought, the universal, the Idea, form—call it whatever you like—this is the ultimate reality, the foundation of the world, the absolute beginning of all things. Both Plato and Aristotle believed this. But while Plato started to create mental images of the universal, imagining it existed separately in its own world and could be experienced through the wandering soul's vision, Aristotle recognized that this perspective turns thought into just another thing, reducing it back to a mere particular. He understood that the universal, though real, doesn't have existence in a separate world; it only exists in this world, solely as a formative principle of particular things. This is the central idea of his philosophy. Therefore, Aristotle marks a significant advancement over Plato. His system is the refined and complete version of Greek idealism. It represents the pinnacle of Greek philosophical thought—the essence and pure extraction of the Greek philosophical spirit, accumulating {333} all that is valuable from his predecessors while discarding everything flawed and worthless—such is Aristotle's philosophy. The Greek spirit could not progress beyond this point; any further development would only lead to decline. And indeed, that is what happened.

Aristotle deserves, too, the credit of having produced the only philosophy of evolution which the world has ever seen, with the exception of that of Hegel; and Hegel was enabled to found a newer theory of evolution only by following largely in the footsteps of Aristotle. This was perhaps Aristotle's most original contribution to thought. Yet the factors of the problem, though not its solution, he took from his predecessors. The problem of becoming had tortured Greek thought from the earliest ages. The philosophy of Heracleitus, in which it was most prominent, had failed to solve it. Heracleitus and his successors racked their brains to discover how becoming could be possible. But even if they had solved this minor problem, the greater question still remained in the background, what does this becoming mean? Becoming for them was only meaningless change. It was not development. The world-process was an endless stream of futile and purposeless events, "a tale, told by an idiot, full of sound and fury, signifying nothing." Aristotle not merely asked himself how becoming is possible. He showed that becoming has a meaning, that it signifies something, that the world-process is a rationally ordered development towards a rational end.

Aristotle deserves credit for creating the only philosophy of evolution that the world has ever seen, except for Hegel's; and Hegel could only develop a new theory of evolution by largely following Aristotle's ideas. This was probably Aristotle's most original contribution to thought. However, he took the factors of the problem, but not its solution, from his predecessors. The problem of becoming had puzzled Greek thinkers for centuries. Heraclitus's philosophy, which emphasized this issue, failed to resolve it. He and his followers struggled to understand how becoming could be possible. Even if they had solved this smaller issue, the bigger question still lingered: what does becoming mean? For them, becoming was just meaningless change, not development. The world process was an endless stream of pointless events, "a tale, told by an idiot, full of sound and fury, signifying nothing." Aristotle didn't just wonder how becoming is possible; he demonstrated that becoming has meaning, that it signifies something, and that the world process is a rationally ordered development toward a rational goal.

But, though Aristotle's philosophy is the highest presentation of the truth in ancient times, it cannot be accepted as anything final and faultless. Doubtless no philosophy can ever attain to finality. Let us apply our {334} two-fold test. Does his principle explain the world, and does it explain itself? First, does it explain the world? The cause of Plato's failure here was the dualism in his system between sense and thought, between matter and the Ideas. It was impossible to derive the world from the Ideas, because they were absolutely separated from the world. The gulf was so great that it could never be bridged. Matter and Idea lay apart, and could never be brought together. Now Aristotle saw this dualism in Plato, and attempted to surmount it. The universal and the particular, he said, do not thus lie apart, in different worlds. The Idea is not a thing here, and matter a thing there, so that these two incommensurables have to be somehow mechanically and violently forced together to form a world. Universal and particular, matter and form, are inseparable. The connexion between them is not mechanical, but organic. The dualism of Plato is thus admitted and refuted. But is it really surmounted? The answer must be in the negative. It is not enough by a tour de force to bring matter and form together, to assert that they are inseparable, while they remain all the time, in principle, separate entities. If the Absolute is form, matter ought to be deduced from form, shown to be merely a projection and manifestation of it. It must be shown that form not only moulds matter but produces it. If we assert that the one primal reality is form, then clearly we must prove that all else in the world, including matter, arises out of that prime being. Either matter arises out of form or it does not. If it does, this arising must be exhibited. If it does not, then form is not the sole ultimate reality, for matter is equally an ultimate, underivative, {335} primordial substance. In that case, we thus have two equally real ultimate beings, each underived from the other, existing side by side from all eternity. This is dualism, and this is the defect of Aristotle. Not only does he not derive matter from form, but he obviously sees no necessity for doing so. He would probably have protested against any attempt to do so, for, when he identifies the formal, final, and efficient causes with each other, leaving out the material cause, this is equivalent to an assertion that matter cannot be reduced to form. Thus his dualism is deliberate and persistent. The world, says Aristotle, is composed of matter and form. Where does this matter come from? As it does not, in his system, arise out of form, we can only conclude that its being is wholly in itself, i.e., that it is a substance, an absolute reality. And this is utterly inconsistent with Aristotle's assertion that it is in itself nothing but a mere potentiality. Thus, in the last resort, this dualism of sense and thought, of matter and Idea, of unlimited and limiting, which runs, "the little rift within the lute," through all Greek philosophy, is not resolved. The world is not explained, because it is not derived from a single principle. If form be the Absolute, the whole world must flow out of it. In Aristotle's system, it does not.

But even though Aristotle's philosophy represents the highest understanding of truth in ancient times, it can't be seen as final or flawless. No philosophy can ever claim to be the ultimate answer. Let’s use our {334} two-part test. Does his principle explain the world, and does it explain itself? First, does it explain the world? Plato failed here because of the dualism in his system between sensory experience and thought, between matter and Ideas. It was impossible to derive the world from the Ideas since they were completely separate from it. The gap was so vast that it could never be bridged. Matter and Idea were apart, and could never be unified. Aristotle recognized this dualism in Plato and tried to overcome it. He argued that the universal and the particular do not exist in two different realms. The Idea isn't something over here while matter is over there, compelling these two fundamentally different things to be awkwardly combined to create a world. The universal and particular, matter and form, are inseparable. Their connection is not mechanical but organic. Plato's dualism is thus acknowledged and challenged. But has it truly been overcome? The answer is no. It's not enough to force matter and form together and claim they are inseparable while they remain separate entities in principle. If the Absolute is form, then matter should be derived from form, shown to be simply a projection and manifestation of it. It needs to be demonstrated that form not only shapes matter but also creates it. If we say that the primal reality is form, then we must clearly show that everything else in the world, including matter, originates from that prime reality. Either matter comes from form or it doesn't. If it does, that process must be illustrated. If it doesn't, then form is not the only ultimate reality, as matter is also a fundamental, underived, {335} primordial substance. This leads to two equally real ultimate beings, each existing independently from the other for all time. This is dualism, and it’s a flaw in Aristotle’s thinking. Not only does he fail to derive matter from form, but he also shows no real need to do so. He would likely have resisted any effort to connect the two because when he equates the formal, final, and efficient causes, ignoring the material cause, it suggests that matter can't be reduced to form. Therefore, his dualism is intentional and persistent. Aristotle states that the world consists of matter and form. Where does this matter originate? Since, in his view, it doesn't arise from form, we must conclude that its existence is entirely self-contained, meaning it is a substance, an absolute reality. This contradicts Aristotle's claim that in itself, matter is just potentiality. Ultimately, this dualism of sensory experience and thought, of matter and Idea, of unlimited and limiting factors, which weaves through all Greek philosophy, remains unresolved. The world isn't explained because it's not derived from a single principle. If form is the Absolute, then the entire world must flow from it. In Aristotle's system, it does not.

Secondly, is the principle of form self-explanatory? Here, again, we must answer negatively. Most of what was said of Plato under this head applies equally to Aristotle. Plato asserted that the Absolute is reason, and it was therefore incumbent on him to show that his account of reason was truly rational. He failed to do so. Aristotle asserts the same thing, for form is only {336} another word for reason. Hence he must show us that this form is a rational principle, and this means that he must show us that it is necessary. But he fails to do so. How is form a necessary and self-determining principle? Why should there be such a principle as form? We cannot see any necessity. It is a mere fact. It is nothing but an ultimate mystery. It is so, and that is an end of it. But why it should be so, we cannot see. Nor can we see why there should be any of the particular kinds of form that there are. To explain this, Aristotle ought to have shown that the forms constitute a systematic unity, that they can be deduced one from another, just as we saw that Plato ought to have deduced all the Ideas from one another. Thus Aristotle asserts that the form of plants is nutrition, of animals sensation, and that the one passes into the other. But even if this assertion be true, it is a mere fact. He ought not merely to have asserted this, but to have deduced sensation from nutrition. Instead of being content to allege that, as a fact, nutrition passes into sensation, he ought to have shown that it must pass into sensation, that the passage from one to the other is a logical necessity. Otherwise, we cannot see the reason why this change occurs. That is to say, the change is not explained.

Secondly, is the principle of form self-explanatory? Here, again, we must answer no. Most of what was said about Plato in this context applies to Aristotle as well. Plato claimed that the Absolute is reason, so it was his responsibility to demonstrate that his understanding of reason was genuinely rational. He didn’t succeed in doing that. Aristotle makes the same claim because form is just another term for reason. Therefore, he needs to demonstrate that this form is a rational principle, which means he has to prove that it is necessary. But he fails to do so. How is form a necessary and self-determining principle? Why should such a principle as form exist? We cannot see any necessity. It is simply a fact. It is nothing more than an ultimate mystery. It is as it is, and that’s the end of it. But why it should be this way, we cannot understand. Nor can we explain why there are any of the specific types of form that exist. To clarify this, Aristotle should have shown that the forms create a systematic unity, that they can be derived from one another, just as we noted that Plato should have deduced all the Ideas from each other. Aristotle claims that the form of plants is nutrition, that of animals is sensation, and that one transitions into the other. But even if this claim is true, it remains a mere fact. He should have not only stated this but also derived sensation from nutrition. Rather than just asserting that, as a fact, nutrition leads to sensation, he should have demonstrated that it must transition into sensation, that the change from one to the other is a logical necessity. Otherwise, we don’t understand why this change happens. In other words, the change is not explained.

Consider the effects of this omission upon the theory of evolution. We are told that the world-process moves towards an end, and that this end is the self-realization of reason, and that it is proximately attained in man, because man is a reasoning being. So far this is quite intelligible. But this implies that each step in evolution is higher than the last because it approaches nearer to {337} the end of the world-process. And as that end is the realization of reason, this is equivalent to saying that each step is higher than the last because it is more rational. But how is sensation more rational than nutrition? Why should it not be the other way about? Nutrition passes through sensation into human reason. But why should not sensation pass through nutrition into human reason? Why should not the order be reversed? We cannot explain. And such an admission is absolutely fatal to any philosophy of evolution. The whole object of such a philosophy is to make it clear to us why the higher form is higher, and why the lower is lower: why, for example, nutrition must, as lower, come first, and sensation second, and not vice versa. If we can see no reason why the order should not be reversed, this simply means that our philosophy of evolution has failed in its main point. It means that we cannot see any real difference between lower and higher, and that therefore we have merely change without development, since it is indifferent whether A passes into B, or B into A. The only way in which Aristotle could have surmounted these difficulties would have been to prove that sensation is a development of reason which goes beyond nutrition. And he could only do this by showing that sensation logically arises out of nutrition. For a logical development is the same as a rational development. He ought to have logically deduced sensation from nutrition, and so with all the other forms. As it is, all that can be said is that Aristotle was the founder of a philosophy of evolution because he saw that evolution implies movement towards an end, and because he attempted to point out the different stages in the attainment of that end, {338} but that he failed rationally to develop the doctrine stage by stage.

Consider the impact of this omission on the theory of evolution. We are told that the process of the world moves toward a goal, and that this goal is the self-realization of reason, which is primarily achieved in humans because humans are reasoning beings. So far, this makes sense. But this suggests that each step in evolution is an improvement over the last, as it gets closer to the end of the world process. And since that end is the realization of reason, this implies that each step is better because it is more rational. However, how is sensation more rational than nutrition? Why shouldn’t it be the other way around? Nutrition leads to sensation, which then leads to human reason. But why couldn’t sensation lead to nutrition and then to human reason? Why should the order not be flipped? We cannot explain this. And acknowledging this is critically damaging to any philosophy of evolution. The whole purpose of such a philosophy is to clarify why the higher form is higher and why the lower is lower: why, for example, nutrition must come first as the lower and sensation second, and not the other way around. If we can’t see a reason why the order should be reversed, it simply means that our philosophy of evolution has failed in its fundamental argument. It suggests that we can't identify any real difference between lower and higher, meaning we have mere change without true development, as it makes no difference whether A becomes B or B becomes A. The only way Aristotle could have resolved these issues would have been to demonstrate that sensation is a development of reason that surpasses nutrition. And he could only do this by proving that sensation logically follows from nutrition. For a logical development is the same as a rational development. He should have logically deduced sensation from nutrition, and the same for all other forms. As it stands, all we can say is that Aristotle was the originator of a philosophy of evolution because he recognized that evolution implies moving toward a goal, and because he attempted to outline the different stages in achieving that goal, {338} but he failed to logically develop the doctrine stage by stage.

As neither the principle of form in general was shown to be necessary, nor were the particular forms deduced from each other, we have to conclude that Aristotle like Plato, named a self-explanatory principle, reason or form, as ultimate principle of things, but failed to show in detail that it is self-explanatory. Yet, in spite these defects, the philosophy of Aristotle is one of the greatest philosophies that the world has ever seen, or is ever likely to see. If it does not solve all problems, it does render the world more intelligible to us than it was before.

Since neither the general principle of form was proven to be necessary, nor were the specific forms derived from each other, we must conclude that, like Plato, Aristotle named a self-explanatory principle, reason or form, as the ultimate principle of things, but did not adequately demonstrate that it is self-explanatory. However, despite these shortcomings, Aristotle's philosophy is among the greatest that the world has ever known or is likely to know. While it may not answer every question, it does make the world clearer to us than it was before.


THE GENERAL CHARACTER OF POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY

THE GENERAL CHARACTER OF POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY

The rest of the story of Greek philosophy is soon told, for it is the story of decay. The post-Aristotelian is the least instructive of the three periods of Greek thought, and I shall delineate only its main outlines.

The rest of the story of Greek philosophy is quickly covered, as it represents a decline. The post-Aristotelian era is the least informative of the three periods of Greek thought, and I will outline just its main features.

The general characteristics of the decay of thought which set in after Aristotle are intimately connected with the political, social, and moral events of the time. Although the huge empire of Alexander had broken up at the conqueror's death, this fact had in no way helped the Greek States to throw off the yoke of their oppressors. With the single exception of Sparta, which stubbornly held out, they had become, for all intents and purposes, subject to the dominion of Macedonia. And the death of Alexander did not alter this fact. It was not merely that rude might had overwhelmed a beautiful and delicate civilization. That civilization itself was decaying. The Greeks had ceased to be a great and free people. Their vitality was ebbing. Had it not been one conqueror it would have been another. They were growing old. They had to give way before younger and sturdier races. It was not so many years now before Greece, passing from one alien yoke to another, was to become no more than a Roman province.

The general characteristics of the decline in thought that began after Aristotle are closely linked to the political, social, and moral events of the time. Although Alexander's vast empire broke apart after his death, this didn't help the Greek states shake off the control of their oppressors. With the exception of Sparta, which held out stubbornly, they were essentially under the rule of Macedonia. The death of Alexander didn't change this reality. It wasn't just that brute force had crushed a beautiful and delicate civilization; that civilization was also in decline. The Greeks had stopped being a great and free people. Their energy was fading. If it hadn't been one conqueror, it would have been another. They were aging and had to yield to younger and stronger races. It wasn't long before Greece, shifting from one foreign domination to another, would become nothing more than a Roman province.

Philosophy is not something that subsists independently of the growth and decay of the spirit of man. It goes hand in hand with political, social, religious, and artistic development. Political organization, art, religion, science, and philosophy, are but different forms in which the life of a people expresses itself. The innermost substance of the national life is found in the national philosophy, and the history of philosophy is the kernel of the history of nations. It was but natural, then, that from the time of Alexander onwards Greek philosophy should exhibit symptoms of decay.

Philosophy doesn’t exist separately from the ups and downs of human spirit. It goes along with political, social, religious, and artistic progress. Political systems, art, religion, science, and philosophy are just different ways that a society expresses itself. The core essence of national life is reflected in national philosophy, and the history of philosophy is at the heart of national history. Therefore, it was only natural that from the time of Alexander onward, Greek philosophy would show signs of decline.

