This is a modern-English version of Essays, originally written by Hume, David. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

ESSAYS

By

DAVID HUME

With Biographical Introduction

by

Hannaford Bennett

LONDON
JOHN LONG LTD

Contents

Contents


Biographical Introduction

The material facts in Hume's life are to be found in the autobiography which he prefixed to his History of England. My Own Life, as he calls it, is but a brief exposition, but it is sufficient for its purpose, and the longer biographies of him do little more than amplify the information which he gives us himself. The Humes, it appears, were a remote branch of the family of Lord Hume of Douglas. Hume's father was Joseph Hume, of Ninewells, a minor Scotch laird, who died when his son was an infant. David Hume was born at Edinburgh on April 26th, 1711, during a visit of his parents to the Scotch capital. Hume tells us that his father passed for a man of parts, and that his mother, who herself came of good Scottish family, "was a woman of singular merit; though young and handsome, she devoted herself entirely to the rearing and educating of her children." At school Hume won no special distinction. He matriculated in the class of Greek at the Edinburgh University when he was twelve years old, and, he says "passed through the ordinary course of education with success"; but "our college education in Scotland," he remarks in one of his works, "extending little further than the languages, ends commonly when we are about fourteen or fifteen years of age." During his youth, Mrs. Hume does not appear to have maintained any too flattering opinion of her son's abilities; she considered him a good-natured but "uncommon weak-minded" creature. Possibly her judgment underwent a change in course of time, since she lived to see the beginnings of his literary fame; but his worldly success was long in the making, and he was a middle-aged man before his meagre fortune was converted into anything like a decent maintenance.

The main facts about Hume's life can be found in the autobiography he included in his History of England. My Own Life, as he calls it, is a short overview, but it serves its purpose well, and the longer biographies mainly expand on the details he provides himself. The Humes were a distant branch of the family of Lord Hume of Douglas. Hume's father was Joseph Hume of Ninewells, a minor Scottish landowner, who died when Hume was just a baby. David Hume was born in Edinburgh on April 26, 1711, during a visit by his parents to the Scottish capital. Hume notes that his father was regarded as a man of talent, and that his mother, who came from a respectable Scottish family, “was a woman of unique merit; although young and beautiful, she dedicated herself entirely to raising and educating her children.” At school, Hume didn't stand out in any particular way. He enrolled in the Greek class at Edinburgh University when he was twelve and mentions that he "went through the usual course of education successfully"; however, he observes in one of his works that "our college education in Scotland," which focuses primarily on languages, typically ends when we are around fourteen or fifteen years old. During his youth, Mrs. Hume didn't seem to have a very high opinion of her son’s abilities; she saw him as a good-natured but "rather simple-minded" person. Perhaps her perspective changed over time since she witnessed the start of his literary success; however, his path to worldly success was slow, and he was a middle-aged man before his limited fortune turned into a stable income.

It may have been Hume's apparent vacillation in choosing a career that made this "shrewd Scots wife" hold her son in such small esteem. At first the family tried to launch him into the profession of the law, but "while they fancied I was poring over Voet and Vinnius, Cicero and Virgil were the authors I was secretly devouring." For six years Hume remained at Ninewells and then made "a feeble trial for entering on a more active scene of life." Commerce, this time, was the chosen instrument, but the result was not more successful. "In 1734 I went to Bristol with some recommendations to eminent merchants, but in a few months found that scene totally unsuitable for me." At length—in the middle of 1736 when Hume was twenty-three years of age and without any profession or means of earning a livelihood—he went over to France. He settled first at Rheims, and afterwards at La Flêche in Anjou, and "there I laid that plan of life which I have steadily and successfully pursued. I resolved to make a very rigid frugality supply my deficiency of fortune, to maintain unimpaired my independency, and to regard every object as contemptible except the improvement of my talents in literature." At La Flêche Hume lived in frequent intercourse with the Jesuits at the famous college in which Descartes was educated, and he composed his first book, the Treatise of Human Nature. According to himself "it fell dead-born from the press, without reaching such distinction as even to excite a murmur among the zealots." But this work which was planned before the author was twenty-one and written before he was twenty-five, in the opinion of Professor Huxley, is probably the most remarkable philosophical work, both intrinsically and in its effects upon the course of thought, that has ever been written. Three years later Hume published anonymously, at Edinburgh, the first volume of Essays, Moral and Political, which was followed in 1742 by the second volume. The Essays, he says, were favourably received and soon made me entirely forget my former disappointments.

It might have been Hume's indecision about his career that caused this "shrewd Scots wife" to think so little of her son. Initially, the family tried to push him into law, but "while they thought I was focusing on Voet and Vinnius, Cicero and Virgil were the authors I was secretly reading." Hume stayed at Ninewells for six years before making "a weak attempt to start a more active life." This time, he chose commerce, but it didn't go any better. "In 1734, I went to Bristol with some recommendations from prominent merchants, but within a few months, I realized that place was totally unsuitable for me." Eventually—in the middle of 1736, when Hume was twenty-three and without any career or way to make a living—he moved to France. He first settled in Rheims and then in La Flêche in Anjou, where "I laid out the plan for my life that I have followed steadily and successfully. I decided to let strict frugality make up for my lack of wealth, to keep my independence intact, and to treat everything as unimportant except for improving my talents in literature." In La Flêche, Hume regularly interacted with the Jesuits at the famous college where Descartes was educated, and he wrote his first book, the Treatise of Human Nature. According to him, "it was dead on arrival when published, failing to gain any recognition or even provoke a reaction among the zealots." But this work, which he planned before he turned twenty-one and completed before he was twenty-five, is considered by Professor Huxley to be one of the most outstanding philosophical works ever written, both in its content and its impact on the course of thought. Three years later, Hume published the first volume of Essays, Moral and Political anonymously in Edinburgh, followed in 1742 by the second volume. He mentions that the Essays were well received and soon made him completely forget his earlier disappointments.

In 1745 Hume became tutor to a young nobleman, the Marquis of Annandale, who was mentally affected, but he did not endure the engagement for long. Next year General St. Clair, who had been appointed to command an expedition in the War of the Pragmatic Sanction, invited him to be his secretary, an office to which that of judge-advocate was afterwards added. The expedition was a failure, but General St. Clair, who was afterwards entrusted with embassies to Turin and Vienna, and upon whom Hume seems to have created a favourable impression, insisted that he should accompany him in the same capacity as secretary; he further made him one of his aides-de-camp. Thus Hume had to attire his portly figure in a "scarlet military uniform," and Lord Charlemont who met him in Turin says that he wore his uniform "like a grocer of the train-bands." At Vienna the Empress-Dowager excused him on ceremonial occasions from walking backwards, a concession which was much appreciated by "my companions who were desperately afraid of my falling on them and crushing them." Hume returned to London in 1749. "These years," he says, "were almost the only interruptions my studies have received during the course of my life. I passed them agreeably and in good company, and my appointments, with my frugality, had made me reach a fortune which I called independent, though most of my friends were inclined to smile when I said so; in short, I was now master of near a thousand pounds."

In 1745, Hume became a tutor to a young nobleman, the Marquis of Annandale, who had some mental challenges, but he didn't stick with it for long. The next year, General St. Clair, who had been appointed to lead an expedition during the War of the Pragmatic Sanction, invited him to be his secretary, a role he later combined with that of judge-advocate. The expedition ended up being a failure, but General St. Clair, who was later appointed for missions to Turin and Vienna, seemed to have made a good impression on Hume and insisted that he come along in the same role as secretary; he also made him one of his aides-de-camp. So, Hume had to dress his hefty figure in a "scarlet military uniform," and Lord Charlemont, who encountered him in Turin, remarked that he wore his uniform "like a grocer of the train-bands." In Vienna, the Empress-Dowager allowed him to skip walking backward during ceremonial occasions, a concession that was greatly appreciated by "my companions who were desperately afraid of my falling on them and crushing them." Hume returned to London in 1749. "These years," he says, "were almost the only interruptions my studies have received during the course of my life. I passed them pleasantly and in good company, and my appointments, along with my frugality, had helped me accumulate a fortune that I called independent, even though most of my friends tended to smile when I said so; in short, I was now in possession of nearly a thousand pounds."

While Hume was away with General St. Clair his Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding was published, but it was not more successful than the original Treatise of a portion of which it was a recasting. A new edition of Moral and Political Essays met with no better fate, but these disappointments, he says, "made little or no impression" on him. In 1749 Hume returned to Ninewells, and lived for a while with his brothers. Afterwards he took a flat of his own at Edinburgh, with his sister to keep house for him. At this period the Political Discourses and the Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals were published. Of the Inquiry Hume held the opinion, an opinion, however, which was not shared by the critics, that "it is of all my writings—historical, philosophical, or literary incomparably the best." Slowly and surely his publications were growing in reputation. In 1752 the Faculty of Advocates elected Hume their librarian, an office which was valuable to him, not so much for the emolument as for the extensive library which enabled him to pursue the historical studies upon which he had for some time been engaged. For the next nine years he was occupied with his History of England. The first volume was published in 1754, and the second volume, which met with a better reception than the first, in 1756. Only forty-five copies of the first volume were sold in a twelvemonth; but the subsequent volumes made rapid headway, and raised a great clamour, for in the words of Macaulay, Hume's historical picture, though drawn by a master hand, has all the lights Tory and all the shades Whig. In 1757 one of his most remarkable works, the Natural History of Religion, appeared. The book was attacked—not wholly to Hume's dissatisfaction, for he appreciated fame as well as success—"with all the illiberal petulance, arrogance, and scurrility which distinguish the Warburtonian school."

While Hume was away with General St. Clair, his Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding was published, but it wasn't any more successful than the original Treatise, of which it was a reworking. A new edition of Moral and Political Essays faced the same fate, but these disappointments, he said, "made little or no impression" on him. In 1749, Hume returned to Ninewells and lived for a while with his brothers. Later, he got his own flat in Edinburgh, with his sister handling the household. During this time, Political Discourses and Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals were published. Hume believed that the Inquiry was, in his opinion—though not shared by critics—"the best of all my writings—historical, philosophical, or literary." Gradually, his publications were gaining recognition. In 1752, the Faculty of Advocates elected Hume as their librarian, a role that benefited him, not so much for the salary, but for the extensive library that allowed him to continue his historical studies, which he had been working on for some time. For the next nine years, he focused on his History of England. The first volume was published in 1754, and the second volume, which was better received than the first, came out in 1756. Only forty-five copies of the first volume were sold in its first year; however, the later volumes gained traction quickly and stirred up considerable attention, as Macaulay put it, Hume's historical portrayal, although crafted by a master, contained all the lights of Tory and all the shades of Whig. In 1757, one of his most notable works, the Natural History of Religion, was released. The book faced criticism—not entirely to Hume's discontent, as he valued fame as much as success—"with all the petty spite, arrogance, and vulgarity that characterize the Warburtonian school."

Hume remained in Edinburgh superintending the publication of the History until 1763 when Lord Hertford, who had been appointed ambassador to France, offered him office in the embassy, with the promise of the secretaryship later on. The appointment was the more honourable, inasmuch as Hume was not personally acquainted with Lord Hertford, who had a reputation for virtue and piety, whilst Hume's views about religion had rendered him one of the best abused men of his time. In France Hume's reputation stood higher than it was in England; several of his works had been translated into French; and he had corresponded with Montesquieu, Helvetius and Rousseau. Thus he was received in French society with every mark of distinction. In a letter to Adam Smith in October 1763, he wrote: "I have been three days at Paris and two at Fontainebleau, and have everywhere met with the most extraordinary honours, which the most exorbitant vanity could wish or desire." Great nobles fêted him, and great ladies struggled for the presence of the "gros David" at their receptions or in their boxes at the theatre. "At the opera his broad unmeaning face was usually to be seen entre deux joli minois," says Lord Charlemont. Hume took his honours with satisfaction, but with becoming good sense, and he did not allow these flatteries to turn his head.

Hume stayed in Edinburgh overseeing the publication of the History until 1763, when Lord Hertford, who had been appointed ambassador to France, offered him a position in the embassy, promising him the secretary role later on. The appointment was particularly prestigious since Hume didn’t know Lord Hertford personally, who was known for his virtue and piety, while Hume’s views on religion had made him one of the most criticized men of his time. In France, Hume’s reputation was higher than in England; several of his works had been translated into French, and he had corresponded with Montesquieu, Helvetius, and Rousseau. As a result, he was welcomed in French society with great respect. In a letter to Adam Smith in October 1763, he wrote: "I have been three days in Paris and two in Fontainebleau, and have everywhere received the most extraordinary honors that the most excessive vanity could wish or desire." High-ranking nobles celebrated him, and prominent ladies competed for the presence of the "gros David" at their gatherings or in their theater boxes. "At the opera, his broad, expressionless face was usually seen entre deux joli minois," says Lord Charlemont. Hume accepted his honors with satisfaction and common sense, not letting the flattery go to his head.

In 1767 Hume was back in London, and for the next two years held office as Under-Secretary of State. It is not necessary to dwell upon this period of his life, or to go into the details of his quarrel with Rousseau. In 1769 he returned to Edinburgh "very opulent" in the possession of £1,000 a year, and determined to take the rest of his life easily and pleasantly. He built himself a house in Edinburgh, and for the next six years it was the centre of the most accomplished society in the city. In 1755 Hume's health began to fail, and he knew that his illness must be fatal. Thus he made his will and wrote My Own Life, which ends simply in these words:

In 1767, Hume returned to London and served as Under-Secretary of State for the next two years. There's no need to focus on this part of his life or the details of his disagreements with Rousseau. In 1769, he went back to Edinburgh "very wealthy," with an income of £1,000 a year, and was determined to live the rest of his life comfortably and happily. He built a house in Edinburgh, which became the hub of the city's most refined society for the next six years. By 1755, Hume's health started to decline, and he realized his illness would be fatal. So, he made his will and wrote My Own Life, which concludes simply with these words:

"I now reckon upon a speedy dissolution. I have suffered very little pain from my disorder; and what is more strange have, notwithstanding the great decline of my person, never suffered a moment's abatement of spirits; insomuch that were I to name the period of my life which I should most choose to pass over again, I might be tempted to point to this later period. I possess the same ardour as ever in study, and the same gaiety in company; I consider, besides, that a man of sixty-five, by dying, cuts off only a few years of infirmities; and though I see many symptoms of my literary reputation's breaking out at last with additional lustre, I know that I could have but few years to enjoy it. It is difficult to be more detached from life than I am at present.

"I expect to pass away soon. I've felt very little pain from my illness; and strangely enough, despite my physical decline, I've never felt down. In fact, if I had to choose a time in my life to relive, I might choose this later stage. I still have the same enthusiasm for studying and the same joy in socializing; plus, I believe that at sixty-five, dying just means skipping a few years of difficulties. Even though I see many signs that my literary reputation is finally shining even brighter, I know I wouldn't have many years left to enjoy it. It’s hard to be more detached from life than I am right now."

"To conclude historically with my own character, I am, or rather was (for that is the style I must now use in speaking of myself); I was, I say, a man of mild dispositions, of command of temper, of an open, social, and cheerful humour, capable of attachment, but little susceptible of enmity, and of great moderation in all my passions. Even my love of literary fame, my ruling passion, never soured my temper, notwithstanding my frequent disappointments. My company was not unacceptable to the young and careless, as well as to the studious and literary; and as I took a particular pleasure in the company of modest women, I had no reason to be displeased with the reception I met with from them. In a word, though most men any wise eminent, have found reason to complain of calumny, I never was touched or even attacked by her baleful tooth; and though I wantonly exposed myself to the rage of both civil and religious factions, they seemed to be disarmed in my behalf of their wonted fury. My friends never had occasion to vindicate any one circumstance of my character and conduct; not but that the zealots, we may well suppose, would have been glad to invent and propagate any story to my disadvantage, but they could never find any which they thought would wear the face of probability. I cannot say there is no vanity in making this funeral oration of myself, but I hope it is not a misplaced one; and this is a matter of fact which is easily cleared and ascertained."

"To summarize my historical reflection on myself, I am, or rather was (since that's how I should now refer to myself); I was, as I mentioned, a gentle person, with good self-control, a friendly, sociable, and cheerful attitude, capable of forming attachments but not easily prone to hostility, and very moderate in all my emotions. Even my desire for literary recognition, my driving passion, never dampened my mood, despite my regular disappointments. People, both carefree young ones and serious literary types, generally enjoyed my company; and since I particularly enjoyed the company of modest women, I had no reason to feel dissatisfied with how they received me. In short, although many notable men have found reasons to complain about slander, I was never affected by its harmful sting; and although I carelessly put myself in the path of both civil and religious factions, they seemed to quiet down on my behalf. My friends never had to defend any aspect of my character or behavior; not that the zealots wouldn’t have loved to create and spread stories against me, but they could never find one that seemed credible. I can't deny there’s some vanity in giving this eulogy for myself, but I hope it's not misplaced; this is something that can be easily proven and confirmed."

Hume died in Edinburgh on August 25th, 1776, and a few days later was buried in a spot selected by himself on the Carlton Hill.

Hume passed away in Edinburgh on August 25, 1776, and a few days later was laid to rest in a location he had chosen himself on Carlton Hill.

HANNAFORD BENNETT

HANNAFORD BENNETT


Essays


OF THE DELICACY OF TASTE AND PASSION

Some people are subject to a certain delicacy of passion, which makes them extremely sensible to all the accidents of life, and gives them a lively joy upon every prosperous event, as well as a piercing grief when they meet with misfortune and adversity. Favours and good offices easily engage their friendship, while the smallest injury provokes their resentment. Any honour or mark of distinction elevates them above measure, but they are sensibly touched with contempt. People of this character have, no doubt, more lively enjoyments, as well as more pungent sorrows, than men of cool and sedate tempers. But, I believe, when every thing is balanced, there is no one who would not rather be of the latter character, were he entirely master of his own disposition. Good or ill fortune is very little at our disposal; and when a person that has this sensibility of temper meets with any misfortune, his sorrow or resentment takes entire possession of him, and deprives him of all relish in the common occurrences of life, the right enjoyment of which forms the chief part of our happiness. Great pleasures are much less frequent than great pains, so that a sensible temper must meet with, fewer trials in the former way than in the latter. Not to mention, that men of such lively passions are apt to be transported beyond all bounds of prudence and discretion, and to take false steps in the conduct of life, which are often irretrievable.

Some people have a certain delicacy of passion, making them very sensitive to all life’s ups and downs. They experience intense joy with every success and deep sadness when faced with misfortune and hardship. Kindness and good deeds easily win their friendship, while even the slightest offense sparks their anger. Any recognition or honor lifts their spirits immensely, but they feel hurt deeply by disdain. Such people undoubtedly experience more vivid joys and sharper sorrows than those with calm and steady temperaments. However, I believe that if given the choice, most would prefer to be of the latter nature, fully in control of their own feelings. Good or bad luck is largely out of our hands; and when someone with this sensitive temperament encounters misfortune, their sorrow or anger completely overwhelms them, robbing them of the enjoyment in everyday life, which is essential to our happiness. Great pleasures are much rarer than great pains, so a sensitive temperament endures fewer challenges in joy than in sorrow. Not to mention, individuals with intense emotions often go beyond the limits of reason and discretion, leading to misguided decisions in life that can be hard to recover from.

There is a delicacy of taste observable in some men, which very much resembles this delicacy of passion, and produces the same sensibility to beauty and deformity of every kind, as that does to prosperity and adversity, obligations and injuries. When you present a poem or a picture to a man possessed of this talent, the delicacy of his feeling makes him be sensibly touched with every part of it; nor are the masterly strokes perceived with more exquisite relish and satisfaction, than the negligences or absurdities with disgust and uneasiness. A polite and judicious conversation affords him the highest entertainment; rudeness or impertinence is as great punishment to him. In short, delicacy of taste has the same effect as delicacy of passion. It enlarges the sphere both of our happiness and misery, and makes us sensible to pains as well as pleasures which escape the rest of mankind.

There is a delicacy of taste seen in some men, which closely resembles this delicacy of passion, creating the same sensitivity to beauty and ugliness of all kinds, just as it does to fortune and misfortune, duties and wrongs. When you show a poem or a painting to a man with this ability, his sensitivity allows him to be deeply affected by every aspect of it; he perceives the brilliant details with as much enjoyment and satisfaction as he feels disgust and discomfort towards the mistakes or absurdities. Polite and thoughtful conversation provides him with the greatest pleasure; rudeness or lack of respect feels like a severe punishment to him. In short, delicacy of taste has the same impact as delicacy of passion. It broadens our experiences of both happiness and sadness, making us aware of pains as well as pleasures that others might overlook.

I believe, however, every one will agree with me, that notwithstanding this resemblance, delicacy of taste is as much to be desired and cultivated, as delicacy of passion is to be lamented, and to be remedied, if possible. The good or ill accidents of life are very little at our disposal; but we are pretty much masters what books we shall read, what diversions we shall partake of, and what company we shall keep. Philosophers have endeavoured to render happiness entirely independent of every thing external. The degree of perfection is impossible to be attained; but every wise man will endeavour to place his happiness on such objects chiefly as depend upon himself; and that is not to be attained so much by any other means as by this delicacy of sentiment. When a man is possessed of that talent, he is more happy by what pleases his taste, than by what gratifies his appetites, and receives more enjoyment from a poem, or a piece of reasoning, than the most expensive luxury can afford.

I believe, however, everyone will agree with me that, despite this similarity, having refined taste is just as desirable and important to nurture as having refined emotions is something to be regretted and fixed if possible. We have very little control over the good or bad events in life, but we largely have the power to choose which books we read, what activities we engage in, and who we associate with. Philosophers have tried to make happiness completely independent of anything external. Achieving perfection is impossible, but every wise person will strive to base their happiness on things that depend mostly on themselves; and that isn’t achieved as much through other means as it is through this refined sense of feeling. When someone possesses that talent, they find more happiness in what pleases their taste than in what satisfies their desires, and they derive more enjoyment from a poem or a thoughtful discussion than from the most extravagant luxury.

Whatever connection there may be originally between these two species of delicacy, I am persuaded that nothing is so proper to cure us of this delicacy of passion, as the cultivating of that higher and more refined taste, which enables us to judge of the characters of men, of the compositions of genius, and of the productions of the nobler arts. A greater or less relish for those obvious beauties which strike the senses, depends entirely upon the greater or less sensibility of the temper; but with regard to the sciences and liberal arts, a fine taste is, in some measure, the same with strong sense, or at least depends so much upon it that they are inseparable. In order to judge aright of a composition of genius, there are so many views to be taken in, so many circumstances to be compared, and such a knowledge of human nature requisite, that no man, who is not possessed of the soundest judgment, will ever make a tolerable critic in such performances. And this is a new reason for cultivating a relish in the liberal arts. Our judgment will strengthen by this exercise. We shall form juster notions of life. Many things which please or afflict others, will appear to us too frivolous to engage our attention; and we shall lose by degrees that sensibility and delicacy of passion which is so incommodious.

Whatever connection there may originally be between these two types of delicacy, I believe that nothing better helps us overcome our sensitivity of passion than developing a higher and more refined taste. This taste allows us to evaluate people's character, appreciate genius in creativity, and recognize the achievements of the finer arts. Our varying levels of appreciation for obvious beauties that appeal to our senses depend entirely on our sensitivity. However, when it comes to the sciences and the liberal arts, a fine taste is somewhat synonymous with strong judgment, or at least relies heavily on it, making them inseparable. To correctly evaluate a masterpiece, there are numerous perspectives to consider, various circumstances to compare, and a deep understanding of human nature required. No one who lacks sound judgment can be a decent critic of such works. This provides yet another reason to cultivate an appreciation for the liberal arts. Our judgment will improve through this practice. We’ll develop a clearer understanding of life, and many things that please or upset others will seem too trivial for us to care about. Over time, we'll lose the sensitivity and delicacy of passion that often become a burden.

But perhaps I have gone too far, in saying that a cultivated taste for the polite arts extinguishes the passions, and renders us indifferent to those objects which are so fondly pursued by the rest of mankind. On further reflection, I find, that it rather improves our sensibility for all the tender and agreeable passions; at the same time that it renders the mind incapable of the rougher and more boisterous emotions.

But maybe I went too far in saying that a refined appreciation for the polite arts kills our passions and makes us indifferent to the things that most people passionately pursue. On second thought, I realize that it actually enhances our sensitivity to all the gentle and pleasant emotions, while also making our minds less capable of handling the harsher and more intense feelings.

Ingenuas didicisse fideliter artes,
Emollit mores, nec sinit esse feros.

The innocent have really mastered the skills,
It softens their personality and prevents them from being wild.

For this, I think, there may be assigned two very natural reasons. In the first place, nothing is so improving to the temper as the study of the beauties either of poetry, eloquence, music, or painting. They give a certain elegance of sentiment to which the rest of mankind are strangers. The emotions which they excite are soft and tender. They draw off the mind from the hurry of business and interest; cherish reflection; dispose to tranquillity; and produce an agreeable melancholy, which, of all dispositions of the mind, is the best suited to love and friendship.

For this, I believe there are two very obvious reasons. First, nothing improves our mood like studying the beauty of poetry, eloquence, music, or painting. They provide a certain elegance of feeling that most people don’t experience. The emotions they stir are gentle and tender. They take our minds away from the chaos of work and obligations; encourage reflection; promote peace; and create a pleasant melancholy that is, of all the states of mind, best suited for love and friendship.

In the second place, a delicacy of taste is favourable to love and friendship, by confining our choice to few people, and making us indifferent to the company and conversation of the greater part of men. You will seldom find that mere men of the world, whatever strong sense they may be endowed with, are very nice in distinguishing characters, or in marking those insensible differences and gradations, which make one man preferable to another. Any one that has competent sense is sufficient for their entertainment. They talk to him of their pleasures and affairs, with the same frankness that they would to another; and finding many who are fit to supply his place, they never feel any vacancy or want in his absence. But to make use of the allusion of a celebrated French[1] author, the judgment may be compared to a clock or watch, where the most ordinary machine is sufficient to tell the hours; but the most elaborate alone can point out the minutes and seconds, and distinguish the smallest differences of time. One that has well digested his knowledge both of books and men, has little enjoyment but in the company of a few select companions. He feels too sensibly, how much all the rest of mankind fall short of the notions which he has entertained. And, his affections being thus confined within a narrow circle, no wonder he carries them further than if they were more general and undistinguished. The gaiety and frolic of a bottle companion improves with him into a solid friendship; and the ardours of a youthful appetite become an elegant passion.

In the second place, having refined tastes is beneficial for love and friendship because it limits our choices to just a few people and makes us less interested in the company and conversations of most people. You’ll rarely find that ordinary people, no matter how intelligent they may be, are very skilled at differentiating between characters or noticing the subtle differences and nuances that make one person better than another. Anyone with decent sense is enough for their entertainment. They talk to him about their pleasures and issues with the same openness they would with anyone else, and since they find many who can take his place, they never feel any emptiness or need in his absence. To use the analogy of a well-known French[1] author, judgment can be likened to a clock or watch; a simple timepiece is enough to tell the time, but only a more sophisticated one can indicate minutes and seconds and recognize the slightest differences in time. Someone who has thoroughly absorbed knowledge from both books and life enjoys little more than the company of a few select friends. He acutely feels how far the rest of humanity falls short of the ideas he holds. And with his affections limited to a small circle, it’s no surprise that he feelings run deeper than if they were more widespread and indistinct. The joy and fun of a casual drinking buddy turns into a deep friendship with him, and the passions of youthful desire mature into a refined affection.

[1] Mons. Fontenelle, Pluralité des Mondes, Soir 6.

[1] Mons. Fontenelle, Pluralité des Mondes, Soir 6.


OF THE LIBERTY OF THE PRESS

Nothing is more apt to surprise a foreigner, than the extreme liberty which we enjoy in this country of communicating whatever we please to the public and of openly censuring every measure entered into by the king or his ministers. If the administration resolve upon war, it is affirmed, that, either wilfully or ignorantly, they mistake the interests of the nation; and that peace, in the present situation of affairs, is infinitely preferable. If the passion of the ministers lie towards peace, our political writers breathe nothing but war and devastation, and represent the specific conduct of the government as mean and pusillanimous. As this liberty is not indulged in any other government, either republican or monarchical; in Holland and Venice, more than in France or Spain; it may very naturally give occasion to the question, How it happens that Great Britain alone enjoys this peculiar privilege?

Nothing surprises a foreigner more than the extreme freedom we have in this country to share what we want with the public and to openly criticize any actions taken by the king or his ministers. If the government decides to go to war, it's claimed that, whether intentionally or out of ignorance, they misunderstand the nation's interests; and that in the current situation, peace is far better. If the ministers favor peace, our political writers are all about war and destruction, portraying the government's actions as cowardly and lowly. Since this kind of freedom isn’t found in any other government, whether republican or monarchical, not even in places like Holland and Venice, more than in France or Spain, it naturally raises the question, How is it that Great Britain alone enjoys this unique privilege?

The reason why the laws indulge us in such a liberty, seems to be derived from our mixed form of government, which is neither wholly monarchical, nor wholly republican. It will be found, if I mistake not, a true observation in politics, that the two extremes in government, liberty and slavery, commonly approach nearest to each other; and that, as you depart from the extremes, and mix a little of monarchy with liberty, the government becomes always the more free; and, on the other hand, when you mix a little of liberty with monarchy, the yoke becomes always the more grievous and intolerable. In a government, such as that of France, which is absolute, and where law, custom, and religion concur, all of them, to make the people fully satisfied with their condition, the monarch cannot entertain any jealousy against his subjects, and therefore is apt to indulge them in great liberties, both of speech and action. In a government altogether republican, such as that of Holland, where there is no magistrate so eminent as to give jealousy to the state, there is no danger in intrusting the magistrates with large discretionary powers; and though many advantages result from such powers, in preserving peace and order, yet they lay a considerable restraint on men's actions, and make every private citizen pay a great respect to the government. Thus it seems evident, that the two extremes of absolute monarchy and of a republic, approach near to each other in some material circumstances. In the first, the magistrate has no jealousy of the people; in the second, the people have none of the magistrate: which want of jealousy begets a mutual confidence and trust in both cases, and produces a species of liberty in monarchies, and of arbitrary power in republics.

The reason the laws allow us such freedom seems to come from our mixed form of government, which isn't completely monarchical or completely republican. It appears to be a true political observation that the two extremes of government, liberty and slavery, often get close to each other; and as you move away from those extremes and blend a bit of monarchy with liberty, the government tends to become freer. Conversely, when you mix a bit of liberty with monarchy, the burden becomes heavier and more unbearable. In a government like France’s, which is absolute, and where law, custom, and religion all work together to keep the people content with their situation, the monarch has no reason to feel any jealousy toward his subjects, and therefore is likely to grant them significant liberties in both speech and actions. In a completely republican government, like that of Holland, where there isn't any magistrate so prominent as to create jealousy within the state, there’s no risk in giving magistrates considerable discretionary powers; and while these powers can bring many benefits in maintaining peace and order, they also impose a considerable restraint on individuals' actions and lead every private citizen to show great respect for the government. Thus, it's clear that the two extremes of absolute monarchy and a republic share some important similarities. In the first, the magistrate feels no jealousy of the people; in the second, the people feel none toward the magistrate: this absence of jealousy fosters mutual trust and confidence in both scenarios, creating a form of liberty in monarchies and a form of arbitrary power in republics.

To justify the other part of the foregoing observation, that, in every government, the means are most wide of each other, and that the mixtures of monarchy and liberty render the yoke either more grievous; I must take notice of a remark in Tacitus with regard to the Romans under the Emperors, that they neither could bear total slavery nor total liberty, Nec totam servitutem, nec totam libertatem pati possunt. This remark a celebrated poet has translated and applied to the English, in his lively description of Queen Elizabeth's policy and government.

To elaborate on the previous point, that in every government, the means are often quite different from one another, and that the mix of monarchy and freedom makes the burden either heavier, I should mention a comment from Tacitus about the Romans under the Emperors, that they could neither endure complete slavery nor complete freedom, Nec totam servitutem, nec totam libertatem pati possunt. A well-known poet has translated this observation and applied it to the English in his vivid portrayal of Queen Elizabeth's policies and governance.

Et fit aimer son joug à l'Anglois indompté,
Qui ne peut ni servir, ni vivre en liberté.
HENRIADE, liv. i.

And he comes to appreciate the challenges of the wild English,
Who can neither serve nor live freely.
HENRIADE, Book 1.

According to these remarks, we are to consider the Roman government under the Emperors as a mixture of despotism and liberty, where the despotism prevailed; and the English government as a mixture of the same kind, where the liberty predominates. The consequences are conformable to the foregoing observation, and such as may be expected from those mixed forms of government, which beget a mutual watchfulness and jealousy. The Roman emperors were, many of them, the most frightful tyrants that ever disgraced human nature; and it is evident, that their cruelty was chiefly excited by their jealousy, and by their observing that all the great men of Rome bore with impatience the dominion of a family, which, but a little before, was nowise superior to their own. On the other hand, as the republican part of the government prevails in England, though with a great mixture of monarchy, it is obliged, for its own preservation, to maintain a watchful jealousy over the magistrates, to remove all discretionary powers, and to secure every one's life and fortune by general and inflexible laws. No action must be deemed a crime but what the law has plainly determined to be such: no crime must be imputed to a man but from a legal proof before his judges; and even these judges must be his fellow-subjects, who are obliged, by their own interest, to have a watchful eye over the encroachments and violence of the ministers. From these causes it proceeds, that there is as much liberty, and even perhaps licentiousness, in Great Britain, as there were formerly slavery and tyranny in Rome.

According to these comments, we should view the Roman government under the Emperors as a mix of oppression and freedom, where oppression was dominant; and the English government as a similar mix, where freedom is the stronger element. The outcomes align with the previous point and are what we can expect from these mixed forms of government, which lead to mutual vigilance and mistrust. Many of the Roman emperors were among the most horrific tyrants to ever shame humanity; their cruelty was largely driven by their jealousy, noticing that all the prominent figures of Rome were impatient with being ruled by a family that had, not long before, been no better than their own. On the flip side, since the republican aspect of the government is stronger in England, despite the significant presence of monarchy, it must, for its own survival, keep a constant jealousy over the officials, eliminate all discretionary powers, and ensure everyone's life and property are protected by clear and unwavering laws. No act should be considered a crime unless it is explicitly defined as such by the law; no crime should be attributed to someone without legal proof before their peers; and even these judges must be fellow citizens who, out of their own interest, are required to keep a close watch on the abuses and violence of those in power. Because of these factors, there is as much freedom, and perhaps even excess, in Great Britain as there was once slavery and tyranny in Rome.

These principles account for the great liberty of the press in these kingdoms, beyond what is indulged in any other government. It is apprehended that arbitrary power would steal in upon us, were we not careful to prevent its progress, and were there not any easy method of conveying the alarm from one end of the kingdom to the other. The spirit of the people must frequently be roused, in order to curb the ambition of the court; and the dread of rousing this spirit must be employed to prevent that ambition. Nothing so effectual to this purpose as the liberty of the press; by which all the learning, wit, and genius of the nation, may be employed on the side of freedom, and every one be animated to its defence. As long, therefore, as the republican part of our government can maintain itself against the monarchical, it will naturally be careful to keep the press open, as of importance to its own preservation.[1]

These principles justify the great freedom of the press in our countries, more so than in any other government. We worry that unchecked power could creep in if we aren’t vigilant and don’t have an easy way to spread the word from one end of the nation to the other. The public spirit must often be stirred up to keep the court’s ambitions in check, and the fear of waking this spirit must be used to restrain that ambition. Nothing works better for this than the freedom of the press; it allows all the knowledge, intelligence, and creativity of the nation to support liberty and inspires everyone to defend it. As long as the republican aspect of our government can stand firm against the monarchy, it will naturally strive to keep the press open, as it’s crucial for its own survival.[1]

It must however be allowed, that the unbounded liberty of the press, though it be difficult, perhaps impossible, to propose a suitable remedy for it, is one of the evils attending those mixed forms of government.

It must, however, be acknowledged that the unrestricted freedom of the press, even though it's hard, maybe impossible, to find a proper solution for it, is one of the issues that come with those mixed types of government.

