This is a modern-English version of Unto This Last, and Other Essays on Political Economy, originally written by Ruskin, John. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.

 

E-text prepared by David Clarke
and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team
(http://www.pgdp.net)

E-text prepared by David Clarke
and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team
(http://www.pgdp.net)

 


 

 

 

UNTO THIS LAST
AND OTHER ESSAYS
ON POLITICAL ECONOMY


The World Library


UNTO THIS
LAST

AND OTHER ESSAYS
ON
POLITICAL ECONOMY

BY
JOHN RUSKIN

 

 

 

LONDON
MELBOURNE · & · TORONTO
WARD · LOCK · & · CO · LIMITED
1912


CONTENTS.

PART I.

PAGE
THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF ART7
Lecture 1.11
    1. Discovery23
    2. Application28
Lecture 2.46
    3. Accumulation46
    4. Distribution65
Updates86
   Note 1.—"Fatherly Authority"86
"2.— Right to Public Support"90
"3.—Trial Schools"95
"4.—"Public Favor"101
"Inventing new needs"102
"6. - Economy of Literature"104
"7.—"State Pilots"106
"8.—"Silk and Purple""107

PART II.

PAGE
UNTO THIS LAST117
Essay 
    I.—The Roots of Honour127
    II.—The Veins of Wealth143
    III.—"Qui Judicatis Terram"156
    IV.—Ad Valorem173

PART III.

PAGE
ESSAYS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY[A] 
I.—Maintaining Life: Wealth, Money, and Riches207
    Section 1. Wealth214
        "       2. Money219
        "       3. Riches222
II.—Nature of Wealth, Changes in Value, The National Store, Nature of Labor, Value and Price, The Currency225
III.—The Currency Holders and Store Holders, The Illness of Desire252
IV.—Laws and Governments: Work and Wealth278

 

[A] These Essays were afterwards revised and amplified, and published with others under the title "Munera Pulveris."

[A] These essays were later revised and expanded, and published alongside others under the title "Munera Pulveris."

 


THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF ART.


 

PREFACE.

The greater part of the following treatise remains in the exact form in which it was read at Manchester; but the more familiar passages of it, which were trusted to extempore delivery, have been since written with greater explicitness and fullness than I could give them in speaking; and a considerable number of notes are added, to explain the points which could not be sufficiently considered in the time I had at my disposal in the lecture-room.

The majority of the following essay is in the same format it was presented in at Manchester; however, the more informal parts that were delivered spontaneously have been rewritten with more clarity and detail than I could provide while speaking. Additionally, I've included a significant number of notes to clarify points that couldn't be thoroughly addressed given the limited time I had in the lecture room.

Some apology may be thought due to the reader, for an endeavour to engage his attention on a subject of which no profound study seems compatible with the work in which I am usually employed. But profound study is not, in this case, necessary either to writer or reader, while accurate study, up to a certain point, is necessary for us all. Political economy means, in plain English, nothing more than "citizens' economy"; and its first principles ought, therefore, to be understood by all who mean to take the responsibility of citizens, as those of household economy by all who take the responsibility of householders. Nor are its first principles in the least obscure: they are, many of them, disagreeable in their practical requirements, and people in general pretend that they cannot understand, because they are unwilling to obey them; or, rather, by habitual disobedience, destroy their capacity of understanding them. But there is not one of the really great principles of the science which is either obscure or[Pg 10] disputable—which might not be taught to a youth as soon as he can be trusted with an annual allowance, or to a young lady as soon as she is of age to be taken into counsel by the housekeeper.

Some apology might be owed to the reader for trying to capture their attention on a subject that doesn't seem to align well with my usual work. However, deep study isn't necessary for either the writer or the reader in this case, although a certain level of accurate understanding is important for all of us. Political economy simply means "economy of citizens" in straightforward terms, and its basic principles should be understood by anyone who wants to take on the responsibilities of citizenship, just as the principles of household economy should be understood by those responsible for a household. The basic principles aren't really confusing; rather, many of them are uncomfortable in their practical demands, and people often claim they can't grasp them because they're reluctant to follow them. Or, more accurately, their repeated refusal to comply hampers their ability to understand. Yet, there's not a single one of the foundational principles of this field that is confusing or debatable—any of them could be taught to a young person as soon as they can manage an allowance or to a young woman as soon as she is of age to be involved in household decisions.

I might, with more appearance of justice, be blamed for thinking it necessary to enforce what everybody is supposed to know. But this fault will hardly be found with me, while the commercial events recorded daily in our journals, and still more the explanations attempted to be given of them, show that a large number of our so-called merchants are as ignorant of the nature of money as they are reckless, unjust, and unfortunate in its employment.

I might seem more justified in being criticized for believing it's necessary to emphasize what's supposed to be common knowledge. However, this criticism should be rare since the business news we read every day, along with the explanations that try to clarify them, shows that many of our so-called merchants are just as clueless about the nature of money as they are careless, unfair, and unlucky in using it.

The statements of economical principle given in the text, though I know that most, if not all, of them are accepted by existing authorities on the science, are not supported by references, because I have never read any author on political economy, except Adam Smith, twenty years ago.[1] Whenever I have taken up any modern book upon this subject, I have usually found it encumbered with inquiries into accidental or minor commercial results, for the pursuit of which an ordinary reader could have no leisure, and, by the complication of which, it seemed to me, the authors themselves had been not unfrequently prevented from seeing to the root of the business.

The economic principles outlined in the text, although I know that most, if not all, of them are accepted by current experts in the field, don’t have references because I haven’t read any authors on political economy aside from Adam Smith twenty years ago.[1] Whenever I’ve picked up a modern book on this topic, I usually find it bogged down with questions about trivial or minor commercial effects, which an average reader wouldn’t have time for. This complexity often seems to prevent the authors themselves from getting to the heart of the matter.

Finally, if the reader should feel inclined to blame me for too sanguine a statement of future possibilities in political practice, let him consider how absurd it would have appeared in the days of Edward I. if the present state of social economy had been then predicted as necessary, or even described as possible. And I believe the advance from the days of Edward I. to our own, great as it is confessedly, consists, not so much in what we have actually accomplished, as in what we are now enabled to conceive.

Finally, if the reader feels like blaming me for being overly optimistic about future possibilities in political practice, they should think about how ridiculous it would have seemed back in the days of Edward I. if someone had predicted our current social economy as essential, or even just described it as a possibility. I believe the progress from the time of Edward I. to now, impressive as it is, lies not so much in what we've actually achieved, but in what we are now able to imagine.

FOOTNOTES:

[1] 1857.

1857.


THE POLITICAL ECONOMY OF ART.

LECTURE I.

Among the various characteristics of the age in which we live, as compared with other ages of this not yet very experienced world, one of the most notable appears to me to be the just and wholesome contempt in which we hold poverty. I repeat, the just and wholesome contempt; though I see that some of my hearers look surprised at the expression. I assure them, I use it in sincerity; and I should not have ventured to ask you to listen to me this evening, unless I had entertained a profound respect for wealth—true wealth, that is to say; for, of course, we ought to respect neither wealth nor anything else that is false of its kind: and the distinction between real and false wealth is one of the points on which I shall have a few words presently to say to you. But true wealth I hold, as I said, in great honour; and sympathize, for the most part, with that extraordinary feeling of the present age which publicly pays this honour to riches. I cannot, however, help noticing how extraordinary it is, and how this epoch of ours differs from all bygone epochs in having no philosophical nor religious worshippers of the ragged godship of poverty. In the classical ages, not only there were people who voluntarily lived in tubs, and who used gravely to maintain the superiority of tub-life to town-life, but the Greeks and Latins seem to have looked on these eccentric, and I do not scruple to say, absurd people, with as much respect as we do upon large capitalists and landed proprietors; so that really, in those days, no one could be described as purse proud, but only as empty-purse proud. And no less distinct than the honour which those curious Greek people pay to their conceited poor,[Pg 12] is the disrespectful manner in which they speak of the rich; so that one cannot listen long either to them, or to the Roman writers who imitated them, without finding oneself entangled in all sorts of plausible absurdities; hard upon being convinced of the uselessness of collecting that heavy yellow substance which we call gold, and led generally to doubt all the most established maxims of political economy. Nor are matters much better in the middle ages. For the Greeks and Romans contented themselves with mocking at rich people, and constructing merry dialogues between Charon and Diogenes or Menippus, in which the ferryman and the cynic rejoiced together as they saw kings and rich men coming down to the shore of Acheron, in lamenting and lamentable crowds, casting their crowns into the dark waters, and searching, sometimes in vain, for the last coin out of all their treasures that could ever be of use to them. But these Pagan views of the matter were indulgent, compared with those which were held in the middle ages, when wealth seems to have been looked upon by the best men not only as contemptible, but as criminal. The purse round the neck is, then, one of the principal signs of condemnation in the pictured Inferno; and the Spirit of Poverty is reverenced with subjection of heart, and faithfulness of affection, like that of a loyal knight for his lady, or a loyal subject for his queen. And truly, it requires some boldness to quit ourselves of these feelings, and to confess their partiality or their error, which, nevertheless, we are certainly bound to do. For wealth is simply one of the greatest powers which can be entrusted to human hands: a power, not indeed to be envied, because it seldom makes us happy; but still less to be abdicated or despised; while, in these days, and in this country, it has become a power all the more notable, in that the possessions of a rich man are not represented, as they used to be, by wedges of gold or coffers of jewels, but by masses of men variously employed, over whose bodies and minds the wealth, according to its direction, exercises harmful or helpful influence, and becomes, in that alternative, Mammon either of Unrighteousness or of Righteousness.

Among the various traits of our current age, compared to other times in this not yet very experienced world, one of the most remarkable, in my view, is the fair and healthy disdain we have for poverty. I repeat, the fair and healthy disdain; although I can see that some of you look taken aback by this phrase. I assure you, I mean it sincerely; and I wouldn’t have dared to ask you to listen to me tonight if I didn’t have a deep respect for wealth—true wealth, that is; because, of course, we should not respect either wealth or anything else that is false in its nature: and the difference between real and false wealth is one of the topics I'll touch on shortly. But I do hold true wealth in high regard and generally resonate with the incredible mindset of our time that publicly honors riches. However, I can’t help but point out how unusual it is, and how our era stands apart from all previous ones in that there are no philosophical or religious admirers of the ragged god of poverty. In classical times, there were people who chose to live in tubs, who seriously argued that living in a tub was superior to city life, and the Greeks and Romans seemed to view these eccentric, and I won’t hesitate to say, ridiculous individuals, with as much respect as we give to wealthy capitalists and landowners; so that back then, nobody was considered pompous for their wealth but rather for their lack of it. And just as clear as the honor that those curious Greeks showed their proud poor,[Pg 12] is the disrespectful way they spoke of the rich; so, you can’t listen too long to them, or to the Roman writers who copied them, without getting tangled up in various plausible absurdities; it’s hard not to be convinced of the futility of hoarding that heavy yellow stuff we call gold, leading one to doubt many well-established principles of political economy. The situation wasn’t much better in the Middle Ages. The Greeks and Romans merely mocked rich individuals and created humorous dialogues between Charon and Diogenes or Menippus, in which the ferryman and the cynic rejoiced together as they watched kings and wealthy men arriving at the shore of Acheron in sorrowful, pitiful crowds, throwing their crowns into the dark waters, searching—sometimes in vain—for the last coin from all their riches that could ever be of any use. But these pagan views were lenient compared to those held in the Middle Ages, when the best people viewed wealth as not only contemptible but also criminal. The purse around the neck is, thus, one of the main symbols of condemnation in the illustrated Inferno; and the Spirit of Poverty is revered with deep respect and loyal affection, like a loyal knight for his lady or a faithful subject for his queen. And indeed, it takes some courage to free ourselves from these feelings and acknowledge their bias or their error, which we certainly must do. Because wealth is simply one of the greatest powers that can be entrusted to human hands: a power, not to be envied, as it rarely brings happiness; but even less to be abandoned or scorned; while, in these times, and in this country, it has become a power even more striking, as the possessions of a wealthy person are no longer represented by bars of gold or chests of jewels, but by groups of people engaged in various activities, over whose bodies and minds the wealth, depending on its direction, exerts either harmful or beneficial influence, becoming, in that respect, either Mammon of Unrighteousness or of Righteousness.

Now, it seemed to me that since, in the name you have given to this great gathering of British pictures, you recognise them[Pg 13] as Treasures—that is, I suppose, as part and parcel of the real wealth of the country—you might not be uninterested in tracing certain commercial questions connected with this particular form of wealth. Most persons express themselves as surprised at its quantity; not having known before to what an extent good art had been accumulated in England: and it will, therefore, I should think, be held a worthy subject of consideration, what are the political interests involved in such accumulations; what kind of labour they represent, and how this labour may in general be applied and economized, so as to produce the richest results.

Now, it seems to me that since you call this great gathering of British artworks Treasures—meaning, I suppose, that you see them as an essential part of the country's true wealth—you might be interested in exploring some commercial questions related to this form of wealth. Many people are surprised by how much of it there is, not realizing how much good art has been gathered in England. Therefore, I think it would be worth considering what political interests are involved in such collections, what type of labor they represent, and how this labor can generally be applied and optimized to yield the greatest results.

Now, you must have patience with me, if in approaching the specialty of this subject, I dwell a little on certain points of general political science already known or established: for though thus, as I believe, established, some which I shall have occasion to rest arguments on are not yet by any means universally accepted; and therefore, though I will not lose time in any detailed defence of them, it is necessary that I should distinctly tell you in what form I receive, and wish to argue from them; and this the more, because there may perhaps be a part of my audience who have not interested themselves in political economy, as it bears on ordinary fields of labour, but may yet wish to hear in what way its principles can be applied to Art. I shall, therefore, take leave to trespass on your patience with a few elementary statements in the outset, and with, the expression of some general principles, here and there, in the course of our particular inquiry.

Now, please be patient with me as I discuss the specifics of this subject. I want to spend a little time on some points of political science that are already known or established. While I believe these points are established, some of the arguments I’ll use are not universally accepted yet. So, even though I won't spend much time defending them in detail, I need to clearly state how I understand and want to argue these ideas. This is especially important because some of you may not have focused on political economy as it relates to everyday work, but might be interested in how its principles can be applied to Art. Therefore, I ask for your patience as I start with a few basic statements and share some general principles throughout our discussion.

To begin, then, with one of these necessary truisms: all economy, whether of states, households, or individuals, may be defined to be the art of managing labour. The world is so regulated by the laws of Providence, that a man's labour, well applied, is always amply sufficient to provide him during his life with all things needful to him, and not only with those, but with many pleasant objects of luxury; and yet farther, to procure him large intervals of healthful rest and serviceable leisure. And a nation's labour, well applied, is in like manner, amply sufficient to provide its whole population with good food and comfortable habitation; and not with those only, but with good education besides, and objects of luxury, art treasures, [Pg 14] such as these you have around you now. But by those same laws of Nature and Providence, if the labour of the nation or of the individual be misapplied, and much more if it be insufficient,—if the nation or man be indolent and unwise,—suffering and want result, exactly in proportion to the indolence and improvidence,—to the refusal of labour, or to the misapplication of it. Wherever you see want, or misery, or degradation, in this world about you, there, be sure, either industry has been wanting, or industry has been in error. It is not accident, it is not Heaven-commanded calamity, it is not the original and inevitable evil of man's nature, which fill your streets with lamentation, and your graves with prey. It is only that, when there should have been providence, there has been waste; when there should have been labour, there has been lasciviousness; and, wilfulness, when there should have been subordination.[2]

To start with one of these necessary truths: all economies, whether of countries, households, or individuals, can be defined as the art of managing labor. The world is so structured by the laws of Providence that a person's labor, when used effectively, is always more than enough to provide him with everything he needs in life, along with many enjoyable luxuries; furthermore, it can give him significant time for healthy rest and valuable leisure. Similarly, a nation's labor, when effectively managed, is more than enough to ensure that its entire population has good food and comfortable housing; not only that, but it also provides good education and luxury items, art treasures, [Pg 14] like those you have around you now. However, according to the same laws of Nature and Providence, if the labor of an individual or the nation is misused, and even more so if it is inadequate—if a person or nation is lazy and unwise—suffering and need will follow, directly proportional to their laziness and lack of foresight—to the refusal to work or the misuse of it. Wherever you see poverty, misery, or decline in the world around you, you can be sure that either hard work is lacking or it has been misguided. It is not by chance, nor is it due to a divine calamity, nor is it the innate evil of human nature that fills your streets with cries of sorrow and your graves with victims. It is simply that where there should have been foresight, there has been waste; where there should have been labor, there has been indulgence; and where there should have been order, there has been rebellion.[2]

Now, we have warped the word "economy" in our English: language into a meaning which it has no business whatever to bear. In our use of it, it constantly signifies merely sparing or saving; economy of money means saving money—economy of time, sparing time, and so on. But that is a wholly barbarous use of the word—barbarous in a double sense, for it is not English, and it is bad Greek; barbarous in a treble sense, for it is not English, it is bad Greek, and it is worse sense. Economy no more means saving money than it means spending money. It means, the administration of a house; its stewardship; spending or saving, that is, whether money or time, or anything else, to the best possible advantage. In the simplest and clearest definition of it, economy, whether public or private, means the wise management of labour; and it means this mainly in three senses: namely, first, applying your labour rationally; secondly, preserving its produce carefully; lastly, distributing its produce seasonably.

Now, we have twisted the word "economy" in our English language into a meaning it shouldn't have. In our usage, it usually just means being frugal or saving. For example, "economy of money" means saving money, and "economy of time" means saving time, and so on. But that's a completely incorrect use of the word—incorrect in two ways, because it isn't proper English, and it's also poor Greek; incorrect in a third way, because it isn't English, it's poor Greek, and it's even less accurate. Economy doesn't mean saving money any more than it means spending money. It refers to managing a household; it's about stewardship—whether you’re spending or saving, whether it's money, time, or anything else, to achieve the best possible outcome. Simply put, economy, whether public or private, means the smart management of labor, and it primarily involves three things: first, applying your labor wisely; second, preserving its products carefully; and finally, distributing its products timely.

I say first, applying your labour rationally; that is, so as to obtain the most precious things you can, and the most lasting things, by it: not growing oats in land where you can grow wheat, nor putting fine embroidery on a stuff that will not [Pg 15] wear. Secondly, preserving its produce carefully; that is to say, laying up your wheat wisely in storehouses for the time of famine, and keeping your embroidery watchfully from the moth: and lastly, distributing its produce seasonably; that is to say, being able to carry your corn at once to the place where the people are hungry, and your embroideries to the places where they are gay, so fulfilling in all ways the Wise Man's description, whether of the queenly housewife or queenly nation. "She riseth while it is yet night, and giveth meat to her household, and a portion to her maidens. She maketh herself coverings of tapestry, her clothing is silk and purple. Strength and honour are in her clothing, and she shall rejoice in time to come."

First, I’m saying to use your efforts wisely; that means aiming to get the most valuable and lasting things from them: don’t grow oats in land that can produce wheat, and don’t spend time on fine embroidery with fabric that won’t hold up. Secondly, take care of what you produce; this means storing your wheat wisely in storage for famine times, and keeping your embroidery safe from moths. Lastly, distribute your products at the right times; this means being ready to take your grain to where people are hungry and your embroideries to joyful places, fulfilling in every respect the Wise Man's description of both a capable housewife and a strong nation. "She rises while it is still night and prepares food for her household and assigns tasks to her maidens. She creates coverings out of tapestry, her clothing is silk and purple. Strength and honor are her clothing, and she will rejoice in the future."

Now, you will observe that in this description of the perfect economist, or mistress of a household, there is a studied expression of the balanced division of her care between the two great objects of utility and splendour; in her right hand, food and flax, for life and clothing; in her left hand, the purple and the needlework, for honour and for beauty. All perfect housewifery or national economy is known by these two divisions; wherever either is wanting, the economy is imperfect. If the motive of pomp prevails, and the care of the national economist is directed only to the accumulation of gold, and of pictures, and of silk and marble, you know at once that the time must soon come when all these treasures shall be scattered and blasted in national ruin. If, on the contrary, the element of utility prevails, and the nation disdains to occupy itself in any wise with the arts of beauty or delight, not only a certain quantity of its energy calculated for exercise in those arts alone must be entirely wasted, which is bad economy, but also the passions connected with the utilities of property become morbidly strong, and a mean lust of accumulation merely for the sake of accumulation, or even of labour merely for the sake of labour, will banish at last the serenity and the morality of life, as completely, and perhaps more ignobly, than even the lavishness of pride and the lightness of pleasure. And similarly, and much more visibly, in private and household economy, you may judge always of its perfectness by its fair balance between the use and the pleasure of its possessions.[Pg 16] You will see the wise cottager's garden trimly divided between its well-set vegetables, and its fragrant flowers; you will see the good housewife taking pride in her pretty table-cloth, and her glittering shelves, no less than in her well-dressed dish, and her full storeroom; the care in her countenance will alternate with gaiety, and though you will reverence her in her seriousness, you will know her best by her smile.

Now, you'll notice that in this description of the ideal economist or homemaker, there's a deliberate focus on balancing her attention between the two main goals of practicality and beauty; in her right hand, food and fabric for sustenance and clothing; in her left hand, elegance and craftsmanship for dignity and aesthetics. The perfection of a household or national economy is evident in these two areas; if either one is missing, the economy is lacking. If the drive for showiness takes over, and the national economist focuses solely on amassing wealth, art, silk, and marble, it's clear that a downfall is imminent, and all these treasures will ultimately be lost in national disaster. On the other hand, if the emphasis is on utility, and the nation refuses to engage with the arts of beauty or enjoyment, not only is a portion of its energy directed solely towards those arts wasted— which is poor management— but the desires tied to property become excessively strong, leading to an unhealthy craving for accumulation just for the sake of it, or even working just for work's sake, which will ultimately destroy the peace and morality of life, perhaps even more shamefully than the excesses of arrogance and hedonism. Similarly, and much more visibly, in personal and household management, you can always judge its success by the right balance between the usefulness and enjoyment of its belongings.[Pg 16] You'll see the wise villager's garden neatly divided between well-planted vegetables and fragrant flowers; you'll see the diligent homemaker taking pride not only in her beautiful tablecloth and shining shelves but also in her well-prepared dishes and fully stocked pantry; her expression will shift between seriousness and joy, and while you will admire her solemnity, you will recognize her best by her smile.

Now, as you will have anticipated, I am going to address you, on this and our succeeding evening, chiefly on the subject of that economy which relates rather to the garden than the farm-yard. I shall ask you to consider with me the kind of laws by which we shall best distribute the beds of our national garden, and raise in it the sweetest succession of trees pleasant to the sight, and (in no forbidden sense) to be desired to make us wise. But, before proceeding to open this specialty of our subject, let me pause for a few moments to plead with you for the acceptance of that principle of government or authority which must be at the root of all economy, whether for use or for pleasure. I said, a few minutes ago, that a nation's labour, well applied, was amply sufficient to provide its whole population with good food, comfortable clothing, and pleasant luxury. But the good, instant, and constant application is everything. We must not, when our strong hands are thrown out of work, look wildly about for want of something to do with them. If ever we feel that want, it is a sign that all our household is out of order. Fancy a farmer's wife, to whom one or two of her servants should come at twelve o'clock at noon, crying that they had got nothing to do; that they did not know what to do next: and fancy still farther, the said farmer's wife looking hopelessly about her rooms and yard, they being all the while considerably in disorder, not knowing where to set the spare hand-maidens to work, and at last complaining bitterly that she had been obliged to give them their dinner for nothing. That's the type of the kind of political economy we practise too often in England. Would you not at once assert of such a mistress that she knew nothing of her duties? and would you not be certain, if the household were rightly managed, the mistress would be only too glad at any moment to have the help of any[Pg 17] number of spare hands; that she would know in an instant what to set them to;—in an instant what part of to-morrow's work might be most serviceably forwarded, what part of next month's work most wisely provided for, or what new task of some profitable kind undertaken? and when the evening came, and she dismissed her servants to their recreation or their rest, or gathered them to the reading round the work-table, under the eaves in the sunset, would you not be sure to find that none of them had been overtasked by her, just because none had been left idle; that everything had been accomplished because all had been employed; that the kindness of the mistress had aided her presence of mind, and the slight labour had been entrusted to the weak, and the formidable to the strong; and that as none had been dishonoured by inactivity so none had been broken by toil?