The essential mark of the decay of Greek thought was the intense subjectivism which is a feature of all the post-Aristotelian schools. Not one of them is interested in the solution of the world-problem for its own sake. The pure scientific spirit, the desire for knowledge for its own sake, is gone. That curiosity, that wonder, of which Aristotle speaks as the inspiring spirit of philosophy, is dead. The motive power of philosophy is no longer the disinterested pursuit of truth, but only the desire of the individual to escape from the ills of life. Philosophy only interests men in so far as it affects their lives. It becomes anthropocentric and egocentric. Everything pivots on the individual subject, his destiny, his fate, the welfare of his soul. Religion has long since become corrupted and worthless, and philosophy is now expected to do the work of religion, and to be a haven of refuge from the storms of life. Hence it becomes essentially practical. Before everything else it is ethical. All other departments of thought are now subordinated to ethics. It is not as in the days of the strength and youth of the Greek spirit, when Xenophanes or {341} Anaxagoras looked out into the heavens, and naively wondered what the sun and the stars were, and how the world arose. Men's thought no longer turns outward toward the stars, but only inward upon themselves. It is not the riddle of the universe, but the riddle of human life, which makes them ponder.

The key sign of the decline of Greek thought was the strong focus on individual perspective that characterizes all the schools after Aristotle. None of them care about solving the world's problems for their own sake. The pure scientific spirit, the pursuit of knowledge just for knowledge's sake, is gone. That curiosity and wonder that Aristotle mentioned as the driving force of philosophy has disappeared. The motivation for philosophy is no longer a selfless search for truth, but rather the individual's desire to escape life's challenges. Philosophy matters to people only as it impacts their lives. It becomes centered on humanity and the individual. Everything revolves around the person's experience, their fate, and the well-being of their soul. Religion has long been corrupted and is seen as worthless, so philosophy is expected to take on the role of religion, becoming a sanctuary from life's hardships. Thus, it becomes primarily practical and ethical. Other branches of thought are now secondary to ethics. It’s unlike the days when the Greek spirit was strong and vibrant, when thinkers like Xenophanes or Anaxagoras looked up at the sky and innocently wondered about the sun, the stars, and the origins of the world. People's thoughts no longer reach out toward the stars but only inward to themselves. It’s not the mystery of the universe that they ponder, but the mystery of human life.

This subjectivism has as its necessary consequences, one-sidedness, absence of originality, and finally complete scepticism. Since men are no longer interested in the wider problems of the universe, but only in the comparatively petty problems of human life, their outlook becomes exclusively ethical, narrow, and one-sided. He who cannot forget his own self, cannot merge and lose himself in the universe, but looks at all things only as they affect himself, does not give birth to great and universal thoughts. He becomes self-centred, and makes the universe revolve round him. Hence we no longer have now great, universal, all-embracing systems, like those of Plato and Aristotle. Metaphysics, physics, logic, are not studied for their own sakes, but only as preparations for ethics. Narrowness, however, is always compensated by intensity, which in the end becomes fanaticism. Hence the intense earnestness and almost miraculous heights of fanatical asceticism, to which the Stoics attained. And an unbalanced and one-sided philosophy leads to extremes. Such a philosophy, obsessed by a single idea, unrestrained by any consideration for other and equally important factors of truth, regardless of all other claims, pushes its idea pig-headedly to its logical extreme. Such a procedure results in paradoxes and extravagances. Hence the Stoics, if they made duty their watchword, must needs conceive it in {342} the most extreme opposition to all natural impulses, with a sternness unheard of in any previous ethical doctrine save that of the Cynics. Hence the Sceptics, if they lighted on the thought that knowledge is difficult of attainment, must needs rush to the extreme conclusion that any knowledge is utterly impossible. Hence the Neo-Platonists must needs cap all these tendencies by making out a drunken frenzy of the soul to be the true organ of philosophy, and by introducing into speculation all the fantastic paraphernalia of sorcery, demons, and demi-gods. Absence of sanity and balance, then, are characteristics of the last period of Greek philosophy. The serenity and calm of Plato and Aristotle are gone, and in their place we have turgidity and extravagance.

This subjectivism leads to several inevitable consequences: bias, a lack of originality, and ultimately complete skepticism. People are no longer engaged with the broader issues of the universe, focusing instead on the relatively trivial problems of human life, which causes their perspective to become solely ethical, narrow, and biased. Those who can't forget their own selves, and who look at everything only in terms of how it affects them, won't generate great or universal ideas. They become self-centered, making the universe revolve around their own existence. As a result, we lack the grand, all-encompassing systems that figures like Plato and Aristotle created. Subjects like metaphysics, physics, and logic are no longer studied for their own sake, but only as a means to prepare for ethics. However, this narrowness is often balanced by intensity, which can turn into fanaticism. This is why the Stoics achieved such intense seriousness and almost miraculous heights of fanatical asceticism. An unbalanced and one-sided philosophy tends to lead to extremes. Such a philosophy, fixated on a single idea and ignoring other equally important truths, stubbornly pushes its concept to the extreme. This approach results in paradoxes and absurdities. Therefore, the Stoics, if they made duty their central theme, had to conceive it in direct opposition to all natural impulses, with a strictness that was unprecedented in prior ethical teachings except those of the Cynics. Similarly, the Sceptics, upon realizing that knowledge is hard to attain, had to jump to the extreme conclusion that any knowledge is entirely impossible. Consequently, the Neo-Platonists capped all these trends by claiming that a frantic enthusiasm of the soul is the true source of philosophy and by incorporating into their speculations all sorts of fantastical elements like sorcery, demons, and demi-gods. A lack of sanity and balance, then, defines the final phase of Greek philosophy. The tranquility of Plato and Aristotle has vanished, replaced by bombast and excess.

Lack of originality is a second consequence of the subjectivism of the age. Since metaphysics, physics, and logic are not cultivated, except in a purely practical interest, they do not flourish. Instead of advancing in these arenas of thought, the philosophies of the age go backwards. Older systems, long discredited, are revived, and their dead bones triumphantly paraded abroad. The Stoics return to Heracleitus for their physics, Epicurus resurrects the atomism of Democritus. Even in ethics, on which they concentrate all their thought, these post-Aristotelian systems have nothing essentially new to say. Stoicism borrows its principal ideas from the Cynics, Epicureanism from the Cyrenaics. The post-Aristotelians rearrange old thoughts in a new order. They take up the ideas of the past and exaggerate this or that aspect of them. They twist and turn them in all directions, and squeeze them dry for a drop of new life. {343} But in the end nothing new eventuates. Greek thought is finished, and there is nothing new to be got out of it, torture it how they will. From the first Stoic to the last Neo-Platonist, there is no essentially new principle added to philosophy, unless we count as such the sad and jaded ideas which the Neo-Platonists introduced from the East.

Lack of originality is a second result of the subjectivism of the age. Since metaphysics, physics, and logic are only explored from a practical perspective, they don’t thrive. Instead of progressing in these fields of thought, the philosophies of the time retreat. Older systems, long considered outdated, are revived, and their outdated ideas are proudly displayed. The Stoics look back to Heraclitus for their physics, while Epicurus brings back Democritus' atomism. Even in ethics, which they focus all their thoughts on, these post-Aristotelian systems have nothing fundamentally new to offer. Stoicism takes its main ideas from the Cynics, and Epicureanism draws from the Cyrenaics. The post-Aristotelians rearrange old ideas into a new order. They revisit past concepts and emphasize certain aspects. They twist and manipulate these ideas in every way possible, trying to extract even a little bit of new insight. {343} But ultimately, nothing new emerges. Greek thought has come to an end, and no fresh ideas can be derived from it, no matter how much they try. From the first Stoic to the last Neo-Platonist, no genuinely new principles are added to philosophy, unless we consider the disappointing and tired ideas that the Neo-Platonists brought in from the East.

Lastly, subjectivism ends naturally in scepticism, the denial of all knowledge, the rejection of all philosophy. We have already seen, in the Sophists, the phenomenon of subjectivism leading to scepticism. The Sophists made the individual subject the measure of truth and morals, and in the end this meant the denial of truth and morality altogether. So it is now. The subjectivism of the Stoics and Epicureans is followed by the scepticism of Pyrrho and his successors. With them, as with the Sophists, nothing is true or good in itself, but only opinion makes it so.

Lastly, subjectivism naturally leads to skepticism, which denies all knowledge and dismisses philosophy entirely. We've already seen this with the Sophists, where subjectivism turned into skepticism. The Sophists believed that the individual was the standard for truth and morals, which ultimately resulted in rejecting truth and morality altogether. The same is true today. The subjectivism of the Stoics and Epicureans is followed by the skepticism of Pyrrho and his followers. For them, just like with the Sophists, nothing is true or good in itself; it’s only opinion that gives it meaning.


THE STOICS

The Stoics

Zeno of Cyprus, the founder of the Stoic School, a Greek of Phoenician descent, was born about 342 B.C., and died in 270. He is said to have followed philosophy; because he lost all his property in a ship-wreck--a motive characteristic of the age. He came to Athens, and learned philosophy under Crates the Cynic, Stilpo the Megaric, and Polemo the Academic. About 300 B.C. he founded his school at the Stoa Poecile (many-coloured portico) whence the name Stoic. He died by his own hand. He was followed by Cleanthes, and then by Chrysippus, as leaders of the school. Chrysippus was a man of immense productivity and laborious scholarship. He composed over seven hundred books, but all are lost. Though not the founder, he was the chief pillar of Stoicism. The school attracted many adherents, and flourished for many centuries, not only in Greece, but later in Rome, where the most thoughtful writers, such as Marcus Aurelius, Seneca, and Epictetus, counted themselves among its followers.

Zeno of Cyprus, the founder of the Stoic School, was a Greek of Phoenician descent born around 342 B.C. and died in 270 B.C. It's said he turned to philosophy after losing all his possessions in a shipwreck, which was a common reason during that time. He moved to Athens and studied under Crates the Cynic, Stilpo the Megaric, and Polemo the Academic. Around 300 B.C., he established his school at the Stoa Poecile (the multicolored portico), which is how the name Stoic came about. He died by his own hand. He was succeeded by Cleanthes and then Chrysippus as leaders of the school. Chrysippus was incredibly productive and dedicated to scholarship, writing over seven hundred books, though all of them are lost. Although he wasn't the founder, he was a foundational figure for Stoicism. The school drew many followers and thrived for centuries, not just in Greece but also in Rome, where notable thinkers like Marcus Aurelius, Seneca, and Epictetus identified as followers.

We know little for certain as to what share particular Stoics, Zeno, Cleanthes, or Chrysippus, had in the formation of the doctrines of the school. But after Chrysippus the main lines of the doctrine were complete. {345} We shall deal, therefore, with Stoicism as a whole, and not with the special teaching of particular Stoics. The system is divided into three parts, Logic, Physics, and Ethics, of which the first two are entirely subservient to the last. Stoicism is essentially a system of ethics which, however, is guided by a logic as theory of method, and rests upon physics as foundation.

We don’t know for sure how much Zeno, Cleanthes, or Chrysippus influenced the formation of the school's doctrines. But after Chrysippus, the core ideas were well established. {345} So, we will look at Stoicism as a whole instead of focusing on the specific teachings of individual Stoics. The system is divided into three parts: Logic, Physics, and Ethics, with the first two completely serving the last. Stoicism is fundamentally an ethical system, but it's supported by logic as the method and is based on physics as its foundation.


Logic.

Logic.

We may pass over the formal logic of the Stoics, which is, in all essentials, the logic of Aristotle. To this, however, they added a theory, peculiar to themselves, of the origin of knowledge and the criterion of truth. All knowledge, they said, enters the mind through the senses. The mind is a tabula rasa, upon which sense-impressions are inscribed. It may have a certain activity of its own, but this activity is confined exclusively to materials supplied by the physical organs of sense. This theory stands, of course, in sheer opposition to the idealism of Plato, for whom the mind alone was the source of knowledge, the senses being the sources of all illusion and error. The Stoics denied the metaphysical reality of concepts. Concepts are merely ideas in the mind, abstracted from particulars, and have no reality outside consciousness.

We can skip over the formal logic of the Stoics, which is basically the same as Aristotle's logic. However, they added their own unique theory about how knowledge originates and what defines truth. They argued that all knowledge comes into the mind through the senses. The mind is a tabula rasa, where sense impressions are recorded. It might have some activity of its own, but that activity is limited to what the physical senses provide. This theory directly contradicts Plato's idealism, which held that the mind alone is the source of knowledge, viewing the senses as nothing but sources of illusion and error. The Stoics rejected the metaphysical reality of concepts. Concepts are just ideas in the mind, taken from specific instances, and have no reality outside of consciousness.

Since all knowledge is a knowledge of sense-objects, truth is simply the correspondence of our impressions to things. How are we to know whether our ideas are correct copies of things? How distinguish between reality and imagination, dreams, or illusions? What is the criterion of truth? It cannot lie in concepts, since these are of our own making. Nothing is true save {346} sense-impressions, and therefore the criterion of truth must lie in sensation itself. It cannot be in thought, but must be in feeling. Real objects, said the Stoics, produce in us an intense feeling, or conviction, of their reality. The strength and vividness of the image distinguish these real perceptions from a dream or fancy. Hence the sole criterion of truth is this striking conviction, whereby the real forces itself upon our consciousness, and will not be denied. The relapse into complete subjectivity will here be noted. There is no universally grounded criterion of truth. It is based, not on reason, but on feeling. All depends on the subjective convictions of the individual.

Since all knowledge comes from our senses, truth is just how our impressions match up with reality. How can we tell if our ideas accurately reflect things? How do we differentiate between what’s real and what’s imagined, dreamed, or illusory? What defines truth? It can't be found in concepts since those are created by us. Nothing is true except for {346} sense-impressions, so the measure of truth must come from sensation itself. It isn’t found in thought, but in feeling. Real objects, according to the Stoics, evoke a strong sense of their reality in us. The intensity and clarity of the image set these real perceptions apart from dreams or fantasies. Thus, the only measure of truth is this powerful conviction, where the real asserts itself in our awareness and cannot be ignored. We can observe a return to complete subjectivity here. There’s no universally accepted standard of truth. It relies, not on reason, but on feeling. Everything hinges on the subjective beliefs of the individual.


Physics.

Physics.

The fundamental proposition of the Stoic physics is that "nothing incorporeal exists." This materialism coheres with the sensationalism of their doctrine of knowledge. Plato placed knowledge in thought, and reality, therefore, in the Idea. The Stoics, however, place knowledge in physical sensation, and reality, therefore, in what is known by the senses, matter. All things, they said, even the soul, even God himself, are material and nothing more than material. This belief they based upon two main considerations. Firstly, the unity of the world demands it. The world is one, and must issue from one principle. We must have a monism. The idealism of Plato and Aristotle had resolved itself into a futile struggle against the dualism of matter and thought. Since the gulf cannot be bridged from the side of the Idea, we must take our stand on matter, and reduce mind to it. Secondly, body and soul, God and {347} the world, are pairs which act and react upon one another. The body, for example, produces thoughts (sense-impressions) in the soul, the soul produces movements in the body. This would be impossible if both were not of the same substance. The corporeal cannot act on the incorporeal, nor the incorporeal on the corporeal. There is no point of contact. Hence all must be equally corporeal.

The main idea of Stoic physics is that "nothing incorporeal exists." This materialism aligns with their view on knowledge, which is based on sensations. While Plato defined knowledge as something tied to thought and reality as the Idea, the Stoics argue that knowledge comes from physical sensations, making reality what we can perceive with our senses—essentially, matter. They asserted that everything, including the soul and even God, is purely material. They supported this belief with two key arguments. First, the unity of the world requires it; the world is one and must come from a single principle, necessitating a form of monism. The idealistic views of Plato and Aristotle ended up in a pointless conflict between matter and thought. Since we can't connect the two through the Idea, we must focus on matter and consider mind as part of it. Second, body and soul, God and the world, are interconnected and influence each other. For instance, the body can generate thoughts (sense-impressions) in the soul, while the soul can cause movements in the body. This interaction wouldn’t be possible if they were different substances. The physical cannot influence the non-physical, nor the non-physical the physical, as there’s no shared ground. Therefore, everything must be equally physical.

All things being material, what is the original kind of matter, or stuff, out of which the world is made? The Stoics turned to Heracleitus for an answer. Fire is the primordial kind of being, and all things are composed of fire. With this materialism the Stoics combined pantheism. The primal fire is God. God is related to the world exactly as the soul to the body. The human soul is likewise fire, and comes from the divine fire. It permeates and penetrates the entire body, and, in order that its interpenetration might be regarded as complete, the Stoics denied the impenetrability of matter. Just as the soul-fire permeates the whole body, so God, the primal fire, pervades the entire world. He is the soul of the world. The world is His body.