[1] Since, therefore, the liberty of the press is so essential to the support of our mixed government, this sufficiently decides the second question, Whether this liberty be advantageous or prejudicial, there being nothing of greater importance in every state than the preservation of the ancient government, especially if it be a free one. But I would fain go a step further, and assert, that such a liberty is attended with so few inconveniences, that it may be claimed as the common right of mankind, and ought to be indulged them almost in every government except the ecclesiastical, to which, indeed, it would be fatal. We need not dread from this liberty any such ill consequences as followed from the harangues of the popular demagogues of Athens and Tribunes of Rome. A man reads a book or pamphlet alone and coolly. There is none present from whom he can catch the passion by contagion. He is not hurried away by the force and energy of action. And should he be wrought up to never so seditious a humour, there is no violent resolution presented to him by which he can immediately vent his passion. The liberty of the press, therefore, however abused, can scarce ever excite popular tumults or rebellion. And as to those murmurs or secret discontents it may occasion, it is better they should get vent in words, that they may come to the knowledge of the magistrate before it be too late, in order to his providing a remedy against them. Mankind, it is true, have always a greater propension to believe what is said to the disadvantage of their governors than the contrary; but this inclination is inseparable from them whether they have liberty or not. A whisper may fly as quick, and be as pernicious as a pamphlet. Nay, it will be more pernicious, where men are not accustomed to think freely, or distinguish betwixt truth and falsehood.

[1] Since the freedom of the press is so crucial to supporting our mixed government, this effectively answers the second question, Is this freedom beneficial or harmful? There's nothing more important in any state than preserving the old government, especially if it’s a free one. But I want to go further and say that this freedom comes with so few downsides that it should be recognized as a common right for everyone and should be allowed in almost every government except religious ones, where it could actually be dangerous. We shouldn’t fear the negative outcomes that came from the speeches of the popular leaders in Athens and the Tribunes in Rome. A person reads a book or pamphlet by themselves and calmly. There’s no one there to influence their emotions. They’re not swept up by the force of action. And even if they become very agitated, there's no immediate violent action they can take to express that anger. Therefore, the freedom of the press, despite being misused, rarely incites public riots or rebellion. As for any grievances or hidden discontent it might cause, it’s better for these to come out in words so that the authorities can be aware of them before it’s too late, allowing them to find a solution. It’s true that people tend to be more inclined to believe negative things about their leaders than the opposite, but this tendency exists whether they have freedom or not. A rumor can spread just as quickly and be just as harmful as a pamphlet. In fact, it could be worse in places where people aren't used to thinking freely or distinguishing between truth and falsehood.

It has also been found, as the experience of mankind increases, that the people are no such dangerous monsters as they have been represented, and that it is in every respect better to guide them like rational creatures than to lead or drive them like brute beasts. Before the United Provinces set the example, toleration was deemed incompatible with good government; and it was thought impossible that a number of religious sects could live together in harmony and peace, and have all of them an equal affection to their common country and to each other. England has set a like example of civil liberty; and though this liberty seems to occasion some small ferment at present, it has not as yet produced any pernicious effects; and it is to be hoped that men, being every day more accustomed to the free discussion of public affairs, will improve in their judgment of them, and be with greater difficulty seduced by every idle rumour and popular clamour.

It has also been found, as human experience grows, that the people are not the dangerous monsters they have been made out to be, and that it is in every way better to guide them like rational beings than to control them like animals. Before the United Provinces set the example, tolerance was seen as incompatible with good governance; it was believed that various religious groups could not coexist peacefully and care equally for their shared country and for one another. England has set a similar example of civil liberty; and although this liberty seems to cause some minor unrest right now, it has not yet resulted in any harmful effects; it is to be hoped that as people become more accustomed to openly discussing public matters, they will improve their understanding of them and be less easily swayed by every silly rumor and public outcry.

It is a very comfortable reflection to the lovers of liberty, that this peculiar privilege of Britain is of a kind that cannot easily be wrested from us, and must last as long as our government remains in any degree free and independent. It is seldom that liberty of any kind is lost all at once. Slavery has so frightful an aspect to men accustomed to freedom, that it must steal in upon them by degrees, and must disguise itself in a thousand shapes in order to be received. But if the liberty of the press ever be lost, it must be lost at once. The general laws against sedition and libelling are at present as strong as they possibly can be made. Nothing can impose a further restraint but either the clapping an imprimatur upon the press, or the giving very large discretionary powers to the court to punish whatever displeases them. But these concessions would be such a barefaced violation of liberty, that they will probably be the last efforts of a despotic government. We may conclude that the liberty of Britain is gone for ever when these attempts shall succeed.

It’s a comforting thought for freedom lovers that this unique privilege of Britain is something that can’t easily be taken away from us and should last as long as our government remains at least somewhat free and independent. Liberty is rarely lost all at once. Slavery appears so terrible to people used to freedom that it must creep in gradually and disguise itself in many forms to be accepted. However, if the freedom of the press is ever lost, it would likely happen all at once. The current laws against sedition and libel are as strong as they can be. The only thing that could impose further restrictions would be either putting a stamp of approval on the press or giving the courts excessive power to punish anything they find objectionable. But these measures would be such a blatant violation of liberty that they would probably be the final acts of a tyrannical government. We can say that the freedom of Britain is gone for good if these efforts succeed.


THAT POLITICS MAY BE REDUCED TO A SCIENCE

It is a question with several, whether there be any essential difference between one form of government and another? and, whether every form may not become good or bad, according as it is well or ill administered?[1] Were it once admitted, that all governments are alike, and that the only difference consists in the character and conduct of the governors, most political disputes would be at an end, and all Zeal for one constitution above another must be esteemed mere bigotry and folly. But, though a friend to moderation, I cannot forbear condemning this sentiment, and should be sorry to think, that human affairs admit of no greater stability, than what they receive from the casual humours and characters of particular men.

Is there really a key difference between one form of government and another? And can every form be good or bad depending on how it's run? [1] If we accept that all governments are essentially the same and that the only difference comes from the personalities and actions of those in charge, most political arguments would disappear, and any enthusiasm for one constitution over another would be seen as simple-mindedness and foolishness. However, even though I advocate for moderation, I can't help but reject this idea, and I would be disappointed to believe that human affairs are only as stable as the random moods and personalities of certain individuals.

It is true, those who maintain that the goodness of all government consists in the goodness of the administration, may cite many particular instances in history, where the very same government, in different hands, has varied suddenly into the two opposite extremes of good and bad. Compare the French government under Henry III and under Henry IV. Oppression, levity, artifice, on the part of the rulers; faction, sedition, treachery, rebellion, disloyalty on the part of the subjects: these compose the character of the former miserable era. But when the patriot and heroic prince, who succeeded, was once firmly seated on the throne, the government, the people, every thing, seemed to be totally changed; and all from the difference of the temper and conduct of these two sovereigns.[2] Instances of this kind may be multiplied, almost without number, from ancient as well as modern history, foreign as well as domestic.

It’s true that those who argue that the quality of any government relies on its administration can point to many examples in history where the same government, under different leaders, has swung dramatically between good and bad. Look at the French government under Henry III versus Henry IV. Under Henry III, there was oppression, frivolity, manipulation from the rulers; while the subjects faced factionalism, unrest, betrayal, rebellion, and disloyalty. This defines that unfortunate era. But once the courageous and patriotic prince took the throne, everything changed—the government, the people, everything seemed completely different, all because of the contrasting styles and leadership of these two kings.[2] Such examples can be found in abundance, both in ancient and modern history, from abroad and at home.

But here it may be proper to make a distinction. All absolute governments must very much depend on the administration; and this is one of the great inconveniences attending that form of government. But a republican and free government would be an obvious absurdity, if the particular checks and controls, provided by the constitution had really no influence, and made it not the interest, even of bad men, to act for the public good. Such is the intention of these forms of government, and such is their real effect, where they are wisely constituted: as, on the other hand, they are the source of all disorder, and of the blackest crimes, where either skill or honesty has been wanting in their original frame and institution.

But here it’s important to make a distinction. All absolute governments rely heavily on the administration, and this is one of the major downsides of that type of government. However, a republican and free government would be completely absurd if the specific checks and balances created by the constitution really had no impact, making it not in anyone's interest, even that of bad people, to act for the public good. This is the purpose of these types of government, and this is their true outcome when they are set up wisely; conversely, they become the source of all chaos and the worst crimes when there is a lack of skill or integrity in their initial design and establishment.

So great is the force of laws, and of particular forms of government, and so little dependence have they on the humours and tempers of men, that consequences almost as general and certain may sometimes be deduced from them, as any which the mathematical sciences afford us.

So strong is the power of laws and specific types of government, and so little do they rely on the moods and attitudes of people, that we can often draw conclusions that are nearly as universal and certain from them as we can from the mathematical sciences.

The constitution of the Roman republic gave the whole legislative power to the people, without allowing a negative voice either to the nobility or consuls. This unbounded power they possessed in a collective, not in a representative body. The consequences were: when the people, by success and conquest, had become very numerous, and had spread themselves to a great distance from the capital, the city tribes, though the most contemptible, carried almost every vote: they were, therefore, most cajoled by every one that affected popularity: they were supported in idleness by the general distribution of corn, and by particular bribes, which they received from almost every candidate: by this means, they became every day more licentious, and the Campus Martius was a perpetual scene of tumult and sedition: armed slaves were introduced among these rascally citizens, so that the whole government fell into anarchy; and the greatest happiness which the Romans could look for, was the despotic power of the Cæsars. Such are the effects of democracy without a representative.

The constitution of the Roman republic granted all legislative power to the people, without giving the nobility or consuls any veto. This unlimited power was held collectively, not through a representative body. The consequences were: when the people, through success and conquest, had grown numerous and spread far from the capital, the city tribes, despite being the least esteemed, dominated nearly every vote. As a result, they were constantly flattered by anyone seeking popularity. They were kept idle through the general distribution of grain and specific bribes from almost every candidate. This led them to become increasingly unruly, and the Campus Martius was a constant scene of chaos and unrest. Armed slaves were introduced among these unruly citizens, causing the entire government to descend into anarchy; the greatest hope the Romans could have was the authoritarian rule of the Cæsars. This illustrates the consequences of democracy without representation.

A Nobility may possess the whole, or any part of the legislative power of a state, in two different ways. Either every nobleman shares the power as a part of the whole body, or the whole body enjoys the power as composed of parts, which have each a distinct power and authority. The Venetian aristocracy is an instance of the first kind of government; the Polish, of the second. In the Venetian government the whole body of nobility possesses the whole power, and no nobleman has any authority which he receives not from the whole. In the Polish government every nobleman, by means of his fiefs, has a distinct hereditary authority over his vassals, and the whole body has no authority but what it receives from the concurrence of its parts. The different operations and tendencies of these two species of government might be made apparent even a priori. A Venetian nobility is preferable to a Polish, let the humours and education of men be ever so much varied. A nobility, who possess their power in common, will preserve peace and order, both among themselves, and their subjects; and no member can have authority enough to control the laws for a moment. The nobles will preserve their authority over the people, but without any grievous tyranny, or any breach of private property; because such a tyrannical government promotes not the interests of the whole body, however it may that of some individuals. There will be a distinction of rank between the nobility and people, but this will be the only distinction in the state. The whole nobility will form one body, and the whole people another, without any of those private feuds and animosities, which spread ruin and desolation everywhere. It is easy to see the disadvantages of a Polish nobility in every one of these particulars.

A nobility can hold the entire, or any part of, the legislative power of a state in two different ways. Either every nobleman shares the power collectively as part of the whole group, or the entire group exercises power made up of individuals, each with distinct authority. The Venetian aristocracy is an example of the first type of government; the Polish is an example of the second. In the Venetian system, the entire nobility holds all the power, and no nobleman has authority except what comes from the whole body. In the Polish system, each nobleman, through his fiefs, has distinct hereditary authority over his vassals, while the entire nobility only has authority based on the agreement of its members. The different operations and tendencies of these two types of government could be demonstrated even a priori. A Venetian nobility is better than a Polish one, regardless of the diverse opinions and upbringing of individuals. A nobility that shares their power will maintain peace and order, both among themselves and with their subjects; no member will have enough authority to override the laws for even a moment. The nobles will retain their control over the people but without harsh tyranny or violation of private property; such oppressive governance does not serve the interests of the whole group, even if it benefits a few individuals. There will be a clear distinction of rank between the nobility and the people, but this will be the only division in the state. The entire nobility will act as one body, and the entire people will form another, without the private feuds and animosities that lead to destruction and chaos everywhere. The drawbacks of a Polish nobility are evident in every one of these aspects.

It is possible so to constitute a free government, as that a single person, call him a doge, prince, or king, shall possess a large share of power, and shall form a proper balance or counterpoise to the other parts of the legislature. This chief magistrate may be either elective or hereditary, and though the former institution may, to a superficial view, appear the most advantageous; yet a more accurate inspection will discover in it greater inconveniences than in the latter, and such as are founded on causes and principles eternal and immutable. The filling of the throne, in such a government, is a point of too great and too general interest, not to divide the whole people into factions, whence a civil war, the greatest of ills, may be apprehended, almost with certainty, upon every vacancy. The prince elected must be either a Foreigner or a Native: the former will be ignorant of the people whom he is to govern; suspicious of his new subjects, and suspected by them; giving his confidence entirely to strangers, who will have no other care but of enriching themselves in the quickest manner, while their master's favour and authority are able to support them. A native will carry into the throne all his private animosities and friendships, and will never be viewed in his elevation without exciting the sentiment of envy in those who formerly considered him as their equal. Not to mention that a crown is too high a reward ever to be given to merit alone, and will always induce the candidates to employ force, or money, or intrigue, to procure the votes of the electors: so that such an election will give no better chance for superior merit in the prince, than if the state had trusted to birth alone for determining the sovereign.

It’s possible to create a free government where a single person, whether you call him a doge, prince, or king, holds significant power and maintains a proper balance with the other parts of the legislature. This chief official can be either elected or hereditary. While the former might seem like the better option at first glance, a closer look reveals more drawbacks than in the latter, grounded in causes and principles that are eternal and unchangeable. Filling the throne in such a government is too important and influential not to create factions among the people, which could almost certainly lead to civil war upon every vacancy, the worst of all misfortunes. The elected prince must be either a Foreigner or a Native: a foreigner will be unfamiliar with the people he governs, will be suspicious of them, and they will be suspicious of him; he will give his trust entirely to outsiders who only care about quickly enriching themselves while his favor and power last. A native will bring personal grudges and friendships to the throne and will always be viewed with envy by those who once saw him as their equal. Not to mention that a crown is too great a reward to be based solely on merit and will always encourage candidates to use force, money, or manipulation to secure the votes of electors, meaning such elections are no more likely to yield a superior prince than if the state relied solely on birth to determine its sovereign.

It may, therefore, be pronounced as an universal axiom in politics, That an hereditary prince, a nobility without vassals, and a people voting by their representatives, form the best MONARCHY, ARISTOCRACY, and DEMOCRACY. But in order to prove more fully, that politics admit of general truths, which are invariable by the humour or education either of subject or sovereign, it may not be amiss to observe some other principles of this science, which may seem to deserve that character.

It can, therefore, be stated as a universal truth in politics, that an hereditary prince, a nobility without vassals, and a people voting through their representatives, create the best MONARCHY, ARISTOCRACY, and DEMOCRACY. However, to further demonstrate that politics can have general truths that remain constant regardless of the mood or education of either the subjects or the sovereign, it might be helpful to point out some other principles of this field that may warrant that distinction.

It may easily be observed, that though free governments have been commonly the most happy for those who partake of their freedom; yet are they the most ruinous and oppressive to their provinces: and this observation may, I believe, be fixed as a maxim of the kind we are here speaking of. When a monarch extends his dominions by conquest, he soon learns to consider his old and his new subjects as on the same footing; because, in reality, all his subjects are to him the same, except the few friends and favourites with whom he is personally acquainted. He does not, therefore, make any distinction between them in his general laws; and, at the same time, is careful to prevent all particular acts of oppression on the one as well as the other. But a free state necessarily makes a great distinction, and must always do so till men learn to love their neighbours as well as themselves. The conquerors, in such a government, are all legislators, and will be sure to contrive matters, by restrictions on trade, and by taxes, so as to draw some private, as well as public advantage from their conquests. Provincial governors have also a better chance, in a republic, to escape with their plunder, by means of bribery or intrigue; and their fellow-citizens, who find their own state to be enriched by the spoils of the subject provinces, will be the more inclined to tolerate such abuses. Not to mention, that it is a necessary precaution in a free state to change the governors frequently, which obliges these temporary tyrants to be more expeditious and rapacious, that they may accumulate sufficient wealth before they give place to their successors. What cruel tyrants were the Romans over the world during the time of their commonwealth! It is true, they had laws to prevent oppression in their provincial magistrates; but Cicero informs us, that the Romans could not better consult the interests of the provinces than by repealing these very laws. For, in that case, says he, our magistrates, having entire impunity, would plunder no more than would satisfy their own rapaciousness; whereas, at present, they must also satisfy that of their judges, and of all the great men in Rome, of whose protection they stand in need. Who can read of the cruelties and oppressions of Verres without horror and astonishment? And who is not touched with indignation to hear, that, after Cicero had exhausted on that abandoned criminal all the thunders of his eloquence, and had prevailed so far as to get him condemned to the utmost extent of the laws, yet that cruel tyrant lived peaceably to old age, in opulence and ease, and, thirty years afterwards, was put into the proscription by Mark Antony, on account of his exorbitant wealth, where he fell with Cicero himself, and all the most virtuous men of Rome? After the dissolution of the commonwealth, the Roman yoke became easier upon the provinces, as Tacitus informs us; and it may be observed, that many of the worst emperors, Domitian, for instance, were careful to prevent all oppression on the provinces. In Tiberius's time, Gaul was esteemed richer than Italy itself: nor do I find, during the whole time of the Roman monarchy, that the empire became less rich or populous in any of its provinces; though indeed its valour and military discipline were always upon the decline. The oppression and tyranny of the Carthaginians over their subject states in Africa went so far, as we learn from Polybius, that, not content with exacting the half of all the produce of the land, which of itself was a very high rent, they also loaded them with many other taxes. If we pass from ancient to modern times, we shall still find the observation to hold. The provinces of absolute monarchies are always better treated than those of free states. Compare the Pais conquis of France with Ireland, and you will be convinced of this truth; though this latter kingdom, being in a good measure peopled from England, possesses so many rights and privileges as should naturally make it challenge better treatment than that of a conquered province. Corsica is also an obvious instance to the same purpose.

It’s easy to see that while free governments are usually the happiest for those who enjoy their freedom, they can also be the most ruinous and oppressive to their territories. This observation could, I believe, be established as a principle of the subject we’re discussing. When a monarch expands his rule through conquest, he quickly starts to see both his old and new subjects as equals; because, in truth, all his subjects are essentially the same to him, except for a few friends and favorites he knows personally. He doesn’t make any distinction between them in his general laws; meanwhile, he works to prevent any particular acts of oppression against either group. However, a free state has to make a significant distinction and must continue to do so until people learn to care for others as much as they care for themselves. In such a government, the conquerors are all lawmakers and will naturally set things up, through trade restrictions and taxes, to gain both private and public benefits from their conquests. Provincial governors in a republic also have a better chance of getting away with their plunder due to bribery or schemes; and their fellow citizens, who see their state benefitting from the spoils of the conquered territories, will be more likely to tolerate such injustices. Not to mention that it’s a necessary precaution in a free state to frequently change governors, which pushes these temporary tyrants to be more efficient and greedy, so they can gather enough wealth before passing the reins to their successors. What ruthless tyrants the Romans were to the world during their republic! It’s true they had laws meant to prevent oppression from their provincial officials; but Cicero tells us that they couldn’t better serve the interests of the provinces than by repealing those very laws. He said, in that case, our magistrates, having complete impunity, would plunder only as much as would satisfy their own greed; while, at present, they must also satisfy their judges and powerful men in Rome, whose protection they need. Who can read about the cruelties and oppressions of Verres without horror and disbelief? And who isn’t filled with outrage to hear that, after Cicero had unleashed all the force of his rhetoric against that wretched criminal and managed to have him condemned to the fullest extent of the law, that cruel tyrant lived comfortably into old age, wealthy and at ease, and, thirty years later, was put on the proscription list by Mark Antony due to his excessive riches, where he fell along with Cicero himself and all the most virtuous citizens of Rome? After the republic fell apart, the Roman yoke became lighter on the provinces, as Tacitus points out; and it’s worth noting that many of the worst emperors, like Domitian, were careful to prevent all oppression in the provinces. During Tiberius's reign, Gaul was considered richer than Italy itself: I don’t find any evidence that throughout the era of the Roman monarchy, the empire became less wealthy or populated in any of its provinces; although, truly, its courage and military discipline were always in decline. The oppression and tyranny of the Carthaginians over their subject territories in Africa went so far, according to Polybius, that they were not satisfied with demanding half of all agricultural produce, which was already a very steep tax, but also imposed many other taxes on them. If we shift from ancient to modern times, we will still see this observation hold true. The provinces under absolute monarchies are always better treated than those under free states. Compare the Pays conquis of France with Ireland, and you’ll see this truth clearly; although Ireland, being mostly populated by people from England, has so many rights and privileges that it should naturally demand better treatment than that of a conquered province. Corsica is also a clear example supporting this point.

There is an observation of Machiavel, with regard to the conquests of Alexander the Great, which, I think, may be regarded as one of those eternal political truths, which no time nor accidents can vary. It may seem strange, says that politician, that such sudden conquests, as those of Alexander, should be possessed so peaceably by his successors, and that the Persians, during all the confusions and civil wars among the Greeks, never made the smallest effort towards the recovery of their former independent government. To satisfy us concerning the cause of this remarkable event, we may consider, that a monarch may govern his subjects in two different ways. He may either follow the maxims of the Eastern princes, and stretch his authority so far as to leave no distinction of rank among his subjects, but what proceeds immediately from himself; no advantages of birth; no hereditary honours and possessions; and, in a word, no credit among the people, except from his commission alone. Or a monarch may exert his power after a milder manner, like other European princes; and leave other sources of honour, beside his smile and favour; birth, titles, possessions, valour, integrity, knowledge, or great and fortunate achievements. In the former species of government, after a conquest, it is impossible ever to shake off the yoke; since no one possesses, among the people, so much personal credit and authority as to begin such an enterprise: whereas, in the latter, the least misfortune, or discord among the victors, will encourage the vanquished to take arms, who have leaders ready to prompt and conduct them in every undertaking.[3]

There’s a point made by Machiavelli about the conquests of Alexander the Great that I think can be seen as one of those timeless political truths that won’t change over time or circumstances. It may seem odd, he says, that Alexander’s sudden conquests were held so peacefully by his successors, and that the Persians never made even the smallest effort to regain their previous independence during all the chaos and civil wars among the Greeks. To understand the reason behind this notable event, we can consider that a monarch can govern his subjects in two distinct ways. He can either follow the practices of Eastern kings, extending his authority so much that there’s no distinction of rank among his subjects aside from what he grants himself; no advantages of birth, no hereditary honors or land, and essentially no influence among the people except for his own commission. Or a monarch can exercise his power in a gentler way, like other European rulers, allowing for other sources of honor besides his approval and support; things like birth, titles, property, bravery, integrity, knowledge, or significant achievements. In the first type of government, after a conquest, it’s impossible to shake off the oppression since no one among the people has enough personal respect and authority to start such a movement. In the second type, even the slightest misfortune or conflict among the victors can spur the defeated to take up arms, as they have leaders ready to inspire and guide them in any effort. [3]

Such is the reasoning of Machiavel, which seems solid and conclusive; though I wish he had not mixed falsehood with truth, in asserting that monarchies, governed according to Eastern policy, though more easily kept when once subdued, yet are the most difficult to subdue; since they cannot contain any powerful subject, whose discontent and faction may facilitate the enterprises of an enemy. For, besides, that such a tyrannical government enervates the courage of men, and renders them indifferent towards the fortunes of their sovereigns; besides this, I say, we find by experience, that even the temporary and delegated authority of the generals and magistrates, being always, in such governments, as absolute within its sphere as that of the prince himself, is able, with barbarians accustomed to a blind submission, to produce the most dangerous and fatal revolutions. So that in every respect, a gentle government is preferable, and gives the greatest security to the sovereign as well as to the subject.

This is the reasoning of Machiavelli, which seems solid and conclusive; although I wish he hadn’t mixed truth with falsehood by claiming that monarchies governed by Eastern policies are easier to maintain once they've been subdued, yet are the most challenging to conquer. This is because they can't allow for any powerful subjects whose discontent and faction could help enemies succeed. Furthermore, such a tyrannical government weakens men's courage and makes them indifferent to the fate of their rulers. Additionally, we see from experience that even the temporary and delegated authority of generals and magistrates, which is always as absolute within its scope as that of the prince himself in these kinds of governments, can lead to the most dangerous and fatal revolutions among people who are used to blind obedience. Therefore, in every way, a gentle government is better and provides the greatest security for both the sovereign and the subjects.

Legislators, therefore, ought not to trust the future government of a state entirely to chance, but ought to provide a system of laws to regulate the administration of public affairs to the latest posterity. Effects will always correspond to causes; and wise regulations, in any commonwealth, are the most valuable legacy that can be left to future ages. In the smallest court or office, the stated forms and methods by which business must be conducted, are found to be a considerable check on the natural depravity of mankind. Why should not the case be the same in public affairs? Can we ascribe the stability and wisdom of the Venetian government, through so many ages, to any thing but the form of government? And is it not easy to point out those defects in the original constitution, which produced the tumultuous governments of Athens and Rome, and ended at last in the ruin of these two famous republics? And so little dependence has this affair on the humours and education of particular men, that one part of the same republic may be wisely conducted, and another weakly, by the very same men, merely on account of the differences of the forms and institutions by which these parts are regulated. Historians inform us that this was actually the case with Genoa. For while the state was always full of sedition, and tumult, and disorder, the bank of St. George, which had become a considerable part of the people, was conducted, for several ages, with the utmost integrity and wisdom.

Legislators shouldn’t leave the future governance of a state solely to chance; instead, they should establish a system of laws to manage public affairs for future generations. The outcomes will always align with the causes; smart regulations in any society are the most valuable inheritance for the future. Even in the smallest courtroom or office, the established procedures and methods for conducting business serve as a significant check on people's natural flaws. Why shouldn’t this be the same in public affairs? Can we attribute the stability and wisdom of the Venetian government, which lasted for so many years, to anything other than its governmental structure? Isn’t it clear to point out the flaws in the original constitutions that led to the tumultuous governments of Athens and Rome, which ultimately resulted in the downfall of those two great republics? The situation is so little affected by the personalities and education of individual leaders that one part of the same republic can operate wisely while another can falter, even under the same individuals, simply due to differences in the structures and institutions governing those parts. Historians tell us that this was true for Genoa. While the state was often plagued by unrest and chaos, the Bank of St. George, which became a significant part of the populace, was managed with remarkable integrity and wisdom for many years.

The ages of greatest public spirit are not always most eminent for private virtue. Good laws may beget order and moderation in the government, where the manners and customs have instilled little humanity or justice into the tempers of men. The most illustrious period of the Roman history, considered in a political view, is that between the beginning of the first and end of the last Punic war; the due balance between the nobility and people being then fixed by the contests of the tribunes, and not being yet lost by the extent of conquests. Yet at this very time, the horrid practice of poisoning was so common, that, during part of the season, a Prætor punished capitally for this crime above three thousand persons in a part of Italy; and found informations of this nature still multiplying upon him. There is a similar, or rather a worse instance, in the more early times of the commonwealth; so depraved in private life were that people, whom in their histories we so much admire. I doubt not but they were really more virtuous during the time of the two Triumvirates, when they were tearing their common country to pieces, and spreading slaughter and desolation over the face of the earth, merely for the choice of tyrants.

The times of greatest public spirit don't always align with high private virtue. Good laws can create order and moderation in government, even when the social customs have instilled little compassion or justice in people's character. The most notable period in Roman history, from a political perspective, is between the start of the first Punic War and the end of the last. During this time, a balance between the nobility and the people was maintained through the struggles of the tribunes, and it hadn't yet been undermined by the expansion of conquests. However, at this same time, the dreadful practice of poisoning was so widespread that a Prætor sentenced over three thousand people to death for this crime in a region of Italy during part of the year, and reports of similar crimes continued to increase. There's an even worse example from the earlier days of the Republic; private life was so corrupt among the people we admire in their histories. I'm sure they were actually more virtuous during the era of the two Triumvirates, even as they tore their country apart and caused widespread death and destruction, all for the sake of choosing tyrants.

Here, then, is a sufficient inducement to maintain, with the utmost zeal, in every free state, those forms and institutions by which liberty is secured, the public good consulted, and the avarice or ambition of particular men restrained and punished. Nothing does more honour to human nature, than to see it susceptible of so noble a passion; as nothing can be a greater indication of meanness of heart in any man than to see him destitute of it. A man who loves only himself, without regard to friendship and desert, merits the severest blame; and a man, who is only susceptible of friendship, without public spirit, or a regard to the community, is deficient in the most material part of virtue.

Here’s a compelling reason to passionately uphold, in every free state, those structures and institutions that protect liberty, promote the common good, and keep the greed or ambition of certain individuals in check. There’s nothing that reflects well on human nature more than its capacity for such a noble passion; conversely, there’s nothing that shows greater lowliness of character than to see someone completely lacking it. A person who only cares about themselves, without valuing friendship or merit, deserves harsh criticism; similarly, a person who only feels friendship, without any sense of public duty or concern for the community, is missing a crucial aspect of virtue.

But this is a subject which needs not be longer insisted on at present. There are enow of zealots on both sides, who kindle up the passions of their partisans, and, under pretence of public good, pursue the interests and ends of their particular faction. For my part, I shall always be more fond of promoting moderation than zeal; though perhaps the surest way of producing moderation in every party is to increase our zeal for the public. Let us therefore try, if it be possible, from the foregoing doctrine, to draw a lesson of moderation with regard to the parties into which our country is at present divided; at the same time, that we allow not this moderation to abate the industry and passion, with which every individual is bound to pursue the good of his country.

But this is a topic that doesn't need to be dwelled on right now. There are plenty of zealots on both sides who ignite the passions of their supporters and, under the guise of serving the public good, chase their own faction's interests. Personally, I prefer to promote moderation over zeal; although perhaps the best way to encourage moderation in any party is to strengthen our commitment to the public good. So let's try, if we can, to take a lesson in moderation from the previous discussion regarding the parties that currently divide our country, while also ensuring that this moderation doesn't lessen the effort and passion each individual should have for the welfare of our nation.

Those who either attack or defend a minister in such a government as ours, where the utmost liberty is allowed, always carry matters to an extreme, and exaggerate his merit or demerit with regard to the public. His enemies are sure to charge him with the greatest enormities, both in domestic and foreign management; and there is no meanness or crime, of which, in their account, he is not capable. Unnecessary wars, scandalous treaties, profusion of public treasure, oppressive taxes, every kind of maladministration is ascribed to him. To aggravate the charge, his pernicious conduct, it is said, will extend its baneful influence even to posterity, by undermining the best constitution in the world, and disordering that wise system of laws, institutions, and customs, by which our ancestors, during so many centuries, have been so happily governed. He is not only a wicked minister in himself, but has removed every security provided against wicked ministers for the future.

Those who either criticize or support a minister in a government like ours, where complete freedom is permitted, always take things to the extreme and exaggerate his merits or faults in the eyes of the public. His opponents will definitely accuse him of serious wrongdoing in both domestic and international affairs, claiming he is capable of the lowest acts and crimes. They blame him for unnecessary wars, disgraceful treaties, wasting public money, heavy taxes, and every type of bad governance. To worsen the accusations, they argue that his harmful actions will have a negative impact on future generations by undermining the best constitution in the world and disrupting the wise system of laws, institutions, and customs that have governed our ancestors so well for centuries. He is not just a corrupt minister himself, but he has also removed all the safeguards against corrupt ministers for the future.

On the other hand, the partisans of the minister make his panegyric run as high as the accusation against him, and celebrate his wise, steady, and moderate conduct in every part of his administration. The honour and interest of the nation supported abroad, public credit maintained at home, persecution restrained, faction subdued; the merit of all these blessings is ascribed solely to the minister. At the same time, he crowns all his other merits by a religious care of the best constitution in the world, which he has preserved in all its parts, and has transmitted entire, to be the happiness and security of the latest posterity.

On the other hand, the minister's supporters praise him just as much as his critics accuse him, highlighting his wise, steady, and moderate leadership throughout his time in office. They attribute the nation's honor and interests upheld abroad, public trust maintained at home, suppression of persecution, and pacification of factions entirely to the minister. Additionally, he enhances his reputation by taking great care to protect the best constitution in the world, which he has preserved in its entirety, ensuring the happiness and security of future generations.

When this accusation and panegyric are received by the partisans of each party, no wonder they beget an extraordinary ferment on both sides, and fill the nation with violent animosities. But I would fain persuade these party zealots, that there is a flat contradiction both in the accusation and panegyric, and that it were impossible for either of them to run so high, were it not for this contradiction. If our constitution be really that noble fabric, the pride of Britain, the envy of our neighbours, raised by the labour of so many centuries, repaired at the expense of so many millions, and cemented by such a profusion of blood;[4] I say, if our constitution does in any degree deserve these eulogies, it would never have suffered a wicked and weak minister to govern triumphantly for a course of twenty years, when opposed by the greatest geniuses in the nation, who exercised the utmost liberty of tongue and pen, in parliament, and in their frequent appeals to the people. But, if the minister be wicked and weak, to the degree so strenuously insisted on, the constitution must be faulty in its original principles, and he cannot consistently be charged with undermining the best form of government in the world. A constitution is only so far good, as it provides a remedy against maladministration; and if the British, when in its greatest vigour, and repaired by two such remarkable events as the Revolution and Accession, by which our ancient royal family was sacrificed to it; if our constitution, I say, with so great advantages, does not, in fact, provide any such remedy, we are rather beholden to any minister who undermines it, and affords us an opportunity of erecting a better in its place.

When this accusation and praise are received by the supporters of each side, it’s no surprise that they create a huge uproar on both sides and fill the country with intense animosity. However, I would like to convince these party enthusiasts that there is a clear contradiction in both the accusation and praise, and it wouldn’t be possible for either to be so extreme if it weren’t for this contradiction. If our constitution truly is that noble structure, the pride of Britain, the envy of our neighbors, built over the course of many centuries, supported at the cost of countless millions, and solidified by such a vast amount of blood;[4] I say, if our constitution deserves even a fraction of this admiration, it should never have allowed a wicked and weak minister to govern successfully for twenty years while being challenged by the greatest minds in the nation, who expressed their full freedom of speech and writing in parliament and in their regular appeals to the public. Yet, if the minister is as wicked and weak as so often claimed, the constitution must have flaws in its original principles, and he cannot truthfully be accused of undermining the best form of government in the world. A constitution is only as good as it offers a solution to bad governance; and if the British constitution, at its peak, strengthened by two significant events like the Revolution and Accession, which led to the sacrifice of our ancient royal family, if our constitution, I say, with such significant advantages, does not actually provide any remedy, then we should actually be grateful to any minister who undermines it, as it gives us a chance to create a better system in its place.

I would employ the same topics to moderate the zeal of those who defend the minister. Is our constitution so excellent? Then a change of ministry can be no such dreadful event; since it is essential to such a constitution, in every ministry, both to preserve itself from violation, and to prevent all enormities in the administration. Is our constitution very bad? Then so extraordinary a jealousy and apprehension, on account of changes, is ill placed; and a man should no more be anxious in this case, than a husband, who had married a woman from the stews, should be watchful to prevent her infidelity. Public affairs, in such a government, must necessarily go to confusion, by whatever hands they are conducted; and the zeal of patriots is in that case much less requisite than the patience and submission of philosophers. The virtue and good intention of Cato and Brutus are highly laudable; but to what purpose did their zeal serve? Only to hasten the fatal period of the Roman government, and render its convulsions and dying agonies more violent and painful.

I would use the same points to calm the enthusiasm of those who support the minister. Is our constitution really that great? Then a change in government shouldn’t be such a terrible thing; it’s necessary for any constitution to be able to protect itself from being violated and to stop any wrongdoing in its administration. Is our constitution pretty bad? Then being overly jealous and worried about changes is misplaced; a person should worry about it no more than a husband who married a woman from the streets should worry about her cheating. In such a government, public affairs will inevitably fall apart, regardless of who is in charge; and the passion of patriots is less important than the patience and acceptance of philosophers. The integrity and good intentions of Cato and Brutus are commendable, but what did their fervor really achieve? Just to speed up the tragic end of the Roman government and make its struggles and final moments more intense and painful.