Now, as you might expect, I'm going to talk to you tonight and on the following evening mainly about that kind of economy that has more to do with gardening than with farming. I want you to think with me about the best way to arrange the beds of our national garden and to grow the most beautiful trees that not only look good but also can inspire wisdom in us. But before I dive into this specific topic, let me take a moment to emphasize the principle of governance or authority that must underpin all forms of economy, whether for utility or enjoyment. I mentioned earlier that the hard work of a nation, if applied well, is more than enough to provide its entire population with good food, comfortable clothing, and pleasant luxuries. But the key is applying ourselves well, consistently, and efficiently. When our capable hands find themselves without work, we shouldn't panic or scramble for something to do. If we ever feel that way, it indicates that our entire household is disorganized. Imagine a farmer's wife, whose employees come to her at noon, claiming they have nothing to do and don’t know what to tackle next. Now picture that same farmer's wife glancing around her messy home and yard, not knowing how to assign her extra helpers, and ultimately complaining she had to feed them without them doing any work. That’s a perfect example of the kind of political economy we often practice in England. Wouldn’t you immediately say such a mistress is clueless about her responsibilities? And wouldn’t you agree that if the household were properly managed, she would eagerly welcome any number of extra hands at any given time, and she would know right away what tasks to assign them—whether it’s figuring out what part of tomorrow’s work could use some help, planning ahead for next month, or starting a useful new project? And when evening comes, and she sends her employees off to relax or rest, or gathers them around the table to read by the eaves at sunset, wouldn’t you bet that none of them felt overworked because none had been left idle? Everything would have been done because everyone was engaged, and her kindness would have made her stay calm, delegating lighter tasks to those who needed it and tougher jobs to the capable. Since no one was shamed by doing nothing, no one was broken by too much work, either.

Now, the precise counterpart of such a household would be seen in a nation in which political economy was rightly understood. You complain of the difficulty of finding work for your men. Depend upon it, the real difficulty rather is to find men for your work. The serious question for you is not how many you have to feed, but how much you have to do; it is our inactivity, not our hunger, that ruins us: let us never fear that our servants should have a good appetite—our wealth is in their strength, not in their starvation. Look around this island of yours, and see what you have to do in it. The sea roars against your harbourless cliffs—you have to build the breakwater, and dig the port of refuge; the unclean pestilence ravins in your streets—you have to bring the full stream from the hills, and to send the free winds through the thoroughfare; the famine blanches your lips and eats away your flesh—you have to dig the moor and dry the marsh, to bid the morass give forth instead of engulphing, and to wring the honey and oil out of the rock. These things, and thousands such, we have to do, and shall have to do constantly, on this great farm of ours; for do not suppose that it is anything else than that. Precisely the same laws of economy which apply to the cultivation of a farm or an estate apply to the cultivation of a province or of an island. Whatever rebuke you would address to the improvident master of an[Pg 18] ill-managed patrimony, precisely that rebuke we should address to ourselves, so far as we leave our population in idleness and our country in disorder. What would you say to the lord of an estate who complained to you of his poverty and disabilities, and, when you pointed out to him that his land was half of it overrun with weeds, and that his fences were all in ruin, and that his cattle-sheds were roofless, and his labourers lying under the hedges faint for want of food, he answered to you that it would ruin him to weed his land or to roof his sheds—that those were too costly operations for him to undertake, and that he knew not how to feed his labourers nor pay them? Would you not instantly answer, that instead of ruining him to weed his fields, it would save him; that his inactivity was his destruction, and that to set his labourers to work was to feed them? Now, you may add acre to acre, and estate to estate, as far as you like, but you will never reach a compass of ground which shall escape from the authority of these simple laws. The principles which are right in the administration of a few fields, are right also in the administration of a great country from horizon to horizon: idleness does not cease to be ruinous because it is extensive, nor labour to be productive because it is universal.

Now, the perfect example of such a household would be seen in a nation where political economy is correctly understood. You complain about the difficulty of finding work for your men. Trust me, the real challenge is finding men for your work. The important question for you is not how many you have to feed, but how much you have to do; it's our inactivity, not our hunger, that brings us down: we should never worry about our workers having a good appetite—our wealth lies in their strength, not in their starvation. Look around your island and see what needs to be done. The sea crashes against your barren cliffs—you need to build the breakwater and dig the safe harbor; the filthy disease spreads through your streets—you need to channel the pure water from the hills and let the fresh winds blow through the roads; famine is turning your lips pale and eating away at your flesh—you need to drain the moor and dry the marsh, to make the swamp yield instead of swallowing, and extract honey and oil from the rocks. These tasks, and thousands more, we have to tackle and will need to tackle constantly on this great farm of ours; make no mistake, it is nothing else than that. The same economic laws that apply to managing a farm or an estate apply to managing a province or an island. Whatever criticism you would give to the careless owner of a poorly managed estate, we should apply that same critique to ourselves as long as we leave our population idle and our country in chaos. What would you say to the lord of an estate who complained to you about his poverty and struggles, and when you pointed out that half of his land was overrun with weeds, his fences were falling apart, his barns had no roofs, and his workers were lying under the hedges faint from hunger, he replied that fixing his land or roofing his barns would ruin him—that those were too expensive for him to handle, and that he didn't know how to feed or pay his workers? Wouldn't you immediately reply that instead of ruining him to weed his fields, it would actually save him; that his inactivity was his downfall and that hiring his workers was the way to support them? Now, you can add acre to acre and estate to estate as much as you want, but you will never find a piece of land that escapes these basic laws. The principles that are correct in managing a few fields are also correct in managing a vast country from horizon to horizon: idleness doesn't stop being destructive just because it’s widespread, nor does labor become productive just because it's universal.

Nay, but you reply, there is one vast difference between the nation's economy and the private man's: the farmer has full authority over his labourers; he can direct them to do what is needed to be done, whether they like it or not; and he can turn them away if they refuse to work, or impede others in their working, or are disobedient, or quarrelsome. There is this great difference; it is precisely this difference on which I wish to fix your attention, for it is precisely this difference which you have to do away with. We know the necessity of authority in farm, or in fleet, or in army; but we commonly refuse to admit it in the body of the nation. Let us consider this point a little.

No, but you might say, there’s a big difference between the economy of a nation and that of an individual: the farmer has complete control over his workers; he can instruct them to do what needs to be done, whether they want to or not; and he can let them go if they refuse to work, disrupt others from working, are insubordinate, or argumentative. There is this significant difference; it’s this very difference that I want you to focus on, because it's exactly this difference that you need to eliminate. We understand the need for authority in a farm, a fleet, or an army; yet we often refuse to recognize it in the nation as a whole. Let's think about this a bit.

In the various awkward and unfortunate efforts which the French have made at the development of a social system, they have at least stated one true principle, that of fraternity or brotherhood. Do not be alarmed; they got all wrong in their experiments, because they quite forgot that this fact[Pg 19] of fraternity implied another fact quite as important—that of paternity or fatherhood. That is to say, if they were to regard the nation as one family, the condition of unity in that family consisted no less in their having a head, or a father, than in their being faithful and affectionate members, or brothers. But we must not forget this, for we have long confessed it with our lips, though we refuse to confess it in our lives. For half an hour every Sunday we expect a man in a black gown, supposed to be telling us truth, to address us as brethren, though we should be shocked at the notion of any brotherhood existing among us out of church. And we can hardly read a few sentences on any political subject without running a chance of crossing the phrase "paternal government," though we should be utterly horror-struck at the idea of governments claiming anything like a father's authority over us. Now, I believe those two formal phrases are in both instances perfectly binding and accurate, and that the image of the farm and its servants which I have hitherto used, as expressing a wholesome national organization, fails only of doing so, not because it is too domestic, but because it is not domestic enough; because the real type of a well-organized nation must be presented, not by a farm cultivated by servants who wrought for hire, and might be turned away if they refused to labour, but by a farm in which the master was a father, and in which all the servants were sons; which implied, therefore, in all its regulations, not merely the order of expediency, but the bonds of affection and responsibilities of relationship; and in which all acts and services were not only to be sweetened by brotherly concord, but to be enforced by fatherly authority.[3]

In the various awkward and unfortunate attempts the French have made at developing a social system, they have at least identified one true principle: brotherhood. Don't be alarmed; they got everything wrong in their experiments because they completely ignored another crucial fact—that of fatherhood. In other words, if they were to see the nation as one family, the condition for unity in that family relied as much on having a leader, or a father, as it did on being loyal and caring members, or brothers. But we must remember this, for we have long acknowledged it verbally, even if we refuse to live by it. For half an hour every Sunday, we expect a man in a black robe, who is supposed to speak the truth, to address us as brothers, while we would be appalled at the idea of any sort of brotherhood existing among us outside of church. And we can hardly read a few sentences on any political issue without encountering the term "paternal government," yet we would be horrified at the thought of any government claiming a father’s authority over us. Now, I believe those two formal phrases are, in both cases, perfectly binding and accurate, and that the image of the farm and its laborers that I have used to describe a healthy national organization only fails to do so not because it is too domestic, but because it is not domestic enough; the real model of a well-structured nation must be portrayed not by a farm worked by hired hands who could be dismissed if they refused to labor, but by a farm where the master is a father and all the workers are sons; which implies, therefore, in all its regulations, not just the order of practicality, but the bonds of love and the responsibilities of family ties; and in which all actions and services are not only to be made sweet by brotherly harmony but also enforced by fatherly authority.[3]

Observe, I do not mean in the least that we ought to place such an authority in the hands of any one person, or of any class or body of persons. But I do mean to say that as an individual who conducts himself wisely must make laws for himself which at some time or other may appear irksome or injurious, but which, precisely at the time they appear most irksome, it is most necessary he should obey, so a nation which means to conduct itself wisely, must establish authority over [Pg 20] itself, vested either in kings, councils, or laws, which it must resolve to obey, even at times when the law or authority appears irksome to the body of the people, or injurious to certain masses of it. And this kind of national law has hitherto been only judicial; contented, that is, with an endeavour to prevent and punish violence and crime: but, as we advance in our social knowledge; we shall endeavour to make our government paternal as well as judicial; that is, to establish such laws and authorities as may at once direct us in our occupations, protect us against our follies, and visit us in our distresses: a government which shall repress dishonesty, as now it punishes theft; which shall show how the discipline of the masses may be brought to aid the toils of peace, as discipline of the masses has hitherto knit the sinews of battle; a government which shall have its soldiers of the ploughshare as well as its soldiers of the sword, and which shall distribute more proudly its golden crosses of industry—golden as the glow of the harvest, than now it grants its bronze crosses of honour—bronzed with the crimson of blood.

Look, I’m not saying we should give all the power to just one person, or to any specific group. What I am saying is that an individual who behaves wisely has to create rules for himself that might sometimes seem annoying or harmful. Yet, at the moments when these rules feel the most bothersome, it’s crucial to follow them. Similarly, a nation that aims to operate wisely needs to establish authority over itself, whether that’s through kings, councils, or laws, and it must commit to obeying that authority, even when it seems annoying or harmful to some of its people. Until now, this type of national law has been focused primarily on the judicial aspect, meaning it aimed mostly to prevent and punish violence and crime. However, as we grow in our understanding of society, we should strive to make our government both caring and judicial; that is, we need to create laws and authorities that guide us in our work, protect us from our mistakes, and assist us in our troubles. A government that will curb dishonesty, just as it currently punishes theft; that will demonstrate how the discipline of the masses can support peaceful efforts, just as it has in battle; a government that values its farmers alongside its soldiers, and that proudly grants golden awards for industry—golden like the harvest—rather than the current bronze medals of honor—tainted with blood.

I have not, of course, time to insist on the nature or details of government of this kind; only I wish to plead for your several and future consideration of this one truth, that the notion of Discipline and Interference lies at the very root of all human progress or power; that the "Let alone" principle is, in all things which man has to do with, the principle of death; that it is ruin to him, certain and total, if he lets his land alone—if he lets his fellow-men alone—if he lets his own soul alone. That his whole life, on the contrary, must, if it is healthy life, be continually one of ploughing and pruning, rebuking and helping, governing and punishing; and that therefore it is only in the concession of some great principle of restraint and interference in national action that he can ever hope to find the secret of protection against national degradation. I believe that the masses have a right to claim education from their government; but only so far as they acknowledge the duty of yielding obedience to their government. I believe they have a right to claim employment from their governours; but only so far as they yield to the governour the direction and discipline of their labour; and it is only so far as they grant to the [Pg 21] men whom they may set over them the father's authority to check the childishnesses of national fancy, and direct the waywardnesses of national energy, that they have a right to ask that none of their distresses should be unrelieved, none of their weaknesses unwatched; and that no grief, nor nakedness, nor peril should exist for them, against which the father's hand was not outstretched, or the father's shield uplifted.[4]

I don’t have time to dive into the nature or details of this kind of government; I just want to ask you to consider one important truth: the idea of Discipline and Interference is at the core of all human progress and power. The "Let alone" principle, in everything humans deal with, leads to decline; it’s devastating if you leave your land alone—if you leave your fellow humans alone—if you leave your own soul alone. Instead, if you want to live a healthy life, it should always involve effort—plowing and pruning, correcting and supporting, governing and punishing. It’s only by accepting a significant principle of restraint and interference in national actions that we can hope to protect ourselves from national decline. I believe that people have the right to demand education from their government, but only if they acknowledge the responsibility to obey their government. I believe they have the right to demand jobs from their leaders, but only if they allow those leaders to guide and manage their work. It’s only when they grant authority to those in charge to curb the childish whims of national imagination and guide the unpredictable energy of the nation that they can rightfully expect that none of their struggles should go unaddressed, none of their vulnerabilities unnoticed; and that no sorrow, shame, or danger should exist for them without the protective hand of leadership or the shield of support raised. [Pg 21]

Now, I have pressed this upon you at more length than is needful or proportioned to our present purposes of inquiry, because I would not for the first time speak to you on this subject of political economy without clearly stating what I believe to be its first grand principle. But its bearing on the matter in hand is chiefly to prevent you from at once too violently dissenting from me when what I may state to you as advisable economy in art appears to imply too much restraint or interference with the freedom of the patron or artist. We are a little apt, though, on the whole a prudent nation, to act too immediately on our impulses, even in matters merely commercial; much more in those involving continual appeals to our fancies. How far, therefore, the proposed systems or restraints may be advisable, it is for you to judge; only I pray you not to be offended with them merely because they are systems and restraints. Do you at all recollect that interesting passage of Carlyle, in which he compares, in this country and at this day, the understood and commercial value of man and horse; and in which he wonders that the [Pg 22] horse, with its inferior brains and its awkward hoofiness, instead of handiness, should be always worth so many tens or scores of pounds in the market, while the man, so far from always commanding his price in the market, would often be thought to confer a service on the community by simply killing himself out of their way? Well, Carlyle does not answer his own question, because he supposes we shall at once see the answer. The value of the horse consists simply in the fact of your being able to put a bridle on him. The value of the man consists precisely in the same thing. If you can bridle him, or which is better, if he can bridle himself, he will be a valuable creature directly. Otherwise, in a commercial point of view, his value is either nothing, or accidental only. Only, of course, the proper bridle of man is not a leathern one: what kind of texture it is rightly made of, we find from that command, "Be ye not as the horse or as the mule which have no understanding, whose mouths must be held in with bit and bridle." You are not to be without the reins, indeed, but they are to be of another kind; "I will guide thee with mine Eye." So the bridle of man is to be the Eye of God; and if he rejects that guidance, then the next best for him is the horse's and the mule's, which have no understanding; and if he rejects that, and takes the bit fairly in his teeth, then there is nothing left for him than the blood that comes out of the city, up to the horsebridles.

Now, I've elaborated on this more than necessary for our current discussion because I wanted to clearly express what I believe to be the fundamental principle of political economy. However, my aim is mainly to prevent you from disagreeing too strongly with me when I discuss what I consider sensible economic practices in art, which may seem to impose too much restriction or interference on the freedom of the patron or artist. Though we are generally a careful nation, we can sometimes act impulsively, even in purely commercial matters; this is even truer when it comes to issues that constantly appeal to our emotions. So, how advisable these proposed systems or restrictions are, is for you to decide; I just ask that you don’t dismiss them solely because they are systems and restrictions. Do you remember that fascinating passage by Carlyle, where he compares the understood commercial value of a man and a horse in this country today? He marvels at how the horse, with its inferior intelligence and clumsiness, consistently holds a market value of many tens or scores of pounds, while the man often struggles to command his worth and might even be seen as doing society a favor by simply removing himself from the equation. Carlyle doesn’t provide an answer to his own question because he assumes we’ll see it immediately. The horse's worth lies simply in the fact that you can control it with a bridle. The value of the man lies in the same ability. If you can control him, or, better yet, if he can control himself, he becomes valuable. Otherwise, from a commercial standpoint, his value is either nonexistent or only incidental. However, the appropriate control for a man isn’t a leather bridle: the right one is described by the command, "Be ye not as the horse or as the mule which have no understanding, whose mouths must be held in with bit and bridle." While you shouldn't be without reins, they should be of a different sort; "I will guide thee with mine Eye." Thus, the control for man is the Eye of God; if he refuses that guidance, then his best option is the constraints of the horse and mule, which lack understanding; if he rejects that too and takes the reins in his own hands, the only outcome left is the blood that flows from the city, up to the horsebridles.

Quitting, however, at last these general and serious laws of government—or rather bringing them down to our own business in hand—we have to consider three points of discipline in that particular branch of human labour which is concerned, not with procuring of food, but the expression of emotion; we have to consider respecting art: first, how to apply our labour to it; then, how to accumulate or preserve the results of labour; and then, how to distribute them. But since in art the labour which we have to employ is the labour of a particular class of men—men who have special genius for the business, we have not only to consider how to apply the labour, but first of all, how to produce the labourer; and thus the question in this particular case becomes fourfold: first, how to get your man of genius; then, how to employ your[Pg 23] man of genius; then, how to accumulate and preserve his work in the greatest quantity; and lastly, how to distribute his work to the best national advantage. Let us take up these questions in succession.

Quitting aside, when we look at the broader and fundamental rules of governance—and focus on our specific issue at hand—we need to think about three areas of discipline in that particular aspect of human effort that deals not with gathering food, but with expressing emotions; we need to think about art: first, how to apply our efforts to it; then, how to gather or preserve the results of that effort; and finally, how to share them. However, since in art the effort we need to employ comes from a specific group of people—individuals who have a unique talent for this work—we must not only think about how to apply the effort, but also, first and foremost, how to nurture the talent. Therefore, the question in this case becomes fourfold: first, how to find your talented individual; then, how to utilize your talented individual; next, how to gather and preserve their work in the largest quantity; and lastly, how to distribute their work for the greatest benefit to the nation. Let’s address these questions one by one.

 

I. Discovery.—How are we to get our men of genius: that is to say, by what means may we produce among us, at any given time, the greatest quantity of effective art-intellect? A wide question, you say, involving an account of all the best means of art education. Yes, but I do not mean to go into the consideration of those; I want only to state the few principles which lie at the foundation of the matter. Of these, the first is that you have always to find your artist, not to make him; you can't manufacture him, any more than you can manufacture gold. You can find him, and refine him: you dig him out as he lies nugget-fashion in the mountain-stream; you bring him home; and you make him into current coin, or household plate, but not one grain of him can you originally produce. A certain quantity of art-intellect is born annually in every nation, greater or less according to the nature and cultivation of the nation or race of men; but a perfectly fixed quantity annually, not increaseable by one grain. You may lose it, or you may gather it; you may let it lie loose in the ravine, and buried in the sands, or you may make kings' thrones of it, and overlay temple gates with it, as you choose: but the best you can do with it is always merely sifting, melting, hammering, purifying—never creating. And there is another thing notable about this artistical gold; not only is it limited in quantity, but in use. You need not make thrones or golden gates with it unless you like, but assuredly you can't do anything else with it. You can't make knives of it, nor armour, nor railroads. The gold won't cut you, and it won't carry you; put it to a mechanical use, and you destroy it at once. It is quite true that in the greatest artists, their proper artistical faculty is united with every other; and you may make use of the other faculties, and let the artistical one lie dormant. For aught I know, there may be two or three Leonardo da Vincis employed at[Pg 24] this moment in your harbours and railroads: but you are not employing their Leonardesque or golden faculty there, you are only oppressing and destroying it. And the artistical gift in average men is not joined with others; your born painter, if you don't make a painter of him, won't be a first-rate merchant, or lawyer; at all events, whatever he turns out, his own special gift is unemployed by you; and in no wise helps him in that other business. So here you have a certain quantity of a particular sort of intelligence, produced for you annually by providential laws, which you can only make use of by setting it to its own proper work, and which any attempt to use otherwise involves the dead loss of so much human energy. Well, then, supposing we wish to employ it, how is it to be best discovered and refined? It is easily enough discovered. To wish to employ it is to discover it. All that you need is, a school of trial[5] in every important town, in which those idle farmers' lads whom their masters never can keep out of mischief, and those stupid tailors' 'prentices who are always stitching the sleeves in wrong way upwards, may have a try at this other trade; only this school of trial must not be entirely regulated by formal laws of art education, but must ultimately be the workshop of a good master painter, who will try the lads with one kind of art and another, till he finds out what they are fit for. Next, after your trial school, you want your easy and secure employment, which is the matter of chief importance. For, even on the present system, the boys who have really intense art capacity, generally make painters of themselves; but then, the best half of their early energy is lost in the battle of life. Before a good painter can get employment, his mind has always been embittered, and his genius distorted. A common mind usually stoops, in plastic chill, to whatever is asked of it, and scrapes or daubs its way complacently into public favour.[6] But your great men quarrel with you, and you revenge yourselves by starving them for the first half of their lives. Precisely in the degree in which any painter possesses original genius, is at present the increase of moral certainty that during his early years he will [Pg 25] have a hard battle to fight; and that just at the time when his conceptions ought to be full and happy, his temper gentle, and his hopes enthusiastic—just at that most critical period, his heart is full of anxieties and household cares; he is chilled by disappointments, and vexed by injustice; he becomes obstinate in his errors, no less than in his virtues, and the arrows of his aims are blunted, as the reeds of his trust are broken.

