This is a modern-English version of The Seven Lamps of Architecture, originally written by Ruskin, John. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.


PLATE IX. PLATE IX.—(Frontispiece—Vol. V.)
Decorative patterns from Giotto's Campanile in Florence.

Illustrated Cabinet Edition

The Seven Lamps of Architecture
Lectures on Architecture and Painting
The Study of Architecture

by John Ruskin

Boston
Dana Estes & Company
Publishers


CONTENTS.

 
Seven Lamps of Architecture.
 PAGE
Introduction5
 
Intro9
CHAPTER I.
The Sacrifice Lamp15
CHAPTER II.
The Light of Truth34
CHAPTER III.
The Power Lamp69
CHAPTER IV.
The Beauty Lamp100
CHAPTER V.
The Light of Life142
CHAPTER VI.
The Memory Lamp167
CHAPTER VII.
The Light of Obedience188
 
Notes203
 
Lectures on Architecture and Art.
Introduction213
Lecture 1.217
Lecture 2.248
        Additions to Lectures I. and II.270
Lecture 3. Turner and his Works287
Lecture 4. Pre-Raphaelitism311
        Updates to Lecture IV.334
 
ARCHITECTURE STUDIES.
An Investigation into the Field of Architecture339

LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS.

 
Seven Lamps of Architecture
PLATE PAGE
I.Ornaments from Rouen, St. Lo, and Venice33
II.Part of the Cathedral of St. Lo, Normandy55
III.Traceries from Caen, Bayeux, Rouen, and Beauvais60
IV.Intersectional Moldings66
V.Capital from the Lower Arcade of the Doge’s Palace, Venice88
VI.Arch from the facade of the Church of San Michele in Lucca90
VII.Pierced Ornaments from Lisieux, Bayeux, Verona, and Padua93
VIII.Window from the Ca' Foscari, Venice95
IX.Tracery from the Campanile of Giotto in Florence.Frontispiece.
X.Traceries and Moldings from Rouen and Salisbury122
XI.Balcony in Campo St. Benedetto, Venice131
XII.Fragments from Abbeville, Lucca, Venice, and Pisa149
XIII.Parts of an arcade on the south side of the Cathedral of Ferrara161
XIV.Sculptures from the Rouen Cathedral165
 
Lectures on Architecture and Art
PlateI.Figs.1,3 and 5. Example Diagrams219
"II."2.Window at Oakham Castle221
"III."46. Ash tree spray and its enhancement based on Greek principles.226
"IV."7.Window in Dunblane Cathedral231
"V."8.Medieval Tower235
"VI."9and 10. Lombard Towers238
"VII."11and 12. Spires in Caen and Rouen240
"VIII."13and 14. Illustrative Diagrams253
"IX."15.Sculpture in Lyon254
"X."16.Niche in Amiens255
"XI."17and 18. Tiger's Head, and enhancing it based on Greek principles.258
"XII."19.Garret Window in Hotel de Bourgtheroude265
"XIII."20and 21. Trees, as depicted in the thirteenth century294
"XIV."22.Rocks, as illustrated by the school of Leonardo Da Vinci.296
"XV."23.Branches of Trees, after Titian298

THE
SEVEN LAMPS
OF
ARCHITECTURE


PREFACE.

The memoranda which form the basis of the following Essay have been thrown together during the preparation of one of the sections of the third volume of "Modern Painters."[A] I once thought of giving them a more expanded form; but their utility, such as it may be, would probably be diminished by farther delay in their publication, more than it would be increased by greater care in their arrangement. Obtained in every case by personal observation, there may be among them some details valuable even to the experienced architect; but with respect to the opinions founded upon them I must be prepared to bear the charge of impertinence which can hardly but attach to the writer who assumes a dogmatical tone in speaking of an art he has never practised. There are, however, cases in which men feel too keenly to be silent, and perhaps too strongly to be wrong; I have been forced into this impertinence; and have suffered too much from the destruction or neglect of the architecture I best loved, and from the erection of that which I cannot love, to reason cautiously [Pg 6]respecting the modesty of my opposition to the principles which have induced the scorn of the one, or directed the design of the other. And I have been the less careful to modify the confidence of my statements of principles, because in the midst of the opposition and uncertainty of our architectural systems, it seems to me that there is something grateful in any positive opinion, though in many points wrong, as even weeds are useful that grow on a bank of sand.

The notes that make up the following essay were compiled during the preparation of one of the sections of the third volume of "Modern Painters."[A] I considered expanding them further; however, their usefulness, whatever it may be, would likely decrease from any further delay in publishing them, rather than increase from taking more time to organize them. Each observation comes from my personal experience, and there may be details valuable even to an experienced architect; however, I understand that my opinions could be seen as presumptuous, since I speak with authority about an art I’ve never practiced. Yet, there are situations where one feels too strongly to remain silent, and perhaps too passionately to be incorrect; I've been pushed into this presumption, having suffered greatly from the destruction or disregard of the architecture I cherished, and from the construction of what I cannot appreciate, to carefully consider the nature of my opposition to the principles that have led to the disdain of one style or influenced the design of the other. I have also been less cautious in expressing my confidence in my principles because, amid the opposition and confusion in our architectural systems, I believe there is something refreshing about any definitive opinion, even if incorrect in many aspects, just as even weeds can be beneficial when growing on a bank of sand.

Every apology is, however, due to the reader, for the hasty and imperfect execution of the plates. Having much more serious work in hand, and desiring merely to render them illustrative of my meaning, I have sometimes very completely failed even of that humble aim; and the text, being generally written before the illustration was completed, sometimes naïvely describes as sublime or beautiful, features which the plate represents by a blot. I shall be grateful if the reader will in such cases refer the expressions of praise to the Architecture, and not to the illustration.

Every apology is owed to the reader for the rushed and incomplete execution of the illustrations. With much more important work at hand, and simply wanting to make them clear to my point, I have occasionally failed to achieve even that modest goal; and since the text was mostly written before the illustrations were finished, it often innocently describes as amazing or beautiful elements that the illustration depicts as a smudge. I would appreciate it if the reader could attribute any praise to the Architecture itself, rather than to the illustrations.

So far, however, as their coarseness and rudeness admit, the plates are valuable; being either copies of memoranda made upon the spot, or (Plates IX. and XI.) enlarged and adapted from Daguerreotypes, taken under my own superintendence. Unfortunately, the great distance from the ground of the window which is the subject of Plate IX. renders even the Daguerreotype indistinct; and I cannot answer for the accuracy of any of the mosaic details, more especially of those which surround the window, and which I rather imagine, in the original, to be sculptured in relief. The general proportions are, however, studiously preserved; the spirals of the shafts are counted, and the effect of the whole is as near that of the thing itself, as is necessary for the purposes of illustration for which the plate is given. For the accuracy of the rest I can answer, even to the cracks in the stones, and the number of them; and though the looseness of the drawing, and the picturesque character which is necessarily given by an endeavor to draw old buildings as they actually appear, may perhaps diminish their credit for architectural veracity, they will do so unjustly.

So far, as the roughness and lack of refinement allow, the illustrations are valuable; they are either copies of notes made on-site or (Plates IX. and XI.) enlarged and adapted from Daguerreotypes taken under my direct supervision. Unfortunately, the significant height of the window featured in Plate IX makes even the Daguerreotype unclear; I can’t guarantee the accuracy of any of the intricate details, especially those surrounding the window, which I believe are sculpted in relief in the original. However, the overall proportions are carefully maintained; the spirals of the columns are counted, and the overall effect is as close to the actual thing as needed for illustration purposes. I can confirm the accuracy of the rest, even the cracks in the stones and their quantity; although the loose drawing style and the picturesque quality that come from trying to depict old buildings as they truly look may somewhat undermine their credibility for architectural accuracy, that would be unfair.

The system of lettering adopted in the few instances in which sections have been given, appears somewhat obscure in the references, but it is convenient upon the whole. The line which marks the direction of any section is noted, if the section be symmetrical, by a single letter; and the section itself by the same letter with a line over it, a.—ā. But if the section be unsymmetrical, its direction is noted by two letters, a. a. a2 at its extremities; and the actual section by the same letters with lines over them, ā. ā. ā2, at the corresponding extremities.

The system of lettering used in the few cases where sections are provided seems a bit unclear in the references, but it's generally convenient. The direction of a symmetrical section is indicated by a single letter, and the section itself is represented by that same letter with a line over it, a.—ā. If the section is asymmetrical, its direction is indicated by two letters, a. a. a2, at the ends; and the actual section is represented by those same letters with lines over them, ā. ā. ā2, at the corresponding ends.

The reader will perhaps be surprised by the small number of buildings to which reference has been made. But it is to be remembered that the following chapters pretend only to be a statement of principles, illustrated each by one or two examples, not an essay on European architecture; and those examples I have generally taken either from the buildings which I love best, or from the schools of architecture which, it appeared to me, have been less carefully described than they deserved. I could as fully, though not with the accuracy and certainty derived from personal observation, have illustrated the principles subsequently advanced, from the architecture of Egypt, India, or Spain, as from that to which the reader will find his attention chiefly directed, the Italian Romanesque and Gothic. But my affections, as well as my experience, led me to that line of richly varied and magnificently intellectual schools, which reaches, like a high watershed of Christian architecture, from the Adriatic to the Northumbrian seas, bordered by the impure schools of Spain on the one hand, and of Germany on the other: and as culminating points and centres of this chain, I have considered, first, the cities of the Val d'Arno, as representing the Italian Romanesque and pure Italian Gothic; Venice and Verona as representing the Italian Gothic colored by Byzantine elements; and Rouen, with the associated Norman cities, Caen, Bayeux, and Coutances, as representing the entire range of Northern architecture from the Romanesque to Flamboyant.

The reader might be surprised by the small number of buildings mentioned. However, it's important to remember that the following chapters aim to share principles, each illustrated by one or two examples, rather than providing a comprehensive essay on European architecture. I have generally chosen examples from the buildings I love most or from architectural styles that seemed to be less thoroughly described than they deserve. I could have illustrated the principles later discussed using examples from the architecture of Egypt, India, or Spain, just as easily, albeit without the same level of personal observation accuracy. But my preferences and experiences led me to focus on the richly diverse and intellectually stimulating schools of architecture that stretch like a high ridge of Christian architecture from the Adriatic to the Northumbrian seas, flanked by the less refined schools of Spain on one side and Germany on the other. As key points in this chain, I have looked at the cities of the Val d'Arno for Italian Romanesque and pure Italian Gothic; Venice and Verona for Italian Gothic influenced by Byzantine elements; and Rouen, along with the associated Norman cities of Caen, Bayeux, and Coutances, to represent the full spectrum of Northern architecture from Romanesque to Flamboyant.

I could have wished to have given more examples from our early English Gothic; but I have always found it impossible [Pg 8]to work in the cold interiors of our cathedrals, while the daily services, lamps, and fumigation of those upon the Continent, render them perfectly safe. In the course of last summer I undertook a pilgrimage to the English Shrines, and began with Salisbury, where the consequence of a few days' work was a state of weakened health, which I may be permitted to name among the causes of the slightness and imperfection of the present Essay.

I would have liked to provide more examples from our early English Gothic; however, I've always found it impossible to delve into the cold interiors of our cathedrals, while the daily services, lighting, and incense on the Continent make them completely accessible. Last summer, I took a pilgrimage to the English Shrines, starting with Salisbury, where a few days of work left me in a weakened state of health. I mention this as one of the reasons for the brevity and imperfections of this Essay.


INTRODUCTORY.

Some years ago, in conversation with an artist whose works, perhaps, alone, in the present day, unite perfection of drawing with resplendence of color, the writer made some inquiry respecting the general means by which this latter quality was most easily to be attained. The reply was as concise as it was comprehensive—"Know what you have to do, and do it"—comprehensive, not only as regarded the branch of art to which it temporarily applied, but as expressing the great principle of success in every direction of human effort; for I believe that failure is less frequently attributable to either insufficiency of means or impatience of labor, than to a confused understanding of the thing actually to be done; and therefore, while it is properly a subject of ridicule, and sometimes of blame, that men propose to themselves a perfection of any kind, which reason, temperately consulted, might have shown to be impossible with the means at their command, it is a more dangerous error to permit the consideration of means to interfere with our conception, or, as is not impossible, even hinder our acknowledgment of goodness and perfection in themselves. And this is the more cautiously to be remembered; because, while a man's sense and conscience, aided by Revelation, are always enough, if earnestly directed, to enable him to discover what is right, neither his sense, nor conscience, nor feeling, are ever enough, because they are not intended, to determine for him what is possible. He knows neither his own strength nor that of his fellows, neither the exact dependence to be placed on his allies nor resistance to be expected from his opponents. These are questions respecting which passion may warp his conclusions, and ignorance must limit[Pg 10] them; but it is his own fault if either interfere with the apprehension of duty, or the acknowledgment of right. And, as far as I have taken cognizance of the causes of the many failures to which the efforts of intelligent men are liable, more especially in matters political, they seem to me more largely to spring from this single error than from all others, that the inquiry into the doubtful, and in some sort inexplicable, relations of capability, chance, resistance, and inconvenience, invariably precedes, even if it do not altogether supersede, the determination of what is absolutely desirable and just. Nor is it any wonder that sometimes the too cold calculation of our powers should reconcile us too easily to our shortcomings, and even lead us into the fatal error of supposing that our conjectural utmost is in itself well, or, in other words, that the necessity of offences renders them inoffensive.

A few years ago, I talked with an artist whose work, perhaps uniquely in today’s world, combines perfect drawing with vibrant colors. I asked how to best achieve that vividness. The answer was as brief as it was insightful: "Know what you have to do, and do it." This insight not only applies to art but also represents a fundamental principle of success in all human endeavors. I believe failure often results not from a lack of resources or impatience but from a muddled understanding of what needs to be accomplished. Thus, while it can be ridiculous or even blameworthy for people to aim for an unattainable perfection—one that reason would have shown isn't possible with what they have—it's even more dangerous to let our focus on resources cloud our vision or, worse, prevent us from recognizing good and perfection in themselves. It’s important to remember this carefully, because while a person’s judgment and conscience, guided by revelation, can help them see what is right if they are truly committed, neither their judgment nor conscience nor feelings can determine what is actually possible. They do not know their own strength or that of others, nor how much they can rely on allies or resist opponents. These are issues where passion can skew perceptions and ignorance limits them. However, it is a personal failing if either interferes with recognizing duty or acknowledging right. From what I’ve observed about the many failures intelligent people face, especially in politics, they mostly stem from this one mistake: probing the unclear and complex relationships of ability, luck, resistance, and difficulties almost always happens before, and sometimes instead of, defining what is truly desirable and just. It’s no surprise that being overly cold and calculating about our capabilities can make us too comfortable with our inadequacies and can even lead us to mistakenly believe that what we can only guess at is acceptable, or that the need for imperfection makes it acceptable.

What is true of human polity seems to me not less so of the distinctively political art of Architecture. I have long felt convinced of the necessity, in order to its progress, of some determined effort to extricate from the confused mass of partial traditions and dogmata with which it has become encumbered during imperfect or restricted practice, those large principles of right which are applicable to every stage and style of it. Uniting the technical and imaginative elements as essentially as humanity does soul and body, it shows the same infirmly balanced liability to the prevalence of the lower part over the higher, to the interference of the constructive, with the purity and simplicity of the reflective, element. This tendency, like every other form of materialism, is increasing with the advance of the age; and the only laws which resist it, based upon partial precedents, and already regarded with disrespect as decrepit, if not with defiance as tyrannical, are evidently inapplicable to the new forms and functions of the art, which the necessities of the day demand. How many these necessities may become, cannot be conjectured; they rise, strange and impatient, out of every modern shadow of change. How far it may be possible to meet them without a sacrifice of the essential characters of architectural art, cannot be determined by specific calculation or observance. There is no law, no[Pg 11] principle, based on past practice, which may not be overthrown in a moment, by the arising of a new condition, or the invention of a new material; and the most rational, if not the only, mode of averting the danger of an utter dissolution of all that is systematic and consistent in our practice, or of ancient authority in our judgment, is to cease for a little while, our endeavors to deal with the multiplying host of particular abuses, restraints, or requirements; and endeavor to determine, as the guides of every effort, some constant, general, and irrefragable laws of right—laws, which based upon man's nature, not upon his knowledge, may possess so far the unchangeableness of the one, as that neither the increase nor imperfection of the other may be able to assault or invalidate them.

What holds true for human governance also applies to the unique political art of Architecture. I have long been convinced that, for its progress, we need a concerted effort to extract from the confusing mix of partial traditions and doctrines that it has accumulated due to incomplete or limited practices, those broad principles of right that are relevant to every stage and style. By integrating the technical and creative aspects as fundamentally as humanity connects soul and body, it exhibits the same fragile balance where the lower aspects can overshadow the higher, and where structural concerns interfere with the clarity and simplicity of the reflective side. This inclination, like every other form of materialism, is growing as times change. The only rules resisting it, rooted in partial precedents and already viewed with disregard as outdated, if not with defiance as oppressive, are clearly not suitable for the new forms and functions the demands of our time require. We cannot predict how many of these demands might emerge; they arise, strangely and urgently, from every modern shadow of change. We cannot determine how far we can address them without compromising the essential qualities of architectural art through specific calculations or observations. There is no law, no[Pg 11] principle based on past practice that cannot be quickly overturned by the emergence of a new condition or the invention of a new material; and the most logical, if not the only, way to prevent the complete breakdown of everything systematic and coherent in our practice or of ancient authority in our judgment is to pause briefly in our efforts to tackle the growing number of specific issues, restrictions, or requirements, and instead strive to establish, as the foundation of every effort, some constant, general, and irrefutable laws of right—laws that are based on human nature rather than knowledge, so that they might possess a stability akin to the former, impervious to the impacts of the latter, whether through its growth or shortcoming.

There are, perhaps, no such laws peculiar to any one art. Their range necessarily includes the entire horizon of man's action. But they have modified forms and operations belonging to each of his pursuits, and the extent of their authority cannot surely be considered as a diminution of its weight. Those peculiar aspects of them which belong to the first of the arts, I have endeavored to trace in the following pages; and since, if truly stated, they must necessarily be, not only safeguards against every form of error, but sources of every measure of success, I do not think that I claim too much for them in calling them the Lamps of Architecture, nor that it is indolence, in endeavoring to ascertain the true nature and nobility of their fire, to refuse to enter into any curious or special questioning of the innumerable hindrances by which their light has been too often distorted or overpowered.

There aren't really any laws that are unique to just one art form. Their scope covers all aspects of human action. However, they take on different forms and functions specific to each of a person's activities, and the degree of their influence shouldn't be seen as a reduction in significance. I’ve tried to outline the unique features that relate to the first of the arts in the following pages. If explained correctly, these features should not only protect against various errors but also provide a foundation for achieving success. Therefore, I don't think I'm overreaching by calling them the Lamps of Architecture. Moreover, it’s not laziness to want to understand the true nature and value of their light; it seems unwise to avoid exploring the many challenges that have often distorted or overwhelmed their illumination.

Had this farther examination been attempted, the work would have become certainly more invidious, and perhaps less useful, as liable to errors which are avoided by the present simplicity of its plan. Simple though it be, its extent is too great to admit of any adequate accomplishment, unless by a devotion of time which the writer did not feel justified in withdrawing from branches of inquiry in which the prosecution of works already undertaken has engaged him. Both arrangements and nomenclature are those of convenience rather than of system; the one is arbitrary and the other illogical: nor is[Pg 12] it pretended that all, or even the greater number of, the principles necessary to the well-being of the art, are included in the inquiry. Many, however, of considerable importance will be found to develope themselves incidentally from those more specially brought forward.

If this further examination had been attempted, the work would have definitely become more contentious and possibly less useful, as it could lead to errors that are avoided by the current simplicity of its plan. Simple as it is, its scope is too broad to allow for any meaningful completion without dedicating time that the writer felt was better spent on other research pursuits he is already involved in. Both the organization and naming conventions used are based on convenience rather than a systematic approach; one is arbitrary and the other is illogical. It is not claimed that all, or even the majority of, the principles essential for the effective practice of the art are included in this investigation. However, many, which are quite important, will emerge incidentally from those that are specifically highlighted.

Graver apology is necessary for an apparently graver fault. It has been just said, that there is no branch of human work whose constant laws have not close analogy with those which govern every other mode of man's exertion. But, more than this, exactly as we reduce to greater simplicity and surety any one group of these practical laws, we shall find them passing the mere condition of connection or analogy, and becoming the actual expression of some ultimate nerve or fibre of the mighty laws which govern the moral world. However mean or inconsiderable the act, there is something in the well doing of it, which has fellowship with the noblest forms of manly virtue; and the truth, decision, and temperance, which we reverently regard as honorable conditions of the spiritual being, have a representative or derivative influence over the works of the hand, the movements of the frame, and the action of the intellect.

A more serious apology is needed for a more serious mistake. It has just been said that there is no area of human work whose consistent principles don't closely resemble those that govern every other way humans exert themselves. But, beyond that, just as we simplify and clarify any one group of these practical principles, we will find that they go beyond mere connection or analogy and become the real expression of some fundamental nerve or fiber of the vast laws that govern the moral world. No matter how minor or insignificant the act may seem, there is something in doing it well that connects with the highest forms of human virtue; and the truth, decisiveness, and self-control that we deeply respect as honorable qualities of our spiritual existence have a representative or derived influence on our physical actions, body movements, and mental processes.

And as thus every action, down even to the drawing of a line or utterance of a syllable, is capable of a peculiar dignity in the manner of it, which we sometimes express by saying it is truly done (as a line or tone is true), so also it is capable of dignity still higher in the motive of it. For there is no action so slight, nor so mean, but it may be done to a great purpose, and ennobled therefore; nor is any purpose so great but that slight actions may help it, and may be so done as to help it much, most especially that chief of all purposes, the pleasing of God. Hence George Herbert—

And just like how every action, even something as simple as drawing a line or saying a word, has a certain dignity in how it's done, which we often refer to as being done in a "true" way (like a true line or tone), it can also have an even greater dignity based on its motivation. No action is too small or insignificant that it can't be done for a greater purpose and thus made noble; likewise, there's no great purpose so lofty that small actions can't contribute to it, especially when it comes to the most important purpose of all: pleasing God. Hence George Herbert—

"A servant with this clause
Makes drudgery divine;
Who sweeps a room, as for thy laws,
Makes that and the action fine."

"A servant with this clause
Transforms hard work into something amazing;
Who cleans a room, as if by your rules,
"That makes the task and the effort worthwhile."

Therefore, in the pressing or recommending of any act or manner of acting, we have choice of two separate lines of ar[Pg 13]gument: one based on representation of the expediency or inherent value of the work, which is often small, and always disputable; the other based on proofs of its relations to the higher orders of human virtue, and of its acceptableness, so far as it goes, to Him who is the origin of virtue. The former is commonly the more persuasive method, the latter assuredly the more conclusive; only it is liable to give offence, as if there were irreverence in adducing considerations so weighty in treating subjects of small temporal importance. I believe, however, that no error is more thoughtless than this. We treat God with irreverence by banishing Him from our thoughts, not by referring to His will on slight occasions. His is not the finite authority or intelligence which cannot be troubled with small things. There is nothing so small but that we may honor God by asking His guidance of it, or insult Him by taking it into our own hands; and what is true of the Deity is equally true of His Revelation. We use it most reverently when most habitually: our insolence is in ever acting without reference to it, our true honoring of it is in its universal application. I have been blamed for the familiar introduction of its sacred words. I am grieved to have given pain by so doing; but my excuse must be my wish that those words were made the ground of every argument and the test of every action. We have them not often enough on our lips, nor deeply enough in our memories, nor loyally enough in our lives. The snow, the vapor, and the stormy wind fulfil His word. Are our acts and thoughts lighter and wilder than these—that we should forget it?

Therefore, when advocating for any action or way of acting, we have a choice between two distinct arguments: one that focuses on the practicality or inherent value of the work, which is often minimal and always debatable; the other that relies on evidence of its connection to higher human virtues and its acceptance by the one who is the source of virtue. The first method is usually more convincing, while the second is certainly more definitive; however, it risks offending others, as if bringing up such significant considerations for trivial matters is irreverent. I believe, though, that there is no greater mistake than this. We disrespect God by excluding Him from our thoughts, not by mentioning His will in minor situations. His authority and wisdom are not so limited that He cannot be concerned with small matters. Nothing is too insignificant that we cannot honor God by seeking His guidance on it or insult Him by handling it ourselves; and what applies to God also applies to His Revelation. We treat it with the most reverence when we incorporate it into our everyday lives: our arrogance lies in acting without considering it, and our true respect for it comes from its constant application. I have faced criticism for casually including its sacred words. I regret causing pain by doing so, but my reasoning must be my hope that those words become the foundation of every argument and the measure of every action. We don't speak those words often enough, don't keep them deeply enough in our minds, or don't honor them faithfully enough in our lives. The snow, the vapor, and the stormy wind fulfill His word. Are our actions and thoughts lighter and more reckless than these, that we should forget Him?

I have therefore ventured, at the risk of giving to some passages the appearance of irreverence, to take the higher line of argument wherever it appeared clearly traceable: and this, I would ask the reader especially to observe, not merely because I think it the best mode of reaching ultimate truth, still less because I think the subject of more importance than many others; but because every subject should surely, at a period like the present, be taken up in this spirit, or not at all. The aspect of the years that approach us is as solemn as it is full of mystery; and the weight of evil against which we[Pg 14] have to contend, is increasing like the letting out of water. It is no time for the idleness of metaphysics, or the entertainment of the arts. The blasphemies of the earth are sounding louder, and its miseries heaped heavier every day; and if, in the midst of the exertion which every good man is called upon to put forth for their repression or relief, it is lawful to ask for a thought, for a moment, for a lifting of the finger, in any direction but that of the immediate and overwhelming need, it is at least incumbent upon us to approach the questions in which we would engage him, in the spirit which has become the habit of his mind, and in the hope that neither his zeal nor his usefulness may be checked by the withdrawal of an hour which has shown him how even those things which seemed mechanical, indifferent, or contemptible, depend for their perfection upon the acknowledgment of the sacred principles of faith, truth, and obedience, for which it has become the occupation of his life to contend.

I've taken the risk of making some parts seem irreverent, but I've chosen a more elevated way of discussing things wherever it was clear to me. I ask the reader to pay special attention to this, not just because I believe it's the best way to uncover ultimate truth, and definitely not because I think this topic is more important than others, but because every topic should be approached in this way, especially at a time like now. The years ahead are serious and mysterious; the weight of the challenges we're facing is becoming more overwhelming, like water spilling out. This isn’t a time for idle philosophical discussions or artistic distractions. The world's blasphemies are getting louder, and its suffering is piling up every day. If, amidst the efforts that every decent person is called to make for relief or to combat these issues, we are allowed to take a moment to think, or direct our attention anywhere other than the immediate crisis, we must at least tackle the questions we want to discuss in a way that reflects the mindset that is now common, with the hope that neither the enthusiasm nor the effectiveness of those striving to help will be diminished by the brief withdrawal of focus that reveals how even what seems routine or trivial relies on acknowledging the sacred values of faith, truth, and obedience—values that have become the purpose of their lives to defend.


THE SEVEN LAMPS OF ARCHITECTURE.


CHAPTER I.

THE LAMP OF SACRIFICE.

I. Architecture is the art which so disposes and adorns the edifices raised by man for whatsoever uses, that the sight of them contributes to his mental health, power and pleasure.

I. Architecture is the art that designs and decorates the buildings created by humans for any purpose, so that seeing them enhances their mental well-being, strength, and enjoyment.

It is very necessary, in the outset of all inquiry, to distinguish carefully between Architecture and Building.

It is really important, at the beginning of any investigation, to clearly differentiate between Architecture and Building.

To build, literally to confirm, is by common understanding to put together and adjust the several pieces of any edifice or receptacle of a considerable size. Thus we have church building, house building, ship building, and coach building. That one edifice stands, another floats, and another is suspended on iron springs, makes no difference in the nature of the art, if so it may be called, of building or edification. The persons who profess that art, are severally builders, ecclesiastical, naval, or of whatever other name their work may justify; but building does not become architecture merely by the stability of what it erects; and it is no more architecture which raises a church, or which fits it to receive and contain with comfort a required number of persons occupied in certain religious offices, than it is architecture which makes a carriage commodious or a ship swift. I do not, of course, mean that the word is not often, or even may not be legitimately, applied in such a sense (as we speak of naval architecture); but in that sense architecture ceases to be one of the fine arts, and it is therefore better not to run the risk, by loose nomenclature, of the confusion which would arise, and has often arisen, from[Pg 16] extending principles which belong altogether to building, into the sphere of architecture proper.

To build, which means to confirm, is commonly understood as putting together and arranging various parts of a large structure or container. This includes building churches, houses, ships, and coaches. Whether one structure stands, another floats, or another is supported by springs doesn't change the essence of the craft, if we can call it that, of building. Those who practice this craft are known as builders—ecclesiastical, naval, or by whatever name their work suggests; however, building doesn't become architecture simply because of the stability of the structures created. Constructing a church or making it comfortable for a certain number of people engaged in religious services isn't architecture, just as designing a comfy carriage or a fast ship isn't architecture either. I certainly don't mean to imply that the term can't be used in such ways (as in naval architecture); however, in that context, architecture stops being considered one of the fine arts. Therefore, it's best not to risk confusion, which has often happened, by broadly applying principles that belong strictly to building, instead of to true architecture.

Let us, therefore, at once confine the name to that art which, taking up and admitting, as conditions of its working, the necessities and common uses of the building, impresses on its form certain characters venerable or beautiful, but otherwise unnecessary. Thus, I suppose, no one would call the laws architectural which determine the height of a breastwork or the position of a bastion. But if to the stone facing of that bastion be added an unnecessary feature, as a cable moulding, that is Architecture. It would be similarly unreasonable to call battlements or machicolations architectural features, so long as they consist only of an advanced gallery supported on projecting masses, with open intervals beneath for offence. But if these projecting masses be carved beneath into rounded courses, which are useless, and if the headings of the intervals be arched and trefoiled, which is useless, that is Architecture. It may not be always easy to draw the line so sharply and simply, because there are few buildings which have not some pretence or color of being architectural; neither can there be any architecture which is not based on building, nor any good architecture which is not based on good building; but it is perfectly easy and very necessary to keep the ideas distinct, and to understand fully that Architecture concerns itself only with those characters of an edifice which are above and beyond its common use. I say common; because a building raised to the honor of God, or in memory of men, has surely a use to which its architectural adornment fits it; but not a use which limits, by any inevitable necessities, its plan or details.

Let's narrow down the term to that art which, while acknowledging the requirements and typical functions of a structure, adds to its design certain elements that are either esteemed or aesthetically pleasing, but not essential. For example, no one would classify the rules governing the height of a parapet or the location of a bastion as architectural. However, if an unnecessary detail like a decorative molding is added to the stone surface of that bastion, then that qualifies as Architecture. Similarly, it wouldn't make sense to call battlements or machicolations architectural features as long as they are merely an extended gallery supported by protruding structures with open spaces underneath for defense. But if these protruding parts are carved into rounded designs that serve no real purpose, and if the openings are adorned with arches and ornamental loops, which are also unnecessary, then that is Architecture. It might not always be straightforward to draw a clear line because few buildings lack any semblance of architectural intent; furthermore, no architecture exists without being based on construction, and no quality architecture can emerge from poor building. However, it is essential to keep these concepts separate and to recognize that Architecture is concerned only with those aspects of a building that go beyond its basic usage. I say basic because a structure built to honor God or to commemorate someone indeed has a purpose that its architectural embellishments serve, but it's not a purpose that confines its design or details through any strict necessities.

II. Architecture proper, then, naturally arranges itself under five heads:—

II. Architecture itself can naturally be categorized into five main areas:—

Devotional; including all buildings raised for God's service or honor.
Memorial; including both monuments and tombs.
Civil; including every edifice raised by nations or societies, for purposes of common business or pleasure.
Military; including all private and public architecture of defence.
[Pg 17] Domestic; including every rank and kind of dwelling-place.

Devotional; including all buildings built for God's service or honor.
Memorial; including both monuments and tombs.
Civil; including every structure built by nations or societies for common business or leisure.
Military; including all public and private defense architecture.
[Pg 17] Domestic; including all types of homes.

Now, of the principles which I would endeavor to develope, while all must be, as I have said, applicable to every stage and style of the art, some, and especially those which are exciting rather than directing, have necessarily fuller reference to one kind of building than another; and among these I would place first that spirit which, having influence in all, has nevertheless such especial reference to devotional and memorial architecture—the spirit which offers for such work precious things simply because they are precious; not as being necessary to the building, but as an offering, surrendering, and sacrifice of what is to ourselves desirable. It seems to me, not only that this feeling is in most cases wholly wanting in those who forward the devotional buildings of the present day; but that it would even be regarded as an ignorant, dangerous, or perhaps criminal principle by many among us. I have not space to enter into dispute of all the various objections which may be urged against it—they are many and spacious; but I may, perhaps, ask the reader's patience while I set down those simple reasons which cause me to believe it a good and just feeling, and as well-pleasing to God and honorable in men, as it is beyond all dispute necessary to the production of any great work in the kind with which we are at present concerned.

Now, regarding the principles that I aim to develop, while all of them, as I've mentioned, should apply to every stage and style of the art, some—especially those that are more about evoking emotion than giving direction—naturally relate more closely to one type of building than another. Among these, I want to highlight first the spirit that, while influencing all architecture, has a particularly strong connection to devotional and memorial structures. This spirit offers precious things simply because they are precious—not because they are necessary for the building, but as a gift, a surrender, and a sacrifice of what we personally value. It seems to me that this sentiment is largely absent in those who are promoting current devotional buildings, and some may even view it as an ignorant, dangerous, or perhaps even criminal idea. I don’t have the space to address all the various objections that might be raised against it—they are numerous and substantial—but I would like to ask for the reader's understanding as I outline the simple reasons that lead me to believe this feeling is good and just, honoring to God and respected by people, and absolutely essential for creating any significant work in the field we are currently discussing.

III. Now, first, to define this Lamp, or Spirit of Sacrifice, clearly. I have said that it prompts us to the offering of precious things merely because they are precious, not because they are useful or necessary. It is a spirit, for instance, which of two marbles, equally beautiful, applicable and durable, would choose the more costly because it was so, and of two kinds of decoration, equally effective, would choose the more elaborate because it was so, in order that it might in the same compass present more cost and more thought. It is therefore most unreasoning and enthusiastic, and perhaps best negatively defined, as the opposite of the prevalent feeling of modern times, which desires to produce the largest results at the least cost.

III. First, let’s clearly define this Lamp, or Spirit of Sacrifice. I’ve said that it inspires us to offer valuable things simply because they’re valuable, not because they’re useful or necessary. It’s a spirit that, for example, would choose the more expensive of two equally beautiful, suitable, and durable marbles, and select the more intricate of two equally effective decorations, just to show more expense and thought within the same space. It is, therefore, quite irrational and passionate, and perhaps best described as the opposite of the common mindset today, which aims to achieve the biggest results at the lowest cost.

Of this feeling, then, there are two distinct forms: the first, the wish to exercise self-denial for the sake of self-discipline[Pg 18] merely, a wish acted upon in the abandonment of things loved or desired, there being no direct call or purpose to be answered by so doing; and the second, the desire to honor or please some one else by the costliness of the sacrifice. The practice is, in the first case, either private or public; but most frequently, and perhaps most properly, private; while, in the latter case, the act is commonly, and with greatest advantage, public. Now, it cannot but at first appear futile to assert the expediency of self-denial for its own sake, when, for so many sakes, it is every day necessary to a far greater degree than any of us practise it. But I believe it is just because we do not enough acknowledge or contemplate it as a good in itself, that we are apt to fail in its duties when they become imperative, and to calculate, with some partiality, whether the good proposed to others measures or warrants the amount of grievance to ourselves, instead of accepting with gladness the opportunity of sacrifice as a personal advantage. Be this as it may, it is not necessary to insist upon the matter here; since there are always higher and more useful channels of self-sacrifice, for those who choose to practise it, than any connected with the arts.

This feeling can take two distinct forms: the first is the desire to practice self-denial purely for self-discipline, a wish acted out by giving up things that are loved or desired, without any direct purpose behind it; the second is the desire to honor or please someone else through the value of the sacrifice. In the first case, the practice is often private or public, but it's most commonly and perhaps appropriately private. In the second case, the act is typically public and offers the greatest benefit. At first glance, it may seem pointless to emphasize the usefulness of self-denial for its own sake, especially since it is often required to a greater extent than we usually practice. However, I believe it’s precisely because we don’t acknowledge or reflect on it as a good in itself that we fail to fulfill its duties when they become necessary, and we end up weighing whether the good we do for others justifies the inconvenience to ourselves, instead of joyfully embracing the opportunity for sacrifice as a personal benefit. Regardless, it’s not necessary to dwell on this now; there are always higher and more beneficial ways to practice self-sacrifice for those who choose to do so than anything related to the arts.

While in its second branch, that which is especially concerned with the arts, the justice of the feeling is still more doubtful; it depends on our answer to the broad question, Can the Deity be indeed honored by the presentation to Him of any material objects of value, or by any direction of zeal or wisdom which is not immediately beneficial to men?

While in its second branch, which specifically focuses on the arts, the fairness of this feeling is even more questionable; it relies on how we answer the broader question: Can God truly be honored by offering Him any valuable material objects, or by any efforts of enthusiasm or wisdom that do not directly benefit people?

For, observe, it is not now the question whether the fairness and majesty of a building may or may not answer any moral purpose; it is not the result of labor in any sort of which we are speaking, but the bare and mere costliness—the substance and labor and time themselves: are these, we ask, independently of their result, acceptable offerings to God, and considered by Him as doing Him honor? So long as we refer this question to the decision of feeling, or of conscience, or of reason merely, it will be contradictorily or imperfectly answered; it admits of entire answer only when we have met another and a far different question, whether the Bible be[Pg 19] indeed one book or two, and whether the character of God revealed in the Old Testament be other than His character revealed in the New.

For, look, it’s not about whether the beauty and grandeur of a building serve any moral purpose; we’re not talking about the outcome of labor in any form, but the sheer expense—the materials, labor, and time themselves: are these, we ask, apart from their outcome, acceptable offerings to God, and does He see them as honoring Him? As long as we leave this question to feelings, conscience, or reason alone, it will be answered in conflicting or incomplete ways; it can only be fully answered when we address another, very different question: whether the Bible is one book or two, and whether the character of God shown in the Old Testament is different from His character revealed in the New.

IV. Now, it is a most secure truth, that, although the particular ordinances divinely appointed for special purposes at any given period of man's history, may be by the same divine authority abrogated at another, it is impossible that any character of God, appealed to or described in any ordinance past or present, can ever be changed, or understood as changed, by the abrogation of that ordinance. God is one and the same, and is pleased or displeased by the same things for ever, although one part of His pleasure may be expressed at one time rather than another, and although the mode in which His pleasure is to be consulted may be by Him graciously modified to the circumstances of men. Thus, for instance, it was necessary that, in order to the understanding by man of the scheme of Redemption, that scheme should be foreshown from the beginning by the type of bloody sacrifice. But God had no more pleasure in such sacrifice in the time of Moses than He has now; He never accepted as a propitiation for sin any sacrifice but the single one in prospective; and that we may not entertain any shadow of doubt on this subject, the worthlessness of all other sacrifice than this is proclaimed at the very time when typical sacrifice was most imperatively demanded. God was a spirit, and could be worshipped only in spirit and in truth, as singly and exclusively when every day brought its claim of typical and material service or offering, as now when He asks for none but that of the heart.

IV. Now, it's a well-established truth that while specific rules set by divine authority for particular purposes at any point in history can be revoked by the same authority later on, it's impossible for any aspect of God, referenced or described in any past or present ordinance, to ever change or be understood as having changed due to the revocation of that ordinance. God is consistent and unchanged, and His approval or disapproval of certain things remains the same forever, even if one aspect of His approval might be expressed at one time rather than another, and although the way His approval is sought may be graciously adapted to human circumstances. For example, it was necessary for people to understand the Redemption plan by seeing it symbolized from the beginning through the idea of bloody sacrifice. However, God found no more joy in such sacrifices during Moses's time than He does now; He has never accepted any sacrifice as a way to make up for sin except for the one that was to come. To eliminate any doubt on this matter, the uselessness of all sacrifices other than this one is made clear at the very moment when typical sacrifices were most urgently required. God is a spirit and can only be worshipped in spirit and truth, much as He seeks true devotion now when He requires nothing but what comes from the heart.

So, therefore, it is a most safe and sure principle that, if in the manner of performing any rite at any time, circumstances can be traced which we are either told, or may legitimately conclude, pleased God at that time, those same circumstances will please Him at all times, in the performance of all rites or offices to which they may be attached in like manner; unless it has been afterwards revealed that, for some special purpose, it is now His will that such circumstances should be withdrawn. And this argument will have all the more force if it can be shown that such conditions were not essential to the[Pg 20] completeness of the rite in its human uses and bearings, and only were added to it as being in themselves pleasing to God.

So, it's a solid principle that if we can identify circumstances during any rite that we believe pleased God at that time, those same circumstances will please Him at all times when performing similar rites or practices. This holds true unless it has been revealed later that, for some specific reason, it is now His will to remove those circumstances. This argument is even stronger if we can show that those conditions weren't essential for the rite's effectiveness in human use and were only included because they were pleasing to God in themselves.

V. Now, was it necessary to the completeness, as a type, of the Levitical sacrifice, or to its utility as an explanation of divine purposes, that it should cost anything to the person in whose behalf it was offered? On the contrary, the sacrifice which it foreshowed was to be God's free gift; and the cost of, or difficulty of obtaining, the sacrificial type, could only render that type in a measure obscure, and less expressive of the offering which God would in the end provide for all men. Yet this costliness was generally a condition of the acceptableness of the sacrifice. "Neither will I offer unto the Lord my God of that which doth cost me nothing."[B] That costliness, therefore, must be an acceptable condition in all human offerings at all times; for if it was pleasing to God once, it must please Him always, unless directly forbidden by Him afterwards, which it has never been.

V. Was it really necessary for the completeness of the Levitical sacrifice, as a symbol, or for its usefulness in explaining divine purposes, that it should cost the person on whose behalf it was offered anything? In fact, the sacrifice it represented was meant to be God's free gift; and the expense or difficulty in obtaining the sacrificial symbol could only make that symbol somewhat unclear and less representative of the offering that God would ultimately provide for everyone. Yet this expense was generally a requirement for the acceptance of the sacrifice. "Neither will I offer to the Lord my God anything that costs me nothing." That expense, therefore, must always be an acceptable condition for all human offerings at all times; because if it was pleasing to God once, it must please Him always, unless He explicitly forbids it later, which He has never done.

Again, was it necessary to the typical perfection of the Levitical offering, that it should be the best of the flock? Doubtless the spotlessness of the sacrifice renders it more expressive to the Christian mind; but was it because so expressive that it was actually, and in so many words, demanded by God? Not at all. It was demanded by Him expressly on the same grounds on which an earthly governor would demand it, as a testimony of respect. "Offer it now unto thy governor."[C] And the less valuable offering was rejected, not because it did not image Christ, nor fulfil the purposes of sacrifice, but because it indicated a feeling that would grudge the best of its possessions to Him who gave them; and because it was a bold dishonoring of God in the sight of man. Whence it may be infallibly concluded, that in whatever offerings we may now see reason to present unto God (I say not what these may be), a condition of their acceptableness will be now, as it was then, that they should be the best of their kind.

Again, was it necessary for the typical perfection of the Levitical offering that it had to be the best of the flock? Clearly, the purity of the sacrifice makes it more meaningful to the Christian perspective; however, was it actually demanded by God just because it was so significant? Not at all. He requested it specifically for the same reasons an earthly ruler would—out of respect. "Offer it now unto thy governor." And the less valuable offering was rejected, not because it didn't symbolize Christ or fulfill the purposes of sacrifice, but because it showed an unwillingness to give the best of its possessions to the one who granted them; and it was a blatant dishonor to God in front of others. Therefore, it can be concluded that in any offerings we now feel led to present to God (not specifying what these may be), one essential condition for their acceptance will be, just as it was then, that they should be the best of their kind.

VI. But farther, was it necessary to the carrying out of the Mosaical system, that there should be either art or splendor in the form or services of the tabernacle or temple? Was it [Pg 21]necessary to the perfection of any one of their typical offices, that there should be that hanging of blue, and purple, and scarlet? those taches of brass and sockets of silver? that working in cedar and overlaying with gold? One thing at least is evident: there was a deep and awful danger in it; a danger that the God whom they so worshipped, might be associated in the minds of the serfs of Egypt with the gods to whom they had seen similar gifts offered and similar honors paid. The probability, in our times, of fellowship with the feelings of the idolatrous Romanist is absolutely as nothing compared with the danger to the Israelite of a sympathy with the idolatrous Egyptian;1 no speculative, no unproved danger; but proved fatally by their fall during a month's abandonment to their own will; a fall into the most servile idolatry; yet marked by such offerings to their idol as their leader was, in the close sequel, instructed to bid them offer to God. This danger was imminent, perpetual, and of the most awful kind: it was the one against which God made provision, not only by commandments, by threatenings, by promises, the most urgent, repeated, and impressive; but by temporary ordinances of a severity so terrible as almost to dim for a time, in the eyes of His people, His attribute of mercy. The principal object of every instituted law of that Theocracy, of every judgment sent forth in its vindication, was to mark to the people His hatred of idolatry; a hatred written under their advancing steps, in the blood of the Canaanite, and more sternly still in the darkness of their own desolation, when the children and the sucklings swooned in the streets of Jerusalem, and the lion tracked his prey in the dust of Samaria.[D] Yet against this mortal danger provision was not made in one way (to man's thoughts the simplest, the most natural, the most effective), by withdrawing from the worship of the Divine Being whatever could delight the sense, or shape the imagination, or limit the idea of Deity to place. This one way God refused, demanding for Himself such honors, and accepting for Himself such local dwelling, as had been paid and dedicated to idol gods by heathen worshippers; [Pg 22]and for what reason? Was the glory of the tabernacle necessary to set forth or image His divine glory to the minds of His people? What! purple or scarlet necessary to the people who had seen the great river of Egypt run scarlet to the sea, under His condemnation? What! golden lamp and cherub necessary for those who had seen the fires of heaven falling like a mantle on Mount Sinai, and its golden courts opened to receive their mortal lawgiver? What! silver clasp and fillet necessary when they had seen the silver waves of the Red Sea clasp in their arched hollows the corpses of the horse and his rider? Nay—not so. There was but one reason, and that an eternal one; that as the covenant that He made with men was accompanied with some external sign of its continuance, and of His remembrance of it, so the acceptance of that covenant might be marked and signified by use, in some external sign of their love and obedience, and surrender of themselves and theirs to His will; and that their gratitude to Him, and continual remembrance of Him, might have at once their expression and their enduring testimony in the presentation to Him, not only of the firstlings of the herd and fold, not only of the fruits of the earth and the tithe of time, but of all treasures of wisdom and beauty; of the thought that invents, and the hand that labors; of wealth of wood, and weight of stone; of the strength of iron, and of the light of gold.

VI. But further, was it necessary for the implementation of the Mosaical system to have any art or splendor in the design or services of the tabernacle or temple? Was it essential for the perfection of any of their symbolic roles to have that hanging of blue, purple, and scarlet? Those brass clasps and silver sockets? That carpentry in cedar overlaid with gold? One thing is clear: there was a serious and terrifying risk in it; a risk that the God they worshipped could be associated in the minds of the Egyptian slaves with the gods to whom they had seen similar offerings and honors paid. The likelihood, in our time, of sharing the feelings of the idolatrous Roman is nowhere near as significant as the danger the Israelites faced in sympathizing with the idolatrous Egyptians; no speculative, unproven danger, but one that was fatally demonstrated by their downfall during a month of doing as they pleased, falling into the most degrading idolatry, yet marked by offerings to their idol that their leader was later instructed to have them offer to God. This danger was immediate, constant, and of the most horrible nature: it was the very one for which God made provisions, not only through commandments, threats, and urgent, repeated promises, but also through temporary laws so severe that they nearly obscured His mercy in the eyes of His people. The primary goal of every instituted law in that Theocracy, of every judgment issued in its defense, was to show the people His hatred of idolatry; a hatred that was inscribed on their advancing paths, in the blood of the Canaanites, and even more starkly in the desolation when children and infants collapsed in the streets of Jerusalem, and the lion stalked its prey in the dust of Samaria. Yet against this mortal danger, provision was not made in the simplest way (to human thought the most straightforward, natural, and effective), by removing from the worship of the Divine Being anything that could please the senses, shape the imagination, or confine the concept of Deity to a specific place. This single approach was rejected by God, who demanded for Himself the honors and local dwelling that had been given to idol gods by pagan worshipers; and for what reason? Was the glory of the tabernacle necessary to represent or illustrate His divine glory to His people? What! Was purple or scarlet necessary for people who had seen the river of Egypt run scarlet to the sea, under His condemnation? What! Was a golden lamp and cherub necessary for those who had witnessed the heavenly fire fall like a mantle on Mount Sinai, and its golden courts opened to receive their mortal lawgiver? What! Were silver clasps and fillets required when they had seen the silver waves of the Red Sea clasping the corpses of the horse and his rider in their arched hollows? No—not at all. There was only one reason, and that was an eternal one; that just as the covenant He made with humanity was accompanied by some external sign of its continuation and His remembrance of it, the acceptance of that covenant might be reflected and indicated by use, through some external sign of their love and obedience, and their surrender of themselves and their belongings to His will; and that their gratitude to Him, and continual remembrance of Him, might find expression and enduring testimony through the offering to Him, not only of the firstlings of the herd and fold, not just of the produce of the earth and the tithe of time, but of all treasures of wisdom and beauty; of the creativity of thought and the labor of hands; of resources like wood and stone; of the strength of iron and the brilliance of gold.

And let us not now lose sight of this broad and unabrogated principle—I might say, incapable of being abrogated, so long as men shall receive earthly gifts from God. Of all that they have His tithe must be rendered to Him, or in so far and in so much He is forgotten: of the skill and of the treasure, of the strength and of the mind, of the time and of the toil, offering must be made reverently; and if there be any difference between the Levitical and the Christian offering, it is that the latter may be just so much the wider in its range as it is less typical in its meaning, as it is thankful instead of sacrificial. There can be no excuse accepted because the Deity does not now visibly dwell in His temple; if He is invisible it is only through our failing faith: nor any excuse[Pg 23] because other calls are more immediate or more sacred; this ought to be done, and not the other left undone. Yet this objection, as frequent as feeble, must be more specifically answered.

And let’s not forget this important and unchanging principle—I could even say, one that cannot be changed, as long as people receive earthly gifts from God. Of everything they have, a portion must be given back to Him, or to that extent He is forgotten: from their skills and wealth, their strength and intellect, their time and effort, offerings must be made respectfully; and if there’s any difference between the Levitical and the Christian offering, it’s that the latter can be broader in scope as it is less symbolic in meaning, being thankful instead of sacrificial. There can be no valid reason given because God doesn’t visibly dwell in His temple now; if He is invisible, it’s only because of our weak faith: nor can we excuse ourselves because other demands are more immediate or sacred; this should be done, and not the other neglected. Yet this objection, though common, is weak and requires a more specific response.

VII. It has been said—it ought always to be said, for it is true—that a better and more honorable offering is made to our Master in ministry to the poor, in extending the knowledge of His name, in the practice of the virtues by which that name is hallowed, than in material presents to His temple. Assuredly it is so: woe to all who think that any other kind or manner of offering may in any wise take the place of these! Do the people need place to pray, and calls to hear His word? Then it is no time for smoothing pillars or carving pulpits; let us have enough first of walls and roofs. Do the people need teaching from house to house, and bread from day to day? Then they are deacons and ministers we want, not architects. I insist on this, I plead for this; but let us examine ourselves, and see if this be indeed the reason for our backwardness in the lesser work. The question is not between God's house and His poor: it is not between God's house and His Gospel. It is between God's house and ours. Have we no tesselated colors on our floors? no frescoed fancies on our roofs? no niched statuary in our corridors? no gilded furniture in our chambers? no costly stones in our cabinets? Has even the tithe of these been offered? They are, or they ought to be, the signs that enough has been devoted to the great purposes of human stewardship, and that there remains to us what we can spend in luxury; but there is a greater and prouder luxury than this selfish one—that of bringing a portion of such things as these into sacred service, and presenting them for a memorial[E] that our pleasure as well as our toil has been hallowed by the remembrance of Him who gave both the strength and the reward. And until this has been done, I do not see how such possessions can be retained in happiness. I do not understand the feeling which would arch our own gates and pave our own thresholds, and leave the church with its narrow door and foot-worn sill; the feeling which enriches [Pg 24]our own chambers with all manner of costliness, and endures the bare wall and mean compass of the temple. There is seldom even so severe a choice to be made, seldom so much self-denial to be exercised. There are isolated cases, in which men's happiness and mental activity depend upon a certain degree of luxury in their houses; but then this is true luxury, felt and tasted, and profited by. In the plurality of instances nothing of the kind is attempted, nor can be enjoyed; men's average resources cannot reach it; and that which they can reach, gives them no pleasure, and might be spared. It will be seen, in the course of the following chapters, that I am no advocate for meanness of private habitation. I would fain introduce into it all magnificence, care, and beauty, where they are possible; but I would not have that useless expense in unnoticed fineries or formalities; cornicings of ceilings and graining of doors, and fringing of curtains, and thousands such; things which have become foolishly and apathetically habitual—things on whose common appliance hang whole trades, to which there never yet belonged the blessing of giving one ray of real pleasure, or becoming of the remotest or most contemptible use—things which cause half the expense of life, and destroy more than half its comfort, manliness, respectability, freshness, and facility. I speak from experience: I know what it is to live in a cottage with a deal floor and roof, and a hearth of mica slate; and I know it to be in many respects healthier and happier than living between a Turkey carpet and gilded ceiling, beside a steel grate and polished fender. I do not say that such things have not their place and propriety; but I say this, emphatically, that the tenth part of the expense which is sacrificed in domestic vanities, if not absolutely and meaninglessly lost in domestic discomforts, and incumbrances, would, if collectively offered and wisely employed, build a marble church for every town in England; such a church as it should be a joy and a blessing even to pass near in our daily ways and walks, and as it would bring the light into the eyes to see from afar, lifting its fair height above the purple crowd of humble roofs.

VII. It has been said—and it should always be said, because it’s true—that a better and more honorable gift to our Master is found in serving the poor, spreading the knowledge of His name, and practicing the virtues that honor His name, rather than giving material gifts to His temple. This is certainly the case: woe to those who believe that any other kind of offering can replace these! Do the people need a place to pray and hear His word? Then it’s not the time to smooth pillars or carve pulpits; let’s first ensure we have enough walls and roofs. Do the people need teaching in their homes and daily bread? Then what we need are deacons and ministers, not architects. I insist on this, and I argue for this; but let’s examine ourselves and see if this is truly the reason for our failure in smaller tasks. The issue isn’t between God’s house and the poor: it’s not between God’s house and His Gospel. It’s between God’s house and our own. Do we not have colorful tiles on our floors? No elaborate designs on our ceilings? No decorative statues in our hallways? No lavish furniture in our rooms? No precious stones in our cabinets? Have we even offered a fraction of these? They should be signs that enough has been dedicated to the important responsibilities of humanity, and that we still have what we can spend on luxury; but there is a greater and prouder luxury than selfish indulgence—the luxury of bringing a portion of such things into sacred service and offering them as a reminder that our enjoyment, as well as our hard work, has been blessed by the memory of Him who gave both the strength and the reward. Until this is done, I don’t see how such possessions can bring happiness. I don’t understand the mindset that would beautify our own gateways and pave our own paths while leaving the church with its cramped entrance and worn-out threshold; the mindset that fills our own rooms with all sorts of expensive items while tolerating the bare walls and simple confines of the temple. There is rarely even such a harsh choice to make; seldom is there such a need for self-denial. There are a few situations where people's happiness and mental well-being depend on a certain level of luxury in their homes; but even then, it's true luxury, genuinely felt and appreciated. In most cases, such luxury isn’t pursued, nor can it be enjoyed; the average person's resources can’t support it, and what they can manage brings them no joy and could easily be skipped. As we’ll see in the following chapters, I am not advocating for the sparsity of private living spaces. I would love to see splendor, care, and beauty introduced wherever possible; but I don’t want unnecessary spending on unnoticed adornments or formalities—like ceiling moldings, elaborate door finishes, fringed curtains, and countless other such things—that have become foolishly and lazily routine; things that support entire trades but have never brought genuine pleasure or served even the smallest or most insignificant purpose; things that contribute to half the cost of life and destroy more than half of its comfort, dignity, respectability, freshness, and ease. I speak from experience: I know what it’s like to live in a simple cottage with a wooden floor and roof, and a mica slate hearth; and I know that in many ways it is healthier and happier than living in a place with a Turkey carpet and gilded ceiling, beside a steel grate and polished fender. I’m not saying such things have no place or value; but I strongly affirm that even a tenth of the spending wasted on household luxuries, if not completely lost to domestic discomfort and clutter, would, if collectively given and wisely used, build a beautiful marble church for every town in England; a church that would be a joy and a blessing just to pass by in our daily lives, one that would lift our spirits to see it rising above the sea of humble rooftops.

VIII. I have said for every town: I do not want a marble[Pg 25] church for every village; nay, I do not want marble churches at all for their own sake, but for the sake of the spirit that would build them. The church has no need of any visible splendors; her power is independent of them, her purity is in some degree opposed to them. The simplicity of a pastoral sanctuary is lovelier than the majesty of an urban temple; and it may be more than questioned whether, to the people, such majesty has ever been the source of any increase of effective piety; but to the builders it has been, and must ever be. It is not the church we want, but the sacrifice; not the emotion of admiration, but the act of adoration: not the gift, but the giving.2 And see how much more charity the full understanding of this might admit, among classes of men of naturally opposite feelings; and how much more nobleness in the work. There is no need to offend by importunate, self-proclaiming splendor. Your gift may be given in an unpresuming way. Cut one or two shafts out of a porphyry whose preciousness those only would know who would desire it to be so used; add another month's labor to the undercutting of a few capitals, whose delicacy will not be seen nor loved by one beholder of ten thousand; see that the simplest masonry of the edifice be perfect and substantial; and to those who regard such things, their witness will be clear and impressive; to those who regard them not, all will at least be inoffensive. But do not think the feeling itself a folly, or the act itself useless. Of what use was that dearly-bought water of the well of Bethlehem with which the King of Israel slaked the dust of Adullam?—yet was not thus better than if he had drunk it? Of what use was that passionate act of Christian sacrifice, against which, first uttered by the false tongue, the very objection we would now conquer took a sullen tone for ever?[F] So also let us not ask of what use our offering is to the church: it is at least better for us than if it had been retained for ourselves. It may be better for others also: there is, at any rate, a chance of this; though we must always fearfully and widely shun the thought that the magnificence of the temple can materially add to the efficiency of the worship or to the power [Pg 26]of the ministry. Whatever we do, or whatever we offer, let it not interfere with the simplicity of the one, or abate, as if replacing, the zeal of the other. That is the abuse and fallacy of Romanism, by which the true spirit of Christian offering is directly contradicted. The treatment of the Papists' temple is eminently exhibitory; it is surface work throughout; and the danger and evil of their church decoration lie, not in its reality—not in the true wealth and art of it, of which the lower people are never cognizant—but in its tinsel and glitter, in the gilding of the shrine and painting of the image, in embroidery of dingy robes and crowding of imitated gems; all this being frequently thrust forward to the concealment of what is really good or great in their buildings.3 Of an offering of gratitude which is neither to be exhibited nor rewarded, which is neither to win praise nor purchase salvation, the Romanist (as such) has no conception.

VIII. I’ve said about every town: I don’t want a marble[Pg 25] church for every village; in fact, I don’t want marble churches at all just for their own sake, but for the spirit that would build them. The church doesn’t need any visible grandeur; its power stands apart from that, and its purity is somewhat opposed to it. The simplicity of a countryside sanctuary is more beautiful than the grandeur of a city temple; and it’s certainly debatable whether such grandeur has ever really increased genuine piety among the people; but it has for the builders, and it always will. It’s not the church we want, but the sacrifice; not the feeling of admiration, but the act of adoration; not the gift, but the act of giving. And think about how much more compassion this understanding could allow, among people with naturally opposing feelings; and how much more nobility it could bring to the work. There’s no need to show off with loud, self-serving splendor. Your gift can be given humbly. Carve out one or two columns from a precious porphyry that only those who want it used for that purpose would appreciate; add another month to work on the undercutting of a few capitals, whose delicacy won’t be noticed or loved by one in ten thousand; ensure that the simple masonry of the building is perfect and durable; and for those who appreciate such details, the outcome will be clear and impactful; for those who don’t care, it will at least be unobtrusive. But don’t think that the feeling itself is foolish, or that the act is pointless. What good was that costly water from the well of Bethlehem that the King of Israel used to quench the dust of Adullam?—yet wasn’t it better than if he hadn’t? What was the point of that passionate act of Christian sacrifice, against which, once spoken by a false tongue, the very objection we’re now trying to overcome became a sullen refrain? So let’s not ask what use our offering is to the church: it’s at least better for us than if we kept it for ourselves. It may also benefit others; there’s at least a chance of that, although we must always cautiously avoid the idea that the splendor of the temple can materially enhance the effectiveness of worship or the power[Pg 26] of the ministry. Whatever we do, or whatever we offer, let it not compromise the simplicity of the one, or lessen, as if substituting, the zeal of the other. That’s the misuse and misconception of Romanism, which directly contradicts the true spirit of Christian giving. The way the Papists treat their temple is all about show; it’s all surface work. The danger and harm of their church decoration lie, not in its reality—not in its true wealth and artistry, of which the lower classes are often unaware—but in its flashy and glitzy aspects, the gilded shrines and painted images, the embroidery on dingy robes and the fake gems crowding the scene; all of this often overshadowing what is truly good or great in their buildings. Of an offering of gratitude that isn’t meant to be showcased or rewarded, that isn’t aimed at gaining praise or buying salvation, the Romanist (as such) has no understanding.

IX. While, however, I would especially deprecate the imputation of any other acceptableness or usefulness to the gift itself than that which it receives from the spirit of its presentation, it may be well to observe, that there is a lower advantage which never fails to accompany a dutiful observance of any right abstract principle. While the first fruits of his possessions were required from the Israelite as a testimony of fidelity, the payment of those first fruits was nevertheless rewarded, and that connectedly and specifically, by the increase of those possessions. Wealth, and length of days, and peace, were the promised and experienced rewards of his offering, though they were not to be the objects of it. The tithe paid into the storehouse was the expressed condition of the blessing which there should not be room enough to receive. And it will be thus always: God never forgets any work or labor of love; and whatever it may be of which the first and best proportions or powers have been presented to Him, he will multiply and increase sevenfold. Therefore, though it may not be necessarily the interest of religion to admit the service of the arts, the arts will never flourish until they have been primarily devoted to that service—devoted, both by architect and employer; by the one in scrupulous, earnest, affectionate[Pg 27] design; by the other in expenditure at least more frank, at least less calculating, than that which he would admit in the indulgence of his own private feelings. Let this principle be but once fairly acknowledged among us; and however it may be chilled and repressed in practice, however feeble may be its real influence, however the sacredness of it may be diminished by counter-workings of vanity and self-interest, yet its mere acknowledgment would bring a reward; and with our present accumulation of means and of intellect, there would be such an impulse and vitality given to art as it has not felt since the thirteenth century. And I do not assert this as other than a national consequence: I should, indeed, expect a larger measure of every great and spiritual faculty to be always given where those faculties had been wisely and religiously employed; but the impulse to which I refer, would be, humanly speaking, certain; and would naturally result from obedience to the two great conditions enforced by the Spirit of Sacrifice, first, that we should in everything do our best; and, secondly, that we should consider increase of apparent labor as an increase of beauty in the building. A few practical deductions from these two conditions, and I have done.

IX. However, I would particularly discourage any suggestion that the gift itself holds any value or usefulness beyond what it gains from the spirit in which it is given. It's worth noting that there is a lesser benefit that always comes with a faithful adherence to any abstract principle. While the Israelites were required to offer the first fruits of their possessions as a sign of their loyalty, paying those first fruits was nonetheless rewarded, specifically and consistently, by an increase in those possessions. Wealth, longevity, and peace were the promised and experienced outcomes of their offerings, even though those were not the intended goals. The tithe given to the storehouse was the stated condition for the blessings that would be overflowing. This will always be true: God never forgets any work or act of love; whatever of our best and first efforts we present to Him, He will multiply and increase abundantly. Therefore, while religion may not necessarily require the service of the arts, the arts will never thrive until they are primarily dedicated to that service—dedicated by both the architect and the client; by the architect in meticulous, genuine, heartfelt design; and by the client in spending that is at least more genuine and less calculating than what he would allow for his own personal desires. If this principle is once genuinely accepted among us, and no matter how it may be stifled or weakened in practice, or how its true impact may be diminished by vanity and self-interest, its mere acceptance would yield a reward. With our current accumulation of resources and intelligence, art would experience an energy and vitality it hasn’t known since the thirteenth century. I don’t claim this as anything less than a national outcome: I would indeed expect a greater measure of every significant and spiritual ability to be given where those abilities have been wisely and religiously employed; but the momentum I refer to would, from a human perspective, be certain and would naturally arise from following the two key conditions emphasized by the Spirit of Sacrifice: first, that we strive to give our utmost in everything; and second, that we view an increase in visible effort as an enhancement of beauty in the creation. A few practical insights from these two conditions, and I’m done.

X. For the first: it is alone enough to secure success, and it is for want of observing it that we continually fail. We are none of us so good architects as to be able to work habitually beneath our strength; and yet there is not a building that I know of, lately raised, wherein it is not sufficiently evident that neither architect nor builder has done his best. It is the especial characteristic of modern work. All old work nearly has been hard work. It may be the hard work of children, of barbarians, of rustics; but it is always their utmost. Ours has as constantly the look of money's worth, of a stopping short wherever and whenever we can, of a lazy compliance with low conditions; never of a fair putting forth of our strength. Let us have done with this kind of work at once: cast off every temptation to it: do not let us degrade ourselves voluntarily, and then mutter and mourn over our short comings; let us confess our poverty or our parsimony[Pg 28], but not belie our human intellect. It is not even a question of how much we are to do, but of how it is to be done; it is not a question of doing more, but of doing better. Do not let us boss our roofs with wretched, half-worked, blunt-edged rosettes; do not let us flank our gates with rigid imitations of mediæval statuary. Such things are mere insults to common sense, and only unfit us for feeling the nobility of their prototypes. We have so much, suppose, to be spent in decoration; let us go to the Flaxman of his time, whoever he may be, and bid him carve for us a single statue, frieze or capital, or as many as we can afford, compelling upon him the one condition, that they shall be the best he can do; place them where they will be of the most value, and be content. Our other capitals may be mere blocks, and our other niches empty. No matter: better our work unfinished than all bad. It may be that we do not desire ornament of so high an order; choose, then, a less developed style, also, if you will, rougher material; the law which we are enforcing requires only that what we pretend to do and to give, shall both be the best of their kind; choose, therefore, the Norman hatchet work, instead of the Flaxman frieze and statue, but let it be the best hatchet work; and if you cannot afford marble, use Caen stone, but from the best bed; and if not stone, brick, but the best brick; preferring always what is good of a lower order of work or material, to what is bad of a higher; for this is not only the way to improve every kind of work, and to put every kind of material to better use; but it is more honest and unpretending, and is in harmony with other just, upright, and manly principles, whose range we shall have presently to take into consideration.

X. First of all, just this alone is enough to ensure success, and it's because we often overlook it that we keep failing. None of us are such good builders that we can consistently work below our potential; yet, in every new building I've seen lately, it's obvious that neither the architect nor the builder has truly given their best effort. This is the defining trait of modern construction. Most older work has been done with hard effort. It might be the hard work of children, unrefined individuals, or country folks, but it’s always their utmost effort. Our work often looks like it’s just about cost, showing that we stop when we can, settling for lower standards, instead of genuinely pushing ourselves. We need to put an end to this type of work immediately: let’s reject every temptation to do so; we shouldn’t willingly degrade ourselves and then complain about our shortcomings. Let’s acknowledge our lack of resources or stinginess, but not misrepresent our intellectual capacity. It’s not about how much we do, but about how we do it; it’s not about doing more, but about doing it better. Don’t let’s clutter our roofs with poorly crafted, blunt-edged rosettes; don’t flank our gates with stiff copies of medieval statues. These things are just insults to common sense and make us unable to appreciate the greatness of their originals. Suppose we have some budget for decoration; let’s find the best artist of the time, whoever that may be, and ask them to create a single statue, frieze, or capital, or as many as we can afford, with the strict condition that they must be the best work they can produce; let’s place them where they’ll be most appreciated, and be satisfied. Our other capitals can just be plain blocks, and our empty niches can stay that way. It doesn’t matter: it’s better to have incomplete work than all poorly done work. If we don’t want high-end ornamentation, we can choose a simpler style or rougher material; the rule we're following just requires that whatever we claim to create or offer must be the best quality of its kind; so, if we prefer Norman-style chisel work instead of sculptures and friezes, let it be the best chisel work; and if we can’t afford marble, let’s use Caen stone, but from the highest quality source; and if not stone, then brick, but the best brick; always opting for good quality in a lower category rather than bad quality in a higher one. This approach not only improves every type of work and utilizes every material more effectively, but it is also more honest and straightforward, aligning with other just, upright, and noble principles that we'll need to discuss soon.

XI. The other condition which we had to notice, was the value of the appearance of labor upon architecture. I have spoken of this before;[G] and it is, indeed, one of the most frequent sources of pleasure which belong to the art, always, however, within certain somewhat remarkable limits. For it does not at first appear easily to be explained why labor, as represented by materials of value, should, without sense of [Pg 29]wrong or error, bear being wasted; while the waste of actual workmanship is always painful, so soon as it is apparent. But so it is, that, while precious materials may, with a certain profusion and negligence, be employed for the magnificence of what is seldom seen, the work of man cannot be carelessly and idly bestowed, without an immediate sense of wrong; as if the strength of the living creature were never intended by its Maker to be sacrificed in vain, though it is well for us sometimes to part with what we esteem precious of substance, as showing that in such a service it becomes but dross and dust. And in the nice balance between the straitening of effort or enthusiasm on the one hand, and vainly casting it away upon the other, there are more questions than can be met by any but very just and watchful feeling. In general it is less the mere loss of labor that offends us, than the lack of judgment implied by such loss; so that if men confessedly work for work's sake, and it does not appear that they are ignorant where or how to make their labor tell, we shall not be grossly offended. On the contrary, we shall be pleased if the work be lost in carrying out a principle, or in avoiding a deception. It, indeed, is a law properly belonging to another part of our subject, but it may be allowably stated here, that, whenever, by the construction of a building, some parts of it are hidden from the eye which are the continuation of others bearing some consistent ornament, it is not well that the ornament should cease in the parts concealed; credit is given for it, and it should not be deceptively withdrawn: as, for instance, in the sculpture of the backs of the statues of a temple pediment; never, perhaps, to be seen, but yet not lawfully to be left unfinished. And so in the working out of ornaments in dark concealed places, in which it is best to err on the side of completion; and in the carrying round of string courses, and other such continuous work; not but that they may stop sometimes, on the point of going into some palpably impenetrable recess, but then let them stop boldly and markedly, on some distinct terminal ornament, and never be supposed to exist where they do not. The arches of the towers which flank the transepts of Rouen Cathedral have rosette orna[Pg 30]ments on their spandrils, on the three visible sides; none on the side towards the roof. The right of this is rather a nice point for question.

XI. The other point we need to consider is the importance of how labor appears in architecture. I've mentioned this before;[G] and it’s truly one of the most common sources of enjoyment in this art, always within certain interesting limits. At first, it’s not entirely clear why valuable materials, representing labor, can be wasted without causing discomfort, while wasting actual craftsmanship always feels wrong the moment it becomes obvious. However, it seems that while precious materials can be used with a certain extravagance for impressive but rarely seen details, human effort cannot be carelessly or idly thrown away without creating a feeling of wrongness, as if the energy given by the creator was never meant to be wasted. Although it’s often good for us to part with what we treasure in material things, showing that in such situations it becomes insignificant. The challenge lies in the delicate balance between restricting effort or enthusiasm on one side, and recklessly discarding it on the other; there are more questions to answer than can be addressed by anything but very careful and thoughtful feelings. Generally, it’s not just the loss of labor that bothers us, but the lack of judgment shown by such loss; so if people are clearly working for its own sake and it’s obvious they know where or how to make their effort count, we won’t be overly offended. On the contrary, we’ll feel happy if the work is lost in pursuing a principle or avoiding deceit. This is indeed a principle that pertains more to another topic, but it’s acceptable to mention here that when certain parts of a building are hidden from view, yet continue a consistent ornamentation elsewhere, it’s not appropriate for the ornament to stop in the concealed parts; credit is expected for it, and it shouldn’t be deceptively omitted: for example, in the sculpture on the backs of the statues of a temple pediment; which may never be seen, but shouldn’t be left unfinished. The same goes for details in dark hidden areas; it’s usually better to err on the side of completion, and when carrying out continuous works like string courses, they might stop sometimes at an obviously unreachable area, but they should stop decisively at a distinct terminal ornament and never be assumed to exist where they don’t. The arches of the towers flanking the transepts of Rouen Cathedral have rosette ornaments on their spandrels on the three visible sides; none on the side facing the roof. This raises a rather delicate question.

XII. Visibility, however, we must remember, depends, not only on situation, but on distance; and there is no way in which work is more painfully and unwisely lost than in its over delicacy on parts distant from the eye. Here, again, the principle of honesty must govern our treatment: we must not work any kind of ornament which is, perhaps, to cover the whole building (or at least to occur on all parts of it) delicately where it is near the eye, and rudely where it is removed from it. That is trickery and dishonesty. Consider, first, what kinds of ornaments will tell in the distance and what near, and so distribute them, keeping such as by their nature are delicate, down near the eye, and throwing the bold and rough kinds of work to the top; and if there be any kind which is to be both near and far off, take care that it be as boldly and rudely wrought where it is well seen as where it is distant, so that the spectator may know exactly what it is, and what it is worth. Thus chequered patterns, and in general such ornaments as common workmen can execute, may extend over the whole building; but bas-reliefs, and fine niches and capitals, should be kept down, and the common sense of this will always give a building dignity, even though there be some abruptness or awkwardness, in the resulting arrangements. Thus at San Zeno at Verona, the bas-reliefs, full of incident and interest are confined to a parallelogram of the front, reaching to the height of the capitals of the columns of the porch. Above these, we find a simple though most lovely, little arcade; and above that, only blank wall, with square face shafts. The whole effect is tenfold grander and better than if the entire façade had been covered with bad work, and may serve for an example of the way to place little where we cannot afford much. So, again, the transept gates of Rouen[H] are covered with delicate bas-reliefs (of which I [Pg 31]shall speak at greater length presently) up to about once and a half a man's height; and above that come the usual and more visible statues and niches. So in the campanile at Florence, the circuit of bas-reliefs is on its lowest story; above that come its statues; and above them all its pattern mosaic, and twisted columns, exquisitely finished, like all Italian work of the time, but still, in the eye of the Florentine, rough and commonplace by comparison with the bas-reliefs. So generally the most delicate niche work and best mouldings of the French Gothic are in gates and low windows well within sight; although, it being the very spirit of that style to trust to its exuberance for effect, there is occasionally a burst upwards and blossoming unrestrainably to the sky, as in the pediment of the west front of Rouen, and in the recess of the rose window behind it, where there are some most elaborate flower-mouldings, all but invisible from below, and only adding a general enrichment to the deep shadows that relieve the shafts of the advanced pediment. It is observable, however, that this very work is bad flamboyant, and has corrupt renaissance characters in its detail as well as use; while in the earlier and grander north and south gates, there is a very noble proportioning of the work to the distance, the niches and statues which crown the northern one, at a height of about one hundred feet from the ground, being alike colossal and simple; visibly so from below, so as to induce no deception, and yet honestly and well-finished above, and all that they are expected to be; the features very beautiful, full of expression, and as delicately wrought as any work of the period.

XII. Visibility, however, we must remember, depends, not only on situation, but on distance; and there is no way in which work is more painfully and unwisely lost than in its over delicacy on parts distant from the eye. Here, again, the principle of honesty must govern our treatment: we must not work any kind of ornament which is, perhaps, to cover the whole building (or at least to occur on all parts of it) delicately where it is near the eye, and rudely where it is removed from it. That is trickery and dishonesty. Consider, first, what kinds of ornaments will look good from a distance and which will look better close up, and so distribute them, keeping those that are delicate near the eye, while placing bolder and rougher elements higher up; and if there is something that is meant to be appreciated both up close and from afar, make sure it is crafted just as boldly and coarsely where it is easily seen as it is when viewed from a distance, so that the viewer can understand precisely what it is and how valuable it may be. Thus, checkerboard patterns and generally, ornaments that can be executed by common workers may extend across the entire building; however, bas-reliefs, fine niches, and capitals should be kept lower down, and this common sense will always give a building dignity, even if there is a bit of abruptness or awkwardness in the resulting arrangements. For example, at San Zeno in Verona, the bas-reliefs, full of detail and interest, are confined to a rectangle at the front, reaching up to the height of the capitals of the porch columns. Above these, there's a simple yet lovely little arcade; and above that, just a blank wall with square shafts. The overall effect is ten times grander and better than if the entire façade had been covered with inferior work, and this serves as a good example of how to limit decoration where you can't afford to lavish much. Similarly, the transept gates of Rouen are adorned with delicate bas-reliefs (of which I will talk more about shortly) up to about one and a half times a person's height; and above that are the usual and more prominent statues and niches. In the campanile at Florence, the band of bas-reliefs is on the lowest level; above that are the statues; and above them all is the patterned mosaic and twisted columns, exquisitely finished, like all the Italian work of the time, but still, in the eyes of the Florentine, rough and ordinary compared to the bas-reliefs. Generally, the most delicate niche work and the best moldings of the French Gothic are found in gates and low windows that are well within sight; although, since it is the very essence of that style to rely on its exuberance for effect, there are sometimes upward bursts and flourishing that reach extravagantly into the sky, as seen in the pediment of the west front of Rouen, and in the recess of the rose window behind it, where there are intricate flower moldings, almost invisible from below, only adding a general richness to the deep shadows that accentuate the shafts of the prominent pediment. It's worth noting, however, that this very work is poorly executed flamboyant, showing corrupt Renaissance characteristics in its details as well as its function; whereas in the earlier, grander north and south gates, there is a very noble proportioning of work to distance, with the niches and statues crowning the northern gate, at about one hundred feet up, being both majestic and simple; visibly so from below, so as to not induce any deception, and yet honestly and well-finished above, as they are expected to be; the features are very beautiful, full of expression, and as delicately crafted as any work of the period.

XIII. It is to be remembered, however, that while the ornaments in every fine ancient building, without exception so far as I am aware, are most delicate at the base, they are often in greater effective quantity on the upper parts. In high towers this is perfectly natural and right, the solidity of the foundation being as necessary as the division and penetration of the superstructure; hence the lighter work and richly pierced crowns of late Gothic towers. The campanile of Giotto at Florence, already alluded to, is an exquisite instance[Pg 32] of the union of the two principles, delicate bas-reliefs adorning its massy foundation, while the open tracery of the upper windows attracts the eye by its slender intricacy, and a rich cornice crowns the whole. In such truly fine cases of this disposition the upper work is effective by its quantity and intricacy only, as the lower portions by delicacy; so also in the Tour de Beurre at Rouen, where, however, the detail is massy throughout, subdividing into rich meshes as it ascends. In the bodies of buildings the principle is less safe, but its discussion is not connected with our present subject.

XIII. It’s important to remember that while the decorative elements in every beautiful ancient building, as far as I know, are most delicate at the base, they often appear in greater effective quantity in the upper areas. In tall towers, this is entirely natural and correct; the strength of the foundation is just as important as the division and detail of the structure above it. This leads to the lighter designs and intricately pierced tops of late Gothic towers. Giotto's campanile in Florence, which has been mentioned before, is a stunning example of this combination, featuring delicate bas-reliefs that adorn its sturdy base, while the open tracery of the upper windows draws the eye with its slender complexity, topped off by an ornate cornice. In truly exceptional cases like this, the upper structure is striking due to its quantity and intricacy, whereas the lower parts stand out for their delicacy; the same goes for the Tour de Beurre in Rouen, where the detail is solid throughout, becoming richly intricate as it rises. In the main bodies of buildings, this principle is less reliable, but discussing that isn't relevant to our current topic.

XIV. Finally, work may be wasted by being too good for its material, or too fine to bear exposure; and this, generally a characteristic of late, especially of renaissance, work, is perhaps the worst fault of all. I do not know anything more painful or pitiful than the kind of ivory carving with which the Certosa of Pavia, and part of the Colleone sepulchral chapel at Bergamo, and other such buildings, are incrusted, of which it is not possible so much as to think without exhaustion; and a heavy sense of the misery it would be, to be forced to look at it at all. And this is not from the quantity of it, nor because it is bad work—much of it is inventive and able; but because it looks as if it were only fit to be put in inlaid cabinets and velveted caskets, and as if it could not bear one drifting shower or gnawing frost. We are afraid for it, anxious about it, and tormented by it; and we feel that a massy shaft and a bold shadow would be worth it all. Nevertheless, even in cases like these, much depends on the accomplishment of the great ends of decoration. If the ornament does its duty—if it is ornament, and its points of shade and light tell in the general effect, we shall not be offended by finding that the sculptor in his fulness of fancy has chosen to give much more than these mere points of light, and has composed them of groups of figures. But if the ornament does not answer its purpose, if it have no distant, no truly decorative power; if generally seen it be a mere incrustation and meaningless roughness, we shall only be chagrined by finding when we look close, that the incrustation has cost years of labor and has millions of figures and histories in it [Pg 33] and would be the better of being seen through a Stanhope lens. Hence the greatness of the northern Gothic as contrasted with the latest Italian. It reaches nearly the same extreme of detail; but it never loses sight of its architectural purpose, never fails in its decorative power; not a leaflet in it but speaks, and speaks far off, too; and so long as this be the case, there is no limit to the luxuriance in which such work may legitimately and nobly be bestowed.