I would not be understood to mean, that public affairs deserve no care and attention at all. Would men be moderate and consistent, their claims might be admitted; at least might be examined. The country party might still assert, that our constitution, though excellent, will admit of maladministration to a certain degree; and therefore, if the minister be bad, it is proper to oppose him with a suitable degree of zeal. And, on the other hand, the court party may be allowed, upon the supposition that the minister were good, to defend, and with some zeal too, his administration. I would only persuade men not to contend, as if they were fighting pro aris et focis, and change a good constitution into a bad one, by the violence of their factions.

I don’t mean to suggest that public affairs don’t deserve attention. If people were reasonable and consistent, their claims could be recognized, or at least examined. The country party might still argue that our constitution, while great, can be mismanaged to some extent; therefore, if the minister is ineffective, it’s right to oppose him with a reasonable amount of enthusiasm. On the flip side, the court party could be justified, assuming the minister is competent, to support his administration with some passion as well. I only want to encourage people not to fight as if it’s a battle for their homes and families and to avoid turning a good constitution into a bad one through the aggression of their factions.

I have not here considered any thing that is personal in the present controversy. In the best civil constitutions, where every man is restrained by the most rigid laws, it is easy to discover either the good or bad intentions of a minister, and to judge whether his personal character deserve love or hatred. But such questions are of little importance to the public, and lay those who employ their pens upon them, under a just suspicion either of malevolence or of flattery.[5]

I haven't looked at anything personal in this debate. In the best civil systems, where everyone is bound by strict laws, it's easy to see the good or bad intentions of a leader and to judge whether their personal character deserves love or hate. But these issues are of little importance to the public, and those who write about them justly risk being seen as either malicious or flattering.[5]

[1]
For forms of government let fools contest,
Whate'er is best administered is best.
ESSAY ON MAN, Book 3.

[1]
Let the fools argue about different types of government,
The thing that is managed best is the best.
ESSAY ON MAN, Book 3.

[2] An equal difference of a contrary kind may be found in comparing the reigns of Elizabeth and James, at least with regard to foreign affairs.

[2] A noticeable difference can be seen when comparing the reigns of Elizabeth and James, especially in terms of foreign affairs.

[3] I have taken it for granted, according to the supposition of Machiavel, that the ancient Persians had no nobility; though there is reason to suspect, that the Florentine secretary, who seems to have been better acquainted with the Roman than the Greek authors, was mistaken in this particular. The more ancient Persians, whose manners are described by Xenophon, were a free people, and had nobility. Their ομοτιμοι were preserved even after the extending of their conquests and the consequent change of their government. Arrian mentions them in Darius's time, De exped. Alex. lib. ii. Historians also speak often of the persons in command as men of family. Tygranes, who was general of the Medes under Xerxes, was of the race of Achmænes, Heriod. lib. vii. cap. 62. Artachæus, who directed the cutting of the canal about Mount Athos, was of the same family. Id. cap. 117. Megabyzus was one of the seven eminent Persians who conspired against the Magi. His son, Zopyrus, was in the highest command under Darius, and delivered Babylon to him. His grandson, Megabyzus, commanded the army defeated at Marathon. His great-grandson, Zopyrus, was also eminent, and was banished Persia. Heriod. lib. iii. Thuc. lib. i. Rosaces, who commanded an army in Egypt under Artaxerxes, was also descended from one of the seven conspirators, Diod. Sic. lib. xvi. Agesilaus, in Xenophon. Hist. Græc. lib. iv. being desirous of making a marriage betwixt king Cotys his ally, and the daughter of Spithridates, a Persian of rank, who had deserted to him, first asks Cotys what family Spithridates is of. One of the most considerable in Persia, says Cotys. Ariæus, when offered the sovereignty by Clearchus and the ten thousand Greeks, refused it as of too low a rank, and said, that so many eminent Persians would never endure his rule. Id. de exped. lib. ii. Some of the families descended from the seven Persians above mentioned remained during Alexander's successors; and Mithridates, in Antiochus's time, is said by Polybius to be descended from one of them, lib. v. cap. 43. Artabazus was esteemed as Arrian says, εν τοις πρωτοις Περσων, lib. iii. And when Alexander married in one day 80 of his captains to Persian women, his intention plainly was to ally the Macedonians with the most eminent Persian families. Id. lib. vii. Diodorus Siculus says, they were of the most noble birth in Persia, lib. xvii. The government of Persia was despotic, and conducted in many respects after the Eastern manner, but was not carried so far as to extirpate all nobility, and confound all ranks and orders. It left men who were still great, by themselves and their family, independent of their office and commission. And the reason why the Macedonians kept so easily dominion over them, was owing to other causes easy to be found in the historians, though it must be owned that Machiavel's reasoning is, in itself, just, however doubtful its application to the present case.

[3] I have accepted as true, based on Machiavelli's assumption, that the ancient Persians had no nobility; however, there is reason to believe that the Florentine secretary, who seemed to be more familiar with Roman than Greek authors, might have been wrong about this. The earlier Persians, whose customs are described by Xenophon, were a free people and had a nobility. Their ομοτιμοι continued to exist even after their conquests expanded and their government changed. Arrian mentions them during the time of Darius in De exped. Alex. lib. ii. Historians also frequently refer to the commanders as individuals of notable lineage. Tygranes, who was the general of the Medes under Xerxes, belonged to the Achmænes family, Heriod. lib. vii. cap. 62. Artachæus, who oversaw the digging of the canal around Mount Athos, was from the same family, Id. cap. 117. Megabyzus was one of the seven distinguished Persians who plotted against the Magi. His son, Zopyrus, held a high command under Darius and surrendered Babylon to him. His grandson, Megabyzus, led the army that was defeated at Marathon. His great-grandson, Zopyrus, was also prominent and was exiled from Persia. Heriod. lib. iii. Thuc. lib. i. Rosaces, who led an army in Egypt under Artaxerxes, was also a descendant of one of the seven conspirators, Diod. Sic. lib. xvi. Agesilaus, in Xenophon's Hist. Græc. lib. iv., wishing to arrange a marriage between his ally King Cotys and the daughter of Spithridates, a Persian of high rank who had defected to him, first asked Cotys about Spithridates’ family. "One of the most respected in Persia," Cotys replied. Ariæus, when offered the sovereignty by Clearchus and the ten thousand Greeks, turned it down as being too lowly and claimed that so many distinguished Persians would never accept his rule. Id. de exped. lib. ii. Some of the families descended from the seven Persians mentioned earlier remained influential during Alexander's successors; Mithridates, in the time of Antiochus, is said by Polybius to be descended from one of them, lib. v. cap. 43. Artabazus was considered, as Arrian states, one of the leading Persians, lib. iii. When Alexander married 80 of his commanders to Persian women in a single day, his aim was clearly to connect the Macedonians with the most distinguished Persian families. Id. lib. vii. Diodorus Siculus claims they were of the most noble lineage in Persia, lib. xvii. Persia had a despotic government, run in many ways according to Eastern customs, but it did not go so far as to eliminate all nobility and merge all ranks and orders. It allowed men to remain significant through their own achievements and family, independent of their office and authority. The reason why the Macedonians were able to easily maintain dominance over them is due to other reasons clearly laid out in the historians, though it must be acknowledged that Machiavelli's reasoning is itself sound, no matter how questionable its relevance to this particular situation.

[4] Dissertation on Parties, Letter X.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Dissertation on Parties, Letter X.

[5] What our author's opinion was of the famous minister here pointed at, may be learned from that Essay, printed in the former edition, under the title of 'A Character of Sir Robert Walpole.' It was as follows:—There never was a man whose actions and character have been more earnestly and openly canvassed than those of the present minister, who, having governed a learned and free nation for so long a time, amidst such mighty opposition, may make a large library of what has been wrote for and against him, and is the subject of above half the paper that has been blotted in the nation within these twenty years. I wish, for the honour of our country, that any one character of him had been drawn with such judgment and impartiality as to have some credit with posterity, and to show that our liberty has, once at least, employed to good purpose. I am only afraid of failing in the former quality of judgment; but if it should be so, it is but one page more thrown away, after an hundred thousand upon the same subject, that have perished and become useless. In the mean time, I shall flatter myself with the pleasing imagination, that the following character will be adopted by future historians.

[5] You can find our author's opinion of the well-known minister mentioned here in the Essay printed in the previous edition titled 'A Character of Sir Robert Walpole.' It states:—There has never been a man whose actions and character have been examined more intensively and openly than those of the current minister, who, after governing a knowledgeable and free nation for so long, against immense opposition, could fill a large library with everything that has been written for and against him. He is the focus of more than half the articles written in this nation over the past twenty years. I wish, for the sake of our country's reputation, that a single portrayal of him had been crafted with such wisdom and fairness that it would hold some value for future generations and show that our freedom has, at least once, been used wisely. I only fear I might fail in the first quality of wisdom; but if that happens, it will just be one more page wasted, following hundreds of thousands on the same topic that have already vanished and become irrelevant. In the meantime, I will comfort myself with the nice thought that the following portrayal will be embraced by future historians.

Sir Robert Walpole, Prime Minister of Great Britain, is a man of ability, not a genius, good-natured, not virtuous; constant, not magnanimous; moderate, not equitable.[*] His virtues, in some instances, are free from the alloy of those vices which usually accompany such virtues; he is a generous friend, without being a bitter enemy. His vices, in other instances, are not compensated by those virtues which are nearly allied to them: his want of enterprise is not attended with frugality. The private character of the man is better than the public: his virtues more than his vices: his fortune greater than his fame. With many good qualities, he has incurred the public hatred: with good capacity, he has not escaped ridicule. He would have been esteemed more worthy of his high station, had he never possessed it; and is better qualified for the second than for the first place in any government; his ministry has been more advantageous to his family than to the public, better for this age than for posterity; and more pernicious by bad precedents than by real grievances. During his time trade has flourished, liberty declined, and learning gone to ruin. As I am a man, I love him; as I am a scholar, I hate him; as I am a Briton, I calmly wish his fall. And were I a member of either House, I would give my vote for removing him from St James's; but should be glad to see him retire to Houghton-Hall, to pass the remainder of his days in ease and pleasure.

Sir Robert Walpole, Prime Minister of Great Britain, is a capable man, not a genius; kind, but not virtuous; reliable, but not generous; moderate, not fair. [*] His good qualities sometimes don’t carry the flaws that often go with them; he is a supportive friend without being a harsh enemy. However, his shortcomings aren’t balanced by the good traits that are closely related to them: his lack of ambition doesn’t come with thrift. His private character is better than his public persona: he has more good qualities than bad ones, and his wealth is greater than his reputation. Despite many good traits, he has drawn public dislike; and although he is capable, he hasn’t avoided mockery. He would be seen as more deserving of his high position if he had never held it, and he is better suited for a secondary role than for a top one in any government. His time in office has benefited his family more than the public, has been better for this generation than for the future, and has caused more harm through bad precedents than through real problems. Under his leadership, trade has thrived, freedom has declined, and education has fallen apart. As a man, I admire him; as a scholar, I dislike him; as a Briton, I calmly wish for his downfall. If I were a member of either House, I would vote to remove him from St James's, but I would be happy to see him retire to Houghton-Hall and spend the rest of his days in comfort and enjoyment.

The author is pleased to find, that after animosities are laid, and calumny has ceased, the whole nation almost have returned to the same moderate sentiments with regard to this great man, if they are not rather become more favourable to him, by a very natural transition, from one extreme to another. The author would not oppose these humane sentiments towards the dead; though he cannot forbear observing, that the not paying more of our public debts was, as hinted in this character, a great, and the only great, error in that long administration.

The author is happy to see that after conflicts have settled and false accusations have stopped, nearly the entire nation has come back to a more moderate view of this great man, if not become even more supportive of him, as people naturally shift from one extreme to another. The author doesn't disagree with these kind feelings toward the deceased; however, he can't help but point out that not addressing more of our public debts was, as mentioned in this character, a significant and the only major mistake during that long administration.

[*]Moderate in the exercise of power, not equitable in engrossing it.

[*]Moderate when exercising power, but not fair in taking it all for yourself.


OF THE FIRST PRINCIPLES OF GOVERNMENT

Nothing appears more surprising to those who consider human affairs with a philosophical eye, than the easiness with which the many are governed by the few; and the implicit submission, with which men resign their own sentiments and passions to those of their rulers. When we enquire by what means this wonder is effected, we shall find, that, as Force is always on the side of the governed, the governors have nothing to support them but opinion. It is, therefore, on opinion only that government is founded; and this maxim extends to the most despotic and most military governments, as well as to the most free and most popular. The soldan of Egypt, or the emperor of Rome, might drive his harmless subjects, like brute beasts, against their sentiments and inclination. But he must, at least, have led his mamalukes or prætorian bands, like men, by their opinion.

Nothing seems more surprising to those who look at human affairs with a philosophical perspective than how easily the many are governed by the few; and the unquestioning way in which people give up their own feelings and desires to those in charge. When we explore how this phenomenon occurs, we’ll find that, since force is always on the side of the governed, the rulers have nothing to rely on but public opinion. Therefore, government is based solely on opinion; and this principle applies to the most oppressive and militaristic regimes, as well as to the most free and democratic ones. The sultan of Egypt or the emperor of Rome could drive their harmless subjects, like animals, against their own feelings and inclinations. However, they must have at least led their mamluks or praetorian guards, like human beings, through their opinions.

Opinion is of two kinds, to wit, opinion of interest, and opinion of right. By opinion of INTEREST, I chiefly understand the sense of the general advantage which is reaped from government; together with the persuasion, that the particular government which is established is equally advantageous with any other that could easily be settled. When this opinion prevails among the generality of a state, or among those who have the force in their hands, it gives great security to any government.

Opinion comes in two types: interest-based opinion and opinion based on what is right. By opinion of INTEREST, I mainly mean the understanding of the general benefits derived from government, along with the belief that the current government in place is just as beneficial as any other that could be easily established. When this opinion is held by the majority of a state or by those in power, it provides significant stability for any government.

Right is of two kinds; right to Power, and right to Property. What prevalence opinion of the first kind has over mankind, may easily be understood, by observing the attachment which all nations have to their ancient government, and even to those names which have had the sanction of antiquity. Antiquity always begets the opinion of right; and whatever disadvantageous sentiments we may entertain of mankind, they are always found to be prodigal both of blood and treasure in the maintenance of public justice.[1] There is, indeed, no particular in which, at first sight, there may appear a greater contradiction in the frame of the human mind than the present. When men act in a faction, they are apt, without shame or remorse, to neglect all the ties of honour and morality, in order to serve their party; and yet, when a faction is formed upon a point of right or principle, there is no occasion where men discover a greater obstinacy, and a more determined sense of justice and equity. The same social disposition of mankind is the cause of these contradictory appearances.

Right comes in two forms: the right to power and the right to property. It’s easy to understand the strong hold that the first kind has over people when we notice how attached all nations are to their traditional governments and even to names that carry historical significance. History always creates a sense of entitlement, and no matter our negative views of humanity, people consistently spend both blood and treasure to uphold public justice.[1] In fact, there’s no aspect of human nature that seems more contradictory at first glance than this one. When people act as a group, they often, without shame or regret, ignore all bonds of honor and morality to support their faction; yet, when a faction is based on rights or principles, individuals show an incredible stubbornness and an even stronger sense of justice and fairness. This same social tendency in humans explains these conflicting behaviors.

It is sufficiently understood, that the opinion of right to property is of moment in all matters of government. A noted author has made property the foundation of all government; and most of our political writers seem inclined to follow him in that particular. This is carrying the matter too far; but still it must be owned, that the opinion of right to property has a great influence in this subject.

It is well known that the right to property is significant in all matters of government. A well-known author has made property the basis of all government, and many of our political writers seem to agree with him on this point. This perspective may be taken too far, but it must still be acknowledged that the belief in property rights has a considerable impact on this topic.

Upon these three opinions, therefore, of public interest, of right to power, and of right to property, are all governments founded, and all authority of the few over the many. There are indeed other principles which add force to these, and determine, limit, or alter their operation; such as self-interest, fear, and affection. But still we may assert, that these other principles can have no influence alone, but suppose the antecedent influence of those opinions above mentioned. They are, therefore, to be esteemed the secondary, not the original, principles of government.

Based on these three views—public interest, right to power, and right to property—all governments are established, and all authority of the few over the many stems from them. There are indeed other factors that strengthen these views and shape, limit, or change their impact, such as self-interest, fear, and affection. However, we can still argue that these other factors can't operate independently; they require the foundational influence of the aforementioned views. Therefore, they should be regarded as secondary, not primary, principles of government.

For, first, as to self-interest, by which I mean the expectation of particular rewards, distinct from the general protection which we receive from government, it is evident that the magistrate's authority must be antecedently established, at least be hoped for, in order to produce this expectation. The prospect of reward may augment his authority with regard to some particular persons, but can never give birth to it, with regard to the public. Men naturally look for the greatest favours from their friends and acquaintance; and therefore, the hopes of any considerable number of the state would never centre in any particular set of men, if these men had no other title to magistracy, and had no separate influence over the opinions of mankind. The same observation may be extended to the other two principles of fear and affection. No man would have any reason to fear the fury of a tyrant, if he had no authority over any but from fear; since, as a single man, his bodily force can reach but a small way, and all the further power he possesses must be founded either on our own opinion, or on the presumed opinion of others. And though affection to wisdom and virtue in a sovereign extends very far, and has great influence, yet he must antecedently be supposed invested with a public character, otherwise the public esteem will serve him in no stead, nor will his virtue have any influence beyond a narrow sphere.

For, first, regarding self-interest, which I mean as the expectation of specific rewards, separate from the general protection we get from the government, it’s clear that a magistrate’s authority needs to be established beforehand, or at least anticipated, to create this expectation. The possibility of reward may boost his authority with certain individuals, but it can never create authority for the public. People naturally expect the biggest favors from their friends and acquaintances; therefore, the hopes of a significant number of citizens would never focus on a specific group of people if those people had no other claim to authority and had no special sway over public opinion. The same idea applies to the other two principles of fear and affection. No one would have any reason to fear the wrath of a tyrant if he had authority only based on fear; since, as an individual, his physical power can only reach so far, and any additional power he has must be based on our own views or the assumed views of others. And while affection for wisdom and virtue in a sovereign goes a long way and holds significant influence, he must already be seen as holding a public role; otherwise, public respect won't help him, nor will his virtue have any impact beyond a limited circle.

A government may endure for several ages, though the balance of power and the balance of property do not coincide. This chiefly happens where any rank or order of the state has acquired a large share in the property; but, from the original constitution of the government, has no share in the power. Under what pretence would any individual of that order assume authority in public affairs? As men are commonly much attached to their ancient government, it is not to be expected, that the public would ever favour such usurpations. But where the original constitution allows any share of power, though small, to an order of men who possess a large share of property, it is easy for them gradually to stretch their authority, and bring the balance of power to coincide with that of property. This has been the case with the House of Commons in England.

A government can last for many years, even if the balance of power and property isn’t the same. This mainly happens when a certain group within the state has a large amount of property but doesn’t have any power due to the government’s original setup. Under what pretext would someone from that group take charge in public matters? Since people are usually very loyal to their traditional government, it’s unlikely that the public would support such power grabs. However, if the original setup gives even a small amount of power to a group that holds a lot of property, it becomes easy for them to gradually expand their power and align it with their property. This has been the situation with the House of Commons in England.

Most writers that have treated of the British government, have supposed, that, as the Lower House represents all the Commons of Great Britain, its weight in the scale is proportioned to the property and power of all whom it represents. But this principle must not be received as absolutely true. For though the people are apt to attach themselves more to the House of Commons than to any other member of the constitution, that House being chosen by them as their representatives, and as the public guardians of their liberty; yet are there instances where the House, even when in opposition to the crown, has not been followed by the people, as we may particularly observe of the Tory House of Commons in the reign of King William. Were the members obliged to receive instructions from their constituents, like the Dutch deputies, this would entirely alter the case; and if such immense power and riches, as those of all the Commons of Great Britain, were brought into the scale, it is not easy to conceive, that the crown could either influence that multitude of people, or withstand the balance of property. It is true, the crown has great influence over the collective body in the elections of members; but were this influence, which at present is only exerted once in seven years, to be employed in bringing over the people to every vote, it would soon be wasted, and no skill, popularity, or revenue, could support it. I must, therefore, be of opinion, that an alteration in this particular would introduce a total alteration in our government, and would soon reduce it to a pure republic; and, perhaps, to a republic of no inconvenient form. For though the people, collected in a body like the Roman tribes, be quite unfit for government, yet, when dispersed in small bodies, they are most susceptible both of reason and order; the force of popular currents and tides is in a great measure broken; and the public interests may be pursued with some method and constancy. But it is needless to reason any further concerning a form of government, which is never likely to have place in Great Britain, and which seems not to be the aim of any party amongst us. Let us cherish and improve our ancient government as much as possible, without encouraging a passion for such dangerous novelties.[2]

Most writers discussing the British government have assumed that since the House of Commons represents all the common people of Great Britain, its influence is proportional to the property and power of those it represents. However, this idea shouldn't be accepted as absolutely correct. Although people tend to identify more with the House of Commons than with any other part of the constitution, as they choose it to represent them and act as protectors of their freedom, there are times when the House, even when opposing the crown, hasn't been supported by the public. A clear example is the Tory House of Commons during King William's reign. If members had to take instructions from their constituents, like the Dutch deputies do, the situation would be completely different. If the vast power and wealth of all the common people of Great Britain were factored in, it’s hard to imagine how the crown could sway such a large number or withstand the weight of their property. It’s true that the crown has significant influence over the collective group during elections, but if this influence, which currently only happens every seven years, were used to sway the people on every vote, it would quickly be diminished, and no amount of skill, popularity, or wealth could maintain it. Therefore, I believe that a change in this regard would lead to a complete transformation of our government and might quickly turn it into a pure republic, possibly one without significant downsides. While people acting as a large group, like the Roman tribes, may be unfit for governance, when they are dispersed into smaller groups, they are more receptive to reason and order. The effects of popular movements are largely mitigated, allowing public interests to be pursued with some method and consistency. However, there’s no need to argue further about a form of government that is unlikely to occur in Great Britain and doesn’t seem to be the goal of any party here. Let's support and improve our traditional government as much as we can without fostering a desire for such dangerous changes.[2]

[1] This passion we may denominate enthusiasm, or we may give it what appellation we please; but a politician who should overlook its influence on human affairs, would prove himself to have but a very limited understanding.

[1] We can call this passion enthusiasm, or whatever name we choose; but a politician who ignores its impact on people's lives would show that they have a very narrow understanding.

[2] I shall conclude this subject with observing, that the present political controversy with regard to instructions, is a very frivolous one, and can never be brought to any decision, as it is managed by both parties. The country party do not pretend that a member is absolutely bound to follow instructions as an ambassador or general is confined by his orders, and that his vote is not to be received in the House, but so far as it is conformable to them. The court party, again, do not pretend that the sentiments of the people ought to have no weight with every member; much less that he ought to despise the sentiments of those whom he represents, and with whom he is more particularly connected. And if their sentiments be of weight, why ought they not to express these sentiments? The question then is only concerning the degrees of weight which ought to be placed on instructions. But such is the nature of language, that it is impossible for it to express distinctly these different degrees; and if men will carry on a controversy on this head, it may well happen that they differ in the language, and yet agree in their sentiments; or differ in their sentiments, and yet agree in their language. Besides, how is it possible to fix these degrees, considering the variety of affairs that come before the House, and the variety of places which members represent? Ought the instructions of Totness to have the same weight as those of London? or instructions with regard to the Convention which respected foreign politics to have the same weight as those with regard to the Excise, which respected only our domestic affairs?

[2] I’ll wrap up this topic by saying that the current political debate over instructions is quite trivial and will never reach a conclusion, given how both sides are handling it. The country party doesn’t claim that a member is strictly required to follow instructions like an ambassador or general must follow their orders, and that their vote should only be counted if it aligns with those instructions. On the other hand, the court party doesn’t argue that the opinions of the public shouldn’t matter to each member; even less that a member should disregard the views of those they represent, especially their close connections. If public opinions are important, then why shouldn’t they be articulated? The real question is only about how much weight should be assigned to instructions. However, the nature of language makes it impossible to clearly express these varying weights. If people want to argue about this issue, it’s possible they might use different terms while sharing similar opinions or hold different opinions while using the same terms. Furthermore, how can these weights be established considering the diverse matters that come before the House and the different areas that members represent? Should the instructions from Totness carry the same weight as those from London? Or should the instructions concerning the Convention, which dealt with foreign matters, be treated the same as those related to the Excise, which focused only on domestic issues?


OF THE ORIGIN OF GOVERNMENT

Man, born in a family, is compelled to maintain society from necessity, from natural inclination, and from habit. The same creature, in his further progress, is engaged to establish political society, in order to administer justice, without which there can be no peace among them, nor safety, nor mutual intercourse. We are, therefore, to look upon all the vast apparatus of our government, as having ultimately no other object or purpose but the distribution of justice, or, in other words, the support of the twelve judges. Kings and parliaments, fleets and armies, officers of the court and revenue, ambassadors, ministers, and privy counsellors, are all subordinate in their end to this part of administration. Even the clergy, as their duty leads them to inculcate morality, may justly be thought, so far as regards this world, to have no other useful object of their institution.

Man, born into a family, has to maintain society out of necessity, natural inclination, and habit. As he develops further, he becomes involved in creating a political society to administer justice; without justice, there can be no peace, safety, or mutual interaction. Therefore, we should view all the extensive structures of our government as ultimately aimed at distributing justice, or, in other words, supporting the twelve judges. Kings and parliaments, fleets and armies, court and tax officials, ambassadors, ministers, and advisors are all ultimately focused on this aspect of governance. Even the clergy, in their role to promote morality, can justifiably be seen, in terms of this world, as having no other meaningful purpose for their institution.

All men are sensible of the necessity of justice to maintain peace and order; and all men are sensible of the necessity of peace and order for the maintenance of society. Yet, notwithstanding this strong and obvious necessity, such is the frailty or perverseness of our nature! it is impossible to keep men faithfully and unerringly in the paths of justice. Some extraordinary circumstances may happen, in which a man finds his interests to be more promoted by fraud or rapine, than hurt by the breach which his injustice makes in the social union. But much more frequently he is seduced from his great and important, but distant interests, by the allurement of present, though often very frivolous temptations. This great weakness is incurable in human nature.

All people understand that justice is necessary to maintain peace and order, and everyone recognizes that peace and order are essential for society to function. Yet, despite this clear and strong necessity, the weakness or flaws in our nature make it impossible to keep people consistently on the path of justice. There may be exceptional situations where someone finds that cheating or stealing benefits them more than the harm caused by their injustice to society. However, more often, they are tempted away from their significant but distant interests by the allure of immediate, often trivial, rewards. This fundamental weakness is an inescapable part of human nature.

Men must, therefore, endeavour to palliate what they cannot cure. They must institute some persons under the appellation of magistrates, whose peculiar office it is to point out the decrees of equity, to punish transgressors, to correct fraud and violence, and to oblige men, however reluctant, to consult their own real and permanent interests. In a word, obedience is a new duty which must be invented to support that of justice, and the ties of equity must be corroborated by those of allegiance.

Men must, therefore, try to ease what they can't fix. They need to appoint certain individuals as magistrates, whose specific role is to highlight the rules of fairness, punish wrongdoers, correct deceit and violence, and compel people, no matter how unwilling, to consider their true and lasting interests. In short, obedience is a new responsibility that needs to be created to uphold justice, and the bonds of fairness must be strengthened by those of loyalty.

But still, viewing matters in an abstract light, it may be thought that nothing is gained by this alliance, and that the factitious duty of obedience, from its very nature, lays as feeble a hold of the human mind, as the primitive and natural duty of justice. Peculiar interests and present temptations may overcome the one as well as the other. They are equally exposed to the same inconvenience; and the man who is inclined to be a bad neighbour, must be led by the same motives, well or ill understood, to be a bad citizen or subject. Not to mention, that the magistrate himself may often be negligent, or partial, or unjust in his administration.

But still, looking at things from a broad perspective, one might think that this alliance brings no real benefit, and that the artificial duty of obedience, by its very nature, impacts the human mind just as weakly as the basic and natural duty of justice. Individual interests and current temptations can undermine both just as easily. They are equally susceptible to the same issues; and a person who tends to be a bad neighbor is likely driven by the same motives, whether understood well or poorly, to be a bad citizen or subject. Not to mention that the magistrate might often be neglectful, biased, or unjust in how he governs.

Experience, however, proves that there is a great difference between the cases. Order in society, we find, is much better maintained by means of government; and our duty to the magistrate is more strictly guarded by the principles of human nature, than our duty to our fellow-citizens. The love of dominion, is so strong in the breast of man, that many not only submit to, but court all the dangers, and fatigues, and cares of government; and men, once raised to that station, though often led astray by private passions, find, in ordinary cases, a visible interest in the impartial administration of justice. The persons who first attain this distinction, by the consent, tacit or express, of the people, must be endowed with superior personal qualities of valour, force, integrity, or prudence, which command respect and confidence; and, after government is established, a regard to birth, rank, and station, has a mighty influence over men, and enforces the decrees of the magistrate. The prince or leader exclaims against every disorder which disturbs his society. He summons all his partisans and all men of probity to aid him in correcting and redressing it, and he is readily followed by all indifferent persons in the execution of his office. He soon acquires the power of rewarding these services; and in the progress of society, he establishes subordinate ministers, and often a military force, who find an immediate and a visible interest in supporting his authority. Habit soon consolidates what other principles of human nature had imperfectly founded; and men, once accustomed to obedience, never think of departing from that path, in which they and their ancestors have constantly trod, and to which they are confined by so many urgent and visible motives.

Experience shows that there is a significant difference between the cases. We find that order in society is much better maintained through government; and our duty to the magistrate is more strongly upheld by human nature than our duty to our fellow citizens. The desire for power is so strong in people that many not only submit to, but also seek out, all the dangers, hardships, and responsibilities of government; and those who reach that position, even if often swayed by personal passions, usually see a clear interest in the fair administration of justice. The individuals who first achieve this status, with the agreement of the people, whether explicit or implied, must possess superior qualities of courage, strength, integrity, or wisdom that inspire respect and trust. Once government is set up, factors like birth, rank, and status heavily influence people and reinforce the magistrate's decisions. The prince or leader protests against every disorder that disrupts his society. He calls on all his supporters and all honorable individuals to help him fix and address these issues, and he is easily followed by all neutral people in carrying out his duties. He quickly gains the ability to reward these services, and as society progresses, he establishes subordinate officials and often a military force that has a clear and immediate interest in upholding his authority. Over time, habits strengthen what other aspects of human nature had only partially established; and once people get used to obeying, they rarely consider breaking away from the path that they and their ancestors have consistently followed, a path reinforced by numerous pressing and visible incentives.

But though this progress of human affairs may appear certain and inevitable, and though the support which allegiance brings to justice be founded on obvious principles of human nature, it cannot be expected that men should beforehand be able to discover them, or foresee their operation. Government commences more casually and more imperfectly. It is probable, that the first ascendent of one man over multitudes began during a state of war; where the superiority of courage and of genius discovers itself most visibly, where unanimity and concert are most requisite, and where the pernicious effects of disorder are most sensibly felt. The long continuance of that state, an incident common among savage tribes, inured the people to submission; and if the chieftain possessed as much equity as prudence and valour, he became, even during peace, the arbiter of all differences, and could gradually, by a mixture of force and consent, establish his authority. The benefit sensibly felt from his influence, made it be cherished by the people, at least by the peaceable and well disposed among them; and if his son enjoyed the same good qualities, government advanced the sooner to maturity and perfection; but was still in a feeble state, till the further progress of improvement procured the magistrate a revenue, and enabled him to bestow rewards on the several instruments of his administration, and to inflict punishments on the refractory and disobedient. Before that period, each exertion of his influence must have been particular, and founded on the peculiar circumstances of the case. After it, submission was no longer a matter of choice in the bulk of the community, but was rigorously exacted by the authority of the supreme magistrate.

But while this progress of human affairs might seem certain and inevitable, and even though the support that loyalty provides to justice is based on clear principles of human nature, it’s unrealistic to expect that people can identify or foresee these principles ahead of time. Government starts off in a more casual and imperfect way. It’s likely that the first instances of one person gaining power over many arose during times of war, where bravery and skill are clearly evident, where unity and cooperation are most needed, and where the negative impacts of chaos are strongly felt. The prolonged existence of such a state, which is common among tribal societies, conditioned people to accept submission; and if the leader showed as much fairness as wisdom and bravery, he became, even in peaceful times, the judge of all disputes and could gradually establish his rule through a mix of force and agreement. The noticeable benefits from his leadership made people appreciate it, at least among those who were peaceful and well-intentioned; and if his son shared those positive traits, governance would reach maturity and stability more quickly, yet it remained weak until further developments provided the ruler with an income, allowing him to offer rewards to his officials and impose punishments on the defiant and disobedient. Before that point, every exercise of his power had to be specific and based on the unique details of the situation. After that, submission was no longer optional for most of the society, but was strictly enforced by the authority of the supreme ruler.

In all governments, there is a perpetual intestine struggle, open or secret, between Authority and Liberty, and neither of them can ever absolutely prevail in the contest. A great sacrifice of liberty must necessarily be made in every government; yet even the authority, which confines liberty, can never, and perhaps ought never, in any constitution, to become quite entire and uncontrollable. The sultan is master of the life and fortune of any individual; but will not be permitted to impose new taxes on his subjects: a French monarch can impose taxes at pleasure; but would find it dangerous to attempt the lives and fortunes of individuals. Religion also, in most countries, is commonly found to be a very intractable principle; and other principles or prejudices frequently resist all the authority of the civil magistrate; whose power, being founded on opinion, can never subvert other opinions equally rooted with that of his title to dominion. The government, which, in common appellation, receives the appellation of free, is that which admits of a partition of power among several members, whose united authority is no less, or is commonly greater, than that of any monarch; but who, in the usual course of administration, must act by general and equal laws, that are previously known to all the members, and to all their subjects. In this sense, it must be owned, that liberty is the perfection of civil society; but still authority must be acknowledged essential to its very existence: and in those contests which so often take place between the one and the other, the latter may, on that account, challenge the preference. Unless perhaps one may say (and it may be said with some reason) that a circumstance, which is essential to the existence of civil society, must always support itself, and needs be guarded with less jealousy, than one that contributes only to its perfection, which the indolence of men is so apt to neglect, or their ignorance to overlook.

In every government, there’s a constant internal struggle, whether open or hidden, between Authority and Liberty, and neither can completely dominate the other. A significant loss of liberty is unavoidable in every government; however, the authority that restricts liberty can never, and maybe shouldn’t ever, become entirely absolute and unchecked in any system. The sultan controls the life and wealth of individuals, but is not allowed to impose new taxes on his people. A French monarch can impose taxes as they wish, but would find it risky to threaten the lives and fortunes of individuals. Religion, in most countries, is often a very stubborn principle, and other beliefs or biases often resist the authority of the government, whose power, based on public opinion, can never fully undermine other opinions that are just as deeply rooted as their claim to power. A government typically referred to as free is one that divides power among several members, whose combined authority is equal to, or often greater than, that of any monarch; but who, in their usual operations, must act according to general and equal laws that are known to all its members and all their citizens. In this sense, it must be acknowledged that liberty is the ideal state of civil society; yet authority must also be recognized as essential to its very existence: and in the frequent clashes between the two, the latter may justifiably warrant more priority. Perhaps one could argue (and this could be argued reasonably) that something essential to the existence of civil society should inherently support itself and require less protection than something that merely enhances it, which the laziness of people often tends to neglect or their ignorance to overlook.


OF THE INDEPENDENCY OF PARLIAMENT[1]

Political writers have established it as a maxim, that, in contriving any system of government, and fixing the several checks and controls of the constitution, every man ought to be supposed a knave, and to have no other end, in all his actions, than private interest. By this interest we must govern him, and, by means of it, make him, notwithstanding his insatiable avarice and ambition, cooperate to public good. Without this, say they, we shall in vain boast of the advantages of any constitution, and shall find, in the end, that we have no security for our liberties or possessions, except the good-will of our rulers; that is, we shall have no security at all.