I. Discovery.—How do we get our creative people? In other words, what strategies can we employ to bring forth the greatest amount of artistic talent at any given time? You might say that's a big question that requires a look at all the best methods for art education. Sure, but I'm not going to dive into that; I just want to outline a few key principles that form the foundation. The first principle is that you always need to discover your artist, not create them; you can’t manufacture them, just like you can’t manufacture gold. You find them, refine them: you uncover them like nuggets in a mountain stream, bring them home, and turn them into currency or fine silverware, but you can’t produce even a grain of their essence. Each country sees a certain amount of artistic talent born each year, more or less depending on the nature and development of the people; but it's always a fixed amount—never increasing by even a grain. You might lose it, or you could gather it; you might let it sit idle in a ravine, buried in sand, or you could use it to craft royal thrones or adorn temple gates as you wish: but the best you can ever do with it is sift, melt, hammer, and purify—never create. Another noteworthy aspect of this artistic gold is that not only is it limited in quantity, but also in application. You don't have to use it for thrones or golden gates, but you can’t use it for anything else. You can’t turn it into knives, armor, or railroads. The gold won’t cut, and it won’t carry; if you try to make it mechanical, you immediately destroy it. It's true that the greatest artists combine their artistic talent with other skills, and you can utilize those other skills while neglecting their artistic ones. There might be a couple of Leonardo da Vincis right now working in your harbors and railroads, but you’re not using their artistic talents; you’re actually smothering and wasting them. The artistic flair in ordinary people usually isn't paired with other skills; if you don't cultivate your natural painter, he won’t become an exceptional merchant or lawyer; regardless of what he becomes, his unique talent goes unused by you and doesn’t help him in a different field. So, you have a specific amount of unique intelligence produced for you annually by natural laws, which you can only utilize by putting it to its rightful work, and any attempt to apply it otherwise results in the waste of human potential. Now, if we want to harness it, how can we best discover and refine it? Discovering it is fairly simple. The desire to utilize it is what reveals it. All you need is a trial school in every significant town, where those idle farm boys who can’t stay out of trouble and those clumsy tailoring apprentices who always stitch sleeves the wrong way can try their hand at this different craft; but this trial school shouldn't be strictly formalized with rigid art education laws; it should ultimately serve as a workshop run by a skilled master painter, who will assess the boys' abilities across various arts until he finds where their strengths lie. After your trial school, you need straightforward and secure employment, which is incredibly important. Because even under the current system, boys with real artistic ability usually end up becoming painters on their own; but, unfortunately, much of their early energy is wasted in the struggles of life. Before a good painter finds work, he often feels embittered, and his talent is twisted. A typical person usually compromises, following whatever is demanded of them, and clumsily finds their way into public acceptance. But your great artists clash with you, and in response, you starve them in the first half of their lives. The more original genius a painter possesses, the more likely it is that during their early years, they will face significant challenges; just when their ideas should be flourishing and joyful, their spirit gentle, and their aspirations high—during this critical time, they are often burdened with worries and household responsibilities; they become disheartened by failures and frustrated by unfair treatment; they become stubborn in their flaws, just as much as in their virtues, and their aims are dulled, as their trust is shattered.

What we mainly want, therefore, is a means of sufficient and unagitated employment: not holding out great prizes for which young painters are to scramble; but furnishing all with adequate support, and opportunity to display such power as they possess without rejection or mortification. I need not say that the best field of labour of this kind would be presented by the constant progress of public works involving various decoration; and we will presently examine what kind of public works may thus, advantageously for the nation, be in constant progress. But a more important matter even than this of steady employment, is the kind of criticism with which you, the public, receive the works of the young men submitted to you. You may do much harm by indiscreet praise and by indiscreet blame; but remember, the chief harm is always done by blame. It stands to reason that a young man's work cannot be perfect. It must be more or less ignorant; it must be more or less feeble; it is likely that it may be more or less experimental, and if experimental, here and there mistaken. If, therefore, you allow yourself to launch out into sudden barking at the first faults you see, the probability is that you are abusing the youth for some defect naturally and inevitably belonging to that stage of his progress; and that you might just as rationally find fault with a child for not being as prudent as a privy councillor, or with a kitten for not being as grave as a cat. But there is one fault which you may be quite sure is unnecessary, and therefore a real and blameable fault: that is haste, involving negligence. Whenever you see that a young man's work is either bold or slovenly, then you may attack it firmly; sure of being right. If his work is bold, it is insolent; repress his insolence: if it is slovenly, it is indolent; spur his indolence. So long as he works in that dashing or impetuous way, the[Pg 26] best hope for him is in your contempt: and it is only by the fact of his seeming not to seek your approbation that you may conjecture he deserves it.

What we really want is a way to provide consistent and calm employment: not to dangle huge prizes that young painters will fight over, but to give everyone enough support and a chance to showcase their abilities without being rejected or humiliated. The ideal situation would be ongoing public works that involve various decorations, and we will soon look at what types of public projects could be beneficial for the nation in a constant state of development. However, even more crucial than steady employment is the type of feedback you, the public, give to the works created by these young artists. You can cause a lot of harm with thoughtless praise or criticism; remember, the greater damage is usually done by criticism. It's obvious that a young artist's work can't be flawless. It *has* to be somewhat naïve; it has to be somewhat weak; it’s likely to be somewhat experimental, and if it’s experimental, it may contain errors now and then. So, if you jump to criticize the first mistakes you see, you might just be scolding the young artist for flaws that are natural and inevitable at that point in their development, just like it wouldn’t make sense to criticize a child for not being as savvy as an experienced advisor or to blame a kitten for not being as serious as a cat. However, there is one fault that you can be sure is unnecessary and thus a legitimate reason for criticism: that is rushing, which leads to carelessness. Whenever you notice that a young artist’s work is either bold or careless, you can critique it confidently, knowing you’re right. If their work is bold, it’s arrogant; you should curb their arrogance. If it's careless, it's lazy; you should motivate their laziness. As long as they continue to work in that reckless or rash manner, the[Pg 26] best thing you can do for them is to look down on them; and you can only assume they deserve your approval by the fact that they don’t seem to be seeking it.

But if he does deserve it, be sure that you give it him, else you not only run a chance of driving him from the right road by want of encouragement, but you deprive yourselves of the happiest privilege you will ever have of rewarding his labour. For it is only the young who can receive much reward from men's praise: the old, when they are great, get too far beyond and above you to care what you think of them. You may urge them then with sympathy, and surround them then with acclamation; but they will doubt your pleasure, and despise your praise. You might have cheered them in their race through the asphodel meadows of their youth; you might have brought the proud, bright scarlet into their faces, if you had but cried once to them "Well done," as they dashed up to the first goal of their early ambition. But now, their pleasure is in memory, and their ambition is in heaven. They can be kind to you, but you never more can be kind to them. You may be fed with the fruit and fullness of their old age, but you were as the nipping blight to them in their blossoming, and your praise is only as the warm winds of autumn to the dying branches.

But if he really deserves it, make sure you give it to him; otherwise, you not only risk pushing him away from the right path by not encouraging him, but you also miss out on the greatest opportunity you’ll ever have to reward his hard work. It’s only the young who can truly benefit from praise: when older people achieve greatness, they get too far ahead and above you to care about your opinion. You might try to support them with sympathy and surround them with applause, but they will doubt your sincerity and dismiss your praise. You could have cheered them on during their youthful journey through the fields of their dreams; you could have brought the vibrant red flush to their cheeks if you had just shouted once, "Well done," as they raced toward their early goals. But now, their joy lies in memories, and their ambitions are in another realm. They can show you kindness, but you can’t be kind to them anymore. You may enjoy the rewards of their old age, but you were like a harsh frost to them during their blooming, and your praise is nothing more than the warm autumn winds to dying branches.

There is one thought still, the saddest of all, bearing on this withholding of early help. It is possible, in some noble natures, that the warmth and the affections of childhood may remain unchilled, though unanswered; and that the old man's heart may still be capable of gladness, when the long-withheld sympathy is given at last. But in these noble natures it nearly always happens, that the chief motive of earthly ambition has not been to give delight to themselves, but to their parents. Every noble youth looks back, as to the chiefest joy which this world's honour ever gave him, to the moment when first he saw his father's eyes flash with pride, and his mother turn away her head lest he should take her tears for tears of sorrow. Even the lover's joy, when some worthiness of his is acknowledged before his mistress, is not so great as that, for it is not so pure—the desire to exalt himself in her eyes mixes with that of giving her delight; but he does not[Pg 27] need to exalt himself in his parents' eyes: it is with the pure hope of giving them pleasure that he comes to tell them what he has done, or what has been said of him; and therefore he has a purer pleasure of his own. And this purest and best of rewards you keep from him if you can: you feed him in his tender youth with ashes and dishonour; and then you come to him, obsequious, but too late, with your sharp laurel crown, the dew all dried from off its leaves; and you thrust it into his languid hand, and he looks at you wistfully. What shall he do with it? What can he do, but go and lay it on his mother's grave?

There’s one thought that stands out, the saddest of all, about holding back early support. It’s possible that in some noble souls, the warmth and affection of childhood might stay uncooled, even if they go unanswered; and that an old man’s heart can still find joy when the long-awaited understanding finally comes. But with these noble souls, it often turns out that their main motivation in life isn’t to bring themselves happiness, but to bring joy to their parents. Every noble young person looks back at the greatest joy this world’s recognition has ever offered them—the moment they first saw their father’s eyes light up with pride and their mother turn her head away to hide her tears, which were not of sorrow. Even the happiness a lover feels when his worth is recognized by his partner doesn’t compare, because it’s not as pure—the wish to impress her mingles with the desire to make her happy; but he doesn’t need to impress his parents—he comes to share what he’s accomplished, or what others have said about him, purely hoping to bring them happiness. This is why he experiences a more genuine joy. And this purest and greatest reward is what you deny him if you can: you nourish him in his tender youth with emptiness and shame; then you come to him, fawning but too late, with a sharp laurel crown, its dew long gone; and you push it into his weak hand, and he looks at you with longing. What can he do with it? What can he do except lay it on his mother’s grave?

Thus, then, you see that you have to provide for your young men: first, the searching or discovering school; then the calm employment; then the justice of praise: one thing more you have to do for them in preparing them for full service—namely, to make, in the noble sense of the word, gentlemen of them; that is to say, to take care that their minds receive such training, that in all they paint they shall see and feel the noblest things. I am sorry to say, that of all parts of an artist's education this is the most neglected among us; and that even where the natural taste and feeling of the youth have been pure and true, where there was the right stuff in him to make a gentleman of, you may too frequently discern some jarring rents in his mind, and elements of degradation in his treatment of subject, owing to want of gentle training, and of the liberal influence of literature. This is quite visible in our greatest artists, even in men like Turner and Gainsborough; while in the common grade of our second-rate painters the evil attains a pitch which is far too sadly manifest to need my dwelling upon it. Now, no branch of art economy is more important than that of making the intellect at your disposal pure as well as powerful; so that it may always gather for you the sweetest and fairest things. The same quantity of labour from the same man's hand, will, according as you have trained him, produce a lovely and useful work, or a base and hurtful one, and depend upon it, whatever value it may possess, by reason of the painter's skill, its chief and final value, to any nation, depends upon its being able to exalt and refine, as well as to please; and that[Pg 28] the picture which most truly deserves the name of an art-treasure, is that which has been painted by a good man.

So, you see, you need to prepare your young men like this: first, have them explore and discover their passions; next, help them find calm and fulfilling work; then, ensure they receive fair recognition for their efforts. One more important thing you must do to get them ready for full service is to help them become gentlemen in the noble sense of the word. This means making sure they’re trained to see and feel the most admirable things in everything they create. Unfortunately, I have to say that this part of an artist's education is the most overlooked among us. Even when a young person has a natural talent and sensitivity, and there’s potential to shape him into a gentleman, you can often notice some jarring flaws in his mindset and signs of decline in how he treats his subjects due to a lack of gentle upbringing and the enriching influence of literature. This is clearly evident even in our greatest artists, like Turner and Gainsborough; meanwhile, among the average second-rate painters, the issue is so glaring that it hardly needs further explanation. Now, no aspect of art education is more crucial than ensuring that the intellect you cultivate is both pure and powerful, so it can always gather the most beautiful and inspiring things. The same amount of effort from the same person can produce either a beautiful and beneficial piece of work or a mediocre and harmful one, and believe me, regardless of the technical skill involved, its main and ultimate value to any society rests on its ability to uplift, refine, and please. The painting that truly deserves the title of an art treasure is the one created by a good person.

You cannot but see how far this would lead, if I were to enlarge upon it. I must take it up as a separate subject some other time: only noticing at present that no money could be better spent by a nation than in providing a liberal and disciplined education for its painters, as they advance into the critical period of their youth; and that also, a large part of their power during life depends upon the kind of subjects which you, the public, ask them for, and therefore the kind of thoughts with which you require them to be habitually familiar. I shall have more to say on this head when we come to consider what employment they should have in public buildings.

You can see how far this could go if I keep talking about it. I'll have to discuss it as a separate topic another time: for now, I just want to point out that no money is better invested by a nation than in providing a good and structured education for its artists as they reach their formative years. Furthermore, a significant part of their success throughout life relies on the types of subjects you, the public, request from them, which affects the kind of ideas they become familiar with. I'll share more on this when we talk about their roles in public buildings.

There are many other points of nearly as much importance as these, to be explained with reference to the development of genius; but I should have to ask you to come and hear six lectures instead of two if I were to go into their detail. For instance, I have not spoken of the way in which you ought to look for those artificers in various manual trades, who, without possessing the order of genius which you would desire to devote to higher purposes, yet possess wit, and humour, and sense of colour, and fancy for form—all commercially valuable as quantities of intellect, and all more or less expressible in the lower arts of ironwork, pottery, decorative sculpture, and such like. But these details, interesting as they are, I must commend to your own consideration, or leave for some future inquiry. I want just now only to set the bearings of the entire subject broadly before you, with enough of detailed illustration to make it intelligible; and therefore I must quit the first head of it here, and pass to the second, namely, how best to employ the genius we discover. A certain quantity of able hands and heads being placed at our disposal, what shall we most advisably set them upon?

There are many other points nearly as important as these that need to be explained regarding the development of genius; however, I'd have to ask you to attend six lectures instead of two if I were to go into detail about them. For example, I haven't discussed how to find skilled workers in various trades who, even if they lack the genius you wish to focus on for higher purposes, still have wit, humor, a sense of color, and an eye for form—all of which are commercially valuable aspects of intelligence and can be expressed in the lower arts like ironwork, pottery, decorative sculpture, and so on. But these details, as interesting as they are, I must leave for your own reflection or for future discussion. Right now, I just want to give you a broad overview of the entire topic, with enough detailed examples to make it clear; therefore, I will wrap up this first point and move on to the second, which is how best to utilize the genius we discover. Given a certain number of skilled hands and minds at our disposal, what should we ideally have them work on?

 

II. Application.—There are three main points the economist has to attend to in this.

II. App.—There are three main points that the economist needs to focus on in this.

First, To set his men to various work.[Pg 29]

First, to assign his men to different tasks.[Pg 29]

Secondly, To easy work.

Secondly, make work easier.

Thirdly, To lasting work.

Thirdly, to enduring work.

I shall briefly touch on the first two, for I want to arrest your attention on the last.

I’ll briefly discuss the first two because I want to focus your attention on the last one.

I say first, to various work. Supposing you have two men of equal power as landscape painters—and both of them have an hour at your disposal. You would not set them both to paint the same piece of landscape. You would, of course, rather have two subjects than a repetition of one.

I’ll start by talking about different tasks. Let’s say you have two equally skilled landscape painters, and they both have an hour to work. You wouldn’t have them paint the same landscape. Naturally, you would prefer to have two different scenes instead of just a duplicate of one.

Well, supposing them sculptors, will not the same rule hold? You naturally conclude at once that it will; but you will have hard work to convince your modern architects of that. They will put twenty men to work, to carve twenty capitals; and all shall be the same. If I could show you the architects' yards in England just now, all open at once, perhaps you might see a thousand clever men, all employed in carving the same design. Of the degradation and deathfulness to the art-intellect of the country involved in such a habit, I have more or less been led to speak before now; but I have not hitherto marked its definite tendency to increase the price of work, as such. When men are employed continually in carving the same ornaments, they get into a monotonous and methodical habit of labour—precisely correspondent to that in which they would break stones, or paint house-walls. Of course, what they do so constantly, they do easily; and if you excite them temporarily by an increase of wages, you may get much work done by them in a little time. But, unless so stimulated, men condemned to a monotonous exertion, work—and always, by the laws of human nature, must work—only at a tranquil rate, not producing by any means a maximum result in a given time. But if you allow them to vary their designs, and thus interest their heads and hearts in what they are doing, you will find them become eager, first, to get their ideas expressed, and then to finish the expression of them; and the moral energy thus brought to bear on the matter quickens, and therefore cheapens, the production in a most important degree. Sir Thomas Deane, the architect of the new Museum at Oxford, told me, as I passed through Oxford[Pg 30] on my way here, that he found that, owing to this cause alone, capitals of various design could be executed cheaper than capitals of similar design (the amount of hand labour in each being the same) by about 30 per cent.

Well, if we consider the sculptors, won't the same principle apply? You probably think it will, but convincing modern architects of that is tougher. They will assign twenty workers to carve twenty identical capitals, and all the designs will look the same. If I could show you the architects' yards in England right now, you might see a thousand skilled workers all carving the same design. I've talked about how this practice degrades and stifles the art and intellect of the country before, but I haven't highlighted its clear tendency to drive up the cost of work as such. When people spend their time carving the same ornaments, they fall into a monotonous routine—similar to breaking stones or painting house-walls. Naturally, they become good at what they do frequently, and a temporary increase in pay might motivate them to accomplish lots of work quickly. However, without that extra motivation, people stuck doing repetitive tasks will work— and it’s human nature that they must work—only at a steady pace, not producing a maximum output in a given time. But if you let them change their designs and engage their minds and hearts in their work, they’ll become eager to articulate their ideas and finish their projects, and the enthusiasm they bring to the task significantly speeds up and lowers the cost of production. Sir Thomas Deane, the architect of the new Museum at Oxford, told me, as I passed through Oxford[Pg 30] on my way here, that he found capitals of various designs could be created cheaper than identical ones by about 30 percent, due to this very reason, even though the amount of manual labor was the same in each case.

Well, that is the first way, then, in which you will employ your intellect well; and the simple observance of this plain rule of political economy will effect a noble revolution in your architecture, such as you cannot at present so much as conceive. Then the second way in which we are to guard against waste is by setting our men to the easiest, and therefore the quickest, work which will answer the purpose. Marble, for instance, lasts quite as long as granite, and is much softer to work; therefore, when you get hold of a good sculptor, give him marble to carve—not granite. That, you say, is obvious enough. Yes; but it is not so obvious how much of your workmen's time you waste annually in making them cut glass, after it has got hard, when you ought to make them mould it while it is soft. It is not so obvious how much expense you waste in cutting diamonds and rubies, which are the hardest things you can find, into shapes that mean nothing, when the same men might be cutting sandstone and freestone into shapes that meant something. It is not so obvious how much of the artists' time in Italy you waste, by forcing them to make wretched little pictures for you out of crumbs of stone glued together at enormous cost, when the tenth of the time would make good and noble pictures for you out of water-colour. I could go on giving you almost numberless instances of this great commercial mistake; but I should only weary and confuse you. I therefore commend also this head of our subject to your own meditation, and proceed to the last I named—the last I shall task your patience with to-night. You know we are now considering how to apply our genius; and we were to do it as economists, in three ways:—

Well, that's the first way you'll use your intellect effectively; simply following this straightforward rule of economics will create an amazing transformation in your architecture, something you can't even imagine right now. The second way to prevent waste is by assigning your workers the easiest, and therefore quickest, tasks that will still get the job done. For example, marble lasts just as long as granite and is much easier to work with; so when you have a skilled sculptor, give him marble to carve—not granite. That seems obvious, right? Yes, but what's less obvious is how much time you waste each year making your workers cut glass once it’s hardened, when they should be molding it while it's still soft. It’s also not obvious how much money you waste cutting diamonds and rubies, which are the hardest materials available, into nonsensical shapes when those same workers could be shaping sandstone and freestone into meaningful designs. And it’s not obvious how much of the artists' time in Italy you squander by forcing them to create tiny, terrible pictures from expensive bits of stone, when in just a fraction of the time they could produce beautiful pictures using watercolors. I could give you countless examples of this significant commercial error; but that would only tire and confuse you. So, I encourage you to reflect on this aspect, and I’ll move on to the last point I mentioned—the last one I’ll ask you to bear with me on tonight. You know we’re currently looking at how to apply our creativity; and we're going to do that as economists, in three ways:—

To various work;

To different work;

To easy work;

To do easy work;

To lasting work.

To enduring work.

This lasting of the work, then, is our final question.

This durability of the work, then, is our final question.

Many of you may, perhaps, remember that Michael Angelo was once commanded by Pietro di Medici to mould a statue[Pg 31] out of snow, and that he obeyed the command.[7] I am glad, and we have all reason to be glad, that such a fancy ever came into the mind of the unworthy prince, and for this cause: that Pietro di Medici then gave, at the period of one great epoch of consummate power in the arts, the perfect, accurate; and intensest possible type of the greatest error which nations and princes can commit, respecting the power of genius entrusted to their guidance. You had there, observe, the strongest genius in the most perfect obedience; capable of iron independence, yet wholly submissive to the patron's will; at once the most highly accomplished and the most original, capable of doing as much as man could do, in any direction that man could ask. And its governour, and guide, and patron sets it to build a statue in snow—to put itself into the service of annihilation—to make a cloud of itself, and pass away from the earth.

Many of you might remember that Michael Angelo was once ordered by Pietro di Medici to shape a statue[Pg 31] out of snow, and he followed the order.[7] I'm glad, and we all should be glad, that such a whim entered the mind of the unworthy prince, and for this reason: that Pietro di Medici, at a time of significant achievement in the arts, presented the perfect and most intense example of the greatest mistake that nations and leaders can make regarding the power of genius entrusted to them. Notice that you had the strongest genius in complete obedience; capable of absolute independence, yet entirely submissive to the patron's wishes; at once highly skilled and uniquely original, able to accomplish as much as anyone could request in any direction. And its ruler, guide, and patron commands it to create a statue out of snow—to render itself into nothingness—to turn into a cloud and vanish from the earth.

Now this, so precisely and completely done by Pietro di Medici, is what we are all doing, exactly in the degree in which we direct the genius under our patronage to work in more or less perishable materials. So far as we induce painters to work in fading colours, or architects to build with imperfect structure, or in any other way consult only immediate ease and cheapness in the production of what we want, to the exclusion of provident thought as to its permanence and serviceableness in after ages; so far we are forcing our Michael Angelos to carve in snow. The first duty of the economist in art is, to see that no intellect shall thus glitter merely in the manner of hoar-frost; but that it shall be well vitrified, like a painted window, and shall be set so between shafts of stone and bands of iron, that it shall bear the sunshine upon it, and send the sunshine through it, from generation to generation.

Now what Pietro di Medici did so precisely and thoroughly is what we’re all doing, depending on how we guide the talent we support to work with materials that may not last. When we encourage painters to use fading colors, or architects to build with subpar structures, or if we prioritize ease and low cost over thoughtful consideration for how lasting and useful these works will be in the future, we’re effectively making our Michael Angelos carve in snow. The primary responsibility of those in art and economics is to ensure that no talent merely sparkles like frost but is instead properly vitrified, like a stained glass window, and is positioned between stone pillars and iron bands, allowing it to shine in the sunlight and pass that light through for generations to come.

I can conceive, however, some political economist to interrupt me here, and say, "If you make your art wear too well, you will soon have too much of it; you will throw your artists quite out of work. Better allow for a little wholesome evanescence—beneficent destruction: let each age provide art for itself, or we shall soon have so many good pictures that we shall not know what to do with them."

I can imagine a political economist interrupting me here, saying, "If you make your art last too long, you’ll end up with too much of it; you’ll push your artists out of work. It’s better to allow for a little harmless fade—beneficial destruction: let each era create its own art, or we’ll soon have so many great pieces that we won’t know what to do with them."

[Pg 32] Remember, my dear hearers, who are thus thinking, that political economy, like every other subject, cannot be dealt with effectively if we try to solve two questions at a time instead of one. It is one question, how to get plenty of a thing; and another, whether plenty of it will be good for us. Consider these two matters separately; never confuse yourself by interweaving one with the other. It is one question, how to treat your fields so as to get a good harvest; another, whether you wish to have a good harvest, or would rather like to keep up the price of corn. It is one question, how to graft your trees so as to grow most apples; and quite another, whether having such a heap of apples in the store-room will not make them all rot.

[Pg 32] Remember, my dear listeners, as you're thinking about this, that political economy, like any other topic, can’t be tackled effectively if we try to solve two questions at once instead of one. One question is how to produce an abundance of something; the other is whether having a lot of it will be beneficial for us. Think about these two issues separately; don’t mix them up. One question is how to manage your fields to yield a good harvest; another is whether you actually want a good harvest or would prefer to keep corn prices high. One question is how to graft your trees to grow the most apples; and quite another is whether having a surplus of apples in storage will lead to them all rotting.