XIV. Ultimately, work can be wasted by being too high-quality for its material or too delicate to withstand exposure; this, often seen in late, particularly Renaissance work, is arguably the worst fault of all. I can’t think of anything more painful or pitiful than the kind of ivory carving that decorates the Certosa of Pavia, parts of the Colleone sepulchral chapel in Bergamo, and similar buildings, which is exhausting to even consider, and it feels miserable just to look at it. This isn't due to its quantity or because it's poorly done—much of it is creative and skilled—but because it seems only suitable for inlaid cabinets and plush caskets, as if it couldn’t survive a single rain shower or biting frost. We worry for it, feel anxious about it, and are tormented by it; we sense that a solid column and a bold shadow would be far more worthwhile. However, even in such situations, a lot depends on how well the key decorative goals are achieved. If the ornament serves its function—if it truly adds beauty, and its highlights and shadows contribute to the overall effect—we won’t mind if the sculptor, in a burst of creativity, has chosen to provide much more than just these highlights but has arranged them into groups of figures. But if the ornament fails to serve its purpose, lacking any distant or genuinely decorative impact; if, when viewed as a whole, it seems like just a meaningless surface and roughness, we’ll only feel disappointed when we realize up close that the surface took years of labor and is filled with millions of figures and stories, and it would be better appreciated through a Stanhope lens. This highlights the greatness of northern Gothic as compared to the latest Italian work. It achieves a similar level of detail but never loses sight of its architectural purpose and always maintains its decorative impact; every leaf in it has something to say, and it speaks from a distance, too; as long as that holds true, there’s no limit to the richness in which such work can be legitimately and nobly indulged.

PLATE I. PLATE I.—(Page 33—Vol. V)
Decorations from Rouen, St. Lo, and Venice.

XV. No limit: it is one of the affectations of architects to speak of overcharged ornament. Ornament cannot be overcharged if it be good, and is always overcharged when it is bad. I have given, on the opposite page (fig. 1), one of the smallest niches of the central gate of Rouen. That gate I suppose to be the most exquisite piece of pure flamboyant work existing; for though I have spoken of the upper portions, especially the receding window, as degenerate, the gate itself is of a purer period, and has hardly any renaissance taint. There are four strings of these niches (each with two figures beneath it) round the porch, from the ground to the top of the arch, with three intermediate rows of larger niches, far more elaborate; besides the six principal canopies of each outer pier. The total number of the subordinate niches alone, each worked like that in the plate, and each with a different pattern of traceries in each compartment, is one hundred and seventy-six.4 Yet in all this ornament there is not one cusp, one finial that is useless—not a stroke of the chisel is in vain; the grace and luxuriance of it all are visible—sensible rather—even to the uninquiring eye; and all its minuteness does not diminish the majesty, while it increases the mystery, of the noble and unbroken vault. It is not less the boast of some styles that they can bear ornament, than of others that they can do without it; but we do not often enough reflect that those very styles, of so haughty simplicity, owe part of their pleasurableness to contrast, and would be wearisome if universal. They are but the rests and monotones of the art; it is to its far happier, far higher, exaltation that we owe those fair fronts of variegated mosaic, charged with wild fancies and dark hosts of imagery, thicker and quainter than[Pg 34] ever filled the depth of midsummer dream; those vaulted gates, trellised with close leaves; those window-labyrinths of twisted tracery and starry light; those misty masses of multitudinous pinnacle and diademed tower; the only witnesses, perhaps that remain to us of the faith and fear of nations. All else for which the builders sacrificed, has passed away—all their living interests, and aims, and achievements. We know not for what they labored, and we see no evidence of their reward. Victory, wealth, authority, happiness—all have departed, though bought by many a bitter sacrifice. But of them, and their life, and their toil upon the earth, one reward, one evidence, is left to us in those gray heaps of deep-wrought stone. They have taken with them to the grave their powers, their honors, and their errors; but they have left us their adoration.

XV. No limit: architects often have a tendency to criticize excessive ornamentation. But ornament can’t be excessive if it’s well done, and it always seems excessive when it's poorly executed. On the opposite page (fig. 1), I've shown one of the smallest niches from the central gate of Rouen. I consider that gate to be the most exquisite example of pure flamboyant style that exists; although I’ve mentioned that the upper parts, especially the recessed window, are a decline from this style, the gate itself belongs to a purer period and doesn’t really show any Renaissance influence. There are four rows of these niches (each with two figures underneath it) surrounding the porch, rising from the ground to the top of the arch, plus three intermediate rows of larger, much more detailed niches, in addition to the six main canopies on each outer pier. The total number of smaller niches alone, each crafted like the one in the image and featuring different traceries in each section, is one hundred and seventy-six.4 Yet in all this decoration, there isn’t a single cusp or finial that’s pointless—every chisel mark serves a purpose; the elegance and richness of it all are noticeable—even to the casual observer—and all its intricacies enhance the majesty while adding to the mystery of the grand, unbroken vault above. It’s just as much a point of pride for some styles that they can accommodate ornamentation as it is for others that they can function without it; but we don’t often take the time to consider that those very styles, known for their proud simplicity, gain part of their appeal from contrast, and would become tedious if they were the only option. They are simply the rests and monotones of the art; what we owe to the more joyful, elevated expressions of art are those beautiful facades of colorful mosaics, filled with wild imaginations and a dense array of imagery, more abundant and peculiar than[Pg 34] anything found in midsummer's dream; those vaulted gates, intricately woven with leaves; those window labyrinths of twisted tracery and twinkling light; those hazy masses of numerous pinnacles and crowned towers; perhaps the only remaining witnesses to the faith and fears of nations. Everything else for which the builders sacrificed has disappeared—all their living interests, goals, and accomplishments. We don’t know what they worked for, and see no signs of their rewards. Victory, wealth, power, happiness—all have gone, albeit bought at great cost. But of them, their lives, and their labor on earth, one reward, one testament, remains for us in the gray piles of timeworn stone. They have taken their abilities, their honors, and their mistakes with them to the grave; yet they have left us their reverence.


CHAPTER II.

THE LAMP OF TRUTH.

I. There is a marked likeness between the virtues of man and the enlightenment of the globe he inhabits—the same diminishing gradation in vigor up to the limits of their domains, the same essential separation from their contraries—the same twilight at the meeting of the two: a something wider belt than the line where the world rolls into night, that strange twilight of the virtues; that dusky debateable land, wherein zeal becomes impatience, and temperance becomes severity, and justice becomes cruelty, and faith superstition, and each and all vanish into gloom.

I. There is a clear similarity between the virtues of humans and the enlightenment of the world they live in—the same gradual decline in strength up to the boundaries of their influence, the same fundamental separation from their opposites—the same twilight where the two meet: a broader area than the line where the world fades into darkness, that peculiar twilight of virtues; that shadowy, uncertain territory, where zeal turns into impatience, and temperance shifts to severity, and justice transforms into cruelty, and faith becomes superstition, with each and every one fading into gloom.

Nevertheless, with the greater number of them, though their dimness increases gradually, we may mark the moment of their sunset; and, happily, may turn the shadow back by the way by which it had gone down: but for one, the line of the horizon is irregular and undefined; and this, too, the very equator and girdle of them all—Truth; that only one of which there are no degrees, but breaks and rents continually; that pillar of the earth, yet a cloudy pillar; that golden and narrow line, which the very powers and virtues that lean upon[Pg 35] it bend, which policy and prudence conceal, which kindness and courtesy modify, which courage overshadows with his shield, imagination covers with her wings, and charity dims with her tears. How difficult must the maintenance of that authority be, which, while it has to restrain the hostility of all the worst principles of man, has also to restrain the disorders of his best—which is continually assaulted by the one, and betrayed by the other, and which regards with the same severity the lightest and the boldest violations of its law! There are some faults slight in the sight of love, some errors slight in the estimate of wisdom; but truth forgives no insult, and endures no stain.

However, with many of them, although their brightness slowly fades, we can notice the moment of their decline; and, fortunately, we can reverse the shadow's path as it was when it first dimmed. But for one, the horizon appears jagged and unclear; and this is, in fact, the very center and essence of them all—Truth. There are no degrees to it; it continuously fractures and tears apart; it serves as the foundation of the earth yet remains elusive; that slender and shining line, which even the strengths and virtues that depend on it bend, which strategy and caution hide, which kindness and politeness alter, which bravery shields, imagination blankets, and charity obscures with its sorrowful tears. Maintaining that authority must be incredibly challenging, as it has to contain the aggression of all mankind's worst instincts while also managing the chaos of the best—constantly attacked by the former and betrayed by the latter, and it treats the slightest and boldest breaches of its law with equal seriousness! Some faults may seem minor in the eyes of love, and some mistakes may appear insignificant in the judgment of wisdom; but truth tolerates no disrespect and bears no blemish.

We do not enough consider this; nor enough dread the slight and continual occasions of offence against her. We are too much in the habit of looking at falsehood in its darkest associations, and through the color of its worst purposes. That indignation which we profess to feel at deceit absolute, is indeed only at deceit malicious. We resent calumny, hypocrisy and treachery, because they harm us, not because they are untrue. Take the detraction and the mischief from the untruth, and we are little offended by it; turn it into praise, and we may be pleased with it. And yet it is not calumny nor treachery that does the largest sum of mischief in the world; they are continually crushed, and are felt only in being conquered. But it is the glistening and softly spoken lie; the amiable fallacy; the patriotic lie of the historian, the provident lie of the politician, the zealous lie of the partizan, the merciful lie of the friend, and the careless lie of each man to himself, that cast that black mystery over humanity, through which any man who pierces, we thank as we would thank one who dug a well in a desert; happy in that the thirst for truth still remains with us, even when we have wilfully left the fountains of it.

We don't consider this enough, nor do we dread the small, constant offenses against her. We tend to look at lies through their darkest implications and the worst intentions. The anger we claim to feel at absolute deceit is really only directed at deceit that is harmful. We dislike slander, hypocrisy, and betrayal because they hurt us, not because they are false. Take away the harm and the trouble from a lie, and we aren't very bothered by it; if it turns into praise, we might even like it. However, it's not slander or betrayal that causes the most harm in the world; those are often defeated and felt only when we overcome them. Instead, it's the shiny and softly spoken lies; the pleasant falsehoods; the patriotic lies from historians, the self-serving lies from politicians, the passionate lies from partisans, the kind lies from friends, and the careless lies we tell ourselves that create that dark mystery over humanity. When someone breaks through it, we thank them as if they found a well in a desert, grateful that the thirst for truth still exists within us, even when we've intentionally turned away from its sources.

It would be well if moralists less frequently confused the greatness of a sin with its unpardonableness. The two characters are altogether distinct. The greatness of a fault depends partly on the nature of the person against whom it is committed, partly upon the extent of its consequences. Its par[Pg 36]donableness depends, humanly speaking, on the degree of temptation to it. One class of circumstances determines the weight of the attaching punishment; the other, the claim to remission of punishment: and since it is not easy for men to estimate the relative weight, nor possible for them to know the relative consequences, of crime, it is usually wise in them to quit the care of such nice measurements, and to look to the other and clearer condition of culpability; esteeming those faults worst which are committed under least temptation. I do not mean to diminish the blame of the injurious and malicious sin, of the selfish and deliberate falsity; yet it seems to me, that the shortest way to check the darker forms of deceit is to set watch more scrupulous against those which have mingled, unregarded and unchastised, with the current of our life. Do not let us lie at all. Do not think of one falsity as harmless, and another as slight, and another as unintended. Cast them all aside: they may be light and accidental; but they are an ugly soot from the smoke of the pit, for all that; and it is better that our hearts should be swept clean of them, without over care as to which is largest or blackest. Speaking truth is like writing fair, and comes only by practice; it is less a matter of will than of habit, and I doubt if any occasion can be trivial which permits the practice and formation of such a habit. To speak and act truth with constancy and precision is nearly as difficult, and perhaps as meritorious, as to speak it under intimidation or penalty; and it is a strange thought how many men there are, as I trust, who would hold to it at the cost of fortune or life, for one who would hold to it at the cost of a little daily trouble. And seeing that of all sin there is, perhaps, no one more flatly opposite to the Almighty, no one more "wanting the good of virtue and of being," than this of lying, it is surely a strange insolence to fall into the foulness of it on light or on no temptation, and surely becoming an honorable man to resolve that, whatever semblances or fallacies the necessary course of his life may compel him to bear or to believe, none shall disturb the serenity of his voluntary actions, nor diminish the reality of his chosen delights.[Pg 37]

It would be helpful if moralists didn’t often confuse the seriousness of a sin with how unforgivable it is. These two aspects are completely different. The severity of a wrongdoing depends partly on the nature of the person it’s committed against and partly on the extent of its consequences. Its forgiveness, from a human perspective, relies on the level of temptation leading to it. One set of circumstances influences the weight of the punishment imposed, while the other influences the right to have that punishment lifted. Since it’s not easy for people to gauge the relative weight or know the true consequences of a crime, it’s usually wise for them to leave the job of measuring such nuances aside and focus on the clearer criteria of guilt; considering those wrongs as worst that are committed under minimal temptation. I don’t mean to lessen the blame for harmful and malicious sins, or for selfish and deliberate lies; however, it seems to me that the best way to curb the harsher forms of deceit is to be more vigilant against those minor lies that have blended in, unnoticed and unpunished, with the flow of our lives. Let’s avoid lying altogether. Don’t think of one lie as harmless, another as minor, and yet another as unintended. Dismiss them all: they may seem trivial and accidental, but they are an ugly residue from the depths of immorality, regardless; and it's better for our hearts to be cleansed of them without worrying about which one is worse or more offensive. Speaking the truth is like writing clearly, and it only comes from practice; it’s more about habit than intention, and I doubt any situation can be trivial when it allows for the development of such a habit. Speaking and acting truthfully with consistency and precision is almost as challenging—and perhaps as commendable—as doing so under threat or punishment; and it’s a curious thought how many people there are, as I believe, who would stand by it at the expense of their wealth or life for every one person who would uphold it at the cost of a little daily inconvenience. And considering that of all sins, perhaps none is more directly contrary to the Almighty, none more lacking the essence of virtue and existence, than lying, it surely is a strange arrogance to fall into such uncleanliness over minor or no temptation, and it is absolutely fitting for an honorable person to decide that, no matter what appearances or misconceptions life may force her to face or accept, none shall interfere with the clarity of his intentional actions or diminish the authenticity of his chosen joys.[Pg 37]

II. If this be just and wise for truth's sake, much more is it necessary for the sake of the delights over which she has influence. For, as I advocated the expression of the Spirit of Sacrifice in the acts and pleasures of men, not as if thereby those acts could further the cause of religion, but because most assuredly they might therein be infinitely ennobled themselves, so I would have the Spirit or Lamp of Truth clear in the hearts of our artists and handicraftsmen, not as if the truthful practice of handicrafts could far advance the cause of truth, but because I would fain see the handicrafts themselves urged by the spurs of chivalry: and it is, indeed, marvellous to see what power and universality there is in this single principle, and how in the consulting or forgetting of it lies half the dignity or decline of every art and act of man. I have before endeavored to show its range and power in painting; and I believe a volume, instead of a chapter, might be written on its authority over all that is great in architecture. But I must be content with the force of instances few and familiar, believing that the occasions of its manifestation may be more easily discovered by a desire to be true, than embraced by an analysis of truth.

II. If this is just and wise for the sake of truth, it's even more important for the pleasures it influences. Just as I supported expressing the Spirit of Sacrifice through people's actions and joys—not because those actions could promote religion, but because they could be greatly elevated in themselves—I want the Spirit or Lamp of Truth to shine in the hearts of our artists and craftsmen. Not because practicing their crafts truthfully will significantly advance the cause of truth, but because I want to see those crafts driven by a sense of nobility. It’s truly amazing to realize how much power and universality this single principle holds, and how recognizing or neglecting it determines half the dignity or decline of every art and human action. I’ve previously tried to demonstrate its range and power in painting, and I believe a whole book could be written about its influence on everything great in architecture. But I’ll settle for a few familiar examples, trusting that the desire to be true will make its expressions easier to identify than an analysis of truth itself.

Only it is very necessary in the outset to mark clearly wherein consists the essence of fallacy as distinguished from supposition.

Only it is very important at the beginning to clearly define what distinguishes the essence of a fallacy from that of a supposition.

III. For it might be at first thought that the whole kingdom of imagination was one of deception also. Not so: the action of the imagination is a voluntary summoning of the conceptions of things absent or impossible; and the pleasure and nobility of the imagination partly consist in its knowledge and contemplation of them as such, i.e. in the knowledge of their actual absence or impossibility at the moment of their apparent presence or reality. When the imagination deceives it becomes madness. It is a noble faculty so long as it confesses its own ideality; when it ceases to confess this, it is insanity. All the difference lies in the fact of the confession, in there being no deception. It is necessary to our rank as spiritual creatures, that we should be able to invent and to behold what is not; and to our rank as moral creatures[Pg 38] that we should know and confess at the same time that it is not.

III. At first, it might seem that the entire realm of imagination is just a form of deception. That's not true: the imagination actively calls forth ideas of things that are absent or impossible, and the richness and beauty of imagination come from understanding and reflecting on these ideas as they are, meaning we recognize they are actually absent or impossible even when they seem present or real. When the imagination misleads us, it turns into madness. It remains a noble ability as long as it acknowledges its own ideal nature; when it stops doing that, it becomes insanity. The key difference lies in this acknowledgment, in there being no deception. It's essential for us as spiritual beings to create and perceive what isn’t there; and as moral beings[Pg 38] we must know and admit at the same time that it is not.

IV. Again, it might be thought, and has been thought, that the whole art of painting is nothing else than an endeavor to deceive. Not so: it is, on the contrary, a statement of certain facts, in the clearest possible way. For instance: I desire to give an account of a mountain or of a rock; I begin by telling its shape. But words will not do this distinctly, and I draw its shape, and say, "This was its shape." Next: I would fain represent its color; but words will not do this either, and I dye the paper, and say, "This was its color." Such a process may be carried on until the scene appears to exist, and a high pleasure may be taken in its apparent existence. This is a communicated act of imagination, but no lie. The lie can consist only in an assertion of its existence (which is never for one instant made, implied, or believed), or else in false statements of forms and colors (which are, indeed, made and believed to our great loss, continually). And observe, also, that so degrading a thing is deception in even the approach and appearance of it, that all painting which even reaches the mark of apparent realization, is degraded in so doing. I have enough insisted on this point in another place.

IV. Some might think that the entire art of painting is just an attempt to trick people. That's not true: it’s actually a way to present certain facts as clearly as possible. For example: I want to describe a mountain or a rock; I start by showing its shape. But words can’t clearly convey this, so I draw its shape and say, "This was its shape." Next, I want to show its color; again, words fail, so I dye the paper and say, "This was its color." This process can go on until the scene feels real, and people can derive great pleasure from its apparent existence. This is a shared act of imagination, but it’s not a lie. The only lie would be claiming it exists (which is never, even for a moment, asserted, implied, or believed), or making false statements about its forms and colors (which indeed happen and are believed, to our detriment, all the time). Also, understand that deception is so degrading that any painting that achieves an appearance of reality is diminished by that achievement. I've emphasized this point enough elsewhere.

V. The violations of truth, which dishonor poetry and painting, are thus for the most part confined to the treatment of their subjects. But in architecture another and a less subtle, more contemptible, violation of truth is possible; a direct falsity of assertion respecting the nature of material, or the quantity of labor. And this is, in the full sense of the word, wrong; it is as truly deserving of reprobation as any other moral delinquency; it is unworthy alike of architects and of nations; and it has been a sign, wherever it has widely and with toleration existed, of a singular debasement of the arts; that it is not a sign of worse than this, of a general want of severe probity, can be accounted for only by our knowledge of the strange separation which has for some centuries existed between the arts and all other subjects of human intellect, as matters of conscience. This withdrawal of conscientiousness from among the faculties concerned with art, while it has[Pg 39] destroyed the arts themselves, has also rendered in a measure nugatory the evidence which otherwise they might have presented respecting the character of the respective nations among whom they have been cultivated; otherwise, it might appear more than strange that a nation so distinguished for its general uprightness and faith as the English, should admit in their architecture more of pretence, concealment, and deceit, than any other of this or of past time.

V. The violations of truth that undermine poetry and painting are mostly related to how their subjects are handled. However, in architecture, there's a different, more obvious, and more contemptible violation of truth; this involves directly misrepresenting the nature of materials or the amount of labor involved. This is, in every sense, wrong; it deserves condemnation just like any other moral wrongdoing. It's unworthy of both architects and nations, and where this has been prevalent and tolerated, it's shown a serious decline in the arts. The fact that it doesn't indicate something even worse, like a general lack of integrity, can only be explained by our understanding of the unusual detachment that has existed for centuries between the arts and all other areas of human thought, treating them as matters of conscience. This lack of conscientiousness among those involved in art has not only harmed the arts themselves but has also somewhat negated the insights they could have provided about the character of the nations where they flourished. Otherwise, it might seem more than odd that a nation so known for its overall integrity and honesty, like the English, would allow more pretense, concealment, and deceit in their architecture than any other nation in this or any past era.

They are admitted in thoughtlessness, but with fatal effect upon the art in which they are practised. If there were no other causes for the failures which of late have marked every great occasion for architectural exertion, these petty dishonesties would be enough to account for all. It is the first step and not the least, towards greatness to do away with these; the first, because so evidently and easily in our power. We may not be able to command good, or beautiful, or inventive architecture; but we can command an honest architecture: the meagreness of poverty may be pardoned, the sternness of utility respected; but what is there but scorn for the meanness of deception?

They get in without thinking, but it has serious consequences for the art in which they're involved. Even if there were no other reasons for the recent failures that have marked every significant architectural effort, these small dishonesties would be enough to explain it all. It's the first step, and definitely not the least, towards achieving greatness to eliminate these issues; it's the first step because it's clearly and easily within our control. While we may not be able to create good, beautiful, or innovative architecture, we can create honest architecture. The lack of funds may be forgiven, and the harshness of practicality can be respected; but what can we say about the contempt for the dishonesty that diminishes our work?

VI. Architectural Deceits are broadly to be considered under three heads:—

VI. Architectural Deceits can be generally categorized into three main types:—

1st. The suggestion of a mode of structure or support, other than the true one; as in pendants of late Gothic roofs.

1st. The suggestion of a way to structure or support things, other than the actual one; like in the pendants of late Gothic roofs.

2d. The painting of surfaces to represent some other material than that of which they actually consist (as in the marbling of wood), or the deceptive representation of sculptured ornament upon them.

2d. Painting surfaces to look like a different material than they actually are (like marbled wood) or creating a misleading appearance of sculpted decoration on them.

3d. The use of cast or machine-made ornaments of any kind.

3d. The use of cast or machine-made decorations of any kind.

Now, it may be broadly stated, that architecture will be noble exactly in the degree in which all these false expedients are avoided. Nevertheless, there are certain degrees of them, which, owing to their frequent usage, or to other causes, have so far lost the nature of deceit as to be admissible; as, for instance, gilding, which is in architecture no deceit, because it is therein not understood for gold; while in jewellery it is a deceit, because it is so understood, and therefore altogether to be reprehended. So that there arise, in the application of[Pg 40] the strict rules of right, many exceptions and niceties of conscience; which let us as briefly as possible examine.

Now, it can be generally said that architecture will be great to the extent that all these misleading shortcuts are avoided. However, there are certain levels of them that, due to their common use or other reasons, have lost their deceptive nature well enough to be acceptable. For example, gilding in architecture is not deceitful because it's not perceived as gold; whereas in jewelry, it is considered deceitful because it is understood to be gold, and therefore is entirely to be criticized. This leads to many exceptions and subtle moral dilemmas in applying the strict principles of correctness; which we will examine as briefly as possible.

VII. 1st. Structural Deceits. I have limited these to the determined and purposed suggestion of a mode of support other than the true one. The architect is not bound to exhibit structure; nor are we to complain of him for concealing it, any more than we should regret that the outer surfaces of the human frame conceal much of its anatomy; nevertheless, that building will generally be the noblest, which to an intelligent eye discovers the great secrets of its structure, as an animal form does, although from a careless observer they may be concealed. In the vaulting of a Gothic roof it is no deceit to throw the strength into the ribs of it, and make the intermediate vault a mere shell. Such a structure would be presumed by an intelligent observer, the first time he saw such a roof; and the beauty of its traceries would be enhanced to him if they confessed and followed the lines of its main strength. If, however, the intermediate shell were made of wood instead of stone, and whitewashed to look like the rest,—this would, of course, be direct deceit, and altogether unpardonable.

VII. 1st. Structural Deceits. I’ve limited these to the deliberate and intentional suggestion of a way to support something that isn’t the true one. The architect is not required to show the structure; nor should we criticize him for hiding it, any more than we should regret that the outer surfaces of the human body conceal much of its anatomy; still, that building will usually be the finest, which reveals to an informed eye the great secrets of its structure, just like an animal form does, even though they may be hidden from a casual observer. In the arching of a Gothic roof, it is not deceitful to channel the strength into its ribs and make the intermediate vault a mere shell. An informed observer would assume this the first time he saw such a roof; and the beauty of its patterns would be enhanced for him if they revealed and followed the lines of its main strength. However, if the intermediate shell were made of wood instead of stone and painted to look like the rest—this would clearly be direct deceit and completely unacceptable.

There is, however, a certain deception necessarily occurring in Gothic architecture, which relates, not to the points, but to the manner, of support. The resemblance in its shafts and ribs to the external relations of stems and branches, which has been the ground of so much foolish speculation, necessarily induces in the mind of the spectator a sense or belief of a correspondent internal structure; that is to say, of a fibrous and continuous strength from the root into the limbs, and an elasticity communicated upwards, sufficient for the support of the ramified portions. The idea of the real conditions, of a great weight of ceiling thrown upon certain narrow, jointed lines, which have a tendency partly to be crushed, and partly to separate and be pushed outwards, is with difficulty received; and the more so when the pillars would be, if unassisted, too slight for the weight, and are supported by external flying buttresses, as in the apse of Beauvais, and other such achievements of the bolder Gothic. Now,[Pg 41] there is a nice question of conscience in this, which we shall hardly settle but by considering that, when the mind is informed beyond the possibility of mistake as to the true nature of things, the affecting it with a contrary impression, however distinct, is no dishonesty, but on the contrary, a legitimate appeal to the imagination. For instance, the greater part of the happiness which we have in contemplating clouds, results from the impression of their having massive, luminous, warm, and mountain-like surfaces; and our delight in the sky frequently depends upon our considering it as a blue vault. But we know the contrary, in both instances; we know the cloud to be a damp fog, or a drift of snow flakes; and the sky to be a lightless abyss. There is, therefore, no dishonesty, while there is much delight, in the irresistibly contrary impression. In the same way, so long as we see the stones and joints, and are not deceived as to the points of support in any piece of architecture, we may rather praise than regret the dextrous artifices which compel us to feel as if there were fibre in its shafts and life in its branches. Nor is even the concealment of the support of the external buttress reprehensible, so long as the pillars are not sensibly inadequate to their duty. For the weight of a roof is a circumstance of which the spectator generally has no idea, and the provisions for it, consequently, circumstances whose necessity or adaptation he could not understand. It is no deceit, therefore, when the weight to be borne is necessarily unknown, to conceal also the means of bearing it, leaving only to be perceived so much of the support as is indeed adequate to the weight supposed. For the shafts do, indeed, bear as much as they are ever imagined to bear, and the system of added support is no more, as a matter of conscience, to be exhibited, than, in the human or any other form, mechanical provisions for those functions which are themselves unperceived.

There is, however, a certain deception that inevitably occurs in Gothic architecture, which relates not to the points of support, but to how they are presented. The resemblance of its shafts and ribs to the external shapes of trees and branches, which has inspired so much misguided speculation, naturally leads the viewer to believe in a corresponding internal structure; that is, a fibrous and continuous strength extending from the root into the limbs, and an upward elasticity sufficient to support the branching sections. The reality of the situation—a heavy ceiling resting on narrow, jointed lines that tend to either crush or separate and push outward—is difficult to grasp, especially when the columns, if they were unassisted, would be too slight for the load, being supported by external flying buttresses, like those in the apse of Beauvais and other bold Gothic designs. Now,[Pg 41] there is a delicate question of ethics here, which we will hardly resolve unless we consider that when the mind is fully informed about the true nature of things, affecting it with a contrary impression, regardless of how distinct, is not dishonesty; rather, it's a legitimate appeal to the imagination. For example, much of the joy we find in observing clouds stems from the idea that they have massive, luminous, warm, mountain-like surfaces; and our pleasure in the sky often depends on seeing it as a blue vault. Yet we know the truth in both cases; we recognize that clouds are just damp fog or drifting snowflakes, and the sky is actually a dark void. Therefore, there is no dishonesty—only delight—in this irresistible contrary impression. Similarly, as long as we can see the stones and joints and are not misled about the points of support in any architectural piece, we should appreciate rather than regret the skilled tricks that make us feel as if there is fiber in its shafts and life in its branches. Nor is the concealment of the external buttress's support blameworthy, as long as the columns are not obviously inadequate for their role. Most spectators have no understanding of the roof's weight, and consequently, the measures taken to support it are beyond their comprehension. Thus, it is not deceitful, when the weight to be supported is inherently unknown, to also conceal the means of support, revealing only as much of the structure as is sufficient for the assumed weight. The shafts do indeed support as much as they are perceived to support, and the added support system should not be displayed, just as in human or other forms, mechanical provisions for functions that go unnoticed.

But the moment that the conditions of weight are comprehended, both truth and feeling require that the conditions of support should be also comprehended. Nothing can be worse, either as judged by the taste or the conscience, than[Pg 42] affectedly inadequate supports—suspensions in air, and other such tricks and vanities. Mr. Hope wisely reprehends, for this reason, the arrangement of the main piers of St. Sophia at Constantinople. King's College Chapel, Cambridge, is a piece of architectural juggling, if possible still more to be condemned, because less sublime.

But once we understand the conditions of weight, both truth and feeling demand that we also understand the conditions of support. Nothing is worse, whether judged by taste or morality, than[Pg 42] pretentiously inadequate supports—things like structures that seem to hang in the air, and other such tricks and fancies. Mr. Hope wisely criticizes, for this reason, the arrangement of the main piers of St. Sophia in Constantinople. King's College Chapel in Cambridge is an example of architectural trickery that might be even more worthy of condemnation because it's less grand.

VIII. With deceptive concealments of structure are to be classed, though still more blameable, deceptive assumptions of it—the introduction of members which should have, or profess to have, a duty, and have none. One of the most general instances of this will be found in the form of the flying buttress in late Gothic. The use of that member is, of course, to convey support from one pier to another when the plan of the building renders it necessary or desirable that the supporting masses should be divided into groups, the most frequent necessity of this kind arising from the intermediate range of chapels or aisles between the nave or choir walls and their supporting piers. The natural, healthy, and beautiful arrangement is that of a steeply sloping bar of stone, sustained by an arch with its spandril carried farthest down on the lowest side, and dying into the vertical of the outer pier; that pier being, of course, not square, but rather a piece of wall set at right angles to the supported walls, and, if need be, crowned by a pinnacle to give it greater weight. The whole arrangement is exquisitely carried out in the choir of Beauvais. In later Gothic the pinnacle became gradually a decorative member, and was used in all places merely for the sake of its beauty. There is no objection to this; it is just as lawful to build a pinnacle for its beauty as a tower; but also the buttress became a decorative member; and was used, first, where it was not wanted, and, secondly, in forms in which it could be of no use, becoming a mere tie, not between the pier and wall, but between the wall and the top of the decorative pinnacle, thus attaching itself to the very point where its thrust, if it made any, could not be resisted. The most flagrant instance of this barbarism that I remember (though it prevails partially in all the spires of the Netherlands), is the lantern of St. Ouen at Rouen, where the pierced buttress, having an ogee curve, looks about as much calculated[Pg 43] to bear a thrust as a switch of willow; and the pinnacles, huge and richly decorated, have evidently no work to do whatsoever, but stand round the central tower, like four idle servants, as they are—heraldic supporters, that central tower being merely a hollow crown, which needs no more buttressing than a basket does. In fact, I do not know anything more strange or unwise than the praise lavished upon this lantern; it is one of the basest pieces of Gothic in Europe; its flamboyant traceries of the last and most degraded forms;5 and its entire plan and decoration resembling, and deserving little more credit than, the burnt sugar ornaments of elaborate confectionery. There are hardly any of the magnificent and serene constructions of the early Gothic which have not, in the course of time, been gradually thinned and pared away into these skeletons, which sometimes indeed, when their lines truly follow the structure of the original masses, have an interest like that of the fibrous framework of leaves from which the substance has been dissolved, but which are usually distorted as well as emaciated, and remain but the sickly phantoms and mockeries of things that were; they are to true architecture what the Greek ghost was to the armed and living frame; and the very winds that whistle through the threads of them, are to the diapasoned echoes of the ancient walls, as to the voice of the man was the pining of the spectre.6

VIII. Deceptive concealments of structure include, even more problematically, misleading assumptions about it—the introduction of elements that are supposed to serve a purpose but actually don't. A common example of this is the flying buttress in late Gothic architecture. The purpose of this feature is to transfer support from one pier to another when the building's layout requires or benefits from dividing the supporting masses into groups. This need often arises from the chapels or aisles positioned between the nave or choir walls and their supporting piers. The ideal arrangement is a steeply sloping stone bar supported by an arch, with its spandril extending down the lowest side and connecting to the vertical of the outer pier. This pier should not be square but rather a section of wall angled at right angles to the supported walls, and if necessary, topped with a pinnacle for added weight. This arrangement is beautifully demonstrated in the choir of Beauvais. In later Gothic architecture, the pinnacle gradually became more decorative and was used solely for its aesthetic value. While there’s nothing wrong with building a pinnacle for beauty, the buttress also became decorative, first being placed where it was unnecessary and then designed in forms that were entirely useless. It became a mere tie not between the pier and the wall but between the wall and the top of the decorative pinnacle, attaching itself at a point where any thrust, if present, could not be resisted. One of the most blatant examples of this flaw that I can recall, although it appears to some extent in all the spires of the Netherlands, is the lantern of St. Ouen in Rouen. Here, the pierced buttress, with its ogee curve, seems as likely to bear a load as a willow switch, and the large, richly decorated pinnacles are clearly ineffective, standing around the central tower like four idle servants—they are just decorative supporters, with the central tower being merely a hollow crown that requires no more support than a basket does. In fact, I don’t understand the praise given to this lantern; it is one of the lowest examples of Gothic architecture in Europe, with its flamboyant traceries being of the last and most degraded style. Its entire design and decoration resemble, and deserve little more respect than, the burnt sugar ornaments of elaborate desserts. Hardly any of the magnificent and serene early Gothic structures have not, over time, been gradually reduced to these skeletal forms, which sometimes, when their lines genuinely follow the original shapes, have an intriguing quality similar to the fibrous skeletons of leaves after their substance has dissolved. However, they are usually both distorted and diminished, remaining only as sickly phantoms and mockeries of what once was; they are to true architecture what a shadow is to a living, armed body. The very winds that whistle through them contrast sharply with the resonant echoes of the ancient walls, much like the difference between the voice of a living man and the moan of a ghost.

IX. Perhaps the most fruitful source of these kinds of corruption which we have to guard against in recent times, is one which, nevertheless, comes in a "questionable shape," and of which it is not easy to determine the proper laws and limits; I mean the use of iron. The definition of the art of architecture, given in the first chapter, is independent of its materials: nevertheless, that art having been, up to the beginning of the present century, practised for the most part in clay, stone, or wood, it has resulted that the sense of proportion and the laws of structure have been based, the one altogether, the other in great part, on the necessities consequent on the employment of those materials; and that the entire or principal employment of metallic framework would, therefore, be generally felt as a departure from the first principles of the art. Abstract[Pg 44]edly there appears no reason why iron should not be used as well as wood; and the time is probably near when a new system of architectural laws will be developed, adapted entirely to metallic construction. But I believe that the tendency of all present sympathy and association is to limit the idea of architecture to non-metallic work; and that not without reason. For architecture being in its perfection the earliest, as in its elements it is necessarily the first, of arts, will always precede, in any barbarous nation, the possession of the science necessary either for the obtaining or the management of iron. Its first existence and its earliest laws must, therefore, depend upon the use of materials accessible in quantity, and on the surface of the earth; that is to say, clay, wood, or stone: and as I think it cannot but be generally felt that one of the chief dignities of architecture is its historical use; and since the latter is partly dependent on consistency of style, it will be felt right to retain as far as may be, even in periods of more advanced science, the materials and principles of earlier ages.

IX. One of the biggest sources of corruption we need to be cautious about these days comes in a "questionable form," and it's not easy to determine the right laws and limits for it; I'm talking about the use of iron. The definition of architecture provided in the first chapter is independent of the materials used. However, since architecture was mostly practiced with clay, stone, or wood until the early 21st century, our understanding of proportion and structural rules has mainly been shaped by the needs of those materials. As a result, the use of metal frameworks would generally be seen as a departure from the foundational principles of the art. There seems to be no reason, in theory, why iron can't be used just like wood; and it’s likely that we're approaching a time when a new system of architectural laws will emerge, specifically for metallic construction. However, I believe that the current trend is to limit the concept of architecture to non-metallic work, and there’s good reason for this. Architecture, in its perfect form, is the earliest of the arts, and has to be the first in any primitive society before they have the knowledge to obtain or handle iron. Its initial existence and earliest laws must rely on materials that are plentiful and found on the earth's surface, meaning clay, wood, or stone. I think it’s widely acknowledged that one of architecture’s main dignities is its historical context; and since this history is partly grounded in maintaining a consistent style, it feels appropriate to continue using the materials and principles of earlier times, even as science advances.

X. But whether this be granted me or not, the fact is, that every idea respecting size, proportion, decoration, or construction, on which we are at present in the habit of acting or judging, depends on presupposition of such materials: and as I both feel myself unable to escape the influence of these prejudices, and believe that my readers will be equally so, it may be perhaps permitted to me to assume that true architecture does not admit iron as a constructive material,7 and that such works as the cast-iron central spire of Rouen Cathedral, or the iron roofs and pillars of our railway stations, and of some of our churches, are not architecture at all. Yet it is evident that metals may, and sometimes must, enter into the construction to a certain extent, as nails in wooden architecture, and therefore as legitimately rivets and solderings in stone; neither can we well deny to the Gothic architect the power of supporting statues, pinnacles, or traceries by iron bars; and if we grant this I do not see how we can help allowing Brunelleschi his iron chain around the dome of Florence, or the builders of Salisbury their elaborate iron binding of the central tower.8 If, however, we would not fall into the old sophistry of the[Pg 45] grains of corn and the heap, we must find a rule which may enable us to stop somewhere. This rule is, I think, that metals may be used as a cement but not as a support. For as cements of other kinds are often so strong that the stones may easier be broken than separated, and the wall becomes a solid mass without for that reason losing the character of architecture, there is no reason why, when a nation has obtained the knowledge and practice of iron work, metal rods or rivets should not be used in the place of cement, and establish the same or a greater strength and adherence, without in any wise inducing departure from the types and system of architecture before established; nor does it make any difference except as to sightliness, whether the metal bands or rods so employed, be in the body of the wall or on its exterior, or set as stays and cross-bands; so only that the use of them be always and distinctly one which might be superseded by mere strength of cement; as for instance if a pinnacle or mullion be propped or tied by an iron band, it is evident that the iron only prevents the separation of the stones by lateral force, which the cement would have done, had it been strong enough. But the moment that the iron in the least degree takes the place of the stone, and acts by its resistance to crushing, and bears superincumbent weight, or if it acts by its own weight as a counterpoise, and so supersedes the use of pinnacles or buttresses in resisting a lateral thrust, or if, in the form of a rod or girder, it is used to do what wooden beams would have done as well, that instant the building ceases, so far as such applications of metal extend, to be true architecture.

X. But whether I’m allowed to say this or not, the truth is that every idea we have about size, proportion, decoration, or construction that we currently rely on or judge by is based on assumptions about materials. Since I feel I can't escape these biases, and I believe my readers won’t either, I think it’s fair to suggest that true architecture doesn’t use iron as a structural material, and that features like the cast-iron central spire of Rouen Cathedral or the iron roofs and pillars of our railway stations and some churches aren’t really architecture at all. However, it’s clear that metals can and sometimes must be part of construction to a certain extent, just like nails in wooden architecture, and thus rivets and soldering in stone are equally justified. We can’t deny that Gothic architects had the ability to support statues, pinnacles, or traceries with iron bars; and if we accept this, I don’t see why we shouldn’t allow Brunelleschi's iron chain around the dome of Florence or the intricate iron binding of Salisbury’s central tower. If we want to avoid falling into the old trick of confusing grains of corn with a heap, we need to establish a rule that helps us draw a line. This rule, I believe, is that metals can be used as a cement but not as a support. Just as other types of cement can be so strong that the stones are easier to break than to pull apart, creating a solid mass without losing the essence of architecture, there’s no reason why, once a nation understands and practices working with iron, metal rods or rivets can’t replace cement and provide the same or even greater strength and adherence without deviating from established architectural styles. It doesn’t matter, aside from appearance, whether the metal bands or rods are embedded in the wall, placed on the exterior, or used as stays and cross-bands; as long as their use could always be replaced by strong cement. For example, if a pinnacle or mullion is supported or secured by an iron band, it’s clear the iron is just preventing the stones from separating due to lateral force, a job cement would do if it were strong enough. But the moment iron starts to replace stone, resisting crushing, bearing weight, or acting as a counterweight, replacing the need for pinnacles or buttresses to resist lateral pressure, or if it functions as a rod or girder doing the job of wooden beams, at that point the structure stops being true architecture to the extent that those metal applications exist.

XI. The limit, however, thus determined, is an ultimate one, and it is well in all things to be cautious how we approach the utmost limit of lawfulness; so that, although the employment of metal within this limit cannot be considered as destroying the very being and nature of architecture, it will, if, extravagant and frequent, derogate from the dignity of the work, as well as (which is especially to our present point) from its honesty. For although the spectator is not informed as to the quantity or strength of the cement employed, he will generally conceive the stones of the building to be separable[Pg 46] and his estimate of the skill of the architect will be based in a great measure on his supposition of this condition, and of the difficulties attendant upon it: so that it is always more honorable, and it has a tendency to render the style of architecture both more masculine and more scientific, to employ stone and mortar simply as such, and to do as much as possible with the weight of the one and the strength of the other, and rather sometimes to forego a grace, or to confess a weakness, than attain the one, or conceal the other, by means verging upon dishonesty.

XI. The limit we’ve set is an ultimate one, and it’s wise to be careful about approaching the very edge of what is lawful. While using metal within this limit doesn’t destroy the essence of architecture, if it’s used too extravagantly and frequently, it can detract from the dignity of the work and, especially relevant to our discussion, from its honesty. Even though the viewer isn’t aware of the amount or strength of the cement used, they often assume that the stones of the building can be separated, and their judgment of the architect's skill will largely depend on this assumption and the associated challenges. Therefore, it’s always more respectable and tends to make the architectural style both bolder and more scientific to use stone and mortar in their pure forms, doing as much as possible with their weight and strength, and sometimes choosing to sacrifice elegance or acknowledge a weakness rather than achieve one or hide the other through methods that border on dishonesty.

Nevertheless, where the design is of such delicacy and slightness as, in some parts of very fair and finished edifices, it is desirable that it should be; and where both its completion and security are in a measure dependent on the use of metal, let not such use be reprehended; so only that as much is done as may be, by good mortar and good masonry; and no slovenly workmanship admitted through confidence in the iron helps; for it is in this license as in that of wine, a man may use it for his infirmities, but not for his nourishment.

However, when the design is so delicate and fine, as seen in some beautifully crafted buildings, it’s important that it remains that way. And where both its completion and stability depend in part on the use of metal, don't criticize its use; just make sure that as much as possible is done with quality mortar and good masonry. Poor workmanship shouldn't be allowed just because there’s confidence in the metal supports; it’s like using wine—one can use it for their weaknesses, but not as a substitute for proper sustenance.

XII. And, in order to avoid an over use of this liberty, it would be well to consider what application may be conveniently made of the dovetailing and various adjusting of stones; for when any artifice is necessary to help the mortar, certainly this ought to come before the use of metal, for it is both safer and more honest. I cannot see that any objection can be made to the fitting of the stones in any shapes the architect pleases: for although it would not be desirable to see buildings put together like Chinese puzzles, there must always be a check upon such an abuse of the practice in its difficulty; nor is it necessary that it should be always exhibited, so that it be understood by the spectator as an admitted help, and that no principal stones are introduced in positions apparently impossible for them to retain, although a riddle here and there, in unimportant features, may sometimes serve to draw the eye to the masonry, and make it interesting, as well as to give a delightful sense of a kind of necromantic power in the architect. There is a pretty one in the lintel of the lateral door of the cathedral of Prato[Pg 47] (Plate IV. fig. 4.); where the maintenance of the visibly separate stones, alternate marble and serpentine, cannot be understood until their cross-cutting is seen below. Each block is, of course, of the form given in fig. 5.

XII. To prevent an excessive use of this freedom, it's important to think about how the dovetailing and various adjustments of stones can be applied conveniently. When any trick is needed to support the mortar, it should definitely come before using metal because it’s safer and more straightforward. I don’t think there’s anything wrong with shaping the stones any way the architect wants. Even though buildings shouldn't look like Chinese puzzles, there should always be a limit to such practices due to their complexity. It’s not necessary for these techniques to be obvious, as long as spectators recognize them as a legitimate support, and no major stones are placed in seemingly impossible positions. However, a puzzle here and there in minor features can catch the eye and make the masonry interesting, giving a charming sense of the architect’s skill. A notable example is the lintel of the side door of the cathedral of Prato[Pg 47] (Plate IV. fig. 4.), where the visibly separate stones—alternating marble and serpentine—can only be understood when viewed from below. Each block is, of course, shaped as shown in fig. 5.

XIII. Lastly, before leaving the subject of structural deceits, I would remind the architect who thinks that I am unnecessarily and narrowly limiting his resources or his art, that the highest greatness and the highest wisdom are shown, the first by a noble submission to, the second by a thoughtful providence for, certain voluntarily admitted restraints. Nothing is more evident than this, in that supreme government which is the example, as it is the centre, of all others. The Divine Wisdom is, and can be, shown to us only in its meeting and contending with the difficulties which are voluntarily, and for the sake of that contest, admitted by the Divine Omnipotence: and these difficulties, observe, occur in the form of natural laws or ordinances, which might, at many times and in countless ways, be infringed with apparent advantage, but which are never infringed, whatever costly arrangements or adaptations their observance may necessitate for the accomplishment of given purposes. The example most apposite to our present subject is the structure of the bones of animals. No reason can be given, I believe, why the system of the higher animals should not have been made capable, as that of the Infusoria is, of secreting flint, instead of phosphate of lime, or more naturally still, carbon; so framing the bones of adamant at once. The elephant or rhinoceros, had the earthy part of their bones been made of diamond, might have been as agile and light as grasshoppers, and other animals might have been framed far more magnificently colossal than any that walk the earth. In other worlds we may, perhaps, see such creations; a creation for every element, and elements infinite. But the architecture of animals here, is appointed by God to be a marble architecture, not a flint nor adamant architecture; and all manner of expedients are adopted to attain the utmost degree of strength and size possible under that great limitation. The jaw of the ichthyosaurus is pieced and riveted, the leg of the megatherium is a foot thick, and[Pg 48] the head of the myodon has a double skull; we, in our wisdom, should, doubtless, have given the lizard a steel jaw, and the myodon a cast-iron headpiece, and forgotten the great principle to which all creation bears witness, that order and system are nobler things than power. But God shows us in Himself, strange as it may seem, not only authoritative perfection, but even the perfection of Obedience—an obedience to His own laws: and in the cumbrous movement of those unwieldiest of His creatures we are reminded, even in His divine essence, of that attribute of uprightness in the human creature "that sweareth to his own hurt and changeth not."

XIII. Finally, before wrapping up the topic of structural deceptions, I want to remind any architect who thinks I’m being overly restrictive about his resources or artistry that true greatness and wisdom are revealed through a noble acceptance of, and thoughtful consideration for, some self-imposed limitations. This is evident in the highest form of governance, which serves as both the example and the center of all others. Divine Wisdom can only be understood through its interactions and struggles with challenges that are voluntarily accepted by Divine Omnipotence, and these challenges often take the form of natural laws that could, at many moments and in numerous ways, be violated with seeming benefits, but are never violated, regardless of the costly arrangements required to adhere to them for achieving certain goals. A relevant example for our discussion is the skeletal structure of animals. I can't see a reason why the skeletons of higher animals couldn't have been designed to produce flint like those of the Infusoria, or even more naturally, carbon, thus creating bones of diamond instantly. If an elephant or a rhinoceros had bones made of diamond, they could have been as nimble and light as grasshoppers, and other animals might have been constructed in far grander sizes than any that exist on earth. In other worlds, we might see such creations—one for every element, with infinite elements. But the architecture of animals here is intended by God to be marble architecture, not made of flint or diamond; and all kinds of methods are used to achieve the greatest strength and size possible within that limitation. The jaw of the ichthyosaurus is intricately connected, the leg of the megatherium is a foot thick, and the head of the myodon has a double skull; we, in our wisdom, would certainly have given the lizard a steel jaw and the myodon a cast-iron head, forgetting the great principle that all creation illustrates: that order and system are nobler than mere power. Yet God demonstrates to us, as strange as it might seem, not only unmatched perfection but also the perfection of obedience—to His own laws: and in the cumbersome movements of His heaviest creatures, we are reminded of that quality in humans "who swears to his own harm and does not change."

XIV. 2d. Surface Deceits. These may be generally defined as the inducing the supposition of some form or material which does not actually exist; as commonly in the painting of wood to represent marble, or in the painting of ornaments in deceptive relief, &c. But we must be careful to observe, that the evil of them consists always in definitely attempted deception, and that it is a matter of some nicety to mark the point where deception begins or ends.

XIV. 2d. Surface Deceits. These can generally be defined as creating the impression of some form or material that doesn't actually exist; for example, painting wood to look like marble or creating painted decorations that give a deceptive sense of depth, etc. However, we must be careful to note that the problem lies in the intention to deceive, and it can be quite subtle to identify exactly where deception starts or finishes.

Thus, for instance, the roof of Milan Cathedral is seemingly covered with elaborate fan tracery, forcibly enough painted to enable it, in its dark and removed position, to deceive a careless observer. This is, of course, gross degradation; it destroys much of the dignity even of the rest of the building, and is in the very strongest terms to be reprehended.

Thus, for example, the roof of Milan Cathedral looks like it's covered with intricate fan tracery, painted in such a way that it can trick an inattentive observer from its dark and distant spot. This is, of course, a serious decline; it undermines much of the dignity of the rest of the building and should be strongly criticized.

The roof of the Sistine Chapel has much architectural design in grissaille mingled with the figures of its frescoes; and the effect is increase of dignity.

The ceiling of the Sistine Chapel features a lot of architectural design in gray tones mixed with the figures of its frescoes, and this enhances its overall dignity.

In what lies the distinctive character?

In what does the unique character lie?

In two points, principally:—First. That the architecture is so closely associated with the figures, and has so grand fellowship with them in its forms and cast shadows, that both are at once felt to be of a piece; and as the figures must necessarily be painted, the architecture is known to be so too. There is thus no deception.

In two main points:—First. The architecture is so closely linked with the figures, and it shares such a grand harmony with them in its shapes and shadows, that both are immediately recognized as part of the same whole; and since the figures have to be painted, it's clear that the architecture is as well. There’s no trickery involved.

Second. That so great a painter as Michael Angelo would always stop short in such minor parts of his design, of the de[Pg 49]gree of vulgar force which would be necessary to induce the supposition of their reality; and, strangely as it may sound, would never paint badly enough to deceive.

Second. That such a great painter as Michael Angelo would always hold back on the minor details of his work, to the point where the level of ordinary force needed to suggest their reality would be lacking; and, as strange as it may seem, he would never paint poorly enough to fool anyone.

But though right and wrong are thus found broadly opposed in works severally so mean and so mighty as the roof of Milan and that of the Sistine, there are works neither so great nor so mean, in which the limits of right are vaguely defined, and will need some care to determine; care only, however, to apply accurately the broad principle with which we set out, that no form nor material is to be deceptively represented.

But even though right and wrong are clearly opposed in works as simple as the roof of Milan and as grand as that of the Sistine Chapel, there are works that aren't as great or as simple, where the boundaries of right are not clearly defined and will require some effort to figure out; this effort is just to accurately apply the broad principle we started with, that no form or material should be deceptively represented.

XV. Evidently, then, painting, confessedly such, is no deception: it does not assert any material whatever. Whether it be on wood or on stone, or, as will naturally be supposed, on plaster, does not matter. Whatever the material, good painting makes it more precious; nor can it ever be said to deceive respecting the ground of which it gives us no information. To cover brick with plaster, and this plaster with fresco, is, therefore, perfectly legitimate; and as desirable a mode of decoration as it is constant in the great periods. Verona and Venice are now seen deprived of more than half their former splendor; it depended far more on their frescoes than their marbles. The plaster, in this case, is to be considered as the gesso ground on panel or canvas. But to cover brick with cement, and to divide this cement with joints that it may look like stone, is to tell a falsehood; and is just as contemptible a procedure as the other is noble.

XV. Clearly, painting is not deceptive; it doesn't claim to be anything other than what it is. It doesn't matter if it's on wood, stone, or plaster. Good painting makes any material more valuable; it never misrepresents the material it’s done on. Covering brick with plaster and then painting fresco on that plaster is a completely valid and desirable way to decorate, just as it was in great historical periods. Verona and Venice today show only a fraction of their former glory; that glory relied much more on their frescoes than on their marble. In this case, the plaster is comparable to the gesso used on panels or canvas. However, covering brick with cement and making it look like stone by adding joints is misleading, and it’s just as contemptible as it is admirable to do the opposite.

It being lawful to paint then, is it lawful to paint everything? So long as the painting is confessed—yes; but if, even in the slightest degree, the sense of it be lost, and the thing painted be supposed real—no. Let us take a few instances. In the Campo Santo at Pisa, each fresco is surrounded with a border composed of flat colored patterns of great elegance—no part of it in attempted relief. The certainty of flat surface being thus secured, the figures, though the size of life, do not deceive, and the artist thenceforward is at liberty to put forth his whole power, and to lead us through fields and groves, and depths of pleasant landscape, and to soothe us with the sweet clearness of far off sky, and yet[Pg 50] never lose the severity of his primal purpose of architectural decoration.

Is it legal to paint everything if painting is allowed? As long as the painting is acknowledged—yes; but if even a little bit of its meaning is lost and the painted subject is taken to be real—no. Let's look at a few examples. In the Campo Santo at Pisa, each fresco is bordered by elegantly colored flat patterns—none of it attempts to create depth. By ensuring a flat surface, the figures, even though life-sized, are not deceptive, allowing the artist to fully express their talent and take us through fields, groves, and beautiful landscapes, calming us with the clear blue of the distant sky, yet[Pg 50] never straying from the strict intention of architectural decoration.

In the Camera di Correggio of San Lodovico at Parma, the trellises of vine shadow the walls, as if with an actual arbor; and the troops of children, peeping through the oval openings, luscious in color and faint in light, may well be expected every instant to break through, or hide behind the covert. The grace of their attitudes, and the evident greatness of the whole work, mark that it is painting, and barely redeem it from the charge of falsehood; but even so saved, it is utterly unworthy to take a place among noble or legitimate architectural decoration.

In the Camera di Correggio of San Lodovico at Parma, the vine trellises cast shadows on the walls, resembling a real arbor; and the groups of children, peeking through the oval openings, vibrant in color and faintly lit, seem ready to emerge or hide behind the foliage at any moment. The elegance of their poses, along with the overall grandeur of the piece, clearly shows that this is painting, and just manages to avoid being dismissed as false; however, even with that redemption, it is completely unfit to be considered part of noble or legitimate architectural decoration.

In the cupola of the duomo of Parma the same painter has represented the Assumption with so much deceptive power, that he has made a dome of some thirty feet diameter look like a cloud-wrapt opening in the seventh heaven, crowded with a rushing sea of angels. Is this wrong? Not so: for the subject at once precludes the possibility of deception. We might have taken the vines for a veritable pergoda, and the children for its haunting ragazzi; but we know the stayed clouds and moveless angels must be man's work; let him put his utmost strength to it and welcome, he can enchant us, but cannot betray.

In the dome of the duomo in Parma, the same painter has depicted the Assumption with such stunning skill that he has turned a dome about thirty feet wide into what looks like a cloud-covered opening to the seventh heaven, filled with a rushing sea of angels. Is this wrong? Not at all: for the subject matter itself makes deception impossible. We might have mistaken the vines for a real pergola and the children for its lingering spirits; but we understand that the still clouds and unmoving angels must be created by human hands; no matter how hard he tries, he can amaze us but cannot deceive us.

We may thus apply the rule to the highest, as well as the art of daily occurrence, always remembering that more is to be forgiven to the great painter than to the mere decorative workman; and this especially, because the former, even in deceptive portions, will not trick us so grossly; as we have just seen in Correggio, where a worse painter would have made the thing look like life at once. There is, however, in room, villa, or garden decoration, some fitting admission of trickeries of this kind, as of pictured landscapes at the extremities of alleys and arcades, and ceilings like skies, or painted with prolongations upwards of the architecture of the walls, which things have sometimes a certain luxury and pleasureableness in places meant for idleness, and are innocent enough as long as they are regarded as mere toys.

We can apply this rule to both the highest art and everyday occurrences, always remembering that a great painter deserves more forgiveness than a simple decorative worker. This is particularly true because the former, even when using deceptive techniques, doesn't trick us as blatantly; as we just saw with Correggio, where a lesser painter would have made things look lifelike right away. However, in the decoration of rooms, villas, or gardens, there's a certain acceptable use of tricks, like painted landscapes at the ends of paths and arcades, ceilings that mimic the sky, or extensions of the walls' architecture painted upwards, which sometimes add a sense of luxury and enjoyment in spaces meant for relaxation, and are harmless as long as we see them as mere playful elements.

XVI. Touching the false representation of material, the[Pg 51] question is infinitely more simple, and the law more sweeping; all such imitations are utterly base and inadmissible. It is melancholy to think of the time and expense lost in marbling the shop fronts of London alone, and of the waste of our resources in absolute vanities, in things about which no mortal cares, by which no eye is ever arrested, unless painfully, and which do not add one whit to comfort or cleanliness, or even to that great object of commercial art—conspicuousness. But in architecture of a higher rank, how much more is it to be condemned? I have made it a rule in the present work not to blame specifically; but I may, perhaps, be permitted, while I express my sincere admiration of the very noble entrance and general architecture of the British Museum, to express also my regret that the noble granite foundation of the staircase should be mocked at its landing by an imitation, the more blameable because tolerably successful. The only effect of it is to cast a suspicion upon the true stones below, and upon every bit of granite afterwards encountered. One feels a doubt, after it, of the honesty of Memnon himself. But even this, however derogatory to the noble architecture around it, is less painful than the want of feeling with which, in our cheap modern churches, we suffer the wall decorator to erect about the altar frameworks and pediments daubed with mottled color, and to dye in the same fashions such skeletons or caricatures of columns as may emerge above the pews; this is not merely bad taste; it is no unimportant or excusable error which brings even these shadows of vanity and falsehood into the house of prayer. The first condition which just feeling requires in church furniture is, that it should be simple and unaffected, not fictitious nor tawdry. It may be in our power to make it beautiful, but let it at least be pure; and if we cannot permit much to the architect, do not let us permit anything to the upholsterer; if we keep to solid stone and solid wood, whitewashed, if we like, for cleanliness' sake (for whitewash has so often been used as the dress of noble things that it has thence received a kind of nobility itself), it must be a bad design indeed which is grossly offensive. I recollect no instance of a[Pg 52] want of sacred character, or of any marked and painful ugliness, in the simplest or the most awkwardly built village church, where stone and wood were roughly and nakedly used, and the windows latticed with white glass. But the smoothly stuccoed walls, the flat roofs with ventilator ornaments, the barred windows with jaundiced borders and dead ground square panes, the gilded or bronzed wood, the painted iron, the wretched upholstery of curtains and cushions, and pew heads and altar railings, and Birmingham metal candlesticks, and, above all, the green and yellow sickness of the false marble—disguises all, observe; falsehoods all—who are they who like these things? who defend them? who do them? I have never spoken to any one who did like them, though to many who thought them matters of no consequence. Perhaps not to religion (though I cannot but believe that there are many to whom, as to myself, such things are serious obstacles to the repose of mind and temper which should precede devotional exercises); but to the general tone of our judgment and feeling—yes; for assuredly we shall regard, with tolerance, if not with affection, whatever forms of material things we have been in the habit of associating with our worship, and be little prepared to detect or blame hypocrisy, meanness, and disguise in other kinds of decoration when we suffer objects belonging to the most solemn of all services to be tricked out in a fashion so fictitious and unseemly.

XVI. Regarding the false representation of materials, the[Pg 51] issue is much simpler, and the law is broader; all such imitations are completely unacceptable. It's sad to think about the time and money wasted on decorating shop fronts in London alone, and on our resources spent on absolute vanities—things that no one cares about, that don’t catch anyone's eye unless painfully so, and that don’t enhance comfort, cleanliness, or even what commercial art aims for—visibility. But in higher architecture, how much more condemnable is it? I've made it a point in this work not to criticize specifically; however, I might be allowed to express my genuine admiration for the impressive entrance and overall architecture of the British Museum, while also lamenting that the noble granite foundation of the staircase is undermined at its landing by an imitation, which is more blameworthy because it’s reasonably convincing. The only result is that it casts doubt on the real stones below and every other granite piece encountered afterwards. One starts to question the integrity of Memnon himself. Yet, even this, although damaging to the noble architecture around it, is less frustrating than the insensitivity with which we allow modern church decorators to set up around the altar frameworks and pediments splashed with random colors, and to paint in the same styles those skeletal or caricatured columns that might rise above the pews; this isn’t just bad taste; it is not a trivial or excusable mistake that brings even these shadows of vanity and falsehood into the house of prayer. The first requirement that genuine sensitivity demands in church furniture is that it should be simple and sincere, not fake or gaudy. We may be able to make it beautiful, but let it at least be pure; and if we cannot give much leeway to the architect, let’s not allow anything to the upholsterer; if we stick to solid stone and solid wood, whitewashed if we wish (since whitewash has often been used as the covering for noble things, it has earned a kind of nobility itself), it must be really poorly designed if it’s grossly offensive. I recall no instance of a[Pg 52] lack of sacred character, or any significant and painful ugliness, in the simplest or most awkwardly built village church, where stone and wood were used roughly and openly, and the windows were latticed with white glass. But the smoothly plastered walls, the flat roofs adorned with ventilators, the barred windows with sickly borders and dull square panes, the gilded or bronzed wood, the painted iron, the terrible upholstery of curtains and cushions, and pew ends and altar railings, and Birmingham metal candlesticks, and above all, the sickly green and yellow of the fake marble—disguises all, keep that in mind; all falsehoods—who are the people who like these things? Who defends them? Who creates them? I've never met anyone who did like them, though I have spoken to many who thought they were inconsequential. Perhaps they don’t seem relevant to religion (though I truly believe that for many, like myself, such things are serious barriers to the peace of mind and spirit that should precede devotional activities); but to the general tone of our judgment and feeling—yes; as we are surely inclined to view, with tolerance, if not affection, any forms of material things we have become accustomed to associating with our worship, and will be less prepared to identify or critique hypocrisy, meanness, and deception in other types of decoration when we allow objects related to the most solemn of all services to be adorned in such a fake and inappropriate manner.

XVII. Painting, however, is not the only mode in which material may be concealed, or rather simulated; for merely to conceal is, as we have seen, no wrong. Whitewash, for instance, though often (by no means always) to be regretted as a concealment, is not to be blamed as a falsity. It shows itself for what it is, and asserts nothing of what is beneath it. Gilding has become, from its frequent use, equally innocent. It is understood for what it is, a film merely, and is, therefore, allowable to any extent. I do not say expedient: it is one of the most abused means of magnificence we possess, and I much doubt whether any use we ever make of it, balances that loss of pleasure, which, from the frequent sight and perpetual suspicion of it, we suffer in the contemplation of any[Pg 53]thing that is verily of gold. I think gold was meant to be seldom seen and to be admired as a precious thing; and I sometimes wish that truth should so far literally prevail as that all should be gold that glittered, or rather that nothing should glitter that was not gold. Nevertheless, nature herself does not dispense with such semblance, but uses light for it; and I have too great a love for old and saintly art to part with its burnished field, or radiant nimbus; only it should be used with respect, and to express magnificence, or sacredness, and not in lavish vanity, or in sign painting. Of its expedience, however, any more than of that of color, it is not here the place to speak; we are endeavoring to determine what is lawful, not what is desirable. Of other and less common modes of disguising surface, as of powder of lapis lazuli, or mosaic imitations of colored stones, I need hardly speak. The rule will apply to all alike, that whatever is pretended, is wrong; commonly enforced also by the exceeding ugliness and insufficient appearance of such methods, as lately in the style of renovation by which half the houses in Venice have been defaced, the brick covered first with stucco, and this painted with zigzag veins in imitation of alabaster. But there is one more form of architectural fiction, which is so constant in the great periods that it needs respectful judgment. I mean the facing of brick with precious stone.

XVII. Painting is not the only way to hide or simulate material; after all, just hiding something isn’t wrong. For example, while whitewash is often regrettably used to cover things up, it isn’t false. It shows itself for what it is and doesn’t claim to be anything hidden underneath. Gilding has become equally innocent due to its frequent use. It’s recognized for what it is, just a thin layer, and can be used as much as desired. I’m not saying it’s always a good idea; it’s one of the most overused means of showing off we have, and I seriously doubt that any usage of it makes up for the pleasure we lose from seeing and constantly suspecting it when we’re looking at anything that’s truly made of gold. I believe gold should be seen rarely and admired as a treasure; sometimes, I wish that everything that glitters was really gold, or that nothing would glitter unless it was gold. Still, nature herself uses such appearances through light, and I love old and sacred art too much to let go of its shiny surfaces or glowing halos. However, it should be used respectfully, to convey magnificence or sacredness, and not in excessive vanity or as mere decoration. Regarding its usefulness, like that of color, this isn’t the place to discuss; we’re trying to determine what’s acceptable, not what’s preferable. As for other, less common ways of decorating surfaces, like lapis lazuli powder or mosaic imitations of colored stones, there’s no need to elaborate. The same rule applies to all: whatever pretends to be something it’s not is wrong, often made clear by the extreme ugliness and insufficient quality of such techniques, like the recent renovation style that has defaced half the buildings in Venice, where bricks are first covered with stucco, then painted to look like jagged veins of alabaster. However, there is one more form of architectural deception that is so common in great periods that it deserves careful consideration. I mean the practice of facing bricks with precious stones.

XVIII. It is well known, that what is meant by a church's being built of marble is, in nearly all cases, only that a veneering of marble has been fastened on the rough brick wall, built with certain projections to receive it; and that what appear to be massy stones, are nothing more than external slabs.

XVIII. It is well known that when we say a church is built of marble, it usually just means that a layer of marble has been attached to a rough brick wall, which has been constructed with specific projections to hold it; and that what looks like solid stones are really just exterior slabs.

Now, it is evident, that, in this case, the question of right is on the same ground as in that of gilding. If it be clearly understood that a marble facing does not pretend or imply a marble wall, there is no harm in it; and as it is also evident that, when very precious stones are used, as jaspers and serpentines, it must become, not only an extravagant and vain increase of expense, but sometimes an actual impossibility, to obtain mass of them enough to build with, there is no resource but this of veneering; nor is there anything to be alleged[Pg 54] against it on the head of durability, such work having been by experience found to last as long, and in as perfect condition, as any kind of masonry. It is, therefore, to be considered as simply an art of mosaic on a large scale, the ground being of brick, or any other material; and when lovely stones are to be obtained, it is a manner which should be thoroughly understood, and often practised. Nevertheless, as we esteem the shaft of a column more highly for its being of a single block, and as we do not regret the loss of substance and value which there is in things of solid gold, silver, agate, or ivory; so I think the walls themselves may be regarded with a more just complacency if they are known to be all of noble substance; and that rightly weighing the demands of the two principles of which we have hitherto spoken—Sacrifice and Truth, we should sometimes rather spare external ornament than diminish the unseen value and consistency of what we do; and I believe that a better manner of design, and a more careful and studious, if less abundant decoration would follow, upon the consciousness of thoroughness in the substance. And, indeed, this is to be remembered, with respect to all the points we have examined; that while we have traced the limits of license, we have not fixed those of that high rectitude which refuses license. It is thus true that there is no falsity, and much beauty in the use of external color, and that it is lawful to paint either pictures or patterns on whatever surfaces may seem to need enrichment. But it is not less true, that such practices are essentially unarchitectural; and while we cannot say that there is actual danger in an over use of them, seeing that they have been always used most lavishly in the times of most noble art, yet they divide the work into two parts and kinds, one of less durability than the other, which dies away from it in process of ages, and leaves it, unless it have noble qualities of its own, naked and bare. That enduring noblesse I should, therefore, call truly architectural; and it is not until this has been secured that the accessory power of painting may be called in, for the delight of the immediate time; nor this, as I think, until every resource of a more stable kind has been exhausted. The true colors of architecture are those of natural stone, and [Pg 55] I would fain see these taken advantage of to the full. Every variety of hue, from pale yellow to purple, passing through orange, red, and brown, is entirely at our command; nearly every kind of green and gray is also attainable: and with these, and pure white, what harmonies might we not achieve? Of stained and variegated stone, the quantity is unlimited, the kinds innumerable; where brighter colors are required, let glass, and gold protected by glass, be used in mosaic—a kind of work as durable as the solid stone, and incapable of losing its lustre by time—and let the painter's work be reserved for the shadowed loggia and inner chamber. This is the true and faithful way of building; where this cannot be, the device of external coloring may, indeed, be employed without dishonor; but it must be with the warning reflection, that a time will come when such aids must pass away, and when the building will be judged in its lifelessness, dying the death of the dolphin. Better the less bright, more enduring fabric. The transparent alabasters of San Miniato, and the mosaics of St. Mark's, are more warmly filled, and more brightly touched, by every return of morning and evening rays; while the hues of our cathedrals have died like the iris out of the cloud; and the temples whose azure and purple once flamed above the Grecian promontories, stand in their faded whiteness, like snows which the sunset has left cold.

Now, it's clear that, in this case, the question of what is right is similar to that of gilding. If it's understood that a marble-facing doesn't claim to be a marble wall, there's no harm in it. Additionally, when very precious stones, like jaspers and serpentines, are used, it becomes not only an extravagant and pointless increase in expense, but sometimes an actual impossibility to gather enough of them to build with, leaving us with no choice but to veneer. There’s nothing against it in terms of durability, as experience has shown that such work can last just as long and be in just as perfect condition as any type of masonry. Therefore, it should be viewed simply as a large-scale form of mosaic, with a base of brick or any other material. When beautiful stones are available, this technique should be well understood and frequently practiced. However, just as we value a column's shaft more when it’s made from a single block, and we don't regret the loss of substance and value in solid gold, silver, agate, or ivory, I believe the walls themselves can be appreciated more if they’re known to be made of noble materials. We should weigh the two principles we’ve discussed—Sacrifice and Truth—and sometimes choose to save on external decoration rather than compromise the unseen value and integrity of our work. I believe this awareness will lead to a better style of design and more thoughtful and diligent, albeit less opulent, decoration due to a focus on material quality. It’s crucial to remember that while we have outlined the limits of license, we have not defined the boundaries of a high standard that rejects such license. It's true that there's beauty and no dishonesty in using external color, and it's acceptable to paint pictures or patterns on surfaces that might benefit from embellishment. However, it’s equally true that these practices are fundamentally unarchitectural; while we can’t say there's actual danger in overusing these techniques, given their historic abundance during periods of great art, they do separate the work into two parts and types—one less durable than the other—which eventually degrades over time, leaving the structure vulnerable unless it possesses its own noble qualities. That enduring quality I’d call truly architectural; and it’s only after this is secured that the added benefit of painting can be considered for contemporary enjoyment, but only after all more stable resources have been utilized. The true colors of architecture are those of natural stone, and I would like to see these fully appreciated. We have access to every range of color, from pale yellow to purple, covering orange, red, and brown; nearly every shade of green and gray is also attainable. With these, along with pure white, we can create stunning harmonies! The quantity of stained and varied stone is limitless, with countless types available; where brighter colors are needed, glass and gold protected by glass can be used in mosaic—this method is as durable as solid stone and won’t lose its shine over time. The painter's work should be saved for shadowy loggias and inner chambers. This is the true and faithful way to build; where this isn't possible, external coloring can be used without shame, but it should be done with the understanding that a time will come when these aids must fade away, and the building will be assessed in its lifelessness, dying the death of the dolphin. Better to have a less brilliant, more enduring structure. The transparent alabasters of San Miniato and the mosaics of St. Mark's are more warmly illuminated and more vividly touched by each morning and evening ray; meanwhile, the colors of our cathedrals have faded like an iris from clouds, and the temples that once shone with azure and purple above the Grecian cliffs now stand in their dull whiteness, like snow left cold by the sunset.

PLATE II. PLATE II.—(Page 55—Vol. V.)
A section of the Cathedral of St. Lo, Normandy.

XIX. The last form of fallacy which it will be remembered we had to deprecate, was the substitution of cast or machine work for that of the hand, generally expressible as Operative Deceit.

XIX. The last type of fallacy that we needed to criticize was the replacement of handcrafted work with factory or machine work, often referred to as Operative Deceit.

There are two reasons, both weighty, against this practice; one, that all cast and machine work is bad, as work; the other, that it is dishonest. Of its badness, I shall speak in another place, that being evidently no efficient reason against its use when other cannot be had. Its dishonesty, however, which, to my mind, is of the grossest kind, is, I think, a sufficient reason to determine absolute and unconditional rejection of it.

There are two strong reasons against this practice: first, that all cast and machine work is poor quality; second, that it is dishonest. I will discuss its quality elsewhere, as that's not a strong enough reason to avoid it when no alternatives are available. However, its dishonesty, which I believe is particularly egregious, is a good enough reason for me to completely reject it.

Ornament, as I have often before observed, has two entirely distinct sources of agreeableness: one, that of the ab[Pg 56]stract beauty of its forms, which, for the present, we will suppose to be the same whether they come from the hand or the machine; the other, the sense of human labor and care spent upon it. How great this latter influence we may perhaps judge, by considering that there is not a cluster of weeds growing in any cranny of ruin which has not a beauty in all respects nearly equal, and, in some, immeasurably superior, to that of the most elaborate sculpture of its stones: and that all our interest in the carved work, our sense of its richness, though it is tenfold less rich than the knots of grass beside it; of its delicacy, though it is a thousand fold less delicate; of its admirableness, though a millionfold less admirable; results from our consciousness of its being the work of poor, clumsy, toilsome man. Its true delightfulness depends on our discovering in it the record of thoughts, and intents, and trials, and heart-breakings—of recoveries and joyfulnesses of success: all this can be traced by a practised eye; but, granting it even obscure, it is presumed or understood; and in that is the worth of the thing, just as much as the worth of anything else we call precious. The worth of a diamond is simply the understanding of the time it must take to look for it before it can be cut. It has an intrinsic value besides, which the diamond has not (for a diamond has no more real beauty than a piece of glass); but I do not speak of that at present; I place the two on the same ground; and I suppose that hand-wrought ornament can no more be generally known from machine work, than a diamond can be known from paste; nay, that the latter may deceive, for a moment, the mason's, as the other the jeweller's eye; and that it can be detected only by the closest examination. Yet exactly as a woman of feeling would not wear false jewels, so would a builder of honor disdain false ornaments. The using of them is just as downright and inexcusable a lie. You use that which pretends to a worth which it has not; which pretends to have cost, and to be, what it did not, and is not; it is an imposition, a vulgarity, an impertinence, and a sin. Down with it to the ground, grind it to powder, leave its ragged place upon the wall, rather; you have not paid for it, you[Pg 57] have no business with it, you do not want it. Nobody wants ornaments in this world, but everybody wants integrity. All the fair devices that ever were fancied, are not worth a lie. Leave your walls as bare as a planed board, or build them of baked mud and chopped straw, if need be; but do not rough-cast them with falsehood.

Ornament, as I have pointed out before, has two completely different sources of appeal: one is the abstract beauty of its forms, which we’ll assume is the same whether it comes from a person or a machine; the other is the sense of human labor and care that went into it. We can gauge the significance of this second influence by considering that even a bunch of weeds growing in a crack in a ruin has a beauty that is nearly as great, and in some cases far surpasses, that of the most elaborate sculptures made from its stones. Our fascination with the carved work, our appreciation of its richness, though it’s ten times less rich than the patches of grass beside it; its delicacy, though it’s a thousand times less delicate; and its appeal, though it’s a million times less admirable, all comes from our awareness that it is the product of poor, clumsy, hard-working humans. Its true charm lies in our ability to see it as a record of thoughts, intentions, struggles, and heartaches—of recoveries and joyful successes: all this can be seen by a trained eye; but even if it’s not obvious, it is assumed or understood; and therein lies its value, just like anything else we consider precious. The value of a diamond simply comes from the time it takes to find it before it can be cut. It has an intrinsic value beyond that, which a diamond lacks (because a diamond has no more real beauty than a piece of glass); but I’m not discussing that right now; I’m treating both on equal terms; and I suppose that hand-crafted ornament can’t be recognized any more easily than a diamond can be distinguished from paste; indeed, the latter may trick the mason’s eye, just as the former might deceive the jeweler’s; and it can only be identified by the closest inspection. Yet just as a woman with taste wouldn’t wear fake jewels, a respected builder would reject fake ornaments. Using them is as straightforward and inexcusable a lie. You’re using something that claims to have worth that it doesn’t possess; something that pretends to have cost and to be what it isn’t and won’t be; it’s a fraud, a vulgarity, an impertinence, and a sin. Tear it down, grind it to dust, and leave its ragged place on the wall instead; you haven’t paid for it, you have no right to it, you don’t really want it. Nobody desires ornaments in this world, but everyone wants integrity. All the beautiful designs that have ever been imagined aren’t worth a lie. Leave your walls as bare as a smooth board, or construct them with baked mud and chopped straw if necessary; but don’t cover them with falsehood.

This, then, being our general law, and I hold it for a more imperative one than any other I have asserted; and this kind of dishonesty the meanest, as the least necessary; for ornament is an extravagant and inessential thing; and, therefore, if fallacious, utterly base—this, I say, being our general law, there are, nevertheless, certain exceptions respecting particular substances and their uses.

This is our basic principle, which I consider to be more important than any other I’ve stated; and this type of dishonesty is the lowest, as it is the least essential; because decoration is an unnecessary and excessive thing; and, therefore, if it's misleading, it's completely unworthy—this, I say, is our general principle, yet there are still some exceptions regarding specific substances and their uses.

XX. Thus in the use of brick; since that is known to be originally moulded, there is no reason why it should not be moulded into diverse forms. It will never be supposed to have been cut, and therefore, will cause no deception; it will have only the credit it deserves. In flat countries, far from any quarry of stone, cast brick may be legitimately, and most successfully, used in decoration, and that elaborate, and even refined. The brick mouldings of the Palazzo Pepoli at Bologna, and those which run round the market-place of Vercelli, are among the richest in Italy. So also, tile and porcelain work, of which the former is grotesquely, but successfully, employed in the domestic architecture of France, colored tiles being inserted in the diamond spaces between the crossing timbers; and the latter admirably in Tuscany, in external bas-reliefs, by the Robbia family, in which works, while we cannot but sometimes regret the useless and ill-arranged colors, we would by no means blame the employment of a material which, whatever its defects, excels every other in permanence, and, perhaps, requires even greater skill in its management than marble. For it is not the material, but the absence of the human labor, which makes the thing worthless; and a piece of terra cotta, or of plaster of Paris, which has been wrought by human hand, is worth all the stone in Carrara, cut by machinery. It is, indeed, possible, and even usual, for men to sink into machines themselves, so[Pg 58] that even hand-work has all the characters of mechanism; of the difference between living and dead hand-work I shall speak presently; all that I ask at present is, what it is always in our power to secure—the confession of what we have done, and what we have given; so that when we use stone at all, since all stone is naturally supposed to be carved by hand, we must not carve it by machinery; neither must we use any artificial stone cast into shape, nor any stucco ornaments of the color of stone, or which might in anywise be mistaken for it, as the stucco mouldings in the cortile of the Palazzo Vecchio at Florence, which cast a shame and suspicion over every part of the building. But for ductile and fusible materials, as clay, iron, and bronze, since these will usually be supposed to have been cast or stamped, it is at our pleasure to employ them as we will; remembering that they become precious, or otherwise, just in proportion to the hand-work upon them, or to the clearness of their reception of the hand-work of their mould.