Political writers have established a principle that in designing any system of government and determining the various checks and balances of the constitution, we should consider every person to be a knave who acts solely out of self-interest. We must govern him by this interest and use it to ensure that, despite his endless greed and ambition, he contributes to the public good. Otherwise, they argue, we can’t truly claim the benefits of any constitution and will ultimately find that our liberties and possessions rely solely on the goodwill of our leaders; in other words, we won’t have any security at all.

It is, therefore, a just political maxim, that every man must be supposed a knave; though, at the same time, it appears somewhat strange, that a maxim should be true in politics which is false in fact. But to satisfy us on this head, we may consider, that men are generally more honest in their private than in their public capacity, and will go greater lengths to serve a party, than when their own private interest is alone concerned. Honour is a great check upon mankind: but where a considerable body of men act together, this check is in a great measure removed, since a man is sure to be approved of by his own party, for what promotes the common interest; and he soon learns to despise the clamours of adversaries. To which we may add, that every court or senate is determined by the greater number of voices; so that, if self-interest influences only the majority (as it will always do), the whole senate follows the allurements of this separate interest, and acts as if it contained not one member who had any regard to public interest and liberty.

It is, therefore, a reasonable political principle that every man should be assumed to be self-serving; however, it seems a bit odd that a principle could be true in politics while being false in reality. To explain this, we can consider that people tend to be more honest in their private lives than in public roles, and they will go further to support a group than when their own interests are at stake. Honor keeps people in check, but when a large group of people acts together, that check is largely gone, as individuals are usually praised by their own party for actions that benefit the collective interest, and they quickly learn to ignore the criticism from opponents. Additionally, every court or senate is swayed by the majority vote; thus, if self-interest sways only the majority (which it often does), the entire assembly tends to cater to those individual interests, acting as if no member cares about public interest and freedom.

When there offers, therefore, to our censure and examination, any plan of government, real or imaginary, where the power is distributed among several courts, and several orders of men, we should always consider the separate interest of each court, and each order; and if we find that, by the skilful division of power, this interest must necessarily, in its operation, concur with the public, we may pronounce that government to be wise and happy. If, on the contrary, separate interest be not checked, and be not directed to the public, we ought to look for nothing but faction, disorder, and tyranny from such a government. In this opinion I am justified by experience, as well as by the authority of all philosophers and politicians, both ancient and modern.

Whenever we evaluate any proposed plan of government, whether real or imagined, that divides power among various courts and different groups, we should always consider the individual interests of each court and each group. If we find that this smart division of power aligns their interests with the public good, we can say that government is wise and effective. Conversely, if individual interests are not contained and do not serve the public, we should expect nothing but conflict, chaos, and oppression from that government. My view is backed by both experience and the teachings of philosophers and politicians from both ancient and modern times.

How much, therefore, would it have surprised such a genius as Cicero or Tacitus, to have been told, that in a future age there should arise a very regular system of mixed government, where the authority was so distributed, that one rank, whenever it pleased, might swallow up all the rest, and engross the whole power of the constitution! Such a government, they would say, will not be a mixed government. For so great is the natural ambition of men, that they are never satisfied with power; and if one order of men, by pursuing its own interest, can usurp upon every other order, it will certainly do so, and render itself, as far as possible, absolute and uncontrollable.

How much would it have surprised brilliant thinkers like Cicero or Tacitus to be told that in a future time, there would be a structured system of mixed government where power was so divided that one group could, whenever it wanted, dominate all the others and take all the authority of the constitution! They would argue that this wouldn’t really be a mixed government. The natural ambition of people is so great that they are never satisfied with power; if one group can pursue its own interests to overpower every other group, it definitely will, making itself as absolute and uncontrollable as possible.

But, in this opinion, experience shows they would have been mistaken. For this is actually the case with the British constitution. The share of power allotted by our constitution to the House of Commons, is so great, that it absolutely commands all the other parts of the government. The king's legislative power is plainly no proper check to it. For though the king has a negative in framing laws, yet this, in fact, is esteemed of so little moment, that whatever is voted by the two Houses, is always sure to pass into a law, and the royal assent is little better than a form. The principal weight of the crown lies in the executive; power. But, besides that the executive power in every government is altogether subordinate to the legislative; besides this, I say, the exercise of this power requires an immense expense, and the Commons have assumed to themselves the sole right of granting money. How easy, therefore, would it be for that house to wrest from the crown all these powers, one after another, by making every grant conditional, and choosing their time so well, that their refusal of supply should only distress the government, without giving foreign powers any advantage over us! Did the House of Commons depend in the same manner upon the king, and had none of the members any property but from his gift, would not he command all their resolutions, and be from that moment absolute? As to the House of Lords, they are a very powerful support to the crown, so long as they are, in their turn, supported by it; but both experience and reason show, that they have no force or authority sufficient to maintain themselves alone, without such support.

But in this view, experience shows they would have been wrong. This is exactly the case with the British constitution. The amount of power given to the House of Commons is so significant that it completely controls all other parts of the government. The king's legislative power clearly doesn't serve as an effective check on it. Although the king has the ability to veto laws, this is considered so insignificant that anything passed by the two Houses is always likely to become law, and the royal assent is just a formality. The primary strength of the crown lies in the executive power. However, this executive power is entirely subordinate to the legislative power; moreover, exercising this power requires a huge amount of money, and the Commons have claimed the sole right to grant funds. Therefore, it would be quite easy for that House to strip the crown of all these powers one by one, by making every appropriation conditional and timing it so that their refusal to supply funds only harms the government, without giving foreign powers any advantage over us! If the House of Commons depended on the king in the same way and no members held any property except by his gift, wouldn't he be able to control all their decisions and, from that point, be absolutely in charge? As for the House of Lords, they provide strong support to the crown as long as they are, in turn, supported by it; but both experience and reason indicate that they lack the strength or authority to sustain themselves independently without such support.

How, therefore, shall we solve this paradox? And by what means is this member of our constitution confined within the proper limits, since, from our very constitution, it must necessarily have as much power as it demands, and can only be confined by itself? How is this consistent with our experience of human nature? I answer, that the interest of the body is here restrained by that of the individuals, and that the House of Commons stretches not its power, because such an usurpation would be contrary to the interest of the majority of its members. The crown has so many offices at its disposal, that, when assisted by the honest and disinterested part of the House, it will always command the resolutions of the whole, so far, at least, as to preserve the ancient constitution from danger. We may, therefore, give to this influence what name we please; we may call it by the invidious appellations of corruption and dependence; but some degree and some kind of it are inseparable from the very nature of the constitution, and necessary to the preservation of our mixed government.

How can we solve this paradox? And how is this part of our constitution kept within the right limits, since it must naturally have as much power as it seeks, and can only limit itself? How does this fit with what we know about human nature? I believe that the interests of the collective are checked by those of the individuals, and that the House of Commons does not extend its power because doing so would go against the interests of the majority of its members. The crown controls so many positions that, when supported by the honest and selfless members of the House, it can always sway the decisions of everyone, at least enough to protect the old constitution from harm. Therefore, we can label this influence however we like; we can call it the unflattering names of corruption and dependence; but some form of it is unavoidable in the very nature of our constitution and essential for maintaining our mixed government.

Instead, then, of asserting absolutely, that the dependence of parliament, in every degree, is an infringement of British liberty, the country party should have made some concessions to their adversaries, and have only examined what was the proper degree of this dependence, beyond which it became dangerous to liberty. But such a moderation is not to be expected in party men of any kind. After a concession of this nature, all declamation must be abandoned; and a calm inquiry into the proper degree of court influence and parliamentary dependence would have been expected by the readers. And though the advantage, in such a controversy, might possibly remain to the country party, yet the victory would not be so complete as they wish for, nor would a true patriot have given an entire loose to his zeal, for fear of running matters into a contrary extreme, by diminishing too[2] far the influence of the crown. It was, therefore, thought best to deny that this extreme could ever be dangerous to the constitution, or that the crown could ever have too little influence over members of parliament.

Instead of claiming outright that any degree of parliamentary dependence violates British liberty, the country party should have made some concessions to their opponents and examined what the appropriate level of this dependence is, beyond which it poses a risk to liberty. However, such moderation isn’t typically expected from party members of any kind. After making such a concession, all grandstanding must stop; readers would expect a calm investigation into the right amount of court influence and parliamentary dependence. And while the country party might still benefit in such a debate, their victory wouldn't be as total as they desire, nor would a true patriot completely allow his passion to take over, fearing that it might push things too far in the opposite direction by significantly reducing the crown's influence. Therefore, it was deemed better to reject the idea that this extreme could ever be harmful to the constitution or that the crown could have too little influence over parliament members.

All questions concerning the proper medium between extremes are difficult to be decided; both because it is not easy to find words proper to fix this medium, and because the good and ill, in such cases, run so gradually into each other, as even to render our sentiments doubtful and uncertain. But there is a peculiar difficulty in the present case, which would embarrass the most knowing and most impartial examiner. The power of the crown is always lodged in a single person, either king or minister; and as this person may have either a greater or less degree of ambition, capacity, courage, popularity, or fortune, the power, which is too great in one hand, may become too little in another. In pure republics, where the authority is distributed among several assemblies or senates, the checks and controls are more regular in their operation; because the members of such numerous assemblies may be presumed to be always nearly equal in capacity and virtue; and it is only their number, riches, or authority, which enter into consideration. But a limited monarchy admits not of any such stability; nor is it possible to assign to the crown such a determinate degree of power, as will, in every hand, form a proper counterbalance to the other parts of the constitution. This is an unavoidable disadvantage, among the many advantages attending that species of government.

All questions about finding the right balance between extremes are hard to resolve; partly because it’s tough to find the right words to define that balance, and partly because good and bad in these situations blend together enough to make our feelings doubtful and uncertain. However, there’s a unique difficulty in this situation that would confuse even the most knowledgeable and impartial examiner. The power of the crown is always held by one person, either a king or a minister; and since this person can have varying levels of ambition, skill, bravery, popularity, or luck, the power that’s too much for one may be too little for another. In pure republics, where power is shared among various assemblies or senates, the checks and balances tend to function more effectively because the members of those numerous assemblies are generally expected to be fairly equal in ability and integrity; it’s only their numbers, wealth, or authority that matter. But a limited monarchy doesn’t have that kind of stability; nor can you assign a specific degree of power to the crown that will provide a proper balance against the other parts of the constitution in every situation. This is an unavoidable downside among the many advantages of that type of government.

[1] I have frequently observed, in comparing the conduct of the court and country party, that the former are commonly less assuming and dogmatical in conversation, more apt to make concessions, and though not, perhaps, more susceptible of conviction, yet more able to bear contradiction than the latter, who are apt to fly out upon any opposition, and to regard one as a mercenary, designing fellow, if he argues with any coolness and impartiality, or makes any concessions to their adversaries. This is a fact, which, I believe, every one may have observed who has been much in companies where political questions have been discussed; though, were one to ask the reason of this difference, every party would be apt to assign a different reason. Gentlemen in the opposition will ascribe it to the very nature of their party, which, being founded on public spirit, and a zeal for the constitution, cannot easily endure such doctrines as are of pernicious consequence to liberty. The courtiers, on the other hand, will be apt to put us in mind of the clown mentioned by Lord Shaftesbury. 'A clown,' says that excellent author, 'once took a fancy to hear the Latin disputes of doctors at an university. He was asked what pleasure he could take in viewing such combatants, when he could never know so much as which of the parties had the better.'—'For that matter,' replied the clown, 'I a'n't such a fool neither, but I can see who's the first that puts t'other into a passion.' Nature herself dictated this lesson to the clown, that he who had the better of the argument would be easy and well humoured: but he who was unable to support his cause by reason would naturally lose his temper, and grow violent.

[1] I've often noticed that when comparing the behavior of the court and country parties, the former tend to be less arrogant and dogmatic in conversation, more willing to make concessions, and while they may not necessarily be more open to persuasion, they're generally better at handling disagreement than the latter. Those in the country party often react strongly to any opposition and view anyone who calmly debates or concedes to their rivals as a self-serving, scheming person. This is something I believe anyone who has spent time in discussions about political issues has likely observed; however, if you were to ask each party why this difference exists, they'd probably provide different explanations. Members of the opposition would likely attribute it to the very nature of their party, which is based on public spirit and a commitment to the constitution, making them less tolerant of views that could harm liberty. On the other hand, the courtiers might remind us of the story about the clown mentioned by Lord Shaftesbury. 'A clown,' says that insightful author, 'once took an interest in watching the Latin debates of doctors at a university. He was asked what enjoyment he found in watching such contenders when he couldn't even tell which side was winning.'—'Well,' replied the clown, 'I'm not that foolish; I can tell who gets the other riled up first.' Nature itself taught the clown this lesson: the one who has a stronger argument remains calm and in good spirits, while the one who can't defend their position with reason will end up losing their cool and becoming aggressive.

To which of these reasons will we adhere? To neither of them, in my opinion, unless we have a mind to enlist ourselves and become zealots in either party. I believe I can assign the reason of this different conduct of the two parties, without offending either. The country party are plainly most popular at present, and perhaps have been so in most administrations so that, being accustomed to prevail in company, they cannot endure to hear their opinions controverted, but are so confident on the public favour, as if they were supported in all their sentiments by the most infallible demonstration. The courtiers, on the other hand, are Commonly run down by your popular talkers, that if you speak to them with any moderation, or make them the smallest concessions, they think themselves extremely obliged to you, and are apt to return the favour by a like moderation and facility on their part. To be furious and passionate, they know, would only gain them the character of shameless mercenaries, not that of zealous patriots, which is the character that such a warm behaviour is apt to acquire to the other party.

To which of these reasons will we stick? In my view, to neither, unless we want to commit ourselves and become fanatics for either side. I think I can explain the different behaviors of the two parties without upsetting either one. The country party is clearly more popular right now, and they probably have been throughout most administrations. So, used to winning in groups, they can’t stand to hear their opinions challenged. They are so sure of public support that they act as if their views are backed by undeniable proof. On the other hand, the courtiers are often dismissed by popular speakers. If you talk to them moderately or give them even the slightest concession, they feel incredibly grateful and tend to reciprocate with similar moderation and agreeableness. They know that being angry and passionate would only make them look like shameless mercenaries, not dedicated patriots, which is how such heated behavior is perceived by the other party.

In all controversies, we find, without regarding the truth or falsehood on either side, that those who defend the established and popular opinions are always most dogmatical and imperious in their style: while their adversaries affect almost extraordinary gentleness and moderation, in order to soften, as much as possible, any prejudices that may be Against them. Consider the behaviour of our Freethinkers of all denominations, whether they be such as decry all revelation, or only oppose the exorbitant power of the clergy, Collins, Tindal, Foster, Hoadley. Compare their moderation and good manners with the furious zeal and scurrility of their adversaries, and you will be convinced of the truth of my observation. A like difference may be observed in the conduct of those French writers, who maintained the controversy with regard to ancient and modern learning. Boileau, Monsieur and Madame Dacier, l'Abbé de Bos, who defended the party of the ancients, mixed their reasonings with satire and invective, while Fontenelle, la Motte, Charpentier, and even Perrault, never transgressed the bounds of moderation and good breeding, though provoked by the most injurious treatment of their adversaries.

In every debate, it's clear that regardless of the truth or falsehood on either side, those defending established and popular views tend to be the most dogmatic and commanding in their tone. Meanwhile, their opponents often display an almost remarkable gentleness and restraint to try to reduce any biases that might be against them. Take a look at the behavior of our Freethinkers of all kinds, whether they reject all revelations or just oppose the excessive power of the clergy, like Collins, Tindal, Foster, and Hoadley. When you compare their calmness and politeness to the fierce zeal and insults from their opponents, you’ll see the truth in my observation. A similar difference can be seen in the actions of those French writers who engaged in the debate about ancient versus modern knowledge. Boileau, Monsieur and Madame Dacier, l'Abbé de Bos, defending the ancients, mixed their arguments with satire and aggression, while Fontenelle, la Motte, Charpentier, and even Perrault never crossed the lines of moderation and politeness, even when faced with the most hurtful attacks from their rivals.

I must however observe, that this remark with regard to the seeming moderation of the court party, is entirely confined to conversation, and to gentlemen who have been engaged by interest or inclination in that party. For as to the court writers, being commonly hired scribblers, they are altogether as scurrilous as the mercenaries of the other party: nor has the Gazetteer any advantage, in this respect, above common sense. A man of education will, in any party, discover himself to be such by his goodbreeding and decency, as a scoundrel will always betray the opposite qualities. The false accusers accused, &c. is very scurrilous, though that side of the question, being least popular, should be defended with most moderation. When L—d B—e, L—d M—t, Mr. L—n, take the pen in hand, though they write with warmth, they presume not upon their popularity so far as to transgress the bounds of decency.

I have to point out, though, that this comment about the seemingly moderate behavior of the court party only applies to conversations among gentlemen who have some personal interest or inclination toward that party. As for the court writers, who are usually just paid hacks, they are just as nasty as the hired guns of the other party: and the Gazetteer offers no real advantage in this regard compared to common sense. An educated person will show their character in any party through their manners and decency, while a scoundrel will always reveal their true nature. The false accusers accused, etc., is very offensive, even though this side of the debate, being less popular, should be defended more moderately. When L—d B—e, L—d M—t, and Mr. L—n take up the pen, even though they write passionately, they don't let their popularity lead them to cross the line of decency.

I am led into this train of reflection by considering some papers wrote upon that grand topic of court influence and parliamentary dependence, where, in my humble opinion, the country party show too rigid an inflexibility, and too great a jealousy of making concessions to their adversaries. Their reasonings lose their force by being carried too far and the popularity of their opinions has seduced them to neglect in some measure their justness and solidity. The following reasoning will, I hope, serve to justify me in this opinion.

I started thinking about this after looking at some papers written on the big issue of court influence and parliamentary dependence, where, in my opinion, the country party is too rigid and overly wary of making any concessions to their opponents. Their arguments lose impact because they go too far, and the popularity of their views has led them to somewhat ignore their validity and strength. I hope the following reasoning will justify my opinion.

[2] By that influence of the crown, which I would justify, I mean only that which arises from the offices and honours that are at the disposal of the crown. As to private bribery, it may be considered in the same light as the practice of employing spies, which is scarcely justifiable in a good minister, and is infamous in a bad one; but to be a spy, or to be corrupted, is always infamous under all ministers, and is to be regarded as a shameless prostitution. Polybius justly esteems the pecuniary influence of the senate and censors to be one of the regular and constitutional weights which preserved the balance of the Roman government.—Lib. vi. cap. 15.

[2] By that influence of the crown, which I would defend, I mean only the power that comes from the positions and honors that the crown controls. As for private bribery, it can be seen similarly to the use of spies, which is hardly acceptable for a good minister and is disgraceful for a bad one; however, being a spy or being bribed is always disgraceful, no matter who the minister is, and should be viewed as a shameless act of compromise. Polybius rightly views the monetary influence of the senate and censors as one of the essential and constitutional checks that maintained the balance of the Roman government.—Lib. vi. cap. 15.


WHETHER THE BRITISH GOVERNMENT INCLINES MORE TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY OR TO A REPUBLIC

It affords a violent prejudice against almost every science, that no prudent man, however sure of his principles, dares prophesy concerning any event, or foretell the remote consequences of things. A physician will not venture to pronounce concerning the condition of his patient a fortnight or a month after: and still less dares a politician foretell the situation of public affairs a few years hence. Harrington thought himself so sure of his general principle, that the balance of power depends on that of property, that he ventured to pronounce it impossible ever to reestablish monarchy in England: but his book was scarcely published when the king was restored; and we see that monarchy has ever since subsisted upon the same footing as before. Notwithstanding this unlucky example, I will venture to examine an important question, to wit, Whether the British Government inclines more to absolute monarchy or to a republic; and in which of these two species of government it will most probably terminate? As there seems not to be any great danger of a sudden revolution either way, I shall at least escape the shame attending my temerity, if I should be found to have been mistaken.

It shows a strong bias against almost every science, so that no wise person, no matter how confident in their beliefs, dares to predict any event or foresee the distant consequences of things. A doctor won’t risk saying what his patient’s condition will be in two weeks or a month; even less will a politician dare to predict the state of public affairs a few years down the line. Harrington was so confident in his main idea, that the balance of power depends on that of property, that he boldly claimed it would be impossible to ever restore the monarchy in England. But his book was barely published when the king was reinstated, and we see that monarchy has continued to exist in the same way as before. Despite this unfortunate example, I’m willing to tackle an important question, namely, Whether the British Government leans more towards absolute monarchy or a republic; and which of these two forms of government it is most likely to end up with? Since there doesn’t seem to be much risk of a sudden revolution in either direction, at least I won’t have to face the embarrassment of my boldness if I turn out to be wrong.

Those who assert that the balance of our government inclines towards absolute monarchy, may support their opinion by the following reasons: That property has a great influence on power cannot possibly be denied; but yet the general maxim, that the balance of the one depends on the balance of the other, must be received with several limitations. It is evident, that much less property in a single hand will be able to counterbalance a greater property in several; not only because it is difficult to make many persons combine in the same views and measures, but because property, when united, causes much greater dependence than the same property when dispersed. A hundred persons of £1,000 a year apiece, can consume all their income, and nobody shall ever be the better for them, except their servants and tradesmen, who justly regard their profits as the product of their own labour. But a man possessed of £100,000 a year, if he has either any generosity or any cunning, may create a great dependence by obligations, and still a greater by expectations. Hence we may observe, that, in all free governments, any subject exorbitantly rich has always created jealousy, even though his riches bore no proportion to those of the state. Crassus's fortune, if I remember well, amounted only to about two millions and a half of our money; yet we find, that though his genius was nothing extraordinary, he was able, by means of his riches alone, to counterbalance, during his lifetime, the power of Pompey, as well as that of Cæsar, who afterwards became master of the world. The wealth of the Medici made them masters of Florence, though it is probable it was not considerable, compared to the united property of that opulent republic.

Those who claim that our government leans towards absolute monarchy can back up their view with the following reasons: It’s undeniable that property has a significant impact on power; however, the general principle, that the balance of one depends on the balance of the other, must be taken with several caveats. It's clear that a smaller amount of property in one person's hands cannot match the power of a larger amount spread across many individuals; not only because it’s tough to get many people to agree on the same goals and actions, but also because concentrated property creates much more dependence than the same property divided among many. A hundred people with an income of £1,000 a year each can spend all their income, and no one benefits from it except their servants and tradespeople, who view their earnings as the result of their own efforts. But a person with an annual income of £100,000, whether due to generosity or cunning, can create significant dependence through obligations and even greater dependence through expectations. Thus, it’s evident that in all free governments, any person who is excessively wealthy has generated jealousy, even if their wealth doesn’t compare to that of the state. If I recall correctly, Crassus’s fortune was only about two and a half million of our currency; yet, we find that, despite not being particularly extraordinary, he was able to use his wealth alone to counterbalance the power of both Pompey and Caesar during his lifetime, who later became the master of the world. The wealth of the Medici made them rulers of Florence, even though it was probably not substantial compared to the combined wealth of that prosperous republic.

These considerations are apt to make one entertain a magnificent idea of the British spirit and love of liberty, since we could maintain our free government, during so many centuries, against our sovereigns, who, besides the power, and dignity, and majesty of the crown, have always been possessed of much more property than any subject has ever enjoyed in any commonwealth. But it may be said that this spirit, however great, will never be able to support itself against that immense property which is now lodged in the king, and which is still increasing. Upon a moderate computation, there are near three millions a year at the disposal of the crown. The civil list amounts to near a million; the collection of all taxes to another; and the employments in the army and navy, together with ecclesiastical preferments, to above a third million:—an enormous sum, and what may fairly be computed to be more than a thirtieth part of the whole income and labour of the kingdom. When we add to this great property the increasing luxury of the nation, our proneness to corruption, together with the great power and prerogatives of the crown, and the command of military force, there is no one but must despair of being able, without extraordinary efforts, to support our free government much longer under these disadvantages.

These thoughts might lead someone to think highly of the British spirit and love for freedom, especially since we’ve managed to maintain our free government for so many centuries against our rulers, who, along with the power, dignity, and majesty of the crown, have always had much more wealth than any subject in any commonwealth. However, it can be argued that this spirit, no matter how strong, will struggle to hold its ground against the vast wealth that is currently held by the king, which continues to grow. By a rough estimate, there’s almost three million a year available to the crown. The civil list is around a million; the collection of all taxes adds another million; and the jobs in the army and navy, along with church positions, account for over a third of a million:—an enormous sum that can reasonably be considered more than one-thirtieth of the total income and labor of the country. When we factor in this great wealth along with the rising luxury in the nation, our tendency towards corruption, the significant power and privileges of the crown, and control over military force, it’s hard not to feel hopeless about being able to maintain our free government much longer without extraordinary efforts in light of these challenges.

On the other hand, those who maintain that the bias of the British government leans towards a republic, may support their opinions by specious arguments. It may be said, that though this immense property in the crown be joined to the dignity of first magistrate, and to many other legal powers and prerogatives, which should naturally give it greater influence; yet it really becomes less dangerous to liberty upon that very account. Were England a republic, and were any private man possessed of a revenue, a third, or even a tenth part as large as that of the crown, he would very justly excite jealousy; because he would infallibly have great authority in the government. And such an irregular authority, not avowed by the laws, is always more dangerous than a much greater authority derived from them. A man possessed of usurped power can set no bounds to his pretensions: his partisans have liberty to hope for every thing in his favour: his enemies provoke his ambition with his fears, by the violence of their opposition: and the government being thrown into a ferment, every corrupted humour in the state naturally gathers to him. On the contrary, a legal authority, though great, has always some bounds, which terminate both the hopes and pretensions of the person possessed of it: the laws must have provided a remedy against its excesses: such an eminent magistrate has much to fear, and little to hope, from his usurpations: and as his legal authority is quietly submitted to, he has small temptation and small opportunity of extending it further. Besides, it happens, with regard to ambitious aims and projects, what may be observed with regard to sects of philosophy and religion. A new sect excites such a ferment, and is both opposed and defended with such vehemence, that it always spreads faster, and multiplies its partisans with greater rapidity than any old established opinion, recommended by the sanction of the laws and of antiquity. Such is the nature of novelty, that, where any thing pleases, it becomes doubly agreeable, if new: but if it displeases, it is doubly displeasing upon that very account. And, in most cases, the violence of enemies is favourable to ambitious projects, as well as the zeal of partisans.

On the other hand, those who argue that the British government's bias favors a republic may support their views with misleading arguments. It can be said that, although this vast property is held by the crown along with the title of the chief magistrate and many other legal powers and privileges that should naturally give it greater influence, it actually poses a lesser threat to liberty for that very reason. If England were a republic and any private individual had a revenue that was a third or even a tenth as large as that of the crown, it would justifiably raise concerns; because they'd undoubtedly hold significant power in the government. Such unauthorized authority, not acknowledged by the laws, is always more dangerous than a much larger authority that is legally granted. A person with usurped power can set no limits to their claims: their supporters are free to expect everything in their favor; their opponents stir up their ambitions with their fears through aggressive opposition; and as the government gets thrown into turmoil, every corrupt influence in the state naturally gravitates toward them. Conversely, a legal authority, even if it's substantial, has certain limits that cap the hopes and claims of the person holding it: the laws must have provided a way to address its excesses; such a prominent official has much to fear and little to hope for from their overreach; and as their legal authority is quietly accepted, they have little incentive and few opportunities to extend it further. Additionally, regarding ambitious goals and plans, we can observe what happens with philosophical and religious sects. A new sect stirs up such a disturbance and is both opposed and defended with such intensity that it always spreads faster and gains followers more rapidly than any long-established belief, which is supported by the authority of the laws and tradition. Such is the nature of novelty that when something is pleasing, it becomes even more enjoyable simply because it’s new; but if it’s unappealing, it’s doubly off-putting for that same reason. And in most cases, the hostility of opponents is beneficial to ambitious projects, as is the enthusiasm of supporters.

It may further be said, that, though men be much governed by interest, yet even interest itself, and all human affairs, are entirely governed by opinion. Now, there has been a sudden and sensible change in the opinions of men within these last fifty years, by the progress of learning and of liberty. Most people in this Island have divested themselves of all superstitious reverence to names and authority: the clergy have much lost their credit: their pretensions and doctrines have been ridiculed; and even religion can scarcely support itself in the world. The mere name of king commands little respect; and to talk of a king as God's vicegerent on earth, or to give him any of those magnificent titles which formerly dazzled mankind, would but excite laughter in every one. Though the crown, by means of its large revenue, may maintain its authority, in times of tranquillity, upon private interest and influence, yet, as the least shock or convulsion must break all these interests to pieces, the royal power, being no longer supported by the settled principles and opinions of men, will immediately dissolve. Had men been in the same disposition at the Revolution, as they are at present, monarchy would have run a great risk of being entirely lost in this Island.

It can also be said that while people are often driven by self-interest, even that self-interest and all human activities are completely influenced by opinion. Recently, there has been a noticeable shift in people's opinions over the last fifty years, thanks to advancements in knowledge and freedom. Most people on this Island have shed their blind reverence for names and authority: the clergy have significantly lost their credibility; their claims and beliefs have been mocked; and religion can barely hold its ground anymore. The mere title of king commands little respect, and discussing a king as God's representative on Earth or using those grand titles that once captivated people would provoke laughter from everyone. Although the crown, due to its substantial revenue, can maintain its authority during peaceful times through personal interests and influence, any significant disturbance or upheaval would shatter those interests, and because royal power is no longer backed by established beliefs and opinions, it would quickly collapse. If people's attitudes had been what they are now during the Revolution, monarchy would have faced a serious threat of being completely lost in this Island.

Durst I venture to deliver my own sentiments amidst these opposite arguments, I would assert, that, unless there happen some extraordinary convulsion, the power of the crown, by means of its large revenue, is rather upon the increase; though at the same time, I own that its progress seems very slow, and almost insensible. The tide has run long, and with some rapidity, to the side of popular government, and is just beginning to turn towards monarchy.

If I dare to share my thoughts amid these conflicting viewpoints, I would say that, unless something extraordinary happens, the power of the crown, due to its substantial income, is actually on the rise; however, I admit that this growth appears to be very slow and almost unnoticeable. The momentum has been heavily favoring popular government for a long time and is just starting to shift back toward monarchy.

It is well known, that every government must come to a period, and that death is unavoidable to the political, as well as to the animal body. But, as one kind of death may be preferable to another, it may be inquired, whether it be more desirable for the British constitution to terminate in a popular government, or in an absolute monarchy? Here I would frankly declare, that though liberty be preferable to slavery, in almost every case; yet I should rather wish to see an absolute monarch than a republic in this Island. For let us consider what kind of republic we have reason to expect. The question is not concerning any fine imaginary republic, of which a man forms a plan in his closet. There is no doubt but a popular government may be imagined more perfect than an absolute monarchy, or even than our present constitution. But what reason have we to expect that any such government will ever be established in Great Britain, upon the dissolution of our monarchy? If any single person acquire power enough to take our constitution to pieces, and put it up anew, he is really an absolute monarch; and we have already had an instance of this kind, sufficient to convince us, that such a person will never resign his power, or establish any free government. Matters, therefore, must be trusted to their natural progress and operation; and the House of Commons, according to its present constitution, must be the only legislature in such a popular government. The inconveniences attending such a situation of affairs present themselves by thousands. If the House of Commons, in such a case, ever dissolve itself, which is not to be expected, we may look for a civil war every election. If it continue itself, we shall suffer all the tyranny of a faction sub-divided into new factions. And, as such a violent government cannot long subsist, we shall, at last, after many convulsions and civil wars, find repose in absolute monarchy, which it would have been happier for us to have established peaceably from the beginning. Absolute monarchy, therefore, is the easiest death, the true Euthanasia of the British constitution.

It’s well known that every government comes to an end, and that death is unavoidable for both political structures and living beings. However, one type of death might be better than another, so we can ask if it’s more desirable for the British constitution to end in a popular government or in an absolute monarchy. Personally, I would honestly say that while freedom is generally better than oppression, I would prefer to see an absolute monarch rather than a republic on this Island. Let's think about what kind of republic we could realistically expect. The question isn’t about some idealized republic that someone dreams up in their mind. There’s no doubt that a popular government could be imagined as more perfect than an absolute monarchy or even than our current constitution. But what reason do we have to believe that such a government will ever be created in Great Britain when our monarchy falls apart? If a single person gains enough power to dismantle our constitution and rebuild it, they are essentially an absolute monarch; we’ve already seen an example of this, which proves that such a person will never give up their power or create any free government. Therefore, we must rely on the natural progression and functioning of things, and the House of Commons, as it currently stands, would be the only legislature in a popular government. The complications from such a scenario are numerous. If the House of Commons were to dissolve itself, which isn’t likely to happen, we could anticipate civil war with every election. If it remains intact, we would face all the tyranny of a faction that splits into new factions. And because such a violent government can’t last long, we would eventually, after many upheavals and civil wars, find ourselves settled under absolute monarchy, which would have been better for us to establish peacefully from the start. Therefore, absolute monarchy is the least painful end, the true Euthanasia of the British constitution.

Thus, if we have reason to be more jealous of monarchy, because the danger is more imminent from that quarter; we have also reason to be more jealous of popular government, because that danger is more terrible. This may teach us a lesson of moderation in all our political controversies.

Thus, if we have more reason to be wary of monarchy, because the threat is more immediate from that side; we also have more reason to be wary of popular government, because that threat is more severe. This may teach us a lesson in moderation in all our political debates.


OF PARTIES IN GENERAL

Of all men that distinguish themselves by memorable achievements, the first place of honour seems due to LEGISLATORS and founders of states, who transmit a system of laws and institutions to secure the peace, happiness, and liberty of future generations. The influence of useful inventions in the arts and sciences may, perhaps, extend further than that of wise laws, whose effects are limited both in time and place; but the benefit arising from the former is not so sensible as that which results from the latter. Speculative sciences do, indeed, improve the mind, but this advantage reaches only to a few persons, who have leisure to apply themselves to them. And as to practical arts, which increase the commodities and enjoyments of life, it is well known that men's happiness consists not so much in an abundance of these, as in the peace and security with which they possess them: and those blessings can only be derived from good government. Not to mention, that general virtue and good morals in a state, which are so requisite to happiness, can never arise from the most refined precepts of philosophy, or even the severest injunctions of religion; but must proceed entirely from the virtuous education of youth, the effect of wise laws and institutions. I must, therefore, presume to differ from Lord Bacon in this particular, and must regard antiquity as somewhat unjust in its distribution of honours, when it made gods of all the inventors of useful arts, such as Ceres, Bacchus, Æsculapius and dignified legislators, such as Romulus and Theseus, only with the appellation of demigods and heroes.

Of all the people who stand out for their significant accomplishments, it seems that the top honor goes to lawmakers and founders of nations, who create a system of laws and institutions to ensure the peace, happiness, and freedom of future generations. The impact of beneficial inventions in the arts and sciences might, in some ways, reach further than that of wise laws, which have effects that are limited both in time and place; however, the benefits from the former aren't as noticeable as those resulting from the latter. Theoretical sciences do improve our thinking, but this benefit only applies to a few people who have the time to engage with them. As for practical skills that enhance the goods and pleasures of life, it's well known that people's happiness doesn't depend so much on having many of these but on the peace and security with which they enjoy them—blessings that can only come from good governance. Moreover, the general virtue and morality necessary for happiness in a society cannot stem from the most polished philosophical teachings or even the strictest religious commands; they must come from the moral education of the young, influenced by wise laws and institutions. Therefore, I have to respectfully disagree with Lord Bacon on this point and believe that ancient times were somewhat unfair in their honors when they deified all the inventors of useful arts, like Ceres, Bacchus, and Æsculapius, along with esteemed lawmakers like Romulus and Theseus, who were only called demigods and heroes.

As much as legislators and founders of states ought to be honoured and respected among men, as much ought the founders of sects and factions to be detested and hated; because the influence of faction is directly contrary to that of laws. Factions subvert government, render laws impotent, and beget the fiercest animosities among men of the same nation, who ought to give mutual assistance and protection to each other. And what should render the founders of parties more odious, is the difficulty of extirpating these weeds, when once they have taken root in any state. They naturally propagate themselves for many centuries, and seldom end but by the total dissolution of that government, in which they are sown. They are, besides, plants which grow most plentiful in the richest soil; and though absolute governments be not wholly free from them, it must be confessed, that they rise more easily, and propagate themselves faster in free governments, where they always infect the legislature itself, which alone could be able, by the steady application of rewards and punishments, to eradicate them.