Now, therefore, that we are talking only about grafting and growing, pray do not vex yourselves with thinking what you are to do with the pippins. It may be desirable for us to have much art, or little—we will examine that by and by; but just now, let us keep to the simple consideration how to get plenty of good art if we want it. Perhaps it might be just as well that a man of moderate income should be able to possess a good picture, as that any work of real merit should cost £500 or £1,000; at all events, it is certainly one of the branches of political economy to ascertain how, if we like, we can get things in quantities—plenty of corn, plenty of wine, plenty of gold, or plenty of pictures.

Now, since we're only discussing grafting and growing, please don't get upset thinking about what to do with the pippins. It might be nice for us to have a lot of skill or just a little—we'll look into that later; but for now, let's focus on the straightforward idea of how to get a lot of good art if we want it. Maybe it would be just as reasonable for someone with a moderate income to own a good piece of art as it is for any work of real value to cost £500 or £1,000; at any rate, it’s definitely part of political economy to figure out how we can obtain things in large amounts—lots of grain, lots of wine, lots of gold, or lots of art.

It has just been said, that the first great secret is to produce work that will last. Now, the conditions of work lasting are twofold: it must not only be in materials that will last, but it must be itself of a quality that will last—it must be good enough to bear the test of time. If it is not good, we shall tire of it quickly, and throw it aside—we shall have no pleasure in the accumulation of it. So that the first question of a good art-economist respecting any work is, Will it lose its flavour by keeping? It may be very amusing now, and look much like a work of genius. But what will be its value a hundred years hence?

It has just been said that the first big secret is to create work that will endure. Now, the conditions for work to last are twofold: it must not only be made from materials that are durable, but it must also be of a quality that endures—it must be good enough to withstand the test of time. If it's not good, we will quickly tire of it and cast it aside—we won’t take pleasure in accumulating it. So, the first question a good art economist should ask about any piece is, Will it lose its appeal over time? It might be very entertaining now and seem like a work of genius. But what will its value be a hundred years from now?

You cannot always ascertain this. You may get what you fancy to be work of the best quality, and yet find to your astonishment that it won't keep. But of one thing you may[Pg 33] be sure, that art which is produced hastily will also perish hastily; and that what is cheapest to you now, is likely to be dearest in the end.

You can’t always tell this. You might think you have something of the best quality, but then be surprised when it doesn’t last. However, one thing is certain: art that is made quickly will also fade quickly; and what seems cheapest to you now is likely to cost you the most in the long run.

I am sorry to say, the great tendency of this age is to expend its genius in perishable art of this kind, as if it were a triumph to burn its thoughts away in bonfires. There is a vast quantity of intellect and of labour consumed annually in our cheap illustrated publications; you triumph in them; and you think it is so grand a thing to get so many woodcuts for a penny. Why, woodcuts, penny and all, are as much lost to you as if you had invested your money in gossamer. More lost, for the gossamer could only tickle your face, and glitter in your eyes; it could not catch your feet and trip you up: but the bad art can, and does; for you can't like good woodcuts as long as you look at the bad ones. If we were at this moment to come across a Titian woodcut, or a Durer woodcut, we should not like it—those of us at least who are accustomed to the cheap work of the day. We don't like, and can't like, that long; but when we are tired of one bad cheap thing, we throw it aside and buy another bad cheap thing; and so keep looking at bad things all our lives. Now, the very men who do all that quick bad work for us are capable of doing perfect work. Only, perfect work can't be hurried, and therefore it can't be cheap beyond a certain point. But suppose you pay twelve times as much as you do now, and you have one woodcut for a shilling instead of twelve; and the one woodcut for a shilling is as good as art can be, so that you will never tire of looking at it; and is struck on good paper with good ink, so that you will never wear it out by handling it; while you are sick of your penny-each cuts by the end of the week, and have torn them mostly in half too. Isn't your shilling's worth the best bargain?

I'm sorry to say, the big trend of this age is to waste its talent on disposable art like this, as if it's some kind of victory to burn our ideas away. There's a huge amount of intellect and effort wasted each year on our cheap illustrated publications; you take pride in them; and you think it's amazing to get so many woodcuts for just a penny. Honestly, those woodcuts, no matter how cheap, are just as lost to you as if you'd spent your money on something as insubstantial as gossamer. Even more lost, because gossamer can only tickle your face and shimmer in your eyes; it can’t trip you up. But bad art can, and it does; you can't appreciate good woodcuts as long as you keep looking at bad ones. If we were to stumble upon a Titian woodcut or a Durer woodcut right now, we wouldn't appreciate it—at least those of us who are used to today’s cheap work. We don’t like, and can’t enjoy, that for long; and when we tire of one poor cheap item, we just toss it aside and buy another poor cheap item, so we end up looking at bad things all our lives. The very people who create all that quick, low-quality work for us are actually capable of great work. The thing is, great work can't be rushed, which means it can't be cheap past a certain point. But if you were to pay twelve times as much as you do now and get one woodcut for a shilling instead of twelve; and that one woodcut for a shilling is the best art can be, so you’ll never get tired of looking at it; and it’s printed on good paper with good ink, so you won't wear it out just by handling it; while you’ll have tossed your penny items aside by the end of the week, half of them torn in two. Isn’t your shilling's worth the best deal?

It is not, however, only in getting prints or woodcuts of the best kind that you will practise economy. There is a certain quality about an original drawing which you cannot get in a woodcut, and the best part of the genius of many men is only expressible in original work, whether with pen and ink—pencil or colours. This is not always the case; but in general, the best men are those who can only express themselves on paper or canvass; and you will, therefore, in the long run, get[Pg 34] most for your money by buying original work; proceeding on the principle already laid down, that the best is likely to be the cheapest in the end. Of course, original work cannot be produced under a certain cost. If you want a man to make you a drawing which takes him six days, you must, at all events, keep him for six days in bread and water, fire and lodging; that is the lowest price at which he can do it for you, but that is not very dear: and the best bargain which can possibly be made honestly in art—the very ideal of a cheap purchase to the purchaser—is the original work of a great man fed for as many days as are necessary on bread and water, or perhaps we may say with as many onions as will keep him in good humour. That is the way by which you will always get most for your money; no mechanical multiplication or ingenuity of commercial arrangements will ever get you a better penny's worth of art than that.

It's not just about getting prints or woodcuts of the highest quality that helps you save money. There's a certain essence in an original drawing that woodcuts can't capture, and the true brilliance of many artists can only be expressed through their original work, whether it's in pen and ink, pencil, or color. This isn't always true, but generally, the best artists are those who can only communicate their vision on paper or canvas; therefore, in the long run, you’ll get[Pg 34] the most value for your money by purchasing original work, based on the principle that the best is often the cheapest in the end. Naturally, original work can't be produced for nothing. If you want someone to create a drawing that takes them six days, you need to support them with food, shelter, and basic necessities for those six days; that's the minimum cost. But that's still not expensive: the best deal you can get honestly in art—the ideal of a bargain for you—is the original work of a great artist who has been sustained for as many days as needed on basic food, or perhaps we could say as many onions as it takes to keep them cheerful. That’s how you’ll always get the most value for your money; no mechanical reproduction or clever business strategies can provide you a better deal on art than that.

Without, however, pushing our calculations quite to this prison-discipline extreme, we may lay it down as a rule in art-economy, that original work is, on the whole, cheapest and best worth having. But precisely in proportion to the value of it as a production, becomes the importance of having it executed in permanent materials. And here we come to note the second main error of the day, that we not only ask our workmen for bad art, but we make them put it into bad substance. We have, for example, put a great quantity of genius, within the last twenty years, into water-colour drawing, and we have done this with the most reckless disregard whether either the colours or the paper will stand. In most instances, neither will. By accident, it may happen that the colours in a given drawing have been of good quality, and its paper uninjured by chemical processes. But you take not the least care to ensure these being so; I have myself seen the most destructive changes take place in water-colour drawings within twenty years after they were painted; and from all I can gather respecting the recklessness of modern paper manufacture, my belief is, that though you may still handle an Albert Durer engraving, two hundred years old, fearlessly, not one-half of that time will have passed over your modern water-colours, before most of them will be reduced to mere[Pg 35] white or brown rags; and your descendants, twitching them contemptuously into fragments between finger and thumb, will mutter against you, half in scorn and half in anger, "Those wretched nineteenth-century people! they kept vapouring and fuming about the world, doing what they called business, and they couldn't make a sheet of paper that wasn't rotten." And note that this is no unimportant portion of your art economy at this time. Your water-colour painters are becoming every day capable of expressing greater and better things; and their material is especially adapted to the turn of your best artists' minds. The value which you could accumulate in work of this kind would soon become a most important item in the national art-wealth, if only you would take the little pains necessary to secure its permanence. I am inclined to think, myself, that water-colour ought not to be used on paper at all, but only on vellum, and then, if properly taken care of, the drawing would be almost imperishable. Still, paper is a much more convenient material for rapid work; and it is an infinite absurdity not to secure the goodness of its quality, when we could do so without the slightest trouble. Among the many favours which I am going to ask from our paternal government, when we get it, will be that it will supply its little boys with good paper. You have nothing to do but to let the government establish a paper manufactory, under the superintendence of any of our leading chemists, who should be answerable for the safety and completeness of all the processes of the manufacture. The government stamp on the corner of your sheet of drawing-paper, made in the perfect way, should cost you a shilling, which would add something to the revenue; and when you bought a water-colour drawing for fifty or a hundred guineas, you would have merely to look in the corner for your stamp, and pay your extra shilling for the security that your hundred guineas were given really for a drawing, and not for a coloured rag. There need be no monopoly or restriction in the matter; let the paper manufacturers compete with the government, and if people liked to save their shilling, and take their chance, let them; only, the artist and purchaser might then be sure of good material, if they liked, and now they cannot be.[Pg 36]

Without pushing our calculations too far into the extreme of prison discipline, we can establish a rule in art economics: original work is generally the cheapest and most valuable to have. However, the value of this production increases the importance of executing it with permanent materials. Here, we observe the second major error of our time: not only do we ask our artists for poor quality art, but we also compel them to use inferior materials. For instance, a significant amount of talent has been invested in watercolor drawing over the past twenty years, done with reckless disregard for whether the paints or paper will last. In most cases, neither will. Occasionally, a specific drawing might exist with good quality colors and undamaged paper, but there's no care taken to ensure that. I have personally witnessed significant deterioration in watercolor drawings within twenty years of being created, and based on my understanding of the carelessness in modern paper production, I believe that while you can still handle an Albert Durer engraving that’s two hundred years old without worry, most modern watercolors won't last even half that time before they become mere white or brown rags. Your descendants will likely disdainfully tear them apart between their fingers, muttering in contempt and anger, “Those miserable nineteenth-century folks! They prattled on about making art and couldn’t even produce a decent sheet of paper.” This is a significant aspect of your art economy today. Watercolor painters are increasingly capable of creating greater and better works, and their medium is particularly suited to the creative styles of the best artists. The value created in this type of work could soon become a key part of national art wealth, if only we took the small effort needed to ensure its longevity. Personally, I think watercolor should only be used on vellum instead of paper, as it would then be nearly imperishable with proper care. Still, paper is a much more convenient medium for quick work, and it’s quite absurd not to ensure its quality when we could do so easily. One of many requests I'll have for our future government is to provide good paper for young artists. The government simply needs to set up a paper factory supervised by one of our leading chemists, responsible for all manufacturing processes' safety and quality. A government seal on a properly made sheet of drawing paper should cost you a shilling, adding to government revenue; and when you purchase a watercolor painting for fifty or a hundred guineas, you would just check for the seal and pay an extra shilling for the assurance that your hundred guineas are truly for art, not just a colored rag. There need not be any monopoly or restrictions; let paper manufacturers compete with the government, and if people want to skip the shilling and take the risk, they can. But this way, both artists and buyers could be certain of good materials when now they cannot be.

I should like also to have a government colour manufactory; though that is not so necessary, as the quality of colour is more within the artist's power of testing, and I have no doubt that any painter may get permanent colour from the respectable manufacturers, if he chooses. I will not attempt to follow the subject out at all as it respects architecture, and our methods of modern building; respecting which I have had occasion to speak before now.

I would also like to have a government color factory; although that's not as essential, since artists can better test the quality of color, and I’m sure any painter can get long-lasting color from reputable manufacturers if they want to. I won’t try to explore the topic as it relates to architecture and our modern building methods, which I've mentioned before.

But I cannot pass without some brief notice our habit—continually, as it seems to me, gaining strength—of putting a large quantity of thought and work, annually, into things which are either in their nature necessarily perishable, as dress; or else into compliances with the fashion of the day, in things not necessarily perishable, as plate. I am afraid almost the first idea of a young rich couple setting up house in London, is, that they must have new plate. Their father's plate may be very handsome, but the fashion is changed. They will have a new service from the leading manufacturer, and the old plate, except a few apostle spoons, and a cup which Charles the Second drank a health in to their pretty ancestress, is sent to be melted down, and made up with new flourishes and fresh lustre. Now, so long as this is the case—so long, observe, as fashion has influence on the manufacture of plate—so long you cannot have a goldsmith's art in this country. Do you suppose any workman worthy the name will put his brains into a cup or an urn, which he knows is to go to the melting pot in half a score years? He will not; you don't ask or expect it of him. You ask of him nothing but a little quick handicraft—a clever twist of a handle here, and a foot there, a convolvulus from the newest school of design, a pheasant from Landseer's game cards; a couple of sentimental figures for supporters, in the style of the signs of insurance offices, then a clever touch with the burnisher, and there's your epergne, the admiration of all the footmen at the wedding-breakfast, and the torment of some unfortunate youth who cannot see the pretty girl opposite to him, through its tyrannous branches.

But I can't go without mentioning our habit—one that seems to be getting stronger—of putting a lot of time and effort each year into things that are either meant to wear out, like clothing, or into keeping up with the latest trends, like silverware. I almost think that the first thought of a young, wealthy couple moving into a house in London is that they need new silverware. Their parents’ silver might be really nice, but styles have changed. They'll want a new set from a top manufacturer, and aside from a few apostle spoons and a cup that Charles II used to drink to their lovely ancestor, the old silver gets melted down to be reshaped and polished anew. Now, as long as this is the case—as long as fashion dictates the production of silverware—we cannot have a goldsmith's craft in this country. Do you really think any skilled worker will invest their creativity into a cup or urn that they know will just be melted down in a few years? They won't; you don’t expect them to. You only ask for quick, basic craftsmanship—a nice twist of a handle here, a base there, a curly design from the latest trend, a pheasant from Landseer’s game cards; throw in a couple of sentimental figures like those on insurance signs, then a little finesse with the burnisher, and there’s your centerpiece, the talk of all the servants at the wedding breakfast, and the frustration of some poor guy who can't see the pretty girl sitting across from him because of its overwhelming branches.

But you don't suppose that that's goldsmith's work? Goldsmith's work is made to last, and made with the man's whole[Pg 37] heart and soul in it; true goldsmith's work, when it exists, is generally the means of education of the greatest painters and sculptors of the day. Francia was a goldsmith; Francia was not his own name, but that of his master the jeweller; and he signed his pictures almost always, "Francia, the goldsmith," for love of his master; Ghirlandajo was a goldsmith, and was the master of Michael Angelo; Verrocchio was a goldsmith, and was the master of Leonardo da Vinci. Ghiberti was a goldsmith, and beat out the bronze gates which Michael Angelo said might serve for gates of Paradise.[8] But if ever you want work like theirs again, you must keep it, though it should have the misfortune to become old fashioned. You must not break it up, nor melt it any more. There is no economy in that; you could not easily waste intellect more grievously. Nature may melt her goldsmith's work at every sunset if she chooses; and beat it out into chased bars again at every sunrise; but you must not. The way to have a truly noble service of plate, is to keep adding to it, not melting it. At every marriage, and at every birth, get a new piece of gold or silver if you will, but with noble workmanship on it, done for all time, and put it among your treasures; that is one of the chief things which gold was made for, and made incorruptible for. When we know a little more of political economy, we shall find that none but partially savage nations need, imperatively, gold for their currency;[9] but gold has been given us, among other things, that we might put beautiful work into its imperishable splendour, and that the artists who have the most wilful fancies may have a material which will drag out, and beat out, as their dreams require, and will hold itself together with [Pg 38] fantastic tenacity, whatever rare and delicate service they set it upon.

But you don’t think that that’s goldsmith’s work? Goldsmith’s work is made to last, crafted with the artist's whole[Pg 37] heart and soul; true goldsmith’s work, when it exists, is usually the foundation for educating the greatest painters and sculptors of the time. Francia was a goldsmith; Francia wasn’t his real name, but the name of his master, the jeweler; he almost always signed his paintings, "Francia, the goldsmith," out of love for his master. Ghirlandajo was a goldsmith and was Michelangelo's teacher; Verrocchio was a goldsmith and was Leonardo da Vinci's mentor. Ghiberti was a goldsmith who created the bronze gates that Michelangelo said could serve as the gates of Paradise.[8] But if you want work like theirs again, you have to keep it, even if it risks becoming outdated. You shouldn’t break it apart or melt it down anymore. There’s no savings in that; you couldn’t waste creativity more seriously. Nature may melt her goldsmith’s work at every sunset if she wants and reshape it into bars again at every sunrise; but you mustn't. The way to have a truly noble collection of silverware is to keep adding to it, not melting it down. With every marriage and birth, get a new piece of gold or silver if you like, but with exceptional craftsmanship on it, made to last, and add it to your treasures; that’s one of the main purposes for which gold was created and kept immortal. When we understand a bit more about economics, we’ll find that only somewhat primitive societies absolutely need gold for their currency;[9] but gold has been given to us, among other things, so we can create beautiful work in its enduring splendor, and so that the artists with the wildest ideas have a material they can shape and form as their visions require, maintaining its integrity with[Pg 38] remarkable resilience, no matter the intricate and delicate use they put it to.

So here is one branch of decorative art in which rich people may indulge themselves unselfishly; if they ask for good art in it, they may be sure in buying gold and silver plate that they are enforcing useful education on young artists. But there is another branch of decorative art in which I am sorry to say we cannot, at least under existing circumstances, indulge ourselves, with the hope of doing good to anybody, I mean the great and subtle art of dress.

So here’s one area of decorative art where wealthy people can treat themselves generously; if they seek high-quality art in it, they can be confident that by purchasing gold and silver plates, they are supporting valuable education for young artists. However, there’s another area of decorative art where, unfortunately, we can’t, at least in current conditions, indulge ourselves with the intention of benefiting anyone, and that’s the sophisticated and complex art of fashion.

And here I must interrupt the pursuit of our subject for a moment or two, in order to state one of the principles of political economy, which, though it is, I believe, now sufficiently understood and asserted by the leading masters of the science, is not yet, I grieve to say, acted upon by the plurality of those who have the management of riches. Whenever we spend money, we of course set people to work: that is the meaning of spending money; we may, indeed, lose it without employing anybody; but, whenever we spend it, we set a number of people to work, greater or less, of course, according to the rate of wages, but, in the long run, proportioned to the sum we spend. Well, your shallow people, because they see that however they spend money they are always employing somebody, and, therefore, doing some good, think and say to themselves, that it is all one how they spend it—that all their apparently selfish luxury is, in reality, unselfish, and is doing just as much good as if they gave all their money away, or perhaps more good; and I have heard foolish people even declare it as a principle of political economy, that whoever invented a new want[10] conferred a good on the community. I have not words strong enough—at least I could not, without shocking you, use the words which would be strong enough—to express my estimate of the absurdity and the mischievousness of this popular fallacy. So, putting a great restraint upon myself, and using no hard words, I will simply try to state the nature of it, and the extent of its influence.

And here I need to pause our main discussion for a moment to explain a principle of economics that, while I believe it is now well understood and supported by the leading experts in the field, is still, unfortunately, not acted upon by most of those who manage wealth. Whenever we spend money, we obviously create jobs: that’s the point of spending money. We might lose it without employing anyone, but every time we do spend it, we engage a number of people to work, more or less depending on the wage rates, but ultimately proportional to the amount we spend. Now, some shallow thinkers, seeing that no matter how they spend money they are always employing someone and thus doing some good, convince themselves that it doesn’t matter *how* they spend it—that all their seemingly selfish indulgence is, in fact, unselfish and does just as much good as if they donated all their money, or maybe even more. I have heard foolish people claim it as a principle of economics that whoever creates a new desire[10] brings a benefit to society. I lack the strong words—at least I couldn't use the words that would be potent enough without shocking you—to convey how absurd and harmful this common misconception is. So, exercising a great deal of restraint, and avoiding harsh language, I will simply attempt to explain the nature of this belief and the extent of its influence.

Granted, that whenever we spend money for whatever purpose, we set people to work; and, passing by, for the [Pg 39] moment, the question whether the work we set them to is all equally healthy and good for them, we will assume that whenever we spend a guinea we provide an equal number of people with healthy maintenance for a given time. But, by the way in which we spend it, we entirely direct the labour of those people during that given time. We become their masters or mistresses, and we compel them to produce, within a certain period, a certain article. Now, that article may be a useful and lasting one, or it may be a useless and perishable one—it may be one useful to the whole community, or useful only to ourselves. And our selfishness and folly, or our virtue and prudence, are shown, not by our spending money, but by our spending it for the wrong or the right thing; and we are wise and kind, not in maintaining a certain number of people for a given period, but only in requiring them to produce, during that period, the kind of things which shall be useful to society, instead of those which are only useful to ourselves.

Sure, whenever we spend money for any reason, we create jobs. For now, let's assume that every time we spend a guinea, we provide an equal number of people with healthy support for a certain amount of time. However, how we choose to spend that money completely directs the work those people do during that time. We become their employers and push them to produce a specific item within a set timeframe. That item could be something useful and durable, or it could be something worthless and temporary—it could benefit the whole community, or just ourselves. Our selfishness and foolishness, or our virtue and wisdom, are revealed not just by spending money but by spending it on the right or wrong things. We are wise and kind, not just by supporting a certain number of people for a certain period, but by ensuring they produce things during that time that are beneficial to society, rather than just to ourselves.

Thus, for instance: if you are a young lady, and employ a certain number of sempstresses for a given time, in making a given number of simple and serviceable dresses, suppose, seven; of which you can wear one yourself for half the winter, and give six away to poor girls who have none, you are spending your money unselfishly. But if you employ the same number of sempstresses for the same number of days, in making four, or five, or six beautiful flounces for your own ball-dress—flounces which will clothe no one but yourself, and which you will yourself be unable to wear at more than one ball—you are employing your money selfishly. You have maintained, indeed, in each case, the same number of people; but in the one case you have directed their labour to the service of the community; in the other case you have consumed it wholly upon yourself. I don't say you are never to do so; I don't say you ought not sometimes to think of yourselves only, and to make yourselves as pretty as you can; only do not confuse coquettishness with benevolence, nor cheat yourselves into thinking that all the finery you can wear is so much put into the hungry mouths of those beneath you: it is not so; it is what you yourselves, whether you will or no, must sometimes instinctively feel it to be—it is what those who stand shivering in the streets, forming[Pg 40] a line to watch you as you step out of your carriages, know it to be; those fine dresses do not mean that so much has been put into their mouths, but that so much has been taken out of their mouths. The real politico-economical signification of every one of those beautiful toilettes, is just this; that you have had a certain number of people put for a certain number of days wholly under your authority, by the sternest of slave-masters—hunger and cold; and you have said to them, "I will feed you, indeed, and clothe you, and give you fuel for so many days; but during those days you shall work for me only: your little brothers need clothes, but you shall make none for them: your sick friend needs clothes, but you shall make none for her: you yourself will soon need another, and a warmer dress; but you shall make none for yourself. You shall make nothing but lace and roses for me; for this fortnight to come, you shall work at the patterns and petals, and then I will crush and consume them away in an hour." You will perhaps answer—"It may not be particularly benevolent to do this, and we won't call it so; but at any rate we do no wrong in taking their labour when we pay them their wages: if we pay for their work we have a right to it." No;—a thousand times no. The labour which you have paid for, does indeed become, by the act of purchase, your own labour: you have bought the hands and the time of those workers; they are, by right and justice, your own hands, your own time. But, have you a right to spend your own time, to work with your own hands, only for your own advantage?—much more, when, by purchase, you have invested your own person with the strength of others; and added to your own life, a part of the life of others? You may, indeed, to a certain extent, use their labour for your delight: remember, I am making no general assertions against splendour of dress, or pomp of accessories of life; on the contrary, there are many reasons for thinking that we do not at present attach enough importance to beautiful dress, as one of the means of influencing general taste and character. But I do say, that you must weigh the value of what you ask these workers to produce for you in its own distinct balance; that on its own worthiness or desirableness rests the question of your kindness, and not[Pg 41] merely on the fact of your having employed people in producing it: and I say farther, that as long as there are cold and nakedness in the land around you, so long there can be no question at all but that splendour of dress is a crime. In due time, when we have nothing better to set people to work at, it may be right to let them make lace and cut jewels; but, as long as there are any who have no blankets for their beds, and no rags for their bodies, so long it is blanket-making and tailoring we must set people to work at—not lace.