XX. So, when it comes to using brick, since we know it's originally shaped, there's no reason it can't be formed into different designs. It won't be thought of as cut, so there's no chance of deception; it will get only the recognition it deserves. In flat areas, far from any stone quarry, cast brick can be rightly and very effectively used for decoration, and it can be elaborate and even refined. The brick designs of the Palazzo Pepoli in Bologna and those around the marketplace in Vercelli are some of the richest in Italy. Similarly, tile and porcelain work, where the former is used in a somewhat quirky yet successful way in the domestic architecture of France—colorful tiles filling the diamond spaces between crossed timbers—and the latter is beautifully showcased in Tuscany with external bas-reliefs by the Robbia family. While we may sometimes lament the random and poorly arranged colors, we wouldn't criticize the use of a material that, despite its flaws, outlasts all others and perhaps needs even more skill to handle than marble. It’s not the material itself, but the lack of human craftsmanship that renders a piece worthless; a piece of terracotta or plaster of Paris crafted by human hands is worth more than all the machine-cut stone from Carrara. Indeed, it’s possible—often common—for people to become like machines themselves, so that even hand-crafted work takes on mechanical qualities; I’ll discuss the difference between live and mechanical handwork shortly. For now, all I ask is for us to ensure we acknowledge our work and what we contribute. So, whenever we use stone, since it’s generally expected to be hand-carved, we shouldn’t let machinery do the carving. We also shouldn’t use any artificial stone cast into shape or any stucco ornaments that resemble stone or could be mistaken for it, like the stucco moldings in the courtyard of the Palazzo Vecchio in Florence, which bring shame and suspicion to the entire building. But for flexible and meltable materials like clay, iron, and bronze, which will likely be thought of as cast or stamped, we can use them however we choose, keeping in mind that they gain value based on the craftsmanship involved or how clearly they reflect the handiwork of their mold.

But I believe no cause to have been more active in the degradation of our natural feeling for beauty, than the constant use of cast iron ornaments. The common iron work of the middle ages was as simple as it was effective, composed of leafage cut flat out of sheet iron, and twisted at the workman's will. No ornaments, on the contrary, are so cold, clumsy, and vulgar, so essentially incapable of a fine line, or shadow, as those of cast iron; and while, on the score of truth, we can hardly allege anything against them, since they are always distinguishable, at a glance, from wrought and hammered work, and stand only for what they are, yet I feel very strongly that there is no hope of the progress of the arts of any nation which indulges in these vulgar and cheap substitutes for real decoration. Their inefficiency and paltriness I shall endeavor to show more conclusively in another place, enforcing only, at present, the general conclusion that, if even honest or allowable, they are things in which we can never take just pride or pleasure, and must never be employed in any place wherein they might either themselves obtain the credit of being other and better than they are, or be asso[Pg 59]ciated with the downright work to which it would be a disgrace to be found in their company.

But I believe nothing has been more responsible for degrading our natural appreciation of beauty than the constant use of cast iron ornaments. The common ironwork of the Middle Ages was as simple as it was effective, made up of flat-cut leaf designs from sheet iron, shaped at the craftsman's discretion. In contrast, no ornaments are as cold, awkward, and tasteless, so utterly incapable of graceful lines or shadows, as those made of cast iron. While we can hardly criticize them for authenticity since they're easily recognizable as different from wrought and hammered work, and genuinely represent what they are, I strongly feel there's no hope for the advancement of the arts in any nation that relies on these cheap and vulgar substitutes for true decoration. I will discuss their ineffectiveness and worthlessness more thoroughly elsewhere, but for now, I stress the general conclusion that, even if they're honest or acceptable, we can never take genuine pride or pleasure in them. They should never be used in any setting where they might be mistaken for something better or associated with the real craftsmanship that would be disgraced by being in their presence.

Such are, I believe, the three principal kinds of fallacy by which architecture is liable to be corrupted; there are, however, other and more subtle forms of it, against which it is less easy to guard by definite law, than by the watchfulness of a manly and unaffected spirit. For, as it has been above noticed, there are certain kinds of deception which extend to impressions and ideas only; of which some are, indeed, of a noble use, as that above referred to, the arborescent look of lofty Gothic aisles; but of which the most part have so much of legerdemain and trickery about them, that they will lower any style in which they considerably prevail; and they are likely to prevail when once they are admitted, being apt to catch the fancy alike of uninventive architects and feelingless spectators; just as mean and shallow minds are, in other matters, delighted with the sense of over-reaching, or tickled with the conceit of detecting the intention to over-reach; and when subtleties of this kind are accompanied by the display of such dextrous stone-cutting, or architectural sleight of hand, as may become, even by itself, a subject of admiration, it is a great chance if the pursuit of them do not gradually draw us away from all regard and care for the nobler character of the art, and end in its total paralysis or extinction. And against this there is no guarding, but by stern disdain of all display of dexterity and ingenious device, and by putting the whole force of our fancy into the arrangement of masses and forms, caring no more how these masses and forms are wrought out, than a great painter cares which way his pencil strikes. It would be easy to give many instances of the danger of these tricks and vanities; but I shall confine myself to the examination of one which has, as I think, been the cause of the fall of Gothic architecture throughout Europe. I mean the system of intersectional mouldings, which, on account of its great importance, and for the sake of the general reader, I may, perhaps, be pardoned for explaining elementarily.

I believe there are three main types of fallacies that can corrupt architecture; however, there are also other, subtler forms that are harder to protect against with strict rules than with the vigilance of a sincere and straightforward spirit. As mentioned earlier, there are certain kinds of deception that only affect impressions and ideas. Some of these can actually be quite noble, like the tree-like appearance of tall Gothic aisles; however, most are full of trickery that can diminish any style where they dominate. Once accepted, these deceptive tricks tend to be favored by uninspired architects and unfeeling spectators, much like how shallow minds enjoy the thrill of trickery or the idea of catching someone attempting to deceive. When such subtleties come with impressive stone carving or architectural tricks that could stand alone as admiration-worthy, it’s highly likely that pursuing them will gradually distract us from valuing the true essence of the art, leading to its eventual decline or death. The only way to guard against this is to strongly reject all displays of cleverness and intricate design, focusing instead on the arrangement of masses and forms, caring no more about how they are created than a great painter worries about the direction of their brushstrokes. It would be easy to provide many examples of the risks posed by these tricks and vanities, but I will limit myself to discussing one that I believe has led to the decline of Gothic architecture across Europe. I’m referring to the system of intersecting moldings, which, because of its significance and for the benefit of the general reader, I hope can be explained in a simple way.

XXI. I must, in the first place, however, refer to Professor[Pg 60] Willis's account of the origin of tracery, given in the sixth chapter of his Architecture of the Middle Ages; since the publication of which I have been not a little amazed to hear of any attempts made to resuscitate the inexcusably absurd theory of its derivation from imitated vegetable form—inexcusably, I say, because the smallest acquaintance with early Gothic architecture would have informed the supporters of that theory of the simple fact, that, exactly in proportion to the antiquity of the work, the imitation of such organic forms is less, and in the earliest examples does not exist at all. There cannot be the shadow of a question, in the mind of a person familiarised with any single series of consecutive examples, that tracery arose from the gradual enlargement of the penetrations of the shield of stone which, usually supported by a central pillar, occupied the head of early windows. Professor Willis, perhaps, confines his observations somewhat too absolutely to the double sub-arch. I have given, in Plate VII. fig. 2, an interesting case of rude penetration of a high and simply trefoiled shield, from the church of the Eremitani at Padua. But the more frequent and typical form is that of the double sub-arch, decorated with various piercings of the space between it and the superior arch; with a simple trefoil under a round arch, in the Abbaye aux Hommes, Caen9 (Plate III. fig. 1); with a very beautifully proportioned quatrefoil, in the triforium of Eu, and that of the choir of Lisieux; with quatrefoils, sixfoils, and septfoils, in the transept towers of Rouen (Plate III. fig. 2); with a trefoil awkwardly, and very small quatrefoil above, at Coutances, (Plate III. fig. 3); then, with multiplications of the same figures, pointed or round, giving very clumsy shapes of the intermediate stone (fig. 4, from one of the nave chapels of Rouen, fig. 5, from one of the nave chapels of Bayeaux), and finally, by thinning out the stony ribs, reaching conditions like that of the glorious typical form of the clerestory of the apse of Beauvais (fig. 6).

XXI. First of all, I need to mention Professor[Pg 60] Willis's explanation of the origin of tracery, which he presented in the sixth chapter of his Architecture of the Middle Ages. Since its publication, I've been quite astonished to hear about any attempts to revive the utterly ridiculous theory that tracery comes from imitating plant forms. It's ridiculous, I say, because anyone with even a basic understanding of early Gothic architecture would know that the older the work, the less it resembles organic forms, and in the earliest examples, there's no resemblance at all. There's no doubt in the mind of anyone familiar with a series of consecutive examples that tracery developed from the gradual increase of openings in the stone shield that typically rested on a central pillar at the top of early windows. Professor Willis might focus a bit too strictly on the double sub-arch. I’ve included in Plate VII. fig. 2 an interesting example of a rough opening in a high and simply trefoiled shield from the Eremitani church in Padua. However, the more common and typical form is that of the double sub-arch, adorned with various openings in the space between it and the upper arch; displaying a simple trefoil under a round arch at the Abbaye aux Hommes in Caen (Plate III. fig. 1); a beautifully proportioned quatrefoil in the triforium of Eu and in the choir of Lisieux; quatrefoils, sixfoils, and septfoils in the transept towers of Rouen (Plate III. fig. 2); a trefoil awkwardly combined with a very small quatrefoil above at Coutances (Plate III. fig. 3); and finally, with multiple copies of the same shapes, either pointed or round, creating very clumsy configurations of the stone in between (fig. 4, from one of the nave chapels of Rouen, fig. 5, from one of the nave chapels of Bayeux). Ultimately, by thinning out the stone ribs, we arrive at forms similar to the magnificent typical design of the clerestory of the apse of Beauvais (fig. 6).

PLATE III. PLATE III.—(Page 60—Vol. V.)
Decorative Patterns from Caen, Bayeux, Rouen, and Beauvais.

XXII. Now, it will be noticed that, during the whole of this process, the attention is kept fixed on the forms of the penetrations, that is to say, of the lights as seen from the interior, not of the intermediate stone. All the grace of the [Pg 61] window is in the outline of its light; and I have drawn all these traceries as seen from within, in order to show the effect of the light thus treated, at first in far off and separate stars, and then gradually enlarging, approaching, until they come and stand over us, as it were, filling the whole space with their effulgence. And it is in this pause of the star, that we have the great, pure, and perfect form of French Gothic; it was at the instant when the rudeness of the intermediate space had been finally conquered, when the light had expanded to its fullest, and yet had not lost its radiant unity, principality, and visible first causing of the whole, that we have the most exquisite feeling and most faultless judgments in the management alike of the tracery and decorations. I have given, in Plate X., an exquisite example of it, from a panel decoration of the buttresses of the north door of Rouen; and in order that the reader may understand what truly fine Gothic work is, and how nobly it unites fantasy and law, as well as for our immediate purpose, it will be well that he should examine its sections and mouldings in detail (they are described in the fourth Chapter, § xxvii.), and that the more carefully, because this design belongs to a period in which the most important change took place in the spirit of Gothic architecture, which, perhaps, ever resulted from the natural progress of any art. That tracery marks a pause between the laying aside of one great ruling principle, and the taking up of another; a pause as marked, as clear, as conspicuous to the distant view of after times, as to the distant glance of the traveller is the culminating ridge of the mountain chain over which he has passed. It was the great watershed of Gothic art. Before it, all had been ascent; after it, all was decline; both, indeed, by winding paths and varied slopes; both interrupted, like the gradual rise and fall of the passes of the Alps, by great mountain outliers, isolated or branching from the central chain, and by retrograde or parallel directions of the valleys of access. But the track of the human mind is traceable up to that glorious ridge, in a continuous line, and thence downwards. Like a silver zone[Pg 62]

XXII. Now, you’ll notice that throughout this entire process, the focus is on the shapes of the openings, specifically the light as seen from inside, not the stone in between. All the beauty of the [Pg 61] window lies in the outline of its light; I’ve illustrated all these traceries from within to show how the light appears at first as distant, separate points, then gradually growing larger, getting closer, until it seems to hover above us, filling the entire space with its brightness. It’s in this moment of the light that we see the great, pure, and perfect form of French Gothic; at the instant when the roughness of the intermediate space was finally overcome, when the light had expanded to its fullest, yet still retained its radiant unity and essence. That’s when we experience the most exquisite feelings and flawless judgments in the design of both the tracery and the decorations. In Plate X., I’ve provided a beautiful example from a decorative panel of the buttresses of the north door of Rouen; and to help the reader grasp what truly fine Gothic work is, and how magnificently it merges creativity with structure, as well as for our current purpose, it’s important for them to examine its sections and moldings in detail (they’re described in the fourth Chapter, § xxvii.). This is particularly crucial because this design comes from a time when the most significant change happened in the spirit of Gothic architecture, a change that may have been the result of the natural evolution of any art form. That tracery signifies a pause between letting go of one major guiding principle and adopting another; a pause that is as distinct, clear, and noticeable to the distant observer of future generations as the highest point of a mountain range is to someone traveling across it. It was the great turning point of Gothic art. Before it, everything was ascending; after it, everything was in decline; both paths winding and varied, interrupted like the gradual rise and fall of the Alpine passes, by significant mountain outliers, either isolated or branching from the central range, and by retrograde or parallel paths of the valleys leading in. However, the journey of the human mind can be traced to that glorious ridge in a continuous line, and from there downwards. Like a silver zone[Pg 62]

"Flung about carelessly, it shines afar,
Catching the eye in many a broken link,
In many a turn and traverse, as it glides.
And oft above, and oft below, appears—
* * * * to him who journeys up
As though it were another."

"Thrown around carelessly, it shines far away,
Catching the eye in many a broken connection,
In many twists and turns, as it glides.
And often above, and often below, it shows—
* * * * to the one who travels up
As if it were something else."

And at that point, and that instant, reaching the place that was nearest heaven, the builders looked back, for the last time, to the way by which they had come, and the scenes through which their early course had passed. They turned away from them and their morning light, and descended towards a new horizon, for a time in the warmth of western sun, but plunging with every forward step into more cold and melancholy shade.

And at that moment, as they reached the spot closest to heaven, the builders looked back one last time at the path they had traveled and the scenes they had experienced along the way. They turned away from those memories and the morning light, heading toward a new horizon, basking for a while in the warmth of the western sun, but with each step forward, they sank deeper into a cold and gloomy shadow.

XXIII. The change of which I speak, is inexpressible in few words, but one more important, more radically influential, could not be. It was the substitution of the line for the mass, as the element of decoration.

XXIII. The change I'm talking about is hard to express in just a few words, but it’s incredibly significant and fundamentally impactful. It was the replacement of the line for the mass as the core element of decoration.

We have seen the mode in which the openings or penetration of the window expanded, until what were, at first, awkward forms of intermediate stone, became delicate lines of tracery: and I have been careful in pointing out the peculiar attention bestowed on the proportion and decoration of the mouldings of the window at Rouen, in Plate X., as compared with earlier mouldings, because that beauty and care are singularly significant. They mark that the traceries had caught the eye of the architect. Up to that time, up to the very last instant in which the reduction and thinning of the intervening stone was consummated, his eye had been on the openings only, on the stars of light. He did not care about the stone, a rude border of moulding was all he needed, it was the penetrating shape which he was watching. But when that shape had received its last possible expansion, and when the stone-work became an arrangement of graceful and parallel lines, that arrangement, like some form in a picture, unseen and accidentally developed, struck suddenly, inevitably, on the sight. It had literally not been seen before. It flashed out in an instant as an independent form. It became a feature of the[Pg 63] work. The architect took it under his care, thought over it, and distributed its members as we see.

We have observed how the openings or penetrations of the window grew, evolving from what were initially awkward shapes of intermediate stone into elegant lines of tracery. I've been careful to highlight the unique attention given to the proportions and decoration of the window moldings at Rouen, in Plate X., compared to earlier moldings, because that beauty and detail are particularly meaningful. They indicate that the tracery had caught the architect's eye. Until that moment, right up until the final adjustment of the intervening stone was completed, his focus had been solely on the openings, on the rays of light. He didn’t care about the stone; a rough border of molding was all he needed, as he was preoccupied with the penetrating shape. But once that shape had reached its maximum expansion and the stonework became a composition of graceful and parallel lines, that arrangement, like an unseen form in a picture that had developed unexpectedly, suddenly and inevitably captured attention. It had literally gone unnoticed before. It emerged in an instant as an independent form. It became a distinctive feature of the[Pg 63]work. The architect took it into account, contemplated it, and organized its elements as we see.

Now, the great pause was at the moment when the space and the dividing stone-work were both equally considered. It did not last fifty years. The forms of the tracery were seized with a childish delight in the novel source of beauty; and the intervening space was cast aside, as an element of decoration, for ever. I have confined myself, in following this change, to the window, as the feature in which it is clearest. But the transition is the same in every member of architecture; and its importance can hardly be understood, unless we take the pains to trace it in the universality, of which illustrations, irrelevant to our present purpose, will be found in the third Chapter. I pursue here the question of truth, relating to the treatment of the mouldings.

Now, the great pause happened when both the space and the dividing stonework were equally considered. It didn’t last fifty years. The shapes of the tracery were embraced with a childlike joy in the new source of beauty, and the space in between was dismissed as a decorative element forever. I’ve focused on the window in tracing this change since it’s the clearest example. But the transition is the same in every part of architecture, and its significance can hardly be grasped unless we take the time to see it in the broader context, with illustrations irrelevant to our current focus found in Chapter Three. Here, I continue with the question of truth related to the way the moldings are treated.

XXIV. The reader will observe that, up to the last expansion of the penetrations, the stone-work was necessarily considered, as it actually is, stiff, and unyielding. It was so, also, during the pause of which I have spoken, when the forms of the tracery were still severe and pure; delicate indeed, but perfectly firm.

XXIV. The reader will notice that, up until the last expansion of the penetrations, the stonework was understandably viewed, as it actually is, stiff, and unyielding. It was the same during the pause I mentioned, when the shapes of the tracery remained severe and pure; delicate, for sure, but completely firm.

At the close of the period of pause, the first sign of serious change was like a low breeze, passing through the emaciated tracery, and making it tremble. It began to undulate like the threads of a cobweb lifted by the wind. It lost its essence as a structure of stone. Reduced to the slenderness of threads, it began to be considered as possessing also their flexibility. The architect was pleased with this his new fancy, and set himself to carry it out; and in a little time, the bars of tracery were caused to appear to the eye as if they had been woven together like a net. This was a change which sacrificed a great principle of truth; it sacrificed the expression of the qualities of the material; and, however delightful its results in their first developments, it was ultimately ruinous.

At the end of the pause, the first sign of serious change felt like a gentle breeze moving through the thin framework, making it shudder. It started to sway like the strands of a spiderweb caught in the wind. It lost its solid, stone-like essence. Reduced to the thinness of threads, it began to be seen as having their flexibility as well. The architect was excited about this new idea and set out to bring it to life; soon, the bars of the framework appeared to the eye as if they were woven together like a net. This change sacrificed a key principle of truth; it disregarded the qualities of the material itself, and while its initial results were delightful, it ultimately led to disaster.

For, observe the difference between the supposition of ductility, and that of elastic structure noticed above in the resemblance to tree form. That resemblance was not sought, but necessary; it resulted from the natural conditions of strength[Pg 64] in the pier or trunk, and slenderness in the ribs or branches, while many of the other suggested conditions of resemblance were perfectly true. A tree branch, though in a certain sense flexible, is not ductile; it is as firm in its own form as the rib of stone; both of them will yield up to certain limits, both of them breaking when those limits are exceeded; while the tree trunk will bend no more than the stone pillar. But when the tracery is assumed to be as yielding as a silken cord; when the whole fragility, elasticity, and weight of the material are to the eye, if not in terms, denied; when all the art of the architect is applied to disprove the first conditions of his working, and the first attributes of his materials; this is a deliberate treachery, only redeemed from the charge of direct falsehood by the visibility of the stone surface, and degrading all the traceries it affects exactly in the degree of its presence.

Look at the difference between the idea of ductility and that of elastic structure mentioned earlier in relation to the tree-like form. That similarity wasn't intentional, but rather a necessity; it came from the natural strength found in the pier or trunk and the delicacy in the ribs or branches, while many other suggested similarities were completely valid. A tree branch, while somewhat flexible, is not ductile; it holds its shape as firmly as a stone rib does. Both can bend to a certain extent, but they will break if pushed beyond those limits; the tree trunk won't bend any more than the stone pillar will. However, when the design is assumed to be as flexible as a silk cord; when the material's fragility, elasticity, and weight are visually denied, if not in terms; when all the skill of the architect is used to contradict the fundamental aspects of his work and the essential properties of his materials; this is a conscious betrayal, only saved from being outright falsehood by the visible stone surface, and it diminishes all the designs it influences directly in proportion to its presence.

XXV. But the declining and morbid taste of the later architects, was not satisfied with thus much deception. They were delighted with the subtle charm they had created, and thought only of increasing its power. The next step was to consider and represent the tracery, as not only ductile, but penetrable; and when two mouldings met each other, to manage their intersection, so that one should appear to pass through the other, retaining its independence; or when two ran parallel to each other, to represent the one as partly contained within the other, and partly apparent above it. This form of falsity was that which crushed the art. The flexible traceries were often beautiful, though they were ignoble; but the penetrated traceries, rendered, as they finally were, merely the means of exhibiting the dexterity of the stone-cutter, annihilated both the beauty and dignity of the Gothic types. A system so momentous in its consequences deserves some detailed examination.

XXV. But the declining and unhealthy taste of later architects was not satisfied with just a little deception. They were thrilled with the subtle charm they had created and only thought about increasing its impact. The next step was to think about and depict the tracery as not only flexible but also penetrable; when two moldings met, they tried to make it look like one was passing through the other while still being independent. And when two ran parallel to each other, they presented one as partly inside the other and partly visible above it. This kind of dishonesty was what crushed the art. The flexible tracery was often beautiful, even though it lacked nobility; but the penetrated tracery, rendered as it ultimately was, simply showcased the skill of the stonecutter, destroying both the beauty and dignity of the Gothic styles. A system with such significant consequences deserves a closer look.

XXVI. In the drawing of the shafts of the door at Lisieux, under the spandril, in Plate VII., the reader will see the mode of managing the intersection of similar mouldings, which was universal in the great periods. They melted into each other, and became one at the point of crossing, or of contact; and even the suggestion of so sharp intersection as this of Lisieux[Pg 65] is usually avoided (this design being, of course, only a pointed form of the earlier Norman arcade, in which the arches are interlaced, and lie each over the preceding, and under the following, one, as in Anselm's tower at Canterbury), since, in the plurality of designs, when mouldings meet each other, they coincide through some considerable portion of their curves, meeting by contact, rather than by intersection; and at the point of coincidence the section of each separate moulding becomes common to the two thus melted into each other. Thus, in the junction of the circles of the window of the Palazzo Foscari, Plate VIII., given accurately in fig. 8, Plate IV., the section across the line s, is exactly the same as that across any break of the separated moulding above, as s. It sometimes, however, happens, that two different mouldings meet each other. This was seldom permitted in the great periods, and, when it took place, was most awkwardly managed. Fig. 1, Plate IV. gives the junction of the mouldings of the gable and vertical, in the window of the spire of Salisbury. That of the gable is composed of a single, and that of the vertical of a double cavetto, decorated with ball-flowers; and the larger single moulding swallows up one of the double ones, and pushes forward among the smaller balls with the most blundering and clumsy simplicity. In comparing the sections it is to be observed that, in the upper one, the line a b represents an actual vertical in the plane of the window; while, in the lower one, the line c d represents the horizontal, in the plane of the window, indicated by the perspective line d e.

XXVI. In the drawing of the door shafts at Lisieux, under the spandril in Plate VII, you can see how similar mouldings intersect, which was a common practice in the great periods. They blend into each other and become one at the point where they cross or touch; and even the sharp intersection seen in Lisieux[Pg 65] is usually avoided (this design is, of course, just a pointed version of the earlier Norman arcade, where the arches are intertwined, with each arch resting over the one before and under the next, like in Anselm's tower at Canterbury). In various designs, when mouldings meet, they align across a significant portion of their curves and connect through contact rather than intersection; at the point where they connect, the profile of each moulding becomes shared between the two as they blend into each other. For example, in the junction of the circles in the window of the Palazzo Foscari, shown accurately in fig. 8, Plate IV, the profile across line s is exactly the same as that across any break of the separated moulding above, as s. Sometimes, though, two different mouldings do come together. This was rarely allowed in the great periods, and when it happened, it was often handled awkwardly. Fig. 1, Plate IV shows the connection of the gable and vertical mouldings in the window of the spire of Salisbury. The gable moulding is a single piece, while the vertical one has a double cavetto, decorated with ball-flowers; the larger single moulding envelops one of the double ones and awkwardly pushes forward among the smaller balls in a rather clumsy way. When comparing the profiles, it's important to note that in the upper one, line a b shows an actual vertical in the plane of the window, while in the lower one, line c d represents the horizontal in the plane of the window as indicated by the perspective line d e.

XXVII. The very awkwardness with which such occurrences of difficulty are met by the earlier builder, marks his dislike of the system, and unwillingness to attract the eye to such arrangements. There is another very clumsy one, in the junction of the upper and sub-arches of the triforium of Salisbury; but it is kept in the shade, and all the prominent junctions are of mouldings like each other, and managed with perfect simplicity. But so soon as the attention of the builders became, as we have just seen, fixed upon the lines of mouldings instead of the enclosed spaces, those lines began to preserve an independent existence wherever they met; and different mould[Pg 66]ings were studiously associated, in order to obtain variety of intersectional line. We must, however, do the late builders the justice to note that, in one case, the habit grew out of a feeling of proportion, more refined than that of earlier workmen. It shows itself first in the bases of divided pillars, or arch mouldings, whose smaller shafts had originally bases formed by the continued base of the central, or other larger, columns with which they were grouped; but it being felt, when the eye of the architect became fastidious, that the dimension of moulding which was right for the base of a large shaft, was wrong for that of a small one, each shaft had an independent base; at first, those of the smaller died simply down on that of the larger; but when the vertical sections of both became complicated, the bases of the smaller shafts were considered to exist within those of the larger, and the places of their emergence, on this supposition, were calculated with the utmost nicety, and cut with singular precision; so that an elaborate late base of a divided column, as, for instance, of those in the nave of Abbeville, looks exactly as if its smaller shafts had all been finished to the ground first, each with its complete and intricate base, and then the comprehending base of the central pier had been moulded over them in clay, leaving their points and angles sticking out here and there, like the edges of sharp crystals out of a nodule of earth. The exhibition of technical dexterity in work of this kind is often marvellous, the strangest possible shapes of sections being calculated to a hair's-breadth, and the occurrence of the under and emergent forms being rendered, even in places where they are so slight that they can hardly be detected but by the touch. It is impossible to render a very elaborate example of this kind intelligible, without some fifty measured sections; but fig. 6, Plate IV. is a very interesting and simple one, from the west gate of Rouen. It is part of the base of one of the narrow piers between its principal niches. The square column k, having a base with the profile p r, is supposed to contain within itself another similar one, set diagonally, and lifted so far above the inclosing one, as that the recessed part of its profile p r shall fall behind the projecting part of the outer one. The angle of its upper portion exactly meets the plane of the side of the upper inclosing shaft 4, and would, therefore, not be seen, unless two vertical cuts were made to exhibit it, which form two dark lines the whole way up the shaft. Two small pilasters are run, like fastening stitches, through the junction on the front of the shafts. The sections k n taken respectively at the levels k, n, will explain the hypothetical construction of the whole. Fig. 7 is a base, or joint rather (for passages of this form occur again and again, on the shafts of flamboyant work), of one of the smallest piers of the pedestals which support the lost statues of the porch; its section below would be the same as n, and its construction, after what has been said of the other base, will be at once perceived.

XXVII. The awkward way that earlier builders dealt with difficult situations shows their dislike for the system and their reluctance to draw attention to these designs. There's another awkward example in the junction of the upper and sub-arches of the triforium at Salisbury, but it stays in the shadows, while all the prominent junctions use similar moldings and are designed with complete simplicity. However, once the builders started focusing on the lines of moldings instead of the enclosed spaces, those lines began to stand out on their own whenever they met; different moldings were carefully combined to create a variety of intersection lines. It's important to acknowledge that the later builders had a sense of proportion that was more refined than that of earlier ones. This is first seen in the bases of divided pillars or arch moldings, where the smaller shafts originally shared a base with the larger columns they were grouped with. When architects became more discerning, they realized that the size of the molding that was right for a large shaft didn’t work for a small one, so each shaft got its own independent base. At first, the smaller bases simply tapered down into the larger ones, but as the vertical sections of both became more complex, the bases of the smaller shafts were considered to sit within the bases of the larger ones. Their emerging points were calculated very precisely, leading to an intricate design. For example, in the nave of Abbeville, a detailed base of a divided column looks as if each smaller shaft was crafted completely to the ground first, each with its own complex base, before the larger central base was molded over them, leaving parts sticking out like sharp crystals from a clump of earth. The technical skill displayed in this kind of work is often astonishing, with incredibly intricate shapes being measured to the nearest detail, and the under and emerging forms being rendered even in places so slight they can only be felt. It’s hard to explain a very complicated example without around fifty measured sections, but fig. 6, Plate IV. is a very interesting and simple one from the west gate of Rouen. It shows part of the base of one of the narrow piers between the main niches. The square column k, which has a base shaped like p r, is thought to contain another similar column inside it, set diagonally and raised so far that the recessed part of its profile p r is behind the projecting part of the outer one. The angle of its upper section meets the plane of the upper enclosing shaft 4 exactly, so it wouldn't be visible unless two vertical cuts were made to reveal it, creating two dark lines up the shaft. Two small pilasters run like stitching through the junction on the front of the shafts. The sections k n taken at levels k, n will clarify the hypothetical construction of the entire design. Fig. 7 is a base, or more accurately a joint (since this type occurs repeatedly on flamboyant work shafts), from one of the smallest piers of the pedestals supporting the lost statues of the porch; its section below would be the same as n, and its construction, as described for the other base, will be immediately understood.

PLATE IV. PLATE IV.—(Page 66—Vol. V.)
Intersectional Moldings.

XXVIII. There was, however, in this kind of involution, much to be admired as well as reprehended, the proportions of quantities were always as beautiful as they were intricate; and, though the lines of intersection were harsh, they were exquisitely opposed to the flower-work of the interposing mouldings. But the fancy did not stop here; it rose from the bases into the arches; and there, not finding room enough for its exhibition, it withdrew the capitals from the heads even of cylindrical shafts, (we cannot but admire, while we regret, the boldness of the men who could defy the authority and custom of all the nations of the earth for a space of some three thousand years,) in order that the arch mouldings might appear to emerge from the pillar, as at its base they had been lost in it, and not to terminate on the abacus of the capital; then they ran the mouldings across and through each other, at the point of the arch; and finally, not finding their natural directions enough to furnish as many occasions of intersection as they wished, bent them hither and thither, and cut off their ends short, when they had passed the point of intersection. Fig. 2, Plate IV. is part of a flying buttress from the apse of St. Gervais at Falaise, in which the moulding whose section is rudely given above at f, (taken vertically through the point f,) is carried thrice through itself, in the cross-bar and two arches; and the flat fillet is cut off sharp at the end of the cross-bar, for the mere pleasure of the truncation. Fig. 3 is[Pg 68] half of the head of a door in the Stadthaus of Sursee, in which the shaded part of the section of the joint g g, is that of the arch-moulding, which is three times reduplicated, and six times intersected by itself, the ends being cut off when they become unmanageable. This style is, indeed, earlier exaggerated in Switzerland and Germany, owing to the imitation in stone of the dovetailing of wood, particularly of the intersecting of beams at the angles of châlets; but it only furnishes the more plain instance of the danger of the fallacious system which, from the beginning, repressed the German, and, in the end, ruined the French Gothic. It would be too painful a task to follow further the caricatures of form, and eccentricities of treatment, which grow out of this singular abuse—the flattened arch, the shrunken pillar, the lifeless ornament, the liny moulding, the distorted and extravagant foliation, until the time came when, over these wrecks and remnants, deprived of all unity and principle, rose the foul torrent of the renaissance, and swept them all away. So fell the great dynasty of mediæval architecture. It was because it had lost its own strength, and disobeyed its own laws—because its order, and consistency, and organization, had been broken through—that it could oppose no resistance to the rush of overwhelming innovation. And this, observe, all because it had sacrificed a single truth. From that one surrender of its integrity, from that one endeavor to assume the semblance of what it was not, arose the multitudinous forms of disease and decrepitude, which rotted away the pillars of its supremacy. It was not because its time was come; it was not because it was scorned by the classical Romanist, or dreaded by the faithful Protestant. That scorn and that fear it might have survived, and lived; it would have stood forth in stern comparison with the enervated sensuality of the renaissance; it would have risen in renewed and purified honor, and with a new soul, from the ashes into which it sank, giving up its glory, as it had received it, for the honor of God—but its own truth was gone, and it sank forever. There was no wisdom nor strength left in it, to raise it from the dust; and the error of zeal, and the softness of luxury smote it down and dissolved it away.[Pg 69] It is good for us to remember this, as we tread upon the bare ground of its foundations, and stumble over its scattered stones. Those rent skeletons of pierced wall, through which our sea-winds moan and murmur, strewing them joint by joint, and bone by bone, along the bleak promontories on which the Pharos lights came once from houses of prayer—those grey arches and quiet isles under which the sheep of our valleys feed and rest on the turf that has buried their altars—those shapeless heaps, that are not of the Earth, which lift our fields into strange and sudden banks of flowers, and stay our mountain streams with stones that are not their own, have other thoughts to ask from us than those of mourning for the rage that despoiled, or the fear that forsook them. It was not the robber, not the fanatic, not the blasphemer, who sealed the destruction that they had wrought; the war, the wrath, the terror, might have worked their worst, and the strong walls would have risen, and the slight pillars would have started again, from under the hand of the destroyer. But they could not rise out of the ruins of their own violated truth.

XXVIII. However, within this kind of complexity, there was much to admire as well as criticize; the proportions of elements were always as beautiful as they were intricate. While the points of intersection were harsh, they contrasted exquisitely with the decorative details of the surrounding moldings. But the creativity didn’t stop there; it extended from the bases into the arches. Not finding enough space for its expression, it even removed the capitals from the tops of cylindrical shafts. (We can’t help but admire, even as we lament, the audacity of those who could disregard the authority and traditions of all nations for around three thousand years.) This allowed the arch moldings to seem as if they emerged from the pillar, as they had originally been embedded at its base without ending on the capital's abacus. Then they intertwined the moldings across and through each other at the arch's apex; finally, not satisfied with their natural directions to create enough intersections, they bent them in various ways and trimmed their ends short after passing the intersection point. Fig. 2, Plate IV, shows part of a flying buttress from the apse of St. Gervais at Falaise, where the section of the molding, roughly depicted above at f, (taken vertically through the point f), is carried through itself three times in the cross-bar and two arches; the flat fillet is sharply cut off at the end of the cross-bar, simply for the pleasure of the truncation. Fig. 3 is[Pg 68] half of the head of a door in the Stadthaus of Sursee, where the shaded part of the section of the joint g g is that of the arch-molding, which is repeated three times and intersects itself six times, with ends cut off when they become unmanageable. This style was indeed exaggerated earlier in Switzerland and Germany due to the stone imitation of wooden dovetailing, especially at the intersecting beams of châlets. However, it provides a clearer example of the dangers of the misleading system that, from the start, stifled the Germans and eventually ruined the French Gothic. It would be too painful to trace further the distortions of form and eccentricities that arose from this peculiar misuse—the flattened arch, the shrunken pillar, the lifeless ornament, the thin moldings, and the twisted and extravagant foliage—until the time came when, amidst this wreckage and chaos, stripped of all unity and principle, the overwhelming wave of the Renaissance rose and swept everything away. Thus fell the great dynasty of medieval architecture. It collapsed because it had lost its own strength and disobeyed its own principles—because its order, consistency, and organization had been compromised—it couldn't withstand the rush of overwhelming innovation. And all this happened because it sacrificed a single truth. From that one compromise of its integrity, from that one attempt to mimic what it was not, came countless forms of decay and weakness that eroded the pillars of its supremacy. It was not because its time had come; it was not because it was scorned by the classical Romanists or feared by the faithful Protestants. That scorn and fear might have been endured, and it could have thrived; it would have stood starkly against the feeble sensuality of the Renaissance; it could have risen again, renewed and purified, with a new spirit from the ashes into which it fell, relinquishing its glory just as it had received it, for the honor of God—but its own truth was lost, and it sank forever. There was no wisdom or strength left to lift it from the dust; and the error of zeal and the comfort of luxury brought it down and dissolved it away.[Pg 69] It’s important for us to remember this as we walk on the bare ground of its foundations and trip over its scattered stones. Those broken remains of the pierced walls, through which the winds of the sea howl and whisper, scattering them piece by piece along the bleak cliffs where the Pharos once shone from houses of worship—those grey arches and quiet islands under which the sheep from our valleys graze and rest on the turf that has buried their altars—those shapeless piles, not of the Earth, that raise our fields into strange and sudden banks of flowers, and halt our mountain streams with stones that aren't theirs, ask of us more than just mourning for the destruction or the abandonment they faced. It wasn’t the thief, the fanatic, or the blasphemer who sealed their fate; the war, the fury, the fear could have done their worst, and the sturdy walls might have risen again, and the delicate pillars could have reemerged from the hands of the destroyer. But they could not rise from the debris of their own betrayed truth.


CHAPTER III.

THE LAMP OF POWER.

I. In recalling the impressions we have received from the works of man, after a lapse of time long enough to involve in obscurity all but the most vivid, it often happens that we find a strange pre-eminence and durability in many upon whose strength we had little calculated, and that points of character which had escaped the detection of the judgment, become developed under the waste of memory; as veins of harder rock, whose places could not at first have been discovered by the eye, are left salient under the action of frosts and streams. The traveller who desires to correct the errors of his judgment, necessitated by inequalities of temper, infelicities of circumstance, and accidents of association, has no other resource than to wait for the calm verdict of interposing years; and to watch for the new arrangements of eminence and shape[Pg 70] in the images which remain latest in his memory; as in the ebbing of a mountain lake, he would watch the varying outlines of its successive shore, and trace, in the form of its departing waters, the true direction of the forces which had cleft, or the currents which had excavated, the deepest recesses of its primal bed.

I. When we think back on the impressions we've gotten from human creations, after enough time has passed to obscure all but the most striking ones, we often find that many works we didn’t expect to stand out actually have a surprising prominence and endurance. Traits that our judgment may have overlooked become more apparent as memory fades, like veins of harder rock that the eye couldn't detect at first but stand out after frost and streams wear away the surrounding material. A traveler looking to correct mistakes in judgment caused by mood swings, unfortunate circumstances, and random connections has no choice but to wait for the calm judgment of passing years and observe the new formations of importance and shape in the memories that linger; just as they would watch the changing outlines of the shore of a receding mountain lake and trace the true paths of the forces that shaped or carved out the deepest parts of its original bed as the water retreats.

In thus reverting to the memories of those works of architecture by which we have been most pleasurably impressed, it will generally happen that they fall into two broad classes: the one characterized by an exceeding preciousness and delicacy, to which we recur with a sense of affectionate admiration; and the other by a severe, and, in many cases, mysterious, majesty, which we remember with an undiminished awe, like that felt at the presence and operation of some great Spiritual Power. From about these two groups, more or less harmonised by intermediate examples, but always distinctively marked by features of beauty or of power, there will be swept away, in multitudes, the memories of buildings, perhaps, in their first address to our minds, of no inferior pretension, but owing their impressiveness to characters of less enduring nobility—to value of material, accumulation of ornament, or ingenuity of mechanical construction. Especial interest may, indeed, have been awakened by such circumstances, and the memory may have been, consequently, rendered tenacious of particular parts or effects of the structure; but it will recall even these only by an active effort, and then without emotion; while in passive moments, and with thrilling influence, the image of purer beauty, and of more spiritual power, will return in a fair and solemn company; and while the pride of many a stately palace, and the wealth of many a jewelled shrine, perish from our thoughts in a dust of gold, there will rise, through their dimness, the white image of some secluded marble chapel, by river or forest side, with the fretted flower-work shrinking under its arches, as if under vaults of late-fallen snow; or the vast weariness of some shadowy wall whose separate stones are like mountain foundations, and yet numberless.

When we think back on the memories of architectural works that have impressed us the most, we generally categorize them into two main types: one type is characterized by an exquisite tenderness and delicate beauty, which we remember with fond admiration; the other type is marked by a strong and often mysterious majesty, evoking a sense of awe, similar to what we experience in the presence of a great Spiritual Power. Within these two groups, there are other examples that are somewhat in between, but always defined by qualities of beauty or power. A lot of memories of buildings that might have initially impressed us, perhaps even with significant ambition, will fade away because their impact relies on aspects that are less enduring—like the quality of materials, the richness of decoration, or clever engineering. While these factors may have sparked interest and kept certain details or effects of the structure alive in our memory, we only recall these through conscious effort and without much feeling. In quieter moments, however, we find ourselves recalling images of pure beauty and a deeper spiritual power in a serene and solemn way. While the grandeur of many impressive palaces and the luxury of ornate shrines might fade into a blur of gold, the clear image of some quiet marble chapel by a river or in a forest will emerge through the haze, with its delicate floral designs appearing to shrink beneath its arches like late-fallen snow; or we may visualize the vastness of a shadowy wall made up of stones that resemble mountain foundations, yet are countless in number.

II. Now, the difference between these two orders of build[Pg 71]-ing is not merely that which there is in nature between things beautiful and sublime. It is, also, the difference between what is derivative and original in man's work; for whatever is in architecture fair or beautiful, is imitated from natural forms; and what is not so derived, but depends for its dignity upon arrangement and government received from human mind, becomes the expression of the power of that mind, and receives a sublimity high in proportion to the power expressed. All building, therefore, shows man either as gathering or governing: and the secrets of his success are his knowing what to gather, and how to rule. These are the two great intellectual Lamps of Architecture; the one consisting in a just and humble veneration for the works of God upon the earth, and the other in an understanding of the dominion over those works which has been vested in man.

II. The difference between these two types of building[Pg 71] isn't just the natural distinction between things that are beautiful and those that are sublime. It's also the difference between what's derived and what's original in human creations. Whatever is attractive or beautiful in architecture is copied from natural forms, while what isn’t derived from nature but gains its dignity from arrangement and the organization shaped by human intellect reflects the power of that intellect and achieves a level of sublimity that corresponds to that power. All buildings, therefore, represent humanity either as gatherers or as rulers: the key to their success lies in knowing what to gather and how to manage. These are the two main guiding principles of Architecture: one is a right and humble respect for God's creations on earth, and the other is an understanding of the authority humans have over those creations.

III. Besides this expression of living authority and power, there is, however, a sympathy in the forms of noble building, with what is most sublime in natural things; and it is the governing Power directed by this sympathy, whose operation I shall at present endeavor to trace, abandoning all inquiry into the more abstract fields of invention: for this latter faculty, and the questions of proportion and arrangement connected with its discussion, can only be rightly examined in a general view of all arts; but its sympathy, in architecture, with the vast controlling powers of Nature herself, is special, and may shortly be considered; and that with the more advantage, that it has, of late, been little felt or regarded by architects. I have seen, in recent efforts, much contest between two schools, one affecting originality, and the other legality—many attempts at beauty of design—many ingenious adaptations of construction; but I have never seen any aim at the expression of abstract power; never any appearance of a consciousness that, in this primal art of man, there is room for the marking of his relations with the mightiest, as well as the fairest, works of God; and that those works themselves have been permitted, by their Master and his, to receive an added glory from their association with earnest efforts of human thought. In the edifices of Man there should be found rever[Pg 72]ent worship and following, not only of the spirit which rounds the pillars of the forest, and arches the vault of the avenue—which gives veining to the leaf, and polish to the shell, and grace to every pulse that agitates animal organization,—but of that also which reproves the pillars of the earth, and builds up her barren precipices into the coldness of the clouds, and lifts her shadowy cones of mountain purple into the pale arch of the sky; for these, and other glories more than these, refuse not to connect themselves, in his thoughts, with the work of his own hand; the grey cliff loses not its nobleness when it reminds us of some Cyclopean waste of mural stone; the pinnacles of the rocky promontory arrange themselves, undegraded, into fantastic semblances of fortress towers; and even the awful cone of the far-off mountain has a melancholy mixed with that of its own solitude, which is cast from the images of nameless tumuli on white sea-shores, and of the heaps of reedy clay, into which chambered cities melt in their mortality.

III. In addition to this expression of living authority and power, there’s a connection in the forms of noble buildings with what is most sublime in nature; and it’s the guiding power driven by this connection that I will now attempt to trace, setting aside all exploration into the more abstract fields of invention. This latter ability and the discussions about proportion and arrangement related to it can only be properly examined from a broad perspective of all the arts; but its connection, in architecture, with the vast controlling forces of nature itself is unique and deserves brief consideration, especially since it has, in recent times, been largely overlooked by architects. I've noticed, in recent efforts, a lot of competition between two schools—one striving for originality and the other for tradition—many attempts at design beauty, and many clever construction adaptations; but I’ve never seen any effort aimed at expressing abstract power or any indication of an awareness that, in this fundamental art of humanity, there is space to reflect on our relationship with both the mightiest and the most beautiful works of God; and that those works have been allowed by their Maker to gain additional glory through their association with the sincere efforts of human thought. In human buildings, there should be found reverence, worship, and imitation, not only of the spirit that rounds the pillars of the forest and arches the avenue’s vault—which provides veining to the leaf, polish to the shell, and grace to every heartbeat that energizes living beings—but also of that which shapes the pillars of the earth, builds her barren cliffs into the chill of the clouds, and raises her shadowy purple mountains into the pale sky; for these, and even greater glories, are not separate from the thoughts of human handiwork. The grey cliff does not lose its grandeur when it reminds us of some Cyclopean ruins of stone; the peaks of the rocky promontory remain untainted, arranging themselves in fantastical shapes of fortress towers; and even the formidable cone of the distant mountain carries a sadness mingled with its own solitude, evoking images of nameless burial mounds on white shorelines and of piles of clay, into which ancient cities fade in their mortality.

IV. Let us, then, see what is this power and majesty, which Nature herself does not disdain to accept from the works of man; and what that sublimity in the masses built up by his coralline-like energy, which is honorable, even when transferred by association to the dateless hills, which it needed earthquakes to lift, and deluges to mould.

IV. So, let’s explore what this power and greatness is that Nature herself doesn’t shy away from acknowledging in human creations; and what that nobility is in the structures formed by his coral-like energy, which is admirable, even when it’s linked to the timeless mountains that required earthquakes to rise and floods to shape.

And, first of mere size: It might not be thought possible to emulate the sublimity of natural objects in this respect; nor would it be, if the architect contended with them in pitched battle. It would not be well to build pyramids in the valley of Chamouni; and St. Peter's, among its many other errors, counts for not the least injurious its position on the slope of an inconsiderable hill. But imagine it placed on the plain of Marengo, or, like the Superga of Turin, or like La Salute at Venice! The fact is, that the apprehension of the size of natural objects, as well as of architecture, depends more on fortunate excitement of the imagination than on measurements by the eye; and the architect has a peculiar advantage in being able to press close upon the sight, such magnitude as he can command. There are few rocks, even among the Alps, that have a clear vertical fall as high as the choir of Beauvais; and[Pg 73] if we secure a good precipice of wall, or a sheer and unbroken flank of tower, and place them where there are no enormous natural features to oppose them, we shall feel in them no want of sublimity of size. And it may be matter of encouragement in this respect, though one also of regret, to observe how much oftener man destroys natural sublimity, than nature crushes human power. It does not need much to humiliate a mountain. A hut will sometimes do it; I never look up to the Col de Balme from Chamouni, without a violent feeling of provocation against its hospitable little cabin, whose bright white walls form a visibly four-square spot on the green ridge, and entirely destroy all idea of its elevation. A single villa will often mar a whole landscape, and dethrone a dynasty of hills, and the Acropolis of Athens, Parthenon and all, has, I believe, been dwarfed into a model by the palace lately built beneath it. The fact is, that hills are not so high as we fancy them, and, when to the actual impression of no mean comparative size, is added the sense of the toil of manly hand and thought, a sublimity is reached, which nothing but gross error in arrangement of its parts can destroy.

And, first of all, in terms of size: It might seem impossible to match the greatness of natural objects in this regard; and it wouldn't be if the architect took them on directly. It wouldn’t make sense to build pyramids in the valley of Chamouni; and St. Peter's, among its many flaws, is particularly harmed by its location on the slope of a small hill. But imagine it situated on the plain of Marengo, or like the Superga in Turin, or La Salute in Venice! The truth is, our understanding of the size of both natural objects and architecture relies more on the spark of imagination than on our visual measurements; plus, the architect has a unique advantage in being able to bring immense structures close to our view. There are few rocks, even in the Alps, that drop as vertically as the choir of Beauvais; and if we secure a solid precipice of wall or a steep and continuous tower, and position them where there aren’t any massive natural features to overshadow them, we won’t feel a lack of greatness in their size. It's both encouraging and somewhat disappointing to see how much more often humans diminish natural grandeur than nature diminishes human achievement. It doesn’t take much to belittle a mountain. Sometimes, a simple hut can do it; I never look up at the Col de Balme from Chamouni without feeling a strong irritation toward its welcoming little cabin, whose bright white walls create a visible square on the green ridge, completely ruining the sense of its height. A single villa can often spoil an entire landscape and overshadow a range of hills, and I believe the Acropolis of Athens, Parthenon and all, has been diminished to a model by the palace recently built beneath it. The reality is that hills aren’t as tall as we imagine them to be, and when we combine the actual perception of a considerable size with the appreciation for the labor and creativity of human effort, we reach a sense of greatness that only a serious error in arrangement can ruin.

V. While, therefore, it is not to be supposed that mere size will ennoble a mean design, yet every increase of magnitude will bestow upon it a certain degree of nobleness: so that it is well to determine at first, whether the building is to be markedly beautiful or markedly sublime; and if the latter, not to be withheld by respect to smaller parts from reaching largeness of scale; provided only, that it be evidently in the architect's power to reach at least that degree of magnitude which is the lowest at which sublimity begins, rudely definable as that which will make a living figure look less than life beside it. It is the misfortune of most of our modern buildings that we would fain have an universal excellence in them; and so part of the funds must go in painting, part in gilding, part in fitting up, part in painted windows, part in small steeples, part in ornaments here and there; and neither the windows, nor the steeple, nor the ornaments, are worth their materials. For there is a crust about the impressible part of men's minds, which must be pierced through before they can be touched[Pg 74] to the quick; and though we may prick at it and scratch it in a thousand separate places, we might as well have let it alone if we do not come through somewhere with a deep thrust: and if we can give such a thrust anywhere, there is no need of another; it need not be even so "wide as a church door," so that it be enough. And mere weight will do this; it is a clumsy way of doing it, but an effectual one, too; and the apathy which cannot be pierced through by a small steeple, nor shone through by a small window, can be broken through in a moment by the mere weight of a great wall. Let, therefore, the architect who has not large resources, choose his point of attack first, and, if he choose size, let him abandon decoration; for, unless they are concentrated, and numerous enough to make their concentration conspicuous, all his ornaments together would not be worth one huge stone. And the choice must be a decided one, without compromise. It must be no question whether his capitals would not look better with a little carving—let him leave them huge as blocks; or whether his arches should not have richer architraves—let him throw them a foot higher, if he can; a yard more across the nave will be worth more to him than a tesselated pavement; and another fathom of outer wall, than an army of pinnacles. The limitation of size must be only in the uses of the building, or in the ground at his disposal.

V. While it's clear that just being big doesn't make a mediocre design better, every increase in size does give it a bit more nobility. So, it's important to figure out first if the building is supposed to be really beautiful or really impressive; and if it's the latter, we shouldn't hold back on scale just because of smaller details. As long as the architect can achieve at least the minimum size where impressiveness begins—roughly defined as making a living figure appear smaller than it—he shouldn't be restricted. The unfortunate truth about most modern buildings is that we want them to excel in every way, so part of the budget goes to painting, part to gilding, part to interior fixtures, part to stained glass windows, part to small steeples, and part to decorations here and there; yet neither the windows, the steeple, nor the decorations are worth their materials. There exists a barrier within people's minds that needs to be broken through to truly resonate with them; and even if we poke and scratch at it in many places, it would be better to leave it alone than to not break through somewhere with a significant impact. If we can manage to do that anywhere, there's no need for another—size doesn't have to be as "wide as a church door," as long as it's enough. Even sheer weight is capable of this; it's a blunt approach, but an effective one as well. A small steeple or tiny window won't penetrate the indifference, but a massive wall can do it instantly. Therefore, an architect with limited resources should choose his focus carefully. If he opts for size, he should forgo decoration; because unless decorations are concentrated and numerous enough to stand out, they won’t be worth as much as one giant stone. The decision must be firm, without any compromises. It shouldn't even be a question of whether the capitals would look better with some carving—just leave them as massive as blocks; or whether the arches should have fancier architraves—if he can, he should raise them a foot higher; an additional yard across the nave is more valuable than a fancy tiled floor; and another section of outer wall is worth more than a collection of spires. The only limitations on size should come from the building's purposes or the available land.

VI. That limitation, however, being by such circumstances determined, by what means, it is to be next asked, may the actual magnitude be best displayed; since it is seldom, perhaps never, that a building of any pretension to size looks so large as it is. The appearance of a figure in any distant, more especially in any upper, parts of it will almost always prove that we have under-estimated the magnitude of those parts.

VI. That limitation, however, being determined by such circumstances, we must next ask how the actual size can be best shown; because it's rare, if not impossible, for a building that aims for size to look as large as it truly is. The appearance of a figure in any distant, especially in any higher, parts of it will almost always reveal that we have underestimated the size of those parts.

It has often been observed that a building, in order to show its magnitude, must be seen all at once. It would, perhaps, be better to say, must be bounded as much as possible by continuous lines, and that its extreme points should be seen all at once; or we may state, in simpler terms still, that it must have one visible bounding line from top to bottom, and from end to end. This bounding line from top to bottom may[Pg 75] either be inclined inwards, and the mass, therefore, pyramidical; or vertical, and the mass form one grand cliff; or inclined outwards, as in the advancing fronts of old houses, and, in a sort, in the Greek temple, and in all buildings with heavy cornices or heads. Now, in all these cases, if the bounding line be violently broken; if the cornice project, or the upper portion of the pyramid recede, too violently, majesty will be lost; not because the building cannot be seen all at once,—for in the case of a heavy cornice no part of it is necessarily concealed—but because the continuity of its terminal line is broken, and the length of that line, therefore, cannot be estimated. But the error is, of course, more fatal when much of the building is also concealed; as in the well-known case of the recession of the dome of St. Peter's, and, from the greater number of points of view, in churches whose highest portions, whether dome or tower, are over their cross. Thus there is only one point from which the size of the Cathedral of Florence is felt; and that is from the corner of the Via de' Balestrieri, opposite the south-east angle, where it happens that the dome is seen rising instantly above the apse and transepts. In all cases in which the tower is over the cross, the grandeur and height of the tower itself are lost, because there is but one line down which the eye can trace the whole height, and that is in the inner angle of the cross, not easily discerned. Hence, while, in symmetry and feeling, such designs may often have pre-eminence, yet, where the height of the tower itself is to be made apparent, it must be at the west end, or better still, detached as a campanile. Imagine the loss to the Lombard churches if their campaniles were carried only to their present height over their crosses; or to the Cathedral of Rouen, if the Tour de Beurre were made central, in the place of its present debased spire!

It’s often noted that to showcase a building's size, it needs to be seen all at once. Better put, it should be outlined by continuous lines so that its farthest points are visible together; or to simplify even more, it should have one clear line from top to bottom and from side to side. This line can either slope inward, giving a pyramid shape, stand vertical like a grand cliff, or slope outward, as seen in the fronts of old houses, Greek temples, or any buildings with heavy cornices or caps. In all these cases, if the line is sharply interrupted—if the cornice juts out or the top of the pyramid retreats too drastically—the sense of majesty is lost; not because the building can't be seen as a whole—since heavy cornices don't usually hide any part—but because the continuity of that terminal line is disrupted, making it hard to gauge its length. However, the mistake is worse if much of the building is also hidden; this is evident in the well-known issue with the dome of St. Peter's and, in many perspectives, in churches where the tallest sections, whether domes or towers, sit above their crosses. Thus, the size of the Cathedral of Florence is only truly felt from a specific point: the corner of Via de' Balestrieri, opposite the south-east angle, where the dome rises steeply above the apse and transepts. In cases where the tower is above the cross, the tower's grandeur and height are diminished because the eye can only trace the entire height along one line, which is at the inner angle of the cross and isn’t easily seen. Therefore, while such designs may often excel in symmetry and feeling, if the height of the tower needs to be highlighted, it should be at the west end, or even better, separated as a campanile. Imagine the loss for Lombard churches if their campaniles only reached their current height above the crosses; or for the Cathedral of Rouen, if the Tour de Beurre were centered instead of having its current, lesser spire!

VII. Whether, therefore, we have to do with tower or wall, there must be one bounding line from base to coping; and I am much inclined, myself, to love the true vertical, or the vertical, with a solemn frown of projection (not a scowl), as in the Palazzo Vecchio of Florence. This character is always given to rocks by the poets; with slight foundation indeed[Pg 76] real rocks being little given to overhanging—but with excellent judgment; for the sense of threatening conveyed by this form is a nobler character than that of mere size. And, in buildings, this threatening should be somewhat carried down into their mass. A mere projecting shelf is not enough, the whole wall must, Jupiter like, nod as well as frown. Hence, I think the propped machicolations of the Palazzo Vecchio and Duomo of Florence far grander headings than any form of Greek cornice. Sometimes the projection may be thrown lower, as in the Doge's palace of Venice, where the chief appearance of it is above the second arcade; or it may become a grand swell from the ground, as the head of a ship of the line rises from the sea. This is very nobly attained by the projection of the niches in the third story of the Tour de Beurre at Rouen.

VII. Whether we’re talking about a tower or a wall, there needs to be one continuous line from the base to the top; and I personally tend to favor the true vertical, or the vertical with a serious overhang (not a scowl), like in the Palazzo Vecchio in Florence. Poets often give this quality to rocks, even though real rocks rarely overhang—but they do so with great insight; for the sense of threat conveyed by this shape is a nobler characteristic than just sheer size. In buildings, this sense of threat should also be reflected in their mass. A simple overhanging ledge isn’t enough; the whole wall must, like Jupiter, both nod and frown. Therefore, I believe the supported machicolations of the Palazzo Vecchio and the Duomo in Florence are far more impressive than any type of Greek cornice. Sometimes the overhang can be placed lower, as in the Doge's Palace in Venice, where the main projection is above the second arcade; or it can rise grandly from the ground, like the bow of a large ship emerging from the sea. This is beautifully achieved by the projection of the niches on the third story of the Tour de Beurre in Rouen.

VIII. What is needful in the setting forth of magnitude in height, is right also in the marking it in area—let it be gathered well together. It is especially to be noted with respect to the Palazzo Vecchio and other mighty buildings of its order, how mistakenly it has been stated that dimension, in order to become impressive, should be expanded either in height or length, but not equally: whereas, rather it will be found that those buildings seem on the whole the vastest which have been gathered up into a mighty square, and which look as if they had been measured by the angel's rod, "the length, and the breadth, and the height of it are equal," and herein something is to be taken notice of, which I believe not to be sufficiently, if at all, considered among our architects.

VIII. What's important when showcasing height is also crucial for defining area—everything should be well-organized. It's worth noting, especially regarding the Palazzo Vecchio and other grand buildings of its kind, how wrongly it's been said that dimensions should only be increased in height or length for them to be impressive, but not both equally. In reality, it appears that the most impressive buildings are those that are contained within a strong square shape, giving the impression they have been measured by an angel's rod, "the length, and the breadth, and the height of it are equal." This is something I believe our architects don't really pay enough attention to, if at all.

Of the many broad divisions under which architecture may be considered, none appear to me more significant than that into buildings whose interest is in their walls, and those whose interest is in the lines dividing their walls. In the Greek temple the wall is as nothing; the entire interest is in the detached columns and the frieze they bear; in French Flamboyant, and in our detestable Perpendicular, the object is to get rid of the wall surface, and keep the eye altogether on tracery of line; in Romanesque work and Egyptian, the[Pg 77] wall is a confessed and honored member, and the light is often allowed to fall on large areas of it, variously decorated. Now, both these principles are admitted by Nature, the one in her woods and thickets, the other in her plains, and cliffs, and waters; but the latter is pre-eminently the principle of power, and, in some sense, of beauty also. For, whatever infinity of fair form there may be in the maze of the forest, there is a fairer, as I think, in the surface of the quiet lake; and I hardly know that association of shaft or tracery, for which I would exchange the warm sleep of sunshine on some smooth, broad, human-like front of marble. Nevertheless, if breadth is to be beautiful, its substance must in some sort be beautiful; and we must not hastily condemn the exclusive resting of the northern architects in divided lines, until at least we have remembered the difference between a blank surface of Caen stone, and one mixed from Genoa and Carrara, of serpentine with snow: but as regards abstract power and awfulness, there is no question; without breadth of surface it is in vain to seek them, and it matters little, so that the surface be wide, bold and unbroken, whether it be of brick or of jasper; the light of heaven upon it, and the weight of earth in it, are all we need: for it is singular how forgetful the mind may become both of material and workmanship, if only it have space enough over which to range, and to remind it, however feebly, of the joy that it has in contemplating the flatness and sweep of great plains and broad seas. And it is a noble thing for men to do this with their cut stone or moulded clay, and to make the face of a wall look infinite, and its edge against the sky like an horizon: or even if less than this be reached, it is still delightful to mark the play of passing light on its broad surface, and to see by how many artifices and gradations of tinting and shadow, time and storm will set their wild signatures upon it; and how in the rising or declining of the day the unbroken twilight rests long and luridly on its high lineless forehead, and fades away untraceably down its tiers of confused and countless stone.

Among the various ways to classify architecture, I find one distinction particularly important: buildings that draw interest from their walls and those that capture attention through the lines separating those walls. In a Greek temple, the wall hardly matters; the main focus is on the standalone columns and the frieze they support. In French Flamboyant and our unfortunate Perpendicular style, the goal is to minimize wall surfaces and direct attention solely to intricate line work. In contrast, Romanesque and Egyptian architecture openly celebrate the wall, allowing light to illuminate large, decorated sections of it. Both of these principles are recognized by nature—one in its forests and undergrowth, the other in its open plains, cliffs, and waters. However, the latter principle embodies a greater sense of power and, in some ways, beauty. While there’s a lot of captivating form in the forest’s intricacy, I find there’s an even greater beauty in the calm surface of a tranquil lake. I can hardly think of a detail or decoration I'd trade for the warmth of sunlight on a smooth, broad surface of marble. That said, for expansiveness to be beautiful, it should have a certain beauty in its material. We shouldn’t quickly judge the northern architects for focusing on divided lines until we consider the difference between a plain surface of Caen stone and one that combines materials from Genoa and Carrara, with a blend of serpentine and white stone. However, when it comes to abstract power and awe, there's no debate; without a broad surface, seeking those qualities is futile. It doesn’t matter much whether that surface is made of brick or jasper, as long as it is wide, bold, and unbroken. The light of the sky upon it and the weight of the earth within it are all that we truly need. It’s interesting how easily the mind can forget about the material and craftsmanship when it has enough open space to explore, reminiscent of the joy found in the flatness and expanse of great plains and vast seas. It’s a grand endeavor for people to create this with their cut stone or molded clay, to make the face of a wall seem endless and its edge against the sky look like a horizon. Even if they don't achieve that, it’s still pleasing to observe the interplay of light on its broad surface, and to see how time and storms leave their rugged imprints through varying shades and shadows. In the rise and fall of the day, the unbroken twilight lingers heavily on its towering, featureless face, gradually fading down into its many layers of chaotic stone.

IX. This, then, being, as I think, one of the peculiar elements of sublime architecture, it may be easily seen how neces[Pg 78]sarily consequent upon the love of it will be the choice of a form approaching to the square for the main outline.

IX. This, I believe, is one of the unique aspects of impressive architecture. It's clear how the appreciation of it naturally leads to choosing a square shape for the main outline.

For, in whatever direction the building is contracted, in that direction the eye will be drawn to its terminal lines; and the sense of surface will only be at its fullest when those lines are removed, in every direction, as far as possible. Thus the square and circle are pre-eminently the areas of power among those bounded by purely straight or curved lines; and these, with their relative solids, the cube and sphere, and relative solids of progression (as in the investigation of the laws of proportion I shall call those masses which are generated by the progression of an area of given form along a line in a given direction), the square and cylindrical column, are the elements of utmost power in all architectural arrangements. On the other hand, grace and perfect proportion require an elongation in some one direction: and a sense of power may be communicated to this form of magnitude by a continuous series of any marked features, such as the eye may be unable to number; while yet we feel, from their boldness, decision, and simplicity, that it is indeed their multitude which has embarrassed us, not any confusion or indistinctness of form. This expedient of continued series forms the sublimity of arcades and aisles, of all ranges of columns, and, on a smaller scale, of those Greek mouldings, of which, repeated as they now are in all the meanest and most familiar forms of our furniture, it is impossible altogether to weary. Now, it is evident that the architect has choice of two types of form, each properly associated with its own kind of interest or decoration: the square, or greatest area, to be chosen especially when the surface is to be the subject of thought; and the elongated area, when the divisions of the surface are to be the subjects of thought. Both these orders of form, as I think nearly every other source of power and beauty, are marvellously united in that building which I fear to weary the reader by bringing forward too frequently, as a model of all perfection—the Doge's palace at Venice: its general arrangement, a hollow square; its principal façade, an oblong, elongated to the eye by a range of thirty-four small arches, and thirty-five[Pg 79] columns, while it is separated by a richly-canopied window in the centre, into two massive divisions, whose height and length are nearly as four to five; the arcades which give it length being confined to the lower stories, and the upper, between its broad windows, left a mighty surface of smooth marble, chequered with blocks of alternate rose-color and white. It would be impossible, I believe, to invent a more magnificent arrangement of all that is in building most dignified and most fair.

In any direction that the building is designed, the eye will inevitably be drawn to its edges, and the perception of surface will only be fully realized when those edges are extended as far as possible in all directions. Therefore, the square and circle are the most powerful shapes among those formed by straight or curved lines; along with their corresponding three-dimensional forms, the cube and sphere, and the evolving forms generated by extending an area along a line in a specific direction—which I’ll refer to in my exploration of proportionality—the square and cylindrical column are fundamental elements of strength in architectural designs. Conversely, elegance and ideal proportion require some degree of elongation in one direction: a sense of power can be conveyed through a continuous series of prominent features, which are too numerous for the eye to count; yet, it’s clear that their boldness, clarity, and simplicity contribute to a sense of overwhelming abundance, not confusion or vagueness of form. This approach of using a continuous series creates the grandeur seen in arcades and aisles, in all rows of columns, and, on a smaller scale, in the Greek moldings that are now so commonly found in even the simplest and most familiar pieces of our furniture that we can never truly tire of them. It’s clear that architects have two forms to choose from, each linked to its own distinct style or decoration: the square, or the largest area, is especially suited for when the surface is to be the focus; and the elongated area, for when the divisions of the surface are the focus. Both types of form, along with nearly every other source of power and beauty, are wonderfully combined in a building that I hesitate to mention too often, for fear of wearing out the reader—it is the Doge's Palace in Venice: its overall design is a hollow square; its main façade is an oblong shape, extended visually by a series of thirty-four small arches and thirty-five[Pg 79] columns, separated by a richly canopied window in the center, dividing it into two massive sections, which are proportionate in height and length at nearly four to five; the arcades, which provide its length, are limited to the lower stories, while the upper level, with its broad windows, features a grand surface of smooth marble, checkered with alternating blocks of rose and white. I believe it would be impossible to conceive a more magnificent arrangement of what is most dignified and beautiful in building.

X. In the Lombard Romanesque, the two principles are more fused into each other, as most characteristically in the Cathedral of Pisa: length of proportion, exhibited by an arcade of twenty-one arches above, and fifteen below, at the side of the nave; bold square proportion in the front; that front divided into arcades, placed one above the other, the lowest with its pillars engaged, of seven arches, the four uppermost thrown out boldly from the receding wall, and casting deep shadows; the first, above the basement, of nineteen arches; the second of twenty-one; the third and fourth of eight each; sixty-three arches in all; all circular headed, all with cylindrical shafts, and the lowest with square panellings, set diagonally under their semicircles, an universal ornament in this style (Plate XII., fig. 7); the apse, a semicircle, with a semi-dome for its roof, and three ranges of circular arches for its exterior ornament; in the interior of the nave, a range of circular arches below a circular-arched triforium, and a vast flat surface, observe, of wall decorated with striped marble above; the whole arrangement (not a peculiar one, but characteristic of every church of the period; and, to my feeling, the most majestic; not perhaps the fairest, but the mightiest type of form which the mind of man has ever conceived) based exclusively on associations of the circle and the square.

X. In the Lombard Romanesque style, the two principles blend together more seamlessly, as most notably seen in the Cathedral of Pisa: the elongated proportions are displayed by an arcade of twenty-one arches above and fifteen arches below alongside the nave; a strong square proportion at the front; that front divided into arcades stacked on top of each other, the lowest with its pillars engaged, featuring seven arches, while the four uppermost arches extend boldly from the receding wall, creating deep shadows; the first level, above the basement, has nineteen arches; the second has twenty-one arches; the third and fourth each have eight arches; totaling sixty-three arches; all with circular heads, all featuring cylindrical shafts, and the lowest adorned with square panellings, set diagonally beneath their semicircles, a common decorative element in this style (Plate XII., fig. 7); the apse is a semicircle topped with a semi-dome for its roof, and three rows of circular arches for exterior decoration; inside the nave, there’s a row of circular arches below a circular-arched triforium, and a vast flat surface of wall embellished with patterned marble above; the entire layout (not unique, but typical of every church from this period; and, in my opinion, the most majestic; not necessarily the most beautiful, but the most powerful form ever conceived by the human mind) is grounded entirely in associations of the circle and the square.

I am now, however, trenching upon ground which I desire to reserve for more careful examination, in connection with other æsthetic questions: but I believe the examples I have given will justify my vindication of the square form from the reprobation which has been lightly thrown upon it; nor might this be done for it only as a ruling outline, but as occurring[Pg 80] constantly in the best mosaics, and in a thousand forms of minor decoration, which I cannot now examine; my chief assertion of its majesty being always as it is an exponent of space and surface, and therefore to be chosen, either to rule in their outlines, or to adorn by masses of light and shade those portions of buildings in which surface is to be rendered precious or honorable.

I am now, however, stepping into territory that I want to save for a deeper look later, in relation to other aesthetic issues. But I believe the examples I've provided will support my defense of the square shape against the criticism it has faced too casually. This applies not only to it as a main outline but also to its presence[Pg 80] in many of the finest mosaics and a multitude of minor decorations that I can't explore right now. My main point about its greatness is that it represents space and surface, making it suitable to define their outlines or to enhance certain parts of buildings with light and shadow, elevating those surfaces to make them valuable or esteemed.

XI. Thus far, then, of general forms, and of the modes in which the scale of architecture is best to be exhibited. Let us next consider the manifestations of power which belong to its details and lesser divisions.

XI. So far, we've covered the general forms and the ways the scale of architecture should be displayed. Next, let's look at the expressions of power found in its details and smaller sections.

The first division we have to regard, is the inevitable one of masonry. It is true that this division may, by great art, be concealed; but I think it unwise (as well as dishonest) to do so; for this reason, that there is a very noble character always to be obtained by the opposition of large stones to divided masonry, as by shafts and columns of one piece, or massy lintels and architraves, to wall work of bricks or smaller stones; and there is a certain organization in the management of such parts, like that of the continuous bones of the skeleton, opposed to the vertebræ, which it is not well to surrender. I hold, therefore, that, for this and other reasons, the masonry of a building is to be shown: and also that, with certain rare exceptions (as in the cases of chapels and shrines of most finished workmanship), the smaller the building, the more necessary it is that its masonry should be bold, and vice versâ. For if a building be under the mark of average magnitude, it is not in our power to increase its apparent size (too easily measurable) by any proportionate diminution in the scale of its masonry. But it may be often in our power to give it a certain nobility by building it of massy stones, or, at all events, introducing such into its make. Thus it is impossible that there should ever be majesty in a cottage built of brick; but there is a marked element of sublimity in the rude and irregular piling of the rocky walls of the mountain cottages of Wales, Cumberland, and Scotland. Their size is not one whit diminished, though four or five stones reach at their angles from the ground to the eaves, or though a native rock happen[Pg 81] to project conveniently, and to be built into the framework of the wall. On the other hand, after a building has once reached the mark of majestic size, it matters, indeed, comparatively little whether its masonry be large or small, but if it be altogether large, it will sometimes diminish the magnitude for want of a measure; if altogether small, it will suggest ideas of poverty in material, or deficiency in mechanical resource, besides interfering in many cases with the lines of the design, and delicacy of the workmanship. A very unhappy instance of such interference exists in the façade of the church of St. Madeleine at Paris, where the columns, being built of very small stones of nearly equal size, with visible joints, look as if they were covered with a close trellis. So, then, that masonry will be generally the most magnificent which, without the use of materials systematically small or large, accommodates itself, naturally and frankly, to the conditions and structure of its work, and displays alike its power of dealing with the vastest masses, and of accomplishing its purpose with the smallest, sometimes heaping rock upon rock with Titanic commandment, and anon binding the dusty remnants and edgy splinters into springing vaults and swelling domes. And if the nobility of this confessed and natural masonry were more commonly felt, we should not lose the dignity of it by smoothing surfaces and fitting joints. The sums which we waste in chiselling and polishing stones which would have been better left as they came from the quarry would often raise a building a story higher. Only in this there is to be a certain respect for material also: for if we build in marble, or in any limestone, the known ease of the workmanship will make its absence seem slovenly; it will be well to take advantage of the stone's softness, and to make the design delicate and dependent upon smoothness of chiselled surfaces: but if we build in granite or lava, it is a folly, in most cases, to cast away the labor necessary to smooth it; it is wiser to make the design granitic itself, and to leave the blocks rudely squared. I do not deny a certain splendor and sense of power in the smoothing of granite, and in the entire subduing of its iron resistance to the human supremacy. But, in most cases, I believe, the labor[Pg 82] and time necessary to do this would be better spent in another way; and that to raise a building to a height of a hundred feet with rough blocks, is better than to raise it to seventy with smooth ones. There is also a magnificence in the natural cleavage of the stone to which the art must indeed be great that pretends to be equivalent; and a stern expression of brotherhood with the mountain heart from which it has been rent, ill-exchanged for a glistering obedience to the rule and measure of men. His eye must be delicate indeed, who would desire to see the Pitti palace polished.

The first thing we need to consider is the inevitable division in masonry. While it's true that this division can be hidden with great skill, I believe it's unwise (and dishonest) to do so. This is because there's a noble quality that arises from contrasting large stones with smaller masonry, much like how solid shafts and columns or heavy lintels and architraves stand against brick or smaller stone walls. There's a certain organization in managing these elements, similar to the way continuous bones of the skeleton oppose the vertebrae, which we shouldn’t overlook. Therefore, I maintain that the masonry of a building should be visible. Also, with certain rare exceptions (like in chapels and shrines with highly refined craftsmanship), the smaller the building, the more essential it is for its masonry to be bold, and vice versa. If a building is below average size, we can't really make it seem larger by scaling down its masonry. However, we can often give it a sense of grandeur by using massive stones or incorporating them into its design. A cottage built of brick can never convey majesty, but there's a striking element of sublimity in the rough and uneven stacking of the rocky walls of mountain cottages in Wales, Cumberland, and Scotland. Their size is not reduced at all, even when four or five stones reach from the ground to the eaves, or when a natural rock conveniently projects and is incorporated into the wall. On the other hand, once a building has reached majestic proportions, it doesn’t matter much whether its masonry is large or small; however, if it’s all large, it can sometimes reduce the perception of size due to a lack of contrast, while if it’s all small, it can suggest poverty in materials or lack of craftsmanship, and can interfere with design lines and the delicacy of the workmanship. A very unfortunate example of such interference can be seen in the façade of the church of St. Madeleine in Paris, where the columns, made of small stones of nearly equal size with visible joints, look like they are covered with a close trellis. Thus, the most magnificent masonry will generally be the one that, without relying on systematically small or large materials, naturally and honestly accommodates the structural conditions of its work, showcasing its ability to handle enormous masses while also achieving its purpose with smaller ones, sometimes stacking rocks with a grand style, and at other times binding together dusty remnants and sharp fragments into arched vaults and soaring domes. If the nobility of this honest and natural masonry were more widely appreciated, we wouldn’t lose its dignity by smoothing surfaces and fitting joints. The money wasted on chiseling and polishing stones that would have looked better left as they came from the quarry could often lift a building a story higher. However, there should also be some respect for the material: if we're using marble or any limestone, its known ease of working makes any roughness appear sloppy; in these cases, it’s best to take advantage of the stone's softness and make the design delicate, focusing on smooth, chiseled surfaces. But with granite or lava, it’s often foolish to waste the effort needed to smooth it down; it’s smarter to design in a way that embraces the stone’s roughness, keeping the blocks roughly squared. I don’t deny that there is a certain splendor and sense of power in smoothing granite and fully overcoming its tough, resistant nature. However, in most cases, I believe the time and labor required for this would be better used elsewhere; making a building a hundred feet tall with rough blocks is preferable to making it seventy feet with smooth ones. There’s also magnificence in the natural cleavage of the stone, which is nearly impossible to replicate through art. The stern expression of connection with the mountain it came from is poorly exchanged for a shiny conformity to human standards. One would need to have a remarkably refined taste to desire to see the Pitti Palace polished.

XII. Next to those of the masonry, we have to consider the divisions of the design itself. Those divisions are, necessarily, either into masses of light and shade, or else by traced lines; which latter must be, indeed, themselves produced by incisions or projections which, in some lights, cast a certain breadth of shade, but which may, nevertheless, if finely enough cut, be always true lines, in distant effect. I call, for instance, such panelling as that of Henry the Seventh's chapel, pure linear division.

XII. Following the masonry, we need to consider the divisions of the design itself. These divisions are either into areas of light and shadow or by outlined lines; the latter must be created through cuts or projections that, in certain lighting, cast a specific depth of shadow, but can also remain true lines in distant views if carved finely enough. For example, I refer to the paneling in Henry the Seventh's chapel as a pure linear division.

Now, it does not seem to me sufficiently recollected, that a wall surface is to an architect simply what a white canvas is to a painter, with this only difference, that the wall has already a sublimity in its height, substance, and other characters already considered, on which it is more dangerous to break than to touch with shade the canvas surface. And, for my own part, I think a smooth, broad, freshly laid surface of gesso a fairer thing than most pictures I see painted on it; much more, a noble surface of stone than most architectural features which it is caused to assume. But however this may be, the canvas and wall are supposed to be given, and it is our craft to divide them.

Now, it doesn’t seem to me that it’s been fully recognized that a wall surface is to an architect what a blank canvas is to a painter, with the only difference being that the wall already has a certain grandeur in its height, material, and other qualities that have already been considered, making it riskier to alter than to simply shade the canvas. Personally, I believe a smooth, wide, freshly applied surface of gesso is more appealing than most paintings I see on it; even more so, a beautiful stone surface is better than most architectural features it might take on. However, regardless of this view, the canvas and wall are assumed to be established, and it's our job to differentiate between them.

And the principles on which this division is to be made, are as regards relation of quantities, the same in architecture as in painting, or indeed, in any other art whatsoever, only the painter is by his varied subject partly permitted, partly compelled, to dispense with the symmetry of architectural light and shade, and to adopt arrangements apparently free and accidental. So that in modes of grouping there is much dif[Pg 83]ference (though no opposition) between the two arts; but in rules of quantity, both are alike, so far forth as their commands of means are alike. For the architect, not being able to secure always the same depth or decision of shadow, nor to add to its sadness by color (because even when color is employed, it cannot follow the moving shade), is compelled to make many allowances, and avail himself of many contrivances, which the painter needs neither consider nor employ.

The principles for this division are, in terms of how quantities relate, the same in architecture as in painting, or really in any other art form. However, a painter, due to the variety of subjects, is partially allowed and partially forced to skip the symmetry of architectural light and shadow, adopting arrangements that seem free and random. Therefore, there’s a notable difference (though not an opposition) in the ways these two arts group their elements; however, regarding rules of quantity, they are similar as far as their required means are concerned. The architect, since he can't always ensure the same depth or intensity of shadow, nor enhance it with color (because even when color is used, it can’t match the shifting shade), has to make many compromises and use various techniques that the painter doesn’t have to think about or use.