All things are material, so what is the original kind of matter or stuff that makes up the world? The Stoics looked to Heraclitus for an answer. Fire is the fundamental essence, and everything is made from fire. The Stoics blended this materialism with pantheism. The primal fire is God. God is connected to the world just as the soul is to the body. The human soul is also fire and comes from the divine fire. It spreads throughout the entire body, and to emphasize this complete connection, the Stoics rejected the idea that matter is impenetrable. Just as the soul-fire fills the whole body, so does God, the primal fire, fill the entire world. He is the soul of the world. The world is His body.

But in spite of this materialism, the Stoics averred that God is absolute reason. This is not a return to idealism. It does not imply the incorporeality of God. For reason, like all else, is material. It means simply that the divine fire is a rational element. Since God is reason, it follows that the world is governed by reason, and this means two things. It means, firstly, that there is purpose in the world, and therefore, order, harmony, beauty, and design. Secondly, since reason is law as opposed to the lawless, it means that the universe is {348} subject to the absolute sway of law, is governed by the rigorous necessity of cause and effect.

But despite this materialism, the Stoics asserted that God is absolute reason. This isn’t a return to idealism. It doesn’t suggest that God is non-physical. Just like everything else, reason is material. It simply means that the divine essence is a rational element. Since God embodies reason, it follows that the world is governed by reason, which implies two things. First, it means that there is purpose in the world, leading to order, harmony, beauty, and design. Second, since reason represents law as opposed to chaos, it indicates that the universe is {348} subject to the absolute authority of law and is governed by the strict necessity of cause and effect.

Hence the individual is not free. There can be no true freedom of the will in a world governed by necessity. We may, without harm, say that we choose to do this or that, that our acts are voluntary. But such phrases merely mean that we assent to what we do. What we do is none the less governed by causes, and therefore by necessity.

Therefore, the individual is not free. There can be no real freedom of choice in a world ruled by necessity. We might say that we choose to do one thing or another and that our actions are voluntary. But these expressions simply mean that we agree with what we do. What we do is still driven by causes, and thus by necessity.

The world-process is circular. God changes the fiery substance of himself first into air, then water, then earth. So the world arises. But it will be ended by a conflagration in which all things will return into the primal fire. Thereafter, at a pre-ordained time, God will again transmute himself into a world. It follows from the law of necessity that the course taken by this second, and every subsequent, world, will be identical in every way with the course taken by the first world. The process goes on for ever, and nothing new ever happens. The history of each successive world is the same as that of all the others down to the minutest details.

The process of the world is circular. God transforms his fiery essence first into air, then into water, and finally into earth. This is how the world comes into existence. But it will end in a fire that consumes everything, returning all things to the original fire. After a set time, God will again change himself into a world. According to the law of necessity, the path taken by this second world, and every subsequent one, will be exactly the same as that of the first world. This cycle continues forever, and nothing new ever happens. The history of each new world mirrors that of all previous ones down to the smallest details.

The human soul is part of the divine fire, and proceeds into man from God. Hence it is a rational soul, and this is a point of cardinal importance in connexion with the Stoic ethics. But the soul of each individual does not come direct from God. The divine fire was breathed into the first man, and thereafter passes from parent to child in the act of procreation. After death, all souls, according to some, but only the souls of the good, according to others, continue in individual existence until the general conflagration in which they, and all else, return to God.

The human soul is a part of the divine fire and comes from God. Because of this, it is a rational soul, which is crucial when discussing Stoic ethics. However, each individual’s soul doesn’t come directly from God. The divine fire was breathed into the first human, and from then on, it is passed from parent to child through procreation. After death, some believe that all souls continue to exist individually until the final destruction, while others believe that only the souls of the good persist until they, along with everything else, return to God.


Ethics.

Ethics.

The Stoic ethical teaching is based upon two principles already developed in their physics; first, that the universe is governed by absolute law, which admits of no exceptions; and second, that the essential nature of man is reason. Both are summed up in the famous Stoic maxim, "Live according to nature." For this maxim has two aspects. It means, in the first place, that men should conform themselves to nature in the wider sense, that is, to the laws of the universe, and secondly, that they should conform their actions to nature in the narrower sense, to their own essential nature, reason. These two expressions mean, for the Stoics, the same thing. For the universe is governed not only by law, but by the law of reason, and man in following his own rational nature is ipso facto conforming himself to the laws of the larger world. In a sense, of course, there is no possibility of man's disobeying the laws of nature, for he, like all else in the world, acts of necessity. And it might be asked, what is the use of exhorting a man to obey the laws of the universe, when, as part of the great mechanism of the world, he cannot by any possibility do anything else? It is not to be supposed that a genuine solution of this difficulty is to be found in Stoic philosophy. They urged, however, that, though man will in any case do as the necessity of the world compels him, it is given to him alone, not merely to obey the law, but to assent to his own obedience, to follow the law consciously and deliberately, as only a rational being can.

The Stoic ethical teaching is based on two principles already developed in their physics: first, that the universe operates under absolute law with no exceptions, and second, that human beings are essentially rational. Both principles are captured in the well-known Stoic saying, "Live according to nature." This saying has two aspects. First, it suggests that people should align themselves with nature in a broad sense, meaning they should adhere to the laws of the universe. Second, it implies that they should align their actions with their own essential nature, reason. For the Stoics, these two ideas are interconnected. The universe is governed not only by law but by the law of reason, and when individuals follow their rational nature, they are, in fact, aligning themselves with the laws of the larger world. In a way, there is no possibility for people to disobey the laws of nature, as they, like everything else in the world, act out of necessity. One might wonder what the point is in encouraging someone to obey the laws of the universe when, as part of the grand mechanism of the world, they have no choice but to do so. Stoic philosophy doesn't necessarily provide a complete solution to this issue. However, they maintained that while people will inevitably act as the world’s necessity dictates, it is unique to them to not only obey the law but also to consciously acknowledge their obedience, following the law with awareness and intention, as only a rational being can.

Virtue, then, is the life according to reason. Morality is simply rational action. It is the universal reason which is to govern our lives, not the caprice and self-will {350} of the individual. The wise man consciously subordinates his life to the life of the whole universe, and recognises himself as merely a cog in the great machine. Now the definition of morality as the life according to reason is not a principle peculiar to the Stoics. Both Plato and Aristotle taught the same. In fact, as we have already seen, to found morality upon reason, and not upon the particular foibles, feelings, or intuitions, of the individual self, is the basis of every genuine ethic. But what was peculiar to the Stoics was the narrow and one-sided interpretation which they gave to this principle. Aristotle had taught that the essential nature of man is reason, and that morality consists in following this, his essential nature. But he recognized that the passions and appetites have their place in the human organism. He did not demand their suppression, but merely their control by reason. But the Stoics looked upon the passions as essentially irrational, and demanded their complete extirpation. They envisaged life as a battle against the passions, in which the latter had to be completely annihilated. Hence their ethical views end in a rigorous and unbalanced asceticism.

Virtue, then, is living according to reason. Morality is just rational action. It's universal reason that should guide our lives, not the whims and desires of the individual. The wise person consciously aligns their life with the life of the entire universe and sees themselves as just a small part of the greater whole. The idea of morality as living according to reason is not unique to the Stoics. Both Plato and Aristotle taught the same. In fact, as we’ve already noted, basing morality on reason rather than on personal quirks, feelings, or instincts is the foundation of any true ethical system. However, what was unique to the Stoics was their narrow and extreme interpretation of this principle. Aristotle taught that the essential nature of humanity is reason, and that morality consists of following that essential nature. But he acknowledged that passions and desires have their place within the human experience. He didn’t call for their suppression, only for them to be controlled by reason. In contrast, the Stoics viewed passions as entirely irrational and demanded their total eradication. They saw life as a struggle against passions, which needed to be completely destroyed. As a result, their ethical views led to a strict and unbalanced asceticism.

Aristotle, in his broad and moderate way, though he believed virtue alone to possess intrinsic value, yet allowed to external goods and circumstances a place in the scheme of life. The Stoics asserted that virtue alone is good, vice alone evil, and that all else is absolutely indifferent. Poverty, sickness, pain, and death, are not evils. Riches, health, pleasure, and life, are not goods. A man may commit suicide, for in destroying his life he destroys nothing of value. Above all, pleasure is not a good. One ought not to seek pleasure. Virtue is {351} the only happiness. And man must be virtuous, not for the sake of pleasure, but for the sake of duty. And since virtue alone is good, vice alone evil, there followed the further paradox that all virtues are equally good, and all vices equally evil. There are no degrees.

Aristotle, in his broad and moderate perspective, believed that while virtue has intrinsic value, external goods and circumstances also have their place in life. The Stoics claimed that virtue is the only true good, vice the only true evil, and everything else is entirely indifferent. Poverty, illness, pain, and death are not evils. Wealth, health, pleasure, and life are not goods. A person may choose to end their life, as doing so does not destroy anything of value. Most importantly, pleasure is not a good. One should not pursue pleasure. Virtue is {351} the only source of happiness. A person must be virtuous not for pleasure, but out of a sense of duty. And since virtue is the only good and vice the only evil, this leads to the paradox that all virtues are equally good, and all vices are equally evil. There are no degrees.

Virtue is founded upon reason, and so upon knowledge. Hence the importance of science, physics, logic, which are valued not for themselves, but because they are the foundations of morality. The prime virtue, and the root of all other virtues, is therefore wisdom. The wise man is synonymous with the good man. From the root-virtue, wisdom, spring the four cardinal virtues, insight, bravery, self-control, justice. But since all virtues have one root, he who possesses wisdom possesses all virtue, he who lacks it lacks all. A man is either wholly virtuous, or wholly vicious. The world is divided into wise men and fools, the former perfectly good, the latter absolutely evil. There is nothing between the two. There is no such thing as a gradual transition from one to the other. Conversion must be instantaneous. The wise man is perfect, has all happiness, freedom, riches, beauty. He alone is the perfect king, statesman, poet, prophet, orator, critic, physician. The fool has all vice, all misery, all ugliness, all poverty. And every man is one or the other. Asked where such a wise man was to be found, the Stoics pointed doubtfully at Socrates and Diogenes the Cynic. The number of the wise, they thought, is small, and is continually growing smaller. The world, which they painted in the blackest colours as a sea of vice and misery, grows steadily worse.

Virtue is based on reason, which is built on knowledge. That’s why science, physics, and logic are important; they are valued not for their own sake, but because they form the basis of morality. The most important virtue, the root of all other virtues, is wisdom. A wise person is the same as a good person. From the root virtue of wisdom come the four cardinal virtues: insight, bravery, self-control, and justice. But since all virtues stem from one root, anyone who has wisdom has all virtues, and anyone who lacks it lacks all virtues. A person is either completely virtuous or completely wicked. The world is split into wise people and fools; the wise are perfectly good, while the fools are entirely evil. There’s nothing in between. There’s no gradual change from one to the other. A conversion has to be instant. The wise person is perfect, possessing all happiness, freedom, wealth, and beauty. They are the perfect king, statesman, poet, prophet, orator, critic, and doctor. The fool has all vices, all misery, all ugliness, and all poverty. Every person is one or the other. When asked where to find such a wise person, the Stoics hesitantly pointed to Socrates and Diogenes the Cynic. They believed the number of wise individuals is small and is continually decreasing. They depicted the world in the darkest terms as a sea of vice and misery, getting steadily worse.

In all this we easily recognize the features of a resuscitated Cynicism. But the Stoics modified and softened {352} the harsh outlines of Cynicism, and rounded off its angles. To do this meant inconsistency. It meant that they first laid down harsh principles, and then proceeded to tone them down, to explain them away, to admit exceptions. Such inconsistency the Stoics accepted with their habitual cheerfulness. This process of toning down their first harsh utterances took place mainly in three ways. In the first place, they modified their principle of the complete extirpation of the passions. Since this is impossible, and, if possible, could only lead to immovable inactivity, they admitted that the wise man might exhibit certain mild and rational emotions, and that the roots of the passions might be found in him, though he never allowed them to grow. In the second place, they modified their principle that all else, save virtue and vice, is indifferent. Such a view is unreal, and out of accord with life. Hence the Stoics, with a masterly disregard of consistency, stuck to the principle, and yet declared that among things indifferent some are preferable to others. If the wise man has the choice between health and sickness, he will choose the former. Indifferent things were divided into three classes, those to be preferred, those to be avoided, and those which are absolutely indifferent. In the third place, the Stoics toned down the principle that men are either wholly good, or wholly evil. The famous heroes and statesmen of history, though fools, are yet polluted with the common vices of mankind less than others. Moreover, what were the Stoics to say about themselves? Were they wise men or fools? They hesitated to claim perfection, to put themselves on a level with Socrates and Diogenes. Yet they could not bring themselves to admit that there was {353} no difference between themselves and the common herd. They were "proficients," and, if not absolutely wise, approximated to wisdom.

In all this, we can easily see the traits of a revived Cynicism. But the Stoics adjusted and softened the sharp edges of Cynicism, smoothing out its roughness. This meant inconsistency. It meant they initially set down strict principles and then went on to soften them, rationalize them, and acknowledge exceptions. The Stoics accepted this inconsistency with their usual good humor. They mainly toned down their initial harsh statements in three ways. First, they revised their principle advocating the complete removal of passions. Since this is impossible and would lead to total inactivity if it were, they acknowledged that a wise person might show certain mild and rational emotions, and that the roots of passions could exist within them, though they never allowed them to flourish. Second, they changed their stance that everything except virtue and vice is indifferent. This view is unrealistic and doesn't align with real life. So the Stoics, with impressive disregard for consistency, held onto the principle but also stated that among indifferent things, some are better than others. If the wise person had to choose between health and sickness, they would choose health. Indifferent things were divided into three categories: those to be preferred, those to be avoided, and those that are completely indifferent. Third, the Stoics softened the idea that people are either completely good or completely evil. The famous heroes and statesmen of history, while foolish, generally have fewer common vices than others. Moreover, what could the Stoics say about themselves? Were they wise or foolish? They were reluctant to claim perfection or place themselves on the same level as Socrates and Diogenes. Yet, they couldn't bring themselves to say there was no difference between them and the average person. They considered themselves "proficients," and if not fully wise, they were close to wisdom.

If the Stoics were thus merely less consistent Cynics, and originated nothing in the doctrines of physics and ethics so far considered, yet of one idea at least they can claim to be the inventors. This was the idea of cosmopolitanism. This they deduced from two grounds. Firstly, the universe is one, proceeds from one God, is ordered by one law, and forms one system. Secondly, however much men may differ in unessentials, they share their essential nature, their reason, in common. Hence all men are of one stock, as rational beings, and should form one State. The division of mankind into warring States is irrational and absurd. The wise man is not a citizen of this or that State. He is a citizen of the world.

If the Stoics were just less consistent Cynics and didn’t add anything new to the ideas of physics and ethics we've discussed, they can still claim to have invented one concept: cosmopolitanism. They based this idea on two points. First, the universe is one; it comes from one God, follows one law, and operates as one system. Second, no matter how much people may differ in unimportant ways, they share a common essential nature: their reason. Therefore, all humans are from the same origin as rational beings and should belong to one State. Dividing humanity into fighting States is irrational and ridiculous. The wise person isn’t a citizen of one State or another; they are a citizen of the world.

This is, however, only an application of principles already asserted. The Stoics produced no essentially new thought, in physics, or in ethics. Their entire stock of ideas is but a new combination of ideas already developed by their predecessors. They were narrow, extreme, over-rigorous, and one-sided. Their truths are all half-truths. And they regarded philosophy too subjectively. What alone interested them was the question, how am I to live? Yet in spite of these defects, there is undoubtedly something grand and noble about their zeal for duty, their exaltation above all that is petty and paltry, their uncompromising contempt for all lower ends. Their merit, says Schwegler, was that "in an age of ruin they held fast by the moral idea."

This is just an application of principles that have already been stated. The Stoics didn't introduce any fundamentally new ideas in physics or ethics. Their entire range of concepts is merely a new arrangement of ideas that their predecessors had already explored. They were narrow-minded, extreme, overly strict, and one-sided. Their truths are all partial truths. They approached philosophy too subjectively. What mattered to them most was the question, how should I live? Yet, despite these shortcomings, there is definitely something grand and admirable about their commitment to duty, their rise above everything that is small and trivial, and their unwavering disdain for all lesser goals. Their merit, as Schwegler puts it, was that "in an age of ruin they held fast by the moral idea."


THE EPICUREANS

The Epicureans

Epicurus was born at Samos in 342 B.C. He founded his school a year or two before Zeno founded the Stoa, so that the two schools from the first ran parallel in time. The school of Epicurus lasted over six centuries. Epicurus early became acquainted with the atomism of Democritus, but his learning in earlier systems of philosophy does not appear to have been extensive. He was a man of estimable life and character. He founded his school in 306 B.C. The Epicurean philosophy was both founded and completed by him. No subsequent Epicurean to any appreciable extent added to or altered the doctrines laid down by the founder.