As much as lawmakers and founders of states deserve to be honored and respected, the founders of groups and factions should be detested and hated. The influence of factions directly opposes that of laws. Factions undermine government, make laws ineffective, and create the fiercest hostilities among people of the same nation, who should be supporting and protecting each other. What makes the founders of parties even more repulsive is how hard it is to eliminate these issues once they take root in any state. They naturally propagate for many centuries and rarely end without completely destroying the government in which they grow. Moreover, they thrive most in the richest environments; while absolute governments are not entirely immune to them, it's true that they emerge more easily and spread faster in free governments, where they always infect the legislature itself, which is the only body that could effectively eradicate them through consistent rewards and punishments.

Factions may be divided into Personal and Real; that is, into factions founded on personal friendship or animosity among such as compose the contending parties, and into those founded on some real difference of sentiment or interest. The reason of this distinction is obvious, though I must acknowledge, that parties are seldom found pure and unmixed, either of the one kind or the other. It is not often seen, that a government divides into factions, where there is no difference in the views of the constituent members, either real or apparent, trivial or material: and in those factions, which are founded on the most real and most material difference, there is always observed a great deal of personal animosity or affection. But notwithstanding this mixture, a party may be denominated either personal or real, according to that principle which is predominant, and is found to have the greatest influence.

Factions can be categorized as Personal and Real; that is, into factions based on personal friendships or rivalries among the members of the conflicting groups, and those based on genuine differences in opinions or interests. The reason for this distinction is clear, although I must admit that groups are rarely found to be purely one type or the other. It's uncommon for a government to split into factions where there’s no difference in the perspectives of its members, whether those differences are minor or significant. Even in factions based on the most substantial and important differences, there is usually a noticeable amount of personal hostility or loyalty. However, despite this mix, a faction can be labeled as either personal or real, depending on which principle is most dominant and has the strongest influence.

Personal factions arise most easily in small republics. Every domestic quarrel, there, becomes an affair of state. Love, vanity, emulation, any passion, as well as ambition and resentment, begets public division. The NERI and BIANCHI of Florence, the FREGOSI and ADORNI of Genoa, the COLONNESI and ORSINI of modern Rome, were parties of this kind.

Personal factions emerge most easily in small republics. Every domestic dispute there becomes a matter of public concern. Love, vanity, rivalry, any strong emotion, along with ambition and resentment, leads to public division. The NERI and BIANCHI of Florence, the FREGOSI and ADORNI of Genoa, the COLONNESI and ORSINI of modern Rome, were examples of these kinds of parties.

Men have such a propensity to divide into personal factions, that the smallest appearance of real difference will produce them. What can be imagined more trivial than the difference between one colour of livery and another in horse races? Yet this difference begat two most inveterate factions in the Greek empire, the PRASINI and VENETI, who never suspended their animosities till they ruined that unhappy government.

Men have such a tendency to split into personal groups that even the slightest sign of a real difference can cause it. What could be more trivial than the difference between one color of uniform and another in horse races? Yet this small difference led to two deeply entrenched factions in the Greek empire, the PRASINI and VENETI, who never set aside their feuds until they destroyed that unfortunate government.

We find in the Roman history a remarkable dissension between two tribes, the POLLIA and PAPIRIA, which continued for the space of near three hundred years, and discovered itself in their suffrages at every election of magistrates. This faction was the more remarkable, as it could continue for so long a tract of time; even though it did not spread itself, nor draw any of the other tribes into a share of the quarrel. If mankind had not a strong propensity to such divisions, the indifference of the rest of the community must have suppressed this foolish animosity, that had not any aliment of new benefits and injuries, of general sympathy and antipathy, which never fail to take place, when the whole state is rent into equal factions.

We see in Roman history a significant conflict between two tribes, the POLLIA and PAPIRIA, which lasted for nearly three hundred years and showed up in their votes during every election of magistrates. This rivalry is even more notable because it lasted so long without spreading or involving any of the other tribes in the dispute. If people weren't so inclined toward such divisions, the indifference of the rest of the community would have put an end to this pointless animosity, which had no source of new benefits or grievances, or shared feelings of support and opposition, that usually arise when a whole state is divided into equal factions.

Nothing is more usual than to see parties, which have begun upon a real difference, continue even after that difference is lost. When men are once enlisted on opposite sides, they contract an affection to the persons with whom they are united, and an animosity against their antagonists; and these passions they often transmit to their posterity. The real difference between Guelf and Ghibelline was long lost in Italy, before these factions were extinguished. The Guelfs adhered to the pope, the Ghibellines to the emperor; yet the family of Sforza, who were in alliance with the emperor, though they were Guelfs, being expelled Milan by the king of France, assisted by Jacomo Trivulzio and the Ghibellines, the pope concurred with the latter, and they formed leagues with the pope against the emperor.

Nothing is more common than to see groups that started out with a genuine disagreement continue even after that disagreement has faded away. Once people are aligned on opposite sides, they develop a loyalty to those on their side and hostility toward their opponents, and these feelings often get passed down to their descendants. The actual conflict between the Guelfs and Ghibellines had long been forgotten in Italy before those factions finally disappeared. The Guelfs supported the pope, while the Ghibellines supported the emperor; however, the Sforza family, who were allied with the emperor but considered themselves Guelfs, were expelled from Milan by the king of France with the help of Jacomo Trivulzio and the Ghibellines. The pope then sided with the Ghibellines, and they formed alliances with him against the emperor.

The civil wars which arose some few years ago in Morocco between the Blacks and Whites, merely on account of their complexion, are founded on a pleasant difference. We laugh at them; but, I believe, were things rightly examined, we afford much more occasion of ridicule to the Moors. For, what are all the wars of religion, which have prevailed in this polite and knowing part of the world? They are certainly more absurd than the Moorish civil wars. The difference of complexion is a sensible and a real difference; but the controversy about an article of faith, which is utterly absurd and unintelligible, is not a difference in sentiment, but in a few phrases and expressions, which one party accepts of without understanding them, and the other refuses in the same manner.[1]

The civil wars that broke out a few years ago in Morocco between the Blacks and Whites were solely due to their skin color and are based on a minor difference. We laugh at them; however, I think that if we looked closely, we actually give the Moors much more reason to laugh at us. What are all the religious wars that have taken place in this cultured and knowledgeable part of the world? They are definitely more ridiculous than the Moorish civil wars. The difference in skin color is real and tangible, but the debates over religious beliefs, which are completely nonsensical and incomprehensible, represent not a difference in opinion but merely a few phrases and terms that one side believes without understanding, while the other side rejects in just the same way.[1]

Real factions may be divided into those from interest, from principle, and from affection. Of all factions, the first are the most reasonable, and the most excusable. Where two orders of men, such as the nobles and people, have a distinct authority in a government, not very accurately balanced and modelled, they naturally follow a distinct interest; nor can we reasonably expect a different conduct, considering that degree of selfishness implanted in human nature. It requires great skill in a legislator to prevent such parties; and many philosophers are of opinion, that this secret, like the grand elixir, or perpetual motion, may amuse men in theory, but can never possibly be reduced to practice. In despotic governments, indeed, factions often do not appear; but they are not the less real; or rather, they are more real and more pernicious upon that very account. The distinct orders of men, nobles and people, soldiers and merchants, have all a distinct interest; but the more powerful oppresses the weaker with impunity, and without resistance; which begets a seeming tranquillity in such governments.

Real factions can be categorized into those based on interest, principle, and affection. Among all factions, the first category is the most reasonable and the most justifiable. When two groups, like the nobles and the common people, have a distinct authority in a government that isn't precisely balanced, they naturally pursue different interests. We can't reasonably expect anything different, given the selfishness inherent in human nature. It takes great skill from a legislator to prevent such divisions; many philosophers believe that this solution, much like the grand elixir or perpetual motion, may intrigue people in theory but can never truly be implemented in practice. In despotic governments, factions may not visibly emerge; however, they are still very much real and, in fact, more harmful for that reason. The different groups, such as nobles and commoners, or soldiers and merchants, each have distinct interests, but the stronger ones oppress the weaker ones without fear of repercussions, creating a false sense of peace in such governments.

There has been an attempt in England to divide the landed and trading part of the nation; but without success. The interests of these two bodies are not really distinct, and never will be so, till our public debts increase to such a degree as to become altogether oppressive and intolerable.

There has been an attempt in England to separate the landed and trading parts of the nation; but it hasn't worked. The interests of these two groups aren't truly different, and they probably won't be until our public debts rise to a level that's completely overwhelming and unbearable.

Parties from principle, especially abstract speculative principle, are known only to modern times, and are, perhaps, the most extraordinary and unaccountable phenomenon that has yet appeared in human affairs. Where different principles beget a contrariety of conduct, which is the case with all different political principles, the matter may be more easily explained. A man who esteems the true right of government to lie in one man, or one family, cannot easily agree with his fellow-citizen, who thinks that another man or family is possessed of this right. Each naturally wishes that right may take place, according to his own notions of it. But where the difference of principle is attended with no contrariety of action, but every one may follow his own way, without interfering with his neighbour, as happens in all religious controversies, what madness, what fury, can beget such an unhappy and such fatal divisions?

Parties based on principle, especially those rooted in abstract ideas, are a phenomenon unique to modern times and are possibly the most extraordinary and puzzling phenomenon to arise in human affairs. When different principles lead to conflicting behaviors, as is the case with various political ideologies, the situation is easier to understand. A person who believes that the true authority of government rests with one individual or one family will struggle to agree with a fellow citizen who believes that a different individual or family holds that authority. Each naturally wants their own beliefs about this right to prevail. However, when differences in principle do not result in conflicting actions, and everyone can follow their own path without interfering with others, like in all religious debates, what madness and fury could cause such unfortunate and tragic divisions?

Two men travelling on the highway, the one east, the other west, can easily pass each other, if the way be broad enough: but two men, reasoning upon opposite principles of religion, cannot so easily pass, without shocking, though one should think, that the way were also, in that case, sufficiently broad and that each might proceed, without interruption, in his own course. But such is the nature of the human mind, that it always lays hold on every mind that approaches it; and as it is wonderfully fortified by an unanimity of sentiments, so it is shocked and disturbed by any contrariety. Hence the eagerness which most people discover in a dispute; and hence their impatience of opposition, even in the most speculative and indifferent opinions.

Two men traveling on the highway, one headed east and the other west, can easily pass each other if the road is wide enough. But two men debating different religious views can’t do the same without causing a clash, even if we think the path is broad enough for each to continue on their way without interruptions. The human mind is such that it tends to react to any mind that comes near; it is strengthened by agreement but disturbed by disagreement. This explains the eagerness most people show in arguments and their impatience with opposing views, even in the most abstract or trivial opinions.

This principle, however frivolous it may appear, seems to have been the origin of all religious wars and divisions. But as this principle is universal in human nature, its effects would not have been confined to one age, and to one sect of religion, did it not there concur with other more accidental causes, which raise it to such a height as to produce the greatest misery and devastation. Most religions of the ancient world arose in the unknown ages of government, when men were as yet barbarous and uninstructed, and the prince, as well as peasant, was disposed to receive, with implicit faith, every pious tale or fiction which was offered him. The magistrate embraced the religion of the people, and, entering cordially into the care of sacred matters, naturally acquired an authority in them, and united the ecclesiastical with the civil power. But the Christian religion arising, while principles directly opposite to it were firmly established in the polite part of the world, who despised the nation that first broached this novelty; no wonder that, in such circumstances, it was but little countenanced by the civil magistrate, and that the priesthood was allowed to engross all the authority in the new sect. So bad a use did they make of this power, even in those early times, that the primitive persecutions may, perhaps in part,[2] be ascribed to the violence instilled by them into their followers.

This principle, no matter how silly it might seem, appears to be the root of all religious wars and divisions. Because this principle is a part of human nature, its effects wouldn't be limited to just one era or one religious group unless it coincided with other more random causes, which elevate it to such a level that it leads to immense suffering and destruction. Most ancient religions emerged during the early stages of civilization when people were still primitive and uneducated, and both rulers and common folk were likely to accept any pious story or myth presented to them without question. The government adopted the religion of the people, and by genuinely engaging in spiritual matters, naturally gained authority over them, intertwining religious and civil power. However, when the Christian religion emerged, it faced opposition from established principles in the civilized world, which looked down on the nation that introduced this new idea; it’s no surprise that, under these circumstances, it was hardly supported by the civil authorities, and the priesthood was allowed to hold all the power in the new sect. They misused this power so badly, even in those early days, that the initial persecutions might, in part, be attributed to the aggression instilled in their followers by the leaders.

And the same principles of priestly government continuing, after Christianity became the established religion, they have engendered a spirit of persecution, which has ever since been the poison of human society, and the source of the most inveterate factions in every government. Such divisions, therefore, on the part of the people, may justly be esteemed factions of principle, but, on the part of the priests, who are the prime movers, they are really factions of interest.

And the same principles of religious leadership continued even after Christianity became the official religion, fostering a spirit of persecution that has poisoned human society ever since and created some of the most stubborn divisions in every government. These divisions among the people can rightfully be seen as factions of principle, but for the priests, who are the main instigators, they are truly factions of interest.

There is another cause (beside the authority of the priests, and the separation of the ecclesiastical and civil powers), which has contributed to render Christendom the scene of religious wars and divisions. Religions that arise in ages totally ignorant and barbarous, consist mostly of traditional tales and fictions, which may be different in every sect, without being contrary to each other; and even when they are contrary, every one adheres to the tradition of his own sect, without much reasoning or disputation. But as philosophy was widely spread over the world at the time when Christianity arose, the teachers of the new sect were obliged to form a system of speculative opinions, to divide, with some accuracy, their articles of faith, and to explain, comment, confute, and defend, with all the subtlety of argument and science. Hence naturally arose keenness in dispute, when the Christian religion came to be split into new divisions and heresies: and this keenness assisted the priests in the policy of begetting a mutual hatred and antipathy among their deluded followers. Sects of philosophy, in the ancient world, were more zealous than parties of religion; but, in modern times, parties of religion are more furious and enraged than the most cruel factions that ever arose from interest and ambition.

There’s another reason (besides the authority of the priests and the separation between church and state) that has made Christendom a place of religious wars and divisions. Religions that emerge in completely ignorant and barbaric ages mainly consist of traditional stories and myths, which can differ in every sect without being contradictory to each other; and even when they are, people stick to their own traditions without much thought or debate. However, since philosophy was widely known when Christianity began, the leaders of this new sect had to create a system of speculative beliefs, accurately outline their articles of faith, and explain, comment on, argue against, and defend their views with all the subtlety of logic and knowledge. This naturally led to intense debate when Christianity started splitting into new divisions and heresies, and this intensity helped the priests in fostering mutual hatred and resentment among their misled followers. In the ancient world, philosophical sects were more passionate than religious factions; but in modern times, religious parties are angrier and more heated than the most ruthless factions born from self-interest and ambition.

I have mentioned parties from affection as a kind of real parties, beside those from interest and principle. By parties from affection, I understand those which are founded on the different attachments of men towards particular families and persons whom they desire to rule over them. These factions are often very violent; though, I must own, it may seem unaccountable that men should attach themselves so strongly to persons with whom they are nowise acquainted, whom perhaps they never saw, and from whom they never received, nor can ever hope for, any favour. Yet this we often find to be the case, and even with men, who, on other occasions, discover no great generosity of spirit, nor are found to be easily transported by friendship beyond their own interest. We are apt to think the relation between us and our sovereign very close and intimate. The splendour of majesty and power bestows an importance on the fortunes even of a single person. And when a man's good-nature does not give him this imaginary interest, his ill-nature will, from spite and opposition to persons whose sentiments are different from his own.

I have talked about parties formed out of affection as a type of real party, alongside those based on interest and principle. By parties from affection, I mean those built on people's different connections to particular families and individuals they want to lead them. These factions can be quite intense; although, I must admit, it seems odd that people can feel so strongly about individuals they’ve never met, who they may have never seen, and from whom they have received, or could ever expect to receive, any kind of favor. Yet, we frequently observe this, even among people who, on other occasions, show little generosity or are not easily swayed by friendship beyond their own self-interest. We tend to perceive our relationship with our sovereign as very close and personal. The glory of majesty and power gives significance to the situation of even a single individual. And when someone's goodwill doesn’t provide this imagined connection, their bad temperament will, out of resentment and opposition to those whose views differ from their own.

[1] Besides I do not find that the Whites in Morocco ever imposed on the Blacks any necessity pi altering their complexion, or frightened them with inquisitions and penal laws in case of obstinacy. Nor have the Blacks been more unreasonable in this particular. But is a man's opinion, where he is able to form a real opinion, more at his disposal than his complexion? And can one be induced by force or fear to do more than paint and disguise in the one case as well as in the other.

[1] Besides, I don't see that the Whites in Morocco ever forced the Blacks to change their skin color or intimidated them with interrogations and harsh laws for being stubborn. Nor have the Blacks been unreasonable about this either. But is a person's opinion, when they can truly form one, more under their control than their skin color? And can someone be pressured by force or fear to do more than just cover up and disguise in both situations?

[2] I say in part; for it is a vulgar error to imagine, that the ancients were as great friends to toleration as the English or Dutch are at present. The laws against external superstition, among the Romans, were as ancient as the time of the Twelve Tables; and the Jews, as well as Christians, were sometimes punished by them; though, in general, these laws were not rigorously executed. Immediately after the conquest of Gaul, they forbade all but the natives to be initiated into the religion of the Druids; and this was a kind of persecution. In about a century after this conquest, the emperor Claudius quite abolished that superstition by penal laws; which would have been a very grievous persecution, if the imitation of the Roman manners had not, beforehand, weaned the Gauls from their ancient prejudices. Suetonius in vita Claudii. Pliny ascribes the abolition of the Druidical superstitions to Tiberius, probably because that emperor had taken some steps towards restraining them (lib. xxx. cap. i). This is an instance of the usual caution and moderation of the Romans in such cases; and very different from their violent and sanguinary method of treating the Christians. Hence we may entertain a suspicion, that those furious persecutions of Christianity were in some measure owing to the imprudent zeal and bigotry of the first propagators of that sect; and ecclesiastical history affords us many reasons to confirm this suspicion.

[2] I say in part; because it's a common misconception that the ancients were as supportive of tolerance as the English or Dutch are today. The laws against foreign superstitions among the Romans date back to the time of the Twelve Tables, and both Jews and Christians sometimes faced punishment under these laws, although they weren't generally enforced strictly. Right after the conquest of Gaul, they prohibited anyone except the locals from being initiated into the Druid religion, which was a form of persecution. About a century after this conquest, Emperor Claudius completely abolished that superstition with harsh laws, which would have been a serious persecution if the influence of Roman customs hadn't already distanced the Gauls from their traditional beliefs. Suetonius in vita Claudii. Pliny attributes the end of the Druid superstitions to Tiberius, likely because that emperor had taken steps to limit them (lib. xxx. cap. i). This shows the typical caution and moderation of the Romans in such matters, which contrasts sharply with their brutal and violent treatment of Christians. Thus, we might suspect that those intense persecutions of Christianity were partly due to the reckless zeal and intolerance of the early followers of that faith, and ecclesiastical history provides many reasons to support this suspicion.


OF THE PARTIES OF GREAT BRITAIN

Were the British government proposed as a subject of speculation, one would immediately perceive in it a source of division and party, which it would be almost impossible for it, under any administration, to avoid. The just balance between the republican and monarchical part of our constitution is really in itself so extremely delicate and uncertain, that, when joined to men's passions and prejudices, it is impossible but different opinions must arise concerning it, even among persons of the best understanding. Those of mild tempers, who love peace and order, and detest sedition and civil wars, will always entertain more favourable sentiments of monarchy than men of bold and generous spirits, who are passionate lovers of liberty, and think no evil comparable to subjection and slavery. And though all reasonable men agree in general to preserve our mixed government, yet, when they come to particulars, some will incline to trust greater powers to the crown, to bestow on it more influence, and to guard against its encroachments with less caution, than others who are terrified at the most distant approaches of tyranny and despotic power. Thus are there parties of PRINCIPLE involved in the very nature of our constitution, which may properly enough he denominated those of COURT and COUNTRY.[1] The strength and violence of each of these parties will much depend upon the particular administration. An administration may be so bad, as to throw a great majority into the opposition; as a good administration will reconcile to the court many of the most passionate lovers of liberty. But however the nation may fluctuate between them, the parties themselves will always subsist, so long as we are governed by a limited monarchy.

If the British government were to be the subject of speculation, it would quickly be seen as a source of division and conflict, something it would be nearly impossible to avoid under any administration. The delicate balance between the republican and monarchical aspects of our constitution is so fragile and unpredictable that, when mixed with people's passions and biases, differing opinions are bound to emerge, even among those with the best understanding. Those with calm temperaments, who value peace and order and detest rebellion and civil strife, will generally have a more favorable view of monarchy than those with bold and spirited personalities, who are passionate advocates of liberty and believe that nothing could be worse than subjugation and slavery. While all reasonable people generally agree on preserving our mixed government, when it comes to specifics, some individuals will be more inclined to give more power to the crown, allowing it more influence and being less cautious about its encroachments, while others will be alarmed by even the slightest hint of tyranny and despotic power. Thus, parties based on PRINCIPLE are inherently part of our constitution, which can be aptly described as those of COURT and COUNTRY.[1] The power and intensity of each of these parties will depend greatly on the particular administration. An administration may be so poor that it drives a large majority into opposition, while a good administration can win over many of the most passionate advocates for liberty to the court. However, regardless of how the nation swings between them, the parties will continue to exist as long as we are governed by a limited monarchy.

But, besides this difference of Principle, those parties are very much fomented by a difference of INTEREST, without which they could scarcely ever be dangerous or violent. The crown will naturally bestow all trust and power upon those whose principles, real or pretended, are most favourable to monarchical government; and this temptation will naturally engage them to go greater lengths than their principles would otherwise carry them. Their antagonists, who are disappointed in their ambitious aims, throw themselves into the party whose sentiments incline them to be most jealous of royal power, and naturally carry those sentiments to a greater height than sound politics will justify. Thus Court and Country, which are the genuine offspring of the British government, are a kind of mixed parties, and are influenced both by principle and by interest. The heads of the factions are commonly most governed by the latter motive; the inferior members of them by the former.[2]

But besides this difference in Principle, those parties are largely fueled by a difference in INTEREST, without which they would rarely be dangerous or violent. The crown will naturally place all trust and power in the hands of those whose principles, whether genuine or not, are most supportive of monarchical government; and this temptation will naturally push them to go further than their principles would otherwise allow. Their opponents, who are disillusioned in their ambitious goals, align themselves with the party whose beliefs make them most wary of royal power, and they tend to amplify those beliefs to a degree that sound politics does not support. Thus, Court and Country, which are the true creations of the British government, are a sort of mixed parties, influenced by both principle and interest. The leaders of the factions are usually more driven by the latter motive, while the lower-ranking members are influenced more by the former.[2]

As to ecclesiastical parties, we may observe, that, in all ages of the world, priests have been enemies to liberty;[3] and, it is certain, that this steady conduct of theirs must have been founded on fixed reasons of interest and ambition. Liberty of thinking, and of expressing our thoughts, is always fatal to priestly power, and to those pious frauds on which it is commonly founded; and, by an infallible connection, which prevails among all kinds of liberty, this privilege can never be enjoyed, at least has never yet been enjoyed, but in a free government. Hence it must happen, in such a constitution as that of Great Britain, that the established clergy, while things are in their natural situation, will always be of the Court party; as, on the contrary, dissenters of all kinds will be of the Country party; since they can never hope for that toleration which they stand in need of, but by means of our free government. All princes that have aimed at despotic power have known of what importance it was to gain the established clergy; as the clergy, on their part, have shown a great facility in entering into the views of such princes. Gustavus Vasa was, perhaps, the only ambitious monarch that ever depressed the church, at the same time that he discouraged liberty. But the exorbitant power of the bishops in Sweden, who at that time overtopped the crown itself, together with their attachment to a foreign family, was the reason of his embracing such an unusual system of politics.

Regarding religious groups, we can note that throughout history, priests have often been adversaries of freedom; and it's clear that their consistent behavior is rooted in self-interest and ambition. The freedom to think and express our thoughts is always a threat to priestly authority and the pious deceptions that usually support it. Due to an unavoidable link among all forms of freedom, this right has only been truly enjoyed—if at all—in a free government. Therefore, in a system like that of Great Britain, the established clergy will consistently align with the Court party while dissenters of all kinds will support the Country party, as they can only attain the tolerance they need through our free government. All rulers who have sought absolute power have understood the significance of winning over the established clergy, who, in turn, have shown a willingness to align with the goals of such rulers. Gustavus Vasa might have been the only ambitious king to undermine the church while also stifling freedom. However, the overwhelming power of the bishops in Sweden at that time, who overshadowed the crown, coupled with their loyalty to a foreign dynasty, was why he adopted such an unusual political strategy.

This observation, concerning propensity of priests to the government of a single person, is not true with regard to one sect only. The Presbyterian and Calvinistic clergy in Holland, were professed friends to the family of Orange; as the Arminians, who were esteemed heretics, were of the Louvestein faction, and zealous for liberty. But if a prince have the choice of both, it is easy to see that he will prefer the Episcopal to the Presbyterian form of government, both because of the greater affinity between monarchy and episcopacy, and because of the facility which he will find, in such a government, of ruling the clergy by means of their ecclesiastical superiors.

This observation about how priests tend to prefer a single ruler isn't just true for one group. The Presbyterian and Calvinistic clergy in Holland were known supporters of the House of Orange. On the other hand, the Arminians, who were seen as heretics, were part of the Louvestein faction and were strong advocates for freedom. However, if a prince can choose between the two, it's clear he will lean towards the Episcopal over the Presbyterian system of governance, mainly because monarchy aligns more closely with episcopacy and because he'll find it easier to control the clergy through their ecclesiastical leaders.

If we consider the first rise of parties in England, during the great rebellion, we shall observe that it was conformable to this general theory, and that the species of government gave birth to them by a regular and infallible operation. The English constitution, before that period, had lain in a kind of confusion, yet so as that the subjects possessed many noble privileges, which, though not exactly bounded and secured by law, were universally deemed, from long possession, to belong to them as their birthright. An ambitious, or rather a misguided, prince arose, who deemed all these privileges to be concessions of his predecessors, revocable at pleasure; and, in prosecution of this principle, he openly acted in violation of liberty during the course of several years. Necessity, at last, constrained him to call a parliament; the spirit of liberty arose and spread itself; the prince, being without any support, was obliged to grant every thing required of him; and his enemies, jealous and implacable, set no bounds to their pretensions. Here, then, began those contests in which it was no wonder that men of that age were divided into different parties; since, even at this day, the impartial are at a loss to decide concerning the justice of the quarrel. The pretensions of the parliament, if yielded to, broke the balance of the constitution, by rendering the government almost entirely republican. If not yielded to, the nation was, perhaps, still in danger of absolute power, from the settled principles and inveterate habits of the king, which had plainly appeared in every concession that he had been constrained to make to his people. In this question, so delicate and uncertain, men naturally fell to the side which was most conformable to their usual principles; and the more passionate favourers of monarchy declared for the king, as the zealous friends of liberty sided with the parliament. The hopes of success being nearly equal on both sides, interest had no general influence in this contest; so that ROUNDHEAD and CAVALIER were merely parties of principle, neither of which disowned either monarchy or liberty; but the former party inclined most to the republican part of our government, the latter to the monarchical. In this respect, they may be considered as court and country party, inflamed into a civil war, by an unhappy concurrence of circumstances, and by the turbulent spirit of the age. The commonwealth's men, and the partisans of absolute power, lay concealed in both parties, and formed but an inconsiderable part of them.

If we look at the early rise of political parties in England during the great rebellion, we can see that it aligns with this general idea, and the type of government naturally led to their emergence through a consistent and undeniable process. Before this time, the English constitution was somewhat chaotic, yet the people enjoyed many valuable rights that, although not specifically defined or protected by law, were widely accepted as their birthright due to long-standing practice. An ambitious, or rather misguided, king came along who viewed these rights as merely privileges granted by his predecessors, which he could revoke at will. Acting on this belief, he openly violated liberties for several years. Eventually, necessity forced him to summon a parliament; the spirit of freedom arose and spread. With the king lacking any support, he had to concede to all demands placed upon him, while his adversaries, filled with jealousy and bitterness, pushed their claims to the limits. This led to conflicts where it was no surprise that people of that time were split into various factions, as even today, impartial observers struggle to determine the fairness of the dispute. If the parliament's claims were accepted, it would have upset the balance of the constitution, tipping the government towards a nearly republican structure. If they weren't accepted, the nation might still face the threat of absolute power due to the king's established beliefs and ingrained habits, which were evident in every concession he had been forced to make. In such a nuanced and uncertain matter, people naturally gravitated towards the side that aligned with their usual views; proponents of monarchy supported the king, while passionate advocates for freedom sided with the parliament. Since the odds of victory seemed nearly equal for both sides, personal gain had little effect on the battle, turning the ROUNDHEADS and CAVALIERS into factions guided by principle, neither entirely rejecting monarchy nor freedom; however, the former leaned more towards republicanism, while the latter favored monarchy. In this sense, they can be seen as representatives of court and country parties, driven into a civil war by a series of unfortunate events and the restless spirit of the time. Those supporting the commonwealth and advocates of absolute power were present in both factions but made up only a small part of them.

The clergy had concurred with the king's arbitrary designs; and, in return, were allowed to persecute their adversaries, whom they called heretics and schismatics. The established clergy were Episcopal, the nonconformists Presbyterian; so that all things concurred to throw the former, without reserve, into the king's party, and the latter into that of the parliament.[4]

The clergy agreed with the king's arbitrary plans; in return, they were permitted to persecute their opponents, whom they labeled as heretics and schismatics. The established clergy were Episcopal, while the nonconformists were Presbyterian; therefore, everything aligned to fully support the king's party for the former and the parliament for the latter.[4]

Every one knows the event of this quarrel; fatal to the king first, to the parliament afterwards. After many confusions and revolutions, the royal family was at last restored, and the ancient government reestablished. Charles II was not made wiser by the example of his father, but prosecuted the same measures, though, at first, with more secrecy and caution. New parties arose, under the appellation of Whig and Tory, which have continued ever since to confound and distract our government. To determine the nature of these parties is perhaps one of the most difficult problems that can be met with, and is a proof that history may contain questions as uncertain as any to be found in the most abstract sciences. We have seen the conduct of the two parties, during the course of seventy years, in a vast variety of circumstances, possessed of power, and deprived of it, during peace, and during war: persons, who profess themselves of one side or other, we meet with every hour, in company, in our pleasures, in our serious occupations we ourselves are constrained, in a manner, to take party; and, living in a country of the highest liberty, every one may openly declare all the sentiments and opinions: yet are we at a loss to tell the nature, pretensions, and principles, of the different factions.[5]

Everyone knows about this quarrel; it was fatal first for the king and then for parliament. After many upheavals and changes, the royal family was finally restored, and the old government was reestablished. Charles II didn’t learn from his father’s example but continued the same policies, though initially with more secrecy and caution. New factions emerged, known as Whigs and Tories, which have continued to confuse and disrupt our government ever since. Understanding the nature of these parties is one of the toughest challenges we face, proving that history can pose questions as unclear as those found in the most abstract sciences. We’ve observed the behavior of both parties over seventy years in a wide range of situations, both in power and out, during times of peace and war: we encounter people who identify with one side or the other all the time, in social settings and serious endeavors, and we ourselves are somewhat forced to take a side; yet, even living in a country with the highest freedom, where everyone can openly express their beliefs and opinions, we still struggle to define the nature, claims, and principles of the different factions.[5]

When we compare the parties of WHIG and TORY with those of ROUNDHEAD and CAVALIER, the most obvious difference that appears between them consists in the principles of passive obedience, and indefeasible right, which were but little heard of among the Cavaliers, but became the universal doctrine, and were esteemed the true characteristic of a Tory. Were these principles pushed into their most obvious consequences, they imply a formal renunciation of all our liberties, and an avowal of absolute monarchy; since nothing can be greater absurdity than a limited power, which must not be resisted, even when it exceeds its limitations. But, as the most rational principles are often but a weak counterpoise to passion, it is no wonder that these absurd principles were found too weak for that effect. The Tories, as men, were enemies to oppression; and also as Englishmen, they were enemies to arbitrary power. Their zeal for liberty was, perhaps, less fervent than that of their antagonists, but was sufficient to make them forget all their general principles, when they saw themselves openly threatened with a subversion of the ancient government. From these sentiments arose the Revolution, an event of mighty consequence, and the firmest foundation of British liberty. The conduct of the Tories during that event, and after it, will afford us a true insight into the nature of that party.

When we compare the WHIG and TORY parties with the ROUNDHEAD and CAVALIER ones, the most noticeable difference is in the principles of passive obedience and indefeasible right. These ideas were hardly mentioned among the Cavaliers but became widely accepted and were seen as the defining traits of a Tory. If these principles are taken to their logical extremes, they suggest a complete rejection of all our freedoms and a claim for absolute monarchy, since nothing is more absurd than having limited power that cannot be resisted, even when it goes beyond its limits. However, since the most rational arguments often fall short against strong emotions, it's not surprising that these illogical principles proved too weak for their intended purpose. The Tories, as individuals, opposed oppression; and as Englishmen, they opposed arbitrary power. Their enthusiasm for liberty might have been less intense than that of their opponents, but it was enough for them to overlook their general principles when they felt threatened by the potential collapse of the traditional government. These feelings led to the Revolution, a significant event and the strongest foundation for British liberty. The actions of the Tories during and after this event will give us genuine insight into the nature of that party.

In the first place, they appear to have had the genuine sentiments of Britons in their affection for liberty, and in their determined resolution not to sacrifice it to any abstract principle whatsoever, or to any imaginary rights of princes. This part of their character might justly have been doubted of before the Revolution, from the obvious tendency of their avowed principles, and from their compliances with a court, which seemed to make little secret of its arbitrary designs. The Revolution showed them to have been, in this respect, nothing but a genuine court party, such as might be expected in a British government; that is, lovers of liberty, but greater lovers of monarchy. It must, however, be confessed, that they carried their monarchical principles further even in practice, but more so in theory, than was in any degree consistent with a limited government.

In the first place, they seemed to genuinely share the feelings of Britons in their love for freedom and their strong determination not to give it up for any abstract principle or the made-up rights of kings. Before the Revolution, this aspect of their character could have been justifiably questioned, given the clear direction of their openly stated beliefs and their compliance with a court that clearly had its own authoritarian agenda. The Revolution revealed that they were truly just a typical court party, which is what you might expect in a British government; that is, fans of freedom but even bigger fans of monarchy. However, it's worth noting that they took their monarchical beliefs further in practice—though even more so in theory—than was at all compatible with a limited government.

Secondly, Neither their principles nor affections concurred, entirely or heartily, with the settlement made at the Revolution, or with that which has since taken place. This part of their character may seem opposite to the former, since any other settlement, in those circumstances of the nation, must probably have been dangerous, if not fatal, to liberty. But the heart of man is made to reconcile contradictions; and this contradiction is not greater than that between passive obedience and the resistance employed at the Revolution. A TORY, therefore, since the Revolution, may be defined, in a few words, to be a lover of monarchy, though without abandoning liberty, and a partisan of the family of Stuart: as a WHIG may be defined to be a lover of liberty, though without renouncing monarchy, and a friend to the settlement in the Protestant line.[6]

Secondly, neither their principles nor feelings fully aligned, completely or sincerely, with the settlement made at the Revolution, or with what has occurred since. This aspect of their character might seem contrary to the previous one, as any other settlement in those circumstances could have been dangerous, if not deadly, to liberty. But the human heart is capable of reconciling contradictions; and this contradiction is no greater than that between passive obedience and the resistance that occurred at the Revolution. A TORY, therefore, since the Revolution, can be briefly defined as a supporter of monarchy, yet without giving up on liberty, and a supporter of the Stuart family: while a WHIG can be defined as a supporter of liberty, yet without rejecting monarchy, and a proponent of the settlement in the Protestant line.[6]

These different views, with regard to the settlement of the crown, were accidental, but natural, additions, to the principles of the Court and Country parties, which are the genuine divisions in the British Government. A passionate lover of monarchy is apt to be displeased at any change of the succession, as savouring too much of a commonwealth: a passionate lover of liberty is apt to think that every part of the government ought to be subordinate to the interests of liberty.