XIII. Of these limitations the first consequence is, that positive shade is a more necessary and more sublime thing in an architect's hands than in a painter's. For the latter being able to temper his light with an under-tone throughout, and to make it delightful with sweet color, or awful with lurid color, and to represent distance, and air, and sun, by the depth of it, and fill its whole space with expression, can deal with an enormous, nay, almost with an universal extent of it, and the best painters most delight in such extent; but as light, with the architect, is nearly always liable to become full and untempered sunshine seen upon solid surface, his only rests, and his chief means of sublimity, are definite shades. So that, after size and weight, the Power of architecture may be said to depend on the quantity (whether measured in space or intenseness) of its shadow; and it seems to me, that the reality of its works, and the use and influence they have in the daily life of men (as opposed to those works of art with which we have nothing to do but in times of rest or of pleasure) require of it that it should express a kind of human sympathy, by a measure of darkness as great as there is in human life: and that as the great poem and great fiction generally affect us most by the majesty of their masses of shade, and cannot take hold upon us if they affect a continuance of lyric sprightliness, but must be serious often, and sometimes melancholy, else they do not express the truth of this wild world of ours; so there must be, in this magnificently human art of architecture, some equivalent expression for the trouble and wrath of life, for its sorrow and its mystery: and this it can only give by depth or diffusion of gloom, by the frown upon its[Pg 84] front, and the shadow of its recess. So that Rembrandtism is a noble manner in architecture, though a false one in painting; and I do not believe that ever any building was truly great, unless it had mighty masses, vigorous and deep, of shadow mingled with its surface. And among the first habits that a young architect should learn, is that of thinking in shadow, not looking at a design in its miserable liny skeleton; but conceiving it as it will be when the dawn lights it, and the dusk leaves it; when its stones will be hot and its crannies cool; when the lizards will bask on the one, and the birds build in the other. Let him design with the sense of cold and heat upon him; let him cut out the shadows, as men dig wells in unwatered plains; and lead along the lights, as a founder does his hot metal; let him keep the full command of both, and see that he knows how they fall, and where they fade. His paper lines and proportions are of no value: all that he has to do must be done by spaces of light and darkness; and his business is to see that the one is broad and bold enough not to be swallowed up by twilight, and the other deep enough not to be dried like a shallow pool by a noon-day sun.

XIII. The first consequence of these limitations is that positive shade is more essential and more elevated in an architect's work than in a painter's. A painter can balance light with an undertone throughout, using pleasing colors or dramatic hues, create a sense of distance, air, and sunlight through depth, and fill the entire space with expression, allowing for vast, almost limitless application of these elements, and the best painters thrive on this vastness. However, for an architect, light often becomes harsh and unfiltered sunlight on solid surfaces; therefore, his main sources of greatness and creativity are defined shades. After considering size and weight, we can say that the power of architecture largely depends on the quantity (measured by volume or intensity) of its shadow. It seems to me that the reality of architectural works and their role and impact in everyday life (as opposed to works of art that we only engage with during leisure) require that they express a type of human empathy through a level of darkness that mirrors the darkness in human life. Just as powerful poetry and fiction move us most with their significant masses of shade and lose their impact if they maintain a continuous lightness, instead needing to be serious and sometimes somber to reflect the truths of our chaotic world, architecture must also convey some equivalent expression of life's struggles and sorrows, as well as its mysteries. This can only be achieved through depth or expanse of gloom, the stern appearance of its facade, and the shadows of its recesses. Therefore, the style known as Rembrandtism is admirable in architecture, though misleading in painting. I don't believe any building can be truly great unless it has strong, deep masses of shadow integrated with its surface. One of the first lessons a young architect should learn is to think in terms of shadow, not just see a design as a bare outline; rather, envision it as it will appear when the dawn brightens it and the dusk envelops it, when its stones are warm and its crevices are cool, with lizards basking on one side and birds nesting in the other. He should design with awareness of temperature; let him carve out shadows like digging wells in dry land, and guide the light like a metalworker pouring molten metal; he must maintain complete control over both elements, understanding how they cast and where they dissolve. The lines and proportions on his paper have little significance; all he needs to do is manipulate areas of light and darkness, ensuring that the light is broad and striking enough not to be lost in twilight, and that the dark is deep enough not to evaporate like a shallow pool under the midday sun.

And that this may be, the first necessity is that the quantities of shade or light, whatever they may be, shall be thrown into masses, either of something like equal weight, or else large masses of the one relieved with small of the other; but masses of one or other kind there must be. No design that is divided at all, and is not divided into masses, can ever be of the smallest value: this great law respecting breadth, precisely the same in architecture and painting, is so important, that the examination of its two principal applications will include most of the conditions of majestic design on which I would at present insist.

For this to happen, the first requirement is that the amounts of shade or light, no matter what they are, should be grouped into masses—either similar weights or large masses of one highlighted with small amounts of the other; however, there must be masses of one kind or the other. Any design that's divided and not organized into masses will never hold much value. This essential principle about breadth, which applies equally in architecture and painting, is so crucial that looking at its two main applications will cover most of the key aspects of impressive design that I want to emphasize right now.

XIV. Painters are in the habit of speaking loosely of masses of light and shade, meaning thereby any large spaces of either. Nevertheless, it is convenient sometimes to restrict the term "mass" to the portions to which proper form belongs, and to call the field on which such forms are traced, interval. Thus, in foliage with projecting boughs or stems, we have masses of light, with intervals of shade; and, in[Pg 85] light skies with dark clouds upon them, masses of shade with intervals of light.

XIV. Painters often casually refer to patches of light and shadow, meaning any large areas of either. However, it can be useful to limit the term "mass" to the parts that have a distinct form and refer to the area where those forms are shown as the interval. For example, in foliage with sticking out branches or stems, we have masses of light with intervals of shadow; and in light skies with dark clouds, we have masses of shadow with intervals of light.

This distinction is, in architecture, still more necessary; for there are two marked styles dependent upon it: one in which the forms are drawn with light upon darkness, as in Greek sculpture and pillars; the other in which they are drawn with darkness upon light, as in early Gothic foliation. Now, it is not in the designer's power determinately to vary degrees and places of darkness, but it is altogether in his power to vary in determined directions his degrees of light. Hence, the use of the dark mass characterises, generally, a trenchant style of design, in which the darks and lights are both flat, and terminated by sharp edges; while the use of the light mass is in the same way associated with a softened and full manner of design, in which the darks are much warmed by reflected lights, and the lights are rounded and melt into them. The term applied by Milton to Doric bas-relief—"bossy," is, as is generally the case with Milton's epithets, the most comprehensive and expressive of this manner, which the English language contains; while the term which specifically describes the chief member of early Gothic decoration, feuille, foil or leaf, is equally significative of a flat space of shade.

This distinction is even more essential in architecture; there are two distinct styles that depend on it: one in which forms are created with light on dark, like in Greek sculpture and columns; the other where they are made with dark on light, like in early Gothic leaf patterns. Now, while the designer can't precisely control the levels and locations of darkness, they can totally adjust the degrees of light in set directions. Therefore, using a dark mass typically marks a bold design style, where both darks and lights appear flat and end with sharp edges; while using a light mass is usually linked to a softer, fuller design style, where darks are warmed by reflected lights, and the lights are rounded and blend into them. The term Milton used for Doric bas-relief—"bossy," is, as is often the case with Milton's descriptions, the most comprehensive and expressive in English for this style; while the term specifically describing the main feature of early Gothic decoration, feuille, foil, or leaf, is also very significant for representing a flat space of shade.

XV. We shall shortly consider the actual modes in which these two kinds of mass have been treated. And, first, of the light, or rounded, mass. The modes in which relief was secured for the more projecting forms of bas-relief, by the Greeks, have been too well described by Mr. Eastlake[I] to need recapitulation: the conclusion which forces itself upon us from the facts he has remarked, being one on which I shall have occasion farther to insist presently, that the Greek workman cared for shadow only as a dark field wherefrom his light figure or design might be intelligibly detached: his attention was concentrated on the one aim at readableness, and clearness of accent; and all composition, all harmony, nay, the very vitality and energy of separate groups were, when necessary, sacrificed to plain speaking. Nor was there any predilection for one kind [Pg 86]of form rather than another. Bounded forms were, in the columns and principal decorative members, adopted, not for their own sake, but as characteristic of the things represented. They were beautifully rounded, because the Greek habitually did well what he had to do, not because he loved roundness more than squareness; severely rectilinear forms were associated with the curved ones in the cornice and triglyph, and the mass of the pillar was divided by a fluting, which, in distant effect, destroyed much of its breadth. What power of light these primal arrangements left, was diminished in successive refinements and additions of ornament; and continued to diminish through Roman work, until the confirmation of the circular arch as a decorative feature. Its lovely and simple line taught the eye to ask for a similar boundary of solid form; the dome followed, and necessarily the decorative masses were thenceforward managed with reference to, and in sympathy with, the chief feature of the building. Hence arose, among the Byzantine architects, a system of ornament, entirely restrained within the superfices of curvilinear masses, on which the light fell with as unbroken gradation as on a dome or column, while the illumined surface was nevertheless cut into details of singular and most ingenious intricacy. Something is, of course, to be allowed for the less dexterity of the workmen; it being easier to cut down into a solid block, than to arrange the projecting portions of leaf on the Greek capital: such leafy capitals are nevertheless executed by the Byzantines with skill enough to show that their preference of the massive form was by no means compulsory, nor can I think it unwise. On the contrary, while the arrangements of line are far more artful in the Greek capital, the Byzantine light and shade are as incontestably more grand and masculine, based on that quality of pure gradation, which nearly all natural objects possess, and the attainment of which is, in fact, the first and most palpable purpose in natural arrangements of grand form. The rolling heap of the thunder-cloud, divided by rents, and multiplied by wreaths, yet gathering them all into its broad, torrid, and towering zone, and its midnight darkness opposite; the scarcely less majestic heave of the mountain side, all[Pg 87] torn and traversed by depth of defile and ridge of rock, yet never losing the unity of its illumined swell and shadowy decline; and the head of every mighty tree, rich with tracery of leaf and bough, yet terminated against the sky by a true line, and rounded by a green horizon, which, multiplied in the distant forest, makes it look bossy from above; all these mark, for a great and honored law, that diffusion of light for which the Byzantine ornaments were designed; and show us that those builders had truer sympathy with what God made majestic, than the self-contemplating and self-contented Greek. I know that they are barbaric in comparison; but there is a power in their barbarism of sterner tone, a power not sophistic nor penetrative, but embracing and mysterious; a power faithful more than thoughtful, which conceived and felt more than it created; a power that neither comprehended nor ruled itself, but worked and wandered as it listed, like mountain streams and winds; and which could not rest in the expression or seizure of finite form. It could not bury itself in acanthus leaves. Its imagery was taken from the shadows of the storms and hills, and had fellowship with the night and day of the earth itself.

XV. We’ll soon look at how these two types of mass have been handled. First, let's discuss the light, or rounded, mass. The ways the Greeks achieved relief for the more projecting forms of bas-relief have been well described by Mr. Eastlake[I], so there's no need to recap that. The conclusion that stands out from his observations, which I will emphasize later, is that the Greek craftsman valued shadow only as a dark backdrop from which his light figure or design could stand out clearly: his focus was on clarity and readability; all composition, harmony, and even the energy of separate groups were sacrificed when necessary for straightforward expression. There was no preference for one type of form over another. Defined forms in the columns and main decorative elements were used not for their own sake, but because they suited the things being represented. They were beautifully rounded because the Greek always did well what he set out to do, not because he preferred round shapes to square ones; strict linear forms were used alongside curved ones in the cornice and triglyph, and the pillar's mass was interrupted by fluting, which reduced much of its apparent width from a distance. The light power these initial designs provided gradually diminished with successive refinements and added ornaments; this decline continued through Roman work until the circular arch was established as a decorative feature. Its elegant and simple line taught the eye to seek a similar boundary of solid form; the dome followed, and from then on, the decorative masses were managed in relation to, and in harmony with, the building's main feature. This prompted Byzantine architects to develop a decorative system entirely contained within the surfaces of curvilinear forms, where light fell with smooth gradation, much like on a dome or column, while the illuminated surface was intricately detailed in a unique and clever way. Some credit should be given to the less skillful workmen; it’s easier to carve into a solid block than to arrange projecting leaves on a Greek capital; yet, Byzantine artisans produced leafy capitals well enough to show that their preference for the massive form was not just a requirement, nor do I see it as unwise. In fact, while the arrangements of line are far more refined in Greek capitals, Byzantine light and shade are undoubtedly more grand and powerful, drawing from that quality of pure gradation, which most natural objects possess, and which is ultimately the main purpose in naturally arranged grand forms. The rolling mass of a thundercloud, marked by breaks and enhanced by spirals, yet consolidating all into its broad, torrid, towering expanse, alongside its deep midnight darkness; the equally majestic lift of a mountainside, all torn and traversed by rugged depths and ridges, yet maintaining the unity of its illuminated rise and shadowy fall; and the canopy of every strong tree, rich with patterns of leaves and branches, yet defined against the sky by a true line and framed by a green horizon, which, multiplied in a distant forest, creates a bulging appearance from above; all of these highlight a significant and esteemed principle: the diffusion of light for which the Byzantine ornaments were crafted. They show us that those builders had a deeper connection to what is magnificent in nature than the self-satisfied Greek. I recognize that they seem barbaric by comparison; however, there is a strength in their barbarism that is more somber, a power that is not superficial or penetrating, but all-encompassing and mysterious; a force more devoted than reflective, which felt and conceived more than it crafted; a force that neither understood nor controlled itself, but flowed and roamed freely, like mountain streams and winds; and which could not settle on expressing or capturing finite form. It could not confine itself to acanthus leaves. Its imagery was drawn from the shadows of storms and hills and resonated with the day and night of the earth itself.

XVI. I have endeavored to give some idea of one of the hollow balls of stone which, surrounded by flowing leafage, occur in varied succession on the architrave of the central gate of St. Mark's at Venice, in Plate I. fig. 2. It seems to me singularly beautiful in its unity of lightness, and delicacy of detail, with breadth of light. It looks as if its leaves had been sensitive, and had risen and shut themselves into a bud at some sudden touch, and would presently fall back again into their wild flow. The cornices of San Michele of Lucca, seen above and below the arch, in Plate VI., show the effect of heavy leafage and thick stems arranged on a surface whose curve is a simple quadrant, the light dying from off them as it turns. It would be difficult, as I think, to invent anything more noble; and I insist on the broad character of their arrangement the more earnestly, because, afterwards modified by greater skill in its management, it became characteristic of the richest pieces of Gothic design. The capital, given in[Pg 88] Plate V., is of the noblest period of the Venetian Gothic; and it is interesting to see the play of leafage so luxuriant, absolutely subordinated to the breadth of two masses of light and shade. What is done by the Venetian architect, with a power as irresistible as that of the waves of his surrounding sea, is done by the masters of the Cis-Alpine Gothic, more timidly, and with a manner somewhat cramped and cold, but not less expressing their assent to the same great law. The ice spiculæ of the North, and its broken sunshine, seem to have image in, and influence on the work; and the leaves which, under the Italian's hand, roll, and flow, and bow down over their black shadows, as in the weariness of noon-day heat, are, in the North, crisped and frost-bitten, wrinkled on the edges, and sparkling as if with dew. But the rounding of the ruling form is not less sought and felt. In the lower part of Plate I. is the finial of the pediment given in Plate II., from the cathedral of St. Lo. It is exactly similar in feeling to the Byzantine capital, being rounded under the abacus by four branches of thistle leaves, whose stems, springing from the angles, bend outwards and fall back to the head, throwing their jaggy spines down upon the full light, forming two sharp quatre-foils. I could not get near enough to this finial to see with what degree of delicacy the spines were cut; but I have sketched a natural group of thistle-leaves beside it, that the reader may compare the types, and see with what mastery they are subjected to the broad form of the whole. The small capital from Coutances, Plate XIII. fig. 4, which is of earlier date, is of simpler elements, and exhibits the principle still more clearly; but the St. Lo finial is only one of a thousand instances which might be gathered even from the fully developed flamboyant, the feeling of breadth being retained in minor ornaments long after it had been lost in the main design, and sometimes capriciously renewing itself throughout, as in the cylindrical niches and pedestals which enrich the porches of Caudebec and Rouen. Fig. 1, Plate I. is the simplest of those of Rouen; in the more elaborate there are four projecting sides, divided by buttresses into eight rounded compartments of tracery; even the whole bulk of the outer pier is treated with the same feeling; and though composed partly of concave recesses, partly of square shafts, partly of statues and tabernacle work, arranges itself as a whole into one richly rounded tower.

XVI. I’ve tried to give an idea of one of the hollow stone spheres that appear in varying sequences on the architrave of the central gate of St. Mark's in Venice, as shown in Plate I, fig. 2. It seems extraordinarily beautiful in its lightness and delicate details, complemented by broad areas of light. It looks as if the leaves were sensitive, having risen and closed into a bud at a sudden touch, ready to fall back into their wild arrangement. The cornices of San Michele in Lucca, seen above and below the arch in Plate VI, demonstrate the effect of heavy foliage and thick stems laid out on a surface that forms a simple quadrant, with light fading off them as it curves away. I believe it would be hard to envision anything more noble. I emphasize the broad character of their arrangement because it was later refined through greater skill, becoming a hallmark of the richest Gothic designs. The capital shown in Plate V is from the finest period of Venetian Gothic; its lush play of leaves is beautifully subordinated to the contrast of two masses of light and shade. What the Venetian architect achieves, with a force as compelling as the surrounding sea, is done by the masters of the Cis-Alpine Gothic, albeit more timidly and in a somewhat constrained and cooler manner, yet still adhering to the same great principles. The ice spikes of the North, with its fragmented sunlight, seem to leave an imprint and influence on the work. The leaves that, under the Italian's touch, roll, flow, and sag over their deep shadows as if worn out by midday heat, in the North appear crisp and frost-bitten, with jagged edges that sparkle as if covered with dew. However, the pursuit of a harmonious form remains present. In the lower part of Plate I, there is the finial of the pediment shown in Plate II, from the cathedral of St. Lo. It shares a similar feeling to the Byzantine capital, rounded beneath the abacus by four thistle leaves, whose stems, emerging from the angles, bend outwards and then curve back towards the top, letting their jagged spines descend upon the full light, creating two sharp quatrefoils. I couldn’t get close enough to this finial to see how delicately the spines were carved, but I sketched a natural grouping of thistle leaves next to it for comparison and to illustrate how skillfully they are integrated into the overall shape. The small capital from Coutances, shown in Plate XIII, fig. 4, is earlier and is made up of simpler elements, clearly showcasing this principle; however, the St. Lo finial is just one among countless examples, even from the fully developed flamboyant style, where the sense of breadth is retained in smaller details long after it has diminished in the main design, occasionally reappearing, as in the cylindrical niches and pedestals that adorn the porches of Caudebec and Rouen. Fig. 1, Plate I, is the simplest among those from Rouen; in the more detailed ones, there are four projecting sides, divided by buttresses into eight rounded compartments of tracery; even the entire volume of the outer pier exhibits the same feeling, and though it is composed partly of concave recesses, partly of square shafts, and partly of statues and tabernacle work, it comes together as a whole into a richly rounded tower.

PLATE V. PLATE V.—(Page 88—Vol. V.)
Capital from the Lower Arcade of the Doge's Palace, Venice.

XVII. I cannot here enter into the curious questions connected with the management of larger curved surfaces; into the causes of the difference in proportion necessary to be observed between round and square towers; nor into the reasons why a column or ball may be richly ornamented, while surface decorations would be inexpedient on masses like the Castle of St. Angelo, the tomb of Cecilia Metella, or the dome of St. Peter's. But what has been above said of the desireableness of serenity in plane surfaces, applies still more forcibly to those which are curved; and it is to be remembered that we are, at present, considering how this serenity and power may be carried into minor divisions, not how the ornamental character of the lower form may, upon occasion, be permitted to fret the calmness of the higher. Nor, though the instances we have examined are of globular or cylindrical masses chiefly, is it to be thought that breadth can only be secured by such alone: many of the noblest forms are of subdued curvature, sometimes hardly visible; but curvature of some degree there must be, in order to secure any measure of grandeur in a small mass of light. One of the most marked distinctions between one artist and another, in the point of skill, will be found in their relative delicacy of perception of rounded surface; the full power of expressing the perspective, foreshortening and various undulation of such surface is, perhaps, the last and most difficult attainment of the hand and eye. For instance: there is, perhaps, no tree which has baffled the landscape painter more than the common black spruce fir. It is rare that we see any representation of it other than caricature. It is conceived as if it grew in one plane, or as a section of a tree, with a set of boughs symmetrically dependent on opposite sides. It is thought formal, unmanageable, and ugly. It would be so, if it grew as it is drawn. But the power of the tree is not in that chandelier-like section. It is in the dark, flat, solid tables of[Pg 90] leafage, which it holds out on its strong arms, curved slightly over them like shields, and spreading towards the extremity like a hand. It is vain to endeavor to paint the sharp, grassy, intricate leafage, until this ruling form has been secured; and in the boughs that approach the spectator, the foreshortening of it is like that of a wide hill country, ridge just rising over ridge in successive distances; and the finger-like extremities, foreshortened to absolute bluntness, require a delicacy in the rendering of them like that of the drawing of the hand of the Magdalene upon the vase in Mr. Rogers's Titian. Get but the back of that foliage, and you have the tree; but I cannot name the artist who has thoroughly felt it. So, in all drawing and sculpture, it is the power of rounding, softly and perfectly, every inferior mass which preserves the serenity, as it follows the truth, of Nature, and which demands the highest knowledge and skill from the workman. A noble design may always be told by the back of a single leaf, and it was the sacrifice of this breadth and refinement of surface for sharp edges and extravagant undercutting, which destroyed the Gothic mouldings, as the substitution of the line for the light destroyed the Gothic tracery. This change, however, we shall better comprehend after we have glanced at the chief conditions of arrangement of the second kind of mass; that which is flat, and of shadow only.

XVII. I can't dive into the intricate questions about managing larger curved surfaces, the reasons for the different proportions needed between round and square towers, or why a column or ball can be lavishly decorated while surface decorations wouldn't work on large structures like the Castle of St. Angelo, the tomb of Cecilia Metella, or the dome of St. Peter's. However, the importance of maintaining serenity in flat surfaces applies even more strongly to curved ones. It's important to remember that we're currently discussing how to maintain this serenity and grace in smaller divisions, rather than how the decorative aspects of lower forms can occasionally disrupt the calmness of higher ones. Also, even though we mostly looked at globular or cylindrical shapes, it's not true that breadth can only be achieved through these alone. Many of the most impressive forms have subtle curves that are sometimes barely noticeable; however, some degree of curvature is necessary to achieve any sense of grandeur in a small mass of light. One of the most significant differences between artists comes down to their sensitivity in perceiving rounded surfaces; mastering the ability to express perspective, foreshortening, and the various undulations of such surfaces is possibly the last and most challenging skill to develop. For example, few trees have challenged landscape painters as much as the common black spruce. It's rare to see a depiction of it that isn’t a caricature. People tend to visualize it as if it grows flat, with boughs symmetrically hanging from opposite sides. It’s considered formal, unmanageable, and unattractive. It would be that way if it grew as depicted. But the tree's strength lies not in that chandelier-like silhouette. It's found in the dark, flat, solid layers of foliage that it extends on its strong branches, slightly arched over them like shields, and spreading out at the tips like a hand. It’s pointless to try to paint the detailed, sharp, intricate leaves until that dominant form has been captured. In the branches facing the viewer, the foreshortening resembles a rolling landscape, with ridge upon ridge appearing in the distance; and the finger-like tips, shortened to a blunt end, require the same delicate rendering as the hand of Mary Magdalene on the vase in Mr. Rogers's version of Titian. If you capture the back of that foliage, you have the tree, but I can't name an artist who has truly felt that. Similarly, in all drawing and sculpture, the ability to round every smaller mass softly and perfectly maintains the serenity that reflects the truth of nature and demands the highest level of knowledge and skill from the artist. A noble design can always be recognized by the back of a single leaf, and it was the loss of this breadth and refined surface in favor of sharp edges and extravagant undercutting that caused the decline of Gothic moldings, just as replacing light with line destroyed Gothic tracery. We'll better understand this shift after we examine the main conditions for arranging the second type of mass, which is flat and made up purely of shadow.

PLATE VI. PLATE VI.—(Page 90—Vol. V.)
Arch from the front of the Church of San Michele in Lucca.

XVIII. We have noted above how the wall surface, composed of rich materials, and covered with costly work, in modes which we shall examine in the next Chapter, became a subject of peculiar interest to the Christian architects. Its broad flat lights could only be made valuable by points or masses of energetic shadow, which were obtained by the Romanesque architect by means of ranges of recessed arcade, in the management of which, however, though all the effect depends upon the shadow so obtained, the eye is still, as in classical architecture, caused to dwell upon the projecting columns, capitals, and wall, as in Plate VI. But with the enlargement of the window, which, in the Lombard and Romanesque churches, is usually little more than an arched slit, came the conception of the simpler mode of decoration, by penetrations [Pg 91] which, seen from within, are forms of light, and, from without, are forms of shade. In Italian traceries the eye is exclusively fixed upon the dark forms of the penetrations, and the whole proportion and power of the design are caused to depend upon them. The intermediate spaces are, indeed, in the most perfect early examples, filled with elaborate ornament; but this ornament was so subdued as never to disturb the simplicity and force of the dark masses; and in many instances is entirely wanting. The composition of the whole depends on the proportioning and shaping of the darks; and it is impossible that anything can be more exquisite than their placing in the head window of the Giotto campanile, Plate IX., or the church of Or San Michele. So entirely does the effect depend upon them, that it is quite useless to draw Italian tracery in outline; if with any intention of rendering its effect, it is better to mark the black spots, and let the rest alone. Of course, when it is desired to obtain an accurate rendering of the design, its lines and mouldings are enough; but it often happens that works on architecture are of little use, because they afford the reader no means of judging of the effective intention of the arrangements which they state. No person, looking at an architectural drawing of the richly foliaged cusps and intervals of Or San Michele, would understand that all this sculpture was extraneous, was a mere added grace, and had nothing to do with the real anatomy of the work, and that by a few bold cuttings through a slab of stone he might reach the main effect of it all at once. I have, therefore, in the plate of the design of Giotto, endeavored especially to mark these points of purpose; there, as in every other instance, black shadows of a graceful form lying on the white surface of the stone, like dark leaves laid upon snow. Hence, as before observed, the universal name of foil applied to such ornaments.

XVIII. As mentioned earlier, the wall surface, made of rich materials and adorned with costly work, will be a focus of special interest for Christian architects, which we’ll explore in the next chapter. Its broad flat areas could only become valuable by introducing energetic shadows, which the Romanesque architect achieved with rows of recessed arcades. However, even though the overall effect rests on these shadows, the eye still, as in classical architecture, is drawn to the projecting columns, capitals, and walls, as shown in Plate VI. But with the larger windows, which in Lombard and Romanesque churches are typically just arched slits, came the idea of simpler decoration through openings that, from the inside, create forms of light and, from the outside, create forms of shade. In Italian traceries, the eye focuses entirely on the dark shapes of the openings, and the overall proportion and impact of the design depend on them. The spaces in between are often filled with intricate ornamentation in the most perfect early examples, but this ornamentation is so subtle that it never disrupts the simplicity and strength of the dark masses; in many cases, it is entirely absent. The overall composition relies on the proportion and shaping of these dark areas, and nothing could be more exquisite than their arrangement in the head window of the Giotto campanile, Plate IX, or in the church of Or San Michele. The effect relies so heavily on them that it’s pointless to draw Italian tracery in outline; if you want to capture its effect, it’s better to highlight the dark spots and leave the rest out. Naturally, if you want an accurate depiction of the design, its lines and moldings are sufficient; but often, architectural works are not very helpful because they provide no insight into the intended impact of the arrangements they describe. Anyone looking at an architectural drawing of the richly decorated cusps and intervals of Or San Michele wouldn’t understand that all this sculpture is extraneous, just an added grace, and unrelated to the actual structure; with just a few bold cuts through a stone slab, one could instantly reach the main effect. Therefore, in the design plate of Giotto, I've made a particular effort to highlight these points of purpose; as in every other instance, dark shadows of graceful forms resting on the white stone surface resemble dark leaves on snow. Hence, as previously noted, the term "foil" is universally applied to such ornaments.

XIX. In order to the obtaining their full effect, it is evident that much caution is necessary in the management of the glass. In the finest instances, the traceries are open lights, either in towers, as in this design of Giotto's or in external arcades like that of the Campo Santo at Pisa or the Doge's[Pg 92] palace at Venice; and it is thus only that their full beauty is shown. In domestic buildings, or in windows of churches necessarily glazed, the glass was usually withdrawn entirely behind the traceries. Those of the Cathedral of Florence stand quite clear of it, casting their shadows in well detached lines, so as in most lights to give the appearance of a double tracery. In those few instances in which the glass was set in the tracery itself, as in Or San Michele, the effect of the latter is half destroyed: perhaps the especial attention paid by Orgagna to his surface ornament, was connected with the intention of so glazing them. It is singular to see, in late architecture, the glass, which tormented the older architects, considered as a valuable means of making the lines of tracery more slender; as in the smallest intervals of the windows of Merton College, Oxford, where the glass is advanced about two inches from the centre of the tracery bar (that in the larger spaces being in the middle, as usual), in order to prevent the depth of shadow from farther diminishing the apparent interval. Much of the lightness of the effect of the traceries is owing to this seemingly unimportant arrangement. But, generally speaking, glass spoils all traceries; and it is much to be wished that it should be kept well within them, when it cannot be dispensed with, and that the most careful and beautiful designs should be reserved for situations where no glass would be needed.

XIX. To achieve their full effect, it’s clear that you need to handle the glass with a lot of care. In the best examples, the traceries are open lights, whether in towers, like in Giotto's design, or in external arcades like those of the Campo Santo in Pisa or the Doge's palace in Venice; this is the only way their true beauty is revealed. In homes or in church windows that must be glazed, the glass was usually set back completely behind the traceries. The ones in the Cathedral of Florence stand clear of it, casting their shadows in distinct lines, which often gives the illusion of a double tracery. In the rare cases where the glass was placed within the tracery itself, like in Or San Michele, it somewhat undermines the tracery's effect; perhaps Orgagna's particular focus on his surface ornamentation was meant to accommodate this glazing. It's interesting to note that in later architecture, glass, which troubled earlier architects, is now seen as a valuable tool for making the tracery lines appear more delicate; for instance, in the narrow sections of the windows at Merton College, Oxford, where the glass is set about two inches forward from the center of the tracery bar (with the larger spaces having the glass positioned in the middle, as usual), to avoid the depth of shadow from further reducing the apparent space. A lot of the lightness of the traceries comes from this seemingly minor adjustment. However, as a general rule, glass detracts from all traceries; it’s preferable that it be kept well within them when it can't be avoided, and that the most careful and beautiful designs be reserved for places where glass isn't needed.

XX. The method of decoration by shadow was, as far as we have hitherto traced it, common to the northern and southern Gothic. But in the carrying out of the system they instantly diverged. Having marble at his command, and classical decoration in his sight, the southern architect was able to carve the intermediate spaces with exquisite leafage, or to vary his wall surface with inlaid stones. The northern architect neither knew the ancient work, nor possessed the delicate material; and he had no resource but to cover his walls with holes, cut into foiled shapes like those of the windows. This he did, often with great clumsiness, but always with a vigorous sense of composition, and always, observe, depending on the shadows for effect. Where the wall was thick and could [Pg 93] not be cut through, and the foilings were large, those shadows did not fill the entire space; but the form was, nevertheless, drawn on the eye by means of them, and when it was possible, they were cut clear through, as in raised screens of pediment, like those on the west front of Bayeux; cut so deep in every case, as to secure, in all but a direct low front light, great breadth of shadow.

XX. The method of decoration using shadows was, as we've seen so far, common to both northern and southern Gothic styles. However, in implementing this method, they quickly diverged. With marble at their disposal and classical decorations in view, southern architects were able to carve beautiful leaf patterns in the spaces and embellish their wall surfaces with inlaid stones. The northern architect, lacking knowledge of ancient designs and not having access to such delicate materials, could only cover their walls with openings shaped like the foils of windows. They often did this with a rough hand, but always with a strong sense of composition, relying on the shadows for impact. When the wall was thick and couldn't be cut through, and the foilings were large, those shadows didn’t fill the entire area; still, the shapes were suggested to the eye through them, and whenever feasible, they were cut all the way through, like raised screens on pediments, similar to those on the west front of Bayeux; cut deep enough in every case to create a wide shadow, except when viewed directly from the front.

PLATE VII. PLATE VII.—(Page 93—Vol. V.)
Pierced Ornaments from Lisieux, Bayeux, Verona, and Padua.

The spandril, given at the top of Plate VII., is from the southwestern entrance of the Cathedral of Lisieux; one of the most quaint and interesting doors in Normandy, probably soon to be lost forever, by the continuance of the masonic operations which have already destroyed the northern tower. Its work is altogether rude, but full of spirit; the opposite spandrils have different, though balanced, ornaments very inaccurately adjusted, each rosette or star (as the five-rayed figure, now quite defaced, in the upper portion appears to have been) cut on its own block of stone and fitted in with small nicety, especially illustrating the point I have above insisted upon—the architect's utter neglect of the forms of intermediate stone, at this early period.

The spandril shown at the top of Plate VII is from the southwestern entrance of the Cathedral of Lisieux, one of the most charming and interesting doors in Normandy, which is likely to be lost forever due to ongoing masonry work that has already destroyed the northern tower. Its craftsmanship is quite rough but bursting with character; the opposite spandrils have different, yet balanced, decorations that are poorly aligned. Each rosette or star (like the five-rayed figure, now quite worn, in the upper part) was carved on its own stone block and fitted with some precision, especially highlighting the point I mentioned earlier— the architect's complete disregard for the shapes of the stones in between during this early period.

The arcade, of which a single arch and shaft are given on the left, forms the flank of the door; three outer shafts bearing three orders within the spandril which I have drawn, and each of these shafts carried over an inner arcade, decorated above with quatre-foils, cut concave and filled with leaves, the whole disposition exquisitely picturesque and full of strange play of light and shade.

The arcade, shown with a single arch and shaft on the left, makes up the side of the door; three outer shafts support three levels within the spandrel that I’ve illustrated, and each of these shafts is topped with an inner arcade, adorned above with quatrefoils, cut concave and filled with leaves. The entire arrangement is beautifully picturesque and has a fascinating interplay of light and shadow.

For some time the penetrative ornaments, if so they may be for convenience called, maintained their bold and independent character. Then they multiplied and enlarged, becoming shallower as they did so; then they began to run together, one swallowing up, or hanging on to, another, like bubbles in expiring foam—fig. 4, from a spandril at Bayeux, looks as if it had been blown from a pipe; finally, they lost their individual character altogether, and the eye was made to rest on the separating lines of tracery, as we saw before in the window; and then came the great change and the fall of the Gothic power.[Pg 94]

For a while, the distinctive ornaments, if that's a convenient term, kept their striking and unique style. Then they started to multiply and grow larger, becoming shallower in the process; eventually, they began to merge, one consuming or clinging to another, like bubbles in fading foam—fig. 4, from a spandril at Bayeux, looks like it was formed from a pipe; finally, they lost all individual characteristics, and the viewer's focus shifted to the lines of tracery separating them, just like we saw earlier in the window; then came the significant change and the decline of Gothic influence.[Pg 94]

XXI. Figs. 2 and 3, the one a quadrant of the star window of the little chapel close to St. Anastasia at Verona, and the other a very singular example from the church of the Eremitani at Padua, compared with fig. 5, one of the ornaments of the transept towers of Rouen, show the closely correspondent conditions of the early Northern and Southern Gothic.10 But, as we have said, the Italian architects, not being embarrassed for decoration of wall surface, and not being obliged, like the Northmen, to multiply their penetrations, held to the system for some time longer; and while they increased the refinement of the ornament, kept the purity of the plan. That refinement of ornament was their weak point, however, and opened the way for the renaissance attack. They fell, like the old Romans, by their luxury, except in the separate instance of the magnificent school of Venice. That architecture began with the luxuriance in which all others expired: it founded itself on the Byzantine mosaic and fretwork; and laying aside its ornaments, one by one, while it fixed its forms by laws more and more severe, stood forth, at last, a model of domestic Gothic, so grand, so complete, so nobly systematised, that, to my mind, there never existed an architecture with so stern a claim to our reverence. I do not except even the Greek Doric; the Doric had cast nothing away; the fourteenth century Venetian had cast away, one by one, for a succession of centuries, every splendor that art and wealth could give it. It had laid down its crown and its jewels, its gold and its color, like a king disrobing; it had resigned its exertion, like an athlete reposing; once capricious and fantastic, it had bound itself by laws inviolable and serene as those of nature herself. It retained nothing but its beauty and its power; both the highest, but both restrained. The Doric flutings were of irregular number—the Venetian mouldings were unchangeable. The Doric manner of ornament admitted no temptation, it was the fasting of an anchorite—the Venetian ornament embraced, while it governed, all vegetable and animal forms; it was the temperance of a man, the command of Adam over creation. I do not know so magnificent a marking of human authority as the iron grasp of the Venetian [Pg 95] over his own exuberance of imagination; the calm and solemn restraint with which, his mind filled with thoughts of flowing leafage and fiery life, he gives those thoughts expression for an instant, and then withdraws within those massy bars and level cusps of stone.11

XXI. Figs. 2 and 3 show a section of the star window from the small chapel near St. Anastasia in Verona, and the other is a unique example from the church of the Eremitani in Padua. When compared to fig. 5, an ornament from the transept towers of Rouen, we can see the similar styles between early Northern and Southern Gothic. However, as mentioned before, Italian architects, free from the need to decorate their wall surfaces and not required, like those in the North, to create many openings, adhered to their design principles for a while longer. They refined their ornamentation while maintaining the clarity of their overall layouts. This emphasis on ornamentation, though, became their vulnerability, allowing the Renaissance to take root. They fell into luxury much like the ancient Romans, except for the exceptional case of the grand Venetian school. This architectural style began with an opulence that marked the end of other styles: it was based on Byzantine mosaics and intricate designs, gradually shedding its decorations while adhering to stricter forms. Ultimately, it emerged as a pinnacle of domestic Gothic architecture—grand, complete, and beautifully organized—that I believe deserves our utmost admiration. I make this claim even in comparison to the Greek Doric; unlike the Doric, which discarded nothing, the Venetian style relinquished each decoration, one after another, over many centuries, every luxury that art and wealth could provide. It stripped away its crown and jewels, its gold and color, like a king undressing; it surrendered its vigor, like an athlete resting. Once whimsical and elaborate, it bound itself to unbreakable and serene laws akin to those of nature itself. It kept only its beauty and strength; both at their highest levels, yet both measured. The Doric flutings varied irregularly in number—the Venetian moldings were consistent. The Doric style of decoration bore no temptation; it was the self-denial of a hermit—while the Venetian ornament embraced, yet controlled, all forms of nature; it represented a human's self-discipline, an Adam-like mastery over creation. I don't know of a more impressive demonstration of human authority than the Venetian's firm control over his own imaginative excess. With calm and solemn restraint, filled with visions of flowing leaves and vibrant life, he briefly gives those visions form before retreating behind solid stone barriers and defined edges.

PLATE VIII. PLATE VIII.—(Page 95—Vol. V.)
Window from the Ca' Foscari, Venice.

And his power to do this depended altogether on his retaining the forms of the shadows in his sight. Far from carrying the eye to the ornaments, upon the stone, he abandoned these latter one by one; and while his mouldings received the most shapely order and symmetry, closely correspondent with that of the Rouen tracery, compare Plates III. and VIII., he kept the cusps within them perfectly flat, decorated, if at all, with a trefoil (Palazzo Foscari), or fillet (Doge's Palace) just traceable and no more, so that the quatrefoil, cut as sharply through them as if it had been struck out by a stamp, told upon the eye, with all its four black leaves, miles away. No knots of flowerwork, no ornaments of any kind, were suffered to interfere with the purity of its form: the cusp is usually quite sharp; but slightly truncated in the Palazzo Foscari, and charged with a simple ball in that of the Doge; and the glass of the window, where there was any, was, as we have seen, thrown back behind the stone-work, that no flashes of light might interfere with its depth. Corrupted forms, like those of the Casa d'Oro and Palazzo Pisani, and several others, only serve to show the majesty of the common design.

His ability to do this entirely depended on him keeping the shapes of the shadows in view. Instead of focusing on the decorative elements on the stone, he let them go one by one. While his moldings gained a beautiful form and symmetry, closely matching that of the Rouen tracery, as shown in Plates III. and VIII., he kept the cusps perfectly flat, only occasionally adding a trefoil (Palazzo Foscari) or a barely noticeable fillet (Doge's Palace) so that the quatrefoil, sharply cut through them as if stamped out, stood out with all its four black leaves, visible from a distance. No intertwining floral designs or decorations of any kind were allowed to disrupt the purity of its shape: the cusp is generally quite sharp, but slightly trimmed in the Palazzo Foscari, and topped with a simple ball in the Doge's. The glass in the window, when present, was set back behind the stonework to prevent any flashes of light from distracting from its depth. Deformed designs, like those of the Casa d'Oro and Palazzo Pisani, among others, only highlight the grandeur of the standard pattern.

XXII. Such are the principal circumstances traceable in the treatment of the two kinds of masses of light and darkness, in the hands of the earlier architects; gradation in the one, flatness in the other, and breadth in both, being the qualities sought and exhibited by every possible expedient, up to the period when, as we have before stated, the line was substituted for the mass, as the means of division of surface. Enough has been said to illustrate this, as regards tracery; but a word or two is still necessary respecting the mouldings.

XXII. These are the main factors found in how the early architects handled two types of light and dark elements: they aimed for gradation in one, flatness in the other, and breadth in both. They used every possible method to achieve these qualities until, as mentioned earlier, lines replaced masses as the way to divide surfaces. We've covered enough about this in terms of tracery, but a few more words are needed regarding the moldings.

Those of the earlier times were, in the plurality of instances, composed of alternate square and cylindrical shafts, variously associated and proportioned. Where concave cuttings occur,[Pg 96] as in the beautiful west doors of Bayeux, they are between cylindrical shafts, which they throw out into broad light. The eye in all cases dwells on broad surfaces, and commonly upon few. In course of time, a low ridgy process is seen emerging along the outer edge of the cylindrical shaft, forming a line of light upon it and destroying its gradation. Hardly traceable at first (as on the alternate rolls of the north door of Rouen), it grows and pushes out as gradually as a stag's horns: sharp at first on the edge; but, becoming prominent, it receives a truncation, and becomes a definite fillet on the face of the roll. Not yet to be checked, it pushes forward until the roll itself becomes subordinate to it, and is finally lost in a slight swell upon its sides, while the concavities have all the time been deepening and enlarging behind it, until, from a succession of square or cylindrical masses, the whole moulding has become a series of concavities edged by delicate fillets, upon which (sharp lines of light, observe) the eye exclusively rests. While this has been taking place, a similar, though less total, change has affected the flowerwork itself. In Plate I. fig. 2 (a), I have given two from the transepts of Rouen. It will be observed how absolutely the eye rests on the forms of the leaves, and on the three berries in the angle, being in light exactly what the trefoil is in darkness. These mouldings nearly adhere to the stone; and are very slightly, though sharply, undercut. In process of time, the attention of the architect, instead of resting on the leaves, went to the stalks. These latter were elongated (b, from the south door of St. Lo); and to exhibit them better, the deep concavity was cut behind, so as to throw them out in lines of light. The system was carried out into continually increasing intricacy, until, in the transepts of Beauvais, we have brackets and flamboyant traceries, composed of twigs without any leaves at all. This, however, is a partial, though a sufficiently characteristic, caprice, the leaf being never generally banished, and in the mouldings round those same doors, beautifully managed, but itself rendered liny by bold marking of its ribs and veins, and by turning up, and crisping its edges, large intermediate spaces being always left to be occupied by intertwining stems (c, from Caudebec).[Pg 97] The trefoil of light formed by berries or acorns, though diminished in value, was never lost up to the last period of living Gothic.

Those from earlier times were mostly made of alternating square and cylindrical shafts, arranged and proportioned in various ways. Where there are concave cuttings, like in the beautiful west doors of Bayeux, they are set between cylindrical shafts, which they illuminate with broad light. The eye in all cases focuses on broad surfaces, usually just a few. Over time, a low ridged process appears along the outer edge of the cylindrical shaft, creating a line of light on it and disrupting its gradation. It’s barely noticeable at first (as seen on the alternating rolls of the north door of Rouen), but it grows and extends gradually like a stag's antlers: sharp at first along the edge; but as it becomes more prominent, it gets truncated and turns into a distinct fillet on the face of the roll. Unstoppable, it keeps pushing forward until the roll itself becomes secondary to it and eventually blends into a slight swell on its sides, while the concavities continuously deepen and expand behind it. From a series of square or cylindrical shapes, the entire molding transforms into a sequence of concavities framed by delicate fillets, on which (sharp lines of light, take note) the eye rests exclusively. While this change was happening, a similar, though less complete, transformation occurred with the flowerwork itself. In Plate I. fig. 2 (a), I’ve shown two from the transepts of Rouen. You’ll notice how completely the eye focuses on the shapes of the leaves and the three berries in the corner, illuminated in contrast to the darkness of the trefoil. These moldings nearly cling to the stone and are only slightly, though sharply, undercut. Over time, the architect's attention shifted from the leaves to the stalks. The latter were elongated (b, from the south door of St. Lo); and to showcase them better, a deep concavity was cut behind to highlight them in lines of light. This system became increasingly complex, until in the transepts of Beauvais, we see brackets and flamboyant traceries made of twigs without any leaves at all. However, this is just a partial, though quite distinctive, whim, as leaves were never entirely removed. In the moldings around those same doors, they were beautifully crafted but made to appear line-like by bold highlighting of their ribs and veins, and by curling up and crisping their edges, leaving large gaps occupied by intertwining stems (c, from Caudebec).[Pg 97] The trefoil of light created by berries or acorns, although diminished in significance, was never completely lost up until the final period of living Gothic.

XXIII. It is interesting to follow into its many ramifications, the influence of the corrupting principle; but we have seen enough of it to enable us to draw our practical conclusion—a conclusion a thousand times felt and reiterated in the experience and advice of every practised artist, but never often enough repeated, never profoundly enough felt. Of composition and invention much has been written, it seems to me vainly, for men cannot be taught to compose or to invent; of these, the highest elements of Power in architecture, I do not, therefore, speak; nor, here, of that peculiar restraint in the imitation of natural forms, which constitutes the dignity of even the most luxuriant work of the great periods. Of this restraint I shall say a word or two in the next Chapter; pressing now only the conclusion, as practically useful as it is certain, that the relative majesty of buildings depends more on the weight and vigor of their masses than on any other attribute of their design: mass of everything, of bulk, of light, of darkness, of color, not mere sum of any of these, but breadth of them; not broken light, nor scattered darkness, nor divided weight, but solid stone, broad sunshine, starless shade. Time would fail me altogether, if I attempted to follow out the range of the principle; there is not a feature, however apparently trifling, to which it cannot give power. The wooden fillings of belfry lights, necessary to protect their interiors from rain, are in England usually divided into a number of neatly executed cross-bars, like those of Venetian blinds, which, of course, become as conspicuous in their sharpness as they are uninteresting in their precise carpentry, multiplying, moreover, the horizontal lines which directly contradict those of the architecture. Abroad, such necessities are met by three or four downright penthouse roofs, reaching each from within the window to the outside shafts of its mouldings; instead of the horrible row of ruled lines, the space is thus divided into four or five grand masses of shadow, with grey slopes of roof above, bent or yielding into all kinds of delicious swells and[Pg 98] curves, and covered with warm tones of moss and lichen. Very often the thing is more delightful than the stone-work itself, and all because it is broad, dark, and simple. It matters not how clumsy, how common, the means are, that get weight and shadow—sloping roof, jutting porch, projecting balcony, hollow niche, massy gargoyle, frowning parapet; get but gloom and simplicity, and all good things will follow in their place and time; do but design with the owl's eyes first, and you will gain the falcon's afterwards.

XXIII. It's interesting to explore all the different ways the corrupting principle influences things, but we’ve seen enough to make our practical conclusion—a conclusion that every experienced artist feels and repeats a thousand times, yet is never said often enough or deeply enough understood. A lot has been written about composition and invention, but it seems to me it’s pointless because you can’t really teach someone to compose or invent; therefore, I won’t discuss these highest powers of architecture here. I also won’t comment on the unique restraint needed in mimicking natural forms, which gives dignity to even the most elaborate works from great periods. I’ll touch on this restraint briefly in the next chapter, but for now, I want to emphasize the practical conclusion that the true majesty of buildings relies more on the weight and power of their masses than on any other aspect of their design: the mass of everything—bulk, light, darkness, color—not just the total of these elements but their breadth; not fragmented light, scattered darkness, or divided weight, but solid stone, broad sunlight, and starless shade. I would run out of time if I tried to explore the full range of this principle; there’s not a single detail, however insignificant it may seem, that it can’t enhance. In England, the wooden supports for belfry lights, which are necessary to keep the rain out, are usually made with several neatly crafted crossbars, like Venetian blinds. Unfortunately, these become overly sharp and uninteresting in their exact craftsmanship, adding horizontal lines that contradict the architecture. In other countries, these needs are met with a few straightforward sloped roofs, extending from inside the window to the outer moldings. Instead of a terrible row of straight lines, this creates four or five large shadows, with grey sloped roofs that soften into beautiful shapes and curves, covered with warm tones of moss and lichen. Often, this is more appealing than the stone work itself, simply because it’s broad, dark, and simple. It doesn’t matter how awkward or basic the methods are that create weight and shadow—sloped roofs, jutting porches, projecting balconies, hollow niches, solid gargoyles, or frowning parapets; as long as you achieve gloom and simplicity, all good things will fall into place eventually. Start designing with the perspective of an owl, and you’ll gain the insight of a falcon later.

XXIV. I am grieved to have to insist upon what seems so simple; it looks trite and commonplace when it is written, but pardon me this: for it is anything but an accepted or understood principle in practice, and the less excusably forgotten, because it is, of all the great and true laws of art, the easiest to obey. The executive facility of complying with its demands cannot be too earnestly, too frankly asserted. There are not five men in the kingdom who could compose, not twenty who could cut, the foliage with which the windows of Or San Michele are adorned; but there is many a village clergyman who could invent and dispose its black openings, and not a village mason who could not cut them. Lay a few clover or wood-roof leaves on white paper, and a little alteration in their positions will suggest figures which, cut boldly through a slab of marble, would be worth more window traceries than an architect could draw in a summer's day. There are few men in the world who could design a Greek capital; there are few who could not produce some vigor of effect with leaf designs on Byzantine block: few who could design a Palladian front, or a flamboyant pediment; many who could build a square mass like the Strozzi palace. But I know not how it is, unless that our English hearts have more oak than stone in them, and have more filial sympathy with acorns than Alps; but all that we do is small and mean, if not worse—thin, and wasted, and unsubstantial. It is not modern work only; we have built like frogs and mice since the thirteenth century (except only in our castles). What a contrast between the pitiful little pigeon-holes which stand for doors in the east front of Salisbury, looking like the entrances to a bee[Pg 99]hive or a wasp's nest, and the soaring arches and kingly crowning of the gates of Abbeville, Rouen, and Rheims, or the rock-hewn piers of Chartres, or the dark and vaulted porches and writhed pillars of Verona! Of domestic architecture what need is there to speak? How small, how cramped, how poor, how miserable in its petty neatness is our best! how beneath the mark of attack, and the level of contempt, that which is common with us! What a strange sense of formalised deformity, of shrivelled precision, of starved accuracy, of minute misanthropy have we, as we leave even the rude streets of Picardy for the market towns of Kent! Until that street architecture of ours is bettered, until we give it some size and boldness, until we give our windows recess, and our walls thickness, I know not how we can blame our architects for their feebleness in more important work; their eyes are inured to narrowness and slightness: can we expect them at a word to conceive and deal with breadth and solidity? They ought not to live in our cities; there is that in their miserable walls which bricks up to death men's imaginations, as surely as ever perished forsworn nun. An architect should live as little in cities as a painter. Send him to our hills, and let him study there what nature understands by a buttress, and what by a dome. There was something in the old power of architecture, which it had from the recluse more than from the citizen. The buildings of which I have spoken with chief praise, rose, indeed, out of the war of the piazza, and above the fury of the populace: and Heaven forbid that for such cause we should ever have to lay a larger stone, or rivet a firmer bar, in our England! But we have other sources of power, in the imagery of our iron coasts and azure hills; of power more pure, nor less serene, than that of the hermit spirit which once lighted with white lines of cloisters the glades of the Alpine pine, and raised into ordered spires the wild rocks of the Norman sea; which gave to the temple gate the depth and darkness of Elijah's Horeb cave; and lifted, out of the populous city, grey cliffs of lonely stone, into the midst of sailing birds and silent air.

XXIV. I’m sorry to have to emphasize what seems so simple; it looks cliché and ordinary when written down, but please forgive me for this: it’s anything but an accepted or understood principle in practice. It's even less forgivable to forget it because it's one of the great and true laws of art, and it's the easiest to follow. The ability to meet its requirements cannot be stressed enough. There aren’t five people in the country who could create, not twenty who could carve, the foliage that decorates the windows of Or San Michele; but there are many village clergymen who could design and arrange its black openings, and not a village mason who couldn't cut them. Lay a few clover or woodroof leaves on white paper, and changing their positions slightly will create shapes that, if cut boldly into a slab of marble, would be worth more in window tracery than an architect could sketch in a summer's day. There are few people in the world who could design a Greek capital; there are few who couldn’t create some striking effect with leaf designs on Byzantine blocks: few who could design a Palladian façade or a flamboyant pediment; many who could build a solid structure like the Strozzi palace. But I don't know how it is, unless our English hearts are more oak than stone, having more of a familial connection with acorns than with the Alps; everything we create feels small and inferior, if not worse—thin, wasted, and insubstantial. It’s not just modern work; we’ve built like frogs and mice since the thirteenth century (except for our castles). What a contrast between the pitiful little doorways on the east front of Salisbury, resembling entrances to a beehive or a wasp's nest, and the soaring arches and majestic gates of Abbeville, Rouen, and Rheims, or the rock-hewn piers of Chartres, or the dark and vaulted porches and twisted columns of Verona! What more is there to say about domestic architecture? How small, cramped, poor, and miserable in its trivial neatness is our best! It falls way below the standards of critique and is worthy of contempt, what is common among us! What a strange sense of formalized deformity, shriveled precision, starved accuracy, and tiny misanthropy we feel as we leave even the rough streets of Picardy for the market towns of Kent! Until our urban architecture improves, until we give it some size and boldness, until we carve recess into our windows and thickness into our walls, I don’t know how we can blame our architects for their weakness in more significant work; their eyes are accustomed to narrowness and slightness: can we expect them, on a whim, to understand and handle breadth and solidity? They shouldn’t have to work in our cities; there’s something in their miserable walls that stifles creativity, as sure as any forsworn nun has perished. An architect should live as little in cities as a painter. Send him to our hills, and let him study what nature understands as a buttress and a dome. There was something in the old power of architecture that came from hermits more than from citizens. The buildings I’ve praised rose, indeed, out of the clash of public squares, above the rage of the masses: and Heaven forbid that we should ever have to lay a larger stone or secure a firmer beam in our England for such reasons! But we have other sources of power in the imagery of our iron coasts and azure hills; a power that is purer and no less calm than the hermit spirit that once illuminated the woodland glades with white lines of cloisters and lifted the wild rocks of the Norman sea into organized spires; which gave the temple gate the depth and darkness of Elijah’s Horeb cave; and lifted, from the crowded city, grey cliffs of lonely stone, amidst flying birds and silent air.


CHAPTER IV.

THE LAMP OF BEAUTY.

I. It was stated, in the outset of the preceding chapter, that the value of architecture depended on two distinct characters: the one, the impression it receives from human power; the other, the image it bears of the natural creation. I have endeavored to show in what manner its majesty was attributable to a sympathy with the effort and trouble of human life (a sympathy as distinctly perceived in the gloom and mystery of form, as it is in the melancholy tones of sounds). I desire now to trace that happier element of its excellence, consisting in a noble rendering of images of Beauty, derived chiefly from the external appearances of organic nature.

I. It was mentioned at the beginning of the previous chapter that the value of architecture relies on two distinct aspects: one is the impression it gets from human effort, and the other is the reflection it offers of the natural world. I've tried to explain how its grandeur comes from a connection to the struggles and hard work of human life (a connection that's as clearly felt in the dark and mysterious shapes as it is in the somber sounds). Now, I want to explore that more positive aspect of its greatness, which consists of a beautiful portrayal of images drawn mainly from the outward appearances of the natural world.

It is irrelevant to our present purpose to enter into any inquiry respecting the essential causes of impressions of beauty. I have partly expressed my thoughts on this matter in a previous work, and I hope to develope them hereafter. But since all such inquiries can only be founded on the ordinary understanding of what is meant by the term Beauty, and since they presume that the feeling of mankind on this subject is universal and instinctive, I shall base my present investigation on this assumption; and only asserting that to be beautiful which I believe will be granted me to be so without dispute, I would endeavor shortly to trace the manner in which this element of delight is to be best engrafted upon architectural design, what are the purest sources from which it is to be derived, and what the errors to be avoided in its pursuit.

It doesn't serve our current purpose to explore the fundamental causes of our feelings about beauty. I've shared some of my thoughts on this in a previous work, and I plan to expand on them later. However, since all such inquiries depend on a common understanding of what we mean by the term "Beauty" and assume that people's feelings on this topic are universal and instinctive, I will base my current investigation on this assumption. By asserting that something is beautiful when I believe most would agree with me, I aim to briefly outline how this element of delight can best be integrated into architectural design, identify the purest sources from which it can be drawn, and point out the mistakes to avoid in its pursuit.

II. It will be thought that I have somewhat rashly limited the elements of architectural beauty to imitative forms. I do not mean to assert that every arrangement of line is directly suggested by a natural object; but that all beautiful lines are adaptations of those which are commonest in the external creation; that in proportion to the richness of their association, the resemblance to natural work, as a type and help, must be more closely attempted, and more clearly seen; and that be[Pg 101]yond a certain point, and that a very low one, man cannot advance in the invention of beauty, without directly imitating natural form. Thus, in the Doric temple, the triglyph and cornice are unimitative; or imitative only of artificial cuttings of wood. No one would call these members beautiful. Their influence over us is in their severity and simplicity. The fluting of the column, which I doubt not was the Greek symbol of the bark of the tree, was imitative in its origin, and feebly resembled many caniculated organic structures. Beauty is instantly felt in it, but of a low order. The decoration proper was sought in the true forms of organic life, and those chiefly human. Again: the Doric capital was unimitative; but all the beauty it had was dependent on the precision of its ovolo, a natural curve of the most frequent occurrence. The Ionic capital (to my mind, as an architectural invention, exceedingly base) nevertheless depended for all the beauty that it had on its adoption of a spiral line, perhaps the commonest of all that characterise the inferior orders of animal organism and habitation. Farther progress could not be made without a direct imitation of the acanthus leaf.

II. Some might think I've been a bit hasty in limiting the elements of architectural beauty to imitative forms. I don’t mean to say that every arrangement of lines comes directly from natural objects; rather, I believe that all beautiful lines are adaptations of those that are most common in the natural world. The richer their associations, the more closely they should resemble natural forms, serving as a type and guide. Beyond a certain point—one that's quite low—human creativity in beauty can't progress without directly imitating natural forms. For instance, in the Doric temple, the triglyph and cornice are not imitative or only reminiscent of man-made wood cuttings. No one would call these elements beautiful; their impact lies in their severity and simplicity. The fluting of the column, which I believe represented the bark of a tree, was imitative in its origin and faintly resembled various organic structures. While beauty is immediately perceived in it, it is of a lower order. The true decoration sought was found in the real forms of organic life, particularly those that are human. Furthermore, the Doric capital was not imitative, but its beauty depended on the precision of its ovolo, a natural curve that frequently appears. The Ionic capital (which I personally find to be a very basic architectural invention) gained all its beauty from its use of a spiral line, perhaps the most common feature in lower orders of animal life and habitats. Any further progress relied on a direct imitation of the acanthus leaf.

Again: the Romanesque arch is beautiful as an abstract line. Its type is always before us in that of the apparent vault of heaven, and horizon of the earth. The cylindrical pillar is always beautiful, for God has so moulded the stem of every tree that it is pleasant to the eyes. The pointed arch is beautiful; it is the termination of every leaf that shakes in summer wind, and its most fortunate associations are directly borrowed from the trefoiled grass of the field, or from the stars of its flowers. Further than this, man's invention could not reach without frank imitation. His next step was to gather the flowers themselves, and wreathe them in his capitals.

Again: the Romanesque arch is beautiful as an abstract line. Its form is always present in the apparent vault of the sky and the horizon of the earth. The cylindrical pillar is always beautiful because God designed the stem of every tree to be pleasing to the eyes. The pointed arch is beautiful; it resembles the tip of every leaf that sways in the summer breeze, and its most fortunate connections are directly taken from the trefoiled grass in the field or from the stars of its flowers. Beyond this, human creativity could only go so far without clear imitation. The next step was to gather the flowers themselves and weave them into his capitals.

III. Now, I would insist especially on the fact, of which I doubt not that further illustrations will occur to the mind of every reader, that all most lovely forms and thoughts are directly taken from natural objects; because I would fain be allowed to assume also the converse of this, namely, that forms which are not taken from natural objects must be ugly.[Pg 102] I know this is a bold assumption; but as I have not space to reason out the points wherein essential beauty of form consists, that being far too serious a work to be undertaken in a bye way, I have no other resource than to use this accidental mark or test of beauty, of whose truth the considerations which I hope hereafter to lay before the reader may assure him. I say an accidental mark, since forms are not beautiful because they are copied from nature; only it is out of the power of man to conceive beauty without her aid. I believe the reader will grant me this, even from the examples above advanced; the degree of confidence with which it is granted must attach also to his acceptance of the conclusions which will follow from it; but if it be granted frankly, it will enable me to determine a matter of very essential importance, namely, what is or is not ornament. For there are many forms of so-called decoration in architecture, habitual, and received, therefore, with approval, or at all events without any venture at expression or dislike, which I have no hesitation in asserting to be not ornament at all, but to be ugly things, the expense of which ought in truth to be set down in the architect's contract, as "For Monstrification." I believe that we regard these customary deformities with a savage complacency, as an Indian does his flesh patterns and paint (all nations being in certain degrees and senses savage). I believe that I can prove them to be monstrous, and I hope hereafter to do so conclusively; but, meantime, I can allege in defence of my persuasion nothing but this fact of their being unnatural, to which the reader must attach such weight as he thinks it deserves. There is, however, a peculiar difficulty in using this proof; it requires the writer to assume, very impertinently, that nothing is natural but what he has seen or supposes to exist. I would not do this; for I suppose there is no conceivable form or grouping of forms but in some part of the universe an example of it may be found. But I think I am justified in considering those forms to be most natural which are most frequent; or, rather, that on the shapes which in the every-day world are familiar to the eyes of men, God has stamped those characters of beauty which He has made[Pg 103] it man's nature to love; while in certain exceptional forms He has shown that the adoption of the others was not a matter of necessity, but part of the adjusted harmony of creation. I believe that thus we may reason from Frequency to Beauty and vice versâ; that knowing a thing to be frequent, we may assume it to be beautiful; and assume that which is most frequent to be most beautiful: I mean, of course, visibly frequent; for the forms of things which are hidden in caverns of the earth, or in the anatomy of animal frames, are evidently not intended by their Maker to bear the habitual gaze of man. And, again, by frequency I mean that limited and isolated frequency which is characteristic of all perfection; not mere multitude: as a rose is a common flower, but yet there are not so many roses on the tree as there are leaves. In this respect Nature is sparing of her highest, and lavish of her less, beauty; but I call the flower as frequent as the leaf, because, each in its allotted quantity, where the one is, there will ordinarily be the other.

III. I want to emphasize that all beautiful forms and ideas come directly from nature; I hope every reader will recognize this. I also want to propose the opposite: forms that don't come from nature must be ugly. I know this is a bold statement, but I don't have the space to thoroughly discuss what true beauty of form is, as that would require a much more serious discussion. Instead, I can only rely on this incidental marker or test of beauty, which I hope to support with arguments in the future. I call it an incidental marker because forms aren't beautiful just because they're inspired by nature; it's simply beyond human ability to envision beauty without nature's influence. I believe the reader will agree with me, based on the examples I’ve provided. The level of confidence granted in this statement will influence how readily the reader accepts the conclusions that follow. But if this is accepted openly, it will help me define a critical issue: what counts as ornamentation. There are many forms of decoration in architecture that are commonly accepted without a second thought or any expression of dislike, which I assert are not ornamentation at all but rather ugly elements. The cost of these should honestly be included in the architect's contract as "For Monstrification." I think we look at these habitual deformities with a savage satisfaction, similar to how an Indian might view his body art (since all cultures have some degree of savagery). I believe I can demonstrate they are monstrous, and I hope to do so definitively in the future. In the meantime, I can only support my view by stating that they are unnatural, and the weight given to this will depend on the reader's judgment. However, using this proof is tricky; it means the writer must arrogantly assume that nothing is natural except what he has seen or believes exists. I don't want to do that, as I believe there’s likely no conceivable shape or combination of shapes that doesn’t have an example somewhere in the universe. Still, I feel justified in considering those forms to be the most natural that are the most common; more specifically, that the shapes familiar to our daily lives carry the beauty that God has designed for us to appreciate. In contrast, exceptional forms demonstrate that adopting others wasn’t essential but rather part of the harmonious balance of creation. I believe that from frequency we can conclude beauty and vice versa; that if we know something is frequent, we can assume it's beautiful, and the most common must be the most beautiful. I refer here to forms that are visually frequent; those hidden in caves or within animal bodies clearly aren’t meant for humans to see regularly. Additionally, by frequency, I mean the specific kind associated with perfection, not just sheer quantity: a rose is a common flower, but there aren't as many roses on a tree as there are leaves. In this sense, nature holds back on her finest beauty while being generous with the lesser. However, I consider flowers as frequent as leaves because, within their typical amounts, where one is found, the other usually is too.

IV. The first so-called ornament, then, which I would attack is that Greek fret, now, I believe, usually known by the Italian name Guilloche, which is exactly a case in point. It so happens that in crystals of bismuth formed by the unagitated cooling of the melted metal, there occurs a natural resemblance of it almost perfect. But crystals of bismuth not only are of unusual occurrence in every-day life, but their form is, as far as I know, unique among minerals; and not only unique, but only attainable by an artificial process, the metal itself never being found pure. I do not remember any other substance or arrangement which presents a resemblance to this Greek ornament; and I think that I may trust my remembrance as including most of the arrangements which occur in the outward forms of common and familiar things. On this ground, then, I allege that ornament to be ugly; or, in the literal sense of the word, monstrous; different from anything which it is the nature of man to admire: and I think an uncarved fillet or plinth infinitely preferable to one covered with this vile concatenation of straight lines: unless indeed it be employed as a foil to a true ornament, which it[Pg 104] may, perhaps, sometimes with advantage; or excessively small, as it occurs on coins, the harshness of its arrangement being less perceived.

IV. The first ornament I want to critique is the Greek fret, which I believe is now often referred to by the Italian name Guilloche. This is a perfect example. In bismuth crystals formed by the slow cooling of melted metal, there’s a natural resemblance that’s almost perfect. However, bismuth crystals are not only rare in everyday life, but their shape, as far as I know, is unique among minerals; and it can only be created artificially, since pure metal is never found. I can’t recall any other material or pattern that looks like this Greek ornament, and I believe my memory covers most common and familiar shapes. For this reason, I consider this ornament to be ugly—or, to use the literal term, monstrous—different from anything humans tend to admire. I prefer an uncarved band or base to one covered with this awful mix of straight lines, unless it’s used as a contrast to a true ornament, which might be beneficial at times; or it’s very small, as seen on coins, where the harshness of the design is less noticeable.

V. Often in association with this horrible design we find, in Greek works, one which is as beautiful as this is painful—that egg and dart moulding, whose perfection in its place and way, has never been surpassed. And why is this? Simply because the form of which it is chiefly composed is one not only familiar to us in the soft housing of the bird's nest, but happens to be that of nearly every pebble that rolls and murmurs under the surf of the sea, on all its endless shore. And with that a peculiar accuracy; for the mass which bears the light in this moulding is not in good Greek work, as in the frieze of the Erechtheum, merely of the shape of an egg. It is flattened on the upper surface, with a delicacy and keen sense of variety in the curve which it is impossible too highly to praise, attaining exactly that flattened, imperfect oval, which, in nine cases out of ten, will be the form of the pebble lifted at random from the rolled beach. Leave out this flatness, and the moulding is vulgar instantly. It is singular also that the insertion of this rounded form in the hollow recess has a painted type in the plumage of the Argus pheasant, the eyes of whose feathers are so shaded as exactly to represent an oval form placed in a hollow.

V. Often associated with this dreadful design, we find, in Greek works, one that is as beautiful as it is painful—that egg and dart molding, whose perfection in its context and execution has never been matched. Why is this? Simply because the shape it's mostly made of is not only familiar to us from the soft structure of a bird's nest, but is also typical of nearly every pebble that rolls and whispers under the surf of the sea on its countless shores. And with that, a certain precision; for the mass that holds the light in this molding is not in good Greek work, like in the frieze of the Erechtheum, simply shaped like an egg. It is flattened on the top surface, with a delicacy and sharp sense of variety in the curve that is impossible to overpraise, achieving exactly that flattened, imperfect oval, which, in nine cases out of ten, will be the shape of a pebble picked up randomly from the smooth beach. Leave out this flatness, and the molding becomes instantly commonplace. It is also noteworthy that the inclusion of this rounded shape in the hollow recess has a painted counterpart in the plumage of the Argus pheasant, the eyes of whose feathers are shaded to perfectly represent an oval form set in a hollow.

VI. It will evidently follow, upon our application of this test of natural resemblance, that we shall at once conclude that all perfectly beautiful forms must be composed of curves; since there is hardly any common natural form in which it is possible to discover a straight line. Nevertheless, Architecture, having necessarily to deal with straight lines essential to its purposes in many instances and to the expression of its power in others, must frequently be content with that measure of beauty which is consistent with such primal forms; and we may presume that utmost measure of beauty to have been attained when the arrangements of such lines are consistent with the most frequent natural groupings of them we can discover, although, to find right lines in nature at all, we may be compelled to do violence to her finished work, break[Pg 105] through the sculptured and colored surfaces of her crags, and examine the processes of their crystallisation.

VI. It's clear that when we apply this test of natural resemblance, we can easily conclude that all perfectly beautiful shapes must be made up of curves, since there are very few natural forms where you can find a straight line. However, architecture often has to work with straight lines, which are essential for its purpose in many cases and for expressing its strength in others. Therefore, it has to accept a level of beauty that aligns with these basic forms. We can assume that the highest level of beauty is achieved when the arrangement of these lines reflects the most common natural groupings we observe. Yet, to find straight lines in nature at all, we might need to disturb her complete work, break through the sculpted and colorful surfaces of her cliffs, and look into the processes of their crystallization.

VII. I have just convicted the Greek fret of ugliness, because it has no precedent to allege for its arrangement except an artificial form of a rare metal. Let us bring into court an ornament of Lombard architects, Plate XII., fig. 7, as exclusively composed of right lines as the other, only, observe, with the noble element of shadow added. This ornament, taken from the front of the Cathedral of Pisa, is universal throughout the Lombard churches of Pisa, Lucca, Pistoja, and Florence; and it will be a grave stain upon them if it cannot be defended. Its first apology for itself, made in a hurry, sounds marvellously like the Greek one, and highly dubious. It says that its terminal contour is the very image of a carefully prepared artificial crystal of common salt. Salt being, however, a substance considerably more familiar to us than bismuth, the chances are somewhat in favor of the accused Lombard ornament already. But it has more to say for itself, and more to the purpose; namely, that its main outline is one not only of natural crystallisation, but among the very first and commonest of crystalline forms, being the primal condition of the occurrence of the oxides of iron, copper, and tin, of the sulphurets of iron and lead, of fluor spar, &c.; and that those projecting forms in its surface represent the conditions of structure which effect the change into another relative and equally common crystalline form, the cube. This is quite enough. We may rest assured it is as good a combination of such simple right lines as can be put together, and gracefully fitted for every place in which such lines are necessary.

VII. I have just called out the Greek fret for being ugly because it has no precedent to support its design other than a manufactured shape of a rare metal. Let's bring in an ornament from Lombard architects, Plate XII., fig. 7, which is made up of straight lines just like the Greek version, but notice how it includes the beautiful element of shadow. This ornament, taken from the front of the Cathedral of Pisa, is found throughout the Lombard churches of Pisa, Lucca, Pistoja, and Florence; it would be a serious blow to their reputation if it can’t be defended. Its first defense, rushed and thoughtless, sounds a lot like the Greek one and is quite questionable. It claims that its outer shape looks exactly like a carefully crafted artificial crystal made of common salt. Since salt is much more familiar to us than bismuth, the accused Lombard ornament already has a better chance. But it has more to say for itself, which is even more relevant; its main outline is not only a natural crystal but one of the very first and most common crystalline forms, being the fundamental condition for the occurrence of oxides of iron, copper, and tin, sulfides of iron and lead, fluor spar, etc.; and those protruding shapes on its surface represent structural conditions that facilitate the transition into another related and equally common crystal form, the cube. This should be enough. We can be sure it is the best combination of such simple straight lines that can be put together, elegantly suited for every situation where such lines are needed.

VIII. The next ornament whose cause I would try is that of our Tudor work, the portcullis. Reticulation is common enough in natural form, and very beautiful; but it is either of the most delicate and gauzy texture, or of variously sized meshes and undulating lines. There is no family relation between portcullis and cobwebs or beetles' wings; something like it, perhaps, may be found in some kinds of crocodile armor and on the backs of the Northern divers, but always beautifully varied in size of mesh. There is a dignity in the[Pg 106] thing itself, if its size were exhibited, and the shade given through its bars; but even these merits are taken away in the Tudor diminution of it, set on a solid surface. It has not a single syllable, I believe, to say in its defence. It is another monster, absolutely and unmitigatedly frightful. All that carving on Henry the Seventh's Chapel simply deforms the stones of it.

VIII. The next design I want to discuss is the Tudor portcullis. While intricate patterns are pretty common in nature and can be quite stunning, they tend to be either very delicate and sheer or made up of unevenly sized holes and wavy lines. There's no real connection between portcullises and cobwebs or beetle wings; maybe there are some similarities to certain types of crocodile skin and the backs of Northern divers, but even those have beautifully varied mesh sizes. There's a certain dignity to the portcullis itself, especially if its size is showcased and the shadows it casts through its bars are considered. However, these qualities are completely lost in the Tudor version, which is placed on a solid surface. I don’t think it has any redeeming qualities. It’s just another hideous creation, utterly and completely awful. All that carving on Henry the Seventh's Chapel just ruins the stones.

In the same clause with the portcullis, we may condemn all heraldic decoration, so far as beauty is its object. Its pride and significance have their proper place, fitly occurring in prominent parts of the building, as over its gates; and allowably in places where its legendary may be plainly read, as in painted windows, bosses of ceilings, &c. And sometimes, of course, the forms which it presents may be beautiful, as of animals, or simple symbols like the fleur-de-lis; but, for the most part, heraldic similitudes and arrangements are so professedly and pointedly unnatural, that it would be difficult to invent anything uglier; and the use of them as a repeated decoration will utterly destroy both the power and beauty of any building. Common sense and courtesy also forbid their repetition. It is right to tell those who enter your doors that you are such a one, and of such a rank; but to tell it to them again and again, wherever they turn, becomes soon impertinence, and at last folly. Let, therefore, the entire bearings occur in few places, and these not considered as an ornament, but as an inscription; and for frequent appliance, let any single and fair symbol be chosen out of them. Thus we may multiply as much as we choose the French fleur-de-lis, or the Florentine giglio bianco, or the English rose; but we must not multiply a King's arms.

In the same breath as the portcullis, we can criticize all heraldic decoration, as far as beauty is concerned. Its pride and significance have their rightful place, fittingly seen in prominent parts of the building, like over its gates; and allowed in areas where its meaning can be clearly understood, such as in stained glass windows, ceiling bosses, etc. Sometimes, of course, the designs can be beautiful, like animals or simple symbols such as the fleur-de-lis; but mostly, heraldic symbols and arrangements are so obviously unnatural that it would be hard to think of anything uglier. Using them as a repeated decoration will completely ruin both the impact and beauty of any building. Common sense and respect also discourage their repetition. It's appropriate to let those who enter your doors know who you are and your rank; but to repeat it over and over, wherever they look, quickly becomes rude, and eventually foolish. So, let the full coats of arms be displayed in only a few places, and these should be seen not as decoration, but as an inscription; for frequent use, let a single beautiful symbol be chosen from them. Thus, we can multiply as much as we want the French fleur-de-lis, the Florentine giglio bianco, or the English rose; but we must not replicate a King's arms.

IX. It will also follow, from these considerations, that if any one part of heraldic decoration be worse than another, it is the motto; since, of all things unlike nature, the forms of letters are, perhaps, the most so. Even graphic tellurium and felspar look, at their clearest, anything but legible. All letters are, therefore, to be considered as frightful things, and to be endured only upon occasion; that is to say, in places where the sense of the inscription is of more importance than[Pg 107] external ornament. Inscriptions in churches, in rooms, and on pictures, are often desirable, but they are not to be considered as architectural or pictorial ornaments: they are, on the contrary, obstinate offences to the eye, not to be suffered except when their intellectual office introduces them. Place them, therefore, where they will be read, and there only; and let them be plainly written, and not turned upside down, nor wrong end first. It is an ill sacrifice to beauty to make that illegible whose only merit is in its sense. Write it as you would speak it, simply; and do not draw the eye to it when it would fain rest elsewhere, nor recommend your sentence by anything but a little openness of place and architectural silence about it. Write the Commandments on the Church walls where they may be plainly seen, but do not put a dash and a tail to every letter; and remember that you are an architect, not a writing master.

IX. From these thoughts, it follows that if any part of heraldic decoration is worse than another, it’s the motto; because, of all things that are not natural, letters are probably the most unlike. Even the clearest forms of tellurium and felspar look almost unreadable. All letters should be seen as unpleasant things, tolerated only when necessary; that is, in places where the meaning of the words is more important than[Pg 107] the overall decoration. Signs in churches, rooms, and on paintings can be helpful, but they shouldn’t be seen as part of the architecture or art; rather, they are annoying distractions for the eye that should only be there when their intellectual purpose justifies their presence. Therefore, place them where they’ll be read, and only there; and make sure they’re written clearly, not upside down or backward. It’s a poor compromise to beauty to make something unreadable when its only value lies in its meaning. Write it as you would say it, simply; and don’t draw attention to it when the viewer’s gaze wants to rest elsewhere, nor enhance your message with anything but a bit of open space and architectural stillness around it. Write the Commandments on the Church walls where they can be easily seen, but don’t clutter every letter with unnecessary flourishes; and remember that you are an architect, not a calligrapher.

X. Inscriptions appear sometimes to be introduced for the sake of the scroll on which they are written; and in late and modern painted glass, as well as in architecture, these scrolls are flourished and turned hither and thither as if they were ornamental. Ribands occur frequently in arabesques,—in some of a high order, too,—tying up flowers, or flitting in and out among the fixed forms. Is there anything like ribands in nature? It might be thought that grass and sea-weed afforded apologetic types. They do not. There is a wide difference between their structure and that of a riband. They have a skeleton, an anatomy, a central rib, or fibre, or framework of some kind or another, which has a beginning and an end, a root and head, and whose make and strength effects every direction of their motion, and every line of their form. The loosest weed that drifts and waves under the heaving of the sea, or hangs heavily on the brown and slippery shore, has a marked strength, structure, elasticity, gradation of substance; its extremities are more finely fibred than its centre, its centre than its root; every fork of its ramification is measured and proportioned; every wave of its languid lines is love. It has its allotted size, and place, and function; it is a specific creature. What is there like this in a riband? It has[Pg 108] no structure: it is a succession of cut threads all alike; it has no skeleton, no make, no form, no size, no will of its own. You cut it and crush it into what you will. It has no strength, no languor. It cannot fall into a single graceful form. It cannot wave, in the true sense, but only flutter: it cannot bend, in the true sense, but only turn and be wrinkled. It is a vile thing; it spoils all that is near its wretched film of an existence. Never use it. Let the flowers come loose if they cannot keep together without being tied; leave the sentence unwritten if you cannot write it on a tablet or book, or plain roll of paper. I know what authority there is against me. I remember the scrolls of Perugino's angels, and the ribands of Raphael's arabesques, and of Ghiberti's glorious bronze flowers: no matter; they are every one of them vices and uglinesses. Raphael usually felt this, and used an honest and rational tablet, as in the Madonna di Fuligno. I do not say there is any type of such tablets in nature, but all the difference lies in the fact that the tablet is not considered as an ornament, and the riband, or flying scroll, is. The tablet, as in Albert Durer's Adam and Eve, is introduced for the sake of the writing, understood and allowed as an ugly but necessary interruption. The scroll is extended as an ornamental form, which it is not, nor ever can be.

X. Inscriptions sometimes seem to be added just for the sake of the scroll they’re written on; in modern stained glass and architecture, these scrolls are embellished and twisted around as if they were decorative. Ribbons often appear in arabesques—sometimes of a high quality—tying up flowers or weaving in and out among fixed shapes. Is there anything in nature that resembles ribbons? One might think that grass and seaweed could serve as examples, but they don’t. There’s a significant difference between their structure and that of a ribbon. They have a framework, an anatomy, a central rib, or fiber, or some kind of structure that has a beginning and an end, a root and a tip, and whose makeup and strength determine their motion in every direction and the shape they take. Even the loosest seaweed that drifts and sways in the ocean or clings heavily to the wet, slippery shore has a definite strength, structure, flexibility, and variety in material; its ends are more finely woven than its center, and its center is more refined than its root; each branching fork is measured and proportional; every gentle curve of its lines shows beauty. It has its designated size, place, and role; it is a specific organism. What resembles this in a ribbon? It has no structure: it’s just a series of cut threads that are all the same; it lacks a skeleton, a form, a size, or will of its own. You can cut it and twist it into any shape you like. It has no strength or grace. It can’t take a single elegant form. It can’t wave in the real sense; it can only flutter; it can’t bend genuinely but only twist and wrinkle. It’s a worthless thing; it ruins everything near its miserable existence. Never use it. Let flowers fall apart if they can’t stay together without being tied; leave the sentence unwritten if you can’t inscribe it on a tablet or book, or a simple roll of paper. I know there are authorities against my view. I think of the scrolls in Perugino’s angels, the ribbons in Raphael’s arabesques, and Ghiberti’s beautiful bronze flowers: no matter; they are all vices and uglinesses. Raphael usually recognized this and used a straightforward and sensible tablet, like in the Madonna di Fuligno. I don’t claim there’s any natural counterpart for such tablets, but the key difference is that the tablet is not viewed as decoration, while the ribbon or flowing scroll is. The tablet, as seen in Albert Durer’s Adam and Eve, is included for the sake of the writing, understood and accepted as a necessary but unattractive interruption. The scroll is stretched out as if it were an ornamental form, which it is not, and never can be.