So, for example: if you’re a young woman and hire a certain number of seamstresses for a certain amount of time to make a certain number of simple and useful dresses—let's say seven—where you wear one yourself for half the winter and give six to poor girls who don’t have any, you’re spending your money generously. But if you use the same number of seamstresses for the same amount of time to make four, five, or six beautiful flounces for your own ball gown—flounces that will only benefit you and that you'll only wear to one ball—you’re spending your money selfishly. In both cases, you’ve employed the same number of people, but in the first case, you’ve directed their work toward benefiting the community, while in the second, you’ve consumed it entirely for yourself. I’m not saying you should never do that; I’m not saying you shouldn’t sometimes think only of yourself and try to look as pretty as you can. Just don’t confuse vanity with kindness, or fool yourself into thinking that all the fancy things you wear somehow feed those less fortunate than you. That’s not the case. Deep down, you know it’s not, and those who stand shivering in the streets and form a line to watch you get out of your car know it too. Those fancy dresses don’t mean that something has gone into their mouths; they mean that something has been taken out of their mouths. The true socio-economic meaning of each one of those beautiful outfits is this: you’ve hired a certain number of people for a certain number of days under the most relentless masters—hunger and cold—and you’ve told them, “I will feed you, clothe you, and give you fuel for so many days; but during that time, you will work only for me. Your little brothers need clothes, but you won’t make any for them. Your sick friend needs clothes, but you will make none for her. You yourself will soon need another, warmer dress, but you’ll make none for yourself. You will make only lace and roses for me; for the next two weeks, you will work on the patterns and petals, and then I’ll wear them out in an hour.” You might respond—“It may not be particularly generous, and we won’t call it that, but at least we’re not wrong to take their labor as long as we pay them for it: if we pay for their work, we have a right to it.” No—absolutely not. The labor you’ve paid for does indeed become your own through the act of purchase: you’ve bought the hands and time of those workers; by right and justice, they are your hands, your time. But do you have the right to use your own time and work with your own hands solely for your own benefit?—even more so when, through purchase, you’ve appropriated the strength of others and added to your own life a part of theirs? You can, to some extent, use their labor for your enjoyment: remember, I’m not making general statements against beautiful clothing or luxurious lifestyles; in fact, there are many reasons to believe we currently don’t attach enough importance to beautiful clothing as a means of influencing overall taste and character. But I do say that you must evaluate the value of what you’re asking these workers to create for you on its own merits; the question of your kindness depends not just on the fact that you employed people to make it, but on whether what you are asking them to produce is worthy or desirable. I also state that as long as there are people suffering from cold and nakedness around you, it is unquestionable that lavish clothing is a crime. Eventually, when we have nothing better to have people work on, it may be right to let them create lace and cut jewels; but as long as there are people without blankets for their beds and rags for their bodies, we must have them working on making blankets and clothes—not lace.

And it would be strange, if at any great assembly which, while it dazzled the young and the thoughtless, beguiled the gentler hearts that beat beneath the embroidery, with a placid sensation of luxurious benevolence—as if by all that they wore in waywardness of beauty, comfort had been first given to the distressed, and aid to the indigent; it would be strange, I say, if, for a moment, the spirits of Truth and of Terror, which walk invisibly among the masques of the earth, would lift the dimness from our erring thoughts, and show us how—inasmuch as the sums exhausted for that magnificence would have given back the failing breath to many an unsheltered outcast on moor and street—they who wear it have literally entered into partnership with Death; and dressed themselves in his spoils. Yes, if the veil could be lifted not only from your thoughts, but from your human sight, you would see—the angels do see—on those gay white dresses of yours, strange dark spots, and crimson patterns that you knew not of—spots of the inextinguishable red that all the seas cannot wash away; yes, and among the pleasant flowers that crown your fair heads, and glow on your wreathed hair, you would see that one weed was always twisted which no one thought of—the grass that grows on graves.

And it would be odd if, at any big gathering that dazzled the young and carefree, while charming the softer hearts hidden beneath the fancy clothing, with a calm feeling of luxurious kindness—like all the beautiful things they wore had first offered comfort to the distressed and help to the needy—it would be odd, I say, if for just a moment, the spirits of Truth and Terror, who walk invisibly among the masqueraders of the earth, could clear the fog from our misguided thoughts and reveal how—the amount spent on that extravagance could have restored life to many a homeless soul on the moor and in the street—those who wear it have essentially partnered with Death; and adorned themselves with his spoils. Yes, if the veil could be lifted not only from your thoughts but from your human sight, you would see—the angels do see—on those bright white dresses of yours, strange dark spots and red patterns that you never knew existed—spots of the unending red that all the seas cannot wash away; yes, and among the lovely flowers that crown your beautiful heads and glow in your braided hair, you would see that one weed that was always twisted in— the grass that grows on graves.

It was not, however, this last, this clearest and most appalling view of our subject, that I intended to ask you to take this evening; only it is impossible to set any part of the matter in its true light, until we go to the root of it. But the point which it is our special business to consider is, not whether costliness of dress is contrary to charity; but whether it is not contrary to mere worldly wisdom: whether, even supposing we knew that splendour of dress did not cost suffering or hunger,[Pg 42] we might not put the splendour better in other things than dress. And, supposing our mode of dress were really graceful or beautiful, this might be a very doubtful question; for I believe true nobleness of dress to be an important means of education, as it certainly is a necessity to any nation which wishes to possess living art, concerned with portraiture of human nature. No good historical painting ever yet existed, or ever can exist, where the dresses of the people of the time are not beautiful: and had it not been for the lovely and fantastic dressing of the 13th to the 16th centuries, neither French, nor Florentine, nor Venetian art could have risen to anything like the rank it reached. Still, even then, the best dressing was never the costliest; and its effect depended much more on its beautiful and, in early times, modest, arrangement, and on the simple and lovely masses of its colour, than on gorgeousness of clasp or embroidery. Whether we can ever return to any of those more perfect types of form, is questionable; but there can be no question, that all the money we spend on the forms of dress at present worn, is, so far as any good purpose is concerned, wholly lost. Mind, in saying this, I reckon among good purposes, the purpose which young ladies are said sometimes to entertain—of being married; but they would be married quite as soon (and probably to wiser and better husbands) by dressing quietly, as by dressing brilliantly: and I believe it would only be needed to lay fairly and largely before them the real good which might be effected by the sums they spend in toilettes, to make them trust at once only to their bright eyes and braided hair for all the mischief they have a mind to. I wish we could, for once, get the statistics of a London season. There was much complaining talk in Parliament last week, of the vast sum the nation has given for the best Paul Veronese in Venice—£14,000: I wonder what the nation meanwhile has given for its ball-dresses! Suppose we could see the London milliners' bills, simply for unnecessary breadths of slip and flounce, from April to July; I wonder whether £14,000 would cover them. But the breadths of slip and flounce are by this time as much lost and vanished as last year's snow; only they have done less good: but the Paul Veronese will last for centuries, if we take care of it; and yet we grumble at the price[Pg 43] given for the painting, while no one grumbles at the price of pride.

It wasn't, however, this last, clearest, and most shocking perspective on our topic that I wanted to discuss with you tonight; it's just that we can't truly understand any part of it until we dig deeper. The main point we need to focus on is not whether expensive clothing goes against charity but whether it's against plain common sense. Even if we knew that luxury clothing didn't involve pain or hunger, [Pg 42] might we not allocate that luxury more wisely in other areas than apparel? And if our clothing was genuinely graceful or beautiful, this might be a complicated issue; because I believe that truly noble clothing serves as an essential educational tool, as it is undoubtedly crucial for any nation that wants to cultivate vibrant art related to the portrayal of human nature. No good historical painting has ever existed—or can exist—without the clothing of the era being beautiful: and if it hadn't been for the exquisite and imaginative styles from the 13th to the 16th centuries, neither French, nor Florentine, nor Venetian art could have achieved the heights it did. Still, even back then, the finest attire was never the most expensive; its impact relied much more on its beautiful and, in earlier times, modest design, and on the simple and lovely combinations of colors, rather than on lavish clasps or embroidery. Whether we can ever return to those more ideal forms is uncertain; but there's no doubt that all the money spent on the current styles of dress is, as far as any worthwhile purpose is concerned, entirely wasted. Keep in mind, when I say this, I include among worthwhile purposes the desire young women often have—of getting married; but they would find partners just as quickly (and probably to more sensible and better spouses) by dressing modestly as they would by dressing flamboyantly. I believe if we could clearly present them with the real benefits of the money they spend on fancy clothing, they would quickly rely on nothing but their bright eyes and styled hair for all the attention they desire. I wish we could, for once, obtain the statistics for a London social season. Last week, there was much talk in Parliament about the enormous amount the country paid for the best Paul Veronese painting in Venice—£14,000: I wonder how much the nation has spent on ball gowns in the meantime! Imagine if we could see the milliners' bills from London, simply for unnecessary fabric and embellishments, from April to July; I wonder if £14,000 would even cover that. But the fabric and fluff are now as gone as last year's snow; they've done less good: yet the Paul Veronese will endure for centuries, if we take care of it; and still, we complain about the cost of the painting, while no one grumbles about the price of vanity. [Pg 43]

Time does not permit me to go into any farther illustration of the various modes in which we build our statue out of snow, and waste our labour on things that vanish. I must leave you to follow out the subject for yourselves, as I said I should, and proceed, in our next lecture, to examine the two other branches of our subject, namely, how to accumulate our art, and how to distribute it. But, in closing, as we have been much on the topic of good government, both of ourselves and others, let me just give you one more illustration of what it means, from that old art of which, next evening, I shall try to convince you that the value, both moral and mercantile, is greater than we usually suppose.

Time doesn't allow me to elaborate further on the different ways we create snow sculptures only to see them melt away, wasting our efforts. I'll leave you to explore the topic on your own, as I mentioned I would, and in our next lecture, we'll dive into the other two aspects of our discussion: how to develop our craft and how to share it. But before we wrap up, since we've focused a lot on the idea of good governance—for ourselves and others—I want to share one more example of what that means, drawn from that ancient art form. Tomorrow evening, I will try to convince you that its value, both ethically and financially, is much higher than we typically realize.

One of the frescoes by Ambrozio Lorenzetti, in the town-hall of Siena, represents, by means of symbolical figures, the principles of Good Civic Government and of Good Government in general. The figure representing this noble Civic Government is enthroned, and surrounded by figures representing the Virtues, variously supporting or administering its authority. Now, observe what work is given to each of these virtues. Three winged ones—Faith, Hope, and Charity—surround the head of the figure, not in mere compliance with the common and heraldic laws of precedence among Virtues, such as we moderns observe habitually, but with peculiar purpose on the part of the painter. Faith, as thus represented, ruling the thoughts of the Good Governour, does not mean merely religious faith, understood in those times to be necessary to all persons—governed no less than governours—but it means the faith which enables work to be carried out steadily, in spite of adverse appearances and expediencies; the faith in great principles, by which a civic ruler looks past all the immediate checks and shadows that would daunt a common man, knowing that what is rightly done will have a right issue, and holding his way in spite of pullings at his cloak and whisperings in his ear, enduring, as having in him a faith which is evidence of things unseen. And Hope, in like manner, is here not the heavenward hope which ought to animate the hearts of all men; but she attends upon Good Government, to show that all such[Pg 44] government is expectant as well as conservative; that if it ceases to be hopeful of better things, it ceases to be a wise guardian of present things: that it ought never, as long as the world lasts, to be wholly content with any existing state of institution or possession, but to be hopeful still of more wisdom and power; not clutching at it restlessly or hastily, but feeling that its real life consists in steady ascent from high to higher: conservative, indeed, and jealously conservative of old things, but conservative of them as pillars, not as pinnacles—as aids, but not as idols; and hopeful chiefly, and active, in times of national trial or distress, according to those first and notable words describing the queenly nation. "She riseth, while it is yet night." And again, the winged Charity which is attendant on Good Government has, in this fresco, a peculiar office. Can you guess what? If you consider the character of contest which so often takes place among kings for their crowns, and the selfish and tyrannous means they commonly take to aggrandize or secure their power, you will, perhaps, be surprised to hear that the office of Charity is to crown the King. And yet, if you think of it a little, you will see the beauty of the thought which sets her in this function: since in the first place, all the authority of a good governor should be desired by him only for the good of his people, so that it is only Love that makes him accept or guard his crown: in the second place, his chief greatness consists in the exercise of this love, and he is truly to be revered only so far as his acts and thoughts are those of kindness; so that Love is the light of his crown, as well as the giver of it: lastly, because his strength depends on the affections of his people, and it is only their love which can securely crown him, and for ever. So that Love is the strength of his crown as well as the light of it.

One of the frescoes by Ambrozio Lorenzetti, in the town hall of Siena, depicts, through symbolic figures, the principles of Good Civic Government and Good Government in general. The figure representing this noble Civic Government is seated on a throne and surrounded by figures that embody the Virtues, each supporting or administering its authority. Note the role assigned to each of these virtues. Three winged figures—Faith, Hope, and Charity—surround the head of this figure, not just according to the usual hierarchy among Virtues, as we often see today, but with a specific intention from the painter. Faith, as shown here, guiding the thoughts of the Good Governor, doesn't just mean religious faith, which was believed to be necessary for everyone—both governed and governors—at that time. It represents the faith that allows for steady action despite unfavorable circumstances; the faith in great principles that a civic ruler holds to, looking beyond the immediate setbacks and doubts that would intimidate an ordinary person, knowing that doing what is right will lead to a proper outcome, and staying true to his purpose despite distractions and whispers, embodying a faith that is evidence of things not seen. Similarly, Hope here isn't just the upward hope that should inspire everyone; it supports Good Government to illustrate that such governance is both optimistic and cautious. If it loses hope for improvement, it stops being a wise steward of the present: it should never be completely satisfied with the status quo but remain hopeful for greater wisdom and power—not grasping for it recklessly or hastily, but understanding that its real essence lies in a steady climb from the good to the better. It is indeed conservative, protecting old values fiercely, but as pillars, not as idols—functioning as supports, not as revered objects; and primarily being hopeful and active during national crises, aligned with those famous words describing the noble nation: "She rises, while it is yet night." Lastly, the winged Charity that accompanies Good Government has a unique role in this fresco. Can you guess what it is? Considering the fierce rivalries among kings for their crowns, and the selfish and tyrannical methods they often use to build or secure their power, you might be surprised to learn that Charity's role is to crown the King. Yet, upon reflection, you will appreciate the beauty of this idea: first, all authority a good governor wishes for should be pursued solely for the betterment of his people, so it is Love that drives him to accept or protect his crown. Second, his true greatness lies in exercising this love, and he deserves respect only to the extent that his actions and thoughts reflect kindness; thus, Love is both the light of his crown and its source. Lastly, his strength relies on the affections of his people, as only their love can securely crown him, now and forever. So, Love is both the strength of his crown and its illuminating force.

Then, surrounding the King, or in various obedience to him, appear the dependent virtues, as Fortitude, Temperance, Truth, and other attendant spirits, of all which I cannot now give account, wishing you only to notice the one to whom are entrusted the guidance and administration of the public revenues. Can you guess which it is likely to be? Charity, you would have thought, should have something to do with the business; but not so, for she is too hot to attend carefully[Pg 45] to it. Prudence, perhaps, you think of in the next place. No, she is too timid, and loses opportunities in making up her mind. Can it be Liberality then? No: Liberality is entrusted with some small sums; but she is a bad accountant, and is allowed no important place in the exchequer. But the treasures are given in charge to a virtue of which we hear too little in modern times, as distinct from others; Magnanimity: largeness of heart: not softness or weakness of heart, mind you—but capacity of heart—the great measuring virtue, which weighs in heavenly balances all that may be given, and all that may be gained; and sees how to do noblest things in noblest ways: which of two goods comprehends and therefore chooses the greatest: which of two personal sacrifices dares and accepts the largest: which, out of the avenues of beneficence, treads always that which opens farthest into the blue fields of futurity: that character, in fine, which, in those words taken by us at first for the description of a Queen among the nations, looks less to the present power than to the distant promise; "Strength and honour are in her clothing—and she shall rejoice IN TIME TO COME."

Then, surrounding the King, or showing their loyalty to him, are the supporting virtues like Courage, Self-Control, Truth, and other guiding spirits, about which I can't elaborate right now, but I want you to notice the one responsible for overseeing and managing public finances. Can you guess who it is? You might think Charity should be involved, but that's not the case because she’s too impulsive to handle it carefully[Pg 45]. Perhaps you think of Prudence next. No, she’s too cautious and misses opportunities while she deliberates. Could it be Generosity then? No, Generosity only manages small amounts and isn’t the best at accounting, so she doesn’t have a significant role in the treasury. Instead, the responsibility lies with a virtue we hear too little about these days, distinct from others; Magnanimity: being big-hearted—not soft or weak-hearted, understand—but having the capacity of heart—the great measuring virtue, which weighs in divine balances all that can be given and all that can be gained; and knows how to achieve the most noble deeds in the most admirable ways: which recognizes which of two goods is greater and therefore chooses the best: which of two personal sacrifices dares to accept the largest: which, from the paths of generosity, always follows the one that leads farthest into the bright future: that character which, in words we initially took to describe a Queen among nations, looks less at immediate power and more toward distant promise; "Strength and honour are in her clothing—and she shall rejoice IN TIME TO COME."

FOOTNOTES:

[2] Proverbs xiii. 23: "Much food is in the tillage of the poor: but there is that is destroyed for want of judgment."

[2] Proverbs 13:23: "There's plenty of food from the hard work of the poor, but some is wasted due to lack of wisdom."

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[4] Compare Wordsworth's Essay on the Poor-Law Amendment Bill. I quote one important passage:—"But, if it be not safe to touch the abstract question of man's right in a social state to help himself even in the last extremity, may we not still contend for the duty of a Christian government, standing in loco parentis towards all its subjects, to make such effectual provision that no one shall be in danger of perishing either through the neglect or harshness of its legislation? Or, waiving this, is it not indisputable that the claim of the State to the allegiance, involves the protection of the subject? And, as all rights in one party impose a correlative duty upon another, it follows that the right of the State to require the services of its members, even to the jeoparding of their lives in the common defence, establishes a right in the people (not to be gainsaid by utilitarians and economists) to public support when, from any cause, they may be unable to support themselves."—(See note 2nd in Addenda [p. 90]).

[4] Compare Wordsworth's Essay on the Poor-Law Amendment Bill. I quote an important passage:—"But, if it’s unsafe to discuss the abstract question of a person's right in a society to help themselves even in the most extreme situations, can we not still argue for the obligation of a Christian government, acting in loco parentis towards all its citizens, to ensure that no one is at risk of suffering or dying due to the neglect or cruelty of its laws? Or, putting this aside, isn’t it clear that if the State demands loyalty, it must also protect its citizens? And, since the rights of one person place a corresponding duty on another, it follows that the State’s right to require the services of its citizens, even risking their lives for defense, gives the people (a right not to be denied by utilitarians and economists) the right to public support when, for any reason, they are unable to support themselves."—(See note 2nd in Addenda [p. 90]).

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[7] See the noble passage on this tradition in "Casa Guidi Windows."

[7] Check out the beautiful section on this tradition in "Casa Guidi Windows."

[8] Several reasons may account for the fact that goldsmith's work is so wholesome for young artists; first, that it gives great firmness of hand to deal for some time with a solid substance; again, that it induces caution and steadiness—a boy trusted with chalk and paper suffers an immediate temptation to scrawl upon it and play with it, but he dares not scrawl on gold, and he cannot play with it; and, lastly, that it gives great delicacy and precision of touch to work upon minute forms, and to aim at producing richness and finish of design correspondent to the preciousness of the material.

[8] There are several reasons why working with gold is so beneficial for young artists. First, it helps strengthen their hands by requiring them to work with a solid material for an extended time. Second, it encourages caution and steadiness—while a boy given chalk and paper might be tempted to scribble and play, he won’t dare to mess around with gold, and he can’t play with it. Lastly, it trains them to have great delicacy and precision in working on intricate forms, aiming to create designs that reflect the material's value and beauty.

[9] See note in Addenda on the nature of property [p. 107].

[9] See the note in the Addenda about what property is [p. 107].

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.


LECTURE II.

The heads of our subject which remain for our consideration this evening are, you will remember, the accumulation and the distribution of works of art. Our complete inquiry fell into four divisions—first, how to get our genius; then, how to apply our genius; then, how to accumulate its results; and lastly, how to distribute them. We considered, last evening, how to discover and apply it;—we have to-night to examine the modes of its preservation and distribution.

The topics we need to discuss tonight are, as you may recall, the gathering and sharing of artworks. Our entire exploration is divided into four parts—first, how to discover our talent; then, how to use our talent; next, how to gather its outcomes; and finally, how to share them. Last night, we looked at how to find and use our talent; tonight, we will focus on how to preserve and distribute it.

 

III. Accumulation.—And now, in the outset, it will be well to face that objection which we put aside a little while ago; namely, that perhaps it is not well to have a great deal of good art; and that it should not be made too cheap.

III. Gathering.—Now, at the beginning, it’s important to address the concern we set aside earlier; specifically, that having too much good art might not be beneficial and that it shouldn’t become too affordable.

"Nay," I can imagine some of the more generous among you, exclaiming, "we will not trouble you to disprove that objection; of course it is a selfish and base one: good art, as well as other good things, ought to be made as cheap as possible, and put as far as we can within the reach of everybody."

"Nah," I can picture some of the more generous among you saying, "we won't ask you to disprove that objection; obviously, it's a selfish and low one: good art, like other good things, should be made as affordable as possible and made accessible to everyone."