Epicurus was born on Samos in 342 B.C. He started his school a year or two before Zeno established the Stoa, so the two schools developed around the same time. The school of Epicurus lasted for over six centuries. Epicurus became familiar with Democritus' atomism early on, but he didn't seem to have a wide knowledge of earlier philosophical systems. He was a man of admirable life and character. He founded his school in 306 B.C. The Epicurean philosophy was both established and completed by him. No later Epicurean significantly added to or changed the doctrines set forth by the founder.

The Epicurean system is even more purely practical in tendency than the Stoic. In spite of the fact that Stoicism subordinates logic and physics to ethics, yet the diligence and care which the Stoics bestowed upon such doctrines as those of the criterion of truth, the nature of the world, the soul, and so on, afford evidence of a genuine, if subordinate, interest in these subjects. Epicurus likewise divided his system into logic (which he called canonic), physics, and ethics, yet the two former branches of thought are pursued with an obvious carelessness and absence of interest. It is evident that learned {355} discussions bored Epicurus. His system is amiable and shallow. Knowledge for its own sake is not desired. Mathematics, he said, are useless, because they have no connexion with life. The logic, or canonic, we may pass over completely, as possessing no elements of interest, and come at once to the physics.

The Epicurean system is even more practical than the Stoic one. Even though Stoicism prioritizes ethics over logic and physics, the Stoics still showed a genuine, if secondary, interest in topics like the criterion of truth, the nature of the world, and the soul through the care and attention they gave to these doctrines. Epicurus also divided his system into logic (which he called canonic), physics, and ethics, but he clearly approached the first two areas with a noticeable lack of interest. It’s clear that academic discussions bored Epicurus. His system is friendly but shallow. He did not seek knowledge just for the sake of knowledge. He argued that mathematics is useless because it doesn’t connect to real life. We can completely skip over logic, or canonic, since it has no interesting elements, and go straight to physics.


Physics.

Physics.

Physics interests Epicurus only from one point of view--its power to banish superstitious fear from the minds of men. All supernatural religion, he thought, operates for the most part upon mankind by means of fear. Men are afraid of the gods, afraid of retribution, afraid of death because of the stories of what comes after death. This incessant fear and anxiety is one of the chief causes of the unhappiness of men. Destroy it, and we have at least got rid of the prime hindrance to human happiness. We can only do this by means of a suitable doctrine of physics. What is necessary is to be able to regard the world as a piece of mechanism, governed solely by natural causes, without any interference by supernatural beings, in which man is free to find his happiness how and when he will, without being frightened by the bogeys of popular religion. For though the world is ruled mechanically, man, thought Epicurus in opposition to the Stoics, possesses free will, and the problem of philosophy is to ascertain how he can best use this gift in a world otherwise mechanically governed. What he required, therefore, was a purely mechanical philosophy. To invent such a philosophy for himself was a task not suited to his indolence, and for which he could not pretend to possess the necessary {356} qualifications. Therefore he searched the past, and soon found what he wanted in the atomism of Democritus. This, as an entirely mechanical philosophy, perfectly suited his ends, and the pragmatic spirit in which he chose his beliefs, not on any abstract grounds of their objective truth, but on the basis of his subjective needs and personal wishes, will be noted. It is a sign of the times. When truth comes to be regarded as something that men may construct in accordance with their real or imagined needs, and not in accordance with any objective standard, we are well advanced upon the downward path of decay. Epicurus, therefore, adopted the atomism of Democritus en bloc, or with trifling modifications. All things are composed of atoms and the void. Atoms differ only in shape and weight, not in quality. They fall eternally through the void. By virtue of free will, they deviate infinitesimally from the perpendicular in their fall, and so clash against one another. This, of course, is an invention of Epicurus, and formed no part of the doctrine of Democritus. It might be expected of Epicurus that his modifications would not be improvements. In the present case, the attribution of free will to the atoms adversely affects the logical consistency of the mechanical theory. From the collision of atoms arises a whirling movement out of which the world emerges. Not only the world, but all individual phenomena, are to be explained mechanically. Teleology is rigorously excluded. In any particular case, however, Epicurus is not interested to know what particular causes determine a phenomenon. It is enough for him to be sure that it is wholly determined by mechanical causes, and that supernatural agencies are excluded.

Physics interests Epicurus from only one perspective—its ability to eliminate superstitious fear from people's minds. He believed that all forms of supernatural religion largely affect humanity through fear. People are scared of the gods, scared of punishment, scared of death because of the tales about what happens after. This constant fear and anxiety is one of the main reasons for human unhappiness. If we can eliminate this fear, we remove a major obstacle to happiness. We can achieve this with a proper understanding of physics. It's essential to view the world as a machine, controlled entirely by natural laws, without interference from supernatural beings, allowing individuals to pursue their happiness freely, unafraid of the nightmares of traditional religion. Even though the world operates mechanically, Epicurus, in contrast to the Stoics, believed that humans have free will, and the challenge of philosophy is to discover how to make the best use of this gift in a world dominated by mechanical processes. He therefore needed a purely mechanical philosophy. Creating such a philosophy himself was not in line with his lazy nature, and he knew he lacked the necessary qualifications. So, he looked to the past and quickly found what he was looking for in Democritus's atomism. This philosophical approach, entirely mechanical, matched his needs perfectly, and his pragmatic way of choosing beliefs—not based on their objective truth but according to his personal needs and desires—should be noted. It reflects the era. When truth is seen as something people can construct to fit their real or imagined needs, rather than adhering to any objective standard, we are well on the path of decline. Therefore, Epicurus adopted the atomism of Democritus almost entirely, with only minor changes. Everything is made up of atoms and empty space. Atoms vary only in shape and weight, not in quality. They continuously fall through the void. Due to free will, they make tiny deviations from a straight path in their descent, leading them to collide with one another. This idea of free will affecting atoms is something Epicurus invented and was not part of Democritus's theory. It might be expected that Epicurus's changes wouldn't make things better. In this instance, attributing free will to atoms undermines the logical consistency of the mechanical theory. From the collisions of atoms springs a swirling motion from which the world arises. Both the world and all individual events are to be explained mechanically. Teleology is strictly ruled out. However, Epicurus is not concerned with which specific causes explain an event. It's sufficient for him to know that it is entirely caused by mechanical factors, and that supernatural influences are not involved.

The soul being composed of atoms which are scattered at death, a future life is not to be thought of. But this is to be regarded as the greatest blessing. It frees us from the fear of death, and the fear of a hereafter. Death is not an evil. For if death is, we are not; if we are, death is not. When death comes we shall not feel it, for is it not the end of all feeling and consciousness? And there is no reason to fear now what we know that we shall not feel when it comes.

The soul is made up of atoms that disperse when we die, so we shouldn't think about an afterlife. This is actually a blessing because it frees us from the fear of death and what comes after it. Death isn't a bad thing. If death exists, then we do not; and if we exist, then death does not. When death arrives, we won’t feel it because it marks the end of all feeling and awareness. There’s really no reason to fear something we know we won't experience when it happens.

Having thus disposed of the fear of retribution in a future life, Epicurus proceeds to dispose of the fear of the interference of the gods in this life. One might have expected that Epicurus would for this purpose have embraced atheism. But he does not deny the existence of the gods. On the contrary, he believed that there are innumerable gods. They have the form of men, because that is the most beautiful of all forms. They have distinctions in sex. They eat, drink, and talk Greek. Their bodies are composed of a substance like light. But though Epicurus allows them to exist, he is careful to disarm them, and to rob them of their fears. They live in the interstellar spaces, an immortal, calm, and blessed existence. They do not intervene in the affairs of the world, because they are perfectly happy. Why should they burden themselves with the control of that which nowise concerns them? Theirs is the beatitude of a wholly untroubled joy.

Having addressed the fear of punishment in the afterlife, Epicurus goes on to tackle the fear of divine interference in our lives. One might think he would reject the idea of gods entirely, but he doesn’t deny their existence. In fact, he believes there are countless gods. They take on human form because it’s the most beautiful shape. They have genders, eat, drink, and speak Greek. Their bodies are made of a substance similar to light. However, while Epicurus acknowledges their existence, he makes sure to disarm them of any intimidating qualities. They reside in the vastness of space, living an eternal, peaceful, and blissful life. They don’t involve themselves in worldly matters because they are perfectly content. Why would they bother themselves with things that don’t concern them? Their existence is one of complete, untroubled joy.

  "Immortal are they, clothed with powers,
     Not to be comforted at all,
  Lords over all the fruitless hours,
     Too great to appease, too high to appal,
        Too far to call."
  [Footnote 17]
"Immortal are they, dressed in power,  
     Not to be comforted at all,  
  Masters of all the wasted hours,  
     Too great to satisfy, too high to frighten,  
        Too far to reach."  
  [Footnote 17]  

[Footnote 17: A. C. Swinburne's Felise.]

[Footnote 17: A. C. Swinburne's Felise.]

Man, therefore, freed from the fear of death and the fear of the gods, has no duty save to live as happily as he can during his brief space upon earth. We can quit the realm of physics with a light heart, and turn to what alone truly matters, ethics, the consideration of how man ought to conduct his life.

Man, therefore, free from the fear of death and the fear of the gods, has no obligation except to live as happily as possible during his short time on earth. We can leave the world of physics with a light heart and focus on what truly matters, which is ethics, the thought of how man should live his life.


Ethics.

Ethics.

If the Stoics were the intellectual successors of the Cynics, the Epicureans bear the same relation to the Cyrenaics. Like Aristippus, they founded morality upon pleasure, but they differ because they developed a purer and nobler conception of pleasure than the Cyrenaics had known. Pleasure alone is an end in itself. It is the only good. Pain is the only evil. Morality, therefore, is an activity which yields pleasure. Virtue has no value on its own account, but derives its value from the pleasure which accompanies it.

If the Stoics were the intellectual successors of the Cynics, the Epicureans have the same relationship to the Cyrenaics. Like Aristippus, they based morality on pleasure, but they differ because they developed a purer and more refined idea of pleasure than the Cyrenaics had understood. Pleasure is an end in itself. It is the only good. Pain is the only evil. Therefore, morality is an activity that brings pleasure. Virtue doesn't have value on its own; it gets its value from the pleasure that comes with it.

This is the only foundation which Epicurus could find, or desired to find, for moral activity. This is his only ethical principle. The rest of the Epicurean ethics consists in the interpretation of the idea of pleasure. And, firstly, by pleasure Epicurus did not mean, as the Cyrenaics did, merely the pleasure of the moment, whether physical or mental. He meant the pleasure that endures throughout a lifetime, a happy life. Hence we are not to allow ourselves to be enslaved by any particular pleasure or desire. We must master our appetites. We must often forego a pleasure if it leads in the end to greater pain. We must be ready to undergo pain for the sake of a greater pleasure to come.

This is the only basis that Epicurus could find, or wanted to find, for moral actions. This is his sole ethical principle. The rest of Epicurean ethics revolves around the interpretation of the concept of pleasure. First off, when Epicurus talks about pleasure, he isn’t referring to just the fleeting pleasure of the moment, whether physical or mental, like the Cyrenaics did. He is talking about the pleasure that lasts throughout a lifetime—a happy life. Therefore, we shouldn’t let ourselves be enslaved by any specific pleasure or desire. We need to gain control over our cravings. We often have to give up a pleasure if it ultimately leads to greater pain. We should be willing to endure pain for the sake of a greater pleasure that lies ahead.

And it was just for this reason, secondly, that the {359} Epicureans regarded spiritual and mental pleasures as far more important than those of the body. For the body feels pleasure and pain only while they last. The body has in itself neither memory nor fore-knowledge. It is the mind which remembers and foresees. And by far the most potent pleasures and pains are those of remembrance and anticipation. A physical pleasure is a pleasure to the body only now. But the anticipation of a future pain is mental anxiety, the remembrance of a past joy is a present delight. Hence what is to be aimed at above all is a calm untroubled mind, for the pleasures of the body are ephemeral, those of the spirit enduring. The Epicureans, like the Stoics, preached the necessity of superiority to bodily pains and external circumstances. So a man must not depend for his happiness upon externals; he must have his blessedness in his own self. The wise man can be happy even in bodily torment, for in the inner tranquillity of his soul he possesses a happiness which far outweighs any bodily pain. Yet innocent pleasures of sense are neither forbidden, nor to be despised. The wise man will enjoy whatever he can without harm. Of all mental pleasures the Epicureans laid, perhaps, most stress upon friendship. The school was not merely a collection of fellow-philosophers, but above all a society of friends.

And this is why, secondly, the {359} Epicureans considered spiritual and mental pleasures to be much more important than physical ones. The body only experiences pleasure and pain while they're happening. It doesn't have memory or the ability to anticipate. It's the mind that remembers and looks ahead. The strongest pleasures and pains come from memory and anticipation. Physical pleasure only benefits the body in the moment. But thinking about a future pain creates mental anxiety, and remembering a past joy brings present delight. Therefore, the main goal should be a calm and untroubled mind, because bodily pleasures are fleeting, while spiritual ones last. The Epicureans, like the Stoics, emphasized the need to rise above physical pains and outside circumstances. A person shouldn't rely on external factors for happiness; true blessedness comes from within. A wise person can find happiness even in physical suffering because, in the inner peace of their soul, they carry a joy that far surpasses any bodily pain. However, innocent sensory pleasures are neither prohibited nor to be looked down upon. A wise person will enjoy whatever they can without causing harm. Of all mental pleasures, the Epicureans placed perhaps the most emphasis on friendship. Their school was not just a group of fellow philosophers, but primarily a community of friends.

Thirdly, the Epicurean ideal of pleasure tended rather towards a negative than a positive conception of it. It was not the state of enjoyment that they aimed at, much less the excitement of the feelings. Not the feverish pleasures of the world constituted their ideal. They aimed rather at a negative absence of pain, at tranquillity, quiet calm, repose of spirit, undisturbed by fears and {360} anxieties. As so often with men whose ideal is pleasure, their view of the world was tinged with a gentle and even luxurious pessimism. Positive happiness is beyond the reach of mortals. All that man can hope for is to avoid pain, and to live in quiet contentment.

Thirdly, the Epicurean idea of pleasure leaned more toward a negative perspective than a positive one. They weren't focused on enjoying life or feeling excited. Their ideal wasn't based on the intense pleasures of the world. Instead, they sought a state of not feeling pain, characterized by tranquility, calmness, and a peaceful mind, free from fears and {360} anxieties. Like many who pursue pleasure as their ideal, their outlook on life had a touch of gentle and even luxurious pessimism. True happiness is out of reach for humans. All we can really hope for is to avoid pain and to live in quiet contentment.

Fourthly, pleasure does not consist in the multiplication of needs and their subsequent satisfaction. The multiplication of wants only renders it more difficult to satisfy them. It complicates life without adding to happiness. We should have as few needs as possible. Epicurus himself lived a simple life, and advised his followers to do the same. The wise man, he said, living on bread and water, could vie with Zeus himself in happiness. Simplicity, cheerfulness, moderation, temperance, are the best means to happiness. The majority of human wants, and the example of the thirst for fame is quoted, are entirely unnecessary and useless.

Fourth, pleasure doesn't come from multiplying our needs and then satisfying them. Having more wants just makes it harder to meet them. It complicates life without increasing happiness. We should aim to have as few needs as possible. Epicurus lived a simple life and encouraged his followers to do the same. He said that a wise person living on just bread and water could be as happy as Zeus. Simplicity, cheerfulness, moderation, and temperance are the best paths to happiness. Most human wants, like the desire for fame, are completely unnecessary and unhelpful.

Lastly, the Epicurean ideal, though containing no possibility of an exalted nobility, was yet by no means entirely selfish. A kindly, benevolent temper appeared in these men. It is pleasanter, they said, to do a kindness than to receive one. There is little of the stern stuff of heroes, but there is much that is gentle and lovable, in the amiable moralizings of these butterfly-philosophers.

Lastly, the Epicurean ideal, while not allowing for any kind of high nobility, was still not completely selfish. These individuals showed a kind and caring attitude. They believed it was more enjoyable to do a good deed than to receive one. There's not much of the tough stuff of heroes, but a lot that is gentle and lovable in the friendly reflections of these light-hearted thinkers.