XI. But it will be said that all this want of organisation and form might be affirmed of drapery also, and that this latter is a noble subject of sculpture. By no means. When was drapery a subject of sculpture by itself, except in the form of a handkerchief on urns in the seventeenth century and in some of the baser scenic Italian decorations? Drapery, as such, is always ignoble; it becomes a subject of interest only by the colors it bears, and the impressions which it receives from some foreign form or force. All noble draperies, either in painting or sculpture (color and texture being at present out of our consideration), have, so far as they are anything more than necessities, one of two great functions; they are the exponents of motion and of gravitation. They are the most valuable means of expressing past as well as present motion in the figure, and they are almost the only means of[Pg 109] indicating to the eye the force of gravity which resists such motion. The Greeks used drapery in sculpture for the most part as an ugly necessity, but availed themselves of it gladly in all representation of action, exaggerating the arrangements of it which express lightness in the material, and follow gesture in the person. The Christian sculptors, caring little for the body, or disliking it, and depending exclusively on the countenance, received drapery at first contentedly as a veil, but soon perceived a capacity of expression in it which the Greek had not seen or had despised. The principal element of this expression was the entire removal of agitation from what was so pre-eminently capable of being agitated. It fell from their human forms plumb down, sweeping the ground heavily, and concealing the feet; while the Greek drapery was often blown away from the thigh. The thick and coarse stuffs of the monkish dresses, so absolutely opposed to the thin and gauzy web of antique material, suggested simplicity of division as well as weight of fall. There was no crushing nor subdividing them. And thus the drapery gradually came to represent the spirit of repose as it before had of motion, repose saintly and severe. The wind had no power upon the garment, as the passion none upon the soul; and the motion of the figure only bent into a softer line the stillness of the falling veil, followed by it like a slow cloud by drooping rain: only in links of lighter undulation it followed the dances of the angels.

XI. However, some might argue that the lack of organization and structure could also apply to drapery, which is often seen as a noble subject for sculpture. That's not true at all. When has drapery stood alone as a sculpture topic, apart from decorative handkerchiefs on urns in the seventeenth century and some of the less impressive Italian scenery? Drapery, in itself, is always lowly; it only becomes interesting because of its colors and the impressions it gets from other forms or forces. All great draperies, whether in painting or sculpture (we're setting aside color and texture for now), generally serve one of two main purposes; they illustrate motion and gravity. They are the best way to show both past and present movement in figures, and they almost exclusively indicate to the eye the force of gravity that counters that movement. The Greeks primarily used drapery in sculpture as an unattractive necessity, but they gladly employed it in representations of action, amplifying the arrangements that expressed the material's lightness and echoed the gestures of the person. Christian sculptors, who cared little for the human body or even disliked it, initially accepted drapery as a veil, but soon recognized its expressive potential that the Greeks either overlooked or dismissed. The key aspect of this expression was the complete absence of agitation from what could easily be agitated. Drapery fell straight down from their human forms, heavily brushing the ground and hiding the feet, while Greek drapery often billowed away from the thigh. The thick, coarse fabrics of monastic clothing, so contrary to the thin, airy textiles of ancient materials, implied simplicity in division as well as weight in its fall. There was no crushing or subdividing of these fabrics. Gradually, drapery came to symbolize a state of calmness just as it once represented motion, a serene and solemn stillness. The wind had no influence on the garment, just as passion had no effect on the soul; the figure's movement only softened the outline of the falling veil, trailing behind like a slow cloud with gentle rainfall: it only lightly undulated in harmony with the dances of angels.

Thus treated, drapery is indeed noble; but it is as an exponent of other and higher things. As that of gravitation, it has especial majesty, being literally the only means we have of fully representing this mysterious natural force of earth (for falling water is less passive and less defined in its lines). So, again, in sails it is beautiful because it receives the forms of solid curved surface, and expresses the force of another invisible element. But drapery trusted to its own merits, and given for its own sake,—drapery like that of Carlo Dolci and the Caraccis,—is always base.

When treated this way, drapery is truly impressive; however, it serves as a representation of other, greater concepts. Much like gravitation, it possesses a unique grandeur, being the only way we can fully depict this mysterious natural force of the earth (since falling water is less passive and less defined in its shapes). Similarly, in sails, it is beautiful because it takes on the forms of solid, curved surfaces and conveys the power of another unseen element. But drapery that stands on its own merits, created for its own sake—like that of Carlo Dolci and the Caracci—is always inferior.

XII. Closely connected with the abuse of scrolls and bands, is that of garlands and festoons of flowers as an architectural[Pg 110] decoration, for unnatural arrangements are just as ugly as unnatural forms; and architecture, in borrowing the objects of nature, is bound to place them, as far as may be in her power, in such associations as may befit and express their origin. She is not to imitate directly the natural arrangement; she is not to carve irregular stems of ivy up her columns to account for the leaves at the top, but she is nevertheless to place her most exuberant vegetable ornament just where Nature would have placed it, and to give some indication of that radical and connected structure which Nature would have given it. Thus the Corinthian capital is beautiful, because it expands under the abacus just as Nature would have expanded it; and because it looks as if the leaves had one root, though that root is unseen. And the flamboyant leaf mouldings are beautiful, because they nestle and run up the hollows, and fill the angles, and clasp the shafts which natural leaves would have delighted to fill and to clasp. They are no mere cast of natural leaves; they are counted, orderly, and architectural: but they are naturally, and therefore beautifully, placed.

XII. Closely linked to the misuse of scrolls and bands is the misuse of garlands and flower festoons as architectural[Pg 110] decoration. Unnatural arrangements are just as unattractive as unnatural forms. When architecture incorporates elements from nature, it must arrange them in a way that respects and reflects their origins. It shouldn't directly mimic nature's layout; for example, it shouldn't carve irregular ivy stems onto the columns just to justify the leaves at the top. However, it should position its most abundant plant decorations in the spots where nature would have placed them and provide some suggestion of the coherent structure that nature would have created. Hence, the Corinthian capital is beautiful because it expands underneath the abacus just as nature would have. It appears as if the leaves share a single root, even if that root isn’t visible. The elaborate leaf moldings are beautiful because they settle into the hollows, fill the angles, and embrace the shafts in a way that natural leaves would have loved to do. They aren't just replicas of natural leaves; they're carefully counted, organized, and architectural, yet they are placed in a way that feels natural and, as a result, beautiful.

XIII. Now I do not mean to say that Nature never uses festoons: she loves them, and uses them lavishly; and though she does so only in those places of excessive luxuriance wherein it seems to me that architectural types should seldom be sought, yet a falling tendril or pendent bough might, if managed with freedom and grace, be well introduced into luxuriant decoration (or if not, it is not their want of beauty, but of architectural fitness, which incapacitates them for such uses). But what resemblance to such example can we trace in a mass of all manner of fruit and flowers, tied heavily into a long bunch, thickest in the middle, and pinned up by both ends against a dead wall? For it is strange that the wildest and most fanciful of the builders of truly luxuriant architecture never ventured, so far as I know, even a pendent tendril; while the severest masters of the revived Greek permitted this extraordinary piece of luscious ugliness to be fastened in the middle of their blank surfaces. So surely as this arrangement is adopted, the whole value of the flower work is lost. Who among the crowds that gaze upon the building ever pause to[Pg 111] admire the flower work of St. Paul's? It is as careful and as rich as it can be, yet it adds no delightfulness to the edifice. It is no part of it. It is an ugly excrescence. We always conceive the building without it, and should be happier if our conception were not disturbed by its presence. It makes the rest of the architecture look poverty-stricken, instead of sublime; and yet it is never enjoyed itself. Had it been put, where it ought, into the capitals, it would have been beheld with never-ceasing delight. I do not mean that it could have been so in the present building, for such kind of architecture has no business with rich ornament in any place; but that if those groups of flowers had been put into natural places in an edifice of another style, their value would have been felt as vividly as now their uselessness. What applies to festoons is still more sternly true of garlands. A garland is meant to be seen upon a head. There it is beautiful, because we suppose it newly gathered and joyfully worn. But it is not meant to be hung upon a wall. If you want a circular ornament, put a flat circle of colored marble, as in the Casa Doria and other such palaces at Venice; or put a star, or a medallion, or if you want a ring, put a solid one, but do not carve the images of garlands, looking as if they had been used in the last procession, and been hung up to dry, and serve next time withered. Why not also carve pegs, and hats upon them?

XIII. I don’t mean to say that Nature never uses garlands: she loves them and uses them generously; and while she does so only in areas of excessive abundance where architectural styles should rarely be sought, a falling vine or drooping branch could, if handled with freedom and grace, be nicely integrated into lush decoration (or if not, it’s not their lack of beauty, but their unfit architectural nature, that makes them unsuitable for such uses). But what similarity can we find in a mass of all kinds of fruit and flowers, heavily tied into a long bunch, thicker in the middle, and pinned up at both ends against a blank wall? It’s odd that even the most imaginative builders of truly abundant architecture never included, as far as I know, even a drooping vine; while the strictest masters of revived Greek styles allowed this bizarre piece of excessive ugliness to be attached in the middle of their plain surfaces. As soon as this arrangement is made, the whole value of the floral work is lost. Who among the crowds that look at the building ever stops to admire the floral work of St. Paul’s? It is as detailed and luxurious as it can be, yet it adds no charm to the structure. It is not part of it. It’s an ugly blemish. We always picture the building without it, and would be happier if our vision weren’t interrupted by its presence. It makes the rest of the architecture look impoverished instead of majestic; yet it is never appreciated itself. If it had been placed where it belonged, in the capitals, it would have been admired endlessly. I don’t mean it could have been so in the current building, as this style of architecture has no place for rich ornamentation anywhere; but if those groups of flowers had been positioned in natural places within a building of a different style, their value would have been felt just as strongly as their current lack of usefulness. What applies to garlands is even more strictly true for wreaths. A wreath is meant to be worn on a head. There, it’s beautiful because we assume it was freshly gathered and joyfully worn. But it’s not meant to be hung on a wall. If you want a circular decoration, use a flat circle of colored marble, like in the Casa Doria and other palaces in Venice; or use a star, or a medallion, or if you want a ring, use a solid one, but don’t carve images of garlands that look like they’ve just been used in the last parade, then hung up to dry, to be used again when they're withered. Why not also carve pegs and hats onto them?

XIV. One of the worst enemies of modern Gothic architecture, though seemingly an unimportant feature, is an excrescence, as offensive by its poverty as the garland by its profusion, the dripstone in the shape of the handle of a chest of drawers, which is used over the square-headed windows of what we call Elizabethan buildings. In the last Chapter, it will be remembered that the square form was shown to be that of pre-eminent Power, and to be properly adapted and limited to the exhibition of space or surface. Hence, when the window is to be an exponent of power, as for instance in those by M. Angelo in the lower story of the Palazzo Ricardi at Florence, the square head is the most noble form they can assume; but then either their space must be unbroken, and their associated mouldings the most severe, or else the square[Pg 112] must be used as a finial outline, and is chiefly to be associated with forms of tracery, in which the relative form of power, the circle, is predominant, as in Venetian, and Florentine, and Pisan Gothic. But if you break upon your terminal square, or if you cut its lines off at the top and turn them outwards, you have lost its unity and space. It is an including form no longer, but an added, isolated line, and the ugliest possible. Look abroad into the landscape and see if you can discover any one so bent and fragmentary as that of this strange windlass-looking dripstone. You cannot. It is a monster. It unites every element of ugliness, its line is harshly broken in itself, and unconnected with every other; it has no harmony either with structure or decoration, it has no architectural support, it looks glued to the wall, and the only pleasant property it has, is the appearance of some likelihood of its dropping off.

XIV. One of the biggest drawbacks of modern Gothic architecture, even though it seems minor, is an ugly addition that is as offensive due to its simplicity as an overdone decoration is to its excess. It’s the dripstone that looks like the handle of a chest of drawers, which is placed above the square-headed windows of what we call Elizabethan buildings. In the last Chapter, we noted that the square shape symbolizes supreme power and is best suited for displaying space or surface. So, when a window is meant to represent power, like those designed by Michelangelo in the lower level of the Palazzo Ricardi in Florence, the square head is the most dignified form it can take. However, the space must either remain unbroken and the surrounding moldings kept very simple, or the square must serve as a finial outline and be used primarily with types of tracery where the round shape, symbolizing power, is dominant, as seen in Venetian, Florentine, and Pisan Gothic styles. But if you interrupt the terminal square or cut its lines at the top and extend them outward, you lose its unity and the sense of space. It no longer serves as an inclusive shape but becomes an added, isolated line— the ugliest kind. Look around the landscape and see if you can find anything as bent and fragmented as this strange dripstone. You can’t. It’s a monstrosity. It combines every element of ugliness; its line is abruptly broken and disconnected from everything else, it lacks harmony with either structure or decoration, has no architectural support, looks glued to the wall, and the only redeeming feature it possesses is the chance that it might fall off.

I might proceed, but the task is a weary one, and I think I have named those false forms of decoration which are most dangerous in our modern architecture as being legal and accepted. The barbarisms of individual fancy are as countless as they are contemptible; they neither admit attack nor are worth it; but these above named are countenanced, some by the practice of antiquity, all by high authority: they have depressed the proudest, and contaminated the purest schools, and are so established in recent practice that I write rather for the barren satisfaction of bearing witness against them, than with hope of inducing any serious convictions to their prejudice.

I could go on, but it’s a tiring task, and I believe I’ve pointed out the misleading styles of decoration that are most harmful in modern architecture while being accepted as standard. The ridiculous whims of individual creativity are as numerous as they are laughable; they don’t invite criticism and aren’t worth the effort. However, the styles I mentioned have support—some from ancient practices, all backed by authority. They’ve brought down the most prestigious schools and tainted the purest ones, and they’re so ingrained in current practices that I’m writing more for the empty satisfaction of speaking out against them than in hopes of changing anyone's mind about them.

XV. Thus far of what is not ornament. What ornament is, will without difficulty be determined by the application of the same test. It must consist of such studious arrangements of form as are imitative or suggestive of those which are commonest among natural existences, that being of course the noblest ornament which represents the highest orders of existence. Imitated flowers are nobler than imitated stones, imitated animals, than flowers; imitated human form of all animal forms the noblest. But all are combined in the richest ornamental work; and the rock, the fountain, the flowing river with its pebbled bed, the sea, the clouds of[Pg 113] Heaven, the herb of the field, the fruit-tree bearing fruit, the creeping thing, the bird, the beast, the man, and the angel, mingle their fair forms on the bronze of Ghiberti.

XV. Up to this point, we've talked about what is not ornament. What ornament is can easily be figured out by using the same criteria. It should consist of carefully arranged forms that imitate or suggest those commonly found in nature, as those are the most admirable ornaments that represent the highest levels of existence. Imitations of flowers are more refined than imitations of stones, imitations of animals are more refined than flowers, and among all animal forms, the imitation of the human figure is the most noble. However, all of these elements come together in the richest decorative work; the rock, the fountain, the flowing river with its pebbled bed, the sea, the clouds of[Pg 113] Heavens, the plants in the field, the fruit-bearing trees, the creeping creatures, the birds, the beasts, the humans, and the angels all blend their beautiful forms on the bronze of Ghiberti.

Every thing being then ornamental that is imitative, I would ask the reader's attention to a few general considerations, all that can here be offered relating to so vast a subject; which, for convenience sake, may be classed under the three heads of inquiry:—What is the right place for architectural ornament? What is the peculiar treatment of ornament which renders it architectural? and what is the right use of color as associated with architectural imitative form?

Everything that is decorative is imitative, so I’d like to draw the reader's attention to a few general points, all that can be presented on such a vast topic; which, for ease of understanding, can be divided into three main questions:—What is the appropriate place for architectural decoration? What is the specific approach to decoration that makes it architectural? And what is the correct use of color in relation to architectural imitative forms?

XVI. What is the place of ornament? Consider first that the characters of natural objects which the architect can represent are few and abstract. The greater part of those delights by which Nature recommends herself to man at all times, cannot be conveyed by him into his imitative work. He cannot make his grass green and cool and good to rest upon, which in nature is its chief use to man; nor can he make his flowers tender and full of color and of scent, which in nature are their chief powers of giving joy. Those qualities which alone he can secure are certain severe characters of form, such as men only see in nature on deliberate examination, and by the full and set appliance of sight and thought: a man must lie down on the bank of grass on his breast and set himself to watch and penetrate the intertwining of it, before he finds that which is good to be gathered by the architect. So then while Nature is at all times pleasant to us, and while the sight and sense of her work may mingle happily with all our thoughts, and labors, and times of existence, that image of her which the architect carries away represents what we can only perceive in her by direct intellectual exertion, and demands from us, wherever it appears, an intellectual exertion of a similar kind in order to understand it and feel it. It is the written or sealed impression of a thing sought out, it is the shaped result of inquiry and bodily expression of thought.

XVI. What role does ornament play? First, consider that the features of natural objects that an architect can depict are limited and abstract. Most of the pleasures that Nature offers to humanity cannot be reflected in his imitative work. He can't replicate how grass is green, cool, and inviting to rest on—qualities that are its primary use in nature; nor can he make flowers soft, vibrant, and fragrant, which are their main sources of joy in the natural world. The only traits he can capture are certain strict forms that people only notice in nature through careful observation and focused thought. A person must lie on the grass with their chest against the ground and study its intricate patterns to discover what an architect can utilize. Therefore, although Nature is always enjoyable to us and her beauty can enhance all our thoughts, efforts, and phases of life, the version of her that the architect presents reflects what we can only recognize through deliberate intellectual effort, requiring us, wherever it appears, to exert a similar intellectual effort to comprehend and appreciate it. It is a recorded or defined impression of something discovered; it represents the shaped outcome of exploring and the physical expression of thought.

XVII. Now let us consider for an instant what would be the effect of continually repeating an expression of a beautiful[Pg 114] thought to any other of the senses at times when the mind could not address that sense to the understanding of it. Suppose that in time of serious occupation, of stern business, a companion should repeat in our ears continually some favorite passage of poetry, over and over again all day long. We should not only soon be utterly sick and weary of the sound of it, but that sound would at the end of the day have so sunk into the habit of the ear that the entire meaning of the passage would be dead to us, and it would ever thenceforward require some effort to fix and recover it. The music of it would not meanwhile have aided the business in hand, while its own delightfulness would thenceforward be in a measure destroyed. It is the same with every other form of definite thought. If you violently present its expression to the senses, at times when the mind is otherwise engaged, that expression will be ineffective at the time, and will have its sharpness and clearness destroyed forever. Much more if you present it to the mind at times when it is painfully affected or disturbed, or if you associate the expression of pleasant thought with incongruous circumstances, you will affect that expression thenceforward with a painful color for ever.

XVII. Now let’s take a moment to think about what would happen if we kept repeating a beautiful thought to any of our senses when our minds aren’t really focused on it. Imagine if, while we were busy with serious work, a friend kept playing a favorite poem in our ears, over and over all day long. Not only would we quickly get completely tired and fed up with hearing it, but by the end of the day, that sound would have become so ingrained in our ears that we’d lose all sense of its meaning, and it would take effort to remember it again. It wouldn’t help with our work at all, and the joy of it would be somewhat ruined forever. This goes for every other specific thought as well. If you forcefully present it to our senses when our minds are occupied, that expression will be useless at that moment and will lose its sharpness and clarity permanently. Even more so, if you expose it to our minds when we’re upset or disturbed, or if you associate a pleasant thought with inappropriate situations, you’ll forever taint that thought with a negative feeling.

XVIII. Apply this to expressions of thought received by the eye. Remember that the eye is at your mercy more than the ear. "The eye it cannot choose but see." Its nerve is not so easily numbed as that of the ear, and it is often busied in tracing and watching forms when the ear is at rest. Now if you present lovely forms to it when it cannot call the mind to help it in its work, and among objects of vulgar use and unhappy position, you will neither please the eye nor elevate the vulgar object. But you will fill and weary the eye with the beautiful form, and you will infect that form itself with the vulgarity of the thing to which you have violently attached it. It will never be of much use to you any more; you have killed or defiled it; its freshness and purity are gone. You will have to pass it through the fire of much thought before you will cleanse it, and warm it with much love before it will revive.[Pg 115]

XVIII. Think about how we understand things we see. Keep in mind that the eye is more open to influence than the ear. "The eye cannot help but see." Its nerve isn’t as easily numbed as the ear’s, and it often focuses on shapes when the ear is relaxed. Now, if you show beautiful shapes to the eye when it can't engage the mind to assist it, amidst ordinary objects and unpleasant circumstances, you won’t please the eye or uplift the ordinary object. Instead, you’ll overwhelm the eye with the beautiful shape while it becomes tainted by the commonness of the item you forcibly connected it to. It won't be very useful to you anymore; you have diminished or sullied it; its freshness and purity are lost. You'll need to put it through deep contemplation before you can cleanse it, and warm it with genuine affection before it can come back to life.[Pg 115]

XIX. Hence then a general law, of singular importance in the present day, a law of simple common sense,—not to decorate things belonging to purposes of active and occupied life. Wherever you can rest, there decorate; where rest is forbidden, so is beauty. You must not mix ornament with business, any more than you may mix play. Work first, and then rest. Work first and then gaze, but do not use golden ploughshares, nor bind ledgers in enamel. Do not thrash with sculptured flails: nor put bas-reliefs on millstones. What! it will be asked, are we in the habit of doing so? Even so; always and everywhere. The most familiar position of Greek mouldings is in these days on shop fronts. There is not a tradesman's sign nor shelf nor counter in all the streets of all our cities, which has not upon it ornaments which were invented to adorn temples and beautify kings' palaces. There is not the smallest advantage in them where they are. Absolutely valueless—utterly without the power of giving pleasure, they only satiate the eye, and vulgarise their own forms. Many of these are in themselves thoroughly good copies of fine things, which things themselves we shall never, in consequence, enjoy any more. Many a pretty beading and graceful bracket there is in wood or stucco above our grocers' and cheese-mongers' and hosiers' shops: how it is that the tradesmen cannot understand that custom is to be had only by selling good tea and cheese and cloth, and that people come to them for their honesty, and their readiness, and their right wares, and not because they have Greek cornices over their windows, or their names in large gilt letters on their house fronts? how pleasurable it would be to have the power of going through the streets of London, pulling down those brackets and friezes and large names, restoring to the tradesmen the capital they had spent in architecture, and putting them on honest and equal terms, each with his name in black letters over his door, not shouted down the street from the upper stories, and each with a plain wooden shop casement, with small panes in it that people would not think of breaking in order to be sent to prison! How much better for them would it be—how much[Pg 116] happier, how much wiser, to put their trust upon their own truth and industry, and not on the idiocy of their customers. It is curious, and it says little for our national probity on the one hand, or prudence on the other, to see the whole system of our street decoration based on the idea that people must be baited to a shop as moths are to a candle.

XIX. So, there’s a general rule that’s really important today, a rule based on simple common sense: don’t decorate things meant for active and busy lives. Wherever you can relax, go ahead and decorate; where relaxation isn’t allowed, neither is beauty. You shouldn’t mix decoration with work, any more than you would mix play. Work comes first, then you can rest. Get your work done before you start admiring things, but don’t use ornate farming tools or cover notebooks in fancy designs. Don’t use fancy tools for threshing, nor put decorative carvings on millstones. What? You might ask, do we actually do that? Yes, all the time and everywhere. These days, the most common place for Greek decorations is on shop fronts. There isn’t a single shop sign, shelf, or counter in all our cities that doesn’t have decorations originally meant for temples or to beautify royal palaces. They provide no real benefit where they are. They are completely worthless—totally incapable of giving real pleasure; they merely satisfy the eye and cheapen their own designs. Many of these decorations are good copies of beautiful things, which means we’ll never fully appreciate those originals again. There are many nice moldings and elegant brackets made of wood or stucco above the shops of grocers, cheesemongers, and haberdashers: how can these shopkeepers not realize that customers are drawn by good products, and that people come to them for their honesty, responsiveness, and quality goods, not because they have Greek cornices over their windows, or their names in large golden letters on their shop fronts? How nice it would be to walk through the streets of London, tearing down those brackets and friezes and oversized names, giving those shopkeepers back the money they wasted on flashy architecture, and putting them on an equal footing where each has their name in black letters over their door, not shouted from the upper stories, and each has a simple wooden shop window with small panes that won’t make people think about breaking them to land in jail! How much better it would be for them—how much happier, how much smarter—to rely on their own honesty and hard work, rather than the foolishness of their customers. It’s strange, and it doesn’t speak well of our national honesty on one side, or our common sense on the other, to see our entire street decoration system based on the notion that people need to be lured into shops like moths to a flame.

XX. But it will be said that much of the best wooden decoration of the middle ages was in shop fronts. No; it was in house fronts, of which the shop was a part, and received its natural and consistent portion of the ornament. In those days men lived, and intended to live by their shops, and over them, all their days. They were contented with them and happy in them: they were their palaces and castles. They gave them therefore such decoration as made themselves happy in their own habitation, and they gave it for their own sake. The upper stories were always the richest, and the shop was decorated chiefly about the door, which belonged to the house more than to it. And when our tradesmen settle to their shops in the same way, and form no plans respecting future villa architecture, let their whole houses be decorated, and their shops too, but with a national and domestic decoration (I shall speak more of this point in the sixth chapter). However, our cities are for the most part too large to admit of contented dwelling in them throughout life; and I do not say there is harm in our present system of separating the shop from the dwelling-house; only where they are so separated, let us remember that the only reason for shop decoration is removed, and see that the decoration be removed also.

XX. People might argue that a lot of the best wooden decoration from the Middle Ages was found on shop fronts. That's not true; it was on house fronts, which included the shop as part of it and got its share of the ornamentation. Back then, people lived above their shops and planned to stay there for life. They were happy and satisfied with their shops; they were their homes, their palaces, and their castles. Because of that, they decorated their spaces to make themselves comfortable and happy. The upper levels were always the most elaborate, while the shop was mainly adorned around the door, which belonged more to the house. When our tradespeople set up their shops like this without planning for future villa-style homes, their entire houses should be decorated along with their shops, but in a way that reflects national and domestic styles (I'll discuss this more in the sixth chapter). Still, our cities are generally too big to allow for a lifetime of happiness living in them, and I’m not saying there’s anything wrong with our current practice of separating shops from homes; just remember that when they are separate, the main reason for shop decoration is gone, so we should remove that decoration too.

XXI. Another of the strange and evil tendencies of the present day is to the decoration of the railroad station. Now, if there be any place in the world in which people are deprived of that portion of temper and discretion which are necessary to the contemplation of beauty, it is there. It is the very temple of discomfort, and the only charity that the builder can extend to us is to show us, plainly as may be, how soonest to escape from it. The whole system of railroad travelling is addressed to people who, being in a hurry, are there[Pg 117]fore, for the time being, miserable. No one would travel in that manner who could help it—who had time to go leisurely over hills and between hedges, instead of through tunnels and between banks: at least those who would, have no sense of beauty so acute as that we need consult it at the station. The railroad is in all its relations a matter of earnest business, to be got through as soon as possible. It transmutes a man from a traveller into a living parcel. For the time he has parted with the nobler characteristics of his humanity for the sake of a planetary power of locomotion. Do not ask him to admire anything. You might as well ask the wind. Carry him safely, dismiss him soon: he will thank you for nothing else. All attempts to please him in any other way are mere mockery, and insults to the things by which you endeavor to do so. There never was more flagrant nor impertinent folly than the smallest portion of ornament in anything concerned with railroads or near them. Keep them out of the way, take them through the ugliest country you can find, confess them the miserable things they are, and spend nothing upon them but for safety and speed. Give large salaries to efficient servants, large prices to good manufacturers, large wages to able workmen; let the iron be tough, and the brickwork solid, and the carriages strong. The time is perhaps not distant when these first necessities may not be easily met: and to increase expense in any other direction is madness. Better bury gold in the embankments, than put it in ornaments on the stations. Will a single traveller be willing to pay an increased fare on the South Western, because the columns of the terminus are covered with patterns from Nineveh? He will only care less for the Ninevite ivories in the British Museum: or on the North Western, because there are old English-looking spandrils to the roof of the station at Crewe? He will only have less pleasure in their prototypes at Crewe House. Railroad architecture has or would have a dignity of its own if it were only left to its work. You would not put rings on the fingers of a smith at his anvil.

XXI. One of the odd and troubling trends of today is the decoration of train stations. If there’s any place where people are stripped of the patience and good sense needed to appreciate beauty, it’s there. It’s the ultimate hub of discomfort, and the only kindness the builders can show us is to guide us, as clearly as possible, on how to leave it quickly. The entire experience of train travel caters to people who are in a rush and, therefore, temporarily miserable. No one would choose to travel this way if they had the option—if they could leisurely explore hills and countryside rather than being funneled through tunnels and along embankments. At least, those who would lack a strong enough sense of beauty to be concerned about it at the station. Railroads are, at their core, serious business, meant to be completed as quickly as possible. They turn a person from a traveler into a living package. For the duration of the trip, he has sacrificed the finer qualities of humanity for the sheer power of transport. Don’t ask him to appreciate anything. That’s as pointless as asking the wind. Just get him there safely and send him off quickly: he won’t thank you for anything else. Any effort to please him in other ways is just mockery and an insult to the things you try to impress him with. There has never been a more ridiculous or arrogant folly than any hint of decoration in anything related to railroads. Keep them out of sight, take them through the ugliest landscapes you can find, acknowledge them for the sad things they are, and spend nothing on them except for safety and speed. Pay decent salaries to good workers, good prices to reliable manufacturers, and fair wages to skilled laborers; ensure the iron is strong, the brickwork is solid, and the carriages are sturdy. Perhaps the day isn’t far off when these basic needs won’t be easily met, and spending money elsewhere would be insanity. It’s better to bury gold in the embankments than to waste it on decorations at the stations. Will a single traveler be willing to pay a higher fare on the South Western because the columns at the terminus are adorned with designs from Nineveh? They’ll care even less about the Ninevite artifacts in the British Museum. Or on the North Western, because there are old English-style designs on the roof of the station at Crewe? That will only diminish their enjoyment of the originals at Crewe House. Train station architecture could have a dignity all its own if it were just allowed to focus on its purpose. You wouldn’t put rings on a smith’s fingers while he’s at his anvil.

XXII. It is not however only in these marked situations that the abuse of which I speak takes place. There is hardly,[Pg 118] at present, an application of ornamental work, which is not in some sort liable to blame of the same kind. We have a bad habit of trying to disguise disagreeable necessities by some form of sudden decoration, which is, in all other places, associated with such necessities. I will name only one instance, that to which I have alluded before—the roses which conceal the ventilators in the flat roofs of our chapels. Many of those roses are of very beautiful design, borrowed from fine works: all their grace and finish are invisible when they are so placed, but their general form is afterwards associated with the ugly buildings in which they constantly occur; and all the beautiful roses of the early French and English Gothic, especially such elaborate ones as those of the triforium of Coutances, are in consequence deprived of their pleasurable influence: and this without our having accomplished the smallest good by the use we have made of the dishonored form. Not a single person in the congregation ever receives one ray of pleasure from those roof roses; they are regarded with mere indifference, or lost in the general impression of harsh emptiness.

XXII. However, it’s not just in these specific situations that the abuse I’m talking about happens. Almost every use of decorative work today is somehow open to the same criticism. We have a bad habit of trying to cover up unpleasant necessities with a burst of decoration, which in every other context is linked to those necessities. I’ll just mention one example that I’ve referred to before—the roses that hide the vents in the flat roofs of our chapels. Many of those roses are beautifully designed, inspired by fine artworks; but all their elegance and detail are lost in their placement, and their overall shape then becomes associated with the unattractive buildings where they frequently appear. As a result, all the beautiful roses from early French and English Gothic architecture, especially the intricate ones like those found in the triforium of Coutances, lose their enjoyable impact. This happens without us achieving any real benefit from using that disrespected form. Not a single person in the congregation ever experiences any joy from those roof roses; they are met with indifference or are overshadowed by the overall sense of harsh emptiness.

XXIII. Must not beauty, then, it will be asked, be sought for in the forms which we associate with our every-day life? Yes, if you do it consistently, and in places where it can be calmly seen; but not if you use the beautiful form only as a mask and covering of the proper conditions and uses of things, nor if you thrust it into the places set apart for toil. Put it in the drawing-room, not into the workshop; put it upon domestic furniture, not upon tools of handicraft. All men have sense of what is right in this manner, if they would only use and apply that sense; every man knows where and how beauty gives him pleasure, if he would only ask for it when it does so, and not allow it to be forced upon him when he does not want it. Ask any one of the passengers over London Bridge at this instant whether he cares about the forms of the bronze leaves on its lamps, and he will tell you, No. Modify these forms of leaves to a less scale, and put them on his milk-jug at breakfast, and ask him whether he likes them, and he will tell you, Yes. People have no need of teaching if they[Pg 119] could only think and speak truth, and ask for what they like and want, and for nothing else: nor can a right disposition of beauty be ever arrived at except by this common sense, and allowance for the circumstances of the time and place. It does not follow, because bronze leafage is in bad taste on the lamps of London Bridge, that it would be so on those of the Ponte della Trinita; nor, because it would be a folly to decorate the house fronts of Gracechurch Street, that it would be equally so to adorn those of some quiet provincial town. The question of greatest external or internal decoration depends entirely on the conditions of probable repose. It was a wise feeling which made the streets of Venice so rich in external ornament, for there is no couch of rest like the gondola. So, again, there is no subject of street ornament so wisely chosen as the fountain, where it is a fountain of use; for it is just there that perhaps the happiest pause takes place in the labor of the day, when the pitcher is rested on the edge of it, and the breath of the bearer is drawn deeply, and the hair swept from the forehead, and the uprightness of the form declined against the marble ledge, and the sound of the kind word or light laugh mixes with the trickle of the falling water, heard shriller and shriller as the pitcher fills. What pause is so sweet as that—so full of the depth of ancient days, so softened with the calm of pastoral solitude?

XXIII. So, it might be asked, shouldn't we look for beauty in the forms we encounter in our everyday lives? Yes, if you do it consistently and in places where it can be appreciated; but not if you use beautiful forms merely as a facade or cover for the practical conditions and uses of things, nor if you force it into spaces meant for hard work. Place it in the living room, not in the workshop; put it on home furniture, not on tools for manual labor. Everyone has a sense of what feels right in this regard, if only they would use and apply that sense; each person knows where and how beauty brings them joy, if they would only seek it out when it does, and not let it be imposed upon them when they don’t want it. Ask any of the people crossing London Bridge right now if they care about the design of the bronze leaves on the lamps, and they will say no. Scale those leaves down and put them on their milk jug at breakfast, and they will say yes. People don’t need to be taught if they could just think and speak truthfully, asking for what they like and want, and nothing more: a proper arrangement of beauty can only be achieved through this common sense and consideration of the context of time and place. Just because bronze leaves look out of place on the lamps of London Bridge, doesn’t mean they would on those of the Ponte della Trinita; nor does it mean that while decorating the fronts of buildings on Gracechurch Street would be silly, it would be the same in some quiet provincial town. The choice of the best external or internal decoration entirely depends on conditions that allow for rest. It was a smart decision that made the streets of Venice so rich with external ornamentation, because there is no resting place like a gondola. Similarly, no street decoration is as wisely chosen as a fountain, particularly when it serves a purpose; it’s precisely there that one may find the happiest break in the day's labor, when the pitcher rests on the edge, the bearer draws a deep breath, sweeps hair from the forehead, leans against the marble ledge, and the sound of kind words or light laughter blends with the trickle of falling water, more distinct as the pitcher fills. What pause is as sweet as that—so steeped in the depth of ancient days, so softened by the serenity of pastoral solitude?

XXIV. II. Thus far, then, of the place for beauty. We were next to inquire into the characters which fitted it peculiarly for architectural appliance, and into the principles of choice and of arrangement which best regulate the imitation of natural forms in which it consists. The full answering of these questions would be a treatise on the art of design: I intend only to say a few words respecting the two conditions of that art which are essentially architectural,—Proportion and Abstraction. Neither of these qualities is necessary, to the same extent, in other fields of design. The sense of proportion is, by the landscape painter, frequently sacrificed to character and accident; the power of abstraction to that of complete realisation. The flowers of his foreground must often be unmeasured in their quantity, loose in their arrangement: what[Pg 120] is calculated, either in quantity or disposition, must be artfully concealed. That calculation is by the architect to be prominently exhibited. So the abstraction of few characteristics out of many is shown only in the painter's sketch; in his finished work it is concealed or lost in completion. Architecture, on the contrary, delights in Abstraction and fears to complete her forms. Proportion and Abstraction, then, are the two especial marks of architectural design as distinguished from all other. Sculpture must have them in inferior degrees; leaning, on the one hand, to an architectural manner, when it is usually greatest (becoming, indeed, a part of Architecture), and, on the other, to a pictorial manner, when it is apt to lose its dignity, and sink into mere ingenious carving.

XXIV. II. So far, then, about the place for beauty. Next, we need to explore the qualities that make it particularly suited for architectural use, and the principles of selection and arrangement that best guide the imitation of natural forms that it entails. Fully answering these questions would require a detailed discussion on the art of design; I will only mention a few points regarding the two conditions of that art that are fundamentally architectural—Proportion and Abstraction. Neither of these qualities is as necessary in other areas of design. A landscape painter often sacrifices proportion for character and spontaneity; the ability to abstract for total representation. The flowers in his foreground can be unmeasured in number and loosely arranged: anything calculated, whether in quantity or layout, must be cleverly hidden. An architect, however, makes that calculation a prominent feature. Similarly, the abstraction of a few traits out of many is evident only in the painter's sketch; in the finished piece, it is concealed or lost in the details. Architecture, on the other hand, embraces Abstraction and hesitates to finalize its forms. Therefore, Proportion and Abstraction are the two main characteristics of architectural design, setting it apart from all others. Sculpture must have them to a lesser degree; it leans toward an architectural style when it is typically at its peak (essentially becoming part of Architecture), and toward a pictorial style when it tends to lose its dignity and devolve into mere clever carving.

XXV. Now, of Proportion so much has been written, that I believe the only facts which are of practical use have been overwhelmed and kept out of sight by vain accumulations of particular instances and estimates. Proportions are as infinite (and that in all kinds of things, as severally in colors, lines, shades, lights, and forms) as possible airs in music: and it is just as rational an attempt to teach a young architect how to proportion truly and well by calculating for him the proportions of fine works, as it would be to teach him to compose melodies by calculating the mathematical relations of the notes in Beethoven's Adelaïde or Mozart's Requiem. The man who has eye and intellect will invent beautiful proportions, and cannot help it; but he can no more tell us how to do it than Wordsworth could tell us how to write a sonnet, or than Scott could have told us how to plan a romance. But there are one or two general laws which can be told: they are of no use, indeed, except as preventives of gross mistake, but they are so far worth telling and remembering; and the more so because, in the discussion of the subtle laws of proportion (which will never be either numbered or known), architects are perpetually forgetting and transgressing the very simplest of its necessities.

XXV. There’s been so much written about proportion that I believe the truly useful facts have been buried under excessive examples and estimates. Proportions are as infinite (in all kinds of things, like colors, lines, shades, lights, and forms) as the possible tones in music. Trying to teach a young architect to achieve proper proportions by calculating those in great works is just as pointless as teaching him to compose melodies by calculating the mathematical relationships of the notes in Beethoven's Adelaïde or Mozart's Requiem. A person with the right vision and intellect will naturally create beautiful proportions, but they can't explain how to do it any more than Wordsworth could explain how to write a sonnet or Scott could explain how to plan a romance. However, there are one or two general principles to share: while they might not be very helpful aside from preventing major mistakes, they’re still worth noting. This is especially important because, in discussing the subtle laws of proportion (which will never be fully quantified or understood), architects often forget or overlook the very simplest requirements.

XXVI. Of which the first is, that wherever Proportion exists at all, one member of the composition must be either larger than, or in some way supreme over, the rest. There is no[Pg 121] proportion between equal things. They can have symmetry only, and symmetry without proportion is not composition. It is necessary to perfect beauty, but it is the least necessary of its elements, nor of course is there any difficulty in obtaining it. Any succession of equal things is agreeable; but to compose is to arrange unequal things, and the first thing to be done in beginning a composition is to determine which is to be the principal thing. I believe that all that has been written and taught about proportion, put together, is not to the architect worth the single rule, well enforced, "Have one large thing and several smaller things, or one principal thing and several inferior things, and bind them well together." Sometimes there may be a regular gradation, as between the heights of stories in good designs for houses; sometimes a monarch with a lowly train, as in the spire with its pinnacles: the varieties of arrangement are infinite, but the law is universal—have one thing above the rest, either by size, or office, or interest. Don't put the pinnacles without the spire. What a host of ugly church towers have we in England, with pinnacles at the corners, and none in the middle! How many buildings like King's College Chapel at Cambridge, looking like tables upside down, with their four legs in the air! What! it will be said, have not beasts four legs? Yes, but legs of different shapes, and with a head between them. So they have a pair of ears: and perhaps a pair of horns: but not at both ends. Knock down a couple of pinnacles at either end in King's College Chapel, and you will have a kind of proportion instantly. So in a cathedral you may have one tower in the centre, and two at the west end; or two at the west end only, though a worse arrangement: but you must not have two at the west and two at the east end, unless you have some central member to connect them; and even then, buildings are generally bad which have large balancing features at the extremities, and small connecting ones in the centre, because it is not easy then to make the centre dominant. The bird or moth may indeed have wide wings, because the size of the wing does not give supremacy to the wing. The head and life are the mighty things, and the plumes, however wide, are sub[Pg 122]ordinate. In fine west fronts with a pediment and two towers, the centre is always the principal mass, both in bulk and interest (as having the main gateway), and the towers are subordinated to it, as an animal's horns are to its head. The moment the towers rise so high as to overpower the body and centre, and become themselves the principal masses, they will destroy the proportion, unless they are made unequal, and one of them the leading feature of the cathedral, as at Antwerp and Strasburg. But the purer method is to keep them down in due relation to the centre, and to throw up the pediment into a steep connecting mass, drawing the eye to it by rich tracery. This is nobly done in St. Wulfran of Abbeville, and attempted partly at Rouen, though that west front is made up of so many unfinished and supervening designs that it is impossible to guess the real intention of any one of its builders.

XXVI. The first point is that wherever proportion exists, one part of the composition must be either larger than or somehow superior to the others. There is no[Pg 121] proportion among things of equal size. They can only be symmetrical, and symmetry without proportion doesn't count as composition. It's important for achieving perfect beauty, but it's the least essential of its elements, and of course, it's not hard to obtain. Any sequence of equal items is pleasing, but to compose means to arrange unequal elements, and the first step in starting a composition is deciding which will be the main element. I believe that all the knowledge written and taught about proportion combined isn't worth more than one solid rule for the architect: "Have one large element and several smaller ones, or one main feature and several subordinate ones, and tie them together well." Sometimes, there may be a regular gradation, like the heights of stories in well-designed houses; other times, there's a grand figure with a lesser accompanying one, as seen in a spire with its pinnacles. The possible arrangements are endless, but the rule is universal—have one dominant element, whether by size, function, or significance. Don't add pinnacles without a spire. Just look at the ugly church towers we have in England, with pinnacles at the corners but none in the center! How many buildings, like King's College Chapel in Cambridge, look like upside-down tables with all four legs in the air! What! One might say, don’t animals have four legs? Yes, but they have legs of different shapes and a head between them. They also have a pair of ears and, perhaps, a pair of horns—but not on both ends. Take down a couple of pinnacles at either end of King's College Chapel, and you'll create some proportion right away. Similarly, in a cathedral, you can have one tower in the center and two at the west end, or just two at the west end (though that’s a less favorable arrangement); however, you shouldn't have two at the west and two at the east unless you have a central element to connect them. Even then, buildings are generally poor if they have large features at the ends and small connecting ones in the middle, because then it's difficult to make the center stand out. A bird or moth may indeed have wide wings, but the size of the wings doesn't make them the main feature. The head and body are the main elements, and the plumes, no matter how wide, are secondary. In elegant west fronts with a pediment and two towers, the center is always the main mass in terms of size and interest (since it contains the main entrance), and the towers are subordinate to it, just like an animal's horns are to its head. The moment the towers rise high enough to overshadow the central body and become the main features themselves, they’ll disrupt the proportion unless they are unequal, with one of them being the standout element of the cathedral, as seen in Antwerp and Strasbourg. However, the better approach is to keep them proportional to the center and elevate the pediment into a steep, connecting mass, drawing attention through intricate tracery. This is magnificently done in St. Wulfran of Abbeville and is partially attempted at Rouen, although that west front comprises so many unfinished and overlapping designs that it’s impossible to discern the true intention of any of its builders.

PLATE X. PLATE X.—(Page 122—Vol. V.)
Decorative Patterns and Moldings from Rouen and Salisbury.

XXVII. This rule of supremacy applies to the smallest as well as to the leading features: it is interestingly seen in the arrangement of all good mouldings. I have given one, on the opposite page, from Rouen cathedral; that of the tracery before distinguished as a type of the noblest manner of Northern Gothic (Chap. II. § XXII.). It is a tracery of three orders, of which the first is divided into a leaf moulding, fig. 4, and b in the section, and a plain roll, also seen in fig. 4, c in the section; these two divisions surround the entire window or panelling, and are carried by two-face shafts of corresponding sections. The second and third orders are plain rolls following the line of the tracery; four divisions of moulding in all: of these four, the leaf moulding is, as seen in the sections, much the largest; next to it the outer roll; then, by an exquisite alternation, the innermost roll (e), in order that it may not be lost in the recess and the intermediate (d), the smallest. Each roll has its own shaft and capital; and the two smaller, which in effect upon the eye, owing to the retirement of the innermost, are nearly equal, have smaller capitals than the two larger, lifted a little to bring them to the same level. The wall in the trefoiled lights is curved, as from e to f in the section; but in the quatrefoil it is flat, only thrown back to the full depth of the recess below so as to get a sharp shadow [Pg 123] instead of a soft one, the mouldings falling back to it in nearly a vertical curve behind the roll e. This could not, however, be managed with the simpler mouldings of the smaller quatrefoil above, whose half section is given from g to g2; but the architect was evidently fretted by the heavy look of its circular foils as opposed to the light spring of the arches below: so he threw its cusps obliquely clear from the wall, as seen in fig. 2, attached to it where they meet the circle, but with their finials pushed out from the natural level (h, in the section) to that of the first order (g2) and supported by stone props behind, as seen in the profile fig. 2, which I got from the correspondent panel on the buttress face (fig. 1 being on its side), and of which the lower cusps, being broken away, show the remnant of one of their props projecting from the wall. The oblique curve thus obtained in the profile is of singular grace. Take it all in all, I have never met with a more exquisite piece of varied, yet severe, proportioned and general arrangement (though all the windows of the period are fine, and especially delightful in the subordinate proportioning of the smaller capitals to the smaller shafts). The only fault it has is the inevitable misarrangement of the central shafts; for the enlargement of the inner roll, though beautiful in the group of four divisions at the side, causes, in the triple central shaft, the very awkwardness of heavy lateral members which has just been in most instances condemned. In the windows of the choir, and in most of the period, this difficulty is avoided by making the fourth order a fillet which only follows the foliation, while the three outermost are nearly in arithmetical progression of size, and the central triple shaft has of course the largest roll in front. The moulding of the Palazzo Foscari (Plate VIII., and Plate IV. fig. 8) is, for so simple a group, the grandest in effect I have even seen: it is composed of a large roll with two subordinates.

XXVII. This rule of supremacy applies to both the smallest and the most prominent features, and it's interestingly reflected in the arrangement of all good moldings. On the opposite page, I've provided an example from Rouen Cathedral, which is noted for its tracery as a prime example of the finest Northern Gothic style (Chap. II. § XXII.). It consists of three orders; the first is divided into a leaf molding, fig. 4, and b in the section, and a plain roll, also shown in fig. 4, c in the section. These two elements frame the entire window or paneling and are supported by two-faced shafts of corresponding sections. The second and third orders are plain rolls that follow the line of the tracery, totaling four divisions of molding: of these, the leaf molding is, as shown in the sections, by far the largest, followed by the outer roll; then, through an elegant alternation, the innermost roll (e), so it doesn't get lost in the recess, and the intermediate roll (d), which is the smallest. Each roll has its own shaft and capital, and the two smaller ones, which visually appear almost equal due to the setback of the innermost, have smaller capitals than the larger ones, which are slightly raised to match the same level. The wall in the trefoiled lights curves from e to f in the section; however, in the quatrefoil, it's flat, only recessed to the full depth below to create a sharp shadow instead of a soft one, with the moldings falling back in a nearly vertical curve behind the roll e. This couldn’t be achieved with the simpler moldings of the smaller quatrefoil above, whose half section is shown from g to g2; but the architect was clearly concerned about the heavy appearance of its circular foils compared to the light springing arches below. So he angled the cusps away from the wall, as seen in fig. 2, attaching them where they meet the circle but pushing their tips out from the natural level (h, in the section) to that of the first order (g2) and supported by stone props behind, as seen in the profile fig. 2, which I sourced from the corresponding panel on the buttress face (fig. 1 being on its side), where the lower cusps have broken away, revealing a remnant of one of their supports sticking out from the wall. The resulting oblique curve in the profile is remarkably graceful. All in all, I have never encountered a more exquisite example of varied yet severe proportion and overall arrangement (though all windows from this period are beautiful, particularly in the delightful proportioning of the smaller capitals to the smaller shafts). The only flaw is the inevitable misalignment of the central shafts; the enlarged inner roll, while beautiful in the group of four divisions on the sides, leads to the awkwardness of heavy lateral members in the central triple shaft, which has been criticized in most cases. In the windows of the choir and throughout most of the period, this issue is resolved by making the fourth order a fillet that simply follows the foliation, while the three outer ones are almost in arithmetic progression of size, and the central triple shaft naturally has the largest roll in front. The molding of the Palazzo Foscari (Plate VIII., and Plate IV. fig. 8) is, for such a simple group, the most grand in effect I have ever seen: it consists of a large roll with two subordinate rolls.

XXVIII. It is of course impossible to enter into details of instances belonging to so intricate division of our subject, in the compass of a general essay. I can but rapidly name the chief conditions of right. Another of these is the connection[Pg 124] of Symmetry with horizontal, and of Proportion with vertical, division. Evidently there is in symmetry a sense not merely of equality, but of balance: now a thing cannot be balanced by another on the top of it, though it may by one at the side of it. Hence, while it is not only allowable, but often necessary, to divide buildings, or parts of them, horizontally into halves, thirds, or other equal parts, all vertical divisions of this kind are utterly wrong; worst into half, next worst in the regular numbers which more betray the equality. I should have thought this almost the first principle of proportion which a young architect was taught: and yet I remember an important building, recently erected in England, in which the columns are cut in half by the projecting architraves of the central windows; and it is quite usual to see the spires of modern Gothic churches divided by a band of ornament half way up. In all fine spires there are two bands and three parts, as at Salisbury. The ornamented portion of the tower is there cut in half, and allowably, because the spire forms the third mass to which the other two are subordinate: two stories are also equal in Giotto's campanile, but dominant over smaller divisions below, and subordinated to the noble third above. Even this arrangement is difficult to treat; and it is usually safer to increase or diminish the height of the divisions regularly as they rise, as in the Doge's Palace, whose three divisions are in a bold geometrical progression: or, in towers, to get an alternate proportion between the body, the belfry, and the crown, as in the campanile of St. Mark's. But, at all events, get rid of equality; leave that to children and their card houses: the laws of nature and the reason of man are alike against it, in arts, as in politics. There is but one thoroughly ugly tower in Italy that I know of, and that is so because it is divided into vertical equal parts: the tower of Pisa.12

XXVIII. It's obviously impossible to go into detail about the various cases related to such a complex topic in a general essay. I can only quickly mention the main conditions of balance. One of these is the relationship between symmetry and horizontal division, and proportion and vertical division. Clearly, symmetry involves not just equality but also balance: something can't be balanced by another object sitting on top of it, only by one beside it. Therefore, while it's not only acceptable but often necessary to divide buildings or their parts horizontally into halves, thirds, or other equal segments, all vertical divisions of this kind are completely wrong; the worst being those split in half, and next worst are the regular numbers that more obviously show equality. I would have thought this was one of the basic principles of proportion that every young architect learns: yet I remember a significant building recently built in England where the columns are split in half by the protruding architraves of the central windows; and it's quite common to see the spires of modern Gothic churches divided by a band of ornament halfway up. In all fine spires, there are two bands and three sections, like at Salisbury. The decorated part of the tower is cut in half there, which is acceptable because the spire represents the third mass that the other two support: two stories are also equal in Giotto's campanile, but they dominate over the smaller divisions below and are subordinate to the magnificent third above. Even this setup is tricky to handle; and it’s usually safer to either increase or decrease the height of the divisions consistently as they rise, like in the Doge's Palace, whose three sections follow a bold geometric progression. Or, in towers, to create an alternating proportion between the base, the belfry, and the crown, as seen in the campanile of St. Mark's. But, in any case, avoid equality; let that be for kids and their card houses: the laws of nature and human reason oppose it in art, just as in politics. There's only one truly ugly tower in Italy that I'm aware of, and that's because it's divided into vertical equal parts: the Leaning Tower of Pisa.

XXIX. One more principle of Proportion I have to name, equally simple, equally neglected. Proportion is between three terms at least. Hence, as the pinnacles are not enough without the spire, so neither the spire without the pinnacles. All men feel this and usually express their feeling by saying that[Pg 125] the pinnacles conceal the junction of the spire and tower. This is one reason; but a more influential one is, that the pinnacles furnish the third term to the spire and tower. So that it is not enough, in order to secure proportion, to divide a building unequally; it must be divided into at least three parts; it may be into more (and in details with advantage), but on a large scale I find three is about the best number of parts in elevation, and five in horizontal extent, with freedom of increase to five in the one case and seven in the other; but not to more without confusion (in architecture, that is to say; for in organic structure the numbers cannot be limited). I purpose, in the course of works which are in preparation, to give copious illustrations of this subject, but I will take at present only one instance of vertical proportion, from the flower stem of the common water plantain, Alisma Plantago. Fig. 5, Plate XII. is a reduced profile of one side of a plant gathered at random; it is seen to have five masts, of which, however, the uppermost is a mere shoot, and we can consider only their relations up to the fourth. Their lengths are measured on the line A B, which is the actual length of the lowest mass a b, A C=b c, A D=c d, and A E=d e. If the reader will take the trouble to measure these lengths and compare them, he will find that, within half a line, the uppermost A E=5/7 of A D, A D=6/8 of A C, and A C=7/9 of A B; a most subtle diminishing proportion. From each of the joints spring three major and three minor branches, each between each; but the major branches, at any joint, are placed over the minor branches at the joint below, by the curious arrangement of the joint itself—the stem is bluntly triangular; fig. 6 shows the section of any joint. The outer darkened triangle is the section of the lower stem; the inner, left light, of the upper stem; and the three main branches spring from the ledges left by the recession. Thus the stems diminish in diameter just as they diminish in height. The main branches (falsely placed in the profile over each other to show their relations) have respectively seven, six, five, four, and three arm-bones, like the masts of the stem; these divisions being proportioned in the same subtle manner. From the joints of[Pg 126] these, it seems to be the plan of the plant that three major and three minor branches should again spring, bearing the flowers: but, in these infinitely complicated members, vegetative nature admits much variety; in the plant from which these measures were taken the full complement appeared only at one of the secondary joints.

XXIX. I have one more principle of proportion to mention, which is both simple and often overlooked. Proportion involves at least three terms. Just as the pinnacles aren't complete without the spire, the spire also needs the pinnacles. Everyone senses this and usually expresses it by saying that[Pg 125] the pinnacles hide where the spire meets the tower. This is one reason; but a more significant one is that the pinnacles provide the third element between the spire and the tower. Therefore, to achieve proportion, it's not enough to divide a building unevenly; it needs to be divided into at least three parts. It could have more parts (which can be beneficial in details), but generally, I find that three is the best number for vertical elevation and five for horizontal extent, with the option to increase to five in the former case and seven in the latter; however, going beyond that can create confusion (in architecture, at least; in organic structures, the numbers aren't limited). I plan to provide plenty of examples on this topic in future works, but for now, I will share just one example of vertical proportion from the flower stem of the common water plantain, Alisma Plantago. Fig. 5, Plate XII. shows a reduced profile of one side of a randomly gathered plant; it has five masts, although the top one is just a small shoot, so we will only consider the relationships up to the fourth. Their lengths are measured along the line A B, which is the actual length of the lowest mast a b, A C=b c, A D=c d, and A E=d e. If the reader takes the time to measure these lengths and compare them, they will find that, within half a line, the uppermost A E=5/7 of A D, A D=6/8 of A C, and A C=7/9 of A B; revealing a very subtle diminishing proportion. From each joint, three major and three minor branches spring, each separated by the others; but the major branches at any joint are positioned above the minor branches of the joint below, due to the unique arrangement of the joint itself—the stem is bluntly triangular; fig. 6 illustrates the section of any joint. The outer darkened triangle represents the section of the lower stem, while the inner, lighter triangle represents the upper stem; the three main branches emerge from the ledges created by the recession. Thus, the stems shrink in diameter just as they do in height. The main branches (incorrectly displayed in the profile above each other to show their relationships) have seven, six, five, four, and three arm-bones, similar to the masts of the stem; these divisions are proportioned in the same subtle way. From the joints of[Pg 126] these, it appears to be the plant's plan for three major and three minor branches to spring again, bearing the flowers. However, in these infinitely complex parts, nature allows for much variation; in the particular plant from which these measurements were taken, the full complement only appeared at one of the secondary joints.

The leaf of this plant has five ribs on each side, as its flower generally five masts, arranged with the most exquisite grace of curve; but of lateral proportion I shall rather take illustrations from architecture: the reader will find several in the accounts of the Duomo at Pisa and St. Mark's at Venice, in Chap. V. §§ XIV.-XVI. I give these arrangements merely as illustrations, not as precedents: all beautiful proportions are unique, they are not general formulæ.

The leaf of this plant has five veins on each side, and its flower typically has five stems, arranged with an incredible elegance of curve. For side proportions, I will use examples from architecture: you can find several in the descriptions of the Duomo in Pisa and St. Mark's in Venice, in Chap. V. §§ XIV.-XVI. I share these arrangements only as examples, not as rules: all beautiful proportions are unique; they aren't general formulas.

XXX. The other condition of architectural treatment which we proposed to notice was the abstraction of imitated form. But there is a peculiar difficulty in touching within these narrow limits on such a subject as this, because the abstraction of which we find examples in existing art, is partly involuntary; and it is a matter of much nicety to determine where it begins to be purposed. In the progress of national as well as of individual mind, the first attempts at imitation are always abstract and incomplete. Greater completion marks the progress of art, absolute completion usually its decline; whence absolute completion of imitative form is often supposed to be in itself wrong. But it is not wrong always, only dangerous. Let us endeavor briefly to ascertain wherein its danger consists, and wherein its dignity.

XXX. The other aspect of architectural design we wanted to explore is the abstraction of imitated forms. However, it's a bit tricky to discuss this topic within such narrow limits because the abstraction we see in existing art is partly unintentional; it's quite delicate to pinpoint when it starts being deliberate. In both national and individual thought, the earliest attempts at imitation are always abstract and not fully developed. Greater refinement signifies progress in art, while total refinement typically marks its decline; thus, total refinement of imitative form is often seen as inherently flawed. However, it's not always wrong, just risky. Let's try to identify what makes it risky and what gives it its value.

XXXI. I have said that all art is abstract in its beginnings; that is to say, it expresses only a small number of the qualities of the thing represented. Curved and complex lines are represented by straight and simple ones; interior markings of forms are few, and much is symbolical and conventional. There is a resemblance between the work of a great nation, in this phase, and the work of childhood and ignorance, which, in the mind of a careless observer, might attach something like ridicule to it. The form of a tree on the Ninevite sculptures is much like that which, come twenty years ago, was familiar upon samplers; and[Pg 127] the types of the face and figure in early Italian art are susceptible of easy caricature. On the signs which separate the infancy of magnificent manhood from every other, I do not pause to insist (they consist entirely in the choice of the symbol and of the features abstracted); but I pass to the next stage of art, a condition of strength in which the abstraction which was begun in incapability is continued in free will. This is the case, however, in pure sculpture and painting, as well as in architecture; and we have nothing to do but with that greater severity of manner which fits either to be associated with the more realist art. I believe it properly consists only in a due expression of their subordination, an expression varying according to their place and office. The question is first to be clearly determined whether the architecture is a frame for the sculpture, or the sculpture an ornament of the architecture. If the latter, then the first office of that sculpture is not to represent the things it imitates, but to gather out of them those arrangements of form which shall be pleasing to the eye in their intended places. So soon as agreeable lines and points of shade have been added to the mouldings which were meagre, or to the lights which were unrelieved, the architectural work of the imitation is accomplished; and how far it shall be wrought towards completeness or not, will depend upon its place, and upon other various circumstances. If, in its particular use or position, it is symmetrically arranged, there is, of course, an instant indication of architectural subjection. But symmetry is not abstraction. Leaves may be carved in the most regular order, and yet be meanly imitative; or, on the other hand, they may be thrown wild and loose, and yet be highly architectural in their separate treatment. Nothing can be less symmetrical than the group of leaves which join the two columns in Plate XIII.; yet, since nothing of the leaf character is given but what is necessary for the bare suggestion of its image and the attainment of the lines desired, their treatment is highly abstract. It shows that the workman only wanted so much of the leaf as he supposed good for his architecture, and would allow no more; and how much is to be supposed good, depends, as I have said, much more on place and circumstance than on general laws. I know[Pg 128] that this is not usually thought, and that many good architects would insist on abstraction in all cases: the question is so wide and so difficult that I express my opinion upon it most diffidently; but my own feeling is, that a purely abstract manner, like that of our earliest English work, does not afford room for the perfection of beautiful form, and that its severity is wearisome after the eye has been long accustomed to it. I have not done justice to the Salisbury dog-tooth moulding, of which the effect is sketched in fig. 5, Plate X., but I have done more justice to it nevertheless than to the beautiful French one above it; and I do not think that any candid reader would deny that, piquant and spirited as is that from Salisbury, the Rouen moulding is, in every respect, nobler. It will be observed that its symmetry is more complicated, the leafage being divided into double groups of two lobes each, each lobe of different structure. With exquisite feeling, one of these double groups is alternately omitted on the other side of the moulding (not seen in the Plate, but occupying the cavetto of the section), thus giving a playful lightness to the whole; and if the reader will allow for a beauty in the flow of the curved outlines (especially on the angle), of which he cannot in the least judge from my rude drawing, he will not, I think, expect easily to find a nobler instance of decoration adapted to the severest mouldings.

XXXI. I've mentioned that all art starts off as abstract; that is, it only captures a few qualities of what it represents. Curved and complex lines are simplified into straight and simple ones; the intricate details are minimal, with much being symbolic and conventional. There's a similarity between the work of a great nation during this phase and the creations of childhood and ignorance, which might draw some ridicule from a casual observer. The depiction of a tree in ancient Ninevite sculptures resembles designs seen on samplers from twenty years ago; and[Pg 127] the facial and bodily types in early Italian art can easily be exaggerated. I'm not going to dwell on the distinguishing features that separate the early development of great artistry from everything else (which entirely involves the choice of symbols and the abstracted elements); instead, I will move on to the next phase of art, characterized by strength, where the abstraction that began from a lack of skill progresses into a deliberate choice. This applies to pure sculpture and painting, as well as architecture; and we only need to focus on the more serious style that aligns with realist art. I believe this seriousness should reflect their hierarchical relationship, a reflection that changes based on their function and context. We need to clarify first whether architecture serves as a frame for sculpture, or if sculpture is merely an ornament for architecture. If it's the latter, then the primary purpose of that sculpture isn’t to directly represent what it imitates but to distill from them those arrangements that are visually appealing in their specific settings. Once pleasing lines and shades are incorporated into the previously simplistic moldings, the architectural depiction is complete; how completely it is rendered depends on its placement and various other factors. If it's symmetrically arranged in its specific use or location, that instantly indicates its architectural role. However, symmetry doesn't equate to abstraction. Leaves may be carved in the most orderly fashion yet remain poorly imitative; conversely, they can be arranged in a chaotic manner and still be considered highly architectural in their individual treatment. Nothing is less symmetrical than the cluster of leaves joining the two columns in Plate XIII.; yet, since only the necessary elements are presented for a basic suggestion of their image and to achieve the desired lines, their treatment is highly abstract. It indicates that the craftsman only wanted enough of the leaf to suit his architecture and no more; how much is deemed suitable depends, as I've said, more on context and circumstances than on overarching rules. I understand[Pg 128] this isn't the common perspective, and many skilled architects would argue for abstraction in all situations: the scope of this question is broad and complex, so I express my views with caution; however, I feel that a purely abstract style, similar to our earliest English work, doesn’t allow for the refinement of beautiful form, and its severity can become tiresome after prolonged exposure. I haven't fully represented the Salisbury dog-tooth molding, as shown in fig. 5, Plate X., but I believe I've done it more justice than the beautiful French one above it; and I don’t think any fair-minded reader would deny that, while the Salisbury design is lively and spirited, the Rouen molding is nobler in every way. It's worth noting that its symmetry is more intricate, with the leaf design divided into pairs of lobes, each differing in form. With exquisite sensitivity, one of these pairs is alternately left out on the opposite side of the molding (not visible in the Plate, but present in the cavetto of the section), adding a playful lightness to the overall design; and if the reader can appreciate the beauty in the flow of the curved outlines (especially at the angle), which cannot be captured in my rough sketch, I believe they won’t easily find a more impressive instance of decoration suited to the strictest moldings.

Now it will be observed, that there is in its treatment a high degree of abstraction, though not so conventional as that of Salisbury: that is to say, the leaves have little more than their flow and outline represented; they are hardly undercut, but their edges are connected by a gentle and most studied curve with the stone behind; they have no serrations, no veinings, no rib or stalk on the angle, only an incision gracefully made towards their extremities, indicative of the central rib and depression. The whole style of the abstraction shows that the architect could, if he had chosen, have carried the imitation much farther, but stayed at this point of his own free will; and what he has done is also so perfect in its kind, that I feel disposed to accept his authority without question, so far as I can gather it from his works, on the whole subject of abstraction.[Pg 129]

It's clear that the approach here has a high level of abstraction, though it's not as conventional as that of Salisbury. The leaves are depicted with only their flow and outline; they're barely undercut, and their edges connect to the stone behind with a gentle, deliberate curve. There are no serrations, no veins, no rib or stalk at the angle, just a gracefully made incision towards the tips, hinting at the central rib and depression. The overall style of abstraction shows that the architect could have pushed the imitation further if he wanted to, but he chose not to. What he has created is so well done that I feel inclined to accept his perspective on abstraction without doubt, based on what I can gather from his works. [Pg 129]

XXXII. Happily his opinion is frankly expressed. This moulding is on the lateral buttress, and on a level with the top of the north gate; it cannot therefore be closely seen except from the wooden stairs of the belfry; it is not intended to be so seen, but calculated for a distance of, at least, forty to fifty feet from the eye. In the vault of the gate itself, half as near again, there are three rows of mouldings, as I think, by the same designer, at all events part of the same plan. One of them is given in Plate I. fig. 2 a. It will be seen that the abstraction is here infinitely less; the ivy leaves have stalks and associated fruit, and a rib for each lobe, and are so far undercut as to detach their forms from the stone; while in the vine-leaf moulding above, of the same period, from the south gate, serration appears added to other purely imitative characters. Finally, in the animals which form the ornaments of the portion of the gate which is close to the eye, abstraction nearly vanishes into perfect sculpture.

XXXII. Fortunately, his opinion is expressed clearly. This molding is on the side buttress and at the same height as the top of the north gate; therefore, it can only be closely seen from the wooden stairs of the belfry. It’s not meant to be viewed up close but is designed to be appreciated from a distance of at least forty to fifty feet. In the vault of the gate itself, which is even closer, there are three rows of moldings, likely by the same designer, or at least part of the same plan. One of these is shown in Plate I. fig. 2 a. You'll notice that the abstraction here is much less; the ivy leaves have stems and accompanying fruit, and a rib for each lobe, and are undercut enough to stand out from the stone. Meanwhile, in the vine-leaf molding above, from the south gate and from the same period, serration is added to other purely imitative elements. Lastly, in the animals that decorate the part of the gate that's close to view, abstraction nearly disappears into perfect sculpture.

XXXIII. Nearness to the eye, however, is not the only circumstance which influences architectural abstraction. These very animals are not merely better cut because close to the eye; they are put close to the eye that they may, without indiscretion, be better cut, on the noble principle, first I think, clearly enunciated by Mr. Eastlake, that the closest imitation shall be of the noblest object. Farther, since the wildness and manner of growth of vegetation render a bona fide imitation of it impossible in sculpture—since its members must be reduced in number, ordered in direction, and cut away from their roots, even under the most earnestly imitative treatment,—it becomes a point, as I think, of good judgment, to proportion the completeness of execution of parts to the formality of the whole; and since five or six leaves must stand for a tree, to let also five or six touches stand for a leaf. But since the animal generally admits of perfect outline—since its form is detached, and may be fully represented, its sculpture may be more complete and faithful in all its parts. And this principle will be actually found. I believe, to guide the old workmen. If the animal form be in a gargoyle, incomplete, and coining out of a block of stone, or if a head only, as for a boss[Pg 130] or other such partial use, its sculpture will be highly abstract. But if it be an entire animal, as a lizard, or a bird, or a squirrel, peeping among leafage, its sculpture will be much farther carried, and I think, if small, near the eye, and worked in a fine material, may rightly be carried to the utmost possible completion. Surely we cannot wish a less finish bestowed on those which animate the mouldings of the south door of the cathedral of Florence; nor desire that the birds in the capitals of the Doge's palace should be stripped of a single plume.

XXXIII. Being close to the eye isn’t the only factor that affects architectural abstraction. These animals aren’t just better defined because they’re near us; they’re placed close to the eye so that they can be better defined without looking out of place, following the noble idea, first clearly articulated by Mr. Eastlake, that the closest imitation should be of the most admirable object. Furthermore, the wildness and natural growth of plants make it impossible to imitate them faithfully in sculpture—since their parts need to be reduced in number, organized in direction, and detached from their roots, even with the most serious efforts at imitation—so it makes sense, I believe, to balance the level of detail in parts with the overall formality. Since five or six leaves must represent a tree, we should also let five or six strokes represent a leaf. But because animals generally allow for a perfect outline—since their shape is distinct and can be completely represented—their sculpture can be more detailed and accurate in all its elements. This approach will actually be seen, I believe, to guide the work of older craftsmen. If the animal form is represented as a gargoyle, incomplete and emerging from a stone block, or just as a head for a boss or another partial purpose, its sculpture will be quite abstract. However, if it’s a full animal, like a lizard, a bird, or a squirrel peeking through the leaves, its sculpture can be much more detailed, and I think, if small, close to the eye, and crafted from fine material, it should be taken to the maximum level of completion. Surely we wouldn’t want less detail on those that adorn the moldings of the south door of the Florence cathedral; nor would we want the birds in the capitals of the Doge’s palace to lose a single feather.

XXXIV. Under these limitations, then, I think that perfect sculpture may be made a part of the severest architecture; but this perfection was said in the outset to be dangerous. It is so in the highest degree; for the moment the architect allows himself to dwell on the imitated portions, there is a chance of his losing sight of the duty of his ornament, of its business as a part of the composition, and sacrificing its points of shade and effect to the delight of delicate carving. And then he is lost. His architecture has become a mere framework for the setting of delicate sculpture, which had better be all taken down and put into cabinets. It is well, therefore, that the young architect should be taught to think of imitative ornament as of the extreme of grace in language; not to be regarded at first, not to be obtained at the cost of purpose, meaning, force, or conciseness, yet, indeed, a perfection—the least of all perfections, and yet the crowning one of all—one which by itself, and regarded in itself, is an architectural coxcombry, but is yet the sign of the most highly-trained mind and power when it is associated with others. It is a safe manner, as I think, to design all things at first in severe abstraction, and to be prepared, if need were, to carry them out in that form; then to mark the parts where high finish would be admissible, to complete these always with stern reference to their general effect, and then connect them by a graduated scale of abstraction with the rest. And there is one safeguard against danger in this process on which I would finally insist. Never imitate anything but natural forms, and those the noblest, in the completed parts. The [Pg 131] degradation of the cinque cento manner of decoration was not owing to its naturalism, to its faithfulness of imitation, but to its imitation of ugly, i.e. unnatural things. So long as it restrained itself to sculpture of animals and flowers, it remained noble. The balcony, on the opposite page, from a house in the Campo St. Benedetto at Venice, shows one of the earliest occurrences of the cinque cento arabesque, and a fragment of the pattern is given in Plate XII. fig. 8. It is but the arresting upon the stone work of a stem or two of the living flowers, which are rarely wanting in the window above (and which, by the by, the French and Italian peasantry often trellis with exquisite taste about their casements). This arabesque, relieved as it is in darkness from the white stone by the stain of time, is surely both beautiful and pure; and as long as the renaissance ornament remained in such forms it may be beheld with undeserved admiration. But the moment that unnatural objects were associated with these, and armor, and musical instruments, and wild meaningless scrolls and curled shields, and other such fancies, became principal in its subjects, its doom was sealed, and with it that of the architecture of the world.

XXXIV. With these limitations in mind, I think perfect sculpture can be integrated into the strictest architecture; however, this perfection can be quite risky. It really is, because the moment an architect starts to focus on the imitative parts, he risks losing sight of the ornament's purpose as part of the overall design, prioritizing the beauty of delicate carving over its intended effect. Once that happens, it’s all downhill from there. The architecture turns into just a backdrop for delicate sculptures that would be better off displayed in cabinets. Therefore, it's important for young architects to see imitative ornament as the epitome of elegance in language; it shouldn't be the initial focus, and should never be pursued at the expense of purpose, meaning, strength, or brevity. Yet, it is a kind of perfection—though it is the least important of all perfections, it is also the crowning one. It can seem like architectural fussiness when looked at alone, but when associated with other elements, it shows a highly skilled and powerful mind. I believe it's wise to initially design everything with a strict abstract approach, ready to carry them out in that form if necessary; then identify areas where fine details may be appropriate, always keeping in mind their overall effect, and linking them through varying degrees of abstraction with everything else. There's also one crucial safeguard against potential pitfalls that I want to highlight. Only imitate natural forms, and those that are the most noble, in the finished parts. The decline of the cinque cento style of decoration wasn't due to its naturalism or accurate imitation, but rather its imitation of ugly, i.e., unnatural things. It maintained its nobility as long as it stuck to sculptures of animals and flowers. The balcony on the opposite page, from a house in the Campo St. Benedetto in Venice, shows one of the earliest examples of the cinque cento arabesque, and a fragment of the pattern is illustrated in Plate XII, fig. 8. It simply captures on the stonework a stem or two of the living flowers, which are typically found in the window above (and which, by the way, French and Italian peasants often adorn with great taste around their windows). This arabesque, standing out against the white stone due to the stain of time, is undoubtedly beautiful and pure; as long as renaissance ornamentation stayed in such forms, it could be admired without justification. But the moment unnatural objects were introduced, along with armor, musical instruments, random scrolls, curled shields, and other such whims, its downfall was inevitable, along with the architecture of the world.

PLATE XI. PLATE XI.—(Page 131—Vol. V.)
Balcony in the Campo, St. Benedetto, Venice.

XXXV. III. Our final inquiry was to be into the use of color as associated with architectural ornament.

XXXV. III. Our last question was about how color is used in relation to architectural decoration.

I do not feel able to speak with any confidence respecting the touching of sculpture with color. I would only note one point, that sculpture is the representation of an idea, while architecture is itself a real thing. The idea may, as I think, be left colorless, and colored by the beholder's mind: but a reality ought to have reality in all its attributes: its color should be as fixed as its form. I cannot, therefore, consider architecture as in any wise perfect without color. Farther, as I have above noticed, I think the colors of architecture should be those of natural stones; partly because more durable, but also because more perfect and graceful. For to conquer the harshness and deadness of tones laid upon stone or on gesso, needs the management and discretion of a true painter; and on this co-operation we must not calculate in laying down rules for general practice. If Tintoret or Giorgione are at hand, and ask us for a wall to paint, we will alter our whole design[Pg 132] for their sake, and become their servants; but we must, as architects, expect the aid of the common workman only; and the laying of color by a mechanical hand, and its toning under a vulgar eye, are far more offensive than rudeness in cutting the stone. The latter is imperfection only; the former deadness or discordance. At the best, such color is so inferior to the lovely and mellow hues of the natural stone, that it is wise to sacrifice some of the intricacy of design, if by so doing we may employ the nobler material. And if, as we looked to Nature for instruction respecting form, we look to her also to learn the management of color, we shall, perhaps, find that this sacrifice of intricacy is for other causes expedient.

I don't feel confident discussing the use of color in sculpture. I just want to point out that sculpture represents an idea, while architecture is a tangible reality. The idea can, in my opinion, remain colorless and be interpreted by the viewer's imagination; however, a reality should have full reality in all its aspects: its color should be as established as its form. Therefore, I can't consider architecture complete without color. Additionally, as I've noted before, I believe the colors of architecture should reflect the tones of natural stones; this is partly because they are more durable, but also because they are more refined and graceful. To overcome the harshness and lifelessness of colors applied to stone or gesso takes the skill and judgment of a true painter; we can't rely on such collaboration when establishing rules for general practice. If Tintoretto or Giorgione were available and asked us for a wall to paint, we'd change our entire design for them and serve their needs; but as architects, we should only expect assistance from skilled laborers. Using color applied by an unskilled hand, viewed with a lack of refinement, is much more distracting than rough stone cutting. The latter is just imperfection, while the former causes lifelessness or disharmony. Even at its best, such color is far inferior to the beautiful and warm hues of natural stone, making it wise to simplify some design details if it allows us to use superior materials. If we look to Nature for guidance on form, we should also turn to her for lessons on color management; we might find that this simplification is beneficial for other reasons as well.

XXXVI. First, then, I think that in making this reference we are to consider our building as a kind of organized creature; in coloring which we must look to the single and separately organized creatures of Nature, not to her landscape combinations. Our building, if it is well composed, is one thing, and is to be colored as Nature would color one thing—a shell, a flower, or an animal; not as she colors groups of things.

XXXVI. First, I believe that when we refer to this, we should think of our building as a sort of living being; in its coloring, we should look at individual, distinct forms in nature, not at the landscapes made up of multiple elements. Our building, if designed well, is a singular entity and should be colored in the way nature would color a single item—a shell, a flower, or an animal; not in the way she colors groups of objects.

And the first broad conclusion we shall deduce from observance of natural color in such cases will be, that it never follows form, but is arranged on an entirely separate system. What mysterious connection there may be between the shape of the spots on an animal's skin and its anatomical system, I do not know, nor even if such a connection has in any wise been traced: but to the eye the systems are entirely separate, and in many cases that of color is accidentally variable. The stripes of a zebra do not follow the lines of its body or limbs, still less the spots of a leopard. In the plumage of birds, each feather bears a part of the pattern which is arbitrarily carried over the body, having indeed certain graceful harmonies with the form, diminishing or enlarging in directions which sometimes follow, but also not unfrequently oppose, the directions of its muscular lines. Whatever harmonies there may be, are distinctly like those of two separate musical parts, coinciding here and there only—never discordant, but essentially different I hold this, then, for the first great principle[Pg 133] of architectural color. Let it be visibly independent of form. Never paint a column with vertical lines, but always cross it.13 Never give separate mouldings separate colors (I know this is heresy, but I never shrink from any conclusions, however contrary to human authority, to which I am led by observance of natural principles); and in sculptured ornaments I do not paint the leaves or figures (I cannot help the Elgin frieze) of one color and their ground of another, but vary both the ground and the figures with the same harmony. Notice how Nature does it in a variegated flower; not one leaf red and another white, but a point of red and a zone of white, or whatever it may be, to each. In certain places you may run your two systems closer, and here and there let them be parallel for a note or two, but see that the colors and the forms coincide only as two orders of mouldings do; the same for an instant, but each holding its own course. So single members may sometimes have single colors: as a bird's head is sometimes of one color and its shoulders another, you may make your capital of one color and your shaft another; but in general the best place for color is on broad surfaces, not on the points of interest in form. An animal is mottled on its breast and back, rarely on its paws or about its eyes; so put your variegation boldly on the flat wall and broad shaft, but be shy of it in the capital and moulding; in all cases it is a safe rule to simplify color when form is rich, and vice versâ; and I think it would be well in general to carve all capitals and graceful ornaments in white marble, and so leave them.