These different views on the crown’s succession were unintentional but natural extensions of the principles of the Court and Country parties, which truly represent the divisions in British Government. Someone who passionately supports the monarchy tends to be upset by any changes in succession, seeing them as too close to a commonwealth. Conversely, a strong advocate for liberty often believes that every aspect of the government should prioritize individual freedoms.

Some, who will not venture to assert that the real difference between Whig and Tory was lost at the Revolution, seem inclined to think, that the difference is now abolished, and that affairs are so far returned to their natural state, that there are at present no other parties among us but Court and Country; that is, men who, by interest or principle, are attached either to monarchy or liberty. The Tories have been so long obliged to talk in the republican style, that they seem to have made converts of themselves by their hypocrisy, and to have embraced the sentiments, as well as language of their adversaries. There are, however, very considerable remains of that party in England, with all their old prejudices; and a proof that Court and Country are not our only parties, is that almost all the dissenters side with the court, and the lower clergy, at least of the church or England, with the opposition. This may convince us, that some bias still hangs upon our constitution, some extrinsic weight, which turns it from its natural course, and causes a confusion in our parties.[7]

Some people, who won’t boldly claim that the real difference between Whig and Tory vanished at the Revolution, seem to believe that the distinction is now gone, and that things have returned to their natural state, with only Court and Country as parties; that is, those who are connected by interest or principle to either monarchy or liberty. The Tories have been forced to speak in a republican way for so long that they seem to have convinced themselves through their own hypocrisy, adopting the views and language of their opponents. However, there are still significant remnants of that party in England, complete with all their old biases; and one indication that Court and Country aren’t our only factions is that almost all dissenters align with the court, while the lower clergy, particularly from the Church of England, side with the opposition. This may show us that some influence still affects our constitution, creating some outside pressure that disrupts its natural course and causes confusion among our parties.[7]

[1] These words have become of general use, and therefore I shall employ them without intending to express by them an universal blame of the one party, or approbation of the other. The Court party may no doubt, on some occasions, consult best the interest of the country, and the Country party oppose it. In like manner, the Roman parties were denominated Optimates and Populares; and Cicero, like a true party man, defines the Optimates to be such as, in all their public conduct, regulated themselves by the sentiments of the best and worthiest Romans; pro Sextio. The term of Country party may afford a favourable definition or etymology of the same kind; but it would be folly to draw any argument from that head, and I have no regard to it in employing these terms.

[1] These words have become commonly used, so I will use them without meaning to imply universal blame for one side or approval for the other. The Court party may, at times, act in the best interest of the country, while the Country party may oppose that. Similarly, the Roman factions were called Optimates and Populares; and Cicero, as a true party member, describes the Optimates as those who, in all their public actions, align themselves with the views of the best and noblest Romans; pro Sextio. The term Country party may offer a favorable definition or origin of the same kind, but it would be foolish to base any argument on that, and I don’t take that into account when using these terms.

[2] I must be understood to mean this of persons who have any motive for taking party on any side. For, to tell the truth, the greatest part are commonly men who associate themselves they know not why; from example, from passion, from idleness. But still it is requisite there be some source of division, either in principle or interest; otherwise such persons would not find parties to which they could associate themselves.

[2] I mean this about people who have any reason to take sides in any situation. To be honest, most of them are typically individuals who join groups for reasons they can't quite explain; whether it's out of habit, emotional impulse, or just boredom. However, there still has to be some reason for disagreement, either in beliefs or interests; otherwise, these people wouldn't have groups to align themselves with.

[3] This proposition is true, notwithstanding that, in the early times of the English government, the clergy were the great and principal opposers of the crown; but at that time their possessions were so immensely great, that they composed a considerable part of the proprietors of England, and in many contests were direct rivals of the crown.

[3] This statement is true, even though in the early days of English government, the clergy were the main opponents of the crown; at that time, their wealth was so vast that they made up a significant portion of the landowners in England and were direct rivals of the crown in many conflicts.

[4] The clergy had concurred in a shameless manner with the King's arbitrary designs, according to their usual maxims in such cases, and, in return, were allowed to persecute their adversaries, whom they called heretics and schismatics. The established clergy were Episcopal, the nonconformists Presbyterians; so that all things concurred to throw the former, without reserve, into the King's party, and the latter into that of the Parliament. The Cavaliers being the Court party, and the Roundheads the Country party, the union was infallible betwixt the former and the established prelacy, and betwixt the latter and Presbyterian nonconformists. This union is so natural, according to the general principles of politics, that it requires some very extraordinary situation of affairs to break it.

[4] The clergy shamelessly supported the King's arbitrary plans, as was their usual practice in such matters, and in return, they were allowed to persecute their opponents, whom they labeled heretics and schismatics. The established clergy were Episcopal, while the nonconformists were Presbyterians; this alignment effectively pushed the former completely into the King's camp and the latter into the Parliament's. The Cavaliers represented the Court party, and the Roundheads represented the Country party, creating a natural alliance between the established church and the King, and between the nonconformists and the Parliament. This alliance is so typical in political dynamics that it takes a very unusual set of circumstances to disrupt it.

[5] The question is perhaps in itself somewhat difficult, but has been rendered more so by the prejudices and violence of party.

[5] The question is probably a bit challenging on its own, but it's become even more complicated by biases and conflicts within political parties.

[6]The celebrated writer above cited has asserted, that the real distinction betwixt Whig and Tory was lost at the Revolution, and that ever since they have continued to be mere personal parties, like the Guelfs and Ghibellines, after the Emperors had lost all authority in Italy. Such an opinion, were it received, would turn our whole history into an enigma.

[6]The celebrated writer mentioned above has claimed that the real distinction between Whig and Tory was lost at the Revolution, and that ever since, they have continued to exist as mere personal parties, similar to the Guelfs and Ghibellines, after the Emperors had lost all authority in Italy. If this opinion were accepted, it would turn our entire history into a mystery.

I shall first mention, as a proof of a real distinction betwixt these parties, what every one may have observed or heard concerning the conduct and conversation of all his friends and acquaintance on both sides. Have not the Tories always borne an avowed affection to the family of Stuart, and have not their adversaries always opposed with vigour the succession of that family?

I’ll first point out, as proof of a real difference between these groups, what anyone can see or has heard about the behavior and conversations of all their friends and acquaintances on both sides. Haven’t the Tories always shown a clear loyalty to the Stuart family, while their opponents have consistently fought against that family’s succession?

The Tory principles are confessedly the most favourable to monarchy. Yet the Tories have almost always opposed the court these fifty years; nor were they cordial friends to King William, even when employed by him. Their quarrel, therefore, cannot be supposed to have lain with the throne, but with the person who sat on it.

The Tory principles are definitely the most supportive of monarchy. However, the Tories have almost always been against the court in these past fifty years; they weren't really close allies of King William, even when they worked for him. So, their issue likely wasn't with the throne itself, but with the person sitting on it.

They concurred heartily with the court during the four last years of Queen Anne. But is any one at a loss to find the reason?

They wholeheartedly agreed with the court during the last four years of Queen Anne. But is anyone confused about the reason?

The succession of the crown in the British government is a point of too great consequence to be absolutely indifferent to persons who concern themselves, in any degree, about the fortune of the public; much less can it be supposed that the Tory party, who never valued themselves upon moderation, could maintain a stoical indifference in a point of so great importance. Were they, therefore, zealous for the house of Hanover? or was there any thing that kept an opposite zeal from openly appearing, if it did not openly appear, but prudence, and a sense of decency?

The succession of the crown in the British government is a matter of too much importance to be completely indifferent to anyone who cares about the public's well-being. It’s even less believable that the Tory party, which has never prided itself on moderation, could remain completely indifferent about something so significant. So, were they truly passionate supporters of the house of Hanover? Or was there something that prevented an opposing enthusiasm from being openly expressed, if it didn’t show itself openly, but rather just a sense of caution and decency?

It is monstrous to see an established Episcopal clergy in declared opposition to the court, and a nonconformist Presbyterian clergy in conjunction with it. What can produce such an unnatural conduct in both? Nothing, but that the former have espoused monarchical principles too high for the present settlement, which is founded on the principles of liberty, and the latter, being afraid of the prevalence of those high principles, adhere to that party from whom they have reason to expect liberty and toleration.

It’s shocking to see an established Episcopal clergy openly opposing the court, while a nonconformist Presbyterian clergy teams up with it. What could lead to such strange behavior from both sides? Nothing other than the fact that the former have adopted monarchical principles that are too extreme for the current setup, which is based on the principles of liberty, and the latter, fearing the rise of those extreme principles, stick to the party they believe will grant them liberty and toleration.

The different conduct of the two parties, with regard to foreign politics, is also a proof to the same purpose. Holland has always been most favoured by one, and France by the other. In short, the proofs of this kind seem so palpable and evident, that it is almost needless to collect them.

The different behaviors of the two parties regarding foreign politics also serve as evidence for the same point. Holland has always been favored by one party, while France has been favored by the other. In short, the evidence of this is so clear and obvious that it’s almost unnecessary to gather more.

It is however remarkable, that though the principles of Whig and Tory be both of them of a compound nature, yet the ingredients which predominated in both were not correspondent to each other. A Tory loved monarchy, and bore an affection to the family of Stuart; but the latter affection was the predominant inclination of the party. A Whig loved liberty, and was a friend to the settlement in the Protestant line; but the love of liberty was professedly his predominant inclination. The Tories have frequently acted as republicans, where either policy or revenge has engaged them to that conduct; and there was none of the party who, upon the supposition that they were to be disappointed in their views with regard to the succession, would not have desired to impose the strictest limitations on the crown, and to bring our form of government as near republican as possible, in order to depress the family, that, according to their apprehension, succeeded without any just title. The Whigs, it is true, have also taken steps dangerous to liberty, under pretext of securing the succession and settlement of the crown according to their views; but, as the body of the party had no passion for that succession, otherwise than as the means of securing liberty, they have been betrayed into these steps by ignorance or frailty, or the interest of their leaders. The succession of the crown was, therefore, the chief point with the Tories; the security of our liberties with the Whigs.

It is interesting to note that although the principles of Whig and Tory are both complex, the dominant elements in each don't match up. A Tory valued monarchy and had a fondness for the Stuart family; however, this affection was the main inclination of the party. A Whig valued liberty and supported the establishment of a Protestant line; for the Whig, the desire for liberty was clearly his primary inclination. Tories have often acted like republicans when either strategy or revenge motivated them; and there was no member of the party who, believing they would be disappointed in their succession plans, wouldn’t have wanted to impose strict limits on the crown and make our government as republican as possible to undermine the family they thought took power unjustly. The Whigs, it’s true, have also made choices risky to liberty under the guise of protecting the succession and ensuring the crown aligns with their views; but since the majority of the party didn’t have a strong desire for that succession, except as a way to secure liberty, they were misled into those actions by ignorance, weakness, or the interests of their leaders. Therefore, the succession of the crown was the main focus for the Tories; the protection of our liberties was the priority for the Whigs.

It is difficult to penetrate into the thoughts and sentiments of any particular man; but it is almost impossible to distinguish those of a whole party, where it often happens that no two persons agree precisely in the same way of thinking. Yet I will venture to affirm, that it was not so much principle, or an opinion of indefeasible right, that attached the Tories to the ancient family, as affection, or a certain love and esteem for their persons. The same cause divided England formerly betwixt the houses of York and Lancaster, and Scotland betwixt the families of Bruce and Baliol, in an age when political disputes were but little in fashion, and when political principles must of course have had but little influence on mankind. The doctrine of passive obedience is so absurd in itself, and so opposite to our liberties, that it seems to have been chiefly left to pulpit declaimers, and to their deluded followers among the mob Men of better sense were guided by affection, and as to the leaders of this party, it is probable that interest was their sole motive, and that they acted more contrary to their private sentiments than the leaders of the opposite party.

It's tough to understand the thoughts and feelings of any individual man, but it's nearly impossible to figure out what an entire group thinks, since often no two people agree completely on everything. Still, I’d say that it wasn’t so much principle or the belief in an unchallengeable right that connected the Tories to the royal family, but rather affection, or a certain love and respect for them. The same thing split England in the past between the houses of York and Lancaster, and Scotland between the families of Bruce and Baliol, during a time when political disputes weren't very common, and political ideas likely had little impact on people. The idea of passive obedience is so ridiculous and so against our freedoms that it seems to have mainly been left to preachers and their misled followers among the mob. People with better judgment were driven by affection, and as for the leaders of this party, it’s likely that self-interest was their only motivation, acting in ways that were more opposed to their own beliefs than the leaders of the opposing party.

Some who will not venture to assert, that the real difference between Whig and Tory, was lost at the Revolution, seem inclined to think that the difference is now abolished, and that affairs are so far returned to their natural state, that there are at present no other parties amongst us but Court and Country; that is, men who, by interest or principle, are attached either to Monarchy or to Liberty. It must indeed be confessed, that the Tory party seem of late to have decayed much in their numbers, still more in their zeal, and I may venture to say, still more in their credit and authority. There are few men of knowledge or learning, at least few philosophers since Mr. Locke has wrote, who would not be ashamed to be thought of that party; and in almost all companies, the name of Old Whig is mentioned as an incontestable appellation of honour and dignity. Accordingly, the enemies of the ministry, as a reproach, call the courtiers the true Tories and, as an honour, denominate the gentlemen in the Opposition the true Whigs.

Some who won’t dare to claim that the real difference between Whigs and Tories was lost at the Revolution seem to believe that the difference is now gone, and that things have returned to their natural state, where the only parties among us are Court and Country; meaning people who, out of interest or principle, support either Monarchy or Liberty. It must be acknowledged that the Tory party seems to have recently diminished in both numbers and enthusiasm, and I can confidently say even more in their reputation and influence. There are few knowledgeable or educated individuals, at least few philosophers since Mr. Locke wrote, who wouldn’t be embarrassed to be associated with that party; and in nearly all gatherings, the term Old Whig is mentioned as an undeniable mark of honor and respect. Consequently, the ministry's opponents, as an insult, refer to the courtiers as the true Tories and, as a compliment, call the gentlemen in the Opposition the true Whigs.

I shall conclude this subject with observing, that we never had any Tories in Scotland, according to the proper signification of the word, and that the division of parties in this country was really into Whigs and Jacobites. A Jacobite seems to be a Tory, who has no regard to the constitution, but is either a zealous partisan of absolute monarchy, or at least willing to sacrifice our liberties to the obtaining the succession in that family to which he is attached. The reason of the difference betwixt England and Scotland I take to be this. Our political and religious divisions in this country have been, since the Revolution, regularly correspondent to each other. The Presbyterians were all Whigs, without exception; the Episcopalians of the opposite party. And as the clergy of the latter sect were turned out of their churches at the Revolution, they had no motive to make any compliances with the government in their oaths or forms of prayer, but openly avowed the highest principles of their party; which is the cause why their followers have been more barefaced and violent than their brethren of the Tory party in England.

I’ll wrap up this topic by pointing out that we never had any Tories in Scotland, in the true sense of the term. The real political divide in this country has been between Whigs and Jacobites. A Jacobite seems to be a Tory who doesn’t care about the constitution but is either a passionate supporter of absolute monarchy or at least willing to give up our freedoms to support the succession of the royal family he backs. The difference between England and Scotland, as I see it, is this: Our political and religious divisions here have been consistently aligned since the Revolution. All Presbyterians were Whigs, without exception, while the Episcopalians were on the opposite side. When the clergy from the latter group were removed from their churches during the Revolution, they had no reason to comply with the government’s oaths or prayers and instead openly supported their party’s highest principles; this is why their followers have been bolder and more aggressive than the Tories in England.

[7] Some of the opinions delivered in these Essays, with regard to the public transactions in the last century, the Author, on a more accurate examination, found reason to retract in his History of Great Britain. And as he would not enslave himself to the systems of either party, neither would he fetter his judgment by his own preconceived opinions and principles; nor is he ashamed to acknowledge his mistakes. These mistakes were indeed, at that time almost universal in this kingdom.

[7] Some of the views expressed in these Essays about public events from the last century, the Author, upon closer inspection, found it necessary to withdraw in his History of Great Britain. He refused to bind himself to the ideologies of either party, nor did he limit his judgment by his own preconceived beliefs and principles; he is also not afraid to admit his errors. These errors were, in fact, nearly widespread in this kingdom at that time.


OF SUPERSTITION AND ENTHUSIASM

That the corruption of the best of things produces the worst, is grown into a maxim, and is commonly proved, among other instances, by the pernicious effects of superstition and enthusiasm, the corruptions of true religion.

That the corruption of the best of things produces the worst has become a well-known saying, often demonstrated by the harmful effects of superstition and enthusiasm, which are the corrupt forms of true religion.

These two species of false religion, though both pernicious, are yet of a very different, and even of a contrary nature. The mind of man is subject to certain unaccountable terrors and apprehensions, proceeding either from the unhappy situation of private or public affairs, from ill health, from a gloomy and melancholy disposition, or from the concurrence of all these circumstances. In such a state of mind, infinite unknown evils are dreaded from unknown agents; and where real objects of terror are wanting, the soul, active to its own prejudice, and fostering its predominant inclination, finds imaginary ones, to whose power and malevolence it sets no limits. As these enemies are entirely invisible and unknown, the methods taken to appease them are equally unaccountable, and consist in ceremonies, observances, mortifications, sacrifices, presents, or in any practice, however absurd or frivolous, which either folly or knavery recommends to a blind and terrified credulity. Weakness, fear, melancholy, together with ignorance, are, therefore, the true sources of Superstition.

These two kinds of false religion, while both harmful, are very different and even opposed in nature. The human mind is susceptible to various inexplicable fears and anxieties that arise from unfortunate personal or societal circumstances, poor health, a gloomy and depressed state, or a combination of all these factors. In such a troubled state, people fear countless unknown dangers from unseen forces; and when there are no real threats, the mind, working against its own interests and feeding its strongest tendencies, creates imaginary ones, attributing limitless power and malice to them. Since these foes are completely invisible and unknown, the ways people try to placate them are just as irrational, involving rituals, observances, self-denial, sacrifices, gifts, or any action, no matter how absurd or trivial, suggested by either foolishness or deceit to a blind and terrified belief. Thus, weakness, fear, sadness, and ignorance are the real origins of superstition.

But the mind of man is also subject to an unaccountable elevation and presumption, arising from prosperous success, from luxuriant health, from strong spirits, or from a bold and confident disposition. In such a state of mind, the imagination swells with great, but confused conceptions, to which no sublunary beauties or enjoyments can correspond. Every thing mortal and perishable vanishes as unworthy of attention; and a full range is given to the fancy in the invisible regions, or world of Spirits, where the soul is at liberty to indulge itself in every imagination, which may best suit its present taste and disposition. Hence arise raptures, transports, and surprising flights of fancy; and, confidence and presumption still increasing, these raptures, being altogether unaccountable, and seeming quite beyond the reach of our ordinary faculties, are attributed to the immediate inspiration of that Divine Being who is the object of devotion. In a little time, the inspired person comes to regard himself as a distinguished favourite of the Divinity; and when this phrensy once takes place, which is the summit of enthusiasm, every whimsey is consecrated: human reason, and even morality, are rejected as fallacious guides, and the fanatic madman delivers himself over, blindly and without reserve, to the supposed illapses of the Spirit, and to inspiration from above. Hope, pride, presumption, a warm imagination, together with ignorance, are therefore the true sources of Enthusiasm.

But the human mind is also prone to an inexplicable elevation and arrogance that comes from success, good health, a strong spirit, or a bold and confident attitude. In this state of mind, the imagination expands with grand but unclear ideas that can’t be matched by any earthly beauty or pleasure. Everything mortal and temporary seems unworthy of focus; instead, the mind wanders freely in invisible realms or the world of spirits, where the soul can indulge in any fantasy that fits its current mood and desires. This leads to intense joy, excitement, and unexpected bursts of creativity; as confidence and arrogance grow, these feelings—which seem completely beyond our usual limits—are thought to be direct inspiration from the Divine Being who is the focus of our devotion. Before long, the inspired individual starts to see themselves as a special favorite of the divine; once this frenzy occurs, which is the peak of enthusiasm, every whim is treated as sacred. Human reasoning and even morality are dismissed as misleading guides, and the fanatic blindly surrenders to what they believe are divine inspirations. Thus, hope, pride, arrogance, a vivid imagination, along with ignorance, are the true sources of enthusiasm.

These two species of false religion might afford occasion to many speculations, but I shall confine myself, at present, to a few reflections concerning their different influence on government and society.

These two types of false religion could lead to many theories, but I will limit myself for now to a few thoughts about their different effects on government and society.

My first reflection is, that superstition is favourable to priestly power, and enthusiasm not less, or rather more contrary to it, than sound reason and philosophy. As superstition is founded on fear, sorrow, and a depression of spirits, it represents the man to himself in such despicable colours, that he appears unworthy, in his own eyes, of approaching the Divine presence, and naturally has recourse to any other person, whose sanctity of life, or perhaps impudence and cunning, have made him be supposed more favoured by the Divinity. To him the superstitious intrust their devotions to his care they recommend their prayers, petitions, and sacrifices: and by his means, they hope to render their addresses acceptable to their incensed Deity. Hence the origin of Priests, who may justly be regarded as an invention of a timorous and abject superstition, which, ever diffident of itself, dares not offer up its own devotions, but ignorantly thinks to recommend itself to the Divinity, by the mediation of his supposed friends and servants. As superstition is a considerable ingredient in almost all religions, even the most fanatical; there being nothing but philosophy able entirely to conquer these unaccountable terrors; hence it proceeds, that in almost every sect of religion there are priests to be found: but the stronger mixture there is of superstition, the higher is the authority of the priesthood.

My first thought is that superstition supports priestly power, and enthusiasm is just as much, if not more, of a challenge to it than sound reason and philosophy. Superstition is rooted in fear, sorrow, and a low spirit, making people see themselves in such a poor light that they feel unworthy to come before the Divine. Naturally, they turn to someone else they perceive as having a closer connection to the Divine, whether due to their piety, boldness, or cleverness. Superstitious individuals entrust their prayers, requests, and sacrifices to this person, hoping he can present their appeals to an angry God on their behalf. This gives rise to priests, who can rightly be considered a product of timid and fearful superstition. This form of belief, always uncertain about itself, is afraid to express its own worship and instead naïvely thinks it can reach the Divine through supposed friends and servants. Since superstition is a significant part of almost all religions, even the most extreme ones, and philosophy is the only thing that can fully conquer these inexplicable fears, it follows that in nearly every religious sect, priests are present. The greater the superstition, the higher the authority of the priesthood.

On the other hand, it may be observed, that all enthusiasts have been free from the yoke of ecclesiastics, and have expressed great independence in their devotion, with a contempt of forms, ceremonies, and traditions. The Quakers are the most egregious, though, at the same time, the most innocent enthusiasts that have yet been known; and are perhaps the only sect that have never admitted priests among them. The Independents, of all the English sectaries, approach nearest to the Quakers in fanaticism, and in their freedom from priestly bondage. The Presbyterians follow after, at an equal distance, in both particulars. In short, this observation is founded in experience; and will also appear to be founded in reason, if we consider, that, as enthusiasm arises from a presumptuous pride and confidence, it thinks itself sufficiently qualified to approach the Divinity, without any human mediator. Its rapturous devotions are so fervent, that it even imagines itself actually to approach him by the way of contemplation and inward converse; which makes it neglect all those outward ceremonies and observances, to which the assistance of the priests appears so requisite in the eyes of their superstitious votaries. The fanatic consecrates himself, and bestows on his own person a sacred character, much superior to what forms and ceremonious institutions can confer on any other.

On the other hand, it's clear that all enthusiasts have been free from the control of religious authorities and have shown great independence in their devotion, disregarding rules, rituals, and traditions. The Quakers are the most notable example, being both extreme and innocent enthusiasts that have ever existed, and they might be the only group that has never accepted priests among them. The Independents, among all English sects, come closest to the Quakers in their fervor and in their liberation from priestly control. The Presbyterians follow closely behind in both respects. In short, this observation is based on experience and will also seem reasonable if we consider that, as enthusiasm stems from overconfidence and pride, it believes itself capable of approaching the divine without any human intermediary. Its passionate devotion is so intense that it even believes it can actually approach Him through contemplation and inner dialogue, leading it to disregard all those external rituals and practices that seem essential in the eyes of their superstitious followers. The fanatic dedicates themselves and grants their own identity a sacred status, far beyond what any rituals and formal institutions can bestow on anyone else.

My second reflection with regard to these species of false religion is, that religions which partake of enthusiasm, are, on their first rise, more furious and violent than those which partake of superstition; but in a little time become more gentle and moderate. The violence of this species of religion, when excited by novelty, and animated by opposition, appears from numberless instances; of the Anabaptists in Germany, the Camisars in France, the Levellers, and other fanatics in England, and the Covenanters in Scotland. Enthusiasm being founded on strong spirits, and a presumptuous boldness of character, it naturally begets the most extreme resolutions; especially after it rises to that height as to inspire the deluded fanatic with the opinion of Divine illuminations, and with a contempt for the common rules of reason, morality, and prudence.

My second thought about these types of false religions is, that religions driven by enthusiasm are, at their onset, more intense and aggressive than those influenced by superstition; but over time, they tend to become more gentle and moderate. The intensity of this type of religion, when sparked by novelty and fueled by opposition, can be seen in countless examples: the Anabaptists in Germany, the Camisars in France, the Levellers, and other fanatics in England, and the Covenanters in Scotland. Because enthusiasm is rooted in strong emotions and a bold attitude, it naturally leads to extreme decisions; especially when it reaches a point where it convinces the misguided fanatic of divine insights and fosters a disregard for the usual standards of reasoning, morality, and common sense.

It is thus enthusiasm produces the most cruel disorders in human society; but its fury is like that of thunder and tempest, which exhaust themselves in a little time, and leave the air more calm and serene than before. When the first fire of enthusiasm is spent, men naturally, in all fanatical sects, sink into the greatest remissness and coolness in sacred matters; there being no body of men among them endowed with sufficient authority, whose interest is concerned to support the religious spirit; no rites, no ceremonies, no holy observances, which may enter into the common train of life, and preserve the sacred principles from oblivion. Superstition, on the contrary, steals in gradually and insensibly; renders men tame and submissive; is acceptable to the magistrate, and seems inoffensive to the people: till at last the priest, having firmly established his authority, becomes the tyrant and disturber of human society, by his endless contentions, persecutions, and religious wars. How smoothly did the Romish church advance in her acquisition of power! But into what dismal convulsions did she throw all Europe, in order to maintain it! On the other hand, our sectaries, who were formerly such dangerous bigots, are now become very free reasoners; and the Quakers seem to approach nearly the only regular body of Deists in the universe, the literati or the disciples of Confucius in China.[1]

Enthusiasm can create the most destructive chaos in human society; however, its intensity is like that of thunder and storms, which eventually die down and leave the atmosphere calmer and clearer than before. Once the initial spark of enthusiasm fades, people in all fanatical groups tend to fall into a state of great neglect and indifference towards sacred issues. This happens because there's no group among them granted enough authority, nor any vested interest in maintaining a sense of religious fervor; there are no rituals, no ceremonies, and no sacred observances to weave into everyday life and keep the sacred principles from being forgotten. Superstition, on the other hand, creeps in slowly and subtly; it makes people more docile and compliant; it's pleasing to those in power and seems harmless to the general public. Eventually, the priest, having solidified his authority, becomes the oppressor and disruptor of society through his endless disputes, persecutions, and religious wars. The Roman Catholic Church gained power so smoothly! But look at the grim upheavals it caused across Europe to keep that power! Conversely, our sectarians, who were once dangerous zealots, have now turned into free thinkers; and the Quakers seem to be approaching the only coherent group of Deists in the world, similar to the literati or the followers of Confucius in China.[1]

My third observation on this head is, that superstition is an enemy to civil liberty, and enthusiasm a friend to it. As superstition groans under the dominion of priests, and enthusiasm is destructive of all ecclesiastical power, this sufficiently accounts for the present observation. Not to mention that enthusiasm, being the infirmity of bold and ambitious tempers, is naturally accompanied with a spirit of liberty, as superstition, on the contrary, renders men tame and abject, and fits them for slavery. We learn from English history, that, during the civil wars, the Independents and Deists, though the most opposite in their religious principles, yet were united in their political ones, and were alike passionate for a commonwealth. And since the origin of Whig and Tory, the leaders of the Whigs have either been Deists or professed Latitudinarians in their principles; that is, friends to toleration, and indifferent to any particular sect of Christians: while the sectaries, who have all a strong tincture of enthusiasm, have always, without exception, concurred with that party in defence of civil liberty. The resemblance in their superstitions long united the High-Church Tories and the Roman Catholics, in support of prerogative and kingly power, though experience of the tolerating spirit of the Whigs seems of late to have reconciled the Catholics to that party.

My third observation on this subject is, that superstition is an enemy to civil liberty, while enthusiasm is its friend. Superstition suffers under the control of priests, and enthusiasm undermines all ecclesiastical authority, which explains this observation well. Moreover, enthusiasm, being a trait of bold and ambitious personalities, is naturally associated with a spirit of liberty, while superstition, on the other hand, makes people submissive and complacent, preparing them for slavery. We learn from English history that during the civil wars, the Independents and Deists, despite having very different religious beliefs, were united in their political views and both fervently supported a commonwealth. Since the emergence of Whig and Tory, the leaders of the Whigs have either been Deists or self-identified Latitudinarians; that is, they support toleration and are indifferent to any specific Christian sect. Meanwhile, the sectarians, with their strong inclination towards enthusiasm, have consistently supported that party in defense of civil liberty. The similarities in their superstitions have long brought together the High-Church Tories and the Roman Catholics in support of prerogative and royal power, though the experience of the tolerant spirit of the Whigs seems to have recently reconciled the Catholics with that party.

The Molinists and Jansenists in France have a thousand unintelligible disputes, which are not worthy the reflection of a man of sense: but what principally distinguishes these two sects, and alone merits attention, is the different spirit of their religion. The Molinists, conducted by the Jesuits, are great friends to superstition, rigid observers of external forms and ceremonies, and devoted to the authority of the priests, and to tradition. The Jansenists are enthusiasts, and zealous promoters of the passionate devotion, and of the inward life, little influenced by authority, and, in a word, but half Catholics. The consequences are exactly conformable to the foregoing reasoning. The Jesuits are the tyrants of the people, and the slaves of the court; and the Jansenists preserve alive the small sparks of the love of liberty which are to be found in the French nation.

The Molinists and Jansenists in France have countless confusing debates that aren’t worth the time of a sensible person. However, what mainly sets these two groups apart, and what truly deserves attention, is their different approach to religion. The Molinists, led by the Jesuits, are strong supporters of superstition, strict adherents to external rituals and ceremonies, and committed to the authority of priests and tradition. The Jansenists are passionate enthusiasts who promote deep devotion and an internal spiritual life, showing little deference to authority, and essentially are only half-Catholic. The outcomes of this are perfectly in line with the previous reasoning. The Jesuits act as tyrants over the people and are subservient to the court; meanwhile, the Jansenists keep alive the small sparks of the love for liberty that exist within the French nation.

[1] The Chinese literati have no priests or ecclesiastical establishment.

[1] The Chinese intellectuals have no priests or religious institution.


OF THE DIGNITY OR MEANNESS OF HUMAN NATURE

There are certain sects which secretly form themselves in the learned world, as well as factions in the political; and though sometimes they come not to an open rupture, they give a different turn to the ways of thinking of those who have taken part on either side. The most remarkable of this kind are the sects founded on the different sentiments with regard to the dignity of human nature; which is a point that seems to have divided philosophers and poets, as well as divines, from the beginning of the world to this day. Some exalt our species to the skies, and represent man as a kind of human demigod, who derives his origin from heaven, and retains evident marks of his lineage and descent. Others insist upon the blind sides of human nature, and can discover nothing, except vanity, in which man surpasses the other animals, whom he affects so much to despise. If an author possess the talent of rhetoric and declamation, he commonly takes part with the former: if his turn lie towards irony and ridicule, he naturally throws himself into the other extreme.

There are certain groups that quietly form themselves in both the academic world and in politics; and while they may not always come to an open conflict, they influence the way people think on both sides. The most notable among these groups are those based on differing views about the dignity of human nature; this issue seems to have divided philosophers, poets, and theologians from the beginning of time to now. Some elevate our species to great heights, portraying humans as a kind of demigod, stemming from divine origins and showing clear signs of that heritage. Others focus on the flaws of human nature, seeing nothing but vanity as the trait that makes humans superior to the other animals they claim to look down upon. If an author has the skills of rhetoric and persuasion, they usually side with the former group; if their style leans towards irony and mockery, they naturally align with the latter.

I am far from thinking that all those who have depreciated our species have been enemies to virtue, and have exposed the frailties of their fellow-creatures with any bad intention. On the contrary, I am sensible that a delicate sense of morals, especially when attended with a splenetic temper, is apt to give a man a disgust of the world, and to make him consider the common course of human affairs with too much indignation. I must, however, be of opinion, that the sentiments of those who are inclined to think favourably of mankind, are more advantageous to virtue than the contrary principles, which give us a mean opinion of our nature. When a man is prepossessed with a high notion of his rank and character in the creation, he will naturally endeavour to act up to it, and will scorn to do a base or vicious action which might sink him below that figure which he makes in his own imagination. Accordingly, we find, that all our polite and fashionable moralists insist upon this topic, and endeavour to represent vice unworthy of man, as well as odious in itself.[1]

I don't believe that everyone who has criticized our species has been against virtue or has pointed out the weaknesses of others with bad intentions. In fact, I realize that having a keen sense of morals, especially when paired with a bitter attitude, can lead a person to become disillusioned with the world and view the regular course of human affairs with too much anger. However, I think that the views of those who tend to see the good in humanity are more beneficial to virtue than the opposite mindset, which leads us to have a low opinion of our nature. When a person holds a high view of their status and character in the world, they will naturally strive to live up to it and will reject any shameful or immoral actions that could bring them down from the image they have of themselves. Consequently, we see that all our refined and fashionable moral thinkers emphasize this point and try to portray vice as unworthy of humanity, as well as inherently repulsive.[1]

We find new disputes that are not founded on some ambiguity in the expression; and I am persuaded that the present dispute, concerning the dignity or meanness of human nature, is not more exempt from it than any other. It may therefore be worth while to consider what is real, and what is only verbal, in this controversy.

We encounter new disagreements that aren't based on any ambiguity in the wording; and I'm convinced that the current disagreement, regarding the dignity or depravity of human nature, is just as affected by this as any other. It might be helpful to examine what is genuine and what is just superficial in this debate.

That there is a natural difference between merit and demerit, virtue and vice, wisdom and folly, no reasonable man will deny, yet it is evident that, in affixing the term, which denotes either our approbation or blame, we are commonly more influenced by comparison than by any fixed unalterable standard in the nature of things. In like manner, quantity, and extension, and bulk, are by every one acknowledged to be real things: but when we call any animal great or little, we always form a secret comparison between that animal and others of the same species; and it is that comparison which regulates our judgment concerning its greatness. A dog and a horse may be of the very same size, while the one is admired for the greatness of its bulk, and the other for the smallness. When I am present, therefore, at any dispute, I always consider with myself whether it be a question of comparison or not that is the subject of controversy; and if it be, whether the disputants compare the same objects together, or talk of things that are widely different.

There’s a clear natural difference between merit and demerit, virtue and vice, wisdom and folly, and no reasonable person would disagree. However, it’s clear that when we assign terms that reflect our approval or disapproval, we are often more influenced by comparison than by any fixed, unchanging standard in the nature of things. Similarly, quantity, extension, and bulk are recognized as real concepts by everyone. Yet when we describe an animal as great or little, we are always making an implicit comparison between that animal and others of the same species; it is this comparison that shapes our judgment regarding its size. A dog and a horse can be the exact same size, yet one may be admired for its large bulk while the other is appreciated for its smallness. So, when I am involved in any debate, I always think about whether the issue at hand is a matter of comparison or not, and if it is, whether the people debating are comparing the same objects or discussing things that are vastly different.