THE SCEPTICS

THE SKEPTICS

Scepticism is a semi-technical term in philosophy, and means the doctrine which doubts or denies the possibility of knowledge. It is thus destructive of philosophy, since philosophy purports to be a form of knowledge. Scepticism appears and reappears at intervals in the history of thought. We have already met with it among the Sophists. When Gorgias said that, if anything exists, it cannot be known, this was a direct expression of the sceptical spirit. And the Protagorean "Man is the measure of all things" amounts to the same thing, for it implies that man can only know things as they appear to him, and not as they are in themselves. In modern times the most noted sceptic was David Hume, who attempted to show that the most fundamental categories of thought, such as substance and causality, are illusory, and thereby to undermine the fabric of knowledge. Subjectivism usually ends in scepticism. For knowledge is the relation of subject and object, and to lay exclusive emphasis upon one of its terms, the subject, ignoring the object, leads to the denial of the reality of everything except that which appears to the subject. This was so with the Sophists. And now we have the reappearance of a similar {362} phenomenon. The Sceptics, of whom we are about to treat, made their appearance at about the same time as the Stoics and Epicureans. The subjective tendencies of these latter schools find their logical conclusion in the Sceptics. Scepticism makes its appearance usually, but not always, when the spiritual forces of a race are in decay. When its spiritual and intellectual impulses are spent, the spirit flags, grows weary, loses confidence, begins to doubt its power of finding truth; and the despair of truth is scepticism.

Skepticism is a somewhat technical term in philosophy, referring to the belief that knowledge is doubtful or impossible. It undermines philosophy itself, as philosophy claims to be a form of knowledge. Skepticism surfaces at various points in the history of thought. We've already seen it with the Sophists. When Gorgias stated that if anything exists, it can't be known, it was a direct expression of skepticism. Similarly, Protagoras's claim that "Man is the measure of all things" suggests that people can only know things as they seem to them, not as they truly are. In modern times, the most famous skeptic was David Hume, who tried to demonstrate that the most basic categories of thought, like substance and causality, are illusions, thus challenging the foundation of knowledge. Subjectivism often leads to skepticism. Knowledge is the relationship between subject and object, and if one focuses solely on the subject while ignoring the object, it results in denying the reality of everything except what appears to the subject. This was the case with the Sophists. Now, we see a similar {362} phenomenon reemerging. The Skeptics, whom we are about to discuss, emerged around the same time as the Stoics and Epicureans. The subjective tendencies of these later schools logically lead to skepticism. Skepticism often arises, though not always, when a society's spiritual forces are in decline. When its spiritual and intellectual energy is depleted, the spirit weakens, becomes fatigued, loses confidence, and starts to question its ability to uncover truth; the despair over finding truth is what leads to skepticism.


Pyrrho.

Pyrrho.

The first to introduce a thorough-going scepticism among the Greeks was Pyrrho. He was born about 360 B.C., and was originally a painter. He took part in the Indian expedition of Alexander the Great. He left no writings, and we owe our knowledge of his thoughts chiefly to his disciple Timon of Phlius. His philosophy, in common with all post-Aristotelian systems, is purely practical in its outlook. Scepticism, the denial of knowledge, is not posited on account of its speculative interest, but only because Pyrrho sees in it the road to happiness, and the escape from the calamities of life.

The first person to bring a deep skepticism to the Greeks was Pyrrho. He was born around 360 B.C. and initially worked as a painter. He participated in Alexander the Great's expedition to India. He didn’t write anything himself, and our understanding of his ideas primarily comes from his student Timon of Phlius. His philosophy, like all post-Aristotelian systems, is focused on practical application. Skepticism, which denies knowledge, isn't promoted for its theoretical value, but rather because Pyrrho views it as a path to happiness and a way to escape life's troubles.

The proper course of the sage, said Pyrrho, is to ask himself three questions. Firstly, he must ask what things are and how they are constituted; secondly, how we are related to these things; thirdly, what ought to be our attitude towards them. As to what things are, we can only answer that we know nothing. We only know how things appear to us, but of their inner substance we are ignorant. The same thing appears differently to different people, and therefore it is {363} impossible to know which opinion is right. The diversity of opinion among the wise, as well as among the vulgar, proves this. To every assertion the contradictory assertion can be opposed with equally good grounds, and whatever my opinion, the contrary opinion is believed by somebody else who is quite as clever and competent to judge as I am. Opinion we may have, but certainty and knowledge are impossible. Hence our attitude to things (the third question), ought to be complete suspense of judgment. We can be certain of nothing, not even of the most trivial assertions. Therefore we ought never to make any positive statements on any subject. And the Pyrrhonists were careful to import an element of doubt even into the most trifling assertions which they might make in the course of their daily life. They did not say, "it is so," but "it seems so," or "it appears so to me." Every observation would be prefixed with a "perhaps," or "it may be."

The right approach for the sage, according to Pyrrho, is to ask himself three questions. First, he should ask what things are and what they consist of; second, how we relate to these things; and third, what our mindset towards them should be. As for what things are, we can only say that we know nothing. We only understand how things appear to us, but we’re clueless about their true essence. The same thing looks different to different people, so it’s {363} impossible to know which opinion is correct. The variety of opinions among both the wise and the ordinary proves this. To every claim, a contradictory claim can be made with equally valid reasons, and no matter what I believe, someone else who is just as smart and capable of judgment holds the opposite belief. We can have opinions, but certainty and knowledge are out of reach. Therefore, our attitude towards things (the third question) should be complete suspension of judgment. We can’t be sure of anything, not even the most trivial statements. Thus, we should never make any positive claims about any subject. The Pyrrhonists were careful to introduce an element of doubt even into the simplest statements they might make in everyday life. They didn’t say, “it is so,” but “it seems so,” or “it appears so to me.” Every observation was prefaced with a “perhaps,” or “it may be.”

This absence of certainty applies as much to practical as to theoretical matters. Nothing is in itself true or false. It only appears so. In the same way, nothing is in itself good or evil. It is only opinion, custom, law, which makes it so. When the sage realizes this, he will cease to prefer one course of action to another, and the result will be apathy, "ataraxia." All action is the result of preference, and preference is the belief that one thing is better than another. If I go to the north, it is because, for one reason or another, I believe that it is better than going to the south. Suppress this belief, learn that the one is not in reality better than the other, but only appears so, and one would go in no direction at all. Complete suppression of opinion would mean complete {364} suppression of action, and it was at this that Pyrrho aimed. To have no opinions was the sceptical maxim, because in practice it meant apathy, total quietism. All action is founded on belief, and all belief is delusion, hence the absence of all activity is the ideal of the sage. In this apathy he will renounce all desires, for desire is the opinion that one thing is better than another. He will live in complete repose, in undisturbed tranquillity of soul, free from all delusions. Unhappiness is the result of not attaining what one desires, or of losing it when attained. The wise man, being free from desires, is free from unhappiness. He knows that, though men struggle and fight for what they desire, vainly supposing some things better than others, such activity is but a futile struggle about nothing, for all things are equally indifferent, and nothing matters. Between health and sickness, life and death, difference there is none. Yet in so far as the sage is compelled to act, he will follow probability, opinion, custom, and law, but without any belief in the essential validity or truth of these criteria.

This lack of certainty applies as much to practical matters as it does to theoretical ones. Nothing is inherently true or false; it just seems that way. Similarly, nothing is inherently good or evil; it’s only opinion, tradition, or law that define it as such. When a wise person understands this, they stop favoring one action over another, leading to apathy, "ataraxia." All actions stem from preference, and preference is the belief that one option is better than another. If I choose to go north, it's because I believe it's better than going south for some reason. If you remove this belief and realize that neither option is truly better than the other, you’d end up not choosing at all. Completely suppressing opinion would mean completely suppressing action, and that was Pyrrho's goal. The motto of not having opinions meant practical apathy and total stillness. Every action is based on belief, and every belief is an illusion, so for the wise person, the absence of all activity becomes the ideal. In this apathy, they will let go of all desires since desire is the belief that one thing is better than another. They will live in complete peace, with a calm soul, free from all illusions. Unhappiness comes from not achieving what one desires or from losing it once obtained. The wise person, being free from desires, is also free from unhappiness. They understand that while people struggle and fight for what they want, mistakenly thinking some things are better than others, such efforts are ultimately pointless because everything is equally unimportant, and nothing truly matters. There’s no real difference between health and sickness, life and death. However, to the extent that the sage must act, they will adhere to probability, opinion, custom, and law, but without believing in the essential validity or truth of these standards.


The New Academy.

The New Academy.

The scepticism founded by Pyrrho soon became extinct, but an essentially similar doctrine began to be taught in the school of Plato. After the death of Plato, the Academy continued, under various leaders, to follow in the path marked out by the founder. But, under the leadership of Arcesilaus, scepticism was introduced into the school, and from that time, therefore, it is usually known as the New Academy, for though its historical continuity as a school was not broken, its essential character underwent change. What especially {365} characterized the New Academy was its fierce opposition to the Stoics, whom its members attacked as the chief dogmatists of the time. Dogmatism, for us, usually means making assertions without proper grounds. But since scepticism regards all assertions as equally ill-grounded, the holding of any positive opinion whatever is by it regarded as dogmatism. The Stoics were the most powerful, influential, and forceful of all those who at that time held any positive philosophical opinions. Hence they were singled out for attack by the New Academy as the greatest of dogmatists. Arcesilaus attacked especially their doctrine of the criterion of truth. The striking conviction which, according to the Stoics, accompanies truth, equally accompanies error. There is no criterion of truth, either in sense or in reason. "I am certain of nothing," said Arcesilaus; "I am not even certain that I am certain of nothing."

Skepticism started by Pyrrho eventually faded away, but a similar philosophy began to be taught at Plato's school. After Plato's death, the Academy continued under various leaders, sticking to the direction set by its founder. However, under Arcesilaus, skepticism was introduced to the school, and from that point on, it became known as the New Academy. Although its historical continuity wasn’t disrupted, its fundamental character changed. What particularly marked the New Academy was its strong opposition to the Stoics, whom its members criticized as the main dogmatists of the time. Dogmatism generally means making claims without solid evidence. But since skepticism views all claims as equally unsubstantiated, holding any positive opinion is considered dogmatism by skeptics. The Stoics were the most powerful and influential group during that time who had any clear philosophical views. As a result, the New Academy identified them as the leading dogmatists to target. Arcesilaus specifically challenged their theory of the criterion of truth. According to the Stoics, the strong conviction that comes with truth is also present with error. There is no reliable standard for truth, whether through the senses or reasoning. "I am certain of nothing," Arcesilaus said; "I am not even sure that I am certain of nothing."

But the Academics did not draw from their scepticism, as Pyrrho had done, the full logical conclusion as regards action. Men, they thought, must act. And, although certainty and knowledge are impossible, probability is a sufficient guide for action.

But the Academics didn't take their skepticism, like Pyrrho did, to its full logical conclusion when it came to action. They believed people must act. And while certainty and knowledge are impossible, probability is a good enough guide for action.

Carneades is usually considered the greatest of the Academic Sceptics. Yet he added nothing essentially new to their conclusions. He appears, however, to have been a man of singularly acute and powerful mind, whose destructive criticism acted like a battering-ram not only upon Stoicism, but upon all established philosophies. As examples of his thoughts may be mentioned the two following. Firstly, nothing can ever be proved. For the conclusion must be proved by premises, which in turn require proof, and so ad infinitum. Secondly, {366} it is impossible to know whether our ideas of an object are true, i.e., whether they resemble the object, because we cannot compare our idea with the object itself. To do so would involve getting outside our own minds. We know nothing of the object except our idea of it, and therefore we cannot compare the original and the copy, since we can see only the copy.

Carneades is often seen as the greatest of the Academic Sceptics. However, he didn’t really add anything fundamentally new to their conclusions. He seems to have been a person with a remarkably sharp and strong intellect, whose critical analysis hit hard not just on Stoicism, but on all established philosophies. Two examples of his thoughts can be mentioned. First, nothing can ever be proven. The conclusion must be proven by premises, which in turn need proof, creating a never-ending loop. Second, {366} it’s impossible to know if our ideas of an object are true, meaning whether they accurately reflect the object, because we can’t compare our idea with the object itself. Doing so would require stepping outside our own minds. We know nothing about the object except our idea of it, and therefore we can’t compare the original and the copy, since we can only see the copy.


Later Scepticism.

Later skepticism.

After a period of obliteration, Scepticism again revived in the Academy. Of this last phase of Greek scepticism, Aenesidemus, a contemporary of Cicero, is the earliest example, and later we have the well-known names of Simplicius and Sextus Empiricus. The distinctive character of later scepticism is its return to the position of Pyrrho. The New Academy, in its eagerness to overthrow the Stoic dogmatism, had fallen into a dogmatism of its own. If the Stoics dogmatically asserted, the Academics equally dogmatically denied. But wisdom lies neither in assertion nor denial, but in doubt. Hence the later Sceptics returned to the attitude of complete suspense of judgment. Moreover, the Academics had allowed the possibility of probable knowledge. And even this is now regarded as dogmatism. Aenesidemus was the author of the ten well-known arguments to show the impossibility of knowledge. They contain in reality, not ten, but only two or three distinct ideas, several being merely different expressions of the same line of reasoning. They are as follows. (1) The feelings and perceptions of all living beings differ. (2) Men have physical and mental differences, which make things appear different to them. (3) The different senses give different {367} impressions of things. (4) Our perceptions depend on our physical and intellectual conditions at the time of perception. (5) Things appear different in different positions, and at different distances. (6) Perception is never direct, but always through a medium. For example, we see things through the air. (7) Things appear different according to variations in their quantity, colour, motion, and temperature. (8) A thing impresses us differently when it is familiar and when it is unfamiliar. (9) All supposed knowledge is predication. All predicates give us only the relation of things to other things or to ourselves; they never tell us what the thing in itself is. (10) The opinions and customs of men are different in different countries.

After a time of being completely ignored, Skepticism reappeared in the Academy. The first notable figure of this later phase of Greek skepticism is Aenesidemus, who was a contemporary of Cicero, followed by the well-known names of Simplicius and Sextus Empiricus. A key feature of later skepticism is its return to the views of Pyrrho. The New Academy, in its rush to challenge Stoic beliefs, ended up developing its own form of dogmatism. Just as the Stoics firmly asserted their views, the Academics equally firmly denied them. However, true wisdom lies not in asserting or denying, but in questioning. As a result, the later Skeptics adopted a stance of complete uncertainty. Furthermore, the Academics had previously accepted the idea of probable knowledge, which is now seen as dogmatic. Aenesidemus created the ten famous arguments that demonstrate the impossibility of true knowledge. In reality, these arguments consist of only two or three distinct ideas, with many being just different ways of expressing the same reasoning. They are as follows: (1) The feelings and perceptions of all living beings vary. (2) People have physical and mental differences that make things appear differently to them. (3) Different senses provide different {367} impressions of objects. (4) Our perceptions depend on our physical and mental states at the time we perceive them. (5) Objects look different from different angles and distances. (6) Perception is never direct; it always goes through a medium. For instance, we see things through the air. (7) Objects appear differently depending on changes in their size, color, movement, and temperature. (8) We perceive things differently when they are familiar and when they are unfamiliar. (9) All so-called knowledge is based on categorization. All categories only show us how things relate to other things or to ourselves; they never tell us what a thing truly is. (10) People's opinions and customs vary in different countries.


TRANSITION TO NEO-PLATONISM

Transition to Neo-Platonism

It has been doubted whether Neo-Platonism ought to be included in Greek philosophy at all, and Erdmann, in his "History of Philosophy," places it in the medieval division. For, firstly, an interval of no less than five centuries separates the foundation of Neo-Platonism from the foundation of the preceding Greek schools, the Stoic, the Epicurean, and the Sceptic. How long a period this is will be seen if we remember that the entire development of Greek thought from Thales to the Sceptics occupied only about three centuries. Plotinus, the real founder of Neo-Platonism, was born in 205 A.D., so that it is, as far as historical time is concerned, a product of the Christian era. Secondly, its character is largely un-Greek and un-European. The Greek elements are largely swamped by oriental mysticism. Its seat was not in Greece, but at Alexandria, which was not a Greek, but a cosmopolitan, city. Men of all races met here, and, in particular, it was here that East and West joined hands, and the fusion of thought which resulted was Neo-Platonism. But, on the other hand, it seems wrong to include the thought of Plotinus and his successors in medieval philosophy. The whole character of what is usually called medieval philosophy was determined by its growth upon a distinctively Christian soil. It was {369} Christian philosophy. It was the product of the new era which Christianity had substituted for paganism. Neo-Platonism, on the other hand, is not only unchristian, but even anti-christian. The only Christian influence to be detected in it is that of opposition. It is a survival of the pagan spirit in Christian times. In it the old pagan spirit struggles desperately against its younger antagonist, and finally succumbs. In it we see the last gasp and final expiry of the ancient culture of the Greeks. So far as it is not Asiatic in its elements, it draws its inspiration wholly from the philosophies of the past, from the thought and culture of Greece. On the whole, therefore, it is properly classified as the last school of Greek philosophy.