And the first big takeaway from observing natural color in these cases is that it doesn’t follow the shape; instead, it has its own separate system. I don't know what kind of connection there might be between the patterns on an animal’s skin and its anatomy, or if such a connection has even been established. However, to the eye, the systems are completely independent, and in many instances, the colors can change randomly. Zebra stripes don’t follow the contours of their bodies or limbs, and the same goes for leopard spots. In bird feathers, each feather has part of the pattern that is arranged across the body in a way that may be harmonious with the shape, sometimes aligning with it, but often opposing the direction of its muscles. Any harmonies present resemble two distinct musical parts that occasionally overlap but are never discordant—each remains fundamentally different. I consider this the first major principle of architectural color: it should be clearly independent of form. Don't paint a column with vertical lines; always cross them instead. Don’t give separate moldings different colors (I realize this might be considered heresy, but I refuse to shy away from any conclusions that natural principles lead me to, even if they contradict established beliefs). In sculpted decorations, I don’t paint the leaves or figures (I can’t change the Elgin frieze) in one color and their background in another; I adjust both the background and the figures to match a consistent harmony. Look at how nature does it in a colorful flower—no leaf is red while another is white, but rather a spot of red and a band of white, or whatever it may be, for each. In some areas, you can bring your two systems closer together, and let them align for a moment or two, but ensure that colors and shapes only coincide like two different moldings—similar for just a moment, but each continuing on its own path. Sometimes individual parts can have single colors: a bird might have one color on its head and another on its shoulders, so you can make your capital one color and your shaft another. However, generally, the best places for color are on broad surfaces, not where the shape is most interesting. An animal is usually spotted on its chest and back, but rarely on its paws or around its eyes. So, place your variations boldly on the flat walls and broad shafts, but be cautious with them on capitals and moldings. A good rule is to simplify color when the shape is intricate, and vice versa. Overall, I think it would be wise to carve all capitals and elegant decorations in white marble and leave them as such.

XXXVII. Independence then being first secured, what kind of limiting outlines shall we adopt for the system of color itself?

XXXVII. Now that independence is secured, what boundaries should we set for the color system itself?

I am quite sure that any person familiar with natural objects will never be surprised at any appearance of care or finish in them. That is the condition of the universe. But there is cause both for surprise and inquiry whenever we see anything like carelessness or incompletion: that is not a common condition; it must be one appointed for some singular purpose. I believe that such surprise will be forcibly felt by any one who, after studying carefully the lines of some variegated organic[Pg 134] form, will set himself to copy with similar diligence those of its colors. The boundaries of the forms he will assuredly, whatever the object, have found drawn with a delicacy and precision which no human hand can follow. Those of its colors he will find in many cases, though governed always by a certain rude symmetry, yet irregular, blotched, imperfect, liable to all kinds of accidents and awkwardnesses. Look at the tracery of the lines on a camp shell, and see how oddly and awkwardly its tents are pitched. It is not indeed always so: there is occasionally, as in the eye of the peacock's plume, an apparent precision, but still a precision far inferior to that of the drawing of the filaments which bear that lovely stain; and in the plurality of cases a degree of looseness and variation, and, still more singularly, of harshness and violence in arrangement, is admitted in color which would be monstrous in form. Observe the difference in the precision of a fish's scales and of the spots on them.

I'm pretty sure that anyone who knows about natural objects won’t be surprised by any signs of care or detail in them. That’s just how the universe is. But it does raise questions and surprise when we see anything that seems careless or incomplete; that’s not the usual state of things. It must be intended for some special purpose. I think anyone trying to carefully copy the intricate lines of a colorful organic form will feel this surprise strongly. No matter the object, the outlines of the shapes will be drawn with a delicacy and precision that no human can replicate. However, when it comes to colors, he’ll often find them, while always following some rough symmetry, to be irregular, blotchy, imperfect, and subject to all kinds of accidents and awkwardness. Look at the patterns of lines on a clam shell, for example, and see how oddly and unevenly its tents are arranged. It’s not always like this, though—sometimes, like in the eye of a peacock feather, there’s an apparent precision, but it’s still far less precise than the drawing of the threads holding that beautiful color; and in many cases, there is a looseness and variation, along with a strangely harsh and chaotic arrangement in color that would be shocking if it were in form. Notice the difference in the precision of a fish’s scales compared to the spots on them.

XXXVIII. Now, why it should be that color is best seen under these circumstances I will not here endeavor to determine; nor whether the lesson we are to learn from it be that it is God's will that all manner of delights should never be combined in one thing. But the fact is certain, that color is always by Him arranged in these simple or rude forms, and as certain that, therefore, it must be best seen in them, and that we shall never mend by refining its arrangements. Experience teaches us the same thing. Infinite nonsense has been written about the union of perfect color with perfect form. They never will, never can be united. Color, to be perfect, must have a soft outline or a simple one: it cannot have a refined one; and you will never produce a good painted window with good figure-drawing in it. You will lose perfection of color as you give perfection of line. Try to put in order and form the colors of a piece of opal.

XXXVIII. Now, why this color is best seen under these circumstances, I won't try to figure out here; nor will I discuss whether the lesson we should take from it is that it's God's will for all kinds of pleasures to never be combined into one thing. But it’s clear that color is always arranged by Him in these simple or rough forms, and it’s equally clear that it must be best seen in them—and that we won't improve it by refining its arrangements. Experience shows us the same thing. A ton of nonsense has been written about the combination of perfect color with perfect form. They will never unite, and they can’t. For color to be perfect, it must have a soft outline or a simple one; it can’t have a refined one; and you’ll never create a good painted window with good figure-drawing in it. You’ll lose color perfection as you gain line perfection. Try to arrange the colors of a piece of opal.

XXXIX. I conclude, then, that all arrangements of color, for its own sake, in graceful forms, are barbarous; and that, to paint a color pattern with the lovely lines of a Greek leaf moulding, is an utterly savage procedure. I cannot find anything in natural color like this: it is not in the bond. I find[Pg 135] it in all natural form—never in natural color. If, then, our architectural color is to be beautiful as its form was, by being imitative, we are limited to these conditions—to simple masses of it, to zones, as in the rainbow and the zebra; cloudings and flamings, as in marble shells and plumage, or spots of various shapes and dimensions. All these conditions are susceptible of various degrees of sharpness and delicacy, and of complication in arrangement. The zone may become a delicate line, and arrange itself in chequers and zig-zags. The flaming may be more or less defined, as on a tulip leaf, and may at last be represented by a triangle of color, and arrange itself in stars or other shapes; the spot may be also graduated into a stain, or defined into a square or circle. The most exquisite harmonies may be composed of these simple elements: some soft and full of flushed and melting spaces of color; others piquant and sparkling, or deep and rich, formed of close groups of the fiery fragments: perfect and lovely proportion may be exhibited in the relation of their quantities, infinite invention in their disposition: but, in all cases, their shape will be effective only as it determines their quantity, and regulates their operation on each other; points or edges of one being introduced between breadths of others, and so on. Triangular and barred forms are therefore convenient, or others the simplest possible; leaving the pleasure of the spectator to be taken in the color, and in that only. Curved outlines, especially if refined, deaden the color, and confuse the mind. Even in figure painting the greatest colorists have either melted their outline away, as often Correggio and Rubens; or purposely made their masses of ungainly shape, as Titian; or placed their brightest hues in costume, where they could get quaint patterns, as Veronese, and especially Angelico, with whom, however, the absolute virtue of color is secondary to grace of line. Hence, he never uses the blended hues of Correggio, like those on the wing of the little Cupid, in the "Venus and Mercury," but always the severest type—the peacock plume. Any of these men would have looked with infinite disgust upon the leafage and scrollwork which form the ground of color in our modern painted[Pg 136] windows, and yet all whom I have named were much infected with the love of renaissance designs. We must also allow for the freedom of the painter's subject, and looseness of his associated lines; a pattern being severe in a picture, which is over luxurious upon a building. I believe, therefore, that it is impossible to be over quaint or angular in architectural coloring; and thus many dispositions which I have had occasion to reprobate in form, are, in color, the best that can be invented. I have always, for instance, spoken with contempt of the Tudor style, for this reason, that, having surrendered all pretence to spaciousness and breadth,—having divided its surfaces by an infinite number of lines, it yet sacrifices the only characters which can make lines beautiful; sacrifices all the variety and grace which long atoned for the caprice of the Flamboyant, and adopts, for its leading feature, an entanglement of cross bars and verticals, showing about as much invention or skill of design as the reticulation of the bricklayer's sieve. Yet this very reticulation would in color be highly beautiful; and all the heraldry, and other features which, in form, are monstrous, may be delightful as themes of color (so long as there are no fluttering or over-twisted lines in them); and this observe, because, when colored, they take the place of a mere pattern, and the resemblance to nature, which could not be found in their sculptured forms, is found in their piquant variegation of other surfaces. There is a beautiful and bright bit of wall painting behind the Duomo of Verona, composed of coats of arms, whose bearings are balls of gold set in bars of green (altered blue?) and white, with cardinal's hats in alternate squares. This is of course, however, fit only for domestic work. The front of the Doge's palace at Venice is the purest and most chaste model that I can name (but one) of the fit application of color to public buildings. The sculpture and mouldings are all white; but the wall surface is chequered with marble blocks of pale rose, the chequers being in no wise harmonized, or fitted to the forms of the windows; but looking as if the surface had been completed first, and the windows cut out of it. In Plate XII. fig. 2 the reader will see two of the patterns[Pg 137] used in green and white, on the columns of San Michele of Lucca, every column having a different design. Both are beautiful, but the upper one certainly the best. Yet in sculpture its lines would have been perfectly barbarous, and those even of the lower not enough refined.

XXXIX. I conclude that all arrangements of color, simply for aesthetics, in elegant forms, are uncivilized; and that painting a color pattern with the beautiful lines of a Greek leaf design is a completely barbaric act. I can’t find anything in natural colors that resembles this: it doesn’t exist in nature. I find it in all natural forms—never in natural colors. Therefore, if our architectural color is to be as beautiful as its form, by imitating nature, we are limited to these conditions: simple masses, zones like in the rainbow and zebra; cloudings and flames, like in marble shells and feathers, or spots of various shapes and sizes. All these elements can have different degrees of sharpness and delicacy, and can be arranged in complex ways. The zone can become a delicate line and arrange itself in checks and zigzags. The flaming can be more or less defined, like on a tulip leaf, and can ultimately be represented by a triangle of color, arranged in stars or other shapes; the spot can also transition into a stain or be defined as a square or circle. The most exquisite harmonies can be made from these simple elements: some soft with lush and melting spaces of color; others sharp and sparkling, or deep and rich, made of tightly grouped fiery fragments: perfect and beautiful proportions can emerge from the relation of their quantities, infinite creativity in their arrangement: but, in all cases, their shape will only be effective as it influences their quantity and controls their interaction; points or edges of one introduced between areas of others, and so on. Triangular and barred forms are therefore practical, or others that are as simple as possible; allowing the viewer to appreciate the color alone. Curved outlines, especially if refined, dull the color and confuse the mind. Even in figure painting, the greatest colorists have either blended their outlines away, like Correggio and Rubens; or intentionally created masses of awkward shapes, like Titian; or placed their brightest colors in costumes, where they could get interesting patterns, like Veronese, and especially Angelico, though for him, the pure quality of color comes second to line grace. That’s why he never uses the blended hues of Correggio, like those on the wing of little Cupid in "Venus and Mercury," but always the strict type—the peacock feather. Any of these artists would have looked with great disdain at the foliage and scrollwork that make up the background colors in our modern stained glass windows, yet all of them were quite fond of renaissance designs. We must also consider the painter’s freedom regarding subject matter and the looseness of associated lines; a pattern might seem strict in a picture, which could be overly lush on a building. Therefore, I believe it’s impossible to be overly quaint or angular in architectural coloring; thus, many arrangements I’ve criticized in form may be the best solutions in color. For example, I’ve always spoken disdainfully of the Tudor style because, having abandoned any claim to spaciousness and breadth—dividing its surfaces with countless lines—it sacrifices the only qualities that can make lines beautiful; all the variety and grace that long made up for the quirks of the Flamboyant are gone, in favor of a tangle of crossbars and verticals, showing almost as much creativity or design skill as the mesh of a bricklayer's sieve. Yet this very mesh could be quite beautiful when colored; and all the heraldry and other features that are monstrous in form can be delightful as color themes (as long as there are no fluttering or overly twisted lines in them); and take note, because when colored, they serve as mere patterns, and the resemblance to nature, which can’t be found in their sculpted forms, is found in their striking variation across other surfaces. There’s a lovely and vibrant section of wall painting behind the Duomo of Verona, made of coats of arms, whose symbols are gold balls set in green (or altered blue?) and white, with cardinal's hats in alternating squares. This, of course, is only suitable for domestic work. The front of the Doge's palace in Venice is the purest and most chaste example I can name (except one) of color’s proper application to public buildings. The sculptures and moldings are all white; but the wall surface is checkered with pale rose-colored marble blocks, the checks being in no way harmonized or fitted to the window shapes; it looks like the surface was completed first, and then the windows were cut out of it. In Plate XII. fig. 2, the reader will see two patterns[Pg 137] used in green and white on the columns of San Michele of Lucca, each column featuring a different design. Both are beautiful, but the upper one is definitely the best. Yet in sculpture, its lines would be utterly barbaric, even the lower one not refined enough.

XL. Restraining ourselves, therefore, to the use of such simple patterns, so far forth as our color is subordinate either to architectural structure, or sculptural form, we have yet one more manner of ornamentation to add to our general means of effect, monochrome design, the intermediate condition between coloring and carving. The relations of the entire system of architectural decoration may then be thus expressed.

XL. By limiting ourselves to these simple patterns, where our color supports either the architectural structure or the sculptural form, we have one more way to add to our overall effect: monochrome design, which is the middle ground between coloring and carving. The connections within the entire system of architectural decoration can then be described like this.

1. Organic form dominant. True, independent sculpture, and alto-relievo; rich capitals, and mouldings; to be elaborate in completion of form, not abstract, and either to be left in pure white marble, or most cautiously touched with color in points and borders only, in a system not concurrent with their forms.

1. Organic form is key. Genuine, independent sculpture and alto-relievo; intricate capitals and moldings; the focus is on detailed completion of form, not abstraction, and it should either remain in pure white marble or be carefully highlighted with color only at points and edges, in a way that doesn’t clash with their shapes.

2. Organic form sub-dominant. Basso-relievo or intaglio. To be more abstract in proportion to the reduction of depth; to be also more rigid and simple in contour; to be touched with color more boldly and in an increased degree, exactly in proportion to the reduced depth and fulness of form, but still in a system non-concurrent with their forms.

2. Organic form is less prominent. Low relief or engraving. It should be more abstract as the depth is reduced; it should also become more rigid and simple in shape; it should be painted with color more boldly and to a greater extent, in direct proportion to the reduced depth and fullness of form, but still following a style that doesn't match their shapes.

3. Organic form abstracted to outline. Monochrome design, still farther reduced to simplicity of contour, and therefore admitting for the first time the color to be concurrent with its outlines; that is to say, as its name imports, the entire figure to be detached in one color from a ground of another.

3. Organic shape simplified to a basic outline. Monochrome design is further simplified to just the shape, allowing the color to align with its outlines for the first time; in other words, as its name suggests, the entire figure stands out in one color against a different background.

4. Organic forms entirely lost. Geometrical patterns or variable cloudings in the most vivid color.

4. Organic shapes completely gone. Geometric patterns or swirling clouds in the brightest colors.

On the opposite side of this scale, ascending from the color pattern, I would place the various forms of painting which may be associated with architecture: primarily, and as most[Pg 138] fit for such purpose, the mosaic, highly abstract in treatment, and introducing brilliant color in masses; the Madonna of Torcello being, as I think, the noblest type of the manner, and the Baptistery of Parma the richest: next, the purely decorative fresco, like that of the Arena Chapel; finally, the fresco becoming principal, as in the Vatican and Sistine. But I cannot, with any safety, follow the principles of abstraction in this pictorial ornament; since the noblest examples of it appear to me to owe their architectural applicability to their archaic manner; and I think that the abstraction and admirable simplicity which render them fit media of the most splendid coloring, cannot be recovered by a voluntary condescension. The Byzantines themselves would not, I think, if they could have drawn the figure better, have used it for a color decoration; and that use, as peculiar to a condition of childhood, however noble and full of promise, cannot be included among those modes of adornment which are now legitimate or even possible. There is a difficulty in the management of the painted window for the same reason, which has not yet been met, and we must conquer that first, before we can venture to consider the wall as a painted window on a large scale. Pictorial subject, without such abstraction, becomes necessarily principal, or, at all events, ceases to be the architect's concern; its plan must be left to the painter after the completion of the building, as in the works of Veronese and Giorgione on the palaces of Venice.

On the other side of this scale, moving away from the color pattern, I would place the different types of painting associated with architecture. Primarily, and most suitable for this purpose, is the mosaic, which is highly abstract and features bold colors in large areas; I believe the Madonna of Torcello is the finest example of this style, while the Baptistery of Parma is the richest. Next is purely decorative fresco, like that found in the Arena Chapel; and finally, the fresco takes a central role, as seen in the Vatican and Sistine. However, I cannot reliably apply the principles of abstraction to this pictorial decoration. The best examples seem to owe their architectural relevance to their archaic style; I believe that the abstraction and remarkable simplicity that make them ideal for vibrant coloring cannot be achieved through intentional effort. I think the Byzantines, if they could have created a better figure, would not have used it for color decoration; that use, while noble and full of potential, belongs to a more immature state and cannot be considered among the forms of adornment that are now acceptable or even possible. There is a challenge in managing the painted window for the same reason, which hasn’t been resolved yet, and we need to overcome that first before we can think of the wall as a large-scale painted window. Pictorial subjects, without that abstraction, inevitably become central, or at least stop being the architect's focus; their design must be left to the painter after the building is completed, as seen in the works of Veronese and Giorgione on the palaces of Venice.

XLI. Pure architectural decoration, then, may be considered as limited to the four kinds above specified; of which each glides almost imperceptibly into the other. Thus, the Elgin frieze is a monochrome in a state of transition to sculpture, retaining, as I think, the half-cast skin too long. Of pure monochrome, I have given an example in Plate VI., from the noble front of St. Michele of Lucca. It contains forty such arches, all covered with equally elaborate ornaments, entirely drawn by cutting out their ground to about the depth of an inch in the flat white marble, and filling the spaces with pieces of green serpentine; a most elaborate mode of sculpture, requiring excessive care and precision in the fitting of[Pg 139] the edges, and of course double work, the same line needing to be cut both in the marble and serpentine. The excessive simplicity of the forms will be at once perceived; the eyes of the figures of animals, for instance, being indicated only by a round dot, formed by a little inlet circle of serpentine, about half an inch over: but, though simple, they admit often much grace of curvature, as in the neck of the bird seen above the right hand pillar.14 The pieces of serpentine have fallen out in many places, giving the black shadows, as seen under the horseman's arm and bird's neck, and in the semi-circular line round the arch, once filled with some pattern. It would have illustrated my point better to have restored the lost portions, but I always draw a thing exactly as it is, hating restoration of any kind; and I would especially direct the reader's attention to the completion of the forms in the sculptured ornament of the marble cornices, as opposed to the abstraction of the monochrome figures, of the ball and cross patterns between the arches, and of the triangular ornament round the arch on the left.

XLI. Pure architectural decoration can be seen as limited to the four types mentioned above, each seamlessly transitioning into the next. For example, the Elgin frieze is a monochrome that's in the process of becoming sculpture, as it clings to its half-formed state for too long. I provided an example of pure monochrome in Plate VI., from the impressive front of St. Michele of Lucca. It features forty arches, all adorned with intricate ornaments, created by carving away the background to about an inch deep in the flat white marble, then filling the spaces with pieces of green serpentine. This is a highly detailed form of sculpture that demands extreme care and precision in fitting the edges, and it requires double the work since the same line has to be cut into both the marble and the serpentine. The striking simplicity of the forms is immediately noticeable; for instance, the eyes of the animal figures are just represented by a round dot, made by a small circular cut of serpentine about half an inch wide. Despite their simplicity, these forms often have a lot of graceful curves, like in the neck of the bird above the right-hand pillar. The serpentine pieces have fallen out in many areas, creating dark shadows, as seen under the horseman’s arm and the bird’s neck, as well as in the semi-circular line around the arch, which was once decorated with a pattern. Restoring the lost parts would have better illustrated my point, but I prefer to represent things exactly as they are, avoiding any kind of restoration. I particularly want to draw the reader's attention to the completion of the forms in the sculptured ornament of the marble cornices, in contrast to the abstraction of the monochrome figures, the ball and cross patterns between the arches, and the triangular design around the arch on the left.

XLII. I have an intense love for these monochrome figures, owing to their wonderful life and spirit in all the works on which I found them; nevertheless, I believe that the excessive degree of abstraction which they imply necessitates our placing them in the rank of a progressive or imperfect art, and that a perfect building should rather be composed of the highest sculpture (organic form dominant and sub-dominant), associated with pattern colors on the flat or broad surfaces. And we find, in fact, that the cathedral of Pisa, which is a higher type than that of Lucca, exactly follows this condition, the color being put in geometrical patterns on its surfaces, and animal-forms and lovely leafage used in the sculptured cornices and pillars. And I think that the grace of the carved forms is best seen when it is thus boldly opposed to severe traceries of color, while the color itself is, as we have seen, always most piquant when it is put into sharp angular arrangements. Thus the sculpture is approved and set off by the color, and the color seen to the best advantage in its opposition both to the whiteness and the grace of the carved marble.[Pg 140]

XLII. I have a deep appreciation for these monochrome figures because of the incredible life and spirit they bring to the works I found them in. However, I think the high level of abstraction they represent means we should view them as a developing or imperfect art form, and that an ideal building should instead be made of the finest sculpture (with organic forms being dominant and sub-dominant), combined with patterned colors on flat or broad surfaces. In fact, the cathedral of Pisa, which is of a higher standard than that of Lucca, perfectly exemplifies this idea, with colors arranged in geometric patterns on its surfaces, and animal shapes and beautiful foliage featured in the sculpted cornices and pillars. I believe the beauty of the carved forms is best highlighted when it stands in striking contrast to the bold color patterns, while the colors themselves, as we've noted, are most vibrant when arranged sharply in angular designs. In this way, the sculpture is enhanced by the color, and the color is seen in its best light when pitted against the whiteness and elegance of the carved marble.[Pg 140]

XLIII. In the course of this and the preceding chapters, I have now separately enumerated most of the conditions of Power and Beauty, which in the outset I stated to be the grounds of the deepest impressions with which architecture could affect the human mind; but I would ask permission to recapitulate them in order to see if there be any building which I may offer as an example of the unison, in such manner as is possible, of them all. Glancing back, then, to the beginning of the third chapter, and introducing in their place the conditions incidentally determined in the two previous sections, we shall have the following list of noble characters:

XLIII. Throughout this chapter and the ones before it, I have listed most of the aspects of Power and Beauty, which I initially mentioned as the key factors that architecture can have on the human mind. However, I’d like to summarize them again to see if there’s any building that I can use as an example of the harmony, as much as possible, of all these aspects. Looking back to the start of the third chapter and substituting in the conditions defined in the two previous sections, we will have the following list of impressive qualities:

Considerable size, exhibited by simple terminal lines (Chap. III. § 6). Projection towards the top (§ 7). Breadth of flat surface (§ 8). Square compartments of that surface (§ 9). Varied and visible masonry (§ 11). Vigorous depth of shadow (§ 13), exhibited especially by pierced traceries (§ 18). Varied proportion in ascent (Chap. IV. § 28). Lateral symmetry (§ 28). Sculpture most delicate at the base (Chap. I. § 12). Enriched quantity of ornament at the top (§ 13). Sculpture abstract in inferior ornaments and mouldings (Chap. IV. § 31), complete in animal forms (§ 33). Both to be executed in white marble (§ 40). Vivid color introduced in flat geometrical patterns (§ 39), and obtained by the use of naturally colored stone (§ 35).

Considerable size, shown by simple terminal lines (Chap. III. § 6). Projection towards the top (§ 7). Width of the flat surface (§ 8). Square sections of that surface (§ 9). Varied and visible masonry (§ 11). Strong depth of shadow (§ 13), especially shown by pierced traceries (§ 18). Varied proportion in height (Chap. IV. § 28). Side symmetry (§ 28). Most delicate sculpture at the base (Chap. I. § 12). Rich decoration at the top (§ 13). Abstract sculpture in lower ornaments and moldings (Chap. IV. § 31), complete in animal forms (§ 33). Both to be made in white marble (§ 40). Bright color introduced in flat geometric patterns (§ 39), achieved by using naturally colored stone (§ 35).

These characteristics occur more or less in different buildings, some in one and some in another. But all together, and all in their highest possible relative degrees, they exist, as far as I know, only in one building in the world, the Campanile of Giotto at Florence. The drawing of the tracery of its upper story, which heads this chapter, rude as it is, will nevertheless give the reader some better conception of that tower's magnificence than the thin outlines in which it is usually portrayed. In its first appeal to the stranger's eye there is something unpleasing; a mingling, as it seems to him, of over severity with over minuteness. But let him give it time, as he should to all other consummate art. I remember well how, when a boy, I used to despise that Campanile, and think it meanly smooth and finished. But I have since lived beside it many a day, and looked out upon it from my windows by sunlight and[Pg 141] moonlight, and I shall not soon forget how profound and gloomy appeared to me the savageness of the Northern Gothic, when I afterwards stood, for the first time, beneath the front of Salisbury. The contrast is indeed strange, if it could be quickly felt, between the rising of those grey walls out of their quiet swarded space, like dark and barren rocks out of a green lake, with their rude, mouldering, rough-grained shafts, and triple lights, without tracery or other ornament than the martins' nests in the height of them, and that bright, smooth, sunny surface of glowing jasper, those spiral shafts and fairy traceries, so white, so faint, so crystalline, that their slight shapes are hardly traced in darkness on the pallor of the Eastern sky, that serene height of mountain alabaster, colored like a morning cloud, and chased like a sea shell. And if this be, as I believe it, the model and mirror of perfect architecture, is there not something to be learned by looking back to the early life of him who raised it? I said that the Power of human mind had its growth in the Wilderness; much more must the love and the conception of that beauty, whose every line and hue we have seen to be, at the best, a faded image of God's daily work, and an arrested ray of some star of creation, be given chiefly in the places which He has gladdened by planting there the fir tree and the pine. Not within the walls of Florence, but among the far away fields of her lilies, was the child trained who was to raise that headstone of Beauty above the towers of watch and war. Remember all that he became; count the sacred thoughts with which he filled the heart of Italy; ask those who followed him what they learned at his feet; and when you have numbered his labors, and received their testimony, if it seem to you that God had verily poured out upon this His servant no common nor restrained portion of His Spirit, and that he was indeed a king among the children of men, remember also that the legend upon his crown was that of David's:—"I took thee from the sheepcote, and from following the sheep."

These features vary in different buildings, with some present in one and others in another. However, all of them, at their highest levels, exist, as far as I know, only in one building in the world: the Campanile of Giotto in Florence. The drawing of the tracery at the top of this chapter, though it may seem rough, will nonetheless give the reader a better idea of the tower's grandeur than the faint outlines it's typically shown with. At first glance, it might seem off-putting, appearing to blend excessive severity with too much detail. But if you give it some time, as you should with any great work of art, your view may change. I clearly remember when I was a boy, I used to look down on the Campanile, thinking it was plain and overly polished. Since then, I have spent many days admiring it, gazing out from my window at it in sunlight and moonlight. I'll never forget how deep and gloomy the roughness of Northern Gothic felt to me when I first stood beneath the front of Salisbury. The difference is striking, if you can feel it quickly, between the rise of those grey walls from their peaceful, grassy area, like dark, bare rocks emerging from a green lake, with their coarse, weathered shafts and triple windows lacking any decorative details apart from the martins' nests perched high up, and that bright, smooth, sunny surface of glowing jasper, those spiral columns and delicate tracery, so white, so soft, so crystalline that their faint shapes are barely visible against the pale Eastern sky, that calm height of mountain alabaster, tinged like a morning cloud and shaped like a seashell. And if this is, as I believe it is, the perfect model and reflection of ideal architecture, isn't there something to learn by reflecting on the early life of the person who created it? I mentioned that the power of the human mind grows in the wilderness; even more so must the love, and the vision of that beauty, whose every line and color we see as a faded image of God's everyday work and a captured ray of some star of creation, emerge mainly from the places He has brightened by planting the fir and pine trees. Not within the walls of Florence, but amidst the distant fields of her lilies, was raised the child destined to elevate that pinnacle of Beauty above the towers of defense and war. Remember all that he became; count the sacred thoughts he instilled in the heart of Italy; ask those who followed him what they learned at his feet; and when you’ve counted his achievements and received their testimonials, if you feel that God truly poured out a remarkable portion of His Spirit upon this servant and that he was indeed a leader among humanity, remember also that the inscription on his crown was in the spirit of David’s:—"I took you from the sheepfold, and from tending the sheep."


CHAPTER V.

THE LAMP OF LIFE.

I. Among the countless analogies by which the nature and relations of the human soul are illustrated in the material creation, none are more striking than the impressions inseparably connected with the active and dormant states of matter. I have elsewhere endeavored to show, that no inconsiderable part of the essential characters of Beauty depended on the expression of vital energy in organic things, or on the subjection to such energy, of things naturally passive and powerless. I need not here repeat, of what was then advanced, more than the statement which I believe will meet with general acceptance, that things in other respects alike, as in their substance, or uses, or outward forms, are noble or ignoble in proportion to the fulness of the life which either they themselves enjoy, or of whose action they bear the evidence, as sea sands are made beautiful by their bearing the seal of the motion of the waters. And this is especially true of all objects which bear upon them the impress of the highest order of creative life, that is to say, of the mind of man: they become noble or ignoble in proportion to the amount of the energy of that mind which has visibly been employed upon them. But most peculiarly and imperatively does the rule hold with respect to the creations of Architecture, which being properly capable of no other life than this, and being not essentially composed of things pleasant in themselves,—as music of sweet sounds, or painting of fair colors, but of inert substance,—depend, for their dignity and pleasurableness in the utmost degree, upon the vivid expression of the intellectual life which has been concerned in their production.

I. Among the countless comparisons used to illustrate the nature and relationships of the human soul in the physical world, none are more striking than the impressions tied to the active and inactive states of matter. I've shown elsewhere that a significant part of what defines Beauty depends on the expression of vital energy in living things, or on how passive and powerless things are influenced by such energy. I don't need to repeat everything I previously discussed, except to state what I believe most people will agree with: that similar things, whether in their materials, uses, or outward appearances, are considered noble or ignoble based on how much life they embody or evidence, similar to how sea sands become beautiful because they show the movement of water. This is especially true for objects that display the highest level of creative life, which is the human mind: they become noble or ignoble in relation to the amount of mental energy visibly invested in them. This principle is particularly applicable to architectural creations, which inherently possess no other form of life and are not made up of inherently pleasing things—like music with sweet sounds or painting with beautiful colors—but are composed of inert materials. Their dignity and enjoyment rely heavily on the clear expression of the intellectual life that has gone into their creation.

II. Now in all other kind of energies except that of man's mind, there is no question as to what is life, and what is not. Vital sensibility, whether vegetable or animal, may, indeed, be reduced to so great feebleness, as to render its existence a matter of question, but when it is evident at all, it is evident[Pg 143] as such: there is no mistaking any imitation or pretence of it for the life itself; no mechanism nor galvanism can take its place; nor is any resemblance of it so striking as to involve even hesitation in the judgment; although many occur which the human imagination takes pleasure in exalting, without for an instant losing sight of the real nature of the dead things it animates; but rejoicing rather in its own excessive life, which puts gesture into clouds, and joy into waves, and voices into rocks.

II. Now, when it comes to all other forms of energy besides the human mind, there's no doubt about what is alive and what isn’t. Vital sensitivity, whether in plants or animals, can indeed become so weak that its existence is uncertain, but when it's apparent, it's clear as can be: there's no mistaking any imitation or pretense of it for actual life; no machine or electric stimulation can replace it; nor is there any resemblance so striking that it causes even a moment of doubt in our judgment. Although many imitations exist that our imagination enjoys elevating, we never lose sight of the true nature of the lifeless things they're simulating; instead, we take joy in our own vibrant existence, which brings movement to clouds, joy to waves, and sound to rocks.

III. But when we begin to be concerned with the energies of man, we find ourselves instantly dealing with a double creature. Most part of his being seems to have a fictitious counterpart, which it is at his peril if he do not cast off and deny. Thus he has a true and false (otherwise called a living and dead, or a feigned or unfeigned) faith. He has a true and a false hope, a true and a false charity, and, finally, a true and a false life. His true life is like that of lower organic beings, the independent force by which he moulds and governs external things; it is a force of assimilation which converts everything around him into food, or into instruments; and which, however humbly or obediently it may listen to or follow the guidance of superior intelligence, never forfeits its own authority as a judging principle, as a will capable either of obeying or rebelling. His false life is, indeed, but one of the conditions of death or stupor, but it acts, even when it cannot be said to animate, and is not always easily known from the true. It is that life of custom and accident in which many of us pass much of our time in the world; that life in which we do what we have not purposed, and speak what we do not mean, and assent to what we do not understand; that life which is overlaid by the weight of things external to it, and is moulded by them, instead of assimilating them; that, which instead of growing and blossoming under any wholesome dew, is crystallised over with it, as with hoar frost, and becomes to the true life what an arborescence is to a tree, a candied agglomeration of thoughts and habits foreign to it, brittle, obstinate, and icy, which can neither bend nor grow, but must be crushed and broken to bits, if it stand in our way.[Pg 144] All men are liable to be in some degree frost-bitten in this sort; all are partly encumbered and crusted over with idle matter; only, if they have real life in them, they are always breaking this bark away in noble rents, until it becomes, like the black strips upon the birch tree, only a witness of their own inward strength. But, with all the efforts that the best men make, much of their being passes in a kind of dream, in which they indeed move, and play their parts sufficiently, to the eyes of their fellow-dreamers, but have no clear consciousness of what is around them, or within them; blind to the one, insensible to the other, νωθροι. I would not press the definition into its darker application to the dull heart and heavy ear; I have to do with it only as it refers to the too frequent condition of natural existence, whether of nations or individuals, settling commonly upon them in proportion to their age. The life of a nation is usually, like the flow of a lava stream, first bright and fierce, then languid and covered, at last advancing only by the tumbling over and over of its frozen blocks. And that last condition is a sad one to look upon. All the steps are marked most clearly in the arts, and in Architecture more than in any other; for it, being especially dependent, as we have just said, on the warmth of the true life, is also peculiarly sensible of the hemlock cold of the false; and I do not know anything more oppressive, when the mind is once awakened to its characteristics, than the aspect of a dead architecture. The feebleness of childhood is full of promise and of interest,—the struggle of imperfect knowledge full of energy and continuity,—but to see impotence and rigidity settling upon the form of the developed man; to see the types which once had the die of thought struck fresh upon them, worn flat by over use; to see the shell of the living creature in its adult form, when its colors are faded, and its inhabitant perished,—this is a sight more humiliating, more melancholy, than the vanishing of all knowledge, and the return to confessed and helpless infancy.

III. But when we start to focus on human energies, we immediately find ourselves dealing with a dual being. Much of our essence seems to have a false counterpart, which can be dangerous if we fail to acknowledge and discard it. Thus, we possess a true and a false (also known as living and dead, or feigned and genuine) faith. We have a true and a false hope, a true and a false charity, and ultimately, a true and a false life. Our true life resembles that of simpler organisms, the independent force that shapes and controls external things; it’s a force of assimilation that turns everything around us into nourishment or tools; and while it may humbly or obediently follow the guidance of higher intelligence, it never loses its authority as a discerning principle, as a will that can both obey and resist. Our false life is merely a state of stagnation or numbness, yet it operates even when it cannot be said to bring life, and is not always easy to differentiate from the true. It's a life of habit and chance where many of us spend much of our time in the world; it’s a life in which we do things we never intended, say things we don’t mean, and agree to things we don’t understand; a life weighed down by external influences, shaped by them rather than absorbing them; one that, instead of thriving and flourishing under healthy influence, is covered in frost and becomes, to the true life, what a sugary coating is to a fruit, a brittle, stubborn, icy build-up of foreign thoughts and habits that can neither adapt nor grow, but must be shattered if it obstructs our path.[Pg 144] All people are somewhat frostbitten in this way; everyone is partially burdened and encrusted with useless matter; however, if they possess genuine life, they are constantly breaking away this shell in significant ways until it becomes, like the black strips on a birch tree, merely a testament to their inner strength. Yet, despite the efforts of the best among us, much of our existence unfolds in a kind of dream, where we indeed move and play our roles sufficiently to the eyes of other dreamers, but lack a clear awareness of what surrounds us or what lies within; we are blind to one and insensitive to the other, νωθροι. I don’t want to push this definition into its darker implications concerning a dull heart or heavy ear; I only relate it to the too common state of natural existence, whether of nations or individuals, which frequently settles upon them in relation to their age. The life of a nation typically resembles a flowing lava stream, first bright and intense, then sluggish and concealed, ultimately advancing only by the tumbling of its frozen blocks. And that final state is a bleak one to witness. All the stages are distinctly marked in the arts, especially in architecture; as it especially relies, as we have just mentioned, on the warmth of true life, it is also particularly sensitive to the chilling presence of the false; and I cannot think of anything more stifling, once the mind grasps its characteristics, than the appearance of lifeless architecture. The frailty of childhood is full of promise and interest—the struggle of incomplete understanding is full of energy and continuity—but to observe helplessness and rigidity taking over the form of the grown person; to see the types that once displayed the fresh imprint of thought worn down by overuse; to see the shell of the living creature in its mature state, when its colors have faded and its inhabitant has died—this is a sight more humbling, more sorrowful, than the loss of all knowledge and the return to a state of acknowledged and helpless infancy.

Nay, it is to be wished that such return were always possible. There would be hope if we could change palsy into puerility; but I know not how far we can become children[Pg 145] again, and renew our lost life. The stirring which has taken place in our architectural aims and interests within these few years, is thought by many to be full of promise: I trust it is, but it has a sickly look to me. I cannot tell whether it be indeed a springing of seed or a shaking among bones; and I do not think the time will be lost which I ask the reader to spend in the inquiry, how far all that we have hitherto ascertained or conjectured to be the best in principle, may be formally practised without the spirit or the vitality which alone could give it influence, value, or delightfulness.

No, I wish that such a return were always possible. There would be hope if we could turn paralysis into childishness; but I’m not sure how much we can become children again and revive our lost lives. The excitement we've seen in our architectural goals and interests over the past few years seems promising to many: I hope it is, but it looks sickly to me. I can't tell if it's truly a budding of new ideas or just a rattle of old bones; and I don’t think the time will be wasted that I ask the reader to spend exploring how much of what we’ve figured out or imagined to be best in principle can actually be practiced without the spirit or vitality that alone could give it influence, value, or joy.

IV. Now, in the first place—and this is rather an important point—it is no sign of deadness in a present art that it borrows or imitates, but only if it borrows without paying interest, or if it imitates without choice. The art of a great nation, which is developed without any acquaintance with nobler examples than its own early efforts furnish, exhibits always the most consistent and comprehensible growth, and perhaps is regarded usually as peculiarly venerable in its self-origination. But there is something to my mind more majestic yet in the life of an architecture like that of the Lombards, rude and infantine in itself, and surrounded by fragments of a nobler art of which it is quick in admiration and ready in imitation, and yet so strong in its own new instincts that it re-constructs and re-arranges every fragment that it copies or borrows into harmony with its own thoughts,—a harmony at first disjointed and awkward, but completed in the end, and fused into perfect organisation; all the borrowed elements being subordinated to its own primal, unchanged life. I do not know any sensation more exquisite than the discovering of the evidence of this magnificent struggle into independent existence; the detection of the borrowed thoughts, nay, the finding of the actual blocks and stones carved by other hands and in other ages, wrought into the new walls, with a new expression and purpose given to them, like the blocks of unsubdued rocks (to go back to our former simile) which we find in the heart of the lava current, great witnesses to the power which has fused all but those calcined fragments into the mass of its homogeneous fire.[Pg 146]

IV. First of all—and this is a pretty important point—it’s not a sign of weakness in an art form that it borrows or imitates. It only becomes an issue if it borrows without adding anything of its own or if it imitates without making any choices. The art of a great nation, which develops without exposure to better examples than its own early works, shows the most consistent and understandable progress. It is often seen as particularly respected for being self-originated. But I think there’s something even more impressive in the architecture of the Lombards. It seems primitive and youthful on the surface, yet it is surrounded by remnants of a more refined art that it admires and seeks to imitate. Still, it is so confident in its new instincts that it reconstructs every borrowed fragment to fit its own vision—a vision that might start off feeling mismatched and awkward but ultimately becomes unified and perfectly organized; all borrowed elements are made subordinate to its own core, unchanged spirit. There’s nothing quite like the feeling of discovering this incredible struggle for independent existence; finding the borrowed ideas, even spotting the actual blocks and stones shaped by different hands in different times, integrated into new walls, imbued with a fresh purpose—like the unconquered rocks we find in the heart of a lava flow, standing as powerful witnesses to the force that has merged everything else into its molten essence.[Pg 146]

V. It will be asked, How is imitation to be rendered healthy and vital? Unhappily, while it is easy to enumerate the signs of life, it is impossible to define or to communicate life; and while every intelligent writer on Art has insisted on the difference between the copying found in an advancing or recedent period, none have been able to communicate, in the slightest degree, the force of vitality to the copyist over whom they might have influence. Yet it is at least interesting, if not profitable, to note that two very distinguishing characters of vital imitation are, its Frankness and its Audacity; its Frankness is especially singular; there is never any effort to conceal the degree of the sources of its borrowing. Raffaelle carries off a whole figure from Masaccio, or borrows an entire composition from Perugino, with as much tranquillity and simplicity of innocence as a young Spartan pickpocket; and the architect of a Romanesque basilica gathered his columns and capitals where he could find them, as an ant picks up sticks. There is at least a presumption, when we find this frank acceptance, that there is a sense within the mind of power capable of transforming and renewing whatever it adopts; and too conscious, too exalted, to fear the accusation of plagiarism,—too certain that it can prove, and has proved, its independence, to be afraid of expressing its homage to what it admires in the most open and indubitable way; and the necessary consequence of this sense of power is the other sign I have named—the Audacity of treatment when it finds treatment necessary, the unhesitating and sweeping sacrifice of precedent where precedent becomes inconvenient. For instance, in the characteristic forms of Italian Romanesque, in which the hypaethral portion of the heathen temple was replaced by the towering nave, and where, in consequence, the pediment of the west front became divided into three portions, of which the central one, like the apex of a ridge of sloping strata lifted by a sudden fault, was broken away from and raised above the wings; there remained at the extremities of the aisles two triangular fragments of pediment, which could not now be filled by any of the modes of decoration adapted for the unbroken space; and the difficulty became greater[Pg 147] when the central portion of the front was occupied by columnar ranges, which could not, without painful abruptness, terminate short of the extremities of the wings. I know not what expedient would have been adopted by architects who had much respect for precedent, under such circumstances, but it certainly would not have been that of the Pisan,—to continue the range of columns into the pedimental space, shortening them to its extremity until the shaft of the last column vanished altogether, and there remained only its capital resting in the angle on its basic plinth. I raise no question at present whether this arrangement be graceful or otherwise; I allege it only as an instance of boldness almost without a parallel, casting aside every received principle that stood in its way, and struggling through every discordance and difficulty to the fulfilment of its own instincts.

V. It will be asked, How can imitation become healthy and vital? Unfortunately, while it's easy to list the signs of life, it’s impossible to define or convey what life truly is; and although every knowledgeable writer on art has emphasized the difference between copying in a progressive or declining period, none have been able to convey even a little of the vitality to the imitator they might influence. Still, it’s at least interesting, if not beneficial, to observe that two key traits of vital imitation are its Frankness and its Audacity; its Frankness is particularly noteworthy; there's never any attempt to hide where its sources come from. Raffaelle confidently takes an entire figure from Masaccio or borrows a complete composition from Perugino with the same calm and innocent ease as a young Spartan pickpocket; and the architect of a Romanesque basilica collected his columns and capitals from wherever he could find them, just like an ant gathers twigs. There’s at least an indication, when we see this open acceptance, that there’s a mindset of power capable of transforming and renewing whatever it adopts; it’s too self-assured, too elevated to worry about being accused of plagiarism—too confident in its ability to prove, and having proven, its independence to not honor what it admires in the clearest way possible; and the necessary result of this sense of power is the other characteristic I mentioned—the Audacity of approach when it’s needed, the bold and decisive abandonment of tradition when tradition proves inconvenient. For example, in the distinctive forms of Italian Romanesque, where the open-air part of the pagan temple was replaced by the soaring nave, the pediment of the west front became divided into three sections—the central one, like the peak of a ridge of sloping layers lifted by a sudden fault, broken away from and elevated above the wings; this left two triangular fragments of the pediment at the ends of the aisles, which couldn’t now be suited for any of the decorative styles meant for an uninterrupted space; and the challenge increased when the central part of the front was filled with columnar rows, which couldn’t, without jarring abruptness, end before reaching the extremes of the wings. I could only speculate on what solution architects who greatly valued tradition would have used in such a situation, but it certainly wouldn’t have been the approach of the Pisan—to extend the row of columns into the pedimental area, shortening them to the end until the shaft of the last column completely disappeared, leaving just its capital sitting in the corner on its foundational plinth. I’m not questioning whether this design is graceful or not; I’m only pointing it out as an example of boldness that’s almost unmatched, disregarding every accepted principle that stood in its way, and pushing through every discord and challenge to fulfill its own instincts.

VI. Frankness, however, is in itself no excuse for repetition, nor audacity for innovation, when the one is indolent and the other unwise. Nobler and surer signs of vitality must be sought,—signs independent alike of the decorative or original character of the style, and constant in every style that is determinedly progressive.

VI. However, being straightforward is no reason for repeating ourselves, just as being bold is no excuse for making changes when the former is lazy and the latter is unwise. We must look for more genuine and reliable signs of life—signs that are not dependent on whether the style is decorative or original, and that remain constant in any style striving for real progress.

Of these, one of the most important I believe to be a certain neglect or contempt of refinement in execution, or, at all events, a visible subordination of execution to conception, commonly involuntary, but not unfrequently intentional. This is a point, however, on which, while I speak confidently, I must at the same time reservedly and carefully, as there would otherwise be much chance of my being dangerously misunderstood. It has been truly observed and well stated by Lord Lindsay, that the best designers of Italy were also the most careful in their workmanship; and that the stability and finish of their masonry, mosaic, or other work whatsoever, were always perfect in proportion to the apparent improbability of the great designers condescending to the care of details among us so despised. Not only do I fully admit and re-assert this most important fact, but I would insist upon perfect and most delicate finish in its right place, as a characteristic of all the highest schools of architecture, as much as it is[Pg 148] those of painting. But on the other hand, as perfect finish belongs to the perfected art, a progressive finish belongs to progressive art; and I do not think that any more fatal sign of a stupor or numbness settling upon that undeveloped art could possibly be detected, than that it had been taken aback by its own execution, and that the workmanship had gone ahead of the design; while, even in my admission of absolute finish in the right place, as an attribute of the perfected school, I must reserve to myself the right of answering in my own way the two very important questions, what is finish? and what is its right place?

Of these, I believe one of the most important issues is a certain neglect or disregard for refinement in execution, or, in any case, a clear subordination of execution to concept, which is often unintentional but sometimes deliberate. However, while I speak confidently about this, I must also be cautious, as there is a significant risk of being seriously misunderstood. Lord Lindsay has rightly pointed out that the best designers from Italy were also the most meticulous in their craftsmanship; the stability and quality of their masonry, mosaic, or any other work were always perfect in relation to the seemingly unlikely idea that such great designers would bother with the details we often look down upon. I not only acknowledge and reaffirm this crucial fact, but I also emphasize that perfect and delicate finishing in its appropriate context should be a hallmark of all the highest schools of architecture, just as it is in painting. On the flip side, while complete finishing is a feature of perfected art, gradual finishing relates to evolving art; I believe there's no clearer sign of stagnation or dullness settling on an undeveloped art than when it becomes overwhelmed by its own execution, with craftsmanship surpassing the design. Even in my acknowledgment of absolute finish in the appropriate context as a trait of the perfected school, I must reserve the right to answer in my own terms the two important questions: what is finish? and what is its appropriate place?

VII. But in illustrating either of these points, we must remember that the correspondence of workmanship with thought is, in existent examples, interfered with by the adoption of the designs of an advanced period by the workmen of a rude one. All the beginnings of Christian architecture are of this kind, and the necessary consequence is of course an increase of the visible interval between the power of realisation and the beauty of the idea. We have at first an imitation, almost savage in its rudeness, of a classical design; as the art advances, the design is modified by a mixture of Gothic grotesqueness, and the execution more complete, until a harmony is established between the two, in which balance they advance to new perfection. Now during the whole period in which the ground is being recovered, there will be found in the living architecture marks not to be mistaken, of intense impatience; a struggle towards something unattained, which causes all minor points of handling to be neglected; and a restless disdain of all qualities which appear either to confess contentment or to require a time and care which might be better spent. And, exactly as a good and earnest student of drawing will not lose time in ruling lines or finishing backgrounds about studies which, while they have answered his immediate purpose, he knows to be imperfect and inferior to what he will do hereafter,—so the vigor of a true school of early architecture, which is either working under the influence of high example or which is itself in a state of rapid development, is very curiously traceable, among other [Pg 149] signs, in the contempt of exact symmetry and measurement, which in dead architecture are the most painful necessities.

VII. When illustrating either of these points, we have to keep in mind that the alignment of craftsmanship with thought is often disrupted by craftsmen from a less advanced period adopting designs from a more developed one. The early stages of Christian architecture are perfect examples of this, resulting in a growing gap between the ability to realize an idea and the beauty of that idea. Initially, we see a rough imitation of a classical design, almost primitive in its crudeness; as the art progresses, the design evolves through a blend of Gothic oddities, and the execution becomes more refined until a balance is achieved, leading to new perfection. Throughout the entire period of regaining ground, you'll notice clear signs of intense impatience in the existing architecture; a struggle for something that feels just out of reach, which leads to neglecting all the smaller details and a restless disregard for anything that seems to indicate satisfaction or would require time and effort that could be better invested elsewhere. Just as a dedicated drawing student won’t waste time on straight lines or finishing backgrounds of studies that, while serving his immediate needs, he knows are flawed and inferior to what he’ll create in the future—so too can the energy of an early architectural movement, whether influenced by high standards or in rapid development, be traced through various signs, like the disregard for perfect symmetry and measurement, which are the most frustrating requirements in lifeless architecture.

PLATE XII. PLATE XII.—(Page 149—Vol. V.)
Fragments from Abbeville, Lucca, Venice, and Pisa.

VIII. In Plate XII. fig. 1 I have given a most singular instance both of rude execution and defied symmetry, in the little pillar and spandril from a panel decoration under the pulpit of St. Mark's at Venice. The imperfection (not merely simplicity, but actual rudeness and ugliness) of the leaf ornament will strike the eye at once: this is general in works of the time, but it is not so common to find a capital which has been so carelessly cut; its imperfect volutes being pushed up one side far higher than on the other, and contracted on that side, an additional drill hole being put in to fill the space; besides this, the member a, of the mouldings, is a roll where it follows the arch, and a flat fillet at a; the one being slurred into the other at the angle b, and finally stopped short altogether at the other side by the most uncourteous and remorseless interference of the outer moulding: and in spite of all this, the grace, proportion, and feeling of the whole arrangement are so great, that, in its place, it leaves nothing to be desired; all the science and symmetry in the world could not beat it. In fig. 4 I have endeavored to give some idea of the execution of the subordinate portions of a much higher work, the pulpit of St. Andrea at Pistoja, by Nicolo Pisano. It is covered with figure sculptures, executed with great care and delicacy; but when the sculptor came to the simple arch mouldings, he did not choose to draw the eye to them by over precision of work or over sharpness of shadow. The section adopted, k, m, is peculiarly simple, and so slight and obtuse in its recessions as never to produce a sharp line; and it is worked with what at first appears slovenliness, but it is in fact sculptural sketching; exactly correspondent to a painter's light execution of a background: the lines appear and disappear again, are sometimes deep, sometimes shallow, sometimes quite broken off; and the recession of the cusp joins that of the external arch at n, in the most fearless defiance of all mathematical laws of curvilinear contact.

VIII. In Plate XII, fig. 1, I've shown a unique example of both rough craftsmanship and disregard for symmetry, with the small pillar and spandril from a panel decoration beneath the pulpit of St. Mark's in Venice. The imperfection (not just simplicity, but true roughness and unattractiveness) of the leaf ornament is immediately noticeable; this is common in works from that era, but it's rare to find a capital that has been carved so carelessly. Its uneven volutes are pushed up one side much higher than the other and are narrowed on that side, with an extra drill hole added to fill the gap. Additionally, the member a of the moldings has a roll where it follows the arch and a flat fillet at a; the two blend together at the angle b and then abruptly stop on the other side due to the harsh interference of the outer molding. Despite all this, the elegance, proportion, and overall feel of the arrangement are so strong that, in its setting, nothing more could be desired; all the skill and symmetry in the world wouldn’t surpass it. In fig. 4, I've tried to convey the execution of the less prominent parts of a much grander work, the pulpit of St. Andrea in Pistoja, by Nicolo Pisano. It's adorned with figure sculptures, done with great care and delicacy; however, when the sculptor got to the simple arch moldings, he chose not to draw attention to them with excessive precision or harsh shadows. The adopted section, k, m, is particularly straightforward, with such soft and rounded recesses that they never form a sharp line; it’s crafted with what initially looks like carelessness, but is actually sculptural sketching, akin to a painter's light touch in a background. The lines appear and fade, sometimes they’re deep, sometimes shallow, and sometimes they’re abruptly interrupted; the recession of the cusp aligns with that of the external arch at n, boldly defying all mathematical rules of curvilinear contact.

IX. There is something very delightful in this bold expression of the mind of the great master. I do not say that it is[Pg 150] the "perfect work" of patience, but I think that impatience is a glorious character in an advancing school; and I love the Romanesque and early Gothic especially, because they afford so much room for it; accidental carelessness of measurement or of execution being mingled undistinguishably with the purposed departures from symmetrical regularity, and the luxuriousness of perpetually variable fancy, which are eminently characteristic of both styles. How great, how frequent they are, and how brightly the severity of architectural law is relieved by their grace and suddenness, has not, I think, been enough observed; still less, the unequal measurements of even important features professing to be absolutely symmetrical. I am not so familiar with modern practice as to speak with confidence respecting its ordinary precision; but I imagine that the following measures of the western front of the cathedral of Pisa, would be looked upon by present architects as very blundering approximations. That front is divided into seven arched compartments, of which the second, fourth or central, and sixth contain doors; the seven are in a most subtle alternating proportion; the central being the largest, next to it the second and sixth, then the first and seventh, lastly the third and fifth. By this arrangement, of course, these three pairs should be equal; and they are so to the eye, but I found their actual measures to be the following, taken from pillar to pillar, in Italian braccia, palmi (four inches each), and inches:—

IX. There’s something really enjoyable about this bold expression from the great master’s mind. I’m not saying it’s the “perfect work” of patience, but I believe that impatience is a fascinating trait in a progressive school; and I particularly love the Romanesque and early Gothic styles because they allow so much room for it. Accidental inconsistencies in measurement or execution are mixed indistinguishably with intentional deviations from symmetrical regularity, along with the richness of ever-changing creativity that are key features of both styles. The magnitude and frequency of these details, and how beautifully they offset the strictness of architectural rules with their elegance and unpredictability, hasn’t been sufficiently acknowledged; even less so the uneven measurements of important elements that are meant to be perfectly symmetrical. I’m not as familiar with modern practices to confidently discuss their usual precision; however, I assume that the following measurements of the western front of the cathedral of Pisa would be seen by today’s architects as quite inaccurate approximations. That front is divided into seven arched sections, of which the second, fourth (or central), and sixth have doors; the seven are arranged in a very subtle alternating proportion: the central is the largest, followed by the second and sixth, then the first and seventh, and finally the third and fifth. According to this arrangement, these three pairs should be equal; and they appear so to the eye, but I found their actual measurements to be the following, taken from pillar to pillar, in Italian braccia, palmi (four inches each), and inches:—

Braccia.Palmi.Inches.Total in inches.
1. Central door800= 192
2. Northern door63= 157½
3. Southern door643= 163
4. Extreme northern space55= 143½
5. Extreme southern space61= 148½
6. Northern intervals between the doors521= 129
7. Southern intervals between the doors52= 129½

There is thus a difference, severally, between 2, 3 and 4, 5, of five inches and a half in the one case, and five inches in the other.

There is a difference, specifically, between 2, 3 and 4, 5, of five and a half inches in one case, and five inches in the other.

X. This, however, may perhaps be partly attributable to[Pg 151] some accommodation of the accidental distortions which evidently took place in the walls of the cathedral during their building, as much as in those of the campanile. To my mind, those of the Duomo are far the most wonderful of the two: I do not believe that a single pillar of its walls is absolutely vertical: the pavement rises and falls to different heights, or rather the plinth of the walls sinks into it continually to different depths, the whole west front literally overhangs (I have not plumbed it; but the inclination may be seen by the eye, by bringing it into visual contact with the upright pilasters of the Campo Santo): and a most extraordinary distortion in the masonry of the southern wall shows that this inclination had begun when the first story was built. The cornice above the first arcade of that wall touches the tops of eleven out of its fifteen arches; but it suddenly leaves the tops of the four westernmost; the arches nodding westward and sinking into the ground, while the cornice rises (or seems to rise), leaving at any rate, whether by the rise of the one or the fall of the other, an interval of more than two feet between it and the top of the western arch, filled by added courses of masonry. There is another very curious evidence of this struggle of the architect with his yielding wall in the columns of the main entrance. (These notices are perhaps somewhat irrelevant to our immediate subject, but they appear to me highly interesting; and they, at all events, prove one of the points on which I would insist,—how much of imperfection and variety in things professing to be symmetrical the eyes of those eager builders could endure: they looked to loveliness in detail, to nobility in the whole, never to petty measurements.) Those columns of the principal entrance are among the loveliest in Italy; cylindrical, and decorated with a rich arabesque of sculptured foliage, which at the base extends nearly all round them, up to the black pilaster in which they are lightly engaged: but the shield of foliage, bounded by a severe line, narrows to their tops, where it covers their frontal segment only; thus giving, when laterally seen, a terminal line sloping boldly outwards, which, as I think, was meant to conceal the accidental leaning of the western walls, and, by its exagger[Pg 152]ated inclination in the same direction, to throw them by comparison into a seeming vertical.

X. This might be partly due to[Pg 151] some adjustments for the accidental distortions that clearly happened in the walls of the cathedral during its construction, just like those of the campanile. In my opinion, the Duomo's walls are far more remarkable than the other; I don't think a single pillar in those walls is completely vertical. The floor rises and falls at different heights, or rather, the base of the walls sinks into it at varying depths. The entire west front literally overhangs (I haven't measured it precisely; but you can see the tilt with the naked eye, especially when compared to the upright pilasters of the Campo Santo): and a very unusual distortion in the southern wall's masonry indicates that this tilt started when the first story was built. The cornice above the first arcade of that wall touches the tops of eleven out of its fifteen arches, but it suddenly leaves the tops of the four westernmost arches, which lean westward and sink into the ground, while the cornice appears to rise, creating a gap of over two feet between it and the top of the western arch, filled with additional courses of masonry. There’s another fascinating sign of the architect's struggle with the yielding wall in the columns of the main entrance. (These observations might seem somewhat off-topic, but I find them very interesting; and they, in any case, highlight one critical point: how much imperfection and variety those eager builders could tolerate in things that were supposed to be symmetrical—they sought beauty in detail and nobility in the whole, never fussing over precise measurements.) Those columns at the main entrance are among the most beautiful in Italy; they're cylindrical and adorned with an intricate arabesque of sculpted foliage that nearly wraps around the base, up to the black pilaster they’re lightly attached to. But the shield of foliage, framed by a strict line, narrows at the top, where it only covers their frontal segment; this creates, when viewed from the side, a bold outward sloping line that I believe was intended to disguise the accidental leaning of the western walls, making them appear almost vertical by comparison with its exaggerated tilt in the same direction.

XI. There is another very curious instance of distortion above the central door of the west front. All the intervals between the seven arches are filled with black marble, each containing in its centre a white parallelogram filled with animal mosaics, and the whole surmounted by a broad white band, which, generally, does not touch the parallelogram below. But the parallelogram on the north of the central arch has been forced into an oblique position, and touches the white band; and, as if the architect was determined to show that he did not care whether it did or not, the white band suddenly gets thicker at that place, and remains so over the two next arches. And these differences are the more curious because the workmanship of them all is most finished and masterly, and the distorted stones are fitted with as much neatness as if they tallied to a hair's breadth. There is no look of slurring or blundering about it; it is all coolly filled in, as if the builder had no sense of anything being wrong or extraordinary: I only wish we had a little of his impudence.

XI. There's another really strange example of distortion above the central door of the west front. All the spaces between the seven arches are filled with black marble, each featuring a white parallelogram with animal mosaics in the center, topped by a wide white band that usually doesn’t touch the parallelogram below. However, the parallelogram to the north of the central arch is tilted and does touch the white band; and, as if the architect wanted to show that he didn’t care, the white band suddenly gets thicker at that spot and stays that way over the next two arches. These differences are even more interesting because the craftsmanship of all of them is very refined and skillful, and the distorted stones fit together as perfectly as if they matched to the tiniest detail. There's no hint of sloppiness or mistakes; it all looks intentionally filled in, as if the builder didn’t realize anything was off or unusual: I just wish we had a bit of his boldness.

XII. Still, the reader will say that all these variations are probably dependent more on the bad foundation than on the architect's feeling. Not so the exquisite delicacies of change in the proportions and dimensions of the apparently symmetrical arcades of the west front. It will be remembered that I said the tower of Pisa was the only ugly tower in Italy, because its tiers were equal, or nearly so, in height; a fault this, so contrary to the spirit of the builders of the time, that it can be considered only as an unlucky caprice. Perhaps the general aspect of the west front of the cathedral may then have occurred to the reader's mind, as seemingly another contradiction of the rule I had advanced. It would not have been so, however, even had its four upper arcades been actually equal; as they are subordinated to the great seven-arched lower story, in the manner before noticed respecting the spire of Salisbury, and as is actually the case in the Duomo of Lucca and Tower of Pistoja. But the Pisan front is far more subtly proportioned. Not one of its four arcades is of like height[Pg 153] with another. The highest is the third, counting upwards; and they diminish in nearly arithmetical proportion alternately; in the order 3rd, 1st, 2nd, 4th. The inequalities in their arches are not less remarkable: they at first strike the eye as all equal; but there is a grace about them which equality never obtained: on closer observation, it is perceived that in the first row of nineteen arches, eighteen are equal, and the central one larger than the rest; in the second arcade, the nine central arches stand over the nine below, having, like them, the ninth central one largest. But on their flanks, where is the slope of the shoulder-like pediment, the arches vanish, and a wedge-shaped frieze takes their place, tapering outwards, in order to allow the columns to be carried to the extremity of the pediment; and here, where the heights of the shafts are so far shortened, they are set thicker; five shafts, or rather four and a capital, above, to four of the arcade below, giving twenty-one intervals instead of nineteen. In the next or third arcade,—which, remember, is the highest,—eight arches, all equal, are given in the space of the nine below, so that there is now a central shaft instead of a central arch, and the span of the arches is increased in proportion to their increased height. Finally, in the uppermost arcade, which is the lowest of all, the arches, the same in number as those below, are narrower than any of the façade; the whole eight going very nearly above the six below them, while the terminal arches of the lower arcade are surmounted by flanking masses of decorated wall with projecting figures.

XII. Still, the reader might say that all these variations probably come more from a poor foundation than from the architect's intent. However, that's not the case with the exquisite subtleties of change in the proportions and dimensions of the seemingly symmetrical arcades on the west front. It’s worth recalling that I mentioned the tower of Pisa is the only ugly tower in Italy because its layers are equal, or nearly so, in height; this flaw is so against the spirit of the builders of that time that it can only be seen as an unfortunate choice. Perhaps the overall look of the west front of the cathedral may have crossed the reader's mind as an apparent contradiction to the rule I set. Yet, that wouldn't hold true even if its four upper arcades were indeed equal; they are subordinate to the grand seven-arched lower level, similar to what I previously pointed out about the spire of Salisbury, and actually seen in the Duomo of Lucca and the Tower of Pistoja. But the Pisan front is proportioned in a far more subtle way. Not one of its four arcades is the same height as another. The third one is the tallest as you count upwards; they decrease in almost a regular pattern, following the order 3rd, 1st, 2nd, 4th. The inconsistencies in their arches are equally striking: at first glance, they appear to be all equal; but there's a gracefulness to them that true equality never achieved: upon closer inspection, it’s noticeable that in the first row of nineteen arches, eighteen are identical, with the central one larger than the rest; in the second arcade, the nine central arches sit over the nine below, with the ninth central one again the largest. But on the sides, where the slope of the shoulder-like pediment is, the arches disappear, replaced by a wedge-shaped frieze that tapers outward to allow the columns to extend to the edge of the pediment; here, where the heights of the shafts are shortened, they become thicker; five shafts, or rather four with a capital on top, above four in the arcade below create twenty-one intervals instead of nineteen. In the next or third arcade—which, remember, is the highest—eight arches, all equal, fit in the space of the nine below, so that there’s now a central shaft instead of a central arch, and the distance of the arches increases in relation to their greater height. Finally, in the top arcade, which is the lowest of all, the arches, the same number as those below, are narrower than any of the façade; all eight nearly align with the six below them, while the end arches of the lower arcade are topped by flanking sections of decorated wall with projecting figures.

XIV. Now I call that Living Architecture. There is sensation in every inch of it, and an accommodation to every architectural necessity, with a determined variation in arrangement, which is exactly like the related proportions and provisions in the structure of organic form. I have not space to examine the still lovelier proportioning of the external shafts of the apse of this marvellous building. I prefer, lest the reader should think it a peculiar example, to state the structure of another church, the most graceful and grand piece of Romanesque work, as a fragment, in north Italy, that of San Giovanni Evangelista at Pistoja.[Pg 154]

XIV. I call that Living Architecture. There’s a sense of life in every inch of it, perfectly adapted to every architectural need, with a deliberate variation in layout that mirrors the proportional relationships and features found in living forms. I don't have enough space to discuss the even more beautiful proportions of the outer columns of the apse of this amazing building. To avoid any misunderstanding, I’ll mention another church, which is the most elegant and impressive example of Romanesque architecture, as a piece, located in northern Italy: San Giovanni Evangelista in Pistoja.[Pg 154]

The side of that church has three stories of arcade, diminishing in height in bold geometrical proportion, while the arches, for the most part, increase in number in arithmetical, i. e. two in the second arcade, and three in the third, to one in the first. Lest, however, this arrangement should be too formal, of the fourteen arches in the lowest series, that which contains the door is made larger than the rest, and is not in the middle, but the sixth from the West, leaving five on one side and eight on the other. Farther: this lowest arcade is terminated by broad flat pilasters, about half the width of its arches; but the arcade above is continuous; only the two extreme arches at the west end are made larger than all the rest, and instead of coming, as they should, into the space of the lower extreme arch, take in both it and its broad pilaster. Even this, however, was not out of order enough to satisfy the architect's eye; for there were still two arches above to each single one below: so at the east end, where there are more arches, and the eye might be more easily cheated, what does he do but narrow the two extreme lower arches by half a braccio; while he at the same time slightly enlarged the upper ones, so as to get only seventeen upper to nine lower, instead of eighteen to nine. The eye is thus thoroughly confused, and the whole building thrown into one mass, by the curious variations in the adjustments of the superimposed shafts, not one of which is either exactly in nor positively out of its place; and, to get this managed the more cunningly, there is from an inch to an inch and a half of gradual gain in the space of the four eastern arches, besides the confessed half braccio. Their measures, counting from the east, I found as follows:—

The side of that church has three stories of arches that get shorter in a striking geometric pattern, while the arches mostly increase in number in a straightforward way—two in the second row and three in the third, compared to one in the first. To prevent this arrangement from seeming too rigid, the fourteen arches in the bottom row feature a door that is larger than the others and is not in the center but the sixth from the West, leaving five on one side and eight on the other. Additionally, this lowest row ends with broad flat pillars that are about half the width of the arches; the row above is uniform, but the two outer arches at the west end are larger than the rest. Instead of aligning properly with the space of the lower outer arch, they encompass both it and its broad pillar. Still, this wasn’t chaotic enough to satisfy the architect’s vision, as there were still two arches above for every single one below. So at the east end, where there are more arches and the eye might be tricked more easily, he narrows the two outer lower arches by half a braccio; at the same time, he slightly enlarges the upper arches to achieve seventeen upper arches to nine lower ones, instead of eighteen to nine. This way, the eye is thoroughly deceived, and the entire structure is fused into a single mass due to the intricate variations in the alignment of the stacked shafts, none of which are perfectly in or definitely out of place; to pull this off even more cleverly, there is a gradual increase of one to one and a half inches in the space of the four eastern arches, along with the acknowledged half braccio. Their dimensions, starting from the east, were as follows:—

Braccia.Palmi.Inches.
1st301
2nd302
3rd332
4th33

The upper arcade is managed on the same principle; it looks at first as if there were three arches to each under pair; but there are, in reality, only thirty-eight (or thirty-seven, I[Pg 155] am not quite certain of this number) to the twenty-seven below; and the columns get into all manner of relative positions. Even then, the builder was not satisfied, but must needs carry the irregularity into the spring of the arches, and actually, while the general effect is of a symmetrical arcade, there is not one of the arches the same in height as another; their tops undulate all along the wall like waves along a harbor quay, some nearly touching the string course above, and others falling from it as much as five or six inches.

The upper arcade operates on the same concept; at first glance, it seems like there are three arches for each pair below. However, there are actually only thirty-eight (or thirty-seven; I’m not entirely sure about this number) arches compared to the twenty-seven below, and the columns end up in all sorts of different positions. Even then, the builder wasn't satisfied and had to bring the irregularity into the rise of the arches. While the overall look is of a balanced arcade, not a single arch is the same height as another; their tops ripple along the wall like waves at a harbor, some nearly touching the string course above, and others dropping down by as much as five or six inches.

XIV. Let us next examine the plan of the west front of St. Mark's at Venice, which, though in many respects imperfect, is in its proportions, and as a piece of rich and fantastic color, as lovely a dream as ever filled human imagination. It may, perhaps, however, interest the reader to hear one opposite opinion upon this subject, and after what has been urged in the preceding pages respecting proportion in general, more especially respecting the wrongness of balanced cathedral towers and other regular designs, together with my frequent references to the Doge's palace, and campanile of St. Mark's, as models of perfection, and my praise of the former especially as projecting above its second arcade, the following extracts from the journal of Wood the architect, written on his arrival at Venice, may have a pleasing freshness in them, and may show that I have not been stating principles altogether trite or accepted.

XIV. Now let's take a look at the design of the west facade of St. Mark's in Venice, which, while imperfect in many ways, is such a beautiful vision in its proportions and rich, imaginative colors that it dazzles the human mind. However, it might be interesting for the reader to hear a differing opinion on this subject. Having discussed proportion in detail in the previous pages, particularly criticizing the symmetry of cathedral towers and other regular designs, along with my frequent references to the Doge's Palace and the campanile of St. Mark's as examples of perfection—especially praising the former for its projection above its second arcade—the following excerpts from the journal of Wood the architect, written upon his arrival in Venice, might offer a refreshing perspective and demonstrate that I haven't merely been stating overly familiar or accepted principles.

"The strange looking church, and the great ugly campanile, could not be mistaken. The exterior of this church surprises you by its extreme ugliness, more than by anything else."

"The oddly shaped church and the huge, unattractive bell tower are unmistakable. The outside of this church shocks you with its utter ugliness more than anything else."

"The Ducal Palace is even more ugly than anything I have previously mentioned. Considered in detail, I can imagine no alteration to make it tolerable; but if this lofty wall had been set back behind the two stories of little arches, it would have been a very noble production."

"The Ducal Palace is even uglier than anything I've mentioned before. Looking at it closely, I can't think of any changes that would make it acceptable; however, if this tall wall had been set back behind the two stories of small arches, it would have been a really impressive design."

After more observations on "a certain justness of proportion," and on the appearance of riches and power in the church, to which he ascribes a pleasing effect, he goes on: "Some persons are of opinion that irregularity is a necessary part of its[Pg 156] excellence. I am decidedly of a contrary opinion, and am convinced that a regular design of the same sort would be far superior. Let an oblong of good architecture, but not very showy, conduct to a fine cathedral, which should appear between two lofty towers and have two obelisks in front, and on each side of this cathedral let other squares partially open into the first, and one of these extend down to a harbor or sea shore, and you would have a scene which might challenge any thing in existence."

After more observations on "a certain justness of proportion," and on the appearance of wealth and power in the church, which he thinks creates a pleasing effect, he continues: "Some people believe that irregularity is an essential part of its[Pg 156] excellence. I completely disagree and am convinced that a well-structured design of the same type would be much better. Picture a long building with good architecture, not overly flashy, leading to a beautiful cathedral, flanked by two tall towers and featuring two obelisks in front. On each side of this cathedral, let other squares partially connect to the first, with one extending down to a harbor or shoreline, and you would have a view that could rival anything in existence."

Why Mr. Wood was unable to enjoy the color of St. Mark's, or perceive the majesty of the Ducal Palace, the reader will see after reading the two following extracts regarding the Caracci and Michael Angelo.

Why Mr. Wood couldn't appreciate the beauty of St. Mark's or notice the grandeur of the Ducal Palace will become clear after reading the two extracts that follow about the Caracci and Michelangelo.

"The pictures here (Bologna) are to my taste far preferable to those of Venice, for if the Venetian school surpass in coloring, and, perhaps, in composition, the Bolognese is decidedly superior in drawing and expression, and the Caraccis shine here like Gods."

"The pictures here (Bologna) are much more to my liking than those from Venice, because while the Venetian school excels in color and maybe composition, the Bolognese is definitely better in drawing and expression, and the Caraccis shine here like Gods."

"What is it that is so much admired in this artist (M. Angelo)? Some contend for a grandeur of composition in the lines and disposition of the figures; this, I confess, I do not comprehend; yet, while I acknowledge the beauty of certain forms and proportions in architecture, I cannot consistently deny that similar merits may exist in painting, though I am unfortunately unable to appreciate them."

"What is it that people admire so much about this artist (M. Angelo)? Some argue that there’s a greatness in the way he composes the lines and arranges the figures; I have to admit, I don’t really get it. However, while I recognize the beauty in certain forms and proportions in architecture, I can’t consistently deny that similar qualities might be present in painting, even though I sadly can’t appreciate them."

I think these passages very valuable, as showing the effect of a contracted knowledge and false taste in painting upon an architect's understanding of his own art; and especially with what curious notions, or lack of notions, about proportion, that art has been sometimes practised. For Mr. Wood is by no means unintelligent in his observations generally, and his criticisms on classical art are often most valuable. But those who love Titian better than the Caracci, and who see something to admire in Michael Angelo, will, perhaps, be willing to proceed with me to a charitable examination of St. Mark's. For, although, the present course of European events affords us some chance of seeing the changes proposed by Mr. Wood carried into execution, we may still esteem ourselves fortunate in hav[Pg 157]ing first known how it was left by the builders of the eleventh century.

I think these passages are very valuable because they show how limited knowledge and bad taste in painting can affect an architect's understanding of their own art; and especially the odd ideas, or complete lack of ideas, about proportion that have sometimes influenced the practice of that art. Mr. Wood is definitely not lacking in intelligence in his overall observations, and his critiques of classical art are often quite insightful. However, those who prefer Titian over the Caracci and who appreciate something about Michelangelo may be open to joining me in a thoughtful discussion of St. Mark's. Even though the current state of European events gives us a chance to see Mr. Wood's proposed changes put into action, we can still consider ourselves lucky to have first known how it was left by the builders of the eleventh century.

XV. The entire front is composed of an upper and lower series of arches, enclosing spaces of wall decorated with mosaic, and supported on ranges of shafts of which, in the lower series of arches, there is an upper range superimposed on a lower. Thus we have five vertical divisions of the façade; i.e. two tiers of shafts, and the arched wall they bear, below; one tier of shafts, and the arched wall they bear, above. In order, however, to bind the two main divisions together, the central lower arch (the main entrance) rises above the level of the gallery and balustrade which crown the lateral arches.

XV. The entire front consists of an upper and lower series of arches that frame wall sections decorated with mosaics. These arches are supported by rows of columns, with an upper row placed above the lower one in the lower series of arches. This creates five vertical sections of the façade; that is, two rows of columns, along with the arched wall they support below, and one row of columns, along with the arched wall they support above. To connect the two main sections, the central lower arch (the main entrance) rises above the level of the gallery and balustrade that top the side arches.

The proportioning of the columns and walls of the lower story is so lovely and so varied, that it would need pages of description before it could be fully understood; but it may be generally stated thus: The height of the lower shafts, upper shafts, and wall, being severally expressed by a, b, and c, then a:c::c:b (a being the highest); and the diameter of shaft b is generally to the diameter of shaft a as height b is to height a, or something less, allowing for the large plinth which diminishes the apparent height of the upper shaft: and when this is their proportion of width, one shaft above is put above one below, with sometimes another upper shaft interposed: but in the extreme arches a single under shaft bears two upper, proportioned as truly as the boughs of a tree; that is to say, the diameter of each upper = 2/3 of lower. There being thus the three terms of proportion gained in the lower story, the upper, while it is only divided into two main members, in order that the whole height may not be divided into an even number, has the third term added in its pinnacles. So far of the vertical division. The lateral is still more subtle. There are seven arches in the lower story; and, calling the central arch a, and counting to the extremity, they diminish in the alternate order a, c, b, d. The upper story has five arches, and two added pinnacles; and these diminish in regular order, the central being the largest, and the outermost the least. Hence, while one proportion ascends, another descends, like parts in music; and yet the pyramidal form is secured for the whole,[Pg 158] and, which was another great point of attention, none of the shafts of the upper arches stand over those of the lower.

The way the columns and walls of the lower level are designed is really beautiful and diverse, so it would take pages to explain it all completely. But in general, it can be stated like this: The heights of the lower shafts, upper shafts, and wall are represented by a, b, and c respectively, so a:c::c:b (with a being the tallest). The diameter of shaft b is usually to the diameter of shaft a as height b is to height a, or slightly less, taking into account the large base that decreases the visible height of the upper shaft. When this width ratio is established, one shaft is placed above another, sometimes with an additional upper shaft in between. However, in the extreme arches, a single lower shaft supports two upper ones, perfectly proportioned like a tree’s branches; specifically, the diameter of each upper shaft equals 2/3 of the lower one. With this, the three terms of proportion in the lower story are established. In the upper section, while it’s only divided into two main parts to avoid an even division of the total height, a third term is added at the pinnacles. This covers the vertical division. The lateral division is even more intricate. There are seven arches in the lower level; if we call the central arch a and move toward the ends, they decrease alternately in the order a, c, b, d. The upper level has five arches and two extra pinnacles, which diminish in a regular pattern, with the center being the largest and the outermost the smallest. Thus, while one proportion rises, another falls, similar to musical parts; yet, the overall pyramidal shape is maintained, and notably, none of the shafts of the upper arches align directly above those of the lower ones.[Pg 158]

XVI. It might have been thought that, by this plan, enough variety had been secured, but the builder was not satisfied even thus: for—and this is the point bearing on the present part of our subject—always calling the central arch a, and the lateral ones b and c in succession, the northern b and c are considerably wider than the southern b and c, but the southern d is as much wider than the northern d, and lower beneath its cornice besides; and, more than this, I hardly believe that one of the effectively symmetrical members of the façade is actually symmetrical with any other. I regret that I cannot state the actual measures. I gave up the taking them upon the spot, owing to their excessive complexity, and the embarrassment caused by the yielding and subsidence of the arches.

XVI. It might have seemed that this plan provided enough variety, but the builder wasn’t satisfied even then: for—and this is relevant to our discussion—always labeling the central arch as a, and the side ones as b and c in order, the northern b and c are much wider than the southern b and c, but the southern d is also wider than the northern d and is lower beneath its cornice; furthermore, I hardly believe that any of the effectively symmetrical parts of the façade are actually symmetrical with each other. I regret that I can't provide the exact measurements. I stopped taking them on site due to their overwhelming complexity and the issues caused by the shifting and settling of the arches.

Do not let it be supposed that I imagine the Byzantine workmen to have had these various principles in their minds as they built. I believe they built altogether from feeling, and that it was because they did so, that there is this marvellous life, changefulness, and subtlety running through their every arrangement; and that we reason upon the lovely building as we should upon some fair growth of the trees of the earth, that know not their own beauty.

Do not think that I believe the Byzantine workers had these different ideas in mind as they constructed their buildings. I think they built purely out of instinct, and it's because of this that their work has such amazing life, variety, and intricacy in every detail. We analyze these beautiful structures as if they were the natural beauty of trees that are unaware of their own charm.

XVII. Perhaps, however, a stranger instance than any I have yet given, of the daring variation of pretended symmetry, is found in the front of the Cathedral of Bayeux. It consists of five arches with steep pediments, the outermost filled, the three central with doors; and they appear, at first, to diminish in regular proportion from the principal one in the centre. The two lateral doors are very curiously managed. The tympana of their arches are filled with bas-reliefs, in four tiers; in the lowest tier there is in each a little temple or gate containing the principal figure (in that on the right, it is the gate of Hades with Lucifer). This little temple is carried, like a capital, by an isolated shaft which divides the whole arch at about 2/3 of its breadth, the larger portion outmost; and in that larger portion is the inner entrance door. This exact correspondence, in the treatment of both gates, might lead us to expect a corre[Pg 159]spondence in dimension. Not at all. The small inner northern entrance measures, in English feet and inches, 4 ft. 7 in. from jamb to jamb, and the southern five feet exactly. Five inches in five feet is a considerable variation. The outer northern porch measures, from face shaft to face shaft, 13 ft. 11 in., and the southern, 14 ft. 6 in.; giving a difference of 7 in. on 14 ½ ft. There are also variations in the pediment decorations not less extraordinary.