In forming our notions of human nature, we are apt to make a comparison between men and animals, the only creatures endowed with thought that fall under our senses. Certainly this comparison is favourable to mankind. On the one hand, we see a creature whose thoughts are not limited by any narrow bounds, either of place or time; who carries his researches into the most distant regions of this globe, and beyond this globe, to the planets and heavenly bodies; looks backward to consider the first origin, at least the history of the human race; casts his eye forward to see the influence of his actions upon posterity and the judgments which will be formed of his character a thousand years hence; a creature, who traces causes and effects to a great length and intricacy, extracts general principles from particular appearances; improves upon his discoveries; corrects his mistakes; and makes his very errors profitable. On the other hand, we are presented with a creature the very reverse of this; limited in its observations and reasonings to a few sensible objects which surround it; without curiosity, without foresight; blindly conducted by instinct, and attaining, in a short time, its utmost perfection, beyond which it is never able to advance a single step. What a wide difference is there between these creatures! And how exalted a notion must we entertain of the former, in comparison of the latter.

In shaping our views on human nature, we often compare humans to animals, the only beings capable of thought that we can perceive. This comparison definitely favors humanity. On one hand, we have a creature whose thoughts aren't restricted by any limits of place or time; one that explores the farthest corners of this planet and beyond, reaching out to the stars and celestial bodies; looks back to ponder the origins, or at least the history, of the human race; and gazes ahead to see how his actions will affect future generations and the judgments people will pass on his character thousands of years from now; a being that traces causes and effects in great detail, derives general principles from specific observations; builds on his discoveries; corrects his mistakes; and even learns from his failures. On the other hand, we have a creature that is completely different, limited in its observations and reasoning to just a few tangible things around it; lacking curiosity and foresight; blindly guided by instinct, achieving its full potential in a short time and unable to progress beyond that point. What a stark contrast between these creatures! And what an elevated view we must have of the former compared to the latter.

There are two means commonly employed to destroy this conclusion: First, By making an unfair representation of the case, and insisting only upon the weakness of human nature. And, secondly, By forming a new and secret comparison between man and beings of the most perfect wisdom. Among the other excellences of man, this is one, that he can form an idea of perfections much beyond what he has experience of in himself; and is not limited in his conception of wisdom and virtue. He can easily exalt his notions, and conceive a degree of knowledge, which, when compared to his own, will make the latter appear very contemptible, and will cause the difference between that and the sagacity of animals, in a manner, to disappear and vanish. Now this being a point in which all the world is agreed, that human understanding falls infinitely short of perfect wisdom, it is proper we should know when this comparison takes place, that we may not dispute where there is no real difference in our sentiments. Man falls much more short of perfect wisdom, and even of his own ideas of perfect wisdom, than animals do of man; yet the latter difference is so considerable, that nothing but a comparison with the former can make it appear of little moment.

There are two common ways to challenge this conclusion: First, by misrepresenting the situation and focusing only on the flaws of human nature. And, secondly, by making a secret and unfair comparison between humans and beings with perfect wisdom. One of the great things about humans is that we can imagine perfections far beyond our personal experiences and are not limited in our understanding of wisdom and virtue. We can easily elevate our ideas and envision a level of knowledge that, when compared to our own, makes our knowledge seem insignificant and blurs the differences between us and the intelligence of animals. Since it's widely accepted that human understanding falls far short of perfect wisdom, it's important to recognize when this comparison happens so that we don't argue over differences that really aren't there. Humans fall much shorter of perfect wisdom, and even their own ideas of it, than animals do of humans; however, that latter difference is so substantial that only by comparing it to the former can we make it seem less important.

It is also usual to compare one man with another; and finding very few whom we can call wise or virtuous, we are apt to entertain a contemptible notion of our species in general. That we may be sensible of the fallacy of this way of reasoning, we may observe, that the honourable appellations of wise and virtuous are not annexed to any particular degree of those qualities of wisdom and virtue, but arise altogether from the comparison we make between one man and another. When we find a man who arrives at such a pitch of wisdom, as is very uncommon, we pronounce him a wise man: so that to say there are few wise men in the world, is really to say nothing; since it is only by their scarcity that they merit that appellation. Were the lowest of our species as wise as Tully or Lord Bacon, we should still have reason to say that there are few wise men. For in that case we should exalt our notions of wisdom, and should not pay a singular homage to any one who was not singularly distinguished by his talents. In like manner, I have heard it observed by thoughtless people, that there are few women possessed of beauty in comparison of those who want it; not considering that we bestow the epithet of beautiful only on such as possess a degree of beauty that is common to them with a few. The same degree of beauty in a woman is called deformity, which is treated as real beauty in one of our sex.

It’s also common to compare one person to another, and when we find very few we can call wise or virtuous, we tend to hold a pretty low opinion of humanity as a whole. To understand the flaw in this way of thinking, we should recognize that the honorable titles of wise and virtuous aren’t tied to any specific level of those traits, but come from comparing one person to another. When we come across someone who reaches a level of wisdom that is quite rare, we label him a wise man. So when we say there are few wise people in the world, we’re not really saying much; it’s only their rarity that gives them that title. If the least among us were as wise as Tully or Lord Bacon, we’d still have to say there are few wise men, because we’d raise our standards for wisdom and wouldn’t uniquely honor anyone who wasn’t exceptionally gifted. Similarly, I’ve heard clueless people claim that there are few women who are beautiful compared to those who aren’t, not realizing that we only call someone beautiful if they have a level of beauty that is shared with a select few. The same level of beauty in a woman is often considered unattractive, while it’s seen as true beauty in a man.

As it is usual, in forming a notion of our species, to compare it with the other species above or below it, or to compare the individuals of the species among themselves; so we often compare together the different motives or actuating principles of human nature, in order to regulate our judgment concerning it. And, indeed, this is the only kind of comparison which is worth our attention, or decides any thing in the present question. Were our selfish and vicious principles so much predominant above our social and virtuous, as is asserted by some philosophers, we ought undoubtedly to entertain a contemptible notion of human nature.[2]

As is common, when trying to understand our species, we often compare it with other species, either higher or lower, or we compare individuals within our own species. Similarly, we frequently examine the different motivations or driving forces of human nature to help shape our judgment about it. In fact, this is the only type of comparison that truly matters or provides clarity on the issue at hand. If our selfish and corrupt tendencies were really so much stronger than our social and virtuous ones, as some philosophers claim, we would certainly have a low opinion of human nature.[2]

There is much of a dispute of words in all this controversy. When a man denies the sincerity of all public spirit or affection to a country and community, I am at a loss what to think of him. Perhaps he never felt this passion in so clear and distinct a manner as to remove all his doubts concerning its force and reality. But when he proceeds afterwards to reject all private friendship, if no interest or self-love intermix itself; I am then confident that he abuses terms, and confounds the ideas of things; since it is impossible for any one to be so selfish, or rather so stupid, as to make no difference between one man and another, and give no preference to qualities which engage his approbation and esteem. Is he also, say I, as insensible to anger as he pretends to be to friendship? And does injury and wrong no more affect him than kindness or benefits? Impossible: he does not know himself: he has forgotten the movements of his heart; or rather, he makes use of a different language from the rest of his countrymen and calls not things by their proper names. What say you of natural affection? (I subjoin), Is that also a species of self-love? Yes; all is self-love. Your children are loved only because they are yours: your friend for a like reason; and your country engages you only so far as it has a connection with yourself. Were the idea of self removed, nothing would affect you: you would be altogether unactive and insensible: or, if you ever give yourself any movement, it would only be from vanity, and a desire of fame and reputation to this same self. I am willing, reply I, to receive your interpretation of human actions, provided you admit the facts. That species of self-love which displays itself in kindness to others, you must allow to have great influence over human actions, and even greater, on many occasions, than that which remains in its original shape and form. For how few are there, having a family, children, and relations, who do not spend more on the maintenance and education of these than on their own pleasures? This, indeed, you justly observe, may proceed from their self-love, since the prosperity of their family and friends is one, or the chief of their pleasures, as well as their chief honour. Be you also one of these selfish men, and you are sure of every one's good opinion and good-will; or, not to shock your ears with their expressions, the self-love of every one, and mine among the rest, will then incline us to serve you, and speak well of you.

There’s a lot of wordplay in this whole controversy. When someone denies the authenticity of public spirit or love for a country and community, I’m left confused about what to think of them. Maybe they’ve never felt this emotion clearly enough to shake off their doubts about its power and reality. But when they go on to dismiss all private friendship unless it serves their interest or self-love, I’m sure they’re misusing terms and mixing up ideas. It’s impossible for anyone to be so selfish, or rather so clueless, as to see no difference between one person and another and not favor the qualities that earn their approval and respect. I wonder, are they really as numb to anger as they claim to be about friendship? Do they feel no more impacted by harm and wrongdoing than by kindness or benefits? Impossible: they don’t understand themselves; they’ve forgotten their heart’s responses; or rather, they’re using a different language from the rest of us and failing to call things by their correct names. What do you think about natural affection? Is that also a form of self-love? Yes; it’s all self-love. Your children are loved simply because they belong to you: your friend for the same reason; and your country matters to you only to the extent that it connects with yourself. If the idea of self were removed, nothing would matter to you: you would be completely inactive and unfeeling; or, if you ever took action, it would be out of vanity and a desire for fame and reputation for that same self. I’m willing, I reply, to accept your interpretation of human actions, as long as you acknowledge the facts. That kind of self-love that shows up as kindness to others has to have a significant influence on human behavior, often more so than its original form. After all, how many people with families, children, and relatives spend more on supporting and educating them than on their own pleasures? This, as you rightly point out, could stem from their self-love since the success of their family and friends is one of their greatest pleasures as well as their main honor. Be one of those selfish people, and you will certainly gain everyone’s respect and goodwill; or, not to disturb your ears with harsh terms, the self-love of everyone, including myself, will then drive us to support you and speak positively of you.

In my opinion, there are two things which have led astray those philosophers that have insisted so much on the selfishness of man. In the first place, they found that every act of virtue or friendship was attended with a secret pleasure; whence they concluded, that friendship and virtue could not be disinterested. But the fallacy of this is obvious. The virtuous sentiment or passion produces the pleasure, and does not arise from it. I feel a pleasure in doing good to my friend, because I love him; but do not love him for the sake of that pleasure.

In my view, there are two main reasons why some philosophers have gotten it wrong about human selfishness. First, they noticed that every act of kindness or friendship comes with a hidden sense of joy, which led them to conclude that friendship and kindness can’t be genuine. But this reasoning is clearly flawed. The feeling of pleasure comes from the virtuous act itself, not the other way around. I feel happy when I do something good for my friend because I care about him; I don’t care about him just for that happiness.

In the second place, it has always been found, that the virtuous are far from being indifferent to praise; and therefore they have been represented as a set of vainglorious men, who had nothing in view but the applauses of others. But this also is a fallacy. It is very unjust in the world, when they find any tincture of vanity in a laudable action, to depreciate it upon that account, or ascribe it entirely to that motive. The case is not the same with vanity, as with other passions. Where avarice or revenge enters into any seemingly virtuous action, it is difficult for us to determine how far it enters, and it is natural to suppose it the sole actuating principle. But vanity is so closely allied to virtue, and to love the fame of laudable actions approaches so near the love of laudable actions for their own sake, that these passions are more capable of mixture, than any other kinds of affection; and it is almost impossible to have the latter without some degree of the former. Accordingly we find, that this passion for glory is always warped and varied according to the particular taste or disposition of the mind on which it falls. Nero had the same vanity in driving a chariot, that Trajan had in governing the empire with justice and ability. To love the glory of virtuous deeds is a sure proof of the love of virtue.

In the second place, it has always been seen that people with virtue are far from indifferent to praise; so they've been portrayed as a group of boastful individuals who only seek the approval of others. But that's a misconception. It's really unfair when people notice any hint of vanity in a commendable action and then downplay it for that reason or attribute it completely to that motive. The situation with vanity isn't the same as with other emotions. When greed or revenge influences a seemingly virtuous action, it's hard for us to determine how much it plays a role, and it’s natural to think it’s the only driving force. However, vanity is so closely linked to virtue, and the desire for recognition of good deeds is so close to appreciating good actions for their own sake, that these feelings can mix together more easily than other types of emotions; it’s nearly impossible to have the latter without some level of the former. Accordingly, we find that this desire for glory is always shaped and changed by the specific preferences or personality of the person experiencing it. Nero had the same vanity in racing a chariot as Trajan had in ruling the empire justly and effectively. Loving the glory of virtuous actions is a clear sign of genuinely loving virtue.

[1] Women are generally much more flattered in their youth than men, which may proceed from this reason among others, that their chief point of honour is considered as much more difficult than ours, and requires to be supported by all that decent pride which can be instilled into them.

[1] Women are generally more flattered in their youth than men, possibly because their main point of pride is seen as much harder to maintain than ours, and it needs to be upheld by all the decent pride that can be instilled in them.

[2] I may perhaps treat more fully of this subject in some future Essay. In the meantime I shall observe, what has been proved beyond question by several great moralists of the present age, that the social passions are by far the most powerful of any, and that even all the other passions, receive from them their chief force and influence. Whoever desires to see this question treated at large, with the greatest force of argument and eloquence, may consult my Lord Shaftesbury's Enquiry concerning Virtue.

[2] I might explore this topic more thoroughly in a future essay. For now, I want to point out what has been clearly established by several prominent moralists today: social passions are by far the strongest of all, and all other passions derive their main strength and influence from them. Anyone who wants to see this issue addressed in detail, with strong arguments and eloquence, should check out my Lord Shaftesbury's *Enquiry concerning Virtue*.


OF CIVIL LIBERTY

Those who employ their pens on political subjects, free from party rage, and party prejudices, cultivate a science, which, of all others, contributes most to public utility, and even to the private satisfaction of those who addict themselves to the study of it. I am apt, however, to entertain a suspicion, that the world is still too young to fix many general truths in politics, which will remain true to the latest posterity. We have not as yet had experience of three thousand years; so that not only the art of reasoning is still imperfect in this science, as in all others, but we even want sufficient materials upon which we can reason. It is not fully known what degree of refinement, either in virtue or vice, human nature is susceptible of, nor what may be expected of mankind from any great revolution in their education, customs, or principles. Machiavel was certainly a great genius; but, having confined his study to the furious and tyrannical governments of ancient times, or to the little disorderly principalities of Italy, his reasonings, especially upon monarchical government, have been found extremely defective; and there scarcely is any maxim in his Prince which subsequent experience has not entirely refuted. 'A weak prince,' says he, 'is incapable of receiving good counsel; for, if he consult with several, he will not be able to choose among their different counsels. If he abandon himself to one, that minister may perhaps have capacity, but he will not long be a minister. He will be sure to dispossess his master, and place himself and his family upon the throne.' I mention this, among many instances of the errors of that politician, proceeding, in a great measure, from his having lived in too early an age of the world, to be a good judge of political truth. Almost all the princes of Europe are at present governed by their ministers, and have been so for near two centuries, and yet no such event has ever happened, or can possibly happen. Sejanus might project dethroning the Cæsars, but Fleury, though ever so vicious, could not, while in his senses, entertain the least hopes of dispossessing the Bourbons.

Those who write about politics without being swayed by party anger or biases are developing a subject that, more than any other, benefits the public and brings personal satisfaction to those who study it. However, I can't help but feel that the world is still too young to establish many political truths that will remain accurate for future generations. We haven't experienced three thousand years yet; as a result, not only is our understanding of reasoning in this field incomplete, but we also lack enough information to draw solid conclusions. It's still unclear how refined human nature—whether in virtue or vice—can become, or what to expect from people after significant changes in their education, customs, or beliefs. Machiavelli was undeniably a brilliant thinker, but his focus on the brutal and tyrannical governments of the past, or the small chaotic principalities of Italy, has led to serious flaws in his arguments, especially regarding monarchies. Almost every principle in his Prince has been contradicted by later experiences. He claims, "A weak prince cannot take good advice; if he seeks counsel from many, he won't be able to choose among their differing opinions. If he relies on just one advisor, they might be capable, but their time as a minister will be short-lived. They will ensure they displace their ruler and elevate themselves and their family to the throne." I bring this up as just one example of the many mistakes that politician made, largely because he lived in an earlier time and couldn't accurately judge political truths. Nowadays, almost all European rulers are led by their ministers, a situation that has persisted for nearly two centuries, yet such an event as he described has never happened and is unlikely to occur. Sejanus might have plotted to dethrone the Caesars, but Fleury, no matter how corrupt, wouldn't have entertained the slightest hope of unseating the Bourbons while he had his wits about him.

Trade was never esteemed an affair of state till the last century; and there scarcely is any ancient writer on politics who has made mention of it. Even the Italians have kept a profound silence with regard to it, though it has now engaged the chief attention, as well of ministers of state, as of speculative reasoners. The great opulence, grandeur, and military achievements of the two maritime powers, seem first to have instructed mankind in the importance of an extensive commerce.

Trade was never considered a matter of state until the last century; and there are hardly any ancient political writers who mention it. Even the Italians have remained silent about it, although it has now captured the main focus of both government officials and thinkers. The immense wealth, prestige, and military successes of the two maritime powers seem to have been the first lessons for humanity on the significance of extensive commerce.

Having therefore intended, in this Essay, to make a full comparison of civil liberty and absolute government, and to show the great advantages of the former above the latter; I began to entertain a suspicion that no man in this age was sufficiently qualified for such an undertaking, and that, whatever any one should advance on that head, would in all probability be refuted by further experience, and be rejected by posterity. Such mighty revolutions have happened in human affairs, and so many events have arisen contrary to the expectation of the ancients, that they are sufficient to beget the suspicion of still further changes.

Having intended in this essay to fully compare civil liberty and absolute government, and to highlight the significant advantages of the former over the latter, I started to doubt that anyone in this age was truly qualified for such a task. I feared that whatever anyone might claim on this topic would likely be disproven by future events and dismissed by future generations. There have been such major upheavals in human affairs, and so many occurrences that contradict the expectations of the ancients, that it’s reasonable to suspect even more changes are yet to come.

It had been observed by the ancients, that all the arts and sciences arose among free nations; and that the Persians and Egyptians, notwithstanding their ease, opulence, and luxury, made but faint efforts towards a relish in those finer pleasures, which were carried to such perfection by the Greeks, amidst continual wars, attended with poverty, and the greatest simplicity of life and manners. It had also been observed, that, when the Greeks lost their liberty, though they increased mightily in riches by means of the conquests of Alexander, yet the arts, from that moment, declined among them, and have never since been able to raise their head in that climate. Learning was transplanted to Rome, the only free nation at that time in the universe; and having met with so favourable a soil, it made prodigious shoots for above a century; till the decay of liberty produced also the decay of letters, and spread a total barbarism over the world. From these two experiments, of which, each was double in its kind, and showed the fall of learning in absolute governments, as well as its rise in popular ones, Longinus thought himself sufficiently justified in asserting that the arts and sciences could never flourish but in a free government. And in this opinion he has been followed by several eminent writers[1] in our own country, who either confined their view merely to ancient facts, or entertained too great a partiality in favour of that form of government established among us.

It was noted by the ancients that all arts and sciences developed among free nations; and that the Persians and Egyptians, despite their comfort, wealth, and luxury, made only weak attempts at appreciating the finer pleasures that the Greeks perfected, even in the midst of constant wars, poverty, and a simple way of life. It was also noted that when the Greeks lost their freedom, although they greatly increased in wealth through Alexander's conquests, the arts began to decline, and have never recovered in that region. Learning was moved to Rome, the only free nation in the world at that time; and having found a nurturing environment, it flourished for over a century until the decline of liberty led to a drop in letters and spread total barbarism across the globe. From these two cases, each showing the fall of learning in absolute governments and its rise in popular ones, Longinus felt justified in claiming that the arts and sciences could only thrive in a free government. This view has been supported by several prominent writers in our own country, who either focused solely on ancient examples or showed excessive favoritism toward the form of government we have established.

But what would these writers have said to the instances of modern Rome and Florence? Of which the former carried to perfection all the finer arts of sculpture, painting, and music, as well as poetry, though it groaned under tyranny, and under the tyranny of priests, while the latter made its chief progress in the arts and sciences after it began to lose its liberty by the usurpation of the family of Medici. Ariosto, Tasso, Galileo, no more than Raphael or Michael Angelo, were born in republics. And though the Lombard school was famous as well as the Roman, yet the Venetians have had the smallest share in its honours, and seem rather inferior to the other Italians in their genius for the arts and sciences. Rubens established his school at Antwerp, not at Amsterdam. Dresden, not Hamburg, is the centre of politeness in Germany.

But what would these writers have said about modern Rome and Florence? Rome perfected all the finer arts of sculpture, painting, and music, as well as poetry, even while suffering under tyranny, including the tyranny of priests. Florence made its biggest advances in the arts and sciences after it started losing its freedom due to the Medici family's takeover. Ariosto, Tasso, and Galileo, just like Raphael and Michelangelo, were born in republics. And while the Lombard school was well-known, the Venetians contributed the least to its honors and appear to be somewhat inferior to other Italians in their talent for the arts and sciences. Rubens established his school in Antwerp, not Amsterdam. Dresden, not Hamburg, is the center of culture in Germany.

But the most eminent instance of the flourishing of learning in absolute governments is that of France, which scarcely ever enjoyed any established liberty, and yet has carried the arts and sciences as near perfection as any other nation. The English are, perhaps, greater philosophers; the Italians better painters and musicians; the Romans were greater orators; but the French are the only people, except the Greeks, who have been at once philosophers, poets, orators, historians, painters, architects, sculptors, and musicians. With regard to the stage, they have excelled even the Greeks, who far excelled the English. And, in common life, they have, in a great measure, perfected that art, the most useful and agreeable of any, l'Art de Vivre, the art of society and conversation.

But the most notable example of the growth of knowledge in authoritarian states is France, which has rarely experienced true freedom, yet has advanced the arts and sciences as close to perfection as any other country. The English might be better philosophers; the Italians are likely superior painters and musicians; the Romans were known for their exceptional oratory, but the French are the only people, besides the Greeks, who have been philosophers, poets, orators, historians, painters, architects, sculptors, and musicians all at once. In terms of theater, they have even surpassed the Greeks, who were far ahead of the English. Additionally, in everyday life, they have largely perfected that skill, which is the most useful and enjoyable of all, l'Art de Vivre, the art of social interaction and conversation.

If we consider the state of the sciences and polite arts in our own country, Horace's observation, with regard to the Romans, may in a great measure be applied to the British.

If we look at the state of science and the arts in our country, Horace's comment about the Romans can largely be applied to the British.

Sed in longum tamen ævum
Manserunt, hodieque manent vestigia ruris.

But over the years
They have stayed, and today the traces of the countryside are still visible.

The elegance and propriety of style have been very much neglected among us. We have no dictionary of our language, and scarcely a tolerable grammar. The first polite prose we have was writ by a man who is still alive.[2] As to Sprat, Locke, and even Temple, they knew too little of the rules of art to be esteemed elegant writers. The prose of Bacon, Harrington, and Milton, is altogether stiff and pedantic, though their sense be excellent. Men, in this country, have been so much occupied in the great disputes of Religion, Politics, and Philosophy, that they had no relish for the seemingly minute observations of grammar and criticism. And, though this turn of thinking must have considerably improved our sense and our talent of reasoning, it must be confessed, that even in those sciences above mentioned, we have not any standard book which we can transmit to posterity: and the utmost we have to boast of, are a few essays towards a more just philosophy, which indeed promise well, but have not as yet reached any degree of perfection.

The elegance and appropriateness of style have been largely overlooked among us. We don’t have a proper dictionary for our language, and barely any decent grammar. The first refined prose we have was written by a man who is still alive.[2] As for Sprat, Locke, and even Temple, they didn’t know enough about the rules of writing to be considered elegant authors. The prose of Bacon, Harrington, and Milton is entirely stiff and pedantic, even though their ideas are excellent. People in this country have been so focused on the major debates in Religion, Politics, and Philosophy, that they haven’t had an appreciation for the seemingly minor details of grammar and criticism. And while this way of thinking has certainly improved our understanding and reasoning skills, it must be acknowledged that even in the aforementioned fields, we don’t have a standard book that we can pass down to future generations: the most we can claim are a few essays toward a more accurate philosophy, which indeed show promise but haven’t yet achieved any level of perfection.

It has become an established opinion, that commerce can never flourish but in a free government; and this opinion seems to be founded on a longer and larger experience than the foregoing, with regard to the arts and sciences. If we trace commerce in its progress through Tyre, Athens, Syracuse, Carthage, Venice, Florence, Genoa, Antwerp, Holland, England, &c., we shall always find it to have fixed its seat in free governments. The three greatest trading towns now in Europe, are London, Amsterdam, and Hamburg; all free cities, and Protestant cities; that is, enjoying a double liberty. It must, however, be observed, that the great jealousy entertained of late with regard to the commerce of France, seems to prove that this maxim is no more certain and infallible than the foregoing, and that the subjects of an absolute prince may become our rivals in commerce as well as in learning.

It has become widely accepted that commerce can only thrive in a free government; this belief appears to be based on a longer and broader experience than what we've seen with the arts and sciences. If we look at the history of commerce in places like Tyre, Athens, Syracuse, Carthage, Venice, Florence, Genoa, Antwerp, Holland, England, and so on, we will always find that it has established itself in free governments. The three biggest trading cities in Europe today are London, Amsterdam, and Hamburg; all of which are free and Protestant cities, meaning they enjoy a double liberty. However, it should be noted that the strong concerns recently expressed about French commerce suggest that this principle is not as certain and foolproof as the previous one, and that subjects of an absolute ruler can also become our competitors in commerce as well as in learning.

Durst I deliver my opinion in an affair of so much uncertainty, I would assert, that notwithstanding the efforts of the French, there is something hurtful to commerce inherent in the very nature of absolute government, and inseparable from it; though the reason I should assign for this opinion is somewhat different from that which is commonly insisted on. Private property seems to me almost as secure in a civilized European monarchy as in a republic, nor is danger much apprehended, in such a government, from the violence of the sovereign, more than we commonly dread harm from thunder, or earthquakes, or any accident the most unusual and extraordinary. Avarice, the spur of industry, is so obstinate a passion, and works its way through so many real dangers and difficulties, that it is not likely to be scared by an imaginary danger, which is so small, that it scarcely admits of calculation. Commerce, therefore, in my opinion, is apt to decay in absolute governments, not because it is there less secure, but because it is less honourable. A subordination of rank is absolutely necessary to the support of monarchy. Birth, titles, and place, must be honoured above industry and riches; and while these notions prevail, all the considerable traders will be tempted to throw up their commerce, in order to purchase some of those employments, to which privileges and honours are annexed.

If I may share my thoughts on such an uncertain matter, I would say that despite the efforts of the French, there is something damaging to trade that is inherent to the nature of absolute government and cannot be separated from it. The reason I would give for this opinion differs somewhat from the common arguments. Private property seems to be nearly as secure in a civilized European monarchy as it is in a republic, and we don’t typically fear much danger from the sovereign’s violence, much like we worry about thunder, earthquakes, or any rare and extraordinary events. Greed, which drives hard work, is such a strong passion and navigates through many real dangers and challenges, so it’s unlikely to be deterred by a virtually non-existent imagined threat. Therefore, in my view, trade tends to decline in absolute governments, not because it is less safe, but because it is less honorable. A hierarchy of ranks is essential for the support of monarchy. Birth, titles, and status must be valued more than hard work and wealth; as long as these ideas persist, all significant traders will be tempted to abandon their businesses to obtain those positions that come with privileges and honors.

Since I am upon this head, of the alterations which time has produced, or may produce in politics, I must observe, that all kinds of government, free and absolute, seem to have undergone in modern times, a great change for the better, with regard both to foreign and domestic management. The balance of power is a secret in politics, fully known only to the present age; and I must add, that the internal police of states has also received great improvements within the last century. We are informed by Sallust, that Catiline's army was much augmented by the accession of the highwaymen about Rome; though I believe, that all of that profession who are at present dispersed over Europe would not amount to a regiment. In Cicero's pleadings for Milo, I find this argument, among others, made use of to prove that his client had not assassinated Clodius. Had Milo, said he, intended to have killed Clodius, he had not attacked him in the daytime, and at such a distance from the city; he had waylaid him at night, near the suburbs, where it might have been pretended that he was killed by robbers; and the frequency of the accident would have favoured the deceit. This is a surprising proof of the loose policy of Rome, and of the number and force of these robbers, since Clodius was at that time attended by thirty slaves, who were completely armed, and sufficiently accustomed to blood and danger in the frequent tumults excited by that seditious tribune.

Since I'm on the subject of the changes that time has brought or may bring to politics, I have to point out that all forms of government, whether free or absolute, seem to have experienced significant improvements in modern times regarding both foreign and domestic management. The balance of power is a political secret that is well understood only in this era; I should also mention that the internal policing of states has seen considerable advancements over the last century. Sallust informs us that Catiline's army was greatly increased by the addition of highway robbers around Rome; however, I believe that all those in that profession currently scattered across Europe would not even make up a regiment. In Cicero's arguments for Milo, I see this argument, among others, presented to prove that his client did not kill Clodius. Cicero argues that if Milo had intended to kill Clodius, he would not have attacked him in broad daylight and so far from the city. He would have ambushed him at night near the suburbs, where it could have been claimed that he was killed by robbers, and the frequency of such incidents would have supported the deception. This serves as surprising evidence of the lax policies in Rome and the number and strength of these robbers, considering Clodius was at that time accompanied by thirty armed slaves who were well accustomed to violence and danger from the frequent turmoil stirred up by that troublesome tribune.

But though all kinds of government be improved in modern times, yet monarchical government seems to have made the greatest advances towards perfection. It may now be affirmed of civilized monarchies, what was formerly said in praise of republics alone, that they are a government of Laws, not of Men. They are found susceptible of order, method, and constancy, to a surprising degree. Property is there secure, industry encouraged, the arts flourish, and the prince lives secure among his subjects, like a father among his children. There are, perhaps, and have been for two centuries, near two hundred absolute princes, great and small, in Europe; and allowing twenty years to each reign, we may suppose, that there have been in the whole two thousand monarchs, or tyrants, as the Greeks would have called them; yet of these there has not been one, not even Philip II of Spain, so bad as Tiberius, Caligula, Nero, or Domitian, who were four in twelve among the Roman emperors. It must, however, be confessed, that though monarchical governments have approached nearer to popular ones in gentleness and stability, they are still inferior. Our modern education and customs instil more humanity and moderation than the ancient; but have not as yet been able to overcome entirely the disadvantages of that form of government.

But even though all types of government have improved in modern times, monarchical government seems to have made the greatest strides toward perfection. We can now say about civilized monarchies what was once said only in praise of republics: they are a government of Laws, not of Men. They show a surprising degree of order, method, and consistency. Property is secure, industry is encouraged, the arts thrive, and the king lives safely among his subjects, like a father among his children. There have been nearly two hundred absolute princes, great and small, in Europe over the past two centuries; if we assume an average reign of twenty years, we might think there have been around two thousand monarchs, or tyrants, as the Greeks would call them. Yet not one of them, not even Philip II of Spain, has been as bad as Tiberius, Caligula, Nero, or Domitian, who were four out of twelve among the Roman emperors. However, we must admit that although monarchical governments have become gentler and more stable, they are still inferior. Our modern education and customs promote more humanity and moderation than in ancient times, but they have not yet completely overcome the drawbacks of that form of government.

But here I must beg leave to advance a conjecture, which seems probable, but which posterity alone can fully judge of. I am apt to think, that in monarchical governments there is a source of improvement, and in popular governments a source of degeneracy, which in time will bring these species of civil polity still nearer an equality. The greatest abuses which arise in France, the most perfect model of pure monarchy, proceed not from the number or weight of the taxes, beyond what are to be met with in free countries; but from the expensive, unequal, arbitrary, and intricate method of levying them, by which the industry of the poor, especially of the peasants and farmers, is in a great measure discouraged, and agriculture rendered a beggarly and slavish employment. But to whose advantage do these abuses tend? If to that of the nobility, they might be esteemed inherent in that form of government, since the nobility are the true supports of monarchy; and it is natural their interest should be more consulted in such a constitution, than that of the people. But the nobility are, in reality, the chief losers by this oppression, since it ruins their estates, and beggars their tenants. The only gainers by it are the Financiers, a race of men rather odious to the nobility and the whole kingdom. If a prince or minister, therefore, should arise, endowed with sufficient discernment to know his own and the public interest, and with sufficient force of mind to break through ancient customs, we might expect to see these abuses remedied; in which case, the difference between that absolute government and our free one would not appear so considerable as at present.

But here I have to make a guess, which seems likely, but only future generations can really judge. I tend to think that in monarchies, there's a potential for improvement, while in democracies, there’s a potential for decline, which will eventually bring these types of government closer to equality. The worst issues in France, the most ideal example of a pure monarchy, don't come from the amount or burden of taxes, which are similar to those in free countries; instead, they stem from the costly, unequal, arbitrary, and complicated way of collecting them. This process discourages the hard work of the poor, especially the peasants and farmers, making agriculture feel like a degrading and servile job. But who benefits from these problems? If it’s the nobility, then they might be considered a natural part of that government system, since they are the true backbone of monarchy; it’s only expected that their interests should be prioritized over those of the people. However, in reality, the nobility are the primary victims of this oppression, as it destroys their land and impoverishes their tenants. The only ones who profit from it are the Financiers, a group that is quite disliked by the nobility and the entire country. So, if a prince or minister were to come along, possessing enough insight to understand both his own interests and those of the public, and the strong will to challenge outdated practices, we could expect to see these issues fixed; in that case, the difference between that absolute government and our democratic one wouldn’t seem as significant as it does now.

The source of degeneracy which may be remarked in free governments, consists in the practice of contracting debt, and mortgaging the public revenues, by which taxes may, in time, become altogether intolerable, and all the property of the state be brought into the hands of the public The practice is of modern date. The Athenians, though governed by a republic, paid near two hundred per cent. for those sums of money which any emergency made it necessary for them to borrow; as we learn from Xenophon. Among the moderns, the Dutch first introduced the practice of borrowing great sums at low interest, and have wellnigh ruined themselves by it. Absolute princes have also contracted debt; but as an absolute prince may make a bankruptcy when he pleases, his people can never be oppressed by his debts. In popular governments, the people, and chiefly those who have the highest offices, being commonly the public creditors, it is difficult for the state to make use of this remedy, which, however it may sometimes be necessary, is always cruel and barbarous. This, therefore, seems to be an inconvenience which nearly threatens all free governments, especially our own, at the present juncture of affairs. And what a strong motive is this to increase our frugality of public money, lest, for want of it, we be reduced, by the multiplicity of taxes, or, what is worse, by our public impotence and inability for defence, to curse our very liberty, and wish ourselves in the same state of servitude with all the nations who surround us?

The problem with degeneration in free governments comes from borrowing money and putting public revenue up as collateral, which can lead to overwhelming taxes and all state property ending up in public control. This issue is relatively modern. The Athenians, despite being a republic, paid nearly two hundred percent for the money they needed to borrow in emergencies, as noted by Xenophon. Among modern nations, the Dutch were the first to start borrowing large amounts at low interest rates, and they've nearly destroyed themselves because of it. Absolute monarchs have also taken on debt; however, since they can declare bankruptcy at any time, their citizens are not burdened by their debts. In popular governments, it’s harder for the state to use this last-resort option because the people – especially those in high offices – are often the public creditors, making it cruel and harsh. This issue poses a significant threat to all free governments, especially our own, given the current state of affairs. This serves as a strong motivation to be more frugal with public funds, so that we don’t find ourselves drowning in taxes or, worse, feeling powerless and longing for the same kind of servitude that affects the nations around us.

[1] Mr. Addison and Lord Shaftesbury.

Mr. Addison and Lord Shaftesbury.

[2] Dr. Swift.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Dr. Swift.


OF ELOQUENCE

Those who consider the periods and revolutions of human kind, as represented in history, are entertained with a spectacle full of pleasure and variety, and see with surprise the manners, customs, and opinions of the same species susceptible of such prodigious changes in different periods of time. It may, however, be observed, that, in civil history, there is found a much greater uniformity than in the history of learning and science, and that the wars, negotiations, and politics of one age, resemble more those of another than the taste, wit, and speculative principles. Interest and ambition, honour and shame, friendship and enmity, gratitude and revenge, are the prime movers in all public transactions; and these passions are of a very stubborn and untractable nature, in comparison of the sentiments and understanding, which are easily varied by education and example. The Goths were much more inferior to the Romans in taste and science than in courage and virtue.