There has been debate about whether Neo-Platonism should even be considered part of Greek philosophy, and Erdmann, in his "History of Philosophy," places it in the medieval category. First, there is a gap of at least five centuries between the founding of Neo-Platonism and the earlier Greek schools—the Stoics, the Epicureans, and the Skeptics. This gap is significant considering that the entire development of Greek thought from Thales to the Skeptics only took about three centuries. Plotinus, the true founder of Neo-Platonism, was born in 205 A.D., making it, historically speaking, a product of the Christian era. Second, its character is mostly un-Greek and un-European. The Greek elements are largely overshadowed by Eastern mysticism. Its center was not in Greece, but in Alexandria, a cosmopolitan city where people of all races gathered. Notably, it was here that East and West came together, resulting in the fusion of thought we call Neo-Platonism. However, it seems inaccurate to categorize the ideas of Plotinus and his followers as part of medieval philosophy. The overall nature of what is typically defined as medieval philosophy was shaped by its development on distinctly Christian foundations. It was a Christian philosophy. It emerged from the new era that Christianity brought to replace paganism. In contrast, Neo-Platonism is not only non-Christian but even anti-Christian. The only Christian influence found in it is one of opposition. It is a remnant of the pagan spirit during Christian times. Within it, the old pagan spirit struggles against its younger rival but ultimately fades away. In it, we see the last breath and final end of the ancient Greek culture. As far as it is not influenced by Asian elements, it completely derives its inspiration from the philosophies of the past, particularly from Greek thought and culture. Therefore, it is correctly categorized as the final school of Greek philosophy.

The long interval of time which elapsed between the rise of the preceding Greek schools, whose history we have traced, and the foundation of Neo-Platonism, was filled up by the continued existence, in more or less fossilized form, of the main Greek schools, the Academic, the Peripatetic, the Stoic, and the Epicurean, scattered and harried at times by the inroads of scepticism. It would be wearisome to follow in detail the development in these schools, and the more or less trifling disputes of which it consists. No new thought, no original principle, supervened. It is sufficient to say that, as time went on, the differences between the schools became softened, and their agreements became more prominent. As intellectual vigour wanes, there is always the tendency to forget differences, to rest, as the orientals do, in the good-natured and comfortable delusion that all religions and all philosophies really mean much the same thing. Hence eclecticism became characteristic of the schools. {370} They did not keep themselves distinct. We find Stoic doctrines taught by Academics, Academic doctrines by Stoics. Only the Epicureans kept their race pure, and stood aloof from the general eclecticism of the time. Certain other tendencies also made their appearance. There was a recrudescence of Pythagoreanism, with its attendant symbolism and mysticism. There grew up a tendency to exalt the conception of God so high above the world, to widen so greatly the gulf which divides them, that it was felt that there could be no community between the two, that God could not act upon matter, nor matter upon God. Such interaction would contaminate the purity of the Absolute. Hence all kinds of beings were invented, demons, spirits, and angels, intended to fill up the gap, and to act as intermediaries between God and the world.

The long period of time that passed between the rise of the earlier Greek schools we've discussed and the establishment of Neo-Platonism was filled with the ongoing presence, albeit somewhat fossilized, of the main Greek schools: the Academic, the Peripatetic, the Stoic, and the Epicurean. These schools were often disrupted by waves of skepticism. It would be tedious to go into detail about the developments in these schools and the mostly minor disputes they faced. No new ideas or original principles emerged. It's enough to say that, over time, the differences between the schools became less pronounced, while their similarities stood out more. As intellectual energy declines, there’s a tendency to overlook differences, much like the Eastern perspective that all religions and philosophies essentially mean the same thing. As a result, eclecticism became a defining feature of the schools. They didn’t maintain clear distinctions. We see Stoic ideas being taught by Academics and Academic ideas by Stoics. Only the Epicureans maintained their identity, keeping away from the general eclecticism of the time. Other trends also emerged. There was a revival of Pythagoreanism, complete with its symbolism and mysticism. A tendency also arose to elevate the concept of God so far above the world that the chasm between them felt unbridgeable, leading to the belief that God could not interact with matter, nor could matter interact with God. Any such interaction would taint the purity of the Absolute. Consequently, various beings were imagined—demons, spirits, and angels—to fill the void and serve as intermediaries between God and the world.

As an example of these latter tendencies, and as precursor of Neo-Platonism proper, Philo the Jew deserves a brief mention. He lived at Alexandria between 30 B.C. and 50 A.D. A staunch upholder of the religion and scriptures of the Hebrew race, he believed in the verbal inspiration of the Old Testament. But he was learned in Greek studies, and thought that Greek philosophy was a dimmer revelation of those truths which were more perfectly manifested in the sacred books of his own race. And just as Egyptian priests, out of national vanity, made out that Greek philosophy came from Egypt, just as orientals now pretend that it came from India, so Philo declared that the origin of all that was great in Greek philosophy was to be found in Judea. Plato and Aristotle, he was certain, were followers of Moses, used the Old Testament, and gained their wisdom therefrom! {371} Philo's own ideas were governed by the attempt to fuse Jewish theology and Greek philosophy into a homogeneous system. It was Philo, therefore, who was largely responsible for contaminating the pure clear air of Greek thought with the enervating fogs of oriental mysticism.

As an example of these trends and as a precursor to Neo-Platonism, Philo the Jew deserves a brief mention. He lived in Alexandria between 30 B.C. and 50 A.D. A strong supporter of the religion and scriptures of the Hebrew people, he believed in the verbal inspiration of the Old Testament. However, he was well-versed in Greek studies and thought that Greek philosophy was a lesser expression of the truths more perfectly revealed in the sacred texts of his own people. Just as Egyptian priests, out of national pride, claimed that Greek philosophy originated in Egypt, and just as some Easterners now argue that it came from India, Philo asserted that the roots of all that was significant in Greek philosophy could be traced back to Judea. He was convinced that Plato and Aristotle were followers of Moses, used the Old Testament, and derived their wisdom from it! {371} Philo's own ideas were driven by the effort to combine Jewish theology and Greek philosophy into a cohesive system. Therefore, it was Philo who largely contributed to muddling the clear air of Greek thought with the confusing fogs of Eastern mysticism.

Philo taught that God, as the absolutely infinite, must be elevated completely above all that is finite. No name, no thought, can correspond to the infinity of God. He is the unthinkable and the ineffable, and His nature is beyond the reach of reason. The human soul reaches up to God, not through thought, but by means of a mystical inner illumination and revelation that transcends thought. God cannot act directly upon the world, for this would involve His defilement by matter and the limitation of His infinity. There are therefore intermediate spiritual beings, who, as the ministers of God, created and control the world. All these intermediaries are included in the Logos, which is the rational thought which governs the world. The relation of God to the Logos, and of the Logos to the world, is one of progressive emanation. Clearly the idea of emanation is a mere metaphor which explains nothing, and this becomes more evident when Philo compares the emanations to rays of light issuing from an effulgent centre and growing less and less bright as they radiate outwards. When we hear this, we know in what direction we are moving. This has the characteristic ring of Asiatic pseudo-philosophy. It reminds us forcibly of the Upanishads. We are passing out of the realm of thought, reason, and philosophy, into the dream-and-shadow-land of oriental mysticism, where the heavy scents of beautiful poison flowers drug the intellect and obliterate thought in a blissful and languorous repose.

Philo taught that God, being absolutely infinite, must be completely above everything finite. No name or thought can truly capture God's infinity. He is beyond what we can think or express, and His nature goes beyond human reason. The human soul reaches out to God, not through rational thought, but through a mystical inner illumination and revelation that goes beyond ordinary understanding. God cannot act directly in the world because that would mean He becomes tainted by matter and limits His infinity. So, there are intermediate spiritual beings who serve as God’s ministers, creating and managing the world. All these intermediaries are part of the Logos, which is the rational thought governing the world. The relationship between God and the Logos, and between the Logos and the world, is one of progressive emanation. It's clear that the idea of emanation is just a metaphor that doesn't really explain anything, and this becomes even clearer when Philo compares emanations to rays of light coming from a bright center, becoming dimmer as they spread out. When we hear this, we understand the direction of our movement. This has the hallmark of Eastern pseudo-philosophy. It powerfully reminds us of the Upanishads. We are moving away from thought, reason, and philosophy, into the dream-like realm of Eastern mysticism, where the heavy scents of beautiful poisonous flowers cloud the mind and erase clear thinking in a blissful, languorous state.


THE NEO-PLATONISTS

THE NEO-PLATONISTS

The word Neo-Platonism is a misnomer. It does not stand for a genuine revival of Platonism. The Neo-Platonists were no doubt the offspring of Plato, but they were the illegitimate offspring. The true greatness of Plato lay in his rationalistic idealism; his defects were mostly connected with his tendency to myth and mysticism. The Neo-Platonists hailed his defects as the true and inner secret of his doctrine, developed them out of all recognition, and combined them with the hazy dream-philosophies of the East. The reputed founder was Ammonius Saccas, but we may pass him over and come at once to his disciple Plotinus, who was the first to develop Neo-Platonism into a system, was the greatest of all its exponents, and may be regarded as its real founder. He was born in 205 A.D. at Lycopolis in Egypt, went to Rome in 245, founded his School there, and remained at the head of it till his death in 270. He left extensive writings which have been preserved.

The term Neo-Platonism is a mislabeling. It doesn’t represent a true revival of Platonism. The Neo-Platonists were definitely influenced by Plato, but they were his illegitimate heirs. Plato's true greatness was in his rational idealism; his flaws were largely tied to his inclination towards myth and mysticism. The Neo-Platonists embraced these flaws as the genuine inner meaning of his teachings, exaggerated them beyond recognition, and merged them with the vague dream-philosophies of the East. The figure often credited as the founder is Ammonius Saccas, but we can skip over him and go directly to his student Plotinus, who was the first to turn Neo-Platonism into a system, was the greatest of all its supporters, and can be seen as its real founder. He was born in 205 A.D. in Lycopolis, Egypt, moved to Rome in 245, established his School there, and led it until his death in 270. He left a large body of writings that have been preserved.

Plato had shown that the idea of the One, exclusive of all multiplicity, was an impossible abstraction. Even to say "the One is," involves the duality of the One. The Absolute Being can be no abstract unity, but only a unity in multiplicity. Plotinus begins by ignoring this {373} supremely important philosophical principle. He falls back upon the lower level of oriental monism. God, he thinks, is absolutely One. He is the unity which lies beyond all multiplicity. There is in him no plurality, no movement, no distinction. Thought involves the distinction between object and subject; therefore the One is above and beyond thought. Nor is the One describable in terms of volition or activity. For volition involves the distinction between the willer and the willed, activity between the actor and that upon which he acts. God, therefore, is neither thought, nor volition, nor activity. He is beyond all thought and all being. As absolutely infinite, He is also absolutely indeterminate. All predicates limit their subject, and hence nothing can be predicated of the One. He is unthinkable, for all thought limits and confines that which is thought. He is the ineffable and inconceivable. The sole predicates which Plotinus applies to Him are the One and the Good. He sees, however, that these predicates, as much as any others, limit the infinite. He regards them, therefore, not as literally expressing the nature of the infinite, but as figuratively shadowing it forth. They are applied by analogy only. We can, in truth, know nothing of the One, except that it is.

Plato demonstrated that the idea of the One, without any multiplicity, is an impossible concept. Even saying "the One is" implies a duality within the One. The Absolute Being cannot be just an abstract unity; it can only be a unity within multiplicity. Plotinus starts by overlooking this {373} extremely important philosophical principle. He reverts to a simpler form of Eastern monism. He believes that God is absolutely One. He represents the unity that exists beyond all multiplicity. In Him, there is no plurality, no movement, and no distinction. Thinking requires a separation between object and subject; thus, the One exists above and beyond thought. The One also cannot be described in terms of will or action, because will implies a distinction between the one who wills and what is willed, while action separates the doer from what is being acted upon. Therefore, God is neither thought, nor will, nor action. He transcends all thought and existence. As absolutely infinite, He is also completely indeterminate. All definitions limit their subjects, so nothing can be defined about the One. He is beyond thought, as all thought restricts and confines what is being considered. He is the ineffable and inconceivable. The only terms Plotinus uses to describe Him are the One and the Good. However, he acknowledges that these terms, like any others, limit the infinite. He views them not as literal expressions of the nature of the infinite but as figurative hints of it. They are used solely by analogy. In truth, we can know nothing about the One other than that it is.

Now it is impossible to derive the world from a first principle of this kind. As being utterly exalted above the world, God cannot enter into the world. As absolutely infinite, He can never limit Himself to become finite, and so give rise to the world of objects. As absolutely One, the many can never issue out of Him. The One cannot create the world, for creation is an activity, and the One is immutable and excludes all {374} activity. As the infinite first principle of all things, the One must be regarded as in some sense the source of all being. And yet how it can give rise to being is inconceivable, since any such act destroys its unity and infinity. We saw once for all, in the case of the Eleatics, that it is fatal to define the Absolute as unity exclusive of all multiplicity, as immutable essence exclusive of all process, and that if we do so we cut off all hope of showing how the world has issued from the Absolute. It is just the same with Plotinus. There is in his system the absolute contradiction that the One is regarded, on the one hand, as source of the world, and on the other as so exalted above the world that all relationship to the world is impossible. We come, therefore, to a complete deadlock at this point. We can get no further. We can find no way to pass from God to the world. We are involved in a hopeless, logical contradiction. But Plotinus was a mystic, and logical absurdities do not trouble mystics. Being unable to explain how the world can possibly arise out of the vacuum of the One, he has recourse, in the oriental style, to poetry and metaphors. God, by reason of His super-perfection, "overflows" Himself, and this overflow becomes the world. He "sends forth a beam" from Himself. As flame emits light, as snow cold, so do all lower beings issue from the One. Thus, without solving the difficulty, Plotinus deftly smothers it in flowery phrases, and quietly passes on his way.

Now, it’s impossible to derive the world from a first principle like this. Since God is completely beyond the world, He can’t enter it. Being absolutely infinite means He can never limit Himself to become finite, and thus create a world of objects. As the absolute One, the many can never come from Him. The One cannot create the world because creation involves activity, and the One is unchanging and excludes any kind of action. As the infinite first principle of everything, the One must be seen as the source of all being in some sense. However, how it can give rise to being is unimaginable, as any such action would compromise its unity and infinity. We once saw, in the case of the Eleatics, that it’s detrimental to define the Absolute as a unity that excludes all multiplicity, as an unchanging essence that dismisses all processes; doing so dismisses any hope of showing how the world emerged from the Absolute. The same issue arises with Plotinus. His system embodies a fundamental contradiction where the One is seen, on one hand, as the source of the world, and on the other, as so far beyond the world that any relationship to it is impossible. Therefore, we reach a complete deadlock here. We can’t progress further. We can’t find a way to move from God to the world. We’re stuck in an illogical contradiction. But Plotinus was a mystic, and logical absurdities don’t bother mystics. Unable to explain how the world can arise out of the emptiness of the One, he resorts to poetry and metaphors in the oriental style. God, because of His super-perfection, “overflows” Himself, and this overflow becomes the world. He “sends forth a beam” from Himself. Just as a flame gives off light or snow brings cold, all lower beings emerge from the One. Thus, without resolving the issue, Plotinus cleverly obscures it with elaborate language and quietly moves on.

The first emanation from the One is called the Nous. This Nous is thought, mind, reason. We have seen that Plato regarded the Absolute itself as thought. For Plotinus, however, thought is derivative. The One is beyond thought, and thought issues forth from the One {375} as first emanation. The Nous is not discursive thought, however. It is not in time. It is immediate apprehension, or intuition. Its object is twofold. Firstly, it thinks the One, though its thought thereof is necessarily inadequate. Secondly, it thinks itself. It is the thought of thought, like Aristotle's God. It corresponds to Plato's world of Ideas. The Ideas of all things exist in the Nous, and not only the Ideas of classes, but of every individual thing.

The first emanation from the One is called the Nous. This Nous represents thought, mind, and reason. We've seen that Plato viewed the Absolute itself as thought. For Plotinus, though, thought is a derivative concept. The One is beyond thought, and thought emerges from the One as the first emanation. However, the Nous is not discursive thought. It exists outside of time. It is immediate understanding or intuition. Its object is twofold. Firstly, it thinks about the One, although its understanding of it is inevitably limited. Secondly, it thinks about itself. It is the thought of thought, similar to Aristotle's concept of God. It aligns with Plato's realm of Ideas. The Ideas of everything exist within the Nous, including not just the Ideas of categories, but also those of every single entity.