XVII. However, a more striking example of the bold variation of false symmetry can be found in the front of the Cathedral of Bayeux. It features five arches with steep pediments, the outermost filled in, while the three central ones have doors. At first glance, they seem to decrease in uniform proportion from the main one in the center. The two side doors have a fascinating design. The tympanums of their arches are adorned with bas-reliefs in four tiers; in the lowest tier, each has a small temple or gate containing the main figure (the one on the right depicts the gate of Hades with Lucifer). This small temple is supported, like a capital, by a separate shaft that divides the whole arch at about two-thirds of its width, with the larger part on the outside; and in that larger section is the inner entrance door. This precise similarity in the design of both gates might suggest a similarity in size. Not at all. The small inner northern entrance measures, in English feet and inches, 4 ft. 7 in. from jamb to jamb, while the southern one is exactly five feet. Five inches in five feet is a significant difference. The outer northern porch measures 13 ft. 11 in. from face shaft to face shaft, and the southern one measures 14 ft. 6 in.; creating a difference of 7 in. over 14 ½ ft. There are also remarkably unusual differences in the pediment decorations.

XVIII. I imagine I have given instances enough, though I could multiply them indefinitely, to prove that these variations are not mere blunders, nor carelessnesses, but the result of a fixed scorn, if not dislike, of accuracy in measurements; and, in most cases, I believe, of a determined resolution to work out an effective symmetry by variations as subtle as those of Nature. To what lengths this principle was sometimes carried, we shall see by the very singular management of the towers of Abbeville. I do not say it is right, still less that it is wrong, but it is a wonderful proof of the fearlessness of a living architecture; for, say what we will of it, that Flamboyant of France, however morbid, was as vivid and intense in its animation as ever any phase of mortal mind; and it would have lived till now, if it had not taken to telling lies. I have before noticed the general difficulty of managing even lateral division, when it is into two equal parts, unless there be some third reconciling member. I shall give, hereafter, more examples of the modes in which this reconciliation is effected in towers with double lights: the Abbeville architect put his sword to the knot perhaps rather too sharply. Vexed by the want of unity between his two windows he literally laid their heads together, and so distorted their ogee curves, as to leave only one of the trefoiled panels above, on the inner side, and three on the outer side of each arch. The arrangement is given in Plate XII. fig. 3. Associated with the various undulation of flamboyant curves below, it is in the real tower hardly observed, while it binds it into one mass in general effect. Granting it, however, to be ugly and wrong, I like sins of the kind, for the sake of the courage it requires to commit them. In plate II. (part of a small chapel attached to the West front of the[Pg 160] Cathedral of St. Lo), the reader will see an instance, from the same architecture, of a violation of its own principles, for the sake of a peculiar meaning. If there be any one feature which the flamboyant architect loved to decorate richly, it was the niche—it was what the capital is to the Corinthian order; yet in the case before us there is an ugly beehive put in the place of the principal niche of the arch. I am not sure if I am right in my interpretation of its meaning, but I have little doubt that two figures below, now broken away, once represented an Annunciation; and on another part of the same cathedral, I find the descent of the Spirit, encompassed by rays of light, represented very nearly in the form of the niche in question; which appears, therefore, to be intended for a representation of this effulgence, while at the same time it was made a canopy for the delicate figures below. Whether this was its meaning or not, it is remarkable as a daring departure from the common habits of the time.

XVIII. I think I've provided enough examples, though I could easily give more, to show that these variations aren't just mistakes or carelessness; they reflect a deliberate disdain, if not outright dislike, for precision in measurements. In many cases, I believe it's a determined effort to create effective symmetry through variations as subtle as those in nature. To what extremes this principle was sometimes taken can be seen in the unique design of the towers of Abbeville. I’m not saying it’s right, or even wrong, but it’s an impressive example of the boldness of living architecture. Regardless of what we may think of it, that Flamboyant style of France, no matter how peculiar, was as vivid and dynamic as any expression of the human mind; it could have persisted to this day, had it not started to mislead. I've pointed out before the general difficulty of managing even lateral divisions when splitting into two equal parts unless there's some third element to reconcile them. I will provide more examples later on how this reconciliation is achieved in towers with double lights: the architect of Abbeville may have cut the knot a bit too sharply. Frustrated by the lack of unity between his two windows, he literally brought their tops together, which distorted their ogee curves, leaving only one of the trefoiled panels above on the inner side, and three on the outer side of each arch. The arrangement is shown in Plate XII, fig. 3. When viewed alongside the various undulations of the flamboyant curves below, it often goes unnoticed in the actual tower, yet it binds it into a cohesive structure overall. Even if we agree that it's unattractive and wrong, I appreciate such faults for the courage it takes to create them. In Plate II (part of a small chapel attached to the west front of the Cathedral of St. Lo), you'll see an example from the same architecture that violates its own principles for a particular purpose. If there’s one feature that the flamboyant architect loved to lavish with decoration, it was the niche—it’s like what the capital is to the Corinthian order; yet in this case, there’s an ugly beehive occupying the main niche of the arch. I’m not entirely confident in my interpretation of its significance, but I have little doubt that the two figures below, now missing, once depicted an Annunciation. On another part of the same cathedral, I find the descent of the Spirit, surrounded by rays of light, represented almost in the shape of the niche in question; this suggests it was intended to symbolize this illumination while also serving as a canopy for the delicate figures below. Whether or not this was its true meaning, it stands out as a bold deviation from the common practices of the time.

XIX. Far more splendid is a license taken with the niche decoration of the portal of St. Maclou at Rouen. The subject of the tympanum bas-relief is the Last Judgment, and the sculpture of the inferno side is carried out with a degree of power whose fearful grotesqueness I can only describe as a mingling of the minds of Orcagna and Hogarth. The demons are perhaps even more awful than Orcagna's; and, in some of the expressions of debased humanity in its utmost despair, the English painter is at least equalled. Not less wild is the imagination which gives fury and fear even to the placing of the figures. An evil angel, poised on the wing, drives the condemned troops from before the Judgment seat; with his left hand he drags behind him a cloud, which is spreading like a winding-sheet over them all; but they are urged by him so furiously, that they are driven not merely to the extreme limit of that scene, which the sculptor confined elsewhere within the tympanum, but out of the tympanum and into the niches of the arch; while the flames that follow them, bent by the blast, as it seems, of the angel's wings, rush into the niches also, and burst up through their tracery, the three lowermost niches being represented as all on fire, while, [Pg 161] instead of their usual vaulted and ribbed ceiling, there is a demon in the roof of each, with his wings folded over it, grinning down out of the black shadow.

XIX. The decoration of the portal of St. Maclou at Rouen is truly impressive. The tympanum's bas-relief depicts the Last Judgment, and the sculpture on the hell side is so powerful that it feels like a blend of Orcagna and Hogarth. The demons here are possibly even scarier than Orcagna's, and in the expressions of twisted humanity in their deepest despair, the English artist is at least matched. The imagination behind this piece is equally wild, giving a sense of rage and fear even in the arrangement of the figures. An evil angel, hovering in the air, drives the damned souls away from the Judgment seat; with his left hand, he drags a cloud that spreads over them like a shroud, urging them on so fiercely that they are pushed not just to the edge of the scene, as the sculptor has defined it elsewhere within the tympanum, but out of the tympanum and into the niches of the arch; while the flames that chase them, seemingly propelled by the gust of the angel's wings, rush into the niches too, bursting up through their tracery, with the three lowest niches depicted as completely on fire, and instead of their usual vaulted and ribbed ceiling, each features a demon with its wings folded, grinning down from the dark shadows.

PLATE XIII. PLATE XIII.—(Page 161—Vol. V.)
Parts of an Arcade on the South Side of the Ferrara Cathedral.

XX. I have, however, given enough instances of vitality shown in mere daring, whether wise, as surely in this last instance, or inexpedient; but, as a single example of the Vitality of Assimilation, the faculty which turns to its purposes all material that is submitted to it, I would refer the reader to the extraordinary columns of the arcade on the south side of the Cathedral of Ferrara. A single arch of it is given in Plate XIII. on the right. Four such columns forming a group, there are interposed two pairs of columns, as seen on the left of the same plate; and then come another four arches. It is a long arcade of, I suppose, not less than forty arches, perhaps of many more; and in the grace and simplicity of its stilted Byzantine curves I hardly know its equal. Its like, in fancy of column, I certainly do not know; there being hardly two correspondent, and the architect having been ready, as it seems, to adopt ideas and resemblances from any sources whatsoever. The vegetation growing up the two columns is fine, though bizarre; the distorted pillars beside it suggest images of less agreeable character; the serpentine arrangements founded on the usual Byzantine double knot are generally graceful; but I was puzzled to account for the excessively ugly type of the pillar, fig. 3, one of a group of four. It so happened, fortunately for me, that there had been a fair in Ferrara; and, when I had finished my sketch of the pillar, I had to get out of the way of some merchants of miscellaneous wares, who were removing their stall. It had been shaded by an awning supported by poles, which, in order that the covering might be raised or lowered according to the height of the sun, were composed of two separate pieces, fitted to each other by a rack, in which I beheld the prototype of my ugly pillar. It will not be thought, after what I have above said of the inexpedience of imitating anything but natural form, that I advance this architect's practice as altogether exemplary; yet the humility is instructive, which condescended to such sources for motives of thought, the boldness, which could depart so[Pg 162] far from all established types of form, and the life and feeling, which out of an assemblage of such quaint and uncouth materials, could produce an harmonious piece of ecclesiastical architecture.

XX. I have given enough examples of vitality displayed in mere daring, whether it was wise, as in this last example, or not very practical; but, as a single example of the Vitality of Assimilation, the ability to use all materials presented to it, I would direct the reader to the remarkable columns of the arcade on the south side of the Cathedral of Ferrara. A single arch of it is illustrated in Plate XIII on the right. Four such columns form a group, with two pairs of columns in between, as shown on the left of the same plate; then there are another four arches. It’s a long arcade, I assume, with no fewer than forty arches, possibly many more; and in the grace and simplicity of its stilted Byzantine curves, I’m hard-pressed to find anything that compares. I certainly don’t know anything like it in terms of column design; hardly two are alike, and the architect seems to have been willing to borrow ideas and influences from any source. The greenery climbing up the two columns is beautiful, though unusual; the distorted pillars nearby evoke less pleasant imagery; the twisting patterns based on the typical Byzantine double knot are mostly elegant; but I struggled to understand the extremely unattractive style of the pillar, fig. 3, one of a group of four. As luck would have it, a fair was taking place in Ferrara; and after I finished my sketch of the pillar, I had to step aside for some merchants with various goods who were taking down their stall. It had been covered by an awning supported by poles, which were made of two separate pieces that could be adjusted based on the sun’s height, and I saw the prototype of my ugly pillar in that mechanism. After what I’ve said about the impracticality of imitating anything other than natural forms, I don’t present this architect’s practice as completely exemplary; yet the humility in drawing inspiration from such sources is instructive, the boldness to stray so far from all established forms is commendable, and the creativity that could take such quirky and awkward materials and create a harmonious piece of ecclesiastical architecture is truly remarkable.

XXI. I have dwelt, however, perhaps, too long upon that form of vitality which is known almost as much by its errors as by its atonements for them. We must briefly note the operation of it, which is always right, and always necessary, upon those lesser details, where it can neither be superseded by precedents, nor repressed by proprieties.

XXI. I may have spent too much time discussing that kind of vitality that is recognized almost as much for its mistakes as for correcting them. We should quickly recognize its role, which is always correct and always essential, in those smaller details, where it cannot be replaced by past practices or held back by social norms.

I said, early in this essay, that hand-work might always be known from machine-work; observing, however, at the same time, that it was possible for men to turn themselves into machines, and to reduce their labor to the machine level; but so long as men work as men, putting their heart into what they do, and doing their best, it matters not how bad workmen they may be, there will be that in the handling which is above all price: it will be plainly seen that some places have been delighted in more than others—that there has been a pause, and a care about them; and then there will come careless bits, and fast bits; and here the chisel will have struck hard, and there lightly, and anon timidly; and if the man's mind as well as his heart went with his work, all this will be in the right places, and each part will set off the other; and the effect of the whole, as compared with the same design cut by a machine or a lifeless hand, will be like that of poetry well read and deeply felt to that of the same verses jangled by rote. There are many to whom the difference is imperceptible; but to those who love poetry it is everything—they had rather not hear it at all, than hear it ill read; and to those who love Architecture, the life and accent of the hand are everything. They had rather not have ornament at all, than see it ill cut—deadly cut, that is. I cannot too often repeat, it is not coarse cutting, it is not blunt cutting, that is necessarily bad; but it is cold cutting—the look of equal trouble everywhere—the smooth, diffused tranquillity of heartless pains—the regularity of a plough in a level field. The chill is more likely, indeed, to show itself in finished work than in any other—men cool[Pg 163] and tire as they complete: and if completeness is thought to be vested in polish, and to be attainable by help of sand paper, we may as well give the work to the engine-lathe at once. But right finish is simply the full rendering of the intended impression; and high finish is the rendering of a well intended and vivid impression; and it is oftener got by rough than fine handling. I am not sure whether it is frequently enough observed that sculpture is not the mere cutting of the form of anything in stone; it is the cutting of the effect of it. Very often the true form, in the marble, would not be in the least like itself. The sculptor must paint with his chisel: half his touches are not to realize, but to put power into the form: they are touches of light and shadow; and raise a ridge, or sink a hollow, not to represent an actual ridge or hollow, but to get a line of light, or a spot of darkness. In a coarse way, this kind of execution is very marked in old French woodwork; the irises of the eyes of its chimeric monsters being cut boldly into holes, which, variously placed, and always dark, give all kinds of strange and startling expressions, averted and askance, to the fantastic countenances. Perhaps the highest examples of this kind of sculpture-painting are the works of Mino da Fiesole; their best effects being reached by strange angular, and seemingly rude, touches of the chisel. The lips of one of the children on the tombs in the church of the Badia, appear only half finished when they are seen close; yet the expression is farther carried and more ineffable, than in any piece of marble I have ever seen, especially considering its delicacy, and the softness of the child-features. In a sterner kind, that of the statues in the sacristy of St. Lorenzo equals it, and there again by incompletion. I know no example of work in which the forms are absolutely true and complete where such a result is attained; in Greek sculptures is not even attempted.

I mentioned earlier in this essay that handmade work can always be distinguished from machine-made work, while also noting that people can turn themselves into machines and reduce their labor to the level of machines. However, as long as people work as humans, putting their heart into what they do and giving it their best effort, it doesn't matter how poor their skills might be; there will be something in the way they handle their work that is priceless. It will be clear that some areas have been worked on more lovingly than others, that there has been a pause and care taken with them; then there will be parts that are done carelessly and those that are done quickly; sometimes the chisel will strike hard, other times lightly, and at other moments timidly. If a person’s mind as well as their heart is engaged in their work, all this will be properly placed, and each part will complement the others; the overall effect, when compared to the same design produced by a machine or an unfeeling hand, will be like the difference between poetry that is read beautifully and felt deeply versus the same verses recited by rote. For many, the difference may not be noticeable, but for those who appreciate poetry, it means everything—they would prefer not to hear it at all than to hear it poorly read; similarly, for those who appreciate architecture, the life and nuance of the hand matter immensely. They would prefer to have no ornament at all than to see it poorly cut—deadly so. I cannot stress enough that it isn’t coarse cutting or blunt cutting that is inherently bad; rather, it is cold cutting—the uniform appearance of effort everywhere—the smooth, diffuse calm of heartless toil—the regularity of a plow in a flat field. The coldness is more likely to appear in finished work than in any other stage—people cool down and tire as they complete. If people believe that completeness means polish and can be achieved through sanding, we might as well hand the work off to a machine lathe. But the right finish is simply a clear representation of the intended impression; high finish is the creation of a vivid and well-intended impression, and this is often achieved more through rough than fine handling. I'm not sure it’s often recognized that sculpture is not just about cutting the form of something in stone; it’s about carving the effect of it. Very often, the true form in marble wouldn’t look anything like itself. The sculptor has to paint with the chisel: many of his touches are not meant to recreate but to imbue the form with power. They are touches of light and shadow that create a ridge or a hollow not to replicate a real ridge or hollow but to obtain a line of light or a spot of darkness. In a basic way, this kind of workmanship is quite evident in old French woodwork; the irises of the eyes in its fantastic creatures are boldly carved into holes that, through various placements and always in darkness, give all kinds of strange and startling expressions, turning and looking askance, to their fantastical faces. Perhaps the finest examples of this kind of sculptural painting are the works of Mino da Fiesole; their best effects are achieved through strange angular and seemingly rough chisel touches. The lips of one of the children on the tombs in the church of the Badia appear only half-finished when viewed up close; yet the expression conveyed is more profound and ineffable than in any piece of marble I’ve ever seen, especially when considering the delicacy and softness of the child’s features. In a more serious context, the statues in the sacristy of St. Lorenzo match this quality, again through incompletion. I’ve never seen any work where the forms are absolutely true and complete that achieves such a result; it’s not even attempted in Greek sculptures.

XXII. It is evident that, for architectural appliances, such masculine handling, likely as it must be to retain its effectiveness when higher finish would be injured by time, must always be the most expedient; and as it is impossible, even were it desirable that the highest finish should be given to the quantity of work which covers a large building, it will be[Pg 164] understood how precious the intelligence must become, which renders incompletion itself a means of additional expression; and how great must be the difference, when the touches are rude and few, between those of a careless and those of a regardful mind. It is not easy to retain anything of their character in a copy; yet the reader will find one or two illustrative points in the examples, given in Plate XIV., from the bas-reliefs of the north of Rouen Cathedral. There are three square pedestals under the three main niches on each side of it, and one in the centre; each of these being on two sides decorated with five quatrefoiled panels. There are thus seventy quatrefoils in the lower ornament of the gate alone, without counting those of the outer course round it, and of the pedestals outside: each quatrefoil is filled with a bas-relief, the whole reaching to something above a man's height. A modern architect would, of course, have made all the five quatrefoils of each pedestal-side equal: not so the Mediæval. The general form being apparently a quatrefoil composed of semicircles on the sides of a square, it will be found on examination that none of the arcs are semicircles, and none of the basic figures squares. The latter are rhomboids, having their acute or obtuse angles uppermost according to their larger or smaller size; and the arcs upon their sides slide into such places as they can get in the angles of the enclosing parallelogram, leaving intervals, at each of the four angles, of various shapes, which are filled each by an animal. The size of the whole panel being thus varied, the two lowest of the five are tall, the next two short, and the uppermost a little higher than the lowest; while in the course of bas-reliefs which surrounds the gate, calling either of the two lowest (which are equal), a, and either of the next two b, and the fifth and sixth c and d, then d (the largest): c::c:a::a:b. It is wonderful how much of the grace of the whole depends on these variations.

XXII. It’s clear that for architectural details, a more rugged approach is often necessary to maintain effectiveness when a higher finish might deteriorate over time. It's impossible, even if it were ideal, for the intricate finish to be applied to the large amounts of work that cover a big building. One must appreciate how valuable the skill becomes that allows incompletion to serve as a form of expression, and how significant the difference is between rough touches made carelessly and those made with intention. It’s not easy to capture their character in a replica, but the reader will find a few points of interest in the examples shown in Plate XIV., taken from the bas-reliefs at the north side of Rouen Cathedral. There are three square pedestals under the three main niches on each side, plus one in the center; each of these is adorned on two sides with five quatrefoiled panels. In total, there are seventy quatrefoils just in the lower ornament of the gate, not including those on the outer edge and the pedestals outside. Each quatrefoil has a bas-relief, stretching a bit above a man's height. A modern architect would, of course, make all five quatrefoils on each pedestal's side identical, but the Medieval ones did not. While the overall shape seems to be a quatrefoil made of semicircles on the sides of a square, a closer look reveals that none of the arcs are semicircles and none of the base shapes are squares. Instead, they are rhomboids, with their acute or obtuse angles pointing up depending on their size. The arcs fit into the angles of the surrounding parallelogram, leaving spaces in each of the four corners filled by various animals. The size of each panel differs, with the two lowest of the five being tall, the next two being short, and the top one slightly taller than the lowest. In terms of the surrounding bas-reliefs, if we label either of the two lowest as a, either of the next two as b, and the fifth and sixth as c and d, then it follows that d (the largest): c::c:a::a:b. It’s amazing how much the overall elegance relies on these variations.

XXIII. Each of the angles, it was said, is filled by an animal. There are thus 70 x 4=280 animals, all different, in the mere fillings of the intervals of the bas-reliefs. Three of these intervals, with their beasts, actual size, the curves being traced upon the stone, I have given in Plate XIV.

XXIII. It was said that each angle is occupied by an animal. So, there are 70 x 4 = 280 unique animals just in the spaces of the bas-reliefs. I've included three of these spaces, with their animals at actual size and the curves outlined on the stone, in Plate XIV.

PLATE XIV. PLATE XIV.—(Page 165—Vol. V.)
Sculpture from Rouen Cathedral.

I say nothing of their general design, or of the lines of the wings and scales, which are perhaps, unless in those of the central dragon, not much above the usual commonplaces of good ornamental work; but there is an evidence in the features of thoughtfulness and fancy which is not common, at least now-a-days. The upper creature on the left is biting something, the form of which is hardly traceable in the defaced stone—but biting he is; and the reader cannot but recognise in the peculiarly reverted eye the expression which is never seen, as I think, but in the eye of a dog gnawing something in jest, and preparing to start away with it: the meaning of the glance, so far as it can be marked by the mere incision of the chisel, will be felt by comparing it with the eye of the couchant figure on the right, in its gloomy and angry brooding. The plan of this head, and the nod of the cap over its brow, are fine; but there is a little touch above the hand especially well meant: the fellow is vexed and puzzled in his malice; and his hand is pressed hard on his cheek bone, and the flesh of the cheek is wrinkled under the eye by the pressure. The whole, indeed, looks wretchedly coarse, when it is seen on a scale in which it is naturally compared with delicate figure etchings; but considering it as a mere filling of an interstice on the outside of a cathedral gate, and as one of more than three hundred (for in my estimate I did not include the outer pedestals), it proves very noble vitality in the art of the time.

I won’t comment on their overall design or the shapes of the wings and scales, which are probably not much different from the usual good decorative work, except for the central dragon. However, there’s a sense of thoughtfulness and creativity in the features that isn’t common nowadays. The creature on the left is biting something, but the shape of it is hard to identify due to the worn stone—yet he is definitely biting; and you can see in his uniquely turned eye an expression that I think is only found in a dog playfully gnawing something and getting ready to run off with it. You can get the essence of this glance, as much as it can be captured by the chisel’s line, by comparing it to the eye of the figure on the right, which looks gloomy and angry. The design of this head, along with the cap tilted over its brow, is impressive; but there's a nice touch above the hand that stands out: the character looks annoyed and bewildered in his spite, with his hand pressed hard against his cheekbone, causing the skin to wrinkle under his eye from the pressure. Overall, it seems rather crude when compared with delicate figure etchings, but if you think of it simply as a detail on the outside of a cathedral gate and one of over three hundred (not counting the outer pedestals in my estimate), it shows a remarkable vitality in the art of that time.

XXIV. I believe the right question to ask, respecting all ornament, is simply this: Was it done with enjoyment—was the carver happy while he was about it? It may be the hardest work possible, and the harder because so much pleasure was taken in it; but it must have been happy too, or it will not be living. How much of the stone mason's toil this condition would exclude I hardly venture to consider, but the condition is absolute. There is a Gothic church lately built near Rouen, vile enough, indeed, in its general composition, but excessively rich in detail; many of the details are designed with taste, and all evidently by a man who has studied old work closely. But it is all as dead as leaves in December;[Pg 166] there is not one tender touch, not one warm stroke, on the whole façade. The men who did it hated it, and were thankful when it was done. And so long as they do so they are merely loading your walls with shapes of clay: the garlands of everlastings in Père la Chaise are more cheerful ornaments. You cannot get the feeling by paying for it—money will not buy life. I am not sure even that you can get it by watching or waiting for it. It is true that here and there a workman may be found who has it in him, but he does not rest contented in the inferior work—he struggles forward into an Academician; and from the mass of available handicraftsmen the power is gone—how recoverable I know not: this only I know, that all expense devoted to sculptural ornament, in the present condition of that power, comes literally under the head of Sacrifice for the sacrifice's sake, or worse. I believe the only manner of rich ornament that is open to us is the geometrical color-mosaic, and that much might result from our strenuously taking up this mode of design. But, at all events, one thing we have in our power—the doing without machine ornament and cast-iron work. All the stamped metals, and artificial stones, and imitation woods and bronzes, over the invention of which we hear daily exultation—all the short, and cheap, and easy ways of doing that whose difficulty is its honor—are just so many new obstacles in our already encumbered road. They will not make one of us happier or wiser—they will extend neither the pride of judgment nor the privilege of enjoyment. They will only make us shallower in our understandings, colder in our hearts, and feebler in our wits. And most justly. For we are not sent into this world to do any thing into which we cannot put our hearts. We have certain work to do for our bread, and that is to be done strenuously; other work to do for our delight, and that is to be done heartily: neither is to be done by halves or shifts, but with a will; and what is not worth this effort is not to be done at all. Perhaps all that we have to do is meant for nothing more than an exercise of the heart and of the will, and is useless in itself; but, at all events, the little use it has may well be spared if it is not worth putting our hands and our strength to. It does[Pg 167] not become our immortality to take an ease inconsistent with its authority, nor to suffer any instruments with which it can dispense, to come between it and the things it rules: and he who would form the creations of his own mind by any other instrument than his own hand, would, also, if he might, give grinding organs to Heaven's angels, to make their music easier. There is dreaming enough, and earthiness enough, and sensuality enough in human existence without our turning the few glowing moments of it into mechanism; and since our life must at the best be but a vapor that appears for a little time and then vanishes away, let it at least appear as a cloud in the height of Heaven, not as the thick darkness that broods over the blast of the Furnace, and rolling of the Wheel.

XXIV. I think the right question to ask about any decoration is simply this: Was it done with joy? Was the carver happy while creating it? It might have been the toughest job imaginable, made harder because of the pleasure taken in it; but it must have also been joyful, or it won’t feel alive. I can hardly imagine how much of the stone mason's effort this criterion would eliminate, but it is essential. There's a recently built Gothic church near Rouen, which is indeed pretty terrible in its overall design, yet rich in details; many details are tastefully designed, all clearly by someone who has studied older works carefully. But it feels as lifeless as leaves in December; there’s not a single gentle touch or warm stroke across the entire façade. The workers who did it hated it and were relieved when it was finished. As long as that’s the case, they’re just burdening your walls with shapes of clay: the everlasting garlands in Père la Chaise are more cheerful decorations. You can’t buy the feeling with money—no amount can purchase life. I’m not even sure you can attain it by just observing or waiting. It’s true that occasionally, a worker may possess this quality, but he won’t be satisfied with inferior work—he strives to become an Academician; and from the pool of available craftspeople, that power is lost—how it can be regained, I do not know. What I do know is that any money spent on sculptural decoration, given the current state of that craft, is essentially a Sacrifice for the sake of sacrifice, or worse. I believe the only form of rich decorations available to us is the geometric color-mosaic, and I think a lot could come from actively embracing this style of design. Regardless, one thing we can definitely do is to avoid machine-made ornamentation and cast-iron work. All the stamped metals, artificial stones, and imitation woods and bronzes that we hear daily praised—all the quick, cheap, and easy methods for achieving what takes effort and skill—are just more obstacles on our already cluttered path. They won’t make any of us happier or wiser—they won’t enhance our judgment or our ability to enjoy. They’ll only make our understanding shallower, our hearts colder, and our minds weaker. And rightly so. We aren’t in this world to engage in anything we can’t fully invest ourselves in. We have certain jobs to do for our livelihood, and that must be done with vigor; we have other tasks to take on for our enjoyment, and those should be approached wholeheartedly: neither should be done halfway or with shortcuts, but with commitment; and anything that isn’t worth this level of effort shouldn’t be done at all. Perhaps everything we do is just meant to exercise our hearts and will, and is pointless by itself; but at least the little usefulness it has can be skipped if it’s not worth our time and energy. It doesn’t honor our immortality to take an easy way that conflicts with our authority, nor should we allow any tools that it can do without to come between it and the things it oversees: and anyone who wants to create with their mind using any instrument other than their own hand would also, if they could, give mechanical parts to Heaven’s angels to make their music simpler. There’s already enough dreaming, earthiness, and sensuality in human life without transforming its few vibrant moments into machinery; and since our lives, at best, are merely vapor that appears briefly before vanishing, let them at least rise like a cloud high in Heaven, not as the thick darkness that hangs over the blast of the furnace and the turning of the wheel.


CHAPTER VI.

THE LAMP OF MEMORY.

I. Among the hours of his life to which the writer looks back with peculiar gratitude, as having been marked by more than ordinary fulness of joy or clearness of teaching, is one passed, now some years ago, near time of sunset, among the broken masses of pine forest which skirt the course of the Ain, above the village of Champagnole, in the Jura. It is a spot which has all the solemnity, with none of the savageness, of the Alps; where there is a sense of a great power beginning to be manifested in the earth, and of a deep and majestic concord in the rise of the long low lines of piny hills; the first utterance of those mighty mountain symphonies, soon to be more loudly lifted and wildly broken along the battlements of the Alps. But their strength is as yet restrained; and the far-reaching ridges of pastoral mountain succeed each other, like the long and sighing swell which moves over quiet waters from some far-off stormy sea. And there is a deep tenderness pervading that vast monotony. The destructive forces and the stern expression of the central ranges are alike withdrawn. No frost-ploughed, dust-encumbered paths of ancient glacier[Pg 168] fret the soft Jura pastures; no splintered heaps of ruin break the fair ranks of her forests; no pale, defiled, or furious rivers rend their rude and changeful ways among her rocks. Patiently, eddy by eddy, the clear green streams wind along their well-known beds; and under the dark quietness of the undisturbed pines, there spring up, year by year, such company of joyful flowers as I know not the like of among all the blessings of the earth. It was Spring time, too; and all were coming forth in clusters crowded for very love; there was room enough for all, but they crushed their leaves into all manner of strange shapes only to be nearer each other. There was the wood anemone, star after star, closing every now and then into nebulæ: and there was the oxalis, troop by troop like virginal processions of the Mois de Marie, the dark vertical clefts in the limestone choked up with them as with heavy snow, and touched with ivy on the edges—ivy as light and lovely as the vine; and ever and anon, a blue gush of violets, and cowslip bells in sunny places; and in the more open ground, the vetch, and comfrey, and mezereon, and the small sapphire buds of the Polygala Alpina, and the wild strawberry, just a blossom or two, all showered amidst the golden softness of deep, warm, amber-colored moss. I came out presently on the edge of the ravine; the solemn murmur of its waters rose suddenly from beneath, mixed with the singing of the thrushes among the pine boughs; and, on the opposite side of the valley, walled all along as it was by grey cliffs of limestone, there was a hawk sailing slowly off their brow, touching them nearly with his wings, and with the shadows of the pines flickering upon his plumage from above; but with a fall of a hundred fathoms under his breast, and the curling pools of the green river gliding and glittering dizzily beneath him, their foam globes moving with him as he flew. It would be difficult to conceive a scene less dependent upon any other interest than that of its own secluded and serious beauty; but the writer well remembers the sudden blankness and chill which were cast upon it when he endeavored, in order more strictly to arrive at the sources of its impressiveness, to imagine it, for a moment, a scene in some aboriginal forest of the New Con[Pg 169]tinent. The flowers in an instant lost their light, the river its music15; the hills became oppressively desolate; a heaviness in the boughs of the darkened forest showed how much of their former power had been dependent upon a life which was not theirs, how much of the glory of the imperishable, or continually renewed, creation is reflected from things more precious in their memories than it, in its renewing. Those ever springing flowers and ever flowing streams had been dyed by the deep colors of human endurance, valor, and virtue; and the crests of the sable hills that rose against the evening sky received a deeper worship, because their far shadows fell eastward over the iron wall of Joux and the four-square keep of Granson.

I. Among the moments in his life that the writer looks back on with special gratitude, as they were filled with more than usual joy or clarity, is one spent, a few years ago, near sunset, among the scattered pine forests along the Ain River, above the village of Champagnole in the Jura. It’s a place that has all the solemnity but none of the wildness of the Alps; where you can sense a great power beginning to show itself in the earth, and a deep and majestic harmony in the rising lines of pine-covered hills; the first expressions of those mighty mountain symphonies, which will soon become louder and wilder along the peaks of the Alps. But their strength is still held back; and the broad ridges of pastoral mountains follow one after another, like the gentle waves that move across calm waters from a distant stormy sea. There’s a deep tenderness permeating that vast simplicity. The destructive forces and the harsh expressions of the central ranges are both absent. There are no frost-ruined, dust-laden paths of ancient glaciers unsettling the soft Jura pastures; no shattered heaps of ruin disrupt the beautiful rows of her forests; no pale, tainted, or raging rivers carve unsteady paths among her rocks. Patiently, eddy by eddy, the clear green streams flow along their well-known beds; and under the calm stillness of the undisturbed pines, joyful flowers emerge year after year, unlike any I’ve seen among all the treasures of the earth. It was springtime, too, and all were coming out in groups, crowded together with love; there was plenty of room for all, yet they twisted their leaves into strange shapes just to be closer to each other. There was the wood anemone, each one a star, sometimes curling into nebulas: and there was the oxalis, in clusters like pure processions of the Mois de Marie, the dark vertical cracks in the limestone filled with them as though they were heavy snow, touched with ivy on the edges—ivy as light and lovely as the vine; and now and then a burst of blue violets, and cowslip bells in sunny spots; and in the more open areas, the vetch, comfrey, mezereon, and the small sapphire buds of Polygala Alpina, and the wild strawberries, with just a blossom or two, all scattered among the golden softness of deep, warm, amber moss. I soon found myself at the edge of the ravine; the solemn murmur of its waters rose suddenly from below, mixed with the song of the thrushes in the pine boughs; and on the opposite side of the valley, lined with grey limestone cliffs, a hawk was gliding slowly from their edge, nearly touching them with his wings, shadows of the pines flickering over his feathers from above; but with a drop of a hundred fathoms beneath him, and the twisting pools of the green river glittering dizzily below, their foam bubbles moving with him as he flew. It would be hard to imagine a scene less reliant on anything other than its own secluded and serious beauty; but the writer clearly remembers the sudden feeling of emptiness and chill that came over it when he tried, for just a moment, to picture it as a scene in some primeval forest of the New World. The flowers instantly lost their brightness, the river its music; the hills felt oppressively desolate; a weight in the branches of the darkened forest revealed how much of their previous power depended on a life that wasn’t theirs, how much of the glory of the timeless, or always renewed, creation is reflected from things remembered as more precious than itself, in its renewal. Those endlessly blooming flowers and ever-flowing streams had been colored by the deep hues of human endurance, courage, and virtue; and the dark hilltops rising against the evening sky received a deeper reverence, because their long shadows stretched eastward over the iron wall of Joux and the sturdy keep of Granson.

II. It is as the centralisation and protectress of this sacred influence, that Architecture is to be regarded by us with the most serious thought. We may live without her, and worship without her, but we cannot remember without her. How cold is all history how lifeless all imagery, compared to that which the living nation writes, and the uncorrupted marble bears! how many pages of doubtful record might we not often spare, for a few stones left one upon another! The ambition of the old Babel builders was well directed for this world: there are but two strong conquerors of the forgetfulness of men, Poetry and Architecture; and the latter in some sort includes the former, and is mightier in its reality; it is well to have, not only what men have thought and felt, but what their hands have handled, and their strength wrought, and their eyes beheld, all the days of their life. The age of Homer is surrounded with darkness, his very personality with doubt. Not so that of Pericles: and the day is coming when we shall confess, that we have learned more of Greece out of the crumbled fragments of her sculpture than even from her sweet singers or soldier historians. And if indeed there be any profit in our knowledge of the past, or any joy in the thought of being remembered hereafter, which can give strength to present exertion, or patience to present endurance, there are two duties respecting national architecture whose importance it is impossible to overrate; the first, to render the architecture of the[Pg 170] day historical; and, the second, to preserve, as the most precious of inheritances, that of past ages.

II. We should think seriously about Architecture as the central hub and guardian of this sacred influence. We can live and worship without it, but we can’t remember without it. All history feels cold and lifeless compared to what the living nation records and what the unspoiled marble holds! How many pages of questionable records could we often do without for just a few stones stacked together? The ambition of the ancient Babel builders was well-placed for this world: there are only two powerful conquerors of human forgetfulness: Poetry and Architecture; and the latter somewhat encompasses the former and is more powerful in its tangible existence. It’s important to have not just what people have thought and felt, but also what their hands have shaped, their strength has built, and what their eyes have seen throughout their lives. The era of Homer is shrouded in darkness, with even his identity in question. Not so with Pericles: the day will come when we’ll admit that we’ve learned more about Greece from the fragmented remains of her sculpture than from her lovely poets or soldier historians. And if there’s any value in our understanding of the past or any joy in the thought of being remembered in the future that can boost our current efforts or give us patience in present hardships, there are two duties regarding national architecture that are incredibly important: first, to make today’s architecture historical; and second, to preserve the architecture of past ages as one of our most treasured inheritances.

III. It is in the first of these two directions that Memory may truly be said to be the Sixth Lamp of Architecture; for it is in becoming memorial or monumental that a true perfection is attained by civil and domestic buildings; and this partly as they are, with such a view, built in a more stable manner, and partly as their decorations are consequently animated by a metaphorical or historical meaning.

III. In the first of these two directions, Memory can really be considered the Sixth Lamp of Architecture; because it's when buildings become memorial or monumental that they truly reach perfection, both in public and private spaces. This is partly because they are built more solidly with that purpose in mind, and partly because their decorations are infused with a metaphorical or historical significance.

As regards domestic buildings, there must always be a certain limitation to views of this kind in the power, as well as in the hearts, of men; still I cannot but think it an evil sign of a people when their houses are built to last for one generation only. There is a sanctity in a good man's house which cannot be renewed in every tenement that rises on its ruins: and I believe that good men would generally feel this; and that having spent their lives happily and honorably, they would be grieved at the close of them to think that the place of their earthly abode, which had seen, and seemed almost to sympathise in all their honor, their gladness, or their suffering,—that this, with all the record it bare of them, and all of material things that they had loved and ruled over, and set the stamp of themselves upon—was to be swept away, as soon as there was room made for them in the grave; that no respect was to be shown to it, no affection felt for it, no good to be drawn from it by their children; that though there was a monument in the church, there was no warm monument in the heart and house to them; that all that they ever treasured was despised, and the places that had sheltered and comforted them were dragged down to the dust. I say that a good man would fear this; and that, far more, a good son, a noble descendant, would fear doing it to his father's house. I say that if men lived like men indeed, their houses would be temples—temples which we should hardly dare to injure, and in which it would make us holy to be permitted to live; and there must be a strange dissolution of natural affection, a strange unthankfulness for all that homes have given and parents taught, a strange consciousness that we have been unfaithful to our fathers' honor, or that[Pg 171] our own lives are not such as would make our dwellings sacred to our children, when each man would fain build to himself, and build for the little revolution of his own life only. And I look upon those pitiful concretions of lime and clay which spring up in mildewed forwardness out of the kneaded fields about our capital—upon those thin, tottering, foundationless shells of splintered wood and imitated stone—upon those gloomy rows of formalised minuteness, alike without difference and without fellowship, as solitary as similar—not merely with the careless disgust of an offended eye, not merely with sorrow for a desecrated landscape, but with a painful foreboding that the roots of our national greatness must be deeply cankered when they are thus loosely struck in their native ground; that those comfortless and unhonored dwellings are the signs of a great and spreading spirit of popular discontent; that they mark the time when every man's aim is to be in some more elevated sphere than his natural one, and every man's past life is his habitual scorn; when men build in the hope of leaving the places they have built, and live in the hope of forgetting the years that they have lived; when the comfort, the peace, the religion of home have ceased to be felt; and the crowded tenements of a struggling and restless population differ only from the tents of the Arab or the Gipsy by their less healthy openness to the air of heaven, and less happy choice of their spot of earth; by their sacrifice of liberty without the gain of rest, and of stability without the luxury of change.

When it comes to homes, there will always be some limits on the perspectives we have in both the actions and hearts of people. Still, I can't help but see it as a troubling sign when homes are built to last for just one generation. A good person’s home holds a sanctity that can’t be recreated in every building that replaces it. I believe that good people inherently understand this, and after living happy and honorable lives, they would feel saddened at the end to think that the place they called home, which witnessed and almost understood all their honor, joy, and pain—this place, along with everything tied to it that they loved and shaped—would be discarded as soon as there was space made for them in the grave. There would be no respect paid to it, no fondness felt for it, no benefit gleaned from it by their children; that even though there might be a memorial in the church, there would be no heartfelt tribute in the home or among loved ones; that everything they cherished would be disregarded, and the places that had provided comfort would be reduced to rubble. I argue that a good person would fear this, and even more so, a good son or noble descendant would dread doing this to their father’s home. If people truly lived as they should, their houses would be like temples—sacred spaces we would hesitate to damage, where it would feel uplifting to be allowed to live. It must point to a strange breakdown of natural affection, a troubling ingratitude for all that homes have given and parents have taught, a weird awareness that we haven't been true to our fathers' honor, or that our own lives aren't of a standard that would make our homes sacred to our children, when each man only aims to build for himself, focusing solely on the fleeting chapter of his own life. I look at those sad clusters of cement and clay that pop up in grim eagerness from the blended fields around our city—those weak, shaky, foundationless structures made of cheap wood and fake stone—those dull lines of standardized smallness, all alike yet isolated, as lonely as they are similar. I don't just look upon them with the casual disgust of a displeased observer, nor solely with sorrow for a desecrated landscape, but with a painful sense of foreboding that our national greatness must be deeply troubled when we see such loose roots in our own soil; that those uncomfortable and unloved homes indicate a significant and growing spirit of public discontent; that they signal a time when everyone's goal is to rise to a higher status than they naturally hold, while every person's past is viewed with disdain; when people build with the hope of eventually leaving the places they’ve constructed and live with the hope of forgetting the years they’ve spent; when the comfort, peace, and faith found in home no longer resonate; and the cramped homes of a struggling and restless population differ only from the tents of nomads by their poorer ventilation and less fortunate choice of location; by their loss of freedom without the reward of rest, and of stability without the luxury of change.

IV. This is no slight, no consequenceless evil: it is ominous, infectious, and fecund of other fault and misfortune. When men do not love their hearths, nor reverence their thresholds, it is a sign that they have dishonored both, and that they have never acknowledged the true universality of that Christian worship which was indeed to supersede the idolatry, but not the piety, of the pagan. Our God is a household God, as well as a heavenly one; He has an altar in every man's dwelling; let men look to it when they rend it lightly and pour out its ashes. It is not a question of mere ocular delight, it is no question of intellectual pride, or of cultivated and critical fancy, how, and with what aspect of durability[Pg 172] and of completeness, the domestic buildings of a nation shall be raised. It is one of those moral duties, not with more impunity to be neglected because the perception of them depends on a finely toned and balanced conscientiousness, to build our dwellings with care, and patience, and fondness, and diligent completion, and with a view to their duration at least for such a period as, in the ordinary course of national revolutions, might be supposed likely to extend to the entire alteration of the direction of local interests. This at the least; but it would be better if, in every possible instance, men built their own houses on a scale commensurate rather with their condition at the commencement, than their attainments at the termination, of their worldly career; and built them to stand as long as human work at its strongest can be hoped to stand; recording to their children what they have been, and from what, if so it had been permitted them, they had risen. And when houses are thus built, we may have that true domestic architecture, the beginning of all other, which does not disdain to treat with respect and thoughtfulness the small habitation as well as the large, and which invests with the dignity of contented manhood the narrowness of worldly circumstance.

IV. This isn't a minor issue or an insignificant evil: it’s troubling, contagious, and can lead to more faults and misfortunes. When people don’t cherish their homes or respect their doorways, it shows that they’ve disrespected both and that they’ve never recognized the true inclusiveness of that Christian worship meant to replace idolatry, but not the devotion of pagans. Our God is both a household God and a heavenly one; He has an altar in every home; people should remember this when they carelessly damage it and scatter its ashes. It’s not just about visual appeal; it’s not a matter of intellectual pride or sophisticated taste, regarding how and with what durability and completeness a nation’s homes should be built. It’s a moral duty that cannot be neglected, regardless of how finely tuned one’s conscience may be, to construct our homes with care, patience, love, and thoroughness, aiming for them to last at least as long as typical national changes might suggest. This is the least we can do; however, it would be better if, whenever possible, people built their homes based on their circumstances at the start rather than their achievements at the end of their lives. They should aim to make them last as long as human effort can hope to endure, showing their children what they once were and revealing what they might have achieved if given the chance. And when homes are built this way, we can achieve true domestic architecture, the foundation of everything else, which doesn’t overlook the importance of small homes as well as large ones, and which gives the dignity of contented maturity to the simplicity of life's circumstances.

V. I look to this spirit of honorable, proud, peaceful self-possession, this abiding wisdom of contented life, as probably one of the chief sources of great intellectual power in all ages, and beyond dispute as the very primal source of the great architecture of old Italy and France. To this day, the interest of their fairest cities depends, not on the isolated richness of palaces, but on the cherished and exquisite decoration of even the smallest tenements of their proud periods. The most elaborate piece of architecture in Venice is a small house at the head of the Grand Canal, consisting of a ground floor with two stories above, three windows in the first, and two in the second. Many of the most exquisite buildings are on the narrower canals, and of no larger dimensions. One of the most interesting pieces of fifteenth century architecture in North Italy, is a small house in a back street, behind the market-place of Vicenza; it bears date 1481, and the motto,[Pg 173] Il. n'est. rose. sans. épine; it has also only a ground floor and two stories, with three windows in each, separated by rich flower-work, and with balconies, supported, the central one by an eagle with open wings, the lateral ones by winged griffins standing on cornucopiæ. The idea that a house must be large in order to be well built, is altogether of modern growth, and is parallel with the idea, that no picture can be historical, except of a size admitting figures larger than life.

V. I admire this spirit of honorable, proud, peaceful self-possession and the lasting wisdom of a contented life as likely one of the main sources of great intellectual power throughout history, and undoubtedly the fundamental source of the magnificent architecture of old Italy and France. Even today, the charm of their most beautiful cities relies not on the isolated opulence of palaces but on the cherished and exquisite details of even the smallest homes from their proud eras. The most elaborate piece of architecture in Venice is a small house at the head of the Grand Canal, which has a ground floor and two stories above it, with three windows on the first floor and two on the second. Many of the most stunning buildings are located along the narrower canals and are no larger. One of the most intriguing examples of fifteenth-century architecture in Northern Italy is a small house in a back street behind the market square of Vicenza; it dates back to 1481 and has the motto,[Pg 173] Il. n'est. rose. sans. épine; it also consists of just a ground floor and two stories, featuring three windows on each level, separated by rich floral designs, and with balconies supported—the central one by an eagle with open wings, and the side ones by winged griffins standing on cornucopias. The notion that a house must be large to be well-built is a modern idea, and it parallels the belief that no painting can be historical unless it depicts figures larger than life.

VI. I would have, then, our ordinary dwelling-houses built to last, and built to be lovely; as rich and full of pleasantness as may be, within and without; with what degree of likeness to each other in style and manner, I will say presently, under another head; but, at all events, with such differences as might suit and express each man's character and occupation, and partly his history. This right over the house, I conceive, belongs to its first builder, and is to be respected by his children; and it would be well that blank stones should be left in places, to be inscribed with a summary of his life and of its experience, raising thus the habitation into a kind of monument, and developing, into more systematic instructiveness, that good custom which was of old universal, and which still remains among some of the Swiss and Germans, of acknowledging the grace of God's permission to build and possess a quiet resting-place, in such sweet words as may well close our speaking of these things. I have taken them from the front of a cottage lately built among the green pastures which descend from the village of Grindelwald to the lower glacier:—

VI. I would have our regular homes built to last and designed to be beautiful; as rich and pleasant as possible, both inside and out; with a certain degree of similarity in style and appearance, which I will discuss later. However, there should be enough differences to reflect each person's character, occupation, and partly their history. I believe the rights over a house belong to its original builder and should be respected by their descendants. It would be a good idea to leave blank stones in certain spots, to be engraved with a summary of the builder's life and experiences, turning the home into a kind of monument that promotes a more systematic way of learning. This practice was once common and still exists among some Swiss and Germans, where they acknowledge the blessing of being allowed to build and own a peaceful dwelling with meaningful words that may nicely conclude our discussion on these matters. I have taken these words from the front of a cottage recently built among the green pastures that slope down from the village of Grindelwald to the lower glacier:—

"Mit herzlichem Vertrauen
Hat Johannes Mooter und Maria Rubi
Dieses Haus bauen lassen.
Der liebe Gott woll uns bewahren
Vor allem Unglück und Gefahren,
Und es in Segen lassen stehn
Auf der Reise durch diese Jammerzeit
Nach dem himmlischen Paradiese,
Wo alle Frommen wohnen,
Da wird Gott sie belohnen
Mit der Friedenskrone
Zu alle Ewigkeit."

"With heartfelt trust
Johannes Mooter and Maria Rubi
Had this house built.
May God keep us safe
From all misfortune and danger,
And may it stand as a blessing
On the journey through this troubled time
To the heavenly paradise,
Where all the faithful dwell,
There God will reward them
With the crown of peace
For forever.

VII. In public buildings the historical purpose should be still more definite. It is one of the advantages of Gothic architecture,—I use the word Gothic in the most extended sense as broadly opposed to classical,—that it admits of a richness of record altogether unlimited. Its minute and multitudinous sculptural decorations afford means of expressing, either symbolically or literally, all that need be known of national feeling or achievement. More decoration will, indeed, be usually required than can take so elevated a character; and much, even in the most thoughtful periods, has been left to the freedom of fancy, or suffered to consist of mere repetitions of some national bearing or symbol. It is, however, generally unwise, even in mere surface ornament, to surrender the power and privilege of variety which the spirit of Gothic architecture admits; much more in important features—capitals of columns or bosses, and string-courses, as of course in all confessed bas-reliefs. Better the rudest work that tells a story or records a fact, than the richest without meaning. There should not be a single ornament put upon great civic buildings, without some intellectual intention. Actual representation of history has in modern times been checked by a difficulty, mean indeed, but steadfast: that of unmanageable costume; nevertheless, by a sufficiently bold imaginative treatment, and frank use of symbols, all such obstacles may be vanquished; not perhaps in the degree necessary to produce sculpture in itself satisfactory, but at all events so as to enable it to become a grand and expressive element of architectural composition. Take, for example, the management of the capitals of the ducal palace at Venice. History, as such, was indeed entrusted to the painters of its interior, but every capital of its arcades was filled with meaning. The large one, the corner stone of the whole, next the entrance, was devoted to the symbolisation of Abstract Justice; above it is a sculpture of the Judgment of Solomon, remarkable for a beautiful subjection in its treatment to its decorative purpose. The figures, if the subject had been entirely composed of them, would have awkwardly interrupted the line of the angle, and diminished its apparent strength; and therefore in the midst of them, entirely without[Pg 175] relation to them, and indeed actually between the executioner and interceding mother, there rises the ribbed trunk of a massy tree, which supports and continues the shaft of the angle, and whose leaves above overshadow and enrich the whole. The capital below bears among its leafage a throned figure of Justice, Trajan doing justice to the widow, Aristotle "che die legge," and one or two other subjects now unintelligible from decay. The capitals next in order represent the virtues and vices in succession, as preservative or destructive of national peace and power, concluding with Faith, with the inscription "Fides optima in Deo est." A figure is seen on the opposite side of the capital, worshipping the sun. After these, one or two capitals are fancifully decorated with birds (Plate V.), and then come a series representing, first the various fruits, then the national costumes, and then the animals of the various countries subject to Venetian rule.

VII. In public buildings, the historical purpose should be even clearer. One of the advantages of Gothic architecture—I'm using the term Gothic in the broadest sense, contrasting it with classical—is that it allows for an unlimited richness of representation. Its intricate and abundant sculptural decorations provide ways to express, either symbolically or literally, everything that needs to be known about national sentiment or achievement. Generally, more decoration will be required than can maintain such a high character, and much of it, even in the most thoughtful times, has been left to the freedom of creativity or has become mere repetition of some national emblem or symbol. However, it is usually unwise, even in simple surface decoration, to give up the power and privilege of variety that the spirit of Gothic architecture allows; this is even more crucial in important features—like column capitals, bosses, and string courses, as well as in all prominent bas-reliefs. It is better to have the simplest work that tells a story or records a fact than the most elaborate without meaning. Not a single ornament should be added to significant civic buildings without some intellectual purpose. The actual representation of history has, in modern times, faced a persistent yet trivial challenge: the issue of unmanageable costumes; however, with a bold imaginative approach and open use of symbols, these hurdles can be overcome. This may not achieve the level needed for truly satisfying sculpture, but it can still make it a grand and expressive part of architectural design. For instance, look at the capitals of the ducal palace in Venice. While history, in the traditional sense, was entrusted to the painters inside, each capital in its arcades was rich in meaning. The large capital, the cornerstone of the whole structure by the entrance, symbolizes Abstract Justice; above it is a sculpture of the Judgment of Solomon, notable for how beautifully it accommodates its decorative purpose. If the figures had been fully composed, they would have awkwardly interrupted the corner’s line and weakened its visual strength. Therefore, amidst them, entirely unrelated to them, and actually located between the executioner and the interceding mother, rises the ribbed trunk of a sturdy tree that supports and extends the angle’s shaft, with its leaves above enhancing the overall composition. The capital below features, among its foliage, a throned figure of Justice, Trajan administering justice to the widow, Aristotle “che die legge,” and one or two other subjects now lost to decay. The next capitals represent virtues and vices in turn, as either protectors or destroyers of national peace and strength, ending with Faith, accompanied by the inscription "Fides optima in Deo est." A figure is seen on the other side of the capital, worshipping the sun. Following these, one or two capitals are whimsically decorated with birds (Plate V.), and then comes a series that first depicts various fruits, followed by national costumes, and finally the animals from the various lands under Venetian rule.

VIII. Now, not to speak of any more important public building, let us imagine our own India House adorned in this way, by historical or symbolical sculpture: massively built in the first place; then chased with bas-reliefs of our Indian battles, and fretted with carvings of Oriental foliage, or inlaid with Oriental stones; and the more important members of its decoration composed of groups of Indian life and landscape, and prominently expressing the phantasms of Hindoo worship in their subjection to the Cross. Would not one such work be better than a thousand histories? If, however, we have not the invention necessary for such efforts, or if, which is probably one of the most noble excuses we can offer for our deficiency in such matters, we have less pleasure in talking about ourselves, even in marble, than the Continental nations, at least we have no excuse for any want of care in the points which insure the building's endurance. And as this question is one of great interest in its relations to the choice of various modes of decoration, it will be necessary to enter into it at some length.

VIII. Now, putting aside any other important public building, let’s picture our own India House decorated this way, with historical or symbolic sculptures: solidly constructed at first; then embellished with bas-reliefs of our Indian battles, detailed with carvings of Eastern foliage, or inlaid with Eastern stones; and the main features of its decoration featuring groups of Indian life and landscapes, clearly reflecting the visions of Hindu worship in relation to the Cross. Wouldn't one piece like this be worth more than a thousand histories? However, if we lack the creativity needed for such works, or if, perhaps one of the noblest excuses for our shortcomings in this area is that we enjoy talking about ourselves less, even in marble, than the Continental nations do, at least we have no excuse for neglecting the aspects that ensure the building's longevity. And since this issue is very relevant to the choice of different decoration styles, we need to discuss it in detail.

IX. The benevolent regards and purposes of men in masses seldom can be supposed to extend beyond their own generation. They may look to posterity as an audience, may hope for its attention, and labor for its praise: they may trust to[Pg 176] its recognition of unacknowledged merit, and demand its justice for contemporary wrong. But all this is mere selfishness, and does not involve the slightest regard to, or consideration of, the interest of those by whose numbers we would fain swell the circle of our flatterers, and by whose authority we would gladly support our presently disputed claims. The idea of self-denial for the sake of posterity, of practising present economy for the sake of debtors yet unborn, of planting forests that our descendants may live under their shade, or of raising cities for future nations to inhabit, never, I suppose, efficiently takes place among publicly recognised motives of exertion. Yet these are not the less our duties; nor is our part fitly sustained upon the earth, unless the range of our intended and deliberate usefulness include not only the companions, but the successors, of our pilgrimage. God has lent us the earth for our life; it is a great entail. It belongs as much to those who are to come after us, and whose names are already written in the book of creation, as to us; and we have no right, by anything that we do or neglect, to involve them in unnecessary penalties, or deprive them of benefits which it was in our power to bequeath. And this the more, because it is one of the appointed conditions of the labor of men that, in proportion to the time between the seed-sowing and the harvest, is the fulness of the fruit; and that generally, therefore, the farther off we place our aim, and the less we desire to be ourselves the witnesses of what we have labored for, the more wide and rich will be the measure of our success. Men cannot benefit those that are with them as they can benefit those who come after them; and of all the pulpits from which human voice is ever sent forth, there is none from which it reaches so far as from the grave.

IX. The kind intentions and goals of people in groups rarely extend beyond their own generation. They might see future generations as an audience, hoping for their attention and working for their praise. They might trust that future generations will recognize unacknowledged talent and demand justice for the wrongs of today. But all this is just selfishness and shows no real concern for the interests of those whose numbers we would like to increase in our group of admirers, and whose support we would like for our current disputed claims. The idea of sacrificing for the sake of future generations, of being frugal now to benefit those yet to be born, of planting trees so our descendants can enjoy their shade, or building cities for future nations to inhabit, never really plays a significant role in the public motivations for effort. However, these remain our responsibilities; we do not properly fulfill our role on this earth unless our planned usefulness includes not only our contemporaries but also those who will follow us. God has given us the earth for our lifetime; it's a long-term inheritance. It belongs equally to those who will come after us and whose names are already determined in the creation plan, just as much as it does to us. We have no right, by anything we do or fail to do, to cause them unnecessary suffering or deny them benefits we could have left behind. This is even more critical because one of the conditions of human labor is that the time between planting and harvesting affects the abundance of the yield; generally, the further we set our goals and the less we want to witness the results of our labor ourselves, the greater and richer our success is likely to be. People can't benefit those currently alive in the same way they can benefit those who will come after. Of all the sources from which human voices are ever heard, none carries further than from the grave.

X. Nor is there, indeed, any present loss, in such respect, for futurity. Every human action gains in honor, in grace, in all true magnificence, by its regard to things that are to come. It is the far sight, the quiet and confident patience, that, above all other attributes, separate man from man, and near him to his Maker; and there is no action nor art, whose majesty we may not measure by this test. Therefore, when we build, let[Pg 177] us think that we build for ever. Let it not be for present delight, nor for present use alone; let it be such work as our descendants will thank us for, and let us think, as we lay stone on stone, that a time is to come when those stones will be held sacred because our hands have touched them, and that men will say as they look upon the labor and wrought substance of them, "See! this our fathers did for us." For, indeed, the greatest glory of a building is not in its stones, or in its gold. Its glory is in its Age, and in that deep sense of voicefulness, of stern watching, of mysterious sympathy, nay, even of approval or condemnation, which we feel in walls that have long been washed by the passing waves of humanity. It is in their lasting witness against men, in their quiet contrast with the transitional character of all things, in the strength which, through the lapse of seasons and times, and the decline and birth of dynasties, and the changing of the face of the earth, and of the limits of the sea, maintains its sculptured shapeliness for a time insuperable, connects forgotten and following ages with each other, and half constitutes the identity, as it concentrates the sympathy, of nations; it is in that golden stain of time, that we are to look for the real light, and color, and preciousness of architecture; and it is not until a building has assumed this character, till it has been entrusted with the fame, and hallowed by the deeds of men, till its walls have been witnesses of suffering, and its pillars rise out of the shadows of death, that its existence, more lasting as it is than that of the natural objects of the world around it, can be gifted with even so much as these possess of language and of life.

X. There’s no current loss in thinking about the future. Every human action gains honor, grace, and true magnificence by considering what’s to come. It’s the foresight, the calm and confident patience, that sets one person apart from another and brings him closer to his Creator; and there’s no act or craft whose greatness we can’t measure by this standard. So when we build, let us remember we’re building for the long term. It shouldn’t just be for immediate pleasure or use; it should be work our descendants will appreciate, and we should think, as we stack stone upon stone, that someday those stones will be cherished because we touched them, and people will say as they gaze at our handiwork, "Look! This is what our ancestors created for us." Because, truly, the greatest glory of a building isn’t in its stones or its gold. Its glory lies in its age and in that deep sense of presence, of steadfast observation, of mysterious connection, even of approval or disapproval, that we feel in walls that have long endured the tides of humanity. It’s in their enduring testimony against people, in their quiet contrast to the ever-changing nature of everything, in the strength that, through the passage of seasons and times, through the rise and fall of dynasties, and through changes in the landscape and coastlines, maintains its sculpted beauty over time, linking forgotten and future generations while shaping the identity and empathy of nations; it’s in that golden mark of time that we should seek the true light, color, and value of architecture; and it’s not until a building has taken on this character, until it has been infused with fame and sanctified by human actions, until its walls have borne witness to suffering, and its pillars rise from the gloom of death, that its existence, more enduring than the natural objects around it, can be endowed even with the semblance of language and life.

XI. For that period, then, we must build; not, indeed, refusing to ourselves the delight of present completion, nor hesitating to follow such portions of character as may depend upon delicacy of execution to the highest perfection of which they are capable, even although we may know that in the course of years such details must perish; but taking care that for work of this kind we sacrifice no enduring quality, and that the building shall not depend for its impressiveness upon anything that is perishable. This would, indeed, be the law of good composition under any circumstances, the arrange[Pg 178]ment of the larger masses being always a matter of greater importance than the treatment of the smaller; but in architecture there is much in that very treatment which is skilful or otherwise in proportion to its just regard to the probable effects of time: and (which is still more to be considered) there is a beauty in those effects themselves, which nothing else can replace, and which it is our wisdom to consult and to desire. For though, hitherto, we have been speaking of the sentiment of age only, there is an actual beauty in the marks of it, such and so great as to have become not unfrequently the subject of especial choice among certain schools of art, and to have impressed upon those schools the character usually and loosely expressed by the term "picturesque." It is of some importance to our present purpose to determine the true meaning of this expression, as it is now generally used; for there is a principle to be developed from that use which, while it has occultly been the ground of much that is true and just in our judgment of art, has never been so far understood as to become definitely serviceable. Probably no word in the language (exclusive of theological expressions), has been the subject of so frequent or so prolonged dispute; yet none remained more vague in their acceptance, and it seems to me to be a matter of no small interest to investigate the essence of that idea which all feel, and (to appearance) with respect to similar things, and yet which every attempt to define has, as I believe, ended either in mere enumeration of the effects and objects to which the term has been attached, or else in attempts at abstraction more palpably nugatory than any which have disgraced metaphysical investigation on other subjects. A recent critic on Art, for instance, has gravely advanced the theory that the essence of the picturesque consists in the expression of "universal decay." It would be curious to see the result of an attempt to illustrate this idea of the picturesque, in a painting of dead flowers and decayed fruit, and equally curious to trace the steps of any reasoning which, on such a theory, should account for the picturesqueness of an ass colt as opposed to a horse foal. But there is much excuse for even the most utter failure in rea[Pg 179]sonings of this kind, since the subject is, indeed, one of the most obscure of all that may legitimately be submitted to human reason; and the idea is itself so varied in the minds of different men, according to their subjects of study, that no definition can be expected to embrace more than a certain number of its infinitely multiplied forms.

XI. In that time, we need to build; not to deny ourselves the joy of finishing something now, nor to hesitate to pursue aspects of character that depend on achieving the highest quality, even if we know that, over the years, those details will fade away; rather, we must ensure that for this type of work we don’t sacrifice any lasting quality, and that the building's impact doesn’t rely on anything that won’t last. This, indeed, is the guiding principle of good design in any situation, where the arrangement of larger elements is always more important than the treatment of smaller ones; but in architecture, that very treatment is skilled or not based on its awareness of how time will affect it: and (which is even more significant) there is a beauty in those effects that nothing else can replace, and it's wise for us to acknowledge and appreciate it. For although we’ve mainly talked about the feeling of age, there is an actual beauty in the signs of age, so notable that it has often become a deliberate choice among certain art schools, giving these schools a style often described as "picturesque." It’s important for our current focus to clarify what this term truly means as it’s commonly used; there’s a principle to form from that usage which, while it has subtly been the basis for much that is true and fair in our perception of art, has never been fully understood to be practically useful. Probably no other word (except for some theological terms) has been debated so often and so extensively; yet none remains as vague in understanding. It seems quite interesting to explore the essence of this idea that everyone feels, seemingly in relation to similar things, yet every attempt to define it has, in my view, ended either in merely listing the effects and objects tied to the term or in efforts at abstraction that are even more futile than those seen in philosophical debates on other topics. A recent art critic, for example, has seriously proposed that the core of the picturesque lies in expressing "universal decay." It would be intriguing to see what a painting of dead flowers and rotting fruit would illustrate this idea of the picturesque and equally interesting to track the reasoning behind why, under such a theory, a donkey foal would be considered more picturesque than a horse foal. But there’s much justification for even those who utterly fail in reasoning like this, since the subject is one of the most complicated topics that can be rightly posed to human reason; and the idea itself varies in the minds of different people, based on what they study, so no definition can be expected to encompass more than a limited number of its endlessly diverse forms.

XII. That peculiar character, however, which separates the picturesque from the characters of subject belonging to the higher walks of art (and this is all that is necessary for our present purpose to define), may be shortly and decisively expressed. Picturesqueness, in this sense, is Parasitical Sublimity. Of course all sublimity, as well as all beauty, is, in the simple etymological sense, picturesque, that is to say, fit to become the subject of a picture; and all sublimity is, even in the peculiar sense which I am endeavoring to develope, picturesque, as opposed to beauty; that is to say, there is more picturesqueness in the subject of Michael Angelo than of Perugino, in proportion to the prevalence of the sublime element over the beautiful. But that character, of which the extreme pursuit is generally admitted to be degrading to art, is parasitical sublimity; i.e., a sublimity dependent on the accidents, or on the least essential characters, of the objects to which it belongs; and the picturesque is developed distinctively exactly in proportion to the distance from the centre of thought of those points of character in which the sublimity is found. Two ideas, therefore, are essential to picturesqueness,—the first, that of sublimity (for pure beauty is not picturesque at all, and becomes so only as the sublime element mixes with it), and the second, the subordinate or parasitical position of that sublimity. Of course, therefore, whatever characters of line or shade or expression are productive of sublimity, will become productive of picturesqueness; what these characters are I shall endeavor hereafter to show at length; but, among those which are generally acknowledged, I may name angular and broken lines, vigorous oppositions of light and shadow, and grave, deep, or boldly contrasted color; and all these are in a still higher degree effective, when, by resemblance or association, they remind us of objects on which a true and essential sub[Pg 180]limity exists, as of rocks or mountains, or stormy clouds or waves. Now if these characters, or any others of a higher and more abstract sublimity, be found in the very heart and substance of what we contemplate, as the sublimity of Michael Angelo depends on the expression of mental character in his figures far more than even on the noble lines of their arrangement, the art which represents such characters cannot be properly called picturesque: but, if they be found in the accidental or external qualities, the distinctive picturesque will be the result.

XII. However, the unique quality that distinguishes the picturesque from the subjects characteristic of the higher forms of art (which is all we need to define for our current discussion) can be succinctly and clearly articulated. Picturesqueness, in this context, is Parasitical Sublimity. Naturally, all sublimity and all beauty, in the straightforward etymological sense, are picturesque; that is to say, they are suitable to be the subject of a picture. Furthermore, all sublimity is, even in the specific sense I’m trying to explain, picturesque as opposed to beauty; meaning that there is more picturesqueness in Michelangelo's subjects than in Perugino's, in relation to the dominance of the sublime over the beautiful. However, the characteristic that is widely acknowledged as detrimental to art when pursued too intensely is parasitical sublimity; i.e., sublimity that depends on the incidental or less essential qualities of the objects it pertains to; and the picturesque is distinctively developed exactly in proportion to the distance from the center of thought of those character traits where the sublimity is located. Therefore, two concepts are crucial to understanding picturesqueness: the first is the concept of sublimity (since pure beauty is not picturesque at all, and only becomes so when the sublime elements are combined with it), and the second is the subordinate or parasitical nature of that sublimity. Consequently, any characteristics of line, shade, or expression that produce sublimity will also generate picturesqueness. I will attempt to elaborate on what these characteristics are later; among those generally recognized are angular and broken lines, strong contrasts of light and shadow, and deep or boldly contrasting colors; all of which are even more effective when, by resemblance or association, they remind us of objects that possess true and essential sublimity, such as rocks, mountains, stormy clouds, or waves. Now, if these characteristics, or any others that exhibit a higher and more abstract sublimity, are found at the very core and essence of what we observe—like the sublime nature of Michelangelo’s work which relies more on the mental character expressed in his figures than on their noble arrangement—then the art that depicts such characters cannot accurately be labeled as picturesque. However, if they are present in the accidental or external qualities, the distinctive picturesque will emerge as a result.

XIII. Thus, in the treatment of the features of the human face by Francia or Angelico, the shadows are employed only to make the contours of the features thoroughly felt; and to those features themselves the mind of the observer is exclusively directed (that is to say, to the essential characters of the thing represented). All power and all sublimity rest on these; the shadows are used only for the sake of the features. On the contrary, by Rembrandt, Salvator, or Caravaggio, the features are used for the sake of the shadows; and the attention is directed, and the power of the painter addressed to characters of accidental light and shade cast across or around those features. In the case of Rembrandt there is often an essential sublimity in invention and expression besides, and always a high degree of it in the light and shade itself; but it is for the most part parasitical or engrafted sublimity as regards the subject of the painting, and, just so far, picturesque.

XIII. In the depiction of human facial features by Francia or Angelico, shadows are used solely to enhance the contours of the features, drawing the observer's focus directly to those features themselves (that is, to the essential qualities of what is being represented). All power and grandeur rest on these; shadows are merely there to support the features. In contrast, with Rembrandt, Salvator, or Caravaggio, the features serve to highlight the shadows; the attention is directed, and the power of the artist is focused on the elements of varying light and darkness that play across or around those features. In Rembrandt's work, there is often an inherent grandeur in both invention and expression, and always a high level of it in the handling of light and shade itself; however, this grandeur is mostly secondary or added to the main subject of the painting, and thus, to some extent, picturesque.

XIV. Again, in the management of the sculptures of the Parthenon, shadow is frequently employed as a dark field on which the forms are drawn. This is visibly the case in the metopes, and must have been nearly as much so in the pediment. But the use of that shadow is entirely to show the confines of the figures; and it is to their lines, and not to the shapes of the shadows behind them, that the art and the eye are addressed. The figures themselves are conceived as much as possible in full light, aided by bright reflections; they are drawn exactly as, on vases, white figures on a dark ground: and the sculptors have dispensed with, or even struggled to[Pg 181] avoid, all shadows which were not absolutely necessary to the explaining of the form. On the contrary, in Gothic sculpture, the shadow becomes itself a subject of thought. It is considered as a dark color, to be arranged in certain agreeable masses; the figures are very frequently made even subordinate to the placing of its divisions: and their costume is enriched at the expense of the forms underneath, in order to increase the complexity and variety of the points of shade. There are thus, both in sculpture and painting, two, in some sort, opposite schools, of which the one follows for its subject the essential forms of things, and the other the accidental lights and shades upon them. There are various degrees of their contrariety: middle steps, as in the works of Correggio, and all degrees of nobility and of degradation in the several manners: but the one is always recognised as the pure, and the other as the picturesque school. Portions of picturesque treatment will be found in Greek work, and of pure and unpicturesque in Gothic; and in both there are countless instances, as pre-eminently in the works of Michael Angelo, in which shadows become valuable as media of expression, and therefore take rank among essential characteristics. Into these multitudinous distinctions and exceptions I cannot now enter, desiring only to prove the broad applicability of the general definition.

XIV. Once again, when managing the sculptures of the Parthenon, shadow is often used as a dark backdrop on which the forms stand out. This is clearly seen in the metopes and was probably quite similar in the pediment. However, the purpose of that shadow is solely to define the edges of the figures; it is their outlines, not the shapes of the shadows behind them, that engage the art and the viewer. The figures themselves are designed to be as illuminated as possible, enhanced by bright reflections; they are depicted just like white figures on a dark background, as seen on vases: and the sculptors intentionally avoided, or even strived to steer clear of, any shadows that weren’t absolutely necessary to clarify the shape. In contrast, in Gothic sculpture, shadow itself becomes a focal point. It is viewed as a dark color, arranged in certain pleasing groupings; the figures are often rendered to complement the arrangement of shadows, and their costumes are embellished at the cost of the underlying forms to enhance the complexity and variety of shaded areas. Thus, in both sculpture and painting, there exist two somewhat opposing schools: one that focuses on the essential forms of objects and the other on the incidental light and shade upon them. There are various degrees of opposition: intermediate steps, like in the works of Correggio, and all sorts of nuances of nobility and decline in different styles: but one is always recognized as the pure school, while the other is seen as the picturesque school. Elements of picturesque treatment can be found in Greek work, and pure, non-picturesque elements in Gothic; and in both, there are countless examples, especially in the works of Michelangelo, where shadows become important means of expression, and thus rank among the essential characteristics. I cannot go into all these numerous distinctions and exceptions right now; I just want to demonstrate the broad applicability of the general definition.

XV. Again, the distinction will be found to exist, not only between forms and shades as subjects of choice, but between essential and inessential forms. One of the chief distinctions between the dramatic and picturesque schools of sculpture is found in the treatment of the hair. By the artists of the time of Pericles it was considered as an excrescence,16 indicated by few and rude lines, and subordinated in every particular to the principality of the features and person. How completely this was an artistical, not a national idea, it is unnecessary to prove. We need but remember the employment of the Lacedæmonians, reported by the Persian spy on the evening before the battle of Thermopylæ, or glance at any Homeric description of ideal form, to see how purely sculpturesque was the law which reduced the markings of the hair, lest, under the necessary disadvantages of material, they should interfere[Pg 182] with the distinctness of the personal forms. On the contrary, in later sculpture, the hair receives almost the principal care of the workman; and while the features and limbs are clumsily and bluntly executed, the hair is curled and twisted, cut into bold and shadowy projections, and arranged in masses elaborately ornamental: there is true sublimity in the lines and the chiaroscuro of these masses, but it is, as regards the creature represented, parasitical, and therefore picturesque. In the same sense we may understand the application of the term to modern animal painting, distinguished as it has been by peculiar attention to the colors, lustre, and texture of skin; nor is it in art alone that the definition will hold. In animals themselves, when their sublimity depends upon their muscular forms or motions, or necessary and principal attributes, as perhaps more than all others in the horse, we do not call them picturesque, but consider them as peculiarly fit to be associated with pure historical subject. Exactly in proportion as their character of sublimity passes into excrescences;—into mane and beard as in the lion, into horns as in the stag, into shaggy hide as in the instance above given of the ass colt, into variegation as in the zebra, or into plumage,—they become picturesque, and are so in art exactly in proportion to the prominence of these excrescential characters. It may often be most expedient that they should be prominent; often there is in them the highest degree of majesty, as in those of the leopard and boar; and in the hands of men like Tintoret and Rubens, such attributes become means of deepening the very highest and most ideal impressions. But the picturesque direction of their thoughts is always distinctly recognizable, as clinging to the surface, to the less essential character, and as developing out of this a sublimity different from that of the creature itself; a sublimity which is, in a sort, common to all the objects of creation, and the same in its constituent elements, whether it be sought in the clefts and folds of shaggy hair, or in the chasms and rents of rocks, or in the hanging of thickets or hill sides, or in the alternations of gaiety and gloom in the variegation of the shell, the plume, or the cloud.[Pg 183]

XV. Once again, we see a distinction that exists not only between forms and shades as choices but also between essential and non-essential forms. One of the main differences between the dramatic and picturesque schools of sculpture is in how they treat hair. In the time of Pericles, artists viewed it as an extra detail, indicated by just a few rough lines, and it was kept subordinate to the main features and body. It's clear that this was an artistic idea rather than a national one. We just have to think about the Spartans, as reported by the Persian spy on the night before the battle of Thermopylae, or look at any description from Homer that highlights ideal forms, to understand how sculpturesque this approach was; it aimed to minimize hair details so they wouldn't distract from the clarity of the personal forms due to the limitations of the material. In contrast, later sculpture gives almost primary attention to hair; while the features and limbs are often done clumsily, the hair is curled and twisted, sharply projected, and arranged into elaborate decorative masses. There’s true sublimity in the lines and shading of these masses, but in terms of the creature being depicted, it is secondary and hence picturesque. Similarly, we can see how modern animal painting focuses on the colors, sheen, and texture of fur or skin; this definition applies not just in art. When it comes to animals, if their grandeur comes from their muscular forms or movements—especially in horses—we don’t refer to them as picturesque but rather as particularly suited for pure historical representations. The more their grandeur relies on extra features—like a lion's mane and beard, a stag's horns, the shaggy hide of a donkey colt, the stripes on a zebra, or plumage—the more they become picturesque, which is evident in art based on how pronounced those extra features are. There are times when it makes sense for these features to stand out, and they can convey a high degree of majesty, as seen in leopards and boars; in the hands of artists like Tintoretto and Rubens, these features can enhance very profound and ideal impressions. However, their picturesque approach is always clearly visible, focusing on the surface and less essential qualities, creating a type of sublimity that is somewhat universal among all creation and similar in its basic elements, whether it's found in the crevices of shaggy hair, the cracks and gaps in rocks, the thick growth of bushes or hillsides, or the contrasts of brightness and darkness in the patterns of shells, feathers, or clouds.[Pg 182]

XVI. Now, to return to our immediate subject, it so happens that, in architecture, the superinduced and accidental beauty is most commonly inconsistent with the preservation of original character, and the picturesque is therefore sought in ruin, and supposed to consist in decay. Whereas, even when so sought, it consists in the mere sublimity of the rents, or fractures, or stains, or vegetation, which assimilate the architecture with the work of Nature, and bestow upon it those circumstances of color and form which are universally beloved by the eye of man. So far as this is done, to the extinction of the true characters of the architecture, it is picturesque, and the artist who looks to the stem of the ivy instead of the shaft of the pillar, is carrying out in more daring freedom the debased sculptor's choice of the hair instead of the countenance. But so far as it can be rendered consistent with the inherent character, the picturesque or extraneous sublimity of architecture has just this of nobler function in it than that of any other object whatsoever, that it is an exponent of age, of that in which, as has been said, the greatest glory of a building consists; and, therefore, the external signs of this glory, having power and purpose greater than any belonging to their mere sensible beauty, may be considered as taking rank among pure and essential character; so essential to my mind, that I think a building cannot be considered as in its prime until four or five centuries have passed over it; and that the entire choice and arrangement of its details should have reference to their appearance after that period, so that none should be admitted which would suffer material injury either by the weather-staining, or the mechanical degradation which the lapse of such a period would necessitate.

XVI. Now, back to our main topic: in architecture, added and accidental beauty often doesn’t align with maintaining the original character, leading us to think that picturesque beauty comes from ruin and decay. However, even when we look for it in such a way, it’s really about the impressive qualities of cracks, stains, or overgrown vegetation that connect architecture with Nature, giving it colors and shapes that people universally appreciate. When this happens and it overshadows the true architectural features, it becomes picturesque, and an artist focusing on the ivy instead of the pillar is, in a bolder way, making the same misguided choice as a sculptor who prioritizes hair over the face. But when the picturesque or external grandeur of architecture can still align with its inherent character, it has a nobler role than any other object, as it represents age, which is, as mentioned, where a building’s true glory lies. Therefore, the visible signs of this glory, having significance and purpose beyond their mere aesthetic appeal, should be recognized as part of its essential character. I believe a building can’t be seen as truly at its prime until it has aged for four or five centuries, and all choices regarding its details should consider how they will look after that time, ensuring none will suffer significant damage from weathering or natural wear over such a long period.

XVII. It is not my purpose to enter into any of the questions which the application of this principle involves. They are of too great interest and complexity to be even touched upon within my present limits, but this is broadly to be noticed, that those styles of architecture which are picturesque in the sense above explained with respect to sculpture, that is to say, whose decoration depends on the arrangement of[Pg 184] points of shade rather than on purity of outline, do not suffer, but commonly gain in richness of effect when their details are partly worn away; hence such styles, pre-eminently that of French Gothic, should always be adopted when the materials to be employed are liable to degradation, as brick, sandstone, or soft limestone; and styles in any degree dependent on purity of line, as the Italian Gothic, must be practised altogether in hard and undecomposing materials, granite serpentine, or crystalline marbles. There can be no doubt that the nature of the accessible materials influenced the formation of both styles; and it should still more authoritatively determine our choice of either.

XVII. I'm not going to dive into all the questions that come with applying this principle. They are too interesting and complex to cover fully in this space, but it's important to note that architectural styles that are picturesque in the way I've described for sculpture—meaning their decoration relies on the play of light and shadow rather than clean lines—actually benefit from having some of their details worn away. Therefore, styles like French Gothic should always be used when the materials available are prone to wear, such as brick, sandstone, or soft limestone. In contrast, styles that depend on precise lines, like Italian Gothic, should only be worked in durable materials like granite, serpentine, or solid marbles. It's clear that the availability of materials influenced the development of both styles, and this should definitely guide our choice between them.