Pardon me, I am not prepared to admit that. I rather side with the selfish objectors, and believe that art ought not to be made cheap, beyond a certain point; for the amount of pleasure that you can receive from any great work, depends wholly on the quantity of attention and energy of mind you can bring to bear upon it. Now, that attention and energy depend much more on the freshness of the thing than you would at all suppose; unless you very carefully studied the movements of your own minds. If you see things of the same kind and of equal value very frequently, your reverence for them is infallibly diminished, your powers of attention get gradually wearied, and your interest and enthusiasm worn out; and you cannot in that state bring to any given work the energy necessary to enjoy it. If, indeed, the question were only between enjoying a great many pictures each a little,[Pg 47] or one picture very much, the sum of enjoyment being in each case the same, you might rationally desire to possess rather the larger quantity, than the small; both because one work of art always in some sort illustrates another, and because quantity diminishes the chances of destruction. But the question is not a merely arithmetical one of this kind. Your fragments of broken admirations will not, when they are put together, make up one whole admiration; two and two, in this case, do not make four, nor anything like four. Your good picture, or book, or work of art of any kind, is always in some degree fenced and closed about with difficulty. You may think of it as of a kind of cocoa-nut, with very often rather an unseemly shell, but good milk and kernel inside. Now, if you possess twenty cocoa-nuts, and being thirsty, go impatiently from one to the other, giving only a single scratch with the point of your knife to the shell of each, you will get no milk from all the twenty. But if you leave nineteen of them alone, and give twenty cuts to the shell of one, you will get through it, and at the milk of it. And the tendency of the human mind is always to get tired before it has made its twenty cuts; and to try another nut; and moreover, even if it has perseverance enough to crack its nuts, it is sure to try to eat too many, and so choke itself. Hence, it is wisely appointed for us that few of the things we desire can be had without considerable labour, and at considerable intervals of time. We cannot generally get our dinner without working for it, and that gives us appetite for it; we cannot get our holiday without waiting for it, and that gives us zest for it; and we ought not to get our picture without paying for it, and that gives us a mind to look at it. Nay, I will even go so far as to say, that we ought not to get books too cheaply. No book, I believe, is ever worth half so much to its reader as one that has been coveted for a year at a bookstall, and bought out of saved half-pence; and perhaps a day or two's fasting. That's the way to get at the cream of a book. And I should say more on this matter, and protest as energetically as I could against the plague of cheap literature, with which we are just now afflicted, but that I fear your calling me to order, as being unpractical, because I don't quite see my way at present to[Pg 48] making everybody fast for their books. But one may see that a thing is desirable and possible, even though one may not at once know the best way to it—and in my island of Barataria, when I get it well into order, I assure you no book shall be sold for less than a pound sterling; if it can be published cheaper than that, the surplus shall all go into my treasury, and save my subjects taxation in other directions; only people really poor, who cannot pay the pound, shall be supplied with the books they want for nothing, in a certain limited quantity. I haven't made up my mind about the number yet, and there are several other points in the system yet unsettled; when they are all determined, if you will allow me, I will come and give you another lecture, on the political economy of literature.[11]

I'm sorry, but I can't agree with that. I side with the self-interested critics and believe that art shouldn't become too cheap. The enjoyment you get from any great work is entirely dependent on how much attention and mental energy you put into it. This attention and energy rely more on how fresh the experience is than you might think, unless you've really examined your own thought processes. When you see similar things of equal value too often, your respect for them inevitably decreases, your ability to focus wears out, and your interest fades; and in that state, you can't bring the energy needed to truly enjoy a work. If the choice were simply between enjoying many pieces of art a little or one piece a lot, where the total enjoyment was the same, you might reasonably prefer to have more pieces. This is because one work of art often complements another and having more reduces the risk of losing them. But this isn’t just a numbers game. Your fragments of partial admiration won't combine into one complete admiration; two and two won't make four here. A good picture, book, or piece of art is always somewhat surrounded by challenges. You might think of it like a coconut with a tough shell but good milk and meat inside. If you have twenty coconuts and you're thirsty, but you only scratch the shells of each one a little, you won’t get any milk from them. However, if you ignore nineteen coconuts and focus on one, really working at it, you'll break through the shell and get to the milk. The human mind tends to get weary before it puts in the effort to finish, moving on to another coconut; and even if it does manage to crack open a few, it often tries to consume too much at once and ends up overwhelmed. That's why it’s smart that many things we desire require substantial effort and come at intervals. We generally can't eat dinner without working for it, which creates an appetite; we can't have a holiday without waiting for it, which builds excitement; and we shouldn’t get a picture without paying for it, which gives us the motivation to appreciate it. I would even argue against acquiring books too easily. I think no book is ever worth as much to a reader as one that has been yearned for, saved up for at a bookshop, and possibly bought after a couple of days of skipping meals. That's how to truly appreciate a book. I could go on about this and express my opposition to the surplus of cheap literature we're currently experiencing, but I worry you might find me impractical, as I don’t see an immediate way to make everyone fast for their books. Still, it’s possible to desire something and not yet know the best path to obtain it. In my imagined island of Barataria, once I organize it, I assure you no book will be sold for less than a pound sterling. If a book can be published for less, the extra will go into my treasury to save my people from other taxes. Only those truly in need who can’t pay a pound will receive their desired books for free, but in limited quantities. I haven’t decided on the exact number yet, and there are other aspects of the system that are still undecided. Once they're set, if you allow me, I’ll return to give another talk on the political economy of literature.

Meantime, returning to our immediate subject, I say to my generous hearers, who want to shower Titians and Turners upon us, like falling leaves, "Pictures ought not to be too cheap;" but in much stronger tone I would say to those who want to keep up the prices of pictorial property, that pictures ought not to be too dear, that is to say, not as dear as they are. For, as matters at present stand, it is wholly impossible for any man in the ordinary circumstances of English life to possess himself of a piece of great art. A modern drawing of average merit, or a first-class engraving, may perhaps, not without some self-reproach, be purchased out of his savings by a man of narrow income; but a satisfactory example of first-rate art—masterhands' work—is wholly out of his reach. And we are so accustomed to look upon this as the natural course and necessity of things, that we never set ourselves in any wise to diminish the evil; and yet it is an evil perfectly capable of diminution. It is an evil precisely similar in kind to that which existed in the middle ages, respecting good books, and which everybody then, I suppose, thought as natural as we do now our small supply of good pictures. You could not then study the work of a great historian, or great poet, any more than you can now study that of a great painter, but at heavy cost. If you wanted a book, you had to get it written out for you, or to write it out for yourself. But printing came, and the poor man may read his Dante and his Homer; and Dante [Pg 49] and Homer are none the worse for that. But it is only in literature that private persons of moderate fortune can possess and study greatness: they can study at home no greatness in art; and the object of that accumulation which we are at present aiming at, as our third object in political economy, is to bring great art in some degree within the reach of the multitude; and, both in larger and more numerous galleries than we now possess, and by distribution, according to his wealth and wish, in each man's home, to render the influence of art somewhat correspondent in extent to that of literature. Here, then, is the subtle balance which your economist has to strike: to accumulate so much art as to be able to give the whole nation a supply of it, according to its need, and yet to regulate its distribution so that there shall be no glut of it, nor contempt.

In the meantime, getting back to our main point, I say to my generous listeners, who want to practically throw Titians and Turners at us like falling leaves, "Pictures shouldn't be too cheap;" but even more firmly I would say to those who want to keep the prices of artwork high, that pictures shouldn't be too expensive, meaning not as expensive as they are now. As things currently stand, it's practically impossible for anyone in the typical circumstances of English life to own a piece of great art. A modern drawing of average quality, or a top-notch engraving, might be bought—though perhaps with a bit of guilt—from the savings of someone with a low income; but a decent example of first-rate art—work from master artists—is entirely out of reach. We’ve become so used to seeing this as the natural order of things that we never really try to ease the problem; and yet it’s a problem that can definitely be fixed. It’s a problem similar to the one that existed in the Middle Ages regarding good books, which everyone back then probably thought was just as natural as we think our limited access to good pictures is now. Back then, you couldn’t study the work of a great historian or poet any more than you can study that of a great painter now without paying a lot. If you wanted a book, you had to have it copied for you or copy it yourself. But then printing came along, and now a poor person can read their Dante and Homer; and Dante and Homer aren’t any worse off for it. However, it’s only in literature that people of moderate means can own and study greatness; they can’t appreciate greatness in art at home. The goal we’re aiming for now, as our third objective in political economy, is to make great art more accessible to the general public; to have both larger and more numerous galleries than we currently have, and to distribute art according to each person’s wealth and interests in their own homes, thus allowing the influence of art to be somewhat comparable to that of literature. Here is the delicate balance that your economist has to find: to accumulate enough art to supply the entire nation based on its needs, while also regulating its distribution to prevent either a surplus or disdain.

A difficult balance, indeed, for us to hold, if it were left merely to our skill to poise; but the just point between poverty and profusion has been fixed for us accurately by the wise laws of Providence. If you carefully watch for all the genius you can detect, apply it to good service, and then reverently preserve what it produces, you will never have too little art; and if, on the other hand, you never force an artist to work hurriedly, for daily bread, nor imperfectly, because you would rather have showy works than complete ones, you will never have too much. Do not force the multiplication of art, and you will not have it too cheap; do not wantonly destroy it, and you will not have it too dear.

It's definitely a tough balance for us to maintain, especially if it depended solely on our ability to manage it. However, the right balance between scarcity and abundance has been accurately determined by the wise laws of Providence. If you pay close attention to all the creativity you can find, use it for good purposes, and then respectfully preserve what it creates, you'll never run out of art. On the flip side, if you never pressure an artist to work quickly for a paycheck, or push them to produce flashy pieces over complete ones, you'll never have too much. Don't try to force the increase of art, and it won't become too cheap; don't recklessly destroy it, and it won't be too expensive.

"But who wantonly destroys it?" you will ask. Why, we all do. Perhaps you thought, when I came to this part of our subject, corresponding to that set forth in our housewife's economy by the "keeping her embroidery from the moth," that I was going to tell you only how to take better care of pictures, how to clean them, and varnish them, and where to put them away safely when you went out of town. Ah, not at all. The utmost I have to ask of you is, that you will not pull them to pieces, and trample them under your feet. "What!" you will say, "when do we do such things? Haven't we built a perfectly beautiful gallery for all the pictures we have to take care of?" Yes, you have, for the pictures which are definitely sent to Manchester to be taken care of. But there[Pg 50] are quantities of pictures out of Manchester which it is your business, and mine too, to take care of no less than of these, and which we are at this moment employing ourselves in pulling to pieces by deputy. I will tell you what they are, and where they are, in a minute; only first let me state one more of those main principles of political economy on which the matter hinges.

"But who casually destroys it?" you might ask. Well, we all do. You might have thought that when I reached this part of our topic, similar to what a housewife does by "keeping her embroidery safe from moths," I was only going to explain how to take better care of pictures—how to clean and varnish them, and where to store them safely when you go out of town. But that's not the case at all. The most I ask of you is that you don’t tear them apart and stomp on them. "What!" you may say, "when do we do such things? Haven't we built a beautiful gallery to take care of all the pictures?" Yes, you have, for the pictures definitely sent to Manchester for safekeeping. But there[Pg 50] are plenty of pictures from Manchester that it’s your responsibility, and mine too, to care for just as much as these, and we are currently involved in tearing them apart through others. I'll tell you what they are and where they are in a minute; just let me first outline one more of those key principles of political economy on which this matter depends.

I must begin a little apparently wide of the mark, and ask you to reflect if there is any way in which we waste money more in England, than in building fine tombs? Our respect for the dead, when they are just dead, is something wonderful, and the way we show it more wonderful still. We show it with black feathers and black horses; we show it with black dresses and bright heraldries; we show it with costly obelisks and sculptures of sorrow, which spoil half of our most beautiful cathedrals. We show it with frightful gratings and vaults, and lids of dismal stone, in the midst of the quiet grass; and last, and not least, we show it by permitting ourselves to tell any number of lies we think amiable or credible, in the epitaph. This feeling is common to the poor as well as the rich, and we all know how many a poor family will nearly ruin themselves, to testify their respect for some member of it in his coffin, whom they never much cared for when he was out of it; and how often it happens that a poor old woman will starve herself to death, in order that she may be respectably buried.

I need to start off a bit off-topic and ask you to think about whether there's any way we waste more money in England than by building extravagant tombs. Our respect for the dead, especially when they’ve just passed away, is quite remarkable, and the ways we express it are even more striking. We express it with black feathers and black horses; we express it with black clothing and bright heraldry; we express it with expensive obelisks and sculptures of sorrow that ruin half of our most beautiful cathedrals. We express it with awful grates and vaults, and heavy stone lids in the middle of the peaceful grass; and finally, we express it by allowing ourselves to tell any number of lies that we believe are kind or credible in the epitaph. This sentiment is shared by both the poor and the rich, and we all know how many poor families will almost bankrupt themselves to show their respect for a family member in their coffin, someone they often didn't care much for when they were alive; and how frequently it happens that a poor old woman will starve herself just so she can afford a decent burial.

Now, this being one of the most complete and special ways of wasting money;—no money being less productive of good, or of any percentage whatever, than that which we shake away from the ends of undertakers' plumes—it is of course the duty of all good economists, and kind persons, to prove and proclaim continually, to the poor as well as the rich, that respect for the dead is not really shown by laying great stones on them to tell us where they are laid; but by remembering where they are laid, without a stone to help us; trusting them to the sacred grass and saddened flowers; and still more, that respect and love are shown to them, not by great monuments to them which we build with our hands, but by letting the monuments stand, which they built with their own. And this is the point now in question.[Pg 51]

Now, this is one of the most complete and unique ways to waste money; no money is less effective at doing good, or earning any return, than what we throw away on fancy funeral arrangements. It's the responsibility of all thoughtful economists and kind-hearted people to continuously remind both the poor and the rich that honoring the dead isn't really about placing huge stones to mark their graves. It's about remembering where they are without needing a stone for guidance, trusting them to the sacred grass and sorrowful flowers. Even more importantly, we show our respect and love not by constructing grand monuments with our hands, but by allowing the monuments they built with their own hands to stand. And this is the point up for discussion.[Pg 51]

Observe, there are two great reciprocal duties concerning industry, constantly to be exchanged between the living and the dead. We, as we live and work, are to be always thinking of those who are to come after us; that what we do may be serviceable, as far as we can make it so, to them as well as to us. Then, when we die, it is the duty of those who come after us to accept this work of ours with thanks and remembrance, not thrusting it aside or tearing it down the moment they think they have no use for it. And each generation will only be happy or powerful to the pitch that it ought to be, in fulfilling these two duties to the Past and the Future. Its own work will never be rightly done, even for itself—never good, or noble, or pleasurable to its own eyes—if it does not prepare it also for the eyes of generations yet to come. And its own possessions will never be enough for it, and its own wisdom never enough for it, unless it avails itself gratefully and tenderly of the treasures and the wisdom bequeathed to it by its ancestors.

Look, there are two important responsibilities regarding our work that we need to share between the living and the dead. As we live and strive, we should always think about those who will come after us, ensuring that what we do can be useful to them, just as it is to us. Then, when we pass away, it falls to those who follow to accept our work with gratitude and remembrance, not to push it aside or destroy it as soon as they think they don’t need it anymore. Each generation will only find true happiness or strength to the extent that it fulfills these two responsibilities to the Past and the Future. Its work will never be truly completed, even for its own sake—never good, noble, or enjoyable in its own view—if it doesn’t also prepare it for the eyes of future generations. Additionally, its possessions will never be sufficient, and its wisdom will never be enough, unless it wisely and lovingly embraces the gifts and knowledge passed down from its ancestors.

For, be assured, that all the best things and treasures of this world are not to be produced by each generation for itself; but we are all intended, not to carve our work in snow that will melt, but each and all of us to be continually rolling a great white gathering snowball, higher and higher—larger and larger—along the Alps of human power. Thus the science of nations is to be accumulative from father to son: each learning a little more and a little more; each receiving all that was known, and adding its own gain: the history and poetry of nations are to be accumulative; each generation treasuring the history and the songs of its ancestors, adding its own history and its own songs: and the art of nations is to be accumulative, just as science and history are; the work of living men not superseding, but building itself upon the work of the past. Nearly every great and intellectual race of the world has produced, at every period of its career, an art with some peculiar and precious character about it, wholly unattainable by any other race, and at any other time; and the intention of Providence concerning that art, is evidently that it should all grow together into one mighty temple; the rough stones and the smooth all finding their place, and rising, day by day, in richer and higher pinnacles to heaven.[Pg 52]

For be assured, all the best things and treasures in this world aren't meant to be created by each generation for itself; instead, we're all meant to keep rolling a huge snowball—getting bigger and bigger—up the mountains of human potential. The knowledge of nations should build on what's passed down from parents to children: each generation learning a bit more and more, receiving all that was known and adding its own discoveries. The history and poetry of nations should accumulate as well; each generation cherishing the history and songs of their ancestors while adding their own stories and songs. The art of nations is meant to accumulate, just like science and history; the work of living artists should not replace but rather build on the work of the past. Almost every great and intellectual culture has produced unique art at every stage of its journey, with a character that can't be found in any other culture or time. The intention of Providence for that art is clear: it should all grow together into one magnificent temple, with both rough and smooth stones finding their place, rising day by day to create richer and higher pinnacles towards heaven.[Pg 52]

Now, just fancy what a position the world, considered as one great workroom—one great factory in the form of a globe—would have been in by this time, if it had in the least understood this duty, or been capable of it. Fancy what we should have had around us now, if, instead of quarrelling and fighting over their work, the nations had aided each other in their work, or if even in their conquests, instead of effacing the memorials of those they succeeded and subdued, they had guarded the spoils of their victories. Fancy what Europe would be now, if the delicate statues and temples of the Greeks,—if the broad roads and massy walls of the Romans,—if the noble and pathetic architecture of the middle ages, had not been ground to dust by mere human rage. You talk of the scythe of Time, and the tooth of Time: I tell you, Time is scytheless and toothless; it is we who gnaw like the worm—we who smite like the scythe. It is ourselves who abolish—ourselves who consume: we are the mildew, and the flame, and the soul of man is to its own work as the moth, that frets when it cannot fly, and as the hidden flame that blasts where it cannot illumine. All these lost treasures of human intellect have been wholly destroyed by human industry of destruction; the marble would have stood its two thousand years as well in the polished statue as in the Parian cliff; but we men have ground it to powder, and mixed it with our own ashes. The walls and the ways would have stood—it is we who have left not one stone upon another, and restored its pathlessness to the desert; the great cathedrals of old religion would have stood—it is we who have dashed down the carved work with axes and hammers, and bid the mountain-grass bloom upon the pavement, and the sea-winds chaunt in the galleries.

Now, just imagine what a state the world, seen as one huge workspace—one massive factory shaped like a globe—would be in by now, if it had even slightly understood this responsibility or been capable of it. Picture what we would have around us today if, instead of arguing and fighting over their work, the nations had helped each other with their tasks, or if even in their conquests, instead of destroying the legacies of those they conquered, they had preserved the treasures of their victories. Think about what Europe would be now, if the delicate statues and temples of the Greeks—if the wide roads and sturdy walls of the Romans—if the amazing and moving architecture of the Middle Ages had not been ground to dust by sheer human anger. You speak of the scythe of Time and the teeth of Time; I say, Time is without a scythe and without teeth; it is we who gnaw like the worm—we who strike like the scythe. It is ourselves who destroy—ourselves who consume: we are the mildew and the flame, and the soul of man is to its work like the moth, which frets when it cannot fly, and like the hidden flame that destroys where it cannot illuminate. All these lost treasures of human thought have been entirely wiped out by humanity's ability to destroy; the marble would have lasted its two thousand years just as well in the polished statue as in the Parian cliff; but we humans have ground it to powder and mixed it with our own ashes. The walls and the roads would have survived—it is we who have left not one stone upon another and returned the landscape to a barren wasteland; the great cathedrals of old religion would have stood—it is we who have shattered the intricate work with axes and hammers, allowing the mountain grass to grow on the pavement and the sea winds to sing in the galleries.

You will perhaps think all this was somehow necessary for the development of the human race. I cannot stay now to dispute that, though I would willingly; but do you think it is still necessary for that development? Do you think that in this nineteenth century it is still necessary for the European nations to turn all the places where their principal art-treasures are into battle-fields? For that is what they are doing even while I speak; the great firm of the world is managing its business at this moment, just as it has done in past time.[Pg 53] Imagine what would be the thriving circumstances of a manufacturer of some delicate produce—suppose glass, or china—in whose workshop and exhibition rooms all the workmen and clerks began fighting at least once a day, first blowing off the steam, and breaking all the machinery they could reach; and then making fortresses of all the cupboards, and attacking and defending the show-tables, the victorious party finally throwing everything they could get hold of out of the window, by way of showing their triumph, and the poor manufacturer picking up and putting away at last a cup here and a handle there. A fine prosperous business that would be, would it not? and yet that is precisely the way the great manufacturing firm of the world carries on its business.

You might think all of this was somehow needed for the advancement of humanity. I can’t debate that right now, though I would like to; but do you really think it’s still necessary for that progress? Do you believe that in this nineteenth century, European nations still need to turn all the places where their most important art treasures are into battlefields? Because that’s exactly what they’re doing as I speak; the major players on the world stage are running their businesses just as they did in the past.[Pg 53] Imagine how thriving a manufacturer of delicate items—like glass or china—would be if in their workshop and exhibition space all the workers and clerks started fighting at least once a day, first letting off steam and breaking all the machinery they could reach; then making fortresses out of all the cupboards, attacking and defending the display tables, with the winning side finally throwing everything they could find out of the window to celebrate their victory, while the poor manufacturer picked up and put away a cup here and a handle there. That would be quite a successful business, wouldn’t it? Yet that’s exactly how the major manufacturing firm of the world operates.

It has so arranged its political squabbles for the last six or seven hundred years, that not one of them could be fought out but in the midst of its most precious art; and it so arranges them to this day. For example, if I were asked to lay my finger, in a map of the world, on the spot of the world's surface which contained at this moment the most singular concentration of art-teaching and art-treasure, I should lay it on the name of the town of Verona. Other cities, indeed, contain more works of carriageable art, but none contain so much of the glorious local art, and of the springs and sources of art, which can by no means be made subjects of package or porterage, nor, I grieve to say, of salvage. Verona possesses, in the first place, not the largest, but the most perfect and intelligible Roman amphitheatre that exists, still unbroken in circle of step, and strong in succession of vault and arch: it contains minor Roman monuments, gateways, theatres, baths, wrecks of temples, which give the streets of its suburbs a character of antiquity unexampled elsewhere, except in Rome itself. But it contains, in the next place, what Rome does not contain—perfect examples of the great twelfth-century Lombardic architecture, which was the root of all the mediæval art of Italy, without which no Giottos, no Angelicos, no Raphaels would have been possible: it contains that architecture, not in rude forms, but in the most perfect and loveliest types it ever attained—contains those, not in ruins, nor in altered and hardly decipherable fragments, but in churches perfect from[Pg 54] porch to apse, with all their carving fresh, their pillars firm, their joints unloosened. Besides these, it includes examples of the great thirteenth- and fourteenth-century Gothic of Italy, not merely perfect, but elsewhere unrivalled. At Rome, the Roman—at Pisa, the Lombard, architecture may be seen in greater or in equal nobleness; but not at Rome, nor Pisa, nor Florence, nor in any city of the world, is there a great mediæval Gothic like the Gothic of Verona. Elsewhere, it is either less pure in type or less lovely in completion: only at Verona may you see it in the simplicity of its youthful power, and the tenderness of its accomplished beauty. And Verona possesses, in the last place, the loveliest Renaissance architecture of Italy, not disturbed by pride, nor defiled by luxury, but rising in fair fulfilment of domestic service, serenity of effortless grace, and modesty of home seclusion; its richest work given to the windows that open on the narrowest streets and most silent gardens. All this she possesses, in the midst of natural scenery such as assuredly exists nowhere else in the habitable globe—a wild Alpine river foaming at her feet, from whose shore the rocks rise in a great crescent, dark with cypress, and misty with olive: illimitably, from before her southern gates, the tufted plains of Italy sweep and fade in golden light; around her, north and west, the Alps crowd in crested troops, and the winds of Benacus bear to her the coolness of their snows.