From the Nous, as second emanation, proceeds the world-soul. This is, in Erdmann's phrase, a sort of faded-out copy of the Nous, and it is outside time, incorporeal, and indivisible. It works rationally, but yet is not conscious. It has a two-fold aspect, inclining upwards to the Nous on the one hand, and downwards to the world of nature on the other. It produces out of itself the individual souls which inhabit the world.

From the Nous, as the second emanation, comes the world-soul. This is, in Erdmann's words, a sort of faded copy of the Nous, and it exists outside of time, is incorporeal, and indivisible. It operates rationally, yet is not conscious. It has a dual aspect, leaning upwards towards the Nous on one side and downwards towards the natural world on the other. It generates individual souls from itself that inhabit the world.

The idea of emanation is essentially a poetical metaphor, and not a rational concept. It is conceived poetically by Plotinus as resembling light which radiates from a bright centre, and grows dimmer as it passes outwards, till it shades off at last into total darkness. This total darkness is matter. Matter, as negation of light, as the limit of being, is in itself not-being. Thus the crucial difficulty of all Greek philosophy, the problem of the whence of matter, the dualism of matter and thought, which we have seen Plato and Aristotle struggling in vain to subjugate, is loosely and lightly slurred over by Plotinus with poetic metaphors and roseate phrases.

The concept of emanation is primarily a poetic metaphor rather than a logical idea. Plotinus imagines it as similar to light that radiates from a bright center and becomes dimmer as it moves outward, eventually fading into complete darkness. This total darkness represents matter. Matter, being the absence of light and the boundary of existence, is in itself non-being. Therefore, the main challenge of all Greek philosophy—the question of where matter comes from and the dualism of matter and thought—has been only loosely addressed by Plotinus with poetic imagery and flowery language, despite Plato and Aristotle's struggles to resolve it.

Matter Plotinus considers to be the ground of plurality and the cause of all evil. Hence the object of life can {376} only be, as with Plato, to escape from the material world of the senses. The first step in this process of liberation is "katharsis," purification, the freeing of oneself from the dominion of the body and the senses. This includes all the ordinary ethical virtues. The second step is thought, reason, and philosophy. In the third stage the soul rises above thought to an intuition of the Nous. But all these are merely preparatory for the supreme and final stage of exaltation into the Absolute One, by means of trance, rapture, ecstasy. Here all thought is transcended, and the soul passes into a state of unconscious swoon, during which it is mystically united with God. It is not a thought of God, it is not even that the soul sees God, for all such conscious activities involve the separation of the subject from its object. In the ecstasy all such disunion and separation are annihilated. The soul does not look upon God from the outside. It becomes one with God. It is God. Such mystical raptures can, in the nature of the case, only be momentary, and the soul sinks back exhausted to the levels of ordinary consciousness. Plotinus claimed to have been exalted in this divine ecstasy several times during his life.

Matter, according to Plotinus, is the basis of diversity and the source of all evil. Thus, the purpose of life can only be, like with Plato, to escape from the material world of the senses. The first step in this journey toward liberation is "katharsis," or purification, freeing oneself from the control of the body and the senses. This encompasses all the typical ethical virtues. The second step involves thought, reason, and philosophy. In the third stage, the soul rises above thought to grasp the Nous. But all these steps are merely preparation for the ultimate and final stage of elevation into the Absolute One, achieved through trance, rapture, and ecstasy. In this state, all thought is transcended, and the soul enters a state of unconscious bliss, during which it is mystically united with God. It’s not just an idea of God; it’s not even that the soul sees God, since all such conscious activities imply a separation between the subject and its object. In ecstasy, all such divisions and separations vanish. The soul doesn’t observe God from a distance; it becomes one with God. It is God. These mystical experiences can only be temporary, and the soul eventually returns, spent, to the realm of everyday consciousness. Plotinus claimed to have experienced this divine ecstasy several times throughout his life.

After Plotinus Neo-Platonism continues with modifications in his successors, Porphyry, Iamblicus, Syrianus, Proclus, and others.

After Plotinus, Neo-Platonism continues to evolve with changes made by his followers, including Porphyry, Iamblicus, Syrianus, Proclus, and others.

The essential character of Neo-Platonism comes out in its theory of the mystical exaltation of the subject to God. It is the extremity of subjectivism, the forcing of the individual subject to the centre of the universe, to the position of the Absolute Being. And it follows naturally upon the heels of Scepticism. In the Sceptics all faith in the power of thought and reason had finally died out. They {377} took as their watchword the utter impotence of reason to reach the truth. From this it was but a step to the position that, if we cannot attain truth by the natural means of thought, we will do so by a miracle. If ordinary consciousness will not suffice, we will pass beyond ordinary consciousness altogether. Neo-Platonism is founded upon despair, the despair of reason. It is the last frantic struggle of the Greek spirit to reach, by desperate means, by force, the point which it felt it had failed to reach by reason. It seeks to take the Absolute by storm. It feels that where sobriety has failed, the violence of spiritual intoxication may succeed.

The core idea of Neo-Platonism is its belief in the mystical elevation of the individual to God. It represents the peak of subjectivism, positioning the individual at the center of the universe, as the Absolute Being. This idea follows closely after Scepticism. In the Sceptics, all belief in the power of thought and reason had completely faded. They took as their motto the total failure of reason to uncover the truth. From this, it was a small leap to the belief that if we can't find the truth through logical means, we must do so through a miracle. If standard awareness isn't enough, we will go beyond ordinary consciousness entirely. Neo-Platonism is built on the despair of reason. It is the last desperate attempt of the Greek spirit to reach what it felt it had failed to attain through reason alone. It aims to capture the Absolute with sheer force. It believes that where clear thinking has faltered, the intensity of spiritual ecstasy might succeed.

It was natural that philosophy should end here. For philosophy is founded upon reason. It is the effort to comprehend, to understand, to grasp the reality of things intellectually. Therefore it cannot admit anything higher than reason. To exalt intuition, ecstasy, or rapture, above thought--this is death to philosophy. Philosophy in making such an admission, lets out its own life-blood, which is thought. In Neo-Platonism, therefore, ancient philosophy commits suicide. This is the end. The place of philosophy is taken henceforth by religion. Christianity triumphs, and sweeps away all independent thought from its path. There is no more philosophy now till a new spirit of enquiry and wonder is breathed into man at the Renaissance and the Reformation. Then the new era begins, and gives birth to a new philosophic impulse, under the influence of which we are still living. But to reach that new era of philosophy, the human spirit had first to pass through the arid wastes of Scholasticism.

It was only natural that philosophy would come to an end here. Philosophy is based on reason; it's the attempt to understand and intellectually grasp the reality of things. Therefore, it can't accept anything higher than reason. To elevate intuition, ecstasy, or rapture above thought is a fatal blow to philosophy. By making such an acceptance, philosophy loses its essential life force, which is thought. In Neo-Platonism, ancient philosophy essentially ends itself. This marks the conclusion. From now on, religion takes over philosophy's role. Christianity prevails and clears away all independent thought from its path. Philosophy disappears until a new spirit of inquiry and wonder is instilled in humanity during the Renaissance and the Reformation. Thus begins a new era, giving rise to a fresh philosophical movement, which still influences us today. However, to reach that new philosophical era, the human spirit had to endure the barren landscapes of Scholasticism first.

SUBJECT INDEX

Subject Index

A

Abortions,291.

Absolute, The;
as many in one,
70-71, 197;
as reason,
240-1, 307;
as knowable,
299;
as form,
307.
Actuality, 279.
Air, as first principle, 28.
Antinomy, 54.
Appearance, 61.
Aristocracy, 324.
Asceticism, defect of, 317.
Ataraxia, 363.
Atoms, 88 et seq, 356.
Aufklärung, 119-120.

B

Becoming;
Parmenides on,
44;
Heracleitus on,
73;
Empedocles on,
82;
Plato on,
192;
Aristotle on,
279-280
Being;
Parmenides on,
44 et seq;
Plato on,
191,197.

C

Causation, 6-7;
as explanation,
64;
Aristotle's doctrine of,
267-73.
Classification, 199.
Comedy, 330-1.
Concepts;
defined,
143;
identified with definitions,
145;
Socrates's doctrine of,
143-6;
objectivity of,
183;
Stoics on,
345.
Condensation, 28.
Contract, the social, 323.
Cosmopolitanism, 353.
Counter-earth, 38.
Criterion, The Stoic, 345-6.

D

Darwinism, 293.
Death, problem of, 76-7.
Democracy, 123, 325.
Dialectic, 55, 183, 199, 204.
Dichotomy, 200.
Division, 199.
Dualism;
defined,
63;
of Eleatics,
68-70;
of Anaxagoras,
105;
of Plato,
105;
of Aristotle,
334-5.

E

Eclipses, 103.
Ecstasy, 376-7.
Efficient cause, 269;
identified with final cause,
273-4.
Elements, The Four, 83.
Emanation, 371, 374-5.
Empty Space, 47, 89, 291-2
Eros, 204.
Evolution;
Anaximander and,
27;
Aristotle's doctrine of,
307-12, 307-12, 333, 336-7;
Spencer's doctrine of,
308 et seq.
{379}
Evil, problem of, 240-1.
Explanation, scientific, 64-5.
External goods, value of, 159, 31-6, 350, 359.

F

Faith, age of, 151.
Family, The; Aristotle on, 324.
Final cause, 269;
identified with formal cause,
273.
Fire, as first principle, 78, 347.
First Cause, 66.
First Mover, 284-5.
Form, Aristotle's doctrine of, 267, 274-8.
Formal cause, 269;
identified with final cause,
273.
Free Will, 320, 348, 355.
Friendship, 225, 359.

G

Genius, artistic, 231.
Geocentric hypothesis, 38, 211, 305.
Geometry, 3-5, 275.
God;
Xenophanes on,
41-2;
Socrates on,
132;
Plato on,
202-4;
Aristotle on,
283-8;
as first mover,
284-5;
as thought of thought,
285-6;
relation of, to the world,
282;
Plotinus on,
373.
Gods, The;
Democritus on,
92;
Protagoras on,
112;
Socrates on,
132;
Epicurus on,
357.
Good,
The Idea of,
198, 200-1, 244;
as God,
203.
Gravitation, 294-5.

H

Habit, 7.
Happiness;
Antisthenes on,
159;
Plato on,
220-1;
Aristotle on,
314-15;
Stoics on,
351;
Epicurus on,
358, 361;
distinguished from pleasure,
221.
Heavenly bodies, The;
Anaximander on,
26;
Pythagoreans on,
38;
Xenophanes on,
43;
Anaxagoras on,
103;
Plato on,
211;
Aristotle on,
305-6.
Heliocentric hypothesis, 38.
Hinduism, 71, 197, 308, 312-13.

I

Idealism;
of Parmenides,
47 et seq;
essentials of,
48, 49, 235;
Plato as founder of,
235.
Ideas,
Theory of,
174,183-207;
Aristotle on,
262-5.
Imagination, 300.
Immortality;
Atomists on,
92;
Plato on,
175, 212;
Aristotle on,
302-3;
Epicurus on,
357.
Indian Thought, 14-16; see also Hinduism.
Individualism, 323.
Induction, 144, 146, 190, 206, 260.
Infinite divisibility;
Zeno on,
56;
Anaxagoras on,
96;
Aristotle on,
292-3;
Hume on,
57-8;
Kant on,
57;
Hegel on,
58-60.
Inorganic matter, 294-6.
Insight, moral, 318.
Intuition, 153, 375, 377.
Irony, of Socrates, 130.

J

Judaism, 71.
Justice;
Pythagoreans on,
37;
Plato on,
224;
Aristotle on,
319-20.

{380}

K

Knowledge;
of the Infinite,
7-8;
of the Absolute,
299;
through concepts,
146, 182;
Plato on,
177-82;
as recollection,
212-17;
necessary knowledge,
213-15.

L

Life; Aristotle's doctrine of, 296.
Limit, The, 36.
Love, Platonic, 204-6.

M

Marriage, 224.
Material cause, 268.
Materialism;
origin of,
9-11;
of Ionics,
23;
defect of,
66.
Matter;
indestructibility of,
50;
Platonic,
208;
Aristotle's doctrine of,
275-9;
Plotinus on,
375.
Mechanical theories, 88.
Memory, 300.
Monarchy, 324.
Monism, 62-7.
Monstrosities, 29l.
Morality;
founded on reason,
118.
Motion;
Zeno on,
54;
Aristotle on,
29l.
Multiplicity;
Zeno on,
53.
Mysticism, 12, 171, 371, 372, 374, 376.
Myths, of Plato, 170-71, 208, 209, 210, 211.

N

Necessary Knowledge, 213-15;
necessary concepts,
242.
Non-sensuous thought, 8-13.
Not-being, 44, 75, 76, 77, 89, 191, 208, 279, 280.
Nous;
of Anaxagoras,
97-105;
of Plotinus,
375.
Numbers, as first principle, 36.

O

Object, the right of the, 122.
Objectivity;
defined,
113;
of concepts,
183.
Oligarchy, 324.
Opinion,181-2.
Organic matter, organism, 294-6.

P

Pantheism, 312.
Participation, 194, 236.
Personality, 286.
Pleasure, 161-2, 218-19, 350, 358;
distinguished from happiness,
221.
Potentiality, 279.
Pragmatism, 121.
Protestantism, 123.

Q

Quality, mechanical explanation of, 87-8.

R

Rarefaction, 28.
Reality;
distinguished from appearance,
61;
distinguished from existence,
60-1, 246-7.
Reason;
distinguished from sense,
45, 79, 112, 113, 115, 239, 290;
distinguished from cause,
64, 76;
as universal,
113;
as concepts,
144;
supremacy of,
153-4;
as basis of love,
205-6;
as Absolute,
240-1;
passive and active,
300;
as basis of morals,
118, 317, 349-50.
{381}
Recollection;
knowledge as,
212-17;
Aristotle on,
300.
Reincarnation; see Transmigration.
Religion;
relation to philosophy,
14-15, 207;
Xenophanes on,
41-2;
Heracleitus on,
79;
Democritus on,
92;
decay of Greek,
107-8.
Rhetoric, 111, 122.

S

Scepticism, 343, 361.
Sensation;
particularism of,
113;
distinguished from reason,
45, 79, 112, 113, 115, 239, 290.
Slavery, 225, 321.
Soul;
Heracleitus on,
78-9;
Atomists on,
92;
Plato on,
211-17;
Aristotle on,
296 et seq;
Stoics on,
348;
Epicureans on,
357.
Space, 3-4, 56; see also Empty space.
Sphere, of Empedocles, 84.
State, The;
Sophists on,
119;
Plato's,
201-2, 225-29;
Aristotle on,
320-5.
Subject, the right of the, 122, 152.
Subjectivism, Preface, 340-3, 361, 376.
Subjectivity, defined, 113.
Substance;
defined,
186-7;
Ideas as,
186-8;
Aristotle's doctrine of
265-7.
Suicide, 160, 350.
Summum Bonum, 222, 314.
Symbolism, 12.

T

Teleology;
defined,
101;
of Anaxagoras,
104, 105;
of Plato,
201-2;
of Aristotle,
289.
Theosophists, 153-4.
Time, 282, 292.
Timocracy, 324.
Tragedy, 330-1.
Transmigration, 17, 32, 85, 212, 217, 301.
Tyranny, 324.

U

Universals, 188.
Utilitarianism, 220-21, 315.

V

Virtue;
as knowledge,
147, 157;
teachable,
149;
unity of,
149, 223, 351;
as sole good,
159-60, 350;
relation to pleasure,
161, 218-19;
customary and philosophic,
220;
dianoetic,
316, 317;
as the mean,
317.
Void, The, 90.
Vortex, 90, 102.

W

Water, as first principle, 21.
Wise Man, The;
of the Cynics,
160;
of the Cyrenaics,
162;
of the Stoics,
351.
Women, status of, 224.
World-Soul, The, 210, 211, 375.

INDEX OF NAMES

NAMES INDEX

A

Abdera, 86, 112.
Academy, The, 167, 249, 250;
The New,
364-6.
Aegean, The, 18.
Aenesidemus, 366-7.
AEsculapius, 141.
Agrigentum, 81.
Alcibiades, 132, 133.
Alexander the Great, 251, 252, 339, 340, 362.
Alexandria, 368, 370.
Ammonius Saccas, 372.
Amyntas, 249.
Anaxagoras, 22, 30, 82, 86, 91, 94-105, 106, 120, 137, 166, 271, 272, 273, 340
Anaximander, 20, 22, 23, 24-7, 28, 29.
Anaximenes, 20, 22, 23, 27-30, 82, 83, 102, 271.
Andronicus, 262.
Anniceris, 162, 167.
Antiochis, 134.
Antisthenes, 156, 158, 159.
Anytus, 133.
Appolonia, 30.
Apollodorus, 140.
Apology, The, 129, 133, 134, 172, 173.
Arcesilaus, 364, 365.
Arginusae, 134.
Aristippus, 156, 161, 358.
Aristophanes, 135, 152.
Aristotle, 14, 17, 18, 19, 23, 38, 42 (footnote), 55, 95, 98, 99, 106, 122, 148, 150, 191, 193, 231, 233, 248, 249-338, 339, 340, 341, 342, 345, 346, 350, 370;
on Thales,
21-2;
on Anaxagoras,
104, 105;
on Socrates,
147, 317, 320;
on Plato,
193, 262-5, 323-4.