Those who consider the periods and revolutions of humankind, as shown in history, are entertained by a spectacle filled with pleasure and variety, and are surprised by how the behaviors, customs, and opinions of the same species can experience such enormous changes over different periods of time. However, it can be noted that in civil history, there is a greater uniformity compared to the history of learning and science, and the wars, negotiations, and politics of one age are more similar to those of another than the tastes, wit, and philosophical ideas. Interests and ambitions, honor and shame, friendship and enmity, gratitude and revenge are the driving forces behind all public actions; and these passions are much more stubborn and resistant to change than sentiments and understanding, which can easily be influenced by education and examples. The Goths were much more inferior to the Romans in taste and science than in courage and virtue.

But not to compare together nations so widely different, it may be observed, that even this latter period of human learning is, in many respects, of an opposite character to the ancient; and that, if we be superior in philosophy, we are still, notwithstanding all our refinements, much inferior in eloquence.

But not to compare nations that are so different, it can be noted that this later stage of human knowledge is, in many ways, quite different from the ancient one; and that while we may be better in philosophy, we are still, despite all our advancements, much worse in eloquence.

In ancient times, no work of genius was thought to require so great parts and capacity as the speaking in public; and some eminent writers have pronounced the talents even of a great poet or philosopher to be of an inferior nature to those which are requisite for such an undertaking. Greece and Rome produced, each of them, but one accomplished orator; and, whatever praises the other celebrated speakers might merit, they were still esteemed much inferior to those great models of eloquence. It is observable, that the ancient critics could scarcely find two orators in any age who deserved to be placed precisely in the same rank, and possessed the same degree of merit. Calvus, Cælius, Curio, Hortensius, Cæsar, rose one above another: but the greatest of that age was inferior to Cicero, the most eloquent speaker that had ever appeared in Rome. Those of fine taste, however, pronounced this judgment of the Roman orator, as well as of the Grecian, that both of them surpassed in eloquence all that had ever appeared, but that they were far from reaching the perfection of their art, which was infinite, and not only exceeded human force to attain, but human imagination to conceive. Cicero declares himself dissatisfied with his own performances, nay, even with those of Demosthenes. Ita sunt avidæ et capaces meæ aures, says he, et semper aliquid immensum infinitumque desiderant.

In ancient times, no work of genius was considered to require as much skill and ability as public speaking; some distinguished writers even stated that the talents of a great poet or philosopher were inferior to those needed for such a task. Greece and Rome each produced only one truly accomplished orator, and no matter how deserving of praise the other celebrated speakers were, they were still seen as much lesser than these great examples of eloquence. It’s noteworthy that ancient critics could hardly find two orators from any era who deserved to be ranked the same or had the same level of merit. Calvus, Cælius, Curio, Hortensius, and Cæsar each rose above one another, but the greatest of that time was still not on the same level as Cicero, the most eloquent speaker to ever emerge in Rome. Those with refined taste judged both the Roman and Greek orators to surpass all who had come before them in eloquence, but noted they were far from achieving the perfection of their art, which was infinite and beyond what human strength could achieve or human imagination could conceive. Cicero expressed dissatisfaction with his own work, and even with that of Demosthenes. Ita sunt avidæ et capaces meæ aures, he said, et semper aliquid immensum infinitumque desiderant.

Of all the polite and learned nations, England alone possesses a popular government, or admits into the legislature such numerous assemblies as can be supposed to lie under the dominion of eloquence. But what has England to boast of in this particular? In enumerating the great men who have done honour to our country, we exult in our poets and philosophers; but what orators are ever mentioned? or where are the monuments of their genius to be met with? There are found, indeed, in our histories, the names of several, who directed the resolutions of our parliament: but neither themselves nor others have taken the pains to preserve their speeches, and the authority, which they possessed, seems to have been owing to their experience, wisdom, or power, more than to their talents for oratory. At present there are above half a dozen speakers in the two Houses, who, in the judgment of the public, have reached very near the same pitch of eloquence; and no man pretends to give any one the preference above the rest. This seems to me a certain proof, that none of them have attained much beyond a mediocrity in their art, and that the species of eloquence, which they aspire to, gives no exercise to the sublimer faculties of the mind, but may be reached by ordinary talents and a slight application. A hundred cabinet-makers in London can work a table or a chair equally well; but no one poet can write verses with such spirit and elegance as Mr. Pope.

Of all the polite and educated nations, England is the only one that has a popular government or allows such large assemblies into the legislature that can be influenced by eloquence. But what does England really have to brag about in this regard? When we list the great individuals who have brought honor to our country, we take pride in our poets and philosophers; but which orators do we mention? Where are the monuments to their genius? Indeed, our histories include the names of several who guided the decisions of our parliament: however, neither they nor anyone else has made an effort to preserve their speeches, and the authority they had seems to stem more from their experience, wisdom, or power than from their oratory skills. Right now, there are more than half a dozen speakers in the two Houses who, in the public's view, have reached nearly the same level of eloquence; no one claims that any one of them stands out above the others. This seems to me clear evidence that none of them have achieved much beyond mediocrity in their craft, and the kind of eloquence they strive for doesn’t engage the higher faculties of the mind but can be attained through ordinary talent and minimal effort. A hundred cabinet-makers in London can make a table or chair just as well as each other; but no one poet can write verses with the same spirit and elegance as Mr. Pope.

We are told, that, when Demosthenes was to plead, all ingenious men flocked to Athens from the most remote parts of Greece, as to the most celebrated spectacle of the world. At London, you may see men sauntering in the court of requests, while the most important debate is carrying on in the two Houses; and many do not think themselves sufficiently compensated for the losing of their dinners, by all the eloquence of our most celebrated speakers. When old Cibber is to act, the curiosity of several is more excited, than when our prime minister is to defend himself from a motion for his removal or impeachment.

We hear that when Demosthenes was about to speak, clever people traveled from all over Greece to Athens, drawn to what was considered the greatest spectacle in the world. In London, you’ll find people strolling around the court of requests while crucial debates are happening in the two Houses; many feel that missing their dinners isn’t worth it, no matter how eloquently our top speakers perform. When old Cibber is set to act, more people’s curiosity is piqued than when our prime minister faces a motion for removal or impeachment.

Even a person, unacquainted with the noble remains of ancient orators, may judge, from a few strokes, that the style or species of their eloquence was infinitely more sublime than that which modern orators aspire to. How absurd would it appear, in our temperate and calm speakers, to make use of an Apostrophe, like that noble one of Demosthenes, so much celebrated by Quintilian and Longinus, when, justifying the unsuccessful battle of Chæronea, he breaks out, 'No, my fellow-citizens. No: you have not erred. I swear by the manes of those heroes, who fought for the same cause in the plains of Marathon and Platæa.' Who could now endure such a bold and poetical figure as that which Cicero employs, after describing, in the most tragical terms, the crucifixion of a Roman citizen? 'Should I paint the horrors of this scene, not to Roman citizens, not to the allies of our state, not to those who have ever heard of the Roman name, not even to men, but to brute creatures; or, to go further, should I lift up my voice in the most desolate solitude, to the rocks and mountains, yet should I surely see those rude and inanimate parts of nature moved with horror and indignation at the recital of so enormous an action.' With what a blaze of eloquence must such a sentence be surrounded to give it grace, or cause it to make any impression on the hearers! And what noble art and sublime talents are requisite to arrive, by just degrees, at a sentiment so bold and excessive! To inflame the audience, so as to make them accompany the speaker in such violent passions, and such elevated conceptions; and to conceal, under a torrent of eloquence, the artifice by which all this is effectuated! Should this sentiment even appear to us excessive, as perhaps justly it may, it will at least serve to give an idea of the style of ancient eloquence, where such swelling expressions were not rejected as wholly monstrous and gigantic.

Even someone who isn't familiar with the impressive speeches of ancient orators can tell, from just a few examples, that their style of eloquence was way more elevated than what modern speakers aim for. It would seem ridiculous for our composed and mild-mannered speakers to use an Apostrophe like the famous one by Demosthenes, praised by Quintilian and Longinus, when he defends the failed battle of Chæronea by declaring, 'No, my fellow citizens. No: you have not made a mistake. I swear by the manes of those heroes who fought for the same cause on the plains of Marathon and Platæa.' Who could handle such a daring and poetic figure as Cicero used after dramatically describing the crucifixion of a Roman citizen? 'If I were to depict the horrors of this scene, I wouldn't just be speaking to Roman citizens, or to our state's allies, or even to those who have ever heard of the Roman name, but even to animals; or, to take it further, if I were to lift my voice in complete solitude to the rocks and mountains, I would still see those rough and lifeless parts of nature moved with horror and outrage at the telling of such a monstrous act.' Just imagine the level of eloquence needed to make such a sentence feel graceful or to leave an impression on the audience! It takes incredible skill and talent to reach such bold and extreme sentiments! To fire up the audience enough to join the speaker in such intense emotions and lofty ideas, while cleverly hiding the techniques used to achieve this under a flood of eloquence! Even if this sentiment seems excessive to us, which it might rightfully, it at least gives us a glimpse into the style of ancient eloquence, where such grand expressions were not completely dismissed as outrageous or excessive.

Suitable to this vehemence of thought and expression, was the vehemence of action, observed in the ancient orators. The supplosio pedis, or stamping with the foot, was one of the most usual and moderate gestures which they made use of; though that is now esteemed too violent, either for the senate, bar, or pulpit, and is only admitted into the theatre to accompany the most violent passions which are there represented.

Suitable to this intensity of thought and expression was the intensity of action seen in the ancient speakers. The supplosio pedis, or stamping of the foot, was one of the most common and moderate gestures they used; however, it is now considered too extreme for the senate, courtroom, or pulpit, and is only accepted in the theater to accompany the most intense emotions expressed there.

One is somewhat at a loss to what cause we may ascribe so sensible a decline of eloquence in latter ages. The genius of mankind, at all times, is perhaps equal: the moderns have applied themselves, with great industry and success, to all the other arts and sciences: and a learned nation possesses a popular government; a circumstance which seems requisite for the full display of these noble talents: but notwithstanding all these advantages, our progress in eloquence is very inconsiderable, in comparison of the advances which we have made in all other parts of learning.

One is somewhat confused about what causes the noticeable decline in eloquence in recent times. The human intellect, at all times, is likely equal: moderns have dedicated a lot of effort and success to all the other arts and sciences. Moreover, an educated nation has a democratic government; this seems necessary for fully showcasing these noble talents. Yet, despite all these benefits, our progress in eloquence is quite minimal compared to the advancements we've made in all other areas of learning.

Shall we assert, that the strains of ancient eloquence are unsuitable to our age, and ought not to be imitated by modern orators? Whatever reasons may be made use of to prove this, I am persuaded they will be found, upon examination, to be unsound and unsatisfactory.

Shall we say that the styles of ancient speech are not appropriate for our time and should not be copied by today's speakers? No matter what arguments might be offered to support this view, I believe they will ultimately be shown to be flawed and unconvincing.

First, It may be said, that, in ancient times, during the flourishing period of Greek and Roman learning, the municipal laws, in every state, were but few and simple, and the decision of causes was, in a great measure, left to the equity and common sense of the judges. The study of the laws was not then a laborious occupation, requiring the drudgery of a whole life to finish it, and incompatible with every other study or profession. The great statesmen and generals among the Romans were all lawyers; and Cicero, to show the facility of acquiring this science, declares, that in the midst of all his occupations, he would undertake, in a few days, to make himself a complete civilian. Now, where a pleader addresses himself to the equity of his judges, he has much more room to display his eloquence, than where he must draw his arguments from strict laws, statutes, and precedents. In the former case many circumstances must be taken in, many personal considerations regarded, and even favour and inclination, which it belongs to the orator, by his art and eloquence, to conciliate, may be disguised under the appearance of equity. But how shall a modern lawyer have leisure to quit his toilsome occupations, in order to gather the flowers of Parnassus? Or what opportunity shall we have of displaying them, amidst the rigid and subtile arguments, objections, and replies, which he is obliged to make use of? The greatest genius, and greatest orator, who should pretend to plead before the Chancellor, after a month's study of the laws, would only labour to make himself ridiculous.

First, it can be said that in ancient times, during the peak of Greek and Roman learning, the local laws in every state were minimal and straightforward, and the resolution of cases was largely left to the fairness and common sense of the judges. Studying the law wasn’t a demanding job that consumed an entire lifetime, nor was it incompatible with other studies or careers. The prominent statesmen and generals of Rome were all lawyers. Cicero even claimed that amid all his responsibilities, he could become a complete legal expert in just a few days. Nowadays, when a lawyer appeals to the fairness of judges, he has more opportunity to showcase his eloquence than when he must rely on rigid laws, statutes, and precedents. In the first scenario, many factors must be considered, personal circumstances taken into account, and even biases and preferences, which the speaker can smooth over using their skill and eloquence, can be masked by the notion of fairness. But how can a modern lawyer find time to step away from their demanding work to explore the beauty of poetry? And what chance do we have to show off those skills in the midst of strict and intricate arguments, counterarguments, and responses that must be used? The greatest talent and orator, who thinks they can plead before the Chancellor after a month of studying the law, would only end up making themselves look foolish.

I am ready to own, that this circumstance, of the multiplicity and intricacy of laws, is a discouragement to eloquence in modern times; but I assert, that it will not entirely account for the decline of that noble art. It may banish oratory from Westminster Hall, but not from either house of Parliament. Among the Athenians, the Areopagites expressly forbade all allurements of eloquence; and some have pretended, that in the Greek orations, written in the judiciary form, there is not so bold and rhetorical a style as appears in the Roman. But to what a pitch did the Athenians carry their eloquence in the deliberative kind, when affairs of state were canvassed, and the liberty, happiness, and honour of the republic, were the subject of debate! Disputes of this nature elevate the genius above all others, and give the fullest scope to eloquence; and such disputes are very frequent in this nation.

I admit that the complexity and number of laws can discourage eloquence today, but I believe that's not the only reason for the decline of this impressive art. It might drive oratory out of Westminster Hall, but not from either house of Parliament. Among the Athenians, the Areopagites specifically banned any seductive forms of eloquence; some claim that in Greek orations written in the judiciary style, there’s not as bold or rhetorical a tone as found in Roman speeches. But just think about how far the Athenians took their eloquence in deliberative discussions when state affairs were debated and the liberty, happiness, and honor of the republic were at stake! These kinds of debates elevate creativity above all else and allow eloquence to flourish, and such debates are quite common in this country.

Secondly, It may be pretended, that the decline of eloquence is owing to the superior good sense of the moderns, who reject with disdain all those rhetorical tricks employed to seduce the judges, and will admit of nothing but solid argument in any debate or deliberation. If a man be accused of murder, the fact must be proved by witnesses and evidence, and the laws will afterwards determine the punishment of the criminal. It would be ridiculous to describe, in strong colours, the horror and cruelty of the action; to introduce the relations of the dead, and, at a signal, make them throw themselves at the feet of the judges, imploring justice, with tears and lamentations: and still more ridiculous would it be, to employ a picture representing the bloody deed, in order to move the judges by the display of so tragical a spectacle, though we know that this artifice was sometimes practised by the pleaders of old. Now, banish the pathetic from public discourses, and you reduce the speakers merely to modern eloquence; that is, to good sense, delivered in proper expressions.

Secondly, Some might argue that the decline of eloquence is due to the greater good sense of modern people, who dismiss with scorn all the rhetorical tricks used to sway judges and will accept only solid arguments in any debate or discussion. If someone is accused of murder, the facts must be proven by witnesses and evidence, and the law will then decide the punishment for the criminal. It would be absurd to vividly describe the horror and cruelty of the act; to bring in the relatives of the deceased and, at a signal, have them fall at the judges' feet, pleading for justice with tears and cries; and even more ridiculous would be to use a graphic depiction of the bloody act to stir the judges by showcasing such a tragic scene, even though we know this tactic was sometimes used by lawyers in the past. Nowadays, if you remove any emotion from public speeches, you limit speakers to what we call modern eloquence; that is, sound reasoning expressed in appropriate language.

Perhaps it may be acknowledged, that our modern customs, or our superior good sense, if you will, should make our orators more cautious and reserved than the ancient, in attempting to inflame the passions, or elevate the imagination of their audience; but I see no reason why it should make them despair absolutely of succeeding in that attempt. It should make them redouble their art, not abandon it entirely. The ancient orators seem also to have been on their guard against this jealousy of their audience; but they took a different way of eluding it. They hurried away with such a torrent of sublime and pathetic, that they left their hearers no leisure to perceive the artifice by which they were deceived. Nay, to consider the matter aright, they were not deceived by any artifice. The orator, by the force of his own genius and eloquence, first inflamed himself with anger, indignation, pity, sorrow; and then communicated those impetuous movements to his audience.

Maybe it's fair to say that our modern customs, or our greater common sense, if you prefer, should make today's speakers more careful and reserved than those in ancient times when it comes to stirring up the audience's emotions or inspiring their imagination; however, I don't see why it should lead them to give up entirely on this effort. They should work even harder at their craft, not abandon it completely. Ancient speakers also seemed to be aware of this jealousy from their audience, but they approached it differently. They swept their listeners away with such a flood of inspiring and emotional content that there was no time for the audience to notice the tricks being used to captivate them. In fact, if we think about it, they weren’t fooled by any tricks at all. The speaker, through the power of their own talent and eloquence, first ignited their own feelings of anger, indignation, pity, and sorrow; then they shared those intense emotions with the audience.

Does any man pretend to have more good sense than Julius Cæsar?; yet that haughty conqueror, we know, was so subdued by the charms of Cicero's eloquence, that he was, in a manner, constrained to change his settled purpose and resolution, and to absolve a criminal, whom, before that orator pleaded, he was determined to condemn.

Does any man claim to have more common sense than Julius Caesar? Yet that arrogant conqueror, as we know, was so captivated by Cicero's eloquence that he was, in a way, forced to change his fixed intention and decision, and to pardon a criminal whom he had resolved to condemn before that orator spoke.

Some objections, I own, notwithstanding his vast success, may lie against some passages of the Roman orator. He is too florid and rhetorical: his figures are too striking and palpable: the divisions of his discourse are drawn chiefly from the rules of the schools: and his wit disdains not always the artifice even of a pun, rhyme, or jingle of words. The Grecian addressed himself to an audience much less refined than the Roman senate or judges. The lowest vulgar of Athens were his sovereigns, and the arbiters of his eloquence. Yet is his manner more chaste and austere than that of the other. Could it be copied, its success would be infallible over a modern assembly. It is rapid harmony, exactly adjusted to the sense; it is vehement reasoning, without any appearance of art: it is disdain, anger, boldness, freedom, involved in a continued stream of argument: and, of all human productions, the orations of Demosthenes present to us the models which approach the nearest to perfection.

Some objections, I admit, might be raised against certain parts of the Roman orator, despite his significant success. He can be overly flowery and rhetorical; his figures of speech are often too impactful and obvious; the organization of his speeches mainly follows the rules of academic rhetoric; and he doesn’t shy away from using puns, rhymes, or playful wordplay. The Greek orator spoke to an audience that was much less sophisticated than the Roman Senate or judges. The common people of Athens were his rulers and the judges of his eloquence. Yet, his style is more straightforward and serious than that of the other. If it could be replicated, it would certainly succeed with a modern audience. It flows with rapid harmony, perfectly matching the meaning; it features passionate reasoning that appears effortless; it expresses disdain, anger, boldness, and freedom, all woven into a continuous argument; and, among all human creations, the speeches of Demosthenes are the closest models we have to perfection.

Thirdly, It may be pretended, that the disorders of the ancient governments, and the enormous crimes of which the citizens were often guilty, afforded much ampler matter for eloquence than can be met with among the moderns. Were there no Verres or Catiline, there would be no Cicero. But that this reason can have no great influence, is evident. It would be easy to find a Philip in modern times, but where shall we find a Demosthenes?

Thirdly, some might argue that the issues of ancient governments and the serious crimes committed by citizens provided more material for eloquence than what we see today. If there were no Verres or Catiline, we wouldn’t have Cicero. However, it’s clear that this argument doesn’t hold much weight. It would be easy to find a Philip in modern times, but where can we find a Demosthenes?

What remains, then, but that we lay the blame on the want of genius, or of judgment, in our speakers, who either found themselves incapable of reaching the heights of ancient eloquence, or rejected all such endeavours, as unsuitable to the spirit of modern assemblies? A few successful attempts of this nature might rouse the genius of the nation, excite the emulation of the youth, and accustom our ears to a more sublime and more pathetic elocution, than what we have been hitherto entertained with. There is certainly something accidental in the first rise and progress of the arts in any nation. I doubt whether a very satisfactory reason can be given why ancient Rome, though it received all its refinements from Greece, could attain only to a relish for statuary, painting, and architecture, without reaching the practice of these arts. While modern Rome has been excited by a few remains found among the ruins of antiquity, and has produced artists of the greatest eminence and distinction. Had such a cultivated genius for oratory, as Waller's for poetry, arisen during the civil wars, when liberty began to be fully established, and popular assemblies to enter into all the most material points of government, I am persuaded so illustrious an example would have given a quite different turn to British eloquence, and made us reach the perfection of the ancient model. Our orators would then have done honour to their country, as well as our poets, geometers, and philosophers; and British Ciceros have appeared, as well as British Archimedeses and Virgils.[1]

What’s left for us to do but blame the lack of talent or judgment in our speakers? They either felt unable to reach the heights of ancient eloquence or dismissed those efforts as inappropriate for modern gatherings. A few successful attempts in this direction could inspire the nation’s creativity, motivate the youth, and get us used to a more elevated and emotional way of speaking than what we’ve experienced so far. There’s definitely something accidental about how the arts first emerge and develop in any nation. I doubt we can find a solid reason why ancient Rome, despite getting its culture from Greece, only developed a taste for sculpture, painting, and architecture without mastering these arts. Meanwhile, modern Rome has been sparked by a few remnants found among the ruins of the past and has produced some of the most talented and distinguished artists. If we had seen a refined talent for oratory, like Waller's for poetry, arise during the civil wars, when liberty began to take hold and public assemblies started to tackle significant government issues, I believe such a remarkable example would have shifted British eloquence in a different direction and brought us closer to the perfection of the ancient model. Our orators would have honored their country just like our poets, mathematicians, and philosophers; we would have had British Ciceros alongside British Archimedeses and Virgils.[1]

It is seldom or never found, when a false taste in poetry or eloquence prevails among any people, that it has been preferred to a true, upon comparison and reflection. It commonly prevails merely from ignorance of the true, and from the want of perfect models to lead men into a juster apprehension, and more refined relish of those productions of genius. When these appear, they soon unite all suffrages in their favour, and, by their natural and powerful charms, gain over even the most prejudiced to the love and admiration of them. The principles of every passion, and of every sentiment, is in every man; and, when touched properly, they rise to life, and warm the heart, and convey that satisfaction, by which a work of genius is distinguished from the adulterate beauties of a capricious wit and fancy. And, if this observation be true, with regard to all the liberal arts, it must be peculiarly so with regard to eloquence; which, being merely calculated for the public, and for men of the world, cannot, without any pretence of reason, appeal from the people to more refined judges, but must submit to the public verdict without reserve or limitation. Whoever, upon comparison, is deemed by a common audience the greatest orator, ought most certainly to be pronounced such by men of science and erudition. And though an indifferent speaker may triumph for a long time, and be esteemed altogether perfect by the vulgar, who are satisfied with his accomplishments, and know not in what he is defective; yet, whenever the true genius arises, he draws to him the attention of every one, and immediately appears superior to his rival.

It’s rare or never the case that when a false taste in poetry or eloquence takes hold among people, it’s genuinely preferred over a true taste after comparison and reflection. It usually prevails simply due to ignorance of what is true and the lack of strong models to guide people toward a better understanding and deeper appreciation of those works of genius. When these finally appear, they quickly earn everyone's support and, with their natural and powerful appeal, win over even the most biased to appreciate and admire them. The principles of every passion and feeling exist in every person; when touched appropriately, they come to life, warm the heart, and provide that satisfaction that distinguishes a work of genius from the superficial charms of an unpredictable wit and imagination. If this observation holds true for all the liberal arts, it must be especially relevant for eloquence, which, being designed for the public and for people in society, cannot reasonably appeal to a more refined audience but must accept the public's judgment without reservation. Anyone who is considered the greatest orator by a general audience should certainly be acknowledged as such by scholars and experts. And while a mediocre speaker may appear successful for a long time and be seen as perfect by the masses—who are satisfied with his talents and unaware of his shortcomings—whenever true genius emerges, it captures everyone’s attention and quickly shows itself to be superior to its rival.

Now, to judge by this rule, ancient eloquence, that is, the sublime and passionate, is of a much juster taste than the modern, or the argumentative and rational, and, if properly executed, will always have more command and authority over mankind. We are satisfied with our mediocrity, because we have had no experience of any thing better: but the ancients had experience of both; and upon comparison, gave the preference to that kind of which they have left us such applauded models. For, if I mistake not, our modern eloquence is of the same style or species with that which ancient critics denominated Attic eloquence, that is, calm, elegant, and subtile, which instructed the reason more than affected the passions, and never raised its tone above argument or common discourse. Such was the eloquence of Lysias among the Athenians, and of Calvus among the Romans. These were esteemed in their time; but, when compared with Demosthenes and Cicero, were eclipsed like a taper when set in the rays of a meridian sun. Those latter orators possessed the same elegance, and subtilty, and force of argument with the former; but, what rendered them chiefly admirable, was that pathetic and sublime, which, on proper occasions, they threw into their discourse, and by which they commanded the resolution of their audience.

Now, judging by this standard, ancient eloquence, which is grand and passionate, is much more refined than modern eloquence, which tends to be argumentative and rational. When executed well, it always has more influence and authority over people. We're content with our average standards because we've never experienced anything better; but the ancients knew both kinds and preferred the style that produced such celebrated examples. If I’m not mistaken, our modern eloquence resembles what ancient critics called Attic eloquence—calm, elegant, and subtle—which appealed more to reason than to emotions and never raised its tone beyond argument or everyday conversation. This was the style of Lysias among the Athenians and Calvus among the Romans. They were respected in their time, but when measured against Demosthenes and Cicero, they seem dim by comparison, like a candle in the bright light of the midday sun. Those later orators had the same elegance, subtlety, and argumentative strength as the former; however, what made them particularly remarkable was the emotional and elevated elements they infused into their speeches, which gave them the power to inspire their audience.

Of this species of eloquence we have scarcely had any instance in England, at least in our public speakers. In our writers, we have had some instances which have met with great applause, and might assure our ambitious youth of equal or superior glory in attempts for the revival of ancient eloquence. Lord Bolingbroke's productions, with all their defects in argument, method, and precision, contain a force and energy which our orators scarcely ever aim at; though it is evident that such an elevated style has much better grace in a speaker than in a writer, and is assured of more prompt and more astonishing success. It is there seconded by the graces of voice and action: the movements are mutually communicated between the orator and the audience: and the very aspect of a large assembly, attentive to the discourse of one man, must inspire him with a peculiar elevation, sufficient to give a propriety to the strongest figures and expressions. It is true, there is a great prejudice against set speeches; and a man cannot escape ridicule, who repeats a discourse as a schoolboy does his lesson, and takes no notice of any thing that has been advanced in the course of the debate. But where is the necessity of falling into this absurdity? A public speaker must know beforehand the question under debate. He may compose all the arguments, objections, and answers, such as he thinks will be most proper for his discourse. If any thing new occur, he may supply it from his own invention; nor will the difference be very apparent between his elaborate and his extemporary compositions. The mind naturally continues with the same impetus or force, which it has acquired by its motion as a vessel, once impelled by the oars, carries on its course for some time when the original impulse is suspended.

We have hardly seen this type of eloquence in England, at least among our public speakers. In our writers, there are some examples that have received great acclaim and could inspire our ambitious young people to strive for equal or greater recognition by trying to revive ancient eloquence. Lord Bolingbroke's works, despite their flaws in argument, structure, and clarity, possess a force and energy that our speakers rarely aim for; however, it's clear that such an elevated style is much more graceful in a speaker than in a writer, and it tends to achieve quicker and more impressive results. This style is enhanced by the gifts of voice and action: the energy flows between the speaker and the audience, and just seeing a large crowd engaged with one person’s speech is enough to elevate the speaker, giving strength to even the most powerful figures and expressions. It’s true that there is a strong bias against set speeches; someone can easily be mocked for reciting a speech like a schoolboy memorizing a lesson without acknowledging anything that has been said during the debate. But why should we fall into that trap? A public speaker should know the topic being discussed in advance. They can prepare arguments, counterarguments, and responses that they believe will fit their presentation best. If something new arises, they can add it from their own creativity; the difference between their carefully prepared notes and impromptu remarks won't be very noticeable. The mind naturally keeps the same momentum or force it has gained during its thought process, just like a boat continues to move forward for a while after its oars have stopped.

I shall conclude this subject with observing, that, even though our modern orators should not elevate their style, or aspire to a rivalship with the ancient; yet there is, in most of their speeches, a material defect which they might correct, without departing from that composed air of argument and reasoning to which they limit their ambition. Their great affectation of extemporary discourses has made them reject all order and method, which seems so requisite to argument, and without which it is scarcely possible to produce an entire conviction on the mind. It is not that one would recommend many divisions in a public discourse, unless the subject very evidently offer them: but it is easy, without this formality, to observe a method, and make that method conspicuous to the hearers, who will be infinitely pleased to see the arguments rise naturally from one another, and will retain a more thorough persuasion than can arise from the strongest reasons which are thrown together in confusion.

I want to wrap up this topic by noting that, even if today's speakers don't aim to elevate their style or compete with the classics, there’s a significant flaw in many of their speeches that they could fix without losing the composed tone of argumentation they strive for. Their strong emphasis on speaking off-the-cuff has led them to overlook the importance of order and structure, which are essential for persuasive arguments, and without which it’s nearly impossible to fully convince someone. It’s not that I would suggest having many divisions in a public speech, unless the topic clearly calls for it; however, it’s easy to follow a method and make that method clear to the audience. They will appreciate seeing the arguments flow logically from one to another, and they’ll have a stronger conviction than if the strongest points are presented chaotically.

[1] I have confessed that there is something accidental in the origin and progress of the arts in any nation; and yet I cannot forbear thinking, that if the other learned and polite nations of Europe had possessed the same advantages of a popular government, they would probably have carried eloquence to a greater height than it has yet reached in Britain. The French sermons, especially those of Flechier and Bourdaloue, are much superior to the English in this particular; and in Flechier there are many strokes of the most sublime poetry. His funeral sermon on the Marechal de Turenne, is a good instance. None but private causes in that country, are ever debated before their Parliament or Courts of Judicature; but, notwithstanding this disadvantage, there appears a spirit of eloquence in many of their lawyers, which, with proper cultivation and encouragement, might rise to the greatest heights. The pleadings of Patru are very elegant, and give us room to imagine what so fine a genius could have performed in questions concerning public liberty or slavery, peace or war, who exerts himself with such success in debates concerning the price of an old horse, or the gossiping story of a quarrel betwixt an abbess and her nuns. For it is remarkable, that this polite writer, though esteemed by all the men of wit in his time, was never employed in the most considerable causes of their courts of judicature, but lived and died in poverty; from an ancient prejudice industriously propagated by the Dunces in all countries, That a man of genius is unfit for business. The disorders produced by the ministry of Cardinal Mazarine, made the Parliament of Paris enter into the discussion of public affairs; and during that short interval, there appeared many symptoms of the revival of ancient eloquence. The Avocat-General, Talon, in an oration, invoked on his knees the spirit of St Louis to look down with compassion on his divided and unhappy people, and to inspire them, from above, with the love of concord and unanimity. The members of the French Academy have attempted to give us models of eloquence in their harangues at their admittance; but having no subject to discourse upon, they have run altogether into a fulsome strain of panegyric and flattery, the most barren of all subjects. Their style, however, is commonly, on these occasions, very elevated and sublime, and might reach the greatest heights, were it employed on a subject more favourable and engaging.

[1] I admit that there's something random about how the arts start and develop in any country; however, I can't help but think that if other educated and cultured nations in Europe had the same advantages of a popular government, they likely would have taken eloquence to even greater levels than it has achieved in Britain. French sermons, especially those by Flechier and Bourdaloue, are much better than the English ones in this regard; and in Flechier, there are many instances of the most remarkable poetry. His funeral sermon for the Marechal de Turenne is a great example. In that country, only private matters are typically debated in their Parliament or Courts of Justice; yet, despite this limitation, many of their lawyers show a spirit of eloquence that, with the right support and development, could reach impressive heights. Patru's pleadings are quite elegant, leading us to wonder what such a talented mind could have accomplished in discussions about public liberty or issues of war and peace, given that he demonstrates great skill in debates about the price of an old horse or the petty argument between an abbess and her nuns. It's worth noting that this refined writer, despite being respected by all the intellectuals of his time, was never called upon for the most significant cases in their courts, ultimately living and dying in poverty, due to an old bias pushed by the uninformed everywhere, That a man of talent is not suited for real work. The turmoil caused by Cardinal Mazarine's administration led the Parliament of Paris to engage in discussions about public matters; during that brief period, many signs of a revival of ancient eloquence emerged. The Avocat-General, Talon, in a speech, knelt to invoke the spirit of St. Louis to look down with pity on his divided and troubled people, and to inspire them from above with a love for harmony and unity. The members of the French Academy have tried to provide us with models of eloquence in their speeches at their induction; however, lacking a substantive topic to discuss, they have largely resorted to excessive praise and flattery, which is the least fruitful of all topics. Their style, though, is often very elevated and impressive on these occasions and could achieve great heights if focused on a more favorable and engaging subject.

There are some circumstances in the English temper and genius, which are disadvantageous to the progress of eloquence, and render all attempts of that kind more dangerous and difficult among them, than among any other nation in the universe. The English are conspicuous for good sense, which makes them very jealous of any attempts to deceive them, by the flowers of rhetoric and elocution. They are also peculiarly modest; which makes them consider it as a piece of arrogance to offer any thing but reason to public assemblies, or attempt to guide them by passion or fancy. I may, perhaps, be allowed to add that the people in general are not remarkable for delicacy of taste, or for sensibility to the charms of the Muses. Their musical parts, to use the expression of a noble author, are but indifferent. Hence their comic poets, to move them, must have recourse to obscenity; their tragic poets to blood and slaughter. And hence, their orators, being deprived of any such resource, have abandoned altogether the hopes of moving them, and have confined themselves to plain argument and reasoning.

There are some aspects of the English character and nature that make it harder for them to appreciate eloquence, making efforts in that direction riskier and more challenging than in any other nation in the world. The English are known for their good sense, which makes them very wary of being misled by persuasive language and eloquent speech. They are also especially modest; this leads them to view it as arrogant to present anything other than reason in public gatherings or to try to sway them with emotion or imagination. I might also add that people, in general, are not known for their refined taste or their sensitivity to the beauty of poetry. Their appreciation for music, to use a phrase from a famous author, is quite average. As a result, comic poets often resort to obscenity to entertain them, while tragic poets rely on violence and gore. Consequently, orators, lacking any such options, have completely given up on trying to move their audience and have limited themselves to straightforward argument and logic.

These circumstances, joined to particular accidents, may, perhaps, have retarded the growth of eloquence in this kingdom; but will not be able to prevent its success, if ever it appear amongst us. And one may safely pronounce, that this is a field in which the most flourishing laurels may yet be gathered, if any youth of accomplished genius, thoroughly acquainted with all the polite arts, and not ignorant of public business, should appear in Parliament, and accustom our ears to an eloquence more commanding and pathetic. And to confirm me in this opinion, there occur two considerations, the one derived from ancient, the other from modern times.

These circumstances, along with specific events, might have slowed down the development of eloquence in this kingdom, but they won't stop its success if it ever arises among us. It’s safe to say that this is a field where the most impressive achievements could still be made if a talented young person, well-versed in all the refined arts and knowledgeable about public matters, were to emerge in Parliament and get us used to a more powerful and moving form of eloquence. To support this view, there are two factors to consider, one from ancient times and the other from modern times.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!