It has managed its political conflicts for the last six or seven hundred years in such a way that none of them could be resolved except amidst its most valuable art, and it continues to do so today. For instance, if I were asked to pinpoint, on a world map, the exact location that currently holds the most remarkable concentration of art education and art treasures, I would place my finger on the town of Verona. Other cities may have more works of transportable art, but none hold as much of the exceptional local art and the roots and sources of art that cannot be packaged, moved, or, I'm sorry to say, salvaged. Verona boasts, firstly, not the largest but the most complete and understandable Roman amphitheater that exists, still intact in its circular steps, and strong in its series of vaults and arches. It includes minor Roman monuments, gateways, theaters, baths, and the remains of temples, which give the streets of its outskirts a sense of ancient character unmatched anywhere else, except in Rome itself. Additionally, it holds what Rome does not possess—perfect examples of the stunning twelfth-century Lombard architecture, which was the foundation of all medieval art in Italy; without it, there would be no Giottos, no Angelicos, no Raphaels. This architecture is present, not in crude forms, but in the most perfect and beautiful styles it ever achieved—not in ruins or broken fragments, but in churches that are perfect from porch to apse, with all their carvings fresh, their pillars strong, and their joints tight. Moreover, it includes stunning examples of the great thirteenth- and fourteenth-century Gothic architecture of Italy, not only complete but also unparalleled elsewhere. In Rome, the Roman style and in Pisa, the Lombard style may be seen with equal or greater nobility; however, no city in the world, not Rome, Pisa, Florence, or any other, has a Gothic style as grand as that of Verona. Elsewhere, it is either less pure in design or less beautiful in execution: only in Verona can you see it in the simplicity of its youthful strength and the delicacy of its fully realized beauty. Finally, Verona is home to some of the most beautiful Renaissance architecture in Italy, untainted by arrogance or spoiled by opulence, rising gracefully in the fulfillment of its domestic purpose, with a calm and effortless charm, and modest in its home-like setting; its finest work is seen in the windows that overlook the narrowest streets and quietest gardens. All of this exists alongside natural scenery that surely cannot be found anywhere else on Earth—a wild Alpine river rushing at her feet, from whose banks the rocks rise in a grand crescent, darkened with cypress trees and misty with olive groves: endlessly, from her southern gates, the lush plains of Italy stretch out and fade in golden light; surrounding her, to the north and west, the Alps gather in majestic formations, and the winds from Benacus bring her the coolness of their snow.

And this is the city—such, and possessing such things as these—at whose gates the decisive battles of Italy are fought continually: three days her towers trembled with the echo of the cannon of Arcola; heaped pebbles of the Mincio divide her fields to this hour with lines of broken rampart, whence the tide of war rolled back to Novara; and now on that crescent of her eastern cliffs, whence the full moon used to rise through the bars of the cypresses in her burning summer twilights, touching with soft increase of silver light the rosy marbles of her balconies—along the ridge of that encompassing rock, other circles are increasing now, white and pale; walled towers of cruel strength, sable-spotted with cannon-courses. I tell you, I have seen, when the thunderclouds came down on those Italian hills, and all their crags were dipped in the dark, terrible[Pg 55] purple, as if the winepress of the wrath of God had stained their mountain-raiment—I have seen the hail fall in Italy till the forest branches stood stripped and bare as if blasted by the locust; but the white hail never fell from those clouds of heaven as the black hail will fall from the clouds of hell, if ever one breath of Italian life stirs again in the streets of Verona.

And this is the city—just like this and having things like these—where the decisive battles of Italy are constantly fought: for three days, her towers shook with the sound of the cannons from Arcola; the piles of stones from the Mincio still mark her fields with lines of broken walls, from where the wave of war pushed back to Novara; and now on that curve of her eastern cliffs, where the full moon used to rise through the cypress trees in her hot summer evenings, softly illuminating the pink marbles of her balconies with a silver glow—along the top of that surrounding rock, other circles are growing now, pale and white; walled towers of brutal strength, marked with cannon paths. I tell you, I have seen, when dark clouds descended on those Italian hills, and all their peaks were soaked in a dark, terrible purple, as if the wrath of God had stained their mountain clothes—I have seen the hail fall in Italy until the forest branches were left stripped and bare as if they had been destroyed by locusts; but the white hail never fell from those clouds of heaven as the black hail will fall from the clouds of hell, if even one breath of Italian life stirs again in the streets of Verona.

Sad as you will feel this to be, I do not say that you can directly prevent it; you cannot drive the Austrians out of Italy, nor prevent them from building forts where they choose. But I do say,[12] that you, and I, and all of us, ought to be both acting and feeling with a full knowledge and understanding of these things, and that, without trying to excite revolutions or weaken governments, we may give our own thoughts and [Pg 56] help, so as in a measure to prevent needless destruction. We should do this, if we only realized the thing thoroughly. You drive out day by day through your own pretty suburbs, and you think only of making, with what money you have to spare, your gateways handsomer, and your carriage-drives wider—and your drawing-rooms more splendid, having a vague notion that you are all the while patronizing and advancing art, and you make no effort to conceal the fact, that within a few hours' journey of you, there are gateways and drawing-rooms which might just as well be yours as these, all built already; gateways built by the greatest masters of sculpture that ever struck marble; drawing-rooms, painted by Titian and Veronese; and you won't accept, nor save these as they are, but you will rather fetch the house-painter from over the way, and let Titian and Veronese house the rats. "Yes," of course, you answer; "we want nice houses here, not houses in Verona. What should we do with houses in Verona?" And I answer, do precisely what you do with the most expensive part of your possessions here: take pride in them—only a noble pride. You know well, when you examine your own hearts, that the greater part of the sums you spend on possessions are spent for pride. Why are your carriages nicely painted and finished outside? You don't see the outsides as you sit in them—the outsides are for other people to see. Why are your exteriors of houses so well finished, your furniture so polished and costly, but for other people to see? You are just as comfortable yourselves, writing on your old friend of a desk, with the white cloudings in his leather, and using the light of a window which is nothing but a hole in the brick wall. And all that is desirable to be done in this matter, is merely to take pride in preserving great art, instead of in producing mean art; pride in the possession of precious and enduring things, a little way off, instead of slight and perishing things near at hand. You know, in old English times, our kings liked to have lordships and dukedoms abroad, and why should not you merchant princes like to have lordships and estates abroad? Believe me, rightly understood, it would be a prouder, and in the full sense of our English word, more "respectable" thing to be lord of a palace at Verona, or of a cloister full of frescos at Florence, [Pg 57] than to have a file of servants dressed in the finest liveries that ever tailor stitched, as long as would reach from here to Bolton:—yes, and a prouder thing to send people to travel in Italy, who would have to say every now and then, of some fair piece of art, "Ah! this was kept here for us by the good people of Manchester," than to bring them travelling all the way here, exclaiming of your various art treasures, "These were brought here for us, (not altogether without harm) by the good people of Manchester." "Ah!" but you say, "the Art Treasures Exhibition will pay; but Veronese palaces won't." Pardon me. They would pay, less directly, but far more richly. Do you suppose it is in the long run good for Manchester, or good for England, that the Continent should be in the state it is? Do you think the perpetual fear of revolution, or the perpetual repression of thought and energy that clouds and encumbers the nations of Europe, is eventually profitable for us? Were we any the better of the course of affairs in '48; or has the stabling of the dragoon horses in the great houses of Italy, any distinct effect in the promotion of the cotton-trade? Not so. But every stake that you could hold in the stability of the Continent, and every effort that you could make to give example of English habits and principles on the Continent, and every kind deed that you could do in relieving distress and preventing despair on the Continent, would have tenfold reaction on the prosperity of England, and open and urge, in a thousand unforeseen directions, the sluices of commerce and the springs of industry.

Sad as this may sound, I’m not saying you can stop it directly; you can't force the Austrians out of Italy or stop them from building forts wherever they want. But I do say, [12] that you, me, and all of us should be acting and feeling with full awareness and understanding of these issues. Without trying to incite revolutions or undermine governments, we can channel our thoughts and support to help prevent unnecessary destruction. We should do this if we truly understood the situation. You drive through your lovely neighborhoods every day, focusing on making your entrances look nicer, your driveways wider, and your living rooms more luxurious—kind of thinking you're promoting art while ignoring the fact that just a few hours away, there are entrances and living rooms that could just as easily belong to you, already built; entrances crafted by the greatest sculptors ever to work with marble; living rooms painted by Titian and Veronese. Yet, instead of accepting or preserving these as they are, you'd rather hire a house painter from down the street and let Titian and Veronese be forgotten. "Yes," you say, "we want nice houses here, not houses in Verona. What would we do with houses in Verona?” And I say, do exactly what you do with the most expensive things you own here: take pride in them—just a noble kind of pride. You know in your heart that the majority of the money you spend is spent for pride. Why are your carriages beautifully painted and finished? You don’t see the outsides as you ride in them; they’re for everyone else to admire. Why are your house exteriors so well-finished, and your furniture so shiny and expensive? It’s all for others to see. You’re just as comfortable writing at your old, well-loved desk with its worn leather and using the light from a window that’s just a hole in the wall. All that needs to be done in this situation is simply to take pride in preserving great art rather than in creating mediocre art; pride in owning valuable and lasting things far away instead of cheap and temporary things close by. You know that in old England, our kings liked to have lordships and estates abroad, so why shouldn’t you merchant princes want the same? I assure you, if viewed properly, it would be a prouder and, in every sense of the word, more "respectable" thing to own a palace in Verona or a cloister full of frescoes in Florence, than to have a line of servants dressed in the finest uniforms that would reach from here to Bolton. Yes, and it would be more impressive to send people to travel in Italy, who would occasionally say of some beautiful artwork, “Ah! this was kept here for us by the good people of Manchester,” than to bring them to your place here, boasting about your various art treasures, “These were brought here for us (not without some cost) by the good people of Manchester.” “Ah!” but you say, “the Art Treasures Exhibition will pay off; but Veronese palaces won’t.” Excuse me. They would provide returns, not directly, but far richer in value. Do you think it’s good for Manchester or for England that the Continent is in its current state? Do you think the constant fear of revolution or the continuous suppression of thought and energy that burdens Europe is ultimately beneficial for us? Were we any better off after the events of ’48, or has having dragoons stabled in the grand houses of Italy helped the cotton trade? Not at all. But every investment you could make in the stability of the Continent, every effort to showcase English habits and principles there, and every act of kindness to relieve suffering and prevent despair would pay back tenfold in the prosperity of England, opening doors to commerce and industry in a thousand unexpected ways.

I could press, if I chose, both these motives upon you, of pride and self-interest, with more force, but these are not motives which ought to be urged upon you at all. The only motive that I ought to put before you is simply that it would be right to do this; that the holding of property abroad, and the personal efforts of Englishmen to redeem the condition of foreign nations, are among the most direct pieces of duty which our wealth renders incumbent upon us. I do not—and in all truth and deliberateness I say this—I do not know anything more ludicrous among the self-deceptions of well-meaning people than their notion of patriotism, as requiring them to limit their efforts to the good of their own country;[Pg 58]—the notion that charity is a geographical virtue, and that what it is holy and righteous to do for people on one bank of a river, it is quite improper and unnatural to do for people on the other. It will be a wonderful thing, some day or other, for the Christian world to remember, that it went on thinking for two thousand years that neighbours were neighbours at Jerusalem, but not at Jericho; a wonderful thing for us English to reflect, in after-years, how long it was before we could shake hands with anybody across that shallow salt wash, which the very chalk-dust of its two shores whitens from Folkestone to Ambleteuse.

I could push both these motives of pride and self-interest on you even harder, but honestly, those aren’t the reasons I should focus on. The only reason I should present to you is that it’s simply the right thing to do; that owning property abroad and the efforts of English people to improve the situation of foreign nations are some of the most direct responsibilities our wealth requires of us. I genuinely— and I say this with all sincerity— don’t understand anything more ridiculous among the self-deceptions of well-meaning people than their idea of patriotism, which makes them think they should limit their efforts to the good of their own country; the idea that charity is a geographical virtue, and that it’s perfectly acceptable to help people on one side of a river but completely wrong to do the same for those on the other side. It will be remarkable for the Christian world to realize someday that for two thousand years, it thought of neighbors as being only those in Jerusalem, but not in Jericho; a remarkable thing for us English to look back on in the future and think about how long it took for us to be able to shake hands with anyone across that narrow stretch of salt water, which is so thin that the chalk dust from both shores can be seen from Folkestone to Ambleteuse.[Pg 58]

Nor ought the motive of gratitude, as well as that of mercy, to be without its influence on you, who have been the first to ask to see, and the first to show to us, the treasures which this poor lost Italy has given to England. Remember all these things that delight you here were hers—hers either in fact or in teaching; hers, in fact, are all the most powerful and most touching paintings of old time that now glow upon your walls; hers in teaching are all the best and greatest of descendant souls—your Reynolds and your Gainsborough never could have painted but for Venice; and the energies which have given the only true life to your existing art were first stirred by voices of the dead, that haunted the Sacred Field of Pisa.

Nor should gratitude, along with mercy, be without its impact on you, who have been the first to request to see, and the first to show us, the treasures that this poor lost Italy has given to England. Remember that everything you enjoy here originally belonged to her—either in reality or in inspiration; in reality, all the most powerful and moving paintings from the past that now illuminate your walls are hers; in inspiration, all the best and greatest of your artists—your Reynolds and your Gainsborough—could never have painted without Venice; and the creative energies that have breathed true life into your current art were first ignited by the voices of the dead that lingered in the Sacred Field of Pisa.

Well, all these motives for some definite course of action on our part towards foreign countries rest upon very serious facts; too serious, perhaps you will think, to be interfered with; for we are all of us in the habit of leaving great things alone, as if Providence would mind them, and attending ourselves only to little things which we know, practically, Providence doesn't mind unless we do. We are ready enough to give care to the growing of pines and lettuces, knowing that they don't grow Providentially sweet or large unless we look after them; but we don't give any care to the good of Italy or Germany, because we think that they will grow Providentially happy without any of our meddling.

Well, all these reasons for taking a clear course of action towards foreign countries are based on really serious facts; maybe too serious for us to interfere with. We tend to leave big things alone, as if Providence would take care of them, while we focus on small things that we know, practically, Providence won’t manage unless we do. We’re more than willing to pay attention to growing pines and lettuce, knowing that they won’t grow sweet or big on their own unless we care for them; but we don’t bother to think about the well-being of Italy or Germany, because we assume they will somehow become happy without any of our intervention.

Let us leave the great things, then, and think of little things; not of the destruction of whole provinces in war, which it may not be any business of ours to prevent; but of the destruction of poor little pictures in peace, from which it surely would not[Pg 59] be much out of our way to save them. You know I said, just now, we were all of us engaged in pulling pictures to pieces by deputy, and you did not believe me. Consider, then, this similitude of ourselves. Suppose you saw (as I doubt not you often do see) a prudent and kind young lady sitting at work, in the corner of a quiet room, knitting comforters for her cousins, and that just outside, in the hall, you saw a cat and her kittens at play among the family pictures; amusing themselves especially with the best Vandykes, by getting on the tops of the frames, and then scrambling down the canvasses by their claws; and on someone's informing the young lady of these proceedings of the cat and kittens, suppose she answered that it wasn't her cat, but her sister's, and the pictures weren't hers, but her uncle's, and she couldn't leave her work, for she had to make so many pairs of comforters before dinner. Would you not say that the prudent and kind young lady was, on the whole, answerable for the additional touches of claw on the Vandykes? Now, that is precisely what we prudent and kind English are doing, only on a larger scale. Here we sit in Manchester, hard at work, very properly, making comforters for our cousins all over the world. Just outside there in the hall—that beautiful marble hall of Italy—the cats and kittens and monkeys are at play among the pictures: I assure you, in the course of the fifteen years in which I have been working in those places in which the most precious remnants of European art exist, a sensation, whether I would or no, was gradually made distinct and deep in my mind, that I was living and working in the midst of a den of monkeys;—sometimes amiable and affectionate monkeys, with all manner of winning ways and kind intentions;—more frequently selfish and malicious monkeys, but, whatever their disposition, squabbling continually about nuts, and the best places on the barren sticks of trees; and that all this monkeys' den was filled, by mischance, with precious pictures, and the witty and wilful beasts were always wrapping themselves up and going to sleep in pictures, or tearing holes in them to grin through; or tasting them and spitting them out again, or twisting them up into ropes and making swings of them; and that sometimes only, by watching one's opportunity, and bearing[Pg 60] a scratch or a bite, one could rescue the corner of a Tintoret, or Paul Veronese, and push it through the bars into a place of safety. Literally, I assure you, this was, and this is, the fixed impression on my mind of the state of matters in Italy. And see how. The professors of art in Italy, having long followed a method of study peculiar to themselves, have at last arrived at a form of art peculiar to themselves; very different from that which was arrived at by Correggio and Titian. Naturally, the professors like their own form the best; and, as the old pictures are generally not so startling to the eye as the modern ones, the dukes and counts who possess them, and who like to see their galleries look new and fine (and are persuaded also that a celebrated chef-d'œuvre ought always to catch the eye at a quarter of a mile off), believe the professors who tell them their sober pictures are quite faded, and good for nothing, and should all be brought bright again; and, accordingly, give the sober pictures to the professors, to be put right by rules of art. Then, the professors repaint the old pictures in all the principal places, leaving perhaps only a bit of background to set off their own work. And thus the professors come to be generally figured in my mind, as the monkeys who tear holes in the pictures, to grin through. Then the picture-dealers, who live by the pictures, cannot sell them to the English in their old and pure state; all the good work must be covered with new paint, and varnished so as to look like one of the professorial pictures in the great gallery, before it is saleable. And thus the dealers come to be imaged, in my mind, as the monkeys who make ropes of the pictures, to swing by. Then, every now and then, in some old stable or wine-cellar, or timber-shed, behind some forgotten vats or faggots, somebody finds a fresco of Perugino's or Giotto's, but doesn't think much of it, and has no idea of having people coming into his cellar, or being obliged to move his faggots; and so he whitewashes the fresco, and puts the faggots back again; and these kind of persons, therefore, come generally to be imaged in my mind, as the monkeys who taste the pictures, and spit them out, not finding them nice. While, finally, the squabbling for nuts and apples (called in Italy "bella libertà") goes on all day long.[Pg 61]

Let's focus on small things instead of the big ones; not the destruction of entire provinces in war, which may not be our responsibility to prevent, but the destruction of poor little pictures in peace, which it wouldn't take much effort for us to save. You know I just mentioned that we are all involved in tearing pictures apart through others, and you didn’t believe me. Think of this comparison of ourselves. Imagine you saw, as I’m sure you often do, a sensible and kind young woman sitting in the corner of a quiet room, knitting blankets for her cousins, while just outside, in the hallway, a cat and her kittens are playing among the family pictures; amusing themselves especially with the best artworks, climbing on top of the frames, and then scampering down the canvases with their claws. If someone told the young woman about the cat and kittens’ antics, and she responded that it wasn’t her cat but her sister's, and that the pictures didn’t belong to her but to her uncle, and she couldn’t leave her work because she needed to finish several blankets before dinner, wouldn’t you say that the sensible and kind young woman was, in some way, responsible for the extra claw marks on the artworks? That’s exactly what we sensible and kind English are doing, just on a larger scale. Here we are sitting in Manchester, diligently making blankets for our cousins all over the world. Just outside there in that beautiful marble hallway of Italy, the cats, kittens, and monkeys are playing among the pictures: I assure you, over the fifteen years I’ve spent working in places where the most precious remnants of European art exist, a feeling, whether I wanted it to or not, gradually formed in my mind that I was living and working in a den of monkeys; sometimes friendly and affectionate monkeys, full of charming behavior and good intentions; but more often selfish and spiteful monkeys, constantly arguing over nuts and the best spots on barren tree branches; and that this monkey den was filled, by misfortune, with precious pictures, and those witty and mischievous creatures were always wrapping themselves up and going to sleep on the pictures, or tearing holes in them to peek through; or tasting them and spitting them out again, or twisting them into ropes to make swings; and that sometimes, by seizing the opportunity and enduring a scratch or a bite, one could save the corner of a Tintoretto or Paul Veronese and push it through the bars to safety. Literally, I assure you, this is the fixed impression on my mind of the situation in Italy. And look how. The art professors in Italy, following their unique method of study for a long time, have finally developed their own form of art, which is quite different from that created by Correggio and Titian. Naturally, the professors prefer their own style; and since the old pieces usually aren’t as eye-catching as the modern ones, the dukes and counts who own them, who want their galleries to look new and impressive (and are also convinced that a celebrated masterpiece should catch the eye from a quarter of a mile away), believe the professors who tell them their aging pictures are faded and worthless and should be restored to brightness; and so, they give the old pictures to the professors to be fixed according to art rules. Then, the professors repaint the old pictures in all the main areas, perhaps leaving just a bit of the background to highlight their own work. As a result, the professors come to mind as the monkeys who tear holes in the pictures to grin through. Then, the art dealers, who rely on the pictures for their livelihood, can’t sell them to the English in their original and pure state; all the good work must be covered with fresh paint and varnished to resemble one of the professors' works in a great gallery before it can be sold. Thus, the dealers become imaged in my mind as the monkeys who twist the pictures into ropes to swing by. Then, now and then, in some old stable or wine cellar, or lumber shed, hidden behind forgotten barrels or bundles, someone discovers a fresco by Perugino or Giotto but doesn’t think much of it, and has no intention of letting people into his cellar or moving his bundles; so he whitewashes the fresco and puts the bundles back; and these people tend to be seen in my mind as the monkeys who taste the pictures, finding them unappealing and spitting them out. Meanwhile, the bickering over nuts and apples (referred to in Italy as "bella libertà") goes on all day long.

Now, all this might soon be put an end to, if we English, who are so fond of travelling in the body, would also travel a little in soul. We think it a great triumph to get our packages and our persons carried at a fast pace, but we never take the slightest trouble to put any pace into our perceptions; we stay usually at home in thought, or if we ever mentally see the world, it is at the old stage-coach or waggon rate. Do but consider what an odd sight it would be, if it were only quite clear to you how things are really going on—how, here in England, we are making enormous and expensive efforts to produce new art of all kinds, knowing and confessing all the while that the greater part of it is bad, but struggling still to produce new patterns of wall-papers, and new shapes of tea-pots, and new pictures, and statues, and architecture; and pluming and cackling if ever a tea-pot or a picture has the least good in it;—all the while taking no thought whatever of the best possible pictures, and statues, and wall-patterns already in existence, which require nothing but to be taken common care of, and kept from damp and dust: but we let the walls fall that Giotto patterned, and the canvasses rot that Tintoret painted, and the architecture be dashed to pieces that St. Louis built, while we are furnishing our drawing-rooms with prize upholstery, and writing accounts of our handsome warehouses to the country papers. Don't think I use my words vaguely or generally: I speak of literal facts. Giotto's frescos at Assisi are perishing at this moment for want of decent care; Tintoret's pictures in San Sebastian at Venice, are at this instant rotting piecemeal into grey rags; St. Louis's Chapel, at Carcassonne, is at this moment lying in shattered fragments in the market-place. And here we are all cawing and crowing, poor little half-fledged daws as we are, about the pretty sticks and wool in our own nests. There's hardly a day passes, when I am at home, but I get a letter from some well-meaning country clergyman, deeply anxious about the state of his parish church, and breaking his heart to get money together that he may hold up some wretched remnant of Tudor tracery, with one niche in the corner and no statue—when all the while the mightiest piles of religious architecture and sculpture that ever the world saw are being blasted and withered away, without one glance[Pg 62] of pity or regret. The country clergyman does not care for them—he has a sea-sick imagination that cannot cross Channel. What is it to him, if the angels of Assisi fade from its vaults, or the queens and kings of Chartres fall from their pedestals? They are not in his parish.

Now, all this might soon come to an end if we English, who love to travel physically, would also take some time to explore spiritually. We think it’s a huge achievement to have our luggage and ourselves moved quickly, but we never bother to enhance our understanding; we usually stay home in our thoughts, and if we ever envision the world, it’s at the slow pace of an old stagecoach or wagon. Just imagine how strange it would be if it were crystal clear to you how things really are—how, here in England, we are putting in massive and costly efforts to create new art of all kinds, fully aware that most of it is not good, yet still pushing to produce new designs for wallpaper, new shapes for teapots, and new paintings, statues, and buildings; and puffing ourselves up and making a fuss whenever a teapot or picture has even a hint of quality—while completely ignoring the best art—pictures, statues, and wallpaper—that already exists, which just needs to be properly cared for and protected from moisture and dust: yet we let the walls designed by Giotto crumble, the canvases painted by Tintoret rot away, and the architecture built by St. Louis be destroyed, all while we’re decorating our living rooms with award-winning upholstery and writing articles about our beautiful warehouses for local papers. Don't think I’m being vague or general: I'm referring to actual facts. Giotto's frescos in Assisi are deteriorating right now due to a lack of proper care; Tintoret's paintings in San Sebastian in Venice are disintegrating into grey rags as we speak; St. Louis's Chapel in Carcassonne is currently in shattered pieces in the marketplace. And here we are, all squawking and bragging, poor little half-developed crows that we are, about the pretty things in our own homes. Hardly a day goes by when I’m at home that I don’t receive a letter from some well-meaning country clergyman, genuinely worried about the state of his parish church, desperately trying to raise money to preserve some pitiful fragment of Tudor design, with a single niche in the corner and no statue—while all the magnificent works of religious architecture and sculpture that the world has ever seen are being destroyed and fading away, without a single glance of compassion or regret. The country clergyman doesn’t care about them—his imagination is too limited to reach across the Channel. What does it matter to him if the angels in Assisi vanish from the ceilings, or if the kings and queens of Chartres topple from their pedestals? They’re not in his parish.