XVIII. It does not belong to my present plan to consider at length the second head of duty of which I have above spoken; the preservation of the architecture we possess: but a few words may be forgiven, as especially necessary in modern times. Neither by the public, nor by those who have the care of public monuments, is the true meaning of the word restoration understood. It means the most total destruction which a building can suffer: a destruction out of which no remnants can be gathered; a destruction accompanied with false description of the thing destroyed. Do not let us deceive ourselves in this important matter; it is impossible, as impossible as to raise the dead, to restore anything that has ever been great or beautiful in architecture. That which I have above insisted upon as the life of the whole, that spirit which is given only by the hand and eye of the workman, never can be recalled. Another spirit may be given by another time, and it is then a new building; but the spirit of the dead workman cannot be summoned up, and commanded to direct other hands, and other thoughts. And as for direct and simple copying, it is palpably impossible. What copying can there be of surfaces that have been worn half an inch down? The whole finish of the work was in the half inch that is gone; if you attempt to restore that finish, you do it conjecturally; if you copy what is left, granting fidelity to be possible (and what care, or watchfulness, or cost can secure it?), how is the new work better than the old? There was yet in the old[Pg 185] some life, some mysterious suggestion of what it had been, and of what it had lost; some sweetness in the gentle lines which rain and sun had wrought. There can be none in the brute hardness of the new carving. Look at the animals which I have given in Plate 14, as an instance of living work, and suppose the markings of the scales and hair once worn away, or the wrinkles of the brows, and who shall ever restore them? The first step to restoration (I have seen it, and that again and again, seen it on the Baptistery of Pisa, seen it on the Casa d' Oro at Venice, seen it on the Cathedral of Lisieux), is to dash the old work to pieces; the second is usually to put up the cheapest and basest imitation which can escape detection, but in all cases, however careful, and however labored, an imitation still, a cold model of such parts as can be modelled, with conjectural supplements; and my experience has as yet furnished me with only one instance, that of the Palais de Justice at Rouen, in which even this, the utmost degree of fidelity which is possible, has been attained or even attempted.

XVIII. It's not my current goal to go into detail about the second duty I've mentioned, which is preserving the architecture we have, but a few words might be necessary in today's context. Neither the public nor those responsible for public monuments truly understand the meaning of the word restoration. It actually refers to the most complete destruction a building can endure: a destruction from which no remnants can be salvaged; a destruction that comes with misleading descriptions of what was destroyed. Let’s not kid ourselves about this important issue; it's impossible, as impossible as bringing the dead back to life, to restore anything that has ever been great or beautiful in architecture. The essence that I emphasized earlier as essential to the whole—that spirit brought forth solely by the craftsmanship of the worker—can never be recreated. Another spirit may emerge from a different era, and then it's a new building; but the spirit of the original creator cannot be called back to guide other hands and thoughts. As for direct and simple copying, that's clearly impossible. How can you replicate surfaces that have worn down half an inch? The entire detail of the work was in that half inch that’s gone; if you try to restore that detail, you're doing it based on guesswork. If you copy what’s left, assuming that accuracy is possible (and what effort, vigilance, or expense can guarantee that?), how is the new work any better than the old? The original still held some life, some mysterious hint of what it had been and what it had lost; a certain sweetness in the gentle lines shaped by rain and sun. None of that exists in the rigid toughness of the new carving. Look at the animals I showed in Plate 14 as an example of living craftsmanship; imagine the textures of their scales and fur worn away, or the wrinkles of their brows—who could possibly restore them? The first step to restoration (I've seen this time and again, on the Baptistery of Pisa, on the Casa d'Oro in Venice, and on the Cathedral of Lisieux) is to smash the old work to pieces; the second is typically to replace it with the cheapest and most basic imitation that can go unnoticed. But in every case, no matter how careful or detailed, it’s still just an imitation—a cold model of the parts that can be modeled, with speculative additions. My experience has provided me with only one example, that of the Palais de Justice in Rouen, where even this utmost level of fidelity has been achieved or even attempted.

XIX. Do not let us talk then of restoration. The thing is a Lie from beginning to end. You may make a model of a building as you may of a corpse, and your model may have the shell of the old walls within it as your cast might have the skeleton, with what advantage I neither see nor care; but the old building is destroyed, and that more totally and mercilessly than if it had sunk into a heap of dust, or melted into a mass of clay: more has been gleaned out of desolated Nineveh than ever will be out of re-built Milan. But, it is said, there may come a necessity for restoration! Granted. Look the necessity full in the face, and understand it on its own terms. It is a necessity for destruction. Accept it as such, pull the building down, throw its stones into neglected corners, make ballast of them, or mortar, if you will; but do it honestly, and do not set up a Lie in their place. And look that necessity in the face before it comes, and you may prevent it. The principle of modern times (a principle which I believe, at least in France, to be systematically acted on by the masons, in order to find themselves work, as the abbey of St. Ouen was pulled down by the magistrates of the town by way of giving work to some[Pg 186] vagrants,) is to neglect buildings first, and restore them afterwards. Take proper care of your monuments, and you will not need to restore them. A few sheets of lead put in time upon the roof, a few dead leaves and sticks swept in time out of a water-course, will save both roof and walls from ruin. Watch an old building with an anxious care; guard it as best you may, and at any cost from every influence of dilapidation. Count its stones as you would jewels of a crown; set watches about it as if at the gates of a besieged city; bind it together with iron where it loosens; stay it with timber where it declines; do not care about the unsightliness of the aid; better a crutch than a lost limb; and do this tenderly, and reverently, and continually, and many a generation will still be born and pass away beneath its shadow. Its evil day must come at last; but let it come declaredly and openly, and let no dishonoring and false substitute deprive it of the funeral offices of memory.

XIX. Let’s not talk about restoration. It's a complete Lie from start to finish. You can create a model of a building just like you would of a corpse, and your model might have the old walls inside it just as a cast might have a skeleton, but I don’t see any advantage in that, nor do I care. The old building is gone, destroyed more thoroughly and ruthlessly than if it had crumbled into dust or turned into clay. More has been learned from the ruins of Nineveh than will ever come from rebuilt Milan. But people say there might be a need for restoration! Fine. Look that need straight in the eye and understand it for what it is. It’s a need for destruction. Accept it as such, tear the building down, throw its stones into forgotten corners, use them as ballast or mortar if you want; but do it honestly, and don’t put up a Lie in their place. Face that necessity before it arrives, and you might be able to avoid it. The modern principle (which I believe, at least in France, is systematically followed by the masons to create work for themselves, as the abbey of St. Ouen was torn down by the town magistrates to give work to some[Pg 186] vagrants) is to neglect buildings first, then restore them later. Take good care of your monuments, and you won’t need to restore them. A few sheets of lead put on the roof in time, a few dead leaves and sticks cleared from a watercourse will save both the roof and walls from destruction. Watch an old building with great care; protect it as best you can, at any cost, from decay. Count its stones like they are jewels in a crown; keep watch over it like it’s the gate of a besieged city; reinforce it with iron where it starts to loosen; support it with timber if it starts to lean; don’t worry about how ugly the support looks; better a crutch than a lost limb; and do this tenderly, respectfully, and consistently, and many generations will still be born and pass away under its shadow. Its bad day will eventually arrive, but let it come honestly and openly, and let no dishonorable or false substitute rob it of the respects of memory.

XX. Of more wanton or ignorant ravage it is vain to speak; my words will not reach those who commit them, and yet, be it heard or not, I must not leave the truth unstated, that it is again no question of expediency or feeling whether we shall preserve the buildings of past times or not. We have no right whatever to touch them. They are not ours. They belong partly to those who built them, and partly to all the generations of mankind who are to follow us. The dead have still their right in them: that which they labored for, the praise of achievement or the expression of religious feeling, or whatsoever else it might be which in those buildings they intended to be permanent, we have no right to obliterate. What we have ourselves built, we are at liberty to throw down; but what other men gave their strength, and wealth, and life to accomplish, their right over does not pass away with their death; still less is the right to the use of what they have left vested in us only. It belongs to all their successors. It may hereafter be a subject of sorrow, or a cause of injury, to millions, that we have consulted our present convenience by casting down such buildings as we choose to dispense with. That sorrow, that loss we have no right to inflict. Did the cathedral of Avranches belong to the mob who destroyed it, any[Pg 187] more than it did to us, who walk in sorrow to and fro over its foundation? Neither does any building whatever belong to those mobs who do violence to it. For a mob it is, and must be always; it matters not whether enraged, or in deliberate folly; whether countless, or sitting in committees; the people who destroy anything causelessly are a mob, and Architecture is always destroyed causelessly. A fair building is necessarily worth the ground it stands upon, and will be so until central Africa and America shall have become as populous as Middlesex; nor is any cause whatever valid as a ground for its destruction. If ever valid, certainly not now when the place both of the past and future is too much usurped in our minds by the restless and discontented present. The very quietness of nature is gradually withdrawn from us; thousands who once in their necessarily prolonged travel were subjected to an influence, from the silent sky and slumbering fields, more effectual than known or confessed, now bear with them even there the ceaseless fever of their life; and along the iron veins that traverse the frame of our country, beat and flow the fiery pulses of its exertions, hotter and faster every hour. All vitality is concentrated through those throbbing arteries into the central cities; the country is passed over like a green sea by narrow bridges, and we are thrown back in continually closer crowds upon the city gates. The only influence which can in any wise there take the place of that of the woods and fields, is the power of ancient Architecture. Do not part with it for the sake of the formal square, or of the fenced and planted walk, nor of the goodly street nor opened quay. The pride of a city is not in these. Leave them to the crowd; but remember that there will surely be some within the circuit of the disquieted walls who would ask for some other spots than these wherein to walk; for some other forms to meet their sight familiarly: like him who sat so often where the sun struck from the west, to watch the lines of the dome of Florence drawn on the deep sky, or like those, his Hosts, who could bear daily to behold, from their palace chambers, the places where their fathers lay at rest, at the meeting of the dark streets of Verona.

XX. There's no point in discussing the reckless or ignorant destruction; my words won’t reach those who do this, but I have to say the truth: it’s not about what’s convenient or how we feel when it comes to preserving the buildings from the past. We have no right to touch them. They aren't ours. They belong partly to those who built them and partly to all the generations that will come after us. The dead still have a claim to them; what they worked for—the recognition of their achievements, their religious expressions, or anything else they intended to last—we have no right to erase. We can tear down what we’ve built ourselves, but what others have poured their strength, wealth, and lives into still belongs to them even after they are gone; even less does the right to use what they left belong solely to us. It belongs to all who come after them. It may cause future sorrow or harm to millions if we prioritize our current convenience by demolishing buildings we no longer want. We have no right to cause that grief or loss. Did the cathedral of Avranches belong to the mob that destroyed it any more than it belongs to us, who walk sorrowfully over its ruins? No building belongs to those mobs that vandalize it. A mob it is, and it will always be—whether in a rage or in foolishness, whether acting as a crowd or sitting in committees; the people who destroy anything without reason are a mob, and architecture is always destroyed without reason. A well-built structure is inherently worth the ground it’s on, and that value will remain until central Africa and America become as populated as Middlesex; no justification for its destruction is valid. If there was ever a valid reason, it certainly isn’t now when our minds are overly occupied with the restless and discontented present, overshadowing both the past and the future. Nature’s very calmness is slowly slipping away from us; thousands who once traveled slowly and absorbed the influence of the silent sky and still fields now carry the constant stress of their lives with them, even in those moments. The energetic flows of our efforts pulse hotter and faster through the networks of our country every hour. All vitality is concentrated through those throbbing arteries into the cities; the countryside is merely a green sea crossed by narrow bridges, pushing us closer together at the city gates. The only thing that can take the place of the forests and fields there is the power of ancient architecture. Don’t give it up for the sake of a formal square, or a fenced-in walkway, or a nice street or open quay. A city’s pride isn’t in these things. Leave them to the masses; but remember there will surely be some within the walls of the troubled city who will crave other places to walk; for different forms to greet their eyes: like the one who often sat where the sun set to watch the outlines of the dome of Florence against the deep sky, or like those who, from their palace rooms, could bear to see daily the spots where their ancestors lay at rest, at the junction of the dark streets of Verona.


CHAPTER VII.

THE LAMP OF OBEDIENCE.

I. It has been my endeavor to show in the preceding pages how every form of noble architecture is in some sort the embodiment of the Polity, Life, History, and Religious Faith of nations. Once or twice in doing this, I have named a principle to which I would now assign a definite place among those which direct that embodiment; the last place, not only as that to which its own humility would incline, but rather as belonging to it in the aspect of the crowning grace of all the rest; that principle, I mean, to which Polity owes its stability, Life its happiness, Faith its acceptance, Creation its continuance,—Obedience.

I. In the previous pages, I have tried to show how every type of noble architecture reflects the government, life, history, and religious beliefs of nations. A couple of times while doing this, I mentioned a principle that I now want to clearly define among those that influence this reflection; it deserves the last position, not only because its own modesty would suggest it, but also because it represents the ultimate grace of all the others. This principle is what gives stability to government, happiness to life, acceptance to faith, and endurance to creation—Obedience.

Nor is it the least among the sources of more serious satisfaction which I have found in the pursuit of a subject that at first appeared to bear but slightly on the grave interests of mankind, that the conditions of material perfection which it leads me in conclusion to consider, furnish a strange proof how false is the conception, how frantic the pursuit, of that treacherous phantom which men call Liberty; most treacherous, indeed, of all phantoms; for the feeblest ray of reason might surely show us, that not only its attainment, but its being, was impossible. There is no such thing in the universe. There can never be. The stars have it not; the earth has it not; the sea has it not; and we men have the mockery and semblance of it only for our heaviest punishment.

It's also satisfying to realize, as I dive into a topic that initially seemed only slightly related to the serious issues facing humanity, that the idea of material perfection it leads me to consider provides a strange proof of how misguided the idea of Liberty is; truly, it's the most deceitful of all ideas. A little bit of reason should make it clear that neither achieving it nor even having it is possible. It doesn't exist anywhere in the universe. It never will. The stars don't have it; the earth doesn't have it; the sea doesn't have it; and we, as humans, only have the mockery of it, which serves as our greatest punishment.

In one of the noblest poems17 for its imagery and its music belonging to the recent school of our literature, the writer has sought in the aspect of inanimate nature the expression of that Liberty which, having once loved, he had seen among men in its true dyes of darkness. But with what strange fallacy of interpretation! since in one noble line of his invocation he has contradicted the assumptions of the rest, and acknowledged the presence of a subjection, surely not less severe because eternal? How could he otherwise? since i[Pg 189]f there be any one principle more widely than another confessed by every utterance, or more sternly than another imprinted on every atom, of the visible creation, that principle is not Liberty, but Law.

In one of the finest poems17 for its imagery and music from the recent era of our literature, the author explores inanimate nature to express that Liberty which, after experiencing it, he has seen among people in its true shades of darkness. But what a strange twist of interpretation! Since in one powerful line of his invocation, he contradicts the assumptions of the rest and acknowledges the presence of a subjection, surely not any less harsh because it's eternal? How could he see it differently? If there is any principle that is more universally acknowledged in every expression, or more harshly etched into every particle of visible creation, that principle is not Liberty, but Law.

II. The enthusiast would reply that by Liberty he meant the Law of Liberty. Then why use the single and misunderstood word? If by liberty you mean chastisement of the passions, discipline of the intellect, subjection of the will; if you mean the fear of inflicting, the shame of committing a wrong; if you mean respect for all who are in authority, and consideration for all who are in dependence; veneration for the good, mercy to the evil, sympathy with the weak; if you mean watchfulness over all thoughts, temperance in all pleasures, and perseverance in all toils; if you mean, in a word, that Service which is defined in the liturgy of the English church to be perfect Freedom, why do you name this by the same word by which the luxurious mean license, and the reckless mean change; by which the rogue means rapine, and the fool equality, by which the proud mean anarchy, and the malignant mean violence? Call it by any name rather than this, but its best and truest is, Obedience. Obedience is, indeed, founded on a kind of freedom, else its would become mere subjugation, but that freedom is only granted that obedience may be more perfect; and thus, while a measure of license is necessary to exhibit the individual energies of things, the fairness and pleasantness and perfection of them all consist in their Restraint. Compare a river that has burst its banks with one that is bound by them, and the clouds that are scattered over the face of the whole heaven with those that are marshalled into ranks and orders by its winds. So that though restraint, utter and unrelaxing, can never be comely, this is not because it is in itself an evil, but only because, when too great, it overpowers the nature of the thing restrained, and so counteracts the other laws of which that nature is itself composed. And the balance wherein consists the fairness of creation is between the laws of life and being in the things governed and the laws of general sway to which they are subjected; and the suspension or infringement of either kind of law, or, literally,[Pg 190] disorder, is equivalent to, and synonymous with, disease; while the increase of both honor and beauty is habitually on the side of restraint (or the action of superior law) rather than of character (or the action of inherent law). The noblest word in the catalogue of social virtue is "Loyalty," and the sweetest which men have learned in the pastures of the wilderness is "Fold."

II. The enthusiast would say that by Liberty he meant the Law of Liberty. So, why use a single, misunderstood word? If by liberty you mean controlling passions, disciplining the mind, submitting the will; if you mean the fear of causing harm, the shame of doing wrong; if you mean respect for those in authority and consideration for those who rely on others; reverence for the good, mercy toward the evil, empathy for the weak; if you mean being watchful over all thoughts, moderation in all pleasures, and persistence in all efforts; if you mean, in short, the Service that the English church defines as perfect Freedom, why call it by the same name that the rich use for license, and the reckless use for change; that the rogue uses for theft, and the fool uses for equality, that the proud use for anarchy, and the spiteful use for violence? Call it by any other name than this, but its best and truest term is Obedience. Obedience is indeed based on a kind of freedom; otherwise, it would just be subjugation, but that freedom is given so obedience can be more perfect; and so, while a certain amount of liberty is necessary to showcase the individual strengths of things, their fairness, enjoyment, and perfection come from their Restraint. Compare a river that has overflowed its banks to one that is contained by them, and the clouds scattered across the sky to those that are organized into formations by the wind. While complete and unyielding restraint is never graceful, this is not because it is inherently bad, but only because, when excessive, it overwhelms the nature of whatever is being restrained, thus countering the other laws that make up that nature. The balance that underlies the beauty of creation lies between the laws of life and existence in the governed things and the laws of the broader control to which they are subjected; the suspension or violation of either kind of law, or, literally, disorder, is equivalent to, and synonymous with, disease; while the growth of both honor and beauty tends to be on the side of restraint (or the action of higher law) rather than character (or the action of inherent law). The noblest word in the list of social virtues is "Loyalty," and the sweetest one that people have learned in the wilderness is "Fold."

III. Nor is this all; but we may observe, that exactly in proportion to the majesty of things in the scale of being, is the completeness of their obedience to the laws that are set over them. Gravitation is less quietly, less instantly obeyed by a grain of dust than it is by the sun and moon; and the ocean falls and flows under influences which the lake and river do not recognize. So also in estimating the dignity of any action or occupation of men, there is perhaps no better test than the question "are its laws strait?" For their severity will probably be commensurate with the greatness of the numbers whose labor it concentrates or whose interest it concerns.

III. But that's not all; we can also see that the more majestic something is in the hierarchy of existence, the more completely it obeys the laws governing it. A grain of dust is less quick and less willing to obey gravity than the sun and moon are; the ocean reacts to forces that lakes and rivers don’t even notice. Similarly, when assessing the importance of any action or job people do, there’s probably no better measure than asking, "Are the rules strict?" The stricter the rules are, the more they likely reflect the significance of the many people whose work it brings together or whose interests it affects.

This severity must be singular, therefore, in the case of that art, above all others, whose productions are the most vast and the most common; which requires for its practice the co-operation of bodies of men, and for its perfection the perseverance of successive generations. And taking into account also what we have before so often observed of Architecture, her continual influence over the emotions of daily life, and her realism, as opposed to the two sister arts which are in comparison but the picturing of stories and of dreams, we might beforehand expect that we should find her healthy state and action dependent on far more severe laws than theirs; that the license which they extend to the workings of individual mind would be withdrawn by her; and that, in assertion of the relations which she holds with all that is universally important to man, she would set forth, by her own majestic subjection, some likeness of that on which man's social happiness and power depend. We might, therefore, without the light of experience, conclude, that Architecture never could flourish except when it was subjected to a national law as strict and[Pg 191] as minutely authoritative as the laws which regulate religion, policy, and social relations; nay, even more authoritative than these, because both capable of more enforcement, as over more passive matter; and needing more enforcement, as the purest type not of one law nor of another, but of the common authority of all. But in this matter experience speaks more loudly than reason. If there be any one condition which, in watching the progress of architecture, we see distinct and general; if, amidst the counter evidence of success attending opposite accidents of character and circumstance, any one conclusion may be constantly and indisputably drawn, it is this; that the architecture of a nation is great only when it is as universal and as established as its language; and when provincial differences of style are nothing more than so many dialects. Other necessities are matters of doubt: nations have been alike successful in their architecture in times of poverty and of wealth; in times of war and of peace; in times of barbarism and of refinement; under governments the most liberal or the most arbitrary; but this one condition has been constant, this one requirement clear in all places and at all times, that the work shall be that of a school, that no individual caprice shall dispense with, or materially vary, accepted types and customary decorations; and that from the cottage to the palace, and from the chapel to the basilica, and from the garden fence to the fortress wall, every member and feature of the architecture of the nation shall be as commonly current, as frankly accepted, as its language or its coin.

This strictness must be unique, especially when it comes to that art, above all others, whose creations are the most expansive and widely recognized; which demands teamwork for its practice and the dedication of many generations for its perfection. Considering what we have often noted about Architecture, its ongoing impact on daily emotions, and its realism—unlike the two sister arts that merely depict stories and dreams—we might expect to find its well-being and function tied to much stricter rules than those of the other arts; that the freedom they allow for individual creativity would be limited by her; and that, in affirming her connections to everything that is universally significant for humanity, she would, through her own grand style, present a reflection of what human social happiness and strength rely on. Therefore, we could, without experience, conclude that Architecture could never thrive unless it was subjected to a national law as strict and as detailed as the laws governing religion, politics, and social interactions; indeed, even more authoritative than these, because it can be enforced more easily over more passive materials, and requires more oversight, as it represents not just one law but the collective authority of all. However, in this case, experience speaks louder than reason. If there is any one condition that stands out clearly and generally while observing the evolution of architecture; if, despite the contrasting evidence of success arising from different character traits and situations, we can consistently and undeniably conclude one thing, it is this: that a nation's architecture is only great when it is as widespread and established as its language; and when regional differences in style are just like various dialects. Other requirements are uncertain: nations have succeeded in architecture during both poverty and prosperity; during war and peace; in periods of barbarism and sophistication; under the most liberal or most oppressive governments; but this one condition has remained constant, this one necessity clear everywhere and at all times, that the work must come from a collective tradition, that no individual whims should alter or significantly change accepted forms and common decorations; and that from the cottage to the palace, from the chapel to the basilica, and from the garden gate to the fortress wall, every part and feature of a nation's architecture must be as widely recognized and as readily accepted as its language or its currency.

IV. A day never passes without our hearing our English architects called upon to be original, and to invent a new style: about as sensible and necessary an exhortation as to ask of a man who has never had rags enough on his back to keep out cold, to invent a new mode of cutting a coat. Give him a whole coat first, and let him concern himself about the fashion of it afterwards. We want no new style of architecture. Who wants a new style of painting or sculpture? But we want some style. It is of marvellously little importance, if we have a code of laws and they be good laws, whether they be new or old, foreign or native, Roman or Saxon, or Norman or Eng[Pg 192]lish laws. But it is of considerable importance that we should have a code of laws of one kind or another, and that code accepted and enforced from one side of the island to another, and not one law made ground of judgment at York and another in Exeter. And in like manner it does not matter one marble splinter whether we have an old or new architecture, but it matters everything whether we have an architecture truly so called or not; that is, whether an architecture whose laws might be taught at our schools from Cornwall to Northumberland, as we teach English spelling and English grammar, or an architecture which is to be invented fresh every time we build a workhouse or a parish school. There seems to me to be a wonderful misunderstanding among the majority of architects at the present day as to the very nature and meaning of Originality, and of all wherein it consists. Originality in expression does not depend on invention of new words; nor originality in poetry on invention of new measures; nor, in painting, on invention of new colors, or new modes of using them. The chords of music, the harmonies of color, the general principles of the arrangement of sculptural masses, have been determined long ago, and, in all probability, cannot be added to any more than they can be altered. Granting that they may be, such additions or alterations are much more the work of time and of multitudes than of individual inventors. We may have one Van Eyck, who will be known as the introducer of a new style once in ten centuries, but he himself will trace his invention to some accidental bye-play or pursuit; and the use of that invention will depend altogether on the popular necessities or instincts of the period. Originality depends on nothing of the kind. A man who has the gift, will take up any style that is going, the style of his day, and will work in that, and be great in that, and make everything that he does in it look as fresh as if every thought of it had just come down from heaven. I do not say that he will not take liberties with his materials, or with his rules: I do not say that strange changes will not sometimes be wrought by his efforts, or his fancies, in both. But those changes will be instructive, natural, facile, though sometimes marvellous; they[Pg 193] will never be sought after as things necessary to his dignity or to his independence; and those liberties will be like the liberties that a great speaker takes with the language, not a defiance of its rules for the sake of singularity; but inevitable, uncalculated, and brilliant consequences of an effort to express what the language, without such infraction, could not. There may be times when, as I have above described, the life of an art is manifested in its changes, and in its refusal of ancient limitations: so there are in the life of an insect; and there is great interest in the state of both the art and the insect at those periods when, by their natural progress and constitutional power, such changes are about to be wrought. But as that would be both an uncomfortable and foolish caterpillar which, instead of being contented with a caterpillar's life and feeding on caterpillar's food, was always striving to turn itself into a chrysalis; and as that would be an unhappy chrysalis which should lie awake at night and roll restlessly in its cocoon, in efforts to turn itself prematurely into a moth; so will that art be unhappy and unprosperous which, instead of supporting itself on the food, and contenting itself with the customs which have been enough for the support and guidance of other arts before it and like it, is struggling and fretting under the natural limitations of its existence, and striving to become something other than it is. And though it is the nobility of the highest creatures to look forward to, and partly to understand the changes which are appointed for them, preparing for them beforehand; and if, as is usual with appointed changes, they be into a higher state, even desiring them, and rejoicing in the hope of them, yet it is the strength of every creature, be it changeful or not, to rest for the time being, contented with the conditions of its existence, and striving only to bring about the changes which it desires, by fulfilling to the uttermost the duties for which its present state is appointed and continued.

IV. Not a day goes by without hearing our English architects urged to be original and invent a new style: asking this is as sensible and necessary as asking someone who has never had enough rags to keep warm to invent a new way to cut a coat. Give him a proper coat first, and then he can think about its style later. We don’t need a new style of architecture. Who wants a new style of painting or sculpture? But we do want some style. It matters very little if we have a set of laws that are good ones, whether they are new or old, foreign or local, Roman or Saxon, or Norman or English laws. What matters is that we have some sort of legal code that is recognized and enforced across the entire country, rather than one law being used in York and another in Exeter. Similarly, it doesn’t matter one bit whether our architecture is old or new, but it’s incredibly important that we have an architecture that qualifies as architecture; that is, whether it’s an architecture whose principles can be taught in our schools from Cornwall to Northumberland, just like we teach English spelling and grammar, or an architecture that needs to be reinvented every time we build a workhouse or a parish school. It seems there’s a huge misunderstanding among many architects today about what Originality really is and what it entails. Originality in expression isn’t about inventing new words; originality in poetry isn’t about creating new forms; and originality in painting isn’t about coming up with new colors or new ways to use them. The musical chords, the harmonies of color, and the basic principles of arranging sculptural forms were established long ago, and they probably can't be added to any more than they can be changed. Even if they could be, such changes would be more the product of time and many people rather than individual inventors. We might have one Van Eyck, known for introducing a new style once every ten centuries, but he’d trace his invention back to some chance event or interest; and the application of that invention would depend entirely on the popular needs or instincts of the time. Originality is independent of these factors. A person who possesses this gift will adopt any style that exists, the style of their time, and will thrive in it, making everything they create seem as fresh as if every thought had just come from heaven. I’m not saying they won’t take liberties with their materials or their rules; nor am I saying strange changes won’t sometimes arise from their efforts or ideas in both. But those changes will be insightful, natural, effortless, and sometimes astonishing; they won’t be pursued as things essential to their dignity or independence; rather, those liberties will be like the creative liberties a great speaker takes with language, not a defiance of its rules for the sake of being different, but inevitable, unplanned, and brilliant outcomes of the effort to express what the language, without such deviations, could not convey. There may be times, as I described earlier, when the life of an art is revealed in its changes and its rejection of old limitations; the same goes for insects, and there’s great interest in both the art and the insect during those periods when, due to their natural growth and inherent power, such changes are about to happen. But it would be an uncomfortable and foolish caterpillar that, instead of enjoying its caterpillar life and eating caterpillar food, was always trying to transform itself into a chrysalis; and it would be an unhappy chrysalis lying awake at night, rolling restlessly in its cocoon, trying to turn into a moth too soon. Similarly, an art that fails to sustain itself on the traditions and conventions that have supported and guided other similar arts, and instead struggles against the natural constraints of its existence, trying to be something other than what it is, will be unhappy and unsuccessful. While it’s noble for the highest creatures to look forward to, and partially understand, the changes they are meant to undergo, preparing for them in advance; and if, as is usual with inevitable changes, these are for the better, to even desire them and rejoice in the hope of them, it’s still the strength of every creature, whether it changes or not, to find comfort in their current state, focusing only on achieving the changes they desire by fully embracing the responsibilities of their present condition.

V. Neither originality, therefore, nor change, good though both may be, and this is commonly a most merciful and enthusiastic supposition with respect to either, are ever to be sought in themselves, or can ever be healthily obtained by any[Pg 194] struggle or rebellion against common laws. We want neither the one nor the other. The forms of architecture already known are good enough for us, and for far better than any of us: and it will be time enough to think of changing them for better when we can use them as they are. But there are some things which we not only want, but cannot do without; and which all the struggling and raving in the world, nay more, which all the real talent and resolution in England, will never enable us to do without: and these are Obedience, Unity, Fellowship, and Order. And all our schools of design, and committees of tastes; all our academies and lectures, and journalisms, and essays; all the sacrifices which we are beginning to make, all the truth which there is in our English nature, all the power of our English will, and the life of our English intellect, will in this matter be as useless as efforts and emotions in a dream, unless we are contented to submit architecture and all art, like other things, to English law.

V. So, neither originality nor change, though both may be good—and this is often a hopeful and enthusiastic belief about either—should be pursued for their own sake, nor can they be achieved in a healthy way by struggling or rebelling against common rules. We don’t need either. The architectural styles we already have are perfectly fine for us, and far better than what any of us could create: it will be time enough to think about improving them when we can actually utilize them as they are. However, there are certain things we not only desire but cannot live without; no amount of struggle or noise in the world, nor all the real talent and determination in England, will ever help us do without these: Obedience, Unity, Fellowship, and Order. All our design schools, taste committees, academies, lectures, journalism, and essays; all the sacrifices we’re starting to make, all the truth that exists in our English nature, all the strength of our English will, and the energy of our English intellect will be as futile as dreams unless we are willing to submit architecture and all art, like everything else, to English law.

VI. I say architecture and all art; for I believe architecture must be the beginning of arts, and that the others must follow her in their time and order; and I think the prosperity of our schools of painting and sculpture, in which no one will deny the life, though many the health, depends upon that of our architecture. I think that all will languish until that takes the lead, and (this I do not think, but I proclaim, as confidently as I would assert the necessity, for the safety of society, of an understood and strongly administered legal government) our architecture will languish, and that in the very dust, until the first principle of common sense be manfully obeyed, and an universal system of form and workmanship be everywhere adopted and enforced. It may be said that this is impossible. It may be so—I fear it is so: I have nothing to do with the possibility or impossibility of it; I simply know and assert the necessity of it. If it be impossible, English art is impossible. Give it up at once. You are wasting time, and money, and energy upon it, and though you exhaust centuries and treasuries, and break hearts for it, you will never raise it above the merest dilettanteism. Think not of it. It is a dangerous vanity, a mere gulph in which genius[Pg 195] after genius will be swallowed up, and it will not close. And so it will continue to be, unless the one bold and broad step be taken at the beginning. We shall not manufacture art out of pottery and printed stuffs; we shall not reason out art by our philosophy; we shall not stumble upon art by our experiments, not create it by our fancies: I do not say that we can even build it out of brick and stone; but there is a chance for us in these, and there is none else; and that chance rests on the bare possibility of obtaining the consent, both of architects and of the public, to choose a style, and to use it universally.

VI. I talk about architecture and all art because I believe architecture is where the arts should start, and the others should follow in their own time and order. I think the success of our painting and sculpture schools, which everyone acknowledges have life, though many debate their quality, relies on our architecture. I believe everything will struggle until architecture takes the lead, and I’m not just saying this lightly; I assert it confidently, just as I would claim that a fair and strong legal system is essential for society's safety. Our architecture will decline and be left in the dust until we seriously follow the basic principle of common sense and universally adopt and enforce a consistent system of style and craft. Some might argue that this is impossible. Maybe it is; I’m afraid it might be. But I’m not concerned with whether it’s possible or not; I simply recognize and affirm how necessary it is. If it is impossible, then English art is also impossible. You should abandon it right away. You’re wasting time, money, and energy on it, and even if you drain centuries of resources and break hearts, you’ll never elevate it above mere amateurism. Don’t even think about it. It’s a dangerous illusion, a bottomless pit where one talent after another will get lost, and it won’t ever close up again. It will keep on being this way unless we take that one bold and significant step right at the start. We won’t create art from pottery and printed fabrics; we won’t figure it out through philosophy; we won’t accidentally discover it through experiments or invent it with our imaginations. I’m not saying we can even build it from bricks and stones; but there’s a chance for us in these materials, and that’s our only option. That chance relies on getting both architects and the public to agree on a style and to use it universally.

VII. How surely its principles ought at first to be limited, we may easily determine by the consideration of the necessary modes of teaching any other branch of general knowledge. When we begin to teach children writing, we force them to absolute copyism, and require absolute accuracy in the formation of the letters; as they obtain command of the received modes of literal expression, we cannot prevent their falling into such variations as are consistent with their feeling, their circumstances, or their characters. So, when a boy is first taught to write Latin, an authority is required of him for every expression he uses; as he becomes master of the language he may take a license, and feel his right to do so without any authority, and yet write better Latin than when he borrowed every separate expression. In the same way our architects would have to be taught to write the accepted style. We must first determine what buildings are to be considered Augustan in their authority; their modes of construction and laws of proportion are to be studied with the most penetrating care; then the different forms and uses of their decorations are to be classed and catalogued, as a German grammarian classes the powers of prepositions; and under this absolute, irrefragable authority, we are to begin to work; admitting not so much as an alteration in the depth of a cavetto, or the breadth of a fillet. Then, when our sight is once accustomed to the grammatical forms and arrangements, and our thoughts familiar with the expression of them all; when we can speak this dead language naturally, and apply it[Pg 196] to whatever ideas we have to render, that is to say, to every practical purpose of life; then, and not till then, a license might be permitted; and individual authority allowed to change or to add to the received forms, always within certain limits; the decorations, especially, might be made subjects of variable fancy, and enriched with ideas either original or taken from other schools. And thus in process of time and by a great national movement, it might come to pass, that a new style should arise, as language itself changes; we might perhaps come to speak Italian instead of Latin, or to speak modern instead of old English; but this would be a matter of entire indifference, and a matter, besides, which no determination or desire could either hasten or prevent. That alone which it is in our power to obtain, and which it is our duty to desire, is an unanimous style of some kind, and such comprehension and practice of it as would enable us to adapt its features to the peculiar character of every several building, large or small, domestic, civil, or ecclesiastical. I have said that it was immaterial what style was adopted, so far as regards the room for originality which its developement would admit: it is not so, however, when we take into consideration the far more important questions of the facility of adaptation to general purposes, and of the sympathy with which this or that style would be popularly regarded. The choice of Classical or Gothic, again using the latter term in its broadest sense, may be questionable when it regards some single and considerable public building; but I cannot conceive it questionable, for an instant, when it regards modern uses in general: I cannot conceive any architect insane enough to project the vulgarization of Greek architecture. Neither can it be rationally questionable whether we should adopt early or late, original or derivative Gothic: if the latter were chosen, it must be either some impotent and ugly degradation, like our own Tudor, or else a style whose grammatical laws it would be nearly impossible to limit or arrange, like the French Flamboyant. We are equally precluded from adopting styles essentially infantine or barbarous, however Herculean their infancy, or majestic their outlawry, such as our own Norman,[Pg 197] or the Lombard Romanesque. The choice would lie I think between four styles:—1. The Pisan Romanesque; 2. The early Gothic of the Western Italian Republics, advanced as far and as fast as our art would enable us to the Gothic of Giotto; 3. The Venetian Gothic in its purest developement; 4. The English earliest decorated. The most natural, perhaps the safest choice, would be of the last, well fenced from chance of again stiffening into the perpendicular; and perhaps enriched by some mingling of decorative elements from the exquisite decorated Gothic of France, of which, in such cases, it would be needful to accept some well known examples, as the North door of Rouen and the church of St. Urbain at Troyes, for final and limiting authorities on the side of decoration.

VII. We can easily decide how strictly its principles should initially be limited by considering how to teach any other area of general knowledge. When we start teaching children to write, we require them to copy exactly and to form the letters with complete accuracy. As they gain control over established ways of written expression, they will inevitably start to make variations that match their feelings, circumstances, or personalities. Similarly, when a boy is first taught to write in Latin, he needs to reference an authority for every phrase he uses; as he becomes proficient in the language, he can take liberties and feel entitled to do so without having to refer to authority, yet he may write better Latin than when he was overly reliant on borrowed phrases. Likewise, our architects need to learn to write in the accepted style. We first need to identify which buildings are considered authoritative in the Augustan style; we must study their construction methods and proportions meticulously; then we should categorize the various forms and usages of their decorations, much like a German grammarian categorizes the functions of prepositions. Under this absolute, unquestionable authority, we must begin our work; we should not allow even a minor change in the depth of a cavetto or the width of a fillet. Once our eyes have adjusted to the grammatical forms and arrangements, and our minds are familiar with how to express them; when we can naturally communicate in this dead language and apply it to all the ideas we want to express for practical purposes, only then should we be allowed some leeway to adapt or add to the accepted forms, always within certain limits; particularly the decorations could be subjects of creative interpretation, enriched with ideas that may be original or borrowed from other styles. Over time, through a significant national movement, a new style might emerge, just as language evolves; we might eventually find ourselves speaking Italian instead of Latin or using modern English instead of Old English; but this would be completely indifferent, a subject that no decision or desire could hasten or prevent. What we can strive for and should desire is some kind of unified style, and the understanding and practice of it that would enable us to adapt its features to the unique character of each building, regardless of size, whether domestic, civic, or religious. I have noted that the specific style chosen is not important regarding the room for originality it allows; however, this changes significantly when we consider the much more crucial issues of how easily it can adapt to general purposes, and the degree to which a particular style would be received positively by the public. The choice between Classical and Gothic styles, using the latter term broadly, may be questionable for a particular significant public building, but I can’t see it being questionable at all when it comes to modern applications in general: I can’t imagine any architect so misguided as to aim for the popularization of Greek architecture. Similarly, it isn't rationally debatable whether we should go for early or late, original or derivative Gothic: if we choose the latter, it would either be an ineffective and ugly version, like our own Tudor style, or a style whose grammatical rules would be nearly impossible to limit or arrange, like the French Flamboyant. We are also explicitly barred from selecting styles that are essentially primitive or barbaric, regardless of how mighty their origins or how grand their rejection, such as our own Norman style or the Lombard Romanesque. I believe the choice should be between four styles: 1. The Pisan Romanesque; 2. The early Gothic of the Western Italian Republics, developed as far and as fast as our art would allow up to the Gothic of Giotto; 3. The purest development of Venetian Gothic; 4. The earliest decorated English Gothic. The most natural and likely safest choice would be the last one, well protected from the risk of stiffening into the perpendicular again; and perhaps enhanced by incorporating decorative elements from the exquisite decorated Gothic of France, from which we should select noted examples like the North door of Rouen and the church of St. Urbain at Troyes, as final and conclusive references for decoration.

VIII. It is almost impossible for us to conceive, in our present state of doubt and ignorance, the sudden dawn of intelligence and fancy, the rapidly increasing sense of power and facility, and, in its proper sense, of Freedom, which such wholesome restraint would instantly cause throughout the whole circle of the arts. Freed from the agitation and embarrassment of that liberty of choice which is the cause of half the discomforts of the world; freed from the accompanying necessity of studying all past, present, or even possible styles; and enabled, by concentration of individual, and co-operation of multitudinous energy, to penetrate into the uttermost secrets of the adopted style, the architect would find his whole understanding enlarged, his practical knowledge certain and ready to hand, and his imagination playful and vigorous, as a child's would be within a walled garden, who would sit down and shudder if he were left free in a fenceless plain. How many and how bright would be the results in every direction of interest, not to the arts merely, but to national happiness and virtue, it would be as difficult to preconceive as it would seem extravagant to state: but the first, perhaps the least, of them would be an increased sense of fellowship among ourselves, a cementing of every patriotic bond of union, a proud and happy recognition of our affection for and sympathy with each other, and our willingness in all things to submit our[Pg 198]selves to every law that would advance the interest of the community; a barrier, also, the best conceivable, to the unhappy rivalry of the upper and middle classes, in houses, furniture, and establishments; and even a check to much of what is as vain as it is painful in the oppositions of religious parties respecting matters of ritual. These, I say, would be the first consequences. Economy increased tenfold, as it would be by the simplicity of practice; domestic comforts uninterfered with by the caprice and mistakes of architects ignorant of the capacities of the styles they use, and all the symmetry and sightliness of our harmonized streets and public buildings, are things of slighter account in the catalogue of benefits. But it would be mere enthusiasm to endeavor to trace them farther. I have suffered myself too long to indulge in the speculative statement of requirements which perhaps we have more immediate and more serious work than to supply, and of feelings which it may be only contingently in our power to recover. I should be unjustly thought unaware of the difficulty of what I have proposed, or of the unimportance of the whole subject as compared with many which are brought home to our interests and fixed upon our consideration by the wild course of the present century. But of difficulty and of importance it is for others to judge. I have limited myself to the simple statement of what, if we desire to have architecture, we MUST primarily endeavor to feel and do: but then it may not be desirable for us to have architecture at all. There are many who feel it to be so; many who sacrifice much to that end; and I am sorry to see their energies wasted and their lives disquieted in vain. I have stated, therefore, the only ways in which that end is attainable, without venturing even to express an opinion as to its real desirableness. I have an opinion, and the zeal with which I have spoken may sometimes have betrayed it, but I hold to it with no confidence. I know too well the undue importance which the study that every man follows must assume in his own eyes, to trust my own impressions of the dignity of that of Architecture; and yet I think I cannot be utterly mistaken in regarding it as at least useful in the sense of a National employment. I am con[Pg 199]firmed in this impression by what I see passing among the states of Europe at this instant. All the horror, distress, and tumult which oppress the foreign nations, are traceable, among the other secondary causes through which God is working out His will upon them, to the simple one of their not having enough to do. I am not blind to the distress among their operatives; nor do I deny the nearer and visibly active causes of the movement: the recklessness of villany in the leaders of revolt, the absence of common moral principle in the upper classes, and of common courage and honesty in the heads of governments. But these causes themselves are ultimately traceable to a deeper and simpler one: the recklessness of the demagogue, the immorality of the middle class, and the effeminacy and treachery of the noble, are traceable in all these nations to the commonest and most fruitful cause of calamity in households—idleness. We think too much in our benevolent efforts, more multiplied and more vain day by day, of bettering men by giving them advice and instruction. There are few who will take either: the chief thing they need is occupation. I do not mean work in the sense of bread,—I mean work in the sense of mental interest; for those who either are placed above the necessity of labor for their bread, or who will not work although they should. There is a vast quantity of idle energy among European nations at this time, which ought to go into handicrafts; there are multitudes of idle semi-gentlemen who ought to be shoemakers and carpenters; but since they will not be these so long as they can help it, the business of the philanthropist is to find them some other employment than disturbing governments. It is of no use to tell them they are fools, and that they will only make themselves miserable in the end as well as others: if they have nothing else to do, they will do mischief; and the man who will not work, and who has no means of intellectual pleasure, is as sure to become an instrument of evil as if he had sold himself bodily to Satan. I have myself seen enough of the daily life of the young educated men of France and Italy, to account for, as it deserves, the deepest national suffering and degradation; and though, for the most part, our commerce[Pg 200] and our natural habits of industry preserve us from a similar paralysis, yet it would be wise to consider whether the forms of employment which we chiefly adopt or promote, are as well calculated as they might be to improve and elevate us.

VIII. It's nearly impossible for us, in our current state of doubt and ignorance, to imagine the sudden rise of intelligence and creativity, the quickly growing sense of power and ease, and, in its true sense, of Freedom, that such healthy restraint would instantly bring across all areas of art. Free from the stress and confusion of the overwhelming freedom of choice that causes many of the world's discomforts; liberated from the need to study all past, present, or even potential styles; and empowered by a focus on individual effort and collective energy to delve into the deepest secrets of the chosen style, the architect would find their understanding broadened, practical knowledge certain and readily accessible, and imagination lively and vigorous, like a child's in a walled garden, who would feel unsettled if left free in an open field. The outcomes would be numerous and bright in every area of interest, not only in the arts but also in national happiness and virtue; envisioning these outcomes would be as challenging as it would seem extravagant to declare: but the first, perhaps the least, would be a stronger sense of community among us, a strengthening of every patriotic bond, a proud and joyful recognition of our affection and empathy for one another, and our willingness to abide by every law that promotes the community's interests; a barrier, too—the best conceivable—against the unfortunate rivalry among the upper and middle classes regarding homes, furnishings, and lifestyles; and even a limit to much that is as vain as it is distressing in the disputes among religious factions about rituals. These, I suggest, would be the immediate results. Economies would soar as practice becomes simpler; domestic comforts would remain untouched by the whims and errors of architects unfamiliar with the styles they employ, and all the beauty and order of our coordinated streets and public buildings would be lower on the list of benefits. However, it would be naive to attempt to outline them further. I've indulged too long in speculative discussions about needs that we may have more pressing and serious matters to address and emotions that we might only recover by chance. I risk being seen as unaware of the challenges I propose or of the overall triviality of this subject compared to many that are forced upon our attention by the chaotic nature of this century. Yet it is for others to decide about the challenges and the significance. I have confined myself to simply stating what we MUST primarily focus on if we wish to have architecture: but it may not even be in our best interest to have architecture at all. Many believe it is essential; many sacrifice greatly for that purpose, and I regret seeing their energy squandered and their lives troubled in vain. Therefore, I have only indicated the ways in which this goal can be achieved, without even venturing to express an opinion on its genuine desirability. I have an opinion, and the enthusiasm with which I have spoken may have sometimes given it away, but I hold it with little confidence. I know too well the excessive significance that the study each person follows must take in their own perspective to trust my own views on the worthiness of Architecture; yet I think I can't be completely wrong in viewing it as at least beneficial in terms of national employment. I am confirmed in this sentiment by observing what is currently happening in the states of Europe. All the horror, distress, and chaos afflicting foreign nations can, among other secondary causes through which God is fulfilling His will, be traced back to the simple fact that they do not have enough to do. I don't ignore the suffering among their workers, nor do I deny the more immediate and visible causes of the unrest: the irresponsibility of the leaders of revolt, the lack of shared moral standards in the upper classes, and of common courage and integrity in government heads. But these issues stem from deeper, simpler origins: the recklessness of the demagogue, the immorality of the middle class, and the weakness and betrayal of the noble can all be traced back to the most ordinary and productive cause of household calamity—idleness. We focus too much in our charitable efforts, which grow more numerous and increasingly futile every day, on improving people by giving them advice and instruction. Few will take either: what they primarily need is occupation. I don't mean work in terms of earning a living—I mean work as a source of mental engagement; for those who are either above the necessity of labor for their survival or who refuse to work despite needing to. There is a tremendous amount of idle energy among European nations right now that should be directed toward craftsmanship; there are countless semi-gentlemen who ought to be shoemakers or carpenters; but as long as they can avoid it, they will not take on these roles, making it the task of philanthropists to find them alternative employment instead of creating unrest. There's no point in telling them they're foolish and that, in the end, they’ll only bring misery upon themselves and others: if they have nothing else to do, they will cause trouble; and a person who won’t work, without any means of intellectual enjoyment, is bound to become an agent of evil as surely as if they had sold their soul to Satan. I've seen enough of the daily lives of educated young men in France and Italy to understand how they deserve the deepest national suffering and degradation; and although our trade and natural industry habits often shield us from similar paralysis, it would be wise to consider if the forms of work we mainly adopt or promote are truly capable of improving and uplifting us.

We have just spent, for instance, a hundred and fifty millions, with which we have paid men for digging ground from one place and depositing it in another. We have formed a large class of men, the railway navvies, especially reckless, unmanageable, and dangerous. We have maintained besides (let us state the benefits as fairly as possible) a number of iron founders in an unhealthy and painful employment; we have developed (this is at least good) a very large amount of mechanical ingenuity; and we have, in fine, attained the power of going fast from one place to another. Meantime we have had no mental interest or concern ourselves in the operations we have set on foot, but have been left to the usual vanities and cares of our existence. Suppose, on the other hand, that we had employed the same sums in building beautiful houses and churches. We should have maintained the same number of men, not in driving wheelbarrows, but in a distinctly technical, if not intellectual, employment, and those who were more intelligent among them would have been especially happy in that employment, as having room in it for the developement of their fancy, and being directed by it to that observation of beauty which, associated with the pursuit of natural science, at present forms the enjoyment of many of the more intelligent manufacturing operatives. Of mechanical ingenuity, there is, I imagine, at least as much required to build a cathedral as to cut a tunnel or contrive a locomotive: we should, therefore, have developed as much science, while the artistical element of intellect would have been added to the gain. Meantime we should ourselves have been made happier and wiser by the interest we should have taken in the work with which we were personally concerned; and when all was done, instead of the very doubtful advantage of the power of going fast from place to place, we should have had the certain advantage of increased pleasure in stopping at home.[Pg 201]

We just spent, for example, one hundred fifty million, paying people to move dirt from one spot and put it somewhere else. We’ve created a large group of workers, the railway navvies, who can be reckless, unmanageable, and dangerous. We’ve also supported (let’s acknowledge the benefits fairly) a number of ironworkers in a tough and uncomfortable job; we’ve developed (and this is positive) a significant amount of mechanical skill; and we’ve ultimately gained the ability to travel quickly from one place to another. Meanwhile, we haven’t had any real mental interest or involvement in the projects we’ve initiated, just getting caught up in the usual distractions and worries of life. Now, imagine if we had used the same amount of money to build beautiful homes and churches. We would have kept the same number of workers, not just moving earth, but engaged in a more technical, if not intellectual, line of work. Those who were more skilled among them would have been particularly happy in that role, because it would allow them to tap into their creativity and focus on beauty, which, when linked with the pursuit of natural science, is something many of the more insightful manufacturing workers appreciate today. I believe it takes just as much mechanical skill to construct a cathedral as it does to dig a tunnel or design a locomotive, so we would have nurtured as much knowledge, while also adding the artistic aspects of intellect to our achievements. In the process, we would have been happier and wiser because we would have taken a genuine interest in the work we were involved in; and when all was said and done, instead of the uncertain benefit of being able to travel quickly, we would have gained the definite benefit of enjoying our time at home more.[Pg 201]

IX. There are many other less capacious, but more constant, channels of expenditure, quite as disputable in their beneficial tendency; and we are, perhaps, hardly enough in the habit of inquiring, with respect to any particular form of luxury or any customary appliance of life, whether the kind of employment it gives to the operative or the dependant be as healthy and fitting an employment as we might otherwise provide for him. It is not enough to find men absolute subsistence; we should think of the manner of life which our demands necessitate; and endeavor, as far as may be, to make all our needs such as may, in the supply of them, raise, as well as feed, the poor. It is far better to give work which is above the men, than to educate the men to be above their work. It may be doubted, for instance, whether the habits of luxury, which necessitate a large train of men servants, be a wholesome form of expenditure; and more, whether the pursuits which have a tendency to enlarge the class of the jockey and the groom be a philanthropic form of mental occupation. So again, consider the large number of men whose lives are employed by civilized nations in cutting facets upon jewels. There is much dexterity of hand, patience, and ingenuity thus bestowed, which are simply burned out in the blaze of the tiara, without, so far as I see, bestowing any pleasure upon those who wear or who behold, at all compensatory for the loss of life and mental power which are involved in the employment of the workman. He would be far more healthily and happily sustained by being set to carve stone; certain qualities of his mind, for which there is no room in his present occupation, would develope themselves in the nobler; and I believe that most women would, in the end, prefer the pleasure of having built a church, or contributed to the adornment of a cathedral, to the pride of bearing a certain quantity of adamant on their foreheads.

IX. There are many other less substantial, but more consistent, ways of spending money that are just as questionable in their benefits; and we might not often think about whether the types of luxury or everyday items we choose provide a healthy and suitable job for those they employ. It's not enough to ensure people have basic living standards; we should also consider the lifestyle our demands create and try, as much as possible, to make our needs such that they help uplift, not just sustain, the poor. It's much better to give people work that pushes their limits than to elevate them beyond the work available. For instance, one might question whether the lifestyles of luxury that require many servants are a healthy way to spend money, or whether pursuits that expand the roles of jockeys and grooms are truly beneficial to society. Similarly, consider the countless individuals employed by civilized societies to cut facets on gemstones. A lot of skill, patience, and creativity go into this work, but ultimately, it often goes unnoticed or unappreciated through the sparkle of jewelry, without providing any real joy to those who wear or see it that would justify the life and mental energy lost by the workers. They would be much better off and more fulfilled carving stone; certain aspects of their minds that have no space in their current jobs would flourish in that nobler pursuit. I believe most women would ultimately find more satisfaction in having helped build a church or contributed to decorating a cathedral than in showing off a bunch of diamonds on their foreheads.

X. I could pursue this subject willingly, but I have some strange notions about it which it is perhaps wiser not loosely to set down. I content myself with finally reasserting, what has been throughout the burden of the preceding pages, that whatever rank, or whatever importance, may be attributed or[Pg 202] attached to their immediate subject, there is at least some value in the analogies with which its pursuit has presented us, and some instruction in the frequent reference of its commonest necessities to the mighty laws, in the sense and scope of which all men are Builders, whom every hour sees laying the stubble or the stone.

X. I could gladly keep talking about this topic, but I have some odd ideas about it that might be better left unsaid. I’ll just restate what has been the main point of the earlier pages: no matter what status or importance is assigned to the immediate subject, there’s at least some value in the comparisons we've encountered while exploring it, and some lessons in how often its basic needs relate to the powerful principles that guide all people, who are constantly working, laying down the groundwork or building the structures.

I have paused, not once nor twice, as I wrote, and often have checked the course of what might otherwise have been importunate persuasion, as the thought has crossed me, how soon all Architecture may be vain, except that which is not made with hands. There is something ominous in the light which has enabled us to look back with disdain upon the ages among whose lovely vestiges we have been wandering. I could smile when I hear the hopeful exultation of many, at the new reach of worldly science, and vigor of worldly effort; as if we were again at the beginning of days. There is thunder on the horizon as well as dawn. The sun was risen upon the earth when Lot entered into Zoar.

I have stopped, not just once or twice, as I wrote, and often have reflected on what could have been a pushy argument, as the thought hit me, how quickly all architecture might become meaningless, except for what is created without human hands. There’s something unsettling about the light that allows us to look back with scorn at the eras among which we’ve been exploring. I could smile when I hear the optimistic enthusiasm of many, about the new heights of worldly science and the energy of worldly efforts; as if we were back at the beginning of time. There’s thunder on the horizon along with the dawn. The sun had risen on the earth when Lot entered Zoar.


NOTES

Note I.

Page 21.

"With the idolatrous Egyptian."

Page 21.

"With the idol-worshiping Egyptian."

The probability is indeed slight in comparison, but it is a probability nevertheless, and one which is daily on the increase. I trust that I may not be thought to underrate the danger of such sympathy, though I speak lightly of the chance of it. I have confidence in the central religious body of the English and Scottish people, as being not only untainted with Romanism, but immoveably adverse to it: and, however strangely and swiftly the heresy of the Protestant and victory of the Papist may seem to be extending among us, I feel assured that there are barriers in the living faith of this nation which neither can overpass. Yet this confidence is only in the ultimate faithfulness of a few, not in the security of the nation from the sin and the punishment of partial apostasy. Both have, indeed, in some sort, been committed and suffered already; and, in expressing my belief of the close connection of the distress and burden which the mass of the people at present sustain, with the encouragement which, in various directions, has been given to the Papist, do not let me be called superstitious or irrational. No man was ever more inclined than I, both by natural disposition and by many ties of early association, to a sympathy with the principles and forms of the Romanist Church; and there is much in its discipline which conscientiously, as well as sympathetically, I could love and advocate. But, in confessing this strength of affectionate prejudice, surely I vindicate more respect for my firmly expressed belief, that the entire doctrine and system of that Church is in the fullest sense anti-Christian; that its lying and idolatrous Power is the darkest plague that ever held commission to hurt the Earth; that all those yearnings for unity and fellowship, and common obedience, which have been the root of our late heresies, are as false in their grounds as fatal in their termination; that we never can have the remotest fellowship with the utterers of that fearful Falsehood, and live; that we have nothing to look to from them but treacherous hostility; and that, exactly in proportion to the sternness of our separation from them, will be not only[Pg 204] the spiritual but the temporal blessings granted by God to this country. How close has been the correspondence hitherto between the degree of resistance to Romanism marked in our national acts, and the honor with which those acts have been crowned, has been sufficiently proved in a short essay by a writer whose investigations into the influence of Religion upon the fate of Nations have been singularly earnest and successful—a writer with whom I faithfully and firmly believe that England will never be prosperous again, and that the honor of her arms will be tarnished, and her commerce blighted, and her national character degraded, until the Romanist is expelled from the place which has impiously been conceded to him among her legislators. "Whatever be the lot of those to whom error is an inheritance, woe be to the man and the people to whom it is an adoption. If England, free above all other nations, sustained amidst the trials which have covered Europe, before her eyes, with burning and slaughter, and enlightened by the fullest knowledge of divine truth, shall refuse fidelity to the compact by which those matchless privileges have been given, her condemnation will not linger. She has already made one step full of danger. She has committed the capital error of mistaking that for a purely political question which was a purely religious one. Her foot already hangs over the edge of the precipice. It must be retracted, or the empire is but a name. In the clouds and darkness which seem to be deepening on all human policy—in the gathering tumults of Europe, and the feverish discontents at home—it may be even difficult to discern where the power yet lives to erect the fallen majesty of the constitution once more. But there are mighty means in sincerity; and if no miracle was ever wrought for the faithless and despairing, the country that will help itself will never be left destitute of the help of Heaven" (Historical Essays, by the Rev. Dr. Croly, 1842). The first of these essays, "England the Fortress of Christianity," I most earnestly recommend to the meditation of those who doubt that a special punishment is inflicted by the Deity upon all national crime, and perhaps, of all such crime most instantly upon the betrayal on the part of England of the truth and faith with which she has been entrusted.

The chance is indeed small in comparison, but it is a chance nonetheless, and one that is growing every day. I hope I’m not seen as underestimating the danger of such sympathy, even though I speak casually about the likelihood of it. I have faith in the core religious community of the English and Scottish people, believing they are not only free from Roman influences but strongly against them: and despite how strange and fast the spread of Protestant heresy and Papist victory may seem among us, I’m confident that there are barriers in the living faith of this nation that neither can surpass. However, this confidence is based solely on the ultimate faithfulness of a few, not on the nation’s safety from the sin and consequences of partial abandonment of faith. Both have, in some way, already happened; and when I express my belief in the close link between the suffering and burden that most people are currently experiencing and the support that has been given to Papism in various ways, please don’t call me superstitious or irrational. No one has ever been more inclined than I, both by natural tendency and through many early associations, to sympathize with the principles and forms of the Roman Church; and there is much in its discipline that I could genuinely love and advocate. Yet, in admitting this strong affection, I surely affirm more respect for my firmly held belief that the entire doctrine and system of that Church is fully anti-Christian; that its deceitful and idolatrous power is the darkest plague that has ever been allowed to harm the Earth; that all those desires for unity and fellowship, and common obedience, which have been the root of our recent heresies, are as misguided in their foundations as they are deadly in their outcomes; that we can never have the slightest fellowship with the purveyors of that dreadful falsehood and survive; that we can expect nothing from them but treacherous hostility; and that, precisely in proportion to the strictness of our separation from them, will be not only[Pg 204] the spiritual but also the temporal blessings granted by God to this country. The close connection between the level of resistance to Romanism reflected in our national actions, and the honor those actions have received, has been sufficiently demonstrated in a brief essay by a writer who has thoroughly and successfully examined the influence of religion on the fate of nations—a writer with whom I firmly believe that England will never prosper again, and that her military honor will be tarnished, her commerce harmed, and her national character degraded, until the Romanist is removed from the position that has been wrongly given to him among her lawmakers. "Whatever the fate of those for whom error is an inheritance, woe to the man and the people for whom it is an adopted belief. If England, the most free nation of all, stands amid the trials that have engulfed Europe, marked by burning and slaughter before her eyes, and enlightened by the fullest knowledge of divine truth, chooses to abandon the commitment that has given her unmatched privileges, her judgment will come swiftly. She has already taken one perilous step. She has made the grave mistake of confusing what is a purely religious issue with a political one. Her foot hangs perilously over the edge of the precipice. It must be pulled back, or the empire is merely a name. In the clouds and darkness that seem to be enveloping all human governance—in the turmoil brewing in Europe and the restless dissatisfaction at home—it may be challenging to determine where the strength still lies to restore the fallen majesty of the constitution. But there are powerful tools in sincerity; and if no miracle has ever been performed for the unfaithful and hopeless, the nation that strives to help itself will never be left without the assistance of Heaven." (Historical Essays, by the Rev. Dr. Croly, 1842). I highly recommend the first of these essays, "England the Fortress of Christianity," for reflection by those who doubt that a specific punishment comes from God for all national wrongdoings, and perhaps most swiftly upon England's betrayal of the truth and faith she has been entrusted with.

Note II.

Page 25.

"Not the gift, but the giving."

Page 25.

"Not the present, but the act of giving."

Much attention has lately been directed to the subject of religious art, and we are now in possession of all kinds of interpretations and classifications of it, and of the leading facts of its history. But the greatest question of all connected with it remains entirely unanswered,[Pg 205] What good did it do to real religion? There is no subject into which I should so much rejoice to see a serious and conscientious inquiry instituted as this; an inquiry neither undertaken in artistical enthusiasm nor in monkish sympathy, but dogged, merciless and fearless. I love the religious art of Italy as well as most men, but there is a wide difference between loving it as a manifestation of individual feeling, and looking to it as an instrument of popular benefit. I have not knowledge enough to form even the shadow of an opinion on this latter point, and I should be most grateful to any one who would put it in my power to do so. There are, as it seems to me, three distinct questions to be considered: the first, What has been the effect of external splendor on the genuineness and earnestness of Christian worship? the second, What the use of pictorial or sculptural representation in the communication of Christian historical knowledge, or excitement of affectionate imagination? the third, What the influence of the practice of religious art on the life of the artist?

Recently, a lot of attention has been focused on the topic of religious art, and we now have many interpretations and classifications of it, along with key facts about its history. However, the biggest question related to it remains completely unanswered: What real benefit did it provide to true religion? There is no topic on which I would be more eager to see a serious and thoughtful investigation conducted than this one; an investigation that is not driven by artistic enthusiasm or monastic sympathy, but rather is persistent, relentless, and bold. I appreciate the religious art of Italy just like most people do, but there is a significant difference between appreciating it as a representation of personal emotion and viewing it as a means of benefiting the public. I don’t have enough knowledge to form even a vague opinion on this latter point, and I would be very thankful to anyone who could help me understand it better. It seems to me that there are three distinct questions to consider: first, what has been the impact of external splendor on the authenticity and seriousness of Christian worship? Second, what is the value of pictorial or sculptural representation in conveying Christian historical knowledge or stirring affectionate imagination? Third, what is the influence of practicing religious art on the life of the artist?

In answering these inquiries, we should have to consider separately every collateral influence and circumstance; and, by a most subtle analysis, to eliminate the real effect of art from the effects of the abuses with which it was associated. This could be done only by a Christian; not a man who would fall in love with a sweet color or sweet expression, but who would look for true faith and consistent life as the object of all. It never has been done yet, and the question remains a subject of vain and endless contention between parties of opposite prejudices and temperaments.

In addressing these questions, we need to look at each related influence and circumstance individually; and through careful analysis, separate the true impact of art from the negative associations tied to it. Only a Christian could achieve this; not someone who simply admires a pleasing color or expression, but someone who seeks genuine faith and a consistent way of living as the ultimate goal. This has never been accomplished, and the issue continues to spark pointless and ongoing debates among groups with opposing biases and personalities.

Note 3.

Page 26.

"To the concealment of what is really good or great."

Page 26.

"To hiding what is truly good or great."

I have often been surprised at the supposition that Romanism, In its present condition, could either patronise art or profit by it. The noble painted windows of St. Maclou at Rouen, and many other churches in France, are entirely blocked up behind the altars by the erection of huge gilded wooden sunbeams, with interspersed cherubs.

I have often been surprised by the assumption that Romanism, in its current state, could either support art or benefit from it. The beautiful stained glass windows of St. Maclou in Rouen, along with many other churches in France, are completely covered up behind the altars by the installation of large gilded wooden sunbeams adorned with cherubs.

Note 4.

Page 33.

"With different pattern of traceries in each."

Page 33.

"With a different pattern of decorations in each."

I have certainly not examined the seven hundred and four traceries (four to each niche) so as to be sure that none are alike; but they have the aspect of continual variation, and even the roses of the pendants of the small groined niche roofs are all of different patterns.

I definitely haven't looked closely at the seven hundred and four traceries (four in each niche) to confirm that none are the same; however, they seem to show constant variation, and even the roses on the pendant of the small groined niche roofs all have unique patterns.

Note V.

Page 43.

"Its flamboyant traceries of the last and most degraded forms."

Page 43.

"Its bold designs of the most recent and most degraded styles."

They are noticed by Mr. Whewell as forming the figure of the fleur-de-lis, always a mark, when in tracery bars, of the most debased flamboyant. It occurs in the central tower of Bayeux, very richly in the buttresses of St. Gervais at Falaise, and in the small niches of some of the domestic buildings at Rouen. Nor is it only the tower of St. Ouen which is overrated. Its nave is a base imitation, in the flamboyant period, of an early Gothic arrangement; the niches on its piers are barbarisms; there is a huge square shaft run through the ceiling of the aisles to support the nave piers, the ugliest excrescence I ever saw on a Gothic building; the traceries of the nave are the most insipid and faded flamboyant; those of the transept clerestory present a singularly distorted condition of perpendicular; even the elaborate door of the south transept is, for its fine period, extravagant and almost grotesque in its foliation and pendants. There is nothing truly fine in the church but the choir, the light triforium, and tall clerestory, the circle of Eastern chapels, the details of sculpture, and the general lightness of proportion; these merits being seen to the utmost advantage by the freedom of the body of the church from all incumbrance.

Mr. Whewell points out that they resemble the figure of the fleur-de-lis, which is always a sign, when in ornate patterns, of the most degraded flamboyant style. It appears in the central tower of Bayeux, very richly in the buttresses of St. Gervais at Falaise, and in the small niches of some domestic buildings at Rouen. It's not just the tower of St. Ouen that is overrated. Its nave is a poor imitation, during the flamboyant period, of an early Gothic layout; the niches on its piers are barbaric; there is an enormous square shaft running through the ceiling of the aisles to support the nave piers— the ugliest eyesore I’ve ever seen on a Gothic building; the traceries of the nave are bland and faded flamboyant; those of the transept clerestory display a strangely distorted form of perpendicular style; even the elaborate door of the south transept is, for its era, excessive and almost grotesque in its foliage and pendants. The only truly impressive features of the church are the choir, the light triforium, and the tall clerestory, the circle of Eastern chapels, the details of sculpture, and the overall lightness of proportions; these strengths are best highlighted by the open space in the church free from any obstruction.

Note 6.

Compare Iliad Σ. 1. 219 with Odyssey Ω. 1. 5—10.

Compare Iliad Σ. 1. 219 with Odyssey Ω. 1. 5—10.

Note 7.

Page 44.

"Does not admit iron as a constructive material."

Page 44.

"Does not allow iron as a building material."

Except in Chaucer's noble temple of Mars.

Except in Chaucer's great temple of Mars.

"And dounward from an hill under a bent,
Ther stood the temple of Mars, armipotent,
Wrought all of burned stele, of which th' entree
Was longe and streite, and gastly for to see.
And thereout came a rage and swiche a vise,
That it made all the gates for to rise.
The northern light in at the dore shone,
For window on the wall ne was ther none,
Thurgh which men mighten any light discerne
The dore was all of athamant eterne,
[Pg 207]Yclenched overthwart and ende long
With yren tough, and for to make it strong,
Every piler the temple to sustene
Was tonne-gret, of yren bright and shene."

The Knighte's Tale.

"And down from a hill under a slope,
There stood the temple of Mars, all-powerful,
Made entirely of burned steel, with a long and narrow
Entrance that was terrifying to see.
And there came a rage and such a sight,
That it made all the gates rise up.
The northern light shone in through the door,
For there were no windows on the walls,
Through which anyone could discern any light.
The door was made of eternal adamant,
[Pg 207]Clenched across and long on both ends
With tough iron, making it strong,
Every pillar that supported the temple
Was the size of a barrel, bright and shiny iron."

The Knight's Tale.

There is, by the bye, an exquisite piece of architectural color just before:

There is, by the way, a stunning piece of architectural color just ahead:

"And northward, in a turret on the wall
Of alabaster white, and red corall,
An oratorie riche for to see,
In worship of Diane of Chastitee."

"And up north, in a tower on the wall
Of bright white alabaster and red coral,
A stunning oratory to behold,
In honor of Diana of Chastity."

Note 8.

Page 44.

"The Builders of Salisbury."

Page 44.

"The Makers of Salisbury."

"This way of tying walls together with iron, instead of making them of that substance and form, that they shall naturally poise themselves upon their buttment, is against the rules of good architecture, not only because iron is corruptible by rust, but because it is fallacious, having unequal veins in the metal, some places of the same bar being three times stronger than others, and yet all sound to appearance." Survey of Salisbury Cathedral in 1668, by Sir C. Wren. For my own part, I think it better work to bind a tower with iron, than to support a false dome by a brick pyramid.

"This method of connecting walls with iron, rather than constructing them with a material and shape that allows them to naturally balance on their base, goes against the principles of good architecture. This is not only because iron can rust, but also because it is unreliable, having uneven strengths within the metal—some areas of the same bar being up to three times stronger than others, yet all appearing sound." Survey of Salisbury Cathedral in 1668, by Sir C. Wren. Personally, I believe it's a better practice to reinforce a tower with iron than to prop up a flawed dome with a brick pyramid.

Note 9.

Page 60.

Plate III.

Page 60.

Plate 3.

In this plate, figures 4, 5, and 6, are glazed windows, but fig. 2 is the open light of a belfry tower, and figures 1 and 3 are in triforia, the latter also occurring filled, on the central tower of Coutances.

In this plate, figures 4, 5, and 6 are glazed windows, but fig. 2 is the open light of a belfry tower, and figures 1 and 3 are in triforia, with the latter also appearing filled on the central tower of Coutances.

Note X.

Page 94.

"Ornaments of the transept towers of Rouen."

Page 94.

"Decorative features of the transept towers of Rouen."

The reader cannot but observe agreeableness, as a mere arrangement of shade, which especially belongs to the "sacred trefoil." I do not think that the element of foliation has been enough insisted upon in its intimate relations with the power of Gothic work. If I were asked what[Pg 208] was the most distinctive feature of its perfect style, I should say the Trefoil. It is the very soul of it; and I think the loveliest Gothic is always formed upon simple and bold tracings of it, taking place between the blank lancet arch on the one hand, and the overcharged cinquefoiled arch on the other.

The reader can't help but notice the charm that comes from the arrangement of shade, particularly found in the "sacred trefoil." I believe that the aspect of foliage hasn't been emphasized enough in its close connection to the strength of Gothic design. If you asked me what the most distinctive feature of its ideal style is, I would say it's the Trefoil. It embodies its essence, and I believe the most beautiful Gothic designs are always based on simple and bold outlines of it, positioned between the plain lancet arch on one side and the elaborately decorated cinquefoiled arch on the other.

Note 11.

Page 95.

"And levelled cusps of stone."

Page 95.

"And flattened stone edges."

The plate represents one of the lateral windows of the third story of the Palazzo Foscari. It was drawn from the opposite side of the Grand Canal, and the lines of its traceries are therefore given as they appear in somewhat distant effect. It shows only segments of the characteristic quatrefoils of the central windows. I found by measurement their construction exceedingly simple. Four circles are drawn in contact within the large circle. Two tangential lines are then drawn to each opposite pair, enclosing the four circles in a hollow cross. An inner circle struck through the intersections of the circles by the tangents, truncates the cusps.

The plate shows one of the side windows on the third floor of the Palazzo Foscari. It was sketched from across the Grand Canal, so the lines of its designs appear a bit distant. It only displays parts of the typical quatrefoils of the central windows. I discovered that their construction is very straightforward. Four circles are drawn in contact within a larger circle. Then, two lines are drawn tangentially to each opposite pair, creating a hollow cross that encloses the four circles. An inner circle is drawn through the intersections of the circles created by the tangents, trimming the cusps.

Note 12.

Page 124.

"Into vertical equal parts."

"Into equal vertical sections."

Not absolutely so. There are variations partly accidental (or at least compelled by the architect's effort to recover the vertical), between the sides of the stories; and the upper and lower story are taller than the rest. There is, however, an apparent equality between five out of the eight tiers.

Not completely so. There are some variations that are partly accidental (or at least forced by the architect's attempt to straighten things up), between the sides of the floors; and the upper and lower floors are taller than the others. However, there seems to be a noticeable equality between five out of the eight levels.

Note 13.

Page 133.

"Never paint a column with vertical lines."

Page 133.

"Don’t paint a column with vertical lines."

It should be observed, however, that any pattern which gives opponent lines in its parts, may be arranged on lines parallel with the main structure. Thus, rows of diamonds, like spots on a snake's back, or the bones on a sturgeon, are exquisitely applied both to vertical and spiral columns. The loveliest instances of such decoration that I know, are the pillars of the cloister of St. John Lateran, lately illustrated by Mr. Digby Wyatt, in his most valuable and faithful work on antique mosaic.

It should be noted, however, that any design featuring opposing lines can be arranged along lines parallel to the main structure. For example, rows of diamonds, resembling spots on a snake's back or the bones of a sturgeon, are beautifully applied to both vertical and spiral columns. The most stunning examples of such decoration that I know of are the pillars of the cloister of St. John Lateran, recently highlighted by Mr. Digby Wyatt in his invaluable and accurate work on antique mosaic.

Note 14.

On the cover of this volume the reader will find some figure outlines of the same period and character, from the floor of San Miniato at Florence. I have to thank its designer, Mr. W. Harry Rogers, for his intelligent arrangement of them, and graceful adaptation of the connecting arabesque. (Stamp on cloth cover of London edition.)

On the cover of this book, the reader will see some figure outlines from the same time and style, taken from the floor of San Miniato in Florence. I want to thank the designer, Mr. W. Harry Rogers, for his thoughtful arrangement of these figures and elegant adaptation of the connecting arabesque. (Stamp on the cloth cover of the London edition.)

Note 15.

Page 169.

"The flowers lost their light, the river its music."

Page 169.

"The flowers lost their brightness, the river its sound."

Yet not all their light, nor all their music. Compare Modern Painters, vol. ii. sec. 1. chap. iv. SECTION 8.

Yet not all their light, nor all their music. Compare Modern Painters, vol. ii. sec. 1. chap. iv. SECTION 8.

Note 16.

Page 181.

"By the artists of the time of Perides."

Page 181.

"Created by the artists during the era of Perides."

This subordination was first remarked to me by a friend, whose profound knowledge of Greek art will not, I trust, be reserved always for the advantage of his friends only: Mr. C. Newton, of the British Museum.

This subordination was first pointed out to me by a friend, whose deep understanding of Greek art I hope will not always be kept just for the benefit of his friends: Mr. C. Newton, of the British Museum.

Note 17.

Page 188.

"In one of the noblest poems."

Page 188.

"In one of the greatest poems."

Coleridge's Ode to France:

Coleridge's Ode to France:

"Ye Clouds! that far above me float and pause,
Whose pathless march no mortal may control!
Ye Ocean-Waves! that wheresoe'er ye roll,
Yield homage only to eternal laws!
Ye Woods! that listen to the night-birds singing.
Midway the smooth and perilous slope reclined,
Save when your own imperious branches swinging,
Have made a solemn music of the wind!
Where, like a man beloved of God,
Through glooms, which never woodman trod,
How oft, pursuing fancies holy,
My moonlight way o'er flowering weeds I wound,
Inspired, beyond the guess of folly,
[Pg 210]By each rude shape and wild unconquerable sound!
O ye loud Waves! and O ye Forests high!
And O ye Clouds that far above me soared!
Thou rising Sun! thou blue rejoicing Sky!
Yea, everything that is and will be free!
Bear witness for me, wheresoe'er ye be,
With what deep worship I have still adored
The spirit of divinest Liberty."

"Clouds! that float and pause above me,
Whose never-ending journey no one can manage!
Oceans that move wherever you want,
You bow only to eternal laws!
Woods that listen to the night birds singing,
Lying halfway down the smooth and perilous slope,
Except when your powerful branches swinging,
Compose a serious tune with the wind!
Where, like a person favored by God,
Through shadows that no woodsman has walked,
How often, pursuing sacred dreams,
I make my way in the moonlight over blooming weeds,
Inspired beyond what anyone could imagine,
[Pg 210]By each rough shape and wild, unyielding sound!
O loud Waves! and O tall Forests!
Oh, Clouds that flew high above me!
You rising Sun! you blue, joyful Sky!
Yes, everything that is and will be free!
Bear witness for me, no matter where you are,
To the deep admiration I have always shown
"To the spirit of true freedom."

Noble verse, but erring thought: contrast George Herbert:—

Noble verse, but misguided thought: compare George Herbert:—

"Slight those who say amidst their sickly healths,
Thou livest by rule. What doth not so but man?
Houses are built by rule and Commonwealths.
Entice the trusty sun, if that you can,
From his ecliptic line; beckon the sky.
Who lives by rule then, keeps good company.

"Who keeps no guard upon himself is slack,
And rots to nothing at the next great thaw;
Man is a shop of rules: a well-truss'd pack
Whose every parcel underwrites a law.
Lose not thyself, nor give thy humors way;
God gave them to thee under lock and key."

"Don't listen to those who say, despite their poor health, You live by the rules. Who doesn't, if not humanity? Buildings are constructed by rules and societies. Try to lure the dependable sun, if you can, From its usual path; call to the sky. Who lives by the rules, then, surrounds themselves with good company. "Anyone who doesn't keep control over themselves is lazy, And falls apart at the first big change; Humans are a bundle of rules: a well-organized package Where each part is tied to a particular law. Don't lose yourself, nor let your moods take over; God gave them to you with a lock and key."

FOOTNOTES:

[A] The inordinate delay in the appearance of that supplementary volume has, indeed, been chiefly owing to the necessity under which the writer felt himself, of obtaining as many memoranda as possible of mediæval buildings in Italy and Normandy, now in process of destruction, before that destruction should be consummated by the Restorer or Revolutionist. His whole time has been lately occupied in taking drawings from one side of buildings, of which masons were knocking down the other; nor can he yet pledge himself to any time for the publication of the conclusion of "Modern Painters;" he can only promise that its delay shall not be owing to any indolence on his part.

[A] The long wait for that extra volume has mostly been due to the author needing to gather as many notes as possible on medieval buildings in Italy and Normandy that are currently being destroyed, before that destruction is completed by restorers or revolutionaries. Recently, he has spent all his time sketching one side of buildings while masons were tearing down the other. He cannot commit to a specific timeline for the release of the conclusion of "Modern Painters"; he can only assure that its delay isn't due to any laziness on his part.

[B] 2 Sam. xxiv. 24. Deut. xvi. 16, 17.

[B] 2 Sam. 24:24. Deut. 16:16, 17.

[C] Mal. i. 8.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Mal. 1:8.

[D] Lam. ii. 11. 2 Kings xvii. 25.

[D] Lam. ii. 11. 2 Kings xvii. 25.

[E] Num. xxxi. 54. Psa. lxxvi. 11.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Num. 31:54. Ps. 76:11.

[F] John xii. 5.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ John 12:5.

[G] Mod. Painters, Part I. Sec. 1, Chap. 3.

[G] Mod. Painters, Part I. Sec. 1, Chap. 3.

[H] Henceforward, for the sake of convenience, when I name any cathedral town in this manner, let me be understood to speak of its cathedral church.

[H] From now on, for simplicity, when I mention any cathedral town like this, I mean its cathedral church.

[I] Literature of the Fine Arts.—Essay on Bas-relief.

Fine Arts Literature.—Essay on Bas-relief.




        
        
    
Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!