Asia Minor, 18, 20, 72, 94, 95, 250.
Assyria, 13.
Atarneus, 250.
Athens, 94, 95, 112, 127, 128, 129, 131, 133, 134, 135, 136, 137, 165, 166, 167, 169, 249, 250, 251, 252, 254, 344.
Atomists, The, 82, 86-93, 95, 96, 97, 103, 104.
Aurelius, Marcus, 14, 344.

B

Babylon, 252.
Babylonia, 86.
Bacon, Francis, 257-8.
Banquet, The, 132. See also Symposium, The.
Bentham, 220.
Bhagavat Gita, The, 15.
Brahman, 15, 64, 170, 197.
Buddha, The, 213.
Burnet Prof., Preface,25,28,46,91,98.

{383}

C

Carneades, 365.
Chairephon, 129.
Chalcis, 252.
Charmides, The, 172, 173.
China, 13.
Christianity, 69, 70, 71, 101, 369, 377.
Chrysippus, 344.
Cicero, 366.
Clazomenae, 94.
Cleanthes, 344.
Clouds, The, of Aristophanes, 135.
Coleridge, S. T., 263.
Colophon, 41.
Copernicus, 38.
Crates, 344.
Cratylus, 166.
Critias, 118.
Crito, 137, 138, 139, 140, 141.
Crito, The, 172, 173.
Croesus, 20, 21.
Crotona, 31, 33.
Cynics, The, 156, 158-60, 163, 316, 342, 351, 353, 358.
Cyprus, 344.
Cyrenaics, The, 156, 160-2, 163, 218, 342, 358.
Cyrene, 167.

D

Darwin, 308.
Delium, 131.
Delphi, 129.
Democritus, 22, 49, 50, 52, 86, 93, 104, 108, 112, 234, 342, 354, 356.
Diogenes of Apollonia, 30.
Diogenes the Cynic, 159, 351, 352.
Dionysius the Elder, 167, 168.
Dionysius the Younger, 168, 169.

E

Echechrates, 139, 141.
Egypt, 13, 16, 17, 31, 86, 125, 167, 372.
Elea, 40, 41, 43, 52, 60.
Eleatics, The, 22, 23, 40-71, 72, 73, 75, 79, 89, 109, 112, 117, 162, 164, 166, 173, 174, 175, 193, 195, 196, 197, 234, 235, 246, 272, 279, 374.
Eleusinian mysteries, 72.
Empedocles, 17, 22, 49, 52, 81-5, 86, 87-8, 89, 95, 96, 97, 103, 271, 272, 329.
Empiricus, Sextus, 366.
England, 121.
Ephesus, 72, 73.
Epictetus, 14, 344.
Epicureans, The, 89, 90, 91, 342, 343, 354-60, 362, 368, 369.
Epicurus, 342, 345-60.
Erdmann, 46, 98, 368, 375.
Ethics, The, of Aristotle, 319.
Euboea, 252.
Euclid, the geometrician, 33, 113.
Euclid of Megara, 156, 162-3, 166, 167.
Euripides, 94.
Euthyphro, The, 172.

F

France, 121.

G

Gorgias, 110, 111, 116-18, 361.
Gorgias, The, 174, 177.
Grant, Sir A., 295 (footnote).
Greece, 13, 16, 17, 18, 33, 41, 107, 109, 112, 122, 168, 220, 252, 339, 344, 368.
Grote, 98.

{384}

H

Halys, 21.
Hegel, 38, 46, 55, 58-60, 312 (footnote), 333.
Hegesias, 162.
Hellas, 41.
Heracleitus, 22, 72-80, 82, 86, 108, 112, 116, 164, 166, 192, 193, 234, 271, 333, 342, 347.
Hermeias, 250.
Herpyllis, 251.
Hesiod, 41, 72, 77.
Hippias, 110.
Hippias Minor, The, 172.
Hippo, 30.
Homer, 41, 72.
Hume, David, 57, 58, 361.
Hylicists, The, 24.

I

Iamblicus, 376.
Idaeus, 30.
India, 14, 16, 17.
Ionia, 20, 41, 137.
Ionics, The, 20-30, 61, 62, 82, 83, 271, 272.
Islam, 71.
Italy, 18, 31, 40, 167.

J

Japan, 125.
Jàtakas, The, 213.
Judaea, 370.

K

Kant, 55, 57, 213, 215.
Kepler, 65.
Krishna, 15.

L

Laches, The, 172, 173.
Lampsacus, 95.
Leon, 134-5.
Leucippus, 86, 88, 89, 91, 104.
London, 189.
Lucretius, 14.
Lyceum, The, 251.
Lycon, 133.
Lycopolis, 372.
Lysis, The, 172, 173.

M

Macedonia, 249, 252, 339.
Macran, H. S., 312 (footnote).
Megara, 166, 167, 172, 173.
Megarics, The, 156, 162-3.
Melissus, 46.
Melitus, 133.
Memorabilia, The, 142.
Meno, The, 216.
Meru, 15, 16.
Metaphysics, The, of Aristotle, 19, 42, 105, 253, 254, 261, 271.
Metchnikoff, 76.
Miletus, 20, 24, 27.
Mill, J. S., 220, 221, 269.
Milton, 330.
Moses, 370.
Mytilene, 251.

N

Napoleon, 252.
Neo-Platonists, The, 342, 343, 368, 369, 372-377.
Newton, 65.
Nichomachus, 249, 251
Nietzsche, 156.

O

Orphics, The, 17, 32.

P

Paramatman, 15.
Parmenides, 13, 40, 41, 42, 43, 52, 53, 57, 72, 81, 82, 86, 117, 162, 163, 164, 167, 234.
Parmenides, The, 169, 175, 176, 177, 195, 244.
Peloponnese, The, 103.

{385}

Peloponnesian War, The, 131, 165.
Pericles, 94, 95, 137.
Peripatetics, The, 251, 369.
Persians, The, 251.
Phaedo, The, 137, 175, 177.
Phaedrus, The, 172, 175, 177.
Philebus, The, 175, 203.
Philip of Macedonia, 251.
Philo the Jew, 370-1.
Philolaus, 37.
Phlius, 262.
Plato, 1, 13, 17, 19, 23, 38, 50, 51, 52, 55, 95, 99, 101, 104, 106, 122, 129, 132, 133, 137, 141, 142, 150, 156, 164-248, 249, 250, 253, 255, 256, 257, 258, 259, 262-5, 267, 269, 271, 272, 273, 275, 281, 282, 286, 287, 288, 290, 291, 298, 299, 301, 303, 304, 314, 319, 321, 323, 324, 325, 327, 329, 331, 332, 334, 335, 336, 338, 341, 342, 345, 346, 350, 364, 370, 372, 374, 375.
Plotinus, 368, 372-6.
Porphyry, 376.
Proclus, 376.
Poetics, The, of Aristotle, 326.
Polus, 118-9.
Polemo, 344.
Prodicus, 110, 121.
Protagoras, 110, 112-6, 118, 121, 153, 154, 161, 178, 179, 181, 217, 361.
Protagoras, The, 172.
Proxenus, 249.
Pyrrho, 343, 362-4, 365, 366.
Pythagoras, 31, 32, 33, 34, 72, 81, 301.
Pythagoreans, The, 17, 22, 31-9, 43, 44, 61, 62, 109, 164, 167, 169, 191, 209, 217, 272, 291, 370.
Pythias, 251.

R

Republic, The, Preface, 168, 175, 177, 201-2, 225-9, 230, 231.
Rome, 14, 344, 372.
Rotunda, The, 134, 135.

S

Salamis, 134, 135.
Satan, Milton's, 330.
Sceptics, The, 7 (footnote), 342, 361-7, 368, 376.
Schopenhauer, 72.
Schwegler, 46, 353.
Seneca, 14, 344.
Seven Sages, The, 21.
Shaw, Bernard, 126, 156.
Sicily, 18, 81, 112, 176, 168.
Simplicius, 366.
Socrates, 18, 19, 51, 73, 95, 110, 122, 127-54, 155, 156, 157, 158, 159, 160, 161, 163, 164, 166, 167, 168, 169, 172, 173, 182, 183, 193, 223, 234, 252, 317, 320, 352. 352.
Solon, 20.
Sophist, The, 175, 176, 177, 195.
Sophists, The, 18, 19, 24, 106-26, 127, 128, 135, 142, 144, 145, 150, 151, 152, 153, 161, 166, 174, 178, 182, 185, 218, 219, 221, 234, 343, 361.
Sparta, 339.
Spencer, Herbert, 2, 308-12.
Speusippus, 250.
Spinoza, 66, 71, 197.
Stagirus, 249.
Statesman, The, 175, 176.
Stilpo, 344.
Stoa, The, 344.
Stoics, The, 341, 342, 343, 344-53, 358, 359, 362, 365, 366, 368, 369, 370.
Swinburne, A. C., 357.

{386}

Symposium, The, 175, 205-6, 231. See also Banquet, The.
Syracuse, 42, 167, 168, 169.
Syrianus, 376.

T

Thales 20-4, 27, 28, 29, 30, 36, 44, 82, 120, 271, 368.
Thebes, 252.
Thessaly, 137.
Thirty Tyrants, The, 134, 165.
Thrace, 86, 249.
Thrasymachus, 118-9.
Timaeus, The, 38, 171, 175, 177, 190, 208, 210.
Timon of Phlius, 362.
Tolstoi, 230.

U

Upanishads, The, 14, 15, 170, 371.

W

Wallace, 38 (footnote).
Wells, H. G., Preface,
Wilde, Oscar, 126, 156.

X

Xenocrates, 250, 251.
Xenophanes, 40-3, 72, 79, 108, 340.
Xenophon, 132, 141, 142.

Z

Zeller, 98, 101, 176, 202, 209, 224.
Zeno the Eleatic, 40, 52-60, 72, 117, 163, 246, 292.
Zeno the Stoic, 344, 354.
Zeus, 360.

GLASGOW: PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO. LTD.

GLASGOW: PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO. LTD.

NEW WORKS ON PHILOSOPHY

NEW PHILOSOPHY BOOKS


THE IDEA OF PROGRESS: An Inquiry into its Origin and Growth.
By Professor J. B. BURY, D. Litt. 8vo.

THE IDEA OF PROGRESS: An Exploration of its Origin and Development.
By Professor J. B. BURY, D. Litt. 8vo.

MIND-ENERGY.
By Professor HENRI BERGSON.
Translated by Professor H. WILDON CARR, in collaboration with the Author. 8vo.

MIND-ENERGY.
By Professor HENRI BERGSON.
Translated by Professor H. WILDON CARR, in collaboration with the Author. 8vo.

IMPLICATION AND LINEAR INFERENCE.
By BERNARD BOSANQUET, LL.D., F.B.A. Crown 8vo.
7s. 6d. net.

IMPLICATION AND LINEAR INFERENCE.
By BERNARD BOSANQUET, LL.D., F.B.A. Crown 8vo.
£7.50 net.

SPACE, TIME, AND DEITY.
Gifford Lectures at Glasgow, 1916-1918.
By Professor S. ALEXANDER, M.A., LL.D., F.RA. 2 vols. 8vo.

SPACE, TIME, AND DEITY.
Gifford Lectures at Glasgow, 1916-1918.
By Professor S. ALEXANDER, M.A., LL.D., F.RA. 2 vols. 8vo.

THE REIGN OF RELIGION IN CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY.
By Professor S. RADHAKRISHNAN, M.A. Extra Crown 8vo.

THE REIGN OF RELIGION IN CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY.
By Professor S. RADHAKRISHNAN, M.A. Extra Crown 8vo.

ESSAYS IN CRITICAL REALISM:
A Co-operative Study of the Problem of Knowledge.
By Professors DURANT DRAKE, ARTHUR O. LOVEJOY, JAMES BISSETT PRATT, ARTHUR K. ROGERS, GEORGE SANTAYANA, ROY WOOD SELLARS, C. A. STRONG. 8vo.

ESSAYS IN CRITICAL REALISM:
A Collaborative Study of the Problem of Knowledge.
By Professors DURANT DRAKE, ARTHUR O. LOVEJOY, JAMES BISSETT PRATT, ARTHUR K. ROGERS, GEORGE SANTAYANA, ROY WOOD SELLARS, C. A. STRONG. 8vo.

LONDON: MACMILLAN & CO., LTD.

LONDON: MACMILLAN & CO., LTD.


WORKS ON PHILOSOPHY
-----
By Prof. HENRI BERGSON

WORKS ON PHILOSOPHY
-----
By Prof. HENRI BERGSON

CREATIVE EVOLUTION.
Translated by ARTHUR MITCHELL, Ph.D.
8vo. 12s. 6d. net.

CREATIVE EVOLUTION.
Translated by ARTHUR MITCHELL, Ph.D.
8vo. £12.30 net.

LAUGHTER: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic.
Authorised Translation from the Sixth Edition by CLOUDESLEY BRERETON, L. es L. (Paris), M.A. (Cantab.); and FRED ROTHWELL, B.A. (London). Extra Crown 8vo. 4s. 6d. net.

LAUGHTER: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic.
Authorized Translation from the Sixth Edition by CLOUDESLEY BRERETON, L. es L. (Paris), M.A. (Cantab.); and FRED ROTHWELL, B.A. (London). Extra Crown 8vo. £4.6.0. net.

AN INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS.
Translated by T. E. HULME. Crown 8vo. 2d. 6d. net.

AN INTRODUCTION TO METAPHYSICS.
Translated by T. E. HULME. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. net.

-----

Understood! Please provide the text you'd like modernized.

A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF BERGSON'S PHILOSOPHY.
By J. M'KELLAR STEWART, B.A., D.Phil. Extra Crown 8vo.
6s. 6d. net.

A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF BERGSON'S PHILOSOPHY.
By J. M'KELLAR STEWART, B.A., D.Phil. Extra Crown 8vo.
£6.50 net.

HENRI BERGSON. An Account of his Life and Philosophy.
By ALGOT RUHE and NANCY MARGARET PAUL.
With Portrait. Extra Crown 8vo. 6s. 6d. net.

HENRI BERGSON. A Summary of His Life and Philosophy.
By ALGOT RUHE and NANCY MARGARET PAUL.
With Portrait. Extra Crown 8vo. £6.30 net.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF CHANGE.
A Study of the Fundamental Principle of the Philosophy of Bergson.
By H. WILDON CARR. 8vo. 7s. 6d. net.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF CHANGE.
A Study of the Fundamental Principle of Bergson's Philosophy.
By H. WILDON CARR. 8vo. £7.50 net.


By BENEDETTO CROCE

By Benedetto Croce

PHILOSOPHY OF THE PRACTICAL. Economic and Ethic
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A. 8vo. 14s. net.

PHILOSOPHY OF THE PRACTICAL. Economic and Ethic
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A. 8vo. £14.00 net.

AESTHETIC AS SCIENCE OF EXPRESSION AND GENERAL LINGUISTIC.
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A
8vo. 12S. 6d. net.

AESTHETIC AS SCIENCE OF EXPRESSION AND GENERAL LINGUISTIC.
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A
8vo. 12s. 6d. net.

LOGIC AS THE SCIENCE OF THE PURE CONCEPT
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A. 8vo. 14s. net.

LOGIC AS THE SCIENCE OF THE PURE CONCEPT
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE, B.A. 8vo. £14 net.

WHAT IS LIVING AND WHAT IS DEAD OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF HEGEL.
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE B.A. 8vo. 10S. net.

WHAT IS LIVING AND WHAT IS DEAD OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF HEGEL.
Translated by DOUGLAS AINSLIE B.A. 8vo. 10S. net.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF BENEDETTO CROCE:
The Problem of Art and History.
By H. WILDON CARR, Hon. D.Litt.
8vo. 7s. 6d. net.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF BENEDETTO CROCE:
The Problem of Art and History.
By H. WILDON CARR, Hon. D.Litt.
8vo. £7.50 net.

LONDON: MACMILLAN & CO., LTD.

LONDON: MACMILLAN & CO., LTD.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!