"What!" you will say, "are we not to produce any new art, nor take care of our parish churches?" No, certainly not, until you have taken proper care of the art you have got already, and of the best churches out of the parish. Your first and proper standing is not as churchwardens and parish overseers in an English county, but as members of the great Christian community of Europe. And as members of that community (in which alone, observe, pure and precious ancient art exists, for there is none in America, none in Asia, none in Africa), you conduct yourselves precisely as a manufacturer would, who attended to his looms, but left his warehouse without a roof. The rain floods your warehouse, the rats frolic in it, the spiders spin in it, the choughs build in it, the wall-plague frets and festers in it, and still you keep weave, weave, weaving at your wretched webs, and thinking you are growing rich, while more is gnawed out of your warehouse in an hour than you can weave in a twelvemonth.

"What!" you might say, "are we not supposed to create new art or take care of our local churches?" No, definitely not, until you've properly cared for the art you already have and the best churches outside the parish. Your primary role is not as churchwardens and parish overseers in an English county, but as members of the broader Christian community in Europe. And as members of that community (where, note, only pure and valuable ancient art exists—there's none in America, none in Asia, none in Africa), you’re acting just like a manufacturer who looks after his machines but leaves his warehouse without a roof. Rain floods your warehouse, rats play around in it, spiders spin webs in it, choughs build nests in it, and decay eats away at it, yet you keep weaving, weaving, weaving your miserable threads, believing you're becoming wealthy, while more is destroyed in your warehouse in an hour than you can weave in a year.

Even this similitude is not absurd enough to set us rightly forth. The weaver would, or might, at least, hope that his new woof was as stout as the old ones, and that, therefore, in spite of rain and ravage, he would have something to wrap himself in when he needed it. But our webs rot as we spin. The very fact that we despise the great art of the past shows that we cannot produce great art now. If we could do it, we should love it when we saw it done—if we really cared for it, we should recognise it and keep it; but we don't care for it. It is not art that we want; it is amusement, gratification of pride, present gain—anything in the world but art: let it rot, we shall always have enough to talk about and hang over our sideboards.

Even this comparison isn’t absurd enough to truly represent us. The weaver would likely hope that his new fabric is as strong as the old ones, and thus, in spite of rain and wear, he’d have something to cover himself with when he needs it. But our creations deteriorate as we make them. The fact that we look down on the great art of the past indicates that we can't create great art now. If we could do it, we would appreciate it when we see it done—if we truly cared about it, we would recognize it and hold onto it; but we don’t care about it. It’s not art that we want; it’s entertainment, a boost to our pride, immediate rewards—anything but art: let it decay, we’ll always have enough to discuss and display on our sideboards.

You will (I hope) finally ask me what is the outcome of all this, practicable, to-morrow morning by us who are sitting here? These are the main practical outcomes of it: In the first place, don't grumble when you hear of a new picture being bought by Government at a large price. There are[Pg 63] many pictures in Europe now in danger of destruction which are, in the true sense of the word, priceless; the proper price is simply that which it is necessary to give to get and to save them. If you can get them for fifty pounds, do; if not for less than a hundred, do; if not for less than five thousand, do; if not for less than twenty thousand, do; never mind being imposed upon: there is nothing disgraceful in being imposed upon; the only disgrace is in imposing; and you can't in general get anything much worth having, in the way of Continental art, but it must be with the help or connivance of numbers of people who, indeed, ought to have nothing to do with the matter, but who practically have, and always will have, everything to do with it; and if you don't choose to submit to be cheated by them out of a ducat here and a zecchin there, you will be cheated by them out of your picture; and whether you are most imposed upon in losing that, or the zecchins, I think I may leave you to judge; though I know there are many political economists, who would rather leave a bag of gold on a garret-table, than give a porter sixpence extra to carry it downstairs.

You will (I hope) finally ask me what the outcome of all this is, which is practical for us sitting here tomorrow morning? Here are the main practical outcomes: First, don’t complain when you hear about a new painting being purchased by the government for a high price. There are[Pg 63] many artworks in Europe at risk of being destroyed that are truly priceless; the right price is just whatever it takes to acquire and save them. If you can get them for fifty pounds, do it; if not for less than a hundred, do it; if not for less than five thousand, do it; if not for less than twenty thousand, do it; don’t worry about being taken advantage of: there’s nothing shameful in being taken advantage of; the only shame is in taking advantage of others. Generally, you can’t get anything worthwhile in Continental art without the help or involvement of a lot of people who, frankly, should have no part in it but practically do and always will have a hand in it; and if you don’t want to be cheated out of a ducat here and a zecchin there, you’ll end up being cheated out of your painting. Whether losing that is more of a loss than the zecchins, I’ll let you decide; although I know many economists who would rather leave a bag of gold on a table in a garret than give a porter an extra sixpence to carry it downstairs.

That, then, is the first practical outcome of the matter. Never grumble, but be glad when you hear of a new picture being bought at a large price. In the long run, the dearest pictures are always the best bargains; and, I repeat (for else you might think I said it in mere hurry of talk, and not deliberately), there are some pictures which are without price. You should stand, nationally, at the edge of Dover cliffs—Shakespeare's—and wave blank cheques in the eyes of the nations on the other side of the sea, freely offered, for such and such canvasses of theirs.

That, then, is the first practical outcome of the situation. Never complain, but be happy when you hear about a new painting being sold for a high price. In the long run, the most expensive paintings are always the best deals; and I emphasize (so you understand I’m not just saying this off the cuff) that some paintings are priceless. You should stand, as a nation, at the edge of the Dover cliffs—Shakespeare's—and wave blank checks in front of the countries across the sea, offered without hesitation, for specific canvases of theirs.

Then the next practical outcome of it is: Never buy a copy of a picture, under any circumstances whatever. All copies are bad; because no painter who is worth a straw ever will copy. He will make a study of a picture he likes, for his own use, in his own way; but he won't and can't copy; whenever you buy a copy, you buy so much misunderstanding of the original, and encourage a dull person in following a business he is not fit for, besides increasing ultimately chances of mistake and imposture, and farthering, as directly as money[Pg 64] can farther, the cause of ignorance in all directions. You may, in fact, consider yourself as having purchased a certain quantity of mistakes; and, according to your power, being engaged in disseminating them.

Then the next practical outcome of this is: Never buy a copy of a picture, under any circumstances. All copies are bad; because no artist who is worth anything will ever copy. They will study a picture they like, for their own use, in their own way; but they won't and can't copy. Whenever you buy a copy, you are buying a misunderstanding of the original, and encouraging a person who is unqualified to follow a path he is not suited for, in addition to increasing the chances of mistakes and fraud, and furthering, as directly as money [Pg 64] can further, the cause of ignorance in all areas. You might as well consider yourself as having purchased a certain amount of mistakes; and, depending on your ability, being involved in spreading them.

I do not mean, however, that copies should never be made. A certain number of dull persons should always be employed by a Government in making the most accurate copies possible of all good pictures; these copies, though artistically valueless, would be historically and documentarily valuable, in the event of the destruction of the original picture. The studies also made by great artists for their own use, should be sought after with the greatest eagerness; they are often to be bought cheap; and in connection with the mechanical copies, would become very precious: tracings from frescos and other large works are also of great value; for though a tracing is liable to just as many mistakes as a copy, the mistakes in a tracing are of one kind only, which may be allowed for, but the mistakes of a common copyist are of all conceivable kinds: finally, engravings, in so far as they convey certain facts about the pictures, without pretending adequately to represent or give an idea of the pictures, are often serviceable and valuable. I can't, of course, enter into details in these matters just now; only this main piece of advice I can safely give you—never to buy copies of pictures (for your private possession) which pretend to give a facsimile that shall be in any wise representative of, or equal to, the original. Whenever you do so, you are only lowering your taste, and wasting your money. And if you are generous and wise, you will be ready rather to subscribe as much as you would have given for a copy of a great picture, towards its purchase, or the purchase of some other like it, by the nation. There ought to be a great National Society instituted for the purchase of pictures; presenting them to the various galleries in our great cities, and watching there over their safety: but in the meantime, you can always act safely and beneficially by merely allowing your artist friends to buy pictures for you, when they see good ones. Never buy for yourselves, nor go to the foreign dealers; but let any painter whom you know be entrusted, when he finds a neglected old picture in an old house, to try if he cannot get it for you;[Pg 65] then, if you like it, keep it; if not, send it to the hammer, and you will find that you do not lose money on pictures so purchased.

I don’t mean to say that copies should never be made. A certain number of less imaginative people should always be employed by the government to create the most accurate copies possible of all great artwork; these copies, although they may lack artistic value, would be historically and documentarily significant in case the original piece is destroyed. The sketches made by great artists for their own use should also be eagerly sought after; they are often available at a low price and, along with the mechanical copies, could become very valuable: tracings from frescoes and other large works are also important; while a tracing can have as many mistakes as a copy, the mistakes in a tracing are usually of one kind, which can be accounted for, whereas the mistakes from a typical copyist can be all sorts of errors. Finally, engravings, to the extent that they provide certain details about the artworks without claiming to fully represent or capture their essence, can often be useful and valuable. I can’t go into details on this right now; however, I can offer this one key piece of advice—never buy copies of artwork (for your own collection) that claim to be a facsimile that is in any way representative of, or equal to, the original. When you do this, you’re only diminishing your taste and wasting your money. If you're generous and wise, you should instead consider contributing the amount you would have spent on a copy of a great piece towards its purchase, or the purchase of a similar one, by the nation. There should be a National Society established for acquiring artworks; one that presents them to various galleries in our major cities and ensures their protection. In the meantime, you can always make safe and beneficial choices by letting your artist friends buy artwork for you when they come across good pieces. Avoid buying for yourself or dealing with foreign sellers; instead, entrust any painter you know to try to acquire a neglected old painting from an old house when they spot one for you; [Pg 65] then, if you like it, keep it; if not, resell it, and you’ll find that you won’t lose money on artworks purchased in this way.

And the third and chief practical outcome of the matter is this general one: Wherever you go, whatever you do, act more for preservation and less for production. I assure you, the world is, generally speaking, in calamitous disorder, and just because you have managed to thrust some of the lumber aside, and get an available corner for yourselves, you think you should do nothing but sit spinning in it all day long—while, as householders and economists, your first thought and effort should be, to set things more square all about you. Try to set the ground floors in order, and get the rottenness out of your granaries. Then sit and spin, but not till then.

And the third and most important practical takeaway is this general idea: Wherever you go, whatever you do, focus more on preservation and less on production. I promise you, the world is, overall, in a disastrous mess, and just because you’ve managed to clear some clutter and create a usable space for yourselves, you think you should do nothing but relax in it all day long—when, as homeowners and responsible individuals, your first priority and effort should be to organize things better around you. Try to get your ground floors in order and remove the decay from your supplies. Then relax, but not until then.

 

IV. Distribution.—And now, lastly, we come to the fourth great head of our inquiry, the question of the wise distribution of the art we have gathered and preserved. It must be evident to us, at a moment's thought, that the way in which works of art are on the whole most useful to the nation to which they belong, must be by their collection in public galleries, supposing those galleries properly managed. But there is one disadvantage attached necessarily to gallery exhibition, namely, the extent of mischief which may be done by one foolish curator. As long as the pictures which form the national wealth are disposed in private collections, the chance is always that the people who buy them will be just the people who are fond of them; and that the sense of exchangeable value in the commodity they possess, will induce them, even if they do not esteem it themselves, to take such care of it as will preserve its value undiminished. At all events, so long as works of art are scattered through the nation, no universal destruction of them is possible; a certain average only are lost by accidents from time to time. But when they are once collected in a large public gallery, if the appointment of curator becomes in any way a matter of formality, or the post is so lucrative as to be disputed by place-hunters, let but one foolish or careless person get possession of it, and perhaps you may have all your fine pictures repainted,[Pg 66] and the national property destroyed, in a month. That is actually the case at this moment, in several great foreign galleries. They are the places of execution of pictures: over their doors you only want the Dantesque inscription, "Lasciate ogni speranza, voi che entrate."

IV. Distribution.—Finally, we come to the fourth main point of our discussion, the issue of how to wisely distribute the art we have gathered and preserved. It should be clear, upon a moment's reflection, that the best way for works of art to benefit the nation they belong to is through their collection in public galleries, assuming those galleries are well-managed. However, there is one major downside to gallery exhibitions: the potential harm that can be caused by a single thoughtless curator. While artworks are still in private collections, there's a good chance that the buyers will be people who genuinely appreciate them; the value they perceive in what they own will motivate them, even if they don't personally value it, to take care of it and maintain its worth. In any case, as long as artworks are spread throughout the nation, widespread destruction of them isn't possible; only a certain average gets lost to accidents over time. But once they're gathered in a large public gallery, if the curator is appointed as a mere formality, or if the role becomes so desirable that it's contested by opportunists, if one foolish or negligent person takes charge, then in just a month, you could see all your beautiful paintings overhauled,[Pg 66] and national treasures ruined. This is currently the unfortunate reality in several major foreign galleries. They have become execution sites for artworks: over their doors, you only need the Dantesque inscription, "Lasciate ogni speranza, voi che entrate."

Supposing, however, this danger properly guarded against, as it would be always by a nation which either knew the value, or understood the meaning, of painting,[13] arrangement in a public gallery is the safest, as well as the most serviceable, method of exhibiting pictures; and it is the only mode in which their historical value can be brought out, and their historical meaning made clear. But great good is also to be done by encouraging the private possession of pictures; partly as a means of study (much more being always discovered in any work of art by a person who has it perpetually near him than by one who only sees it from time to time), and also as a means of refining the habits and touching the hearts of the masses of the nation in their domestic life.

Supposing, however, this danger is properly guarded against, as it would always be by a nation that either recognizes the value or understands the meaning of painting,[13] displaying artwork in a public gallery is the safest and most effective way to exhibit pictures; it’s the only method that can highlight their historical value and clarify their historical meaning. However, there is also great benefit in encouraging private ownership of art; it serves as a means of study (people discover much more in any artwork when it’s constantly near them than when they only see it occasionally), and it helps refine habits and touch the hearts of the masses in their everyday lives.

For these last purposes the most serviceable art is the living art of the time; the particular tastes of the people will be best met, and their particular ignorances best corrected, by painters labouring in the midst of them, more or less guided to the knowledge of what is wanted by the degree of sympathy with which their work is received. So then, generally, it should be the object of government, and of all patrons of art, to collect, as far as may be, the works of dead masters in public galleries, arranging them so as to illustrate the history of nations, and the progress and influence of their arts; and to encourage the private possession of the works of living masters. And the first and best way in which to encourage such private possession is, of course, to keep down the prices of them as far as you can.

For these purposes, the most useful art is the contemporary art of the time; the specific tastes of the people will be best satisfied, and their specific lack of knowledge best addressed, by artists working among them, who are guided to understand what is needed by how well their work is received. Therefore, it should generally be the goal of the government and all art patrons to collect, as much as possible, the works of deceased masters in public galleries, organizing them to illustrate the history of nations and the development and impact of their arts; and to encourage the private ownership of works by living masters. The first and most effective way to promote such private ownership is, of course, to keep their prices as low as possible.

I hope there are not a great many painters in the room; if there are, I entreat their patience for the next quarter of an hour: if they will bear with me for so long, I hope they will not, finally, be offended by what I am going to say.

I hope there aren't too many artists in the room; if there are, I ask for their patience for the next 15 minutes. If they can hang in there with me for that long, I hope they won't be upset by what I’m about to say.

[Pg 67] I repeat, trusting to their indulgence in the interim, that the first object of our national economy, as respects the distribution of modern art, should be steadily and rationally to limit its prices, since by doing so, you will produce two effects; you will make the painters produce more pictures, two or three instead of one, if they wish to make money; and you will, by bringing good pictures within the reach of people of moderate income, excite the general interest of the nation in them, increase a thousandfold the demand for the commodity, and therefore its wholesome and natural production.

[Pg 67] I want to emphasize, while hoping for your patience in the meantime, that the primary goal of our national economy regarding the distribution of modern art should be to consistently and reasonably limit its prices. By doing this, you will achieve two outcomes: you will encourage artists to create more works—two or three instead of just one, if they want to earn a living; and by making quality art affordable for people with moderate incomes, you will generate a greater interest in these artworks across the nation, vastly increase the demand for them, and thus promote their healthy and natural production.

I know how many objections must arise in your minds at this moment to what I say; but you must be aware that it is not possible for me in an hour to explain all the moral and commercial bearings of such a principle as this. Only, believe me, I do not speak lightly; I think I have considered all the objections which could be rationally brought forward, though I have time at present only to glance at the main one, namely, the idea that the high prices paid for modern pictures are either honourable, or serviceable, to the painter. So far from this being so, I believe one of the principal obstacles to the progress of modern art to be the high prices given for good modern pictures. For observe, first, the action of this high remuneration on the artist's mind. If he "gets on," as it is called, catches the eye of the public, and especially of the public of the upper classes, there is hardly any limit to the fortune he may acquire; so that, in his early years, his mind is naturally led to dwell on this worldly and wealthy eminence as the main thing to be reached by his art; if he finds that he is not gradually rising towards it, he thinks there is something wrong in his work; or, if he is too proud to think that, still the bribe of wealth and honour warps him from his honest labour into efforts to attract attention; and he gradually loses both his power of mind and his rectitude of purpose. This, according to the degree of avarice or ambition which exists in any painter's mind, is the necessary influence upon him of the hope of great wealth and reputation. But the harm is still greater, in so far as the possibility of attaining fortune of this kind tempts people continually to become painters who have no real gift for the work; and on whom these motives of mere worldly interest[Pg 68] have exclusive influence;—men who torment and abuse the patient workers, eclipse or thrust aside all delicate and good pictures by their own gaudy and coarse ones, corrupt the taste of the public, and do the greatest amount of mischief to the schools of art in their day which it is possible for their capacities to effect; and it is quite wonderful how much mischief may be done even by small capacity. If you could by any means succeed in keeping the prices of pictures down, you would throw all these disturbers out of the way at once.

I know you probably have a lot of objections to what I'm saying right now, but you need to realize that I can't explain all the moral and commercial implications of this principle in just one hour. Just believe me when I say that I’m not speaking lightly; I think I’ve thought through all the reasonable objections, although I can only touch on the main one for now: the belief that the high prices paid for modern paintings are either honorable or beneficial to the artist. In fact, I believe one of the major obstacles to the progress of modern art is the high prices for good modern paintings. First, consider how this high pay affects the artist’s mindset. If he “makes it,” as they say, and catches the attention of the public—especially the upper classes—there’s hardly a limit to the fortune he might acquire. Therefore, early on, his focus is naturally drawn to achieving this worldly and wealthy status through his art. If he feels he isn't moving toward that goal, he thinks something is wrong with his work. Even if he’s too proud to think that way, the lure of wealth and recognition can shift his focus from genuine labor to efforts aimed at gaining attention, causing him to gradually lose both his creative power and his integrity of purpose. This influence depends on the level of greed or ambition within any artist; the hope for significant wealth and recognition has a necessary impact on them. The harm goes even further because the possibility of attaining such fortune continually entices individuals without real talent to become painters, driven solely by these worldly interests. These people end up disrupting and taking advantage of dedicated artists, overshadowing or pushing aside all subtle and quality works with their own flashy and粗糙的 paintings, corrupting public taste, and causing the greatest harm they can to the art world in their time—it's astonishing how much damage even those with limited skill can do. If you could somehow manage to keep painting prices low, you would immediately remove all these disruptors from the scene.

You may perhaps think that this severe treatment would do more harm than good, by withdrawing the wholesome element of emulation, and giving no stimulus to exertion; but I am sorry to say that artists will always be sufficiently jealous of one another, whether you pay them large or low prices; and as for stimulus to exertion, believe me, no good work in this world was ever done for money, nor while the slightest thought of money affected the painter's mind. Whatever idea of pecuniary value enters into his thoughts as he works, will, in proportion to the distinctness of its presence, shorten his power. A real painter will work for you exquisitely, if you give him, as I told you a little while ago, bread and water and salt; and a bad painter will work badly and hastily, though you give him a palace to live in, and a princedom to live upon. Turner got, in his earlier years, half-a-crown a day and his supper (not bad pay, neither); and he learned to paint upon that. And I believe that there is no chance of art's truly flourishing in any country, until you make it a simple and plain business, providing its masters with an easy competence, but rarely with anything more. And I say this, not because I despise the great painter, but because I honour him; and I should no more think of adding to his respectability or happiness by giving him riches, than, if Shakespeare or Milton were alive, I should think we added to their respectability, or were likely to get better work from them, by making them millionaires.

You might think that such harsh treatment would cause more harm than good by taking away the healthy competition and providing no motivation to put in effort. However, I regret to say that artists will always be jealous of one another, regardless of whether you pay them high or low rates. As for motivation, trust me, no great work in this world has ever been created for money, nor while any thought of money crossed the artist's mind. Any idea of financial value that enters his thoughts while he works will, to the extent that it's present, diminish his ability. A true artist will create beautiful work for you even if you only offer him bread, water, and salt, while a mediocre artist will work poorly and quickly, no matter how luxurious his living conditions are. Turner, in his early years, earned just two shillings and sixpence a day along with his dinner (which isn’t bad pay), and he learned to paint on that. I believe that art can't truly thrive in any country until it's treated as a straightforward and honest business, providing its masters with a comfortable living, but rarely anything more. I say this not because I look down on great artists, but because I respect them. I wouldn't think of enhancing their dignity or happiness by making them wealthy, just as I wouldn't believe that if Shakespeare or Milton were alive, we would improve their respectability or produce better work by making them millionaires.

But, observe, it is not only the painter himself whom you injure, by giving him too high prices; you injure all the inferior painters of the day. If they are modest, they will be discouraged and depressed by the feeling that their doings are[Pg 69] worth so little, comparatively, in your eyes;—if proud, all their worst passions will be aroused, and the insult or opprobrium which they will try to cast on their successful rival will not only afflict and wound him, but at last sour and harden him: he cannot pass through such a trial without grievous harm.

But, consider this: it's not just the painter you hurt by paying them too much; you also harm all the lesser artists out there. If they’re humble, they'll feel discouraged and down because they think their work is[Pg 69] worth so little to you. If they’re proud, all their worst emotions will come out, and the insult or negativity they throw at their successful peer will not only hurt him but ultimately make him bitter and toughen him up. He can't go through that kind of experience without significant damage.

That, then, is the effect you produce on the painter of mark, and on the inferior ones of his own standing. But you do worse than this; you deprive yourselves, by what you give for the fashionable picture, of the power of helping the younger men who are coming forward. Be it admitted, for argument's sake if you are not convinced by what I have said, that you do no harm to the great man by paying him well; yet certainly you do him no special good. His reputation is established, and his fortune made; he does not care whether you buy or not: he thinks he is rather doing you a favour than otherwise by letting you have one of his pictures at all. All the good you do him is to help him to buy a new pair of carriage horses; whereas, with that same sum which thus you cast away, you might have relieved the hearts and preserved the health of twenty young painters; and if among those twenty, you but chanced on one in whom a true latent power had been hindered by his poverty, just consider what a far-branching, far-embracing good you have wrought with that lucky expenditure of yours. I say, "Consider it" in vain; you cannot consider it, for you cannot conceive the sickness of heart with which a young painter of deep feeling toils through his first obscurity;—his sense of the strong voice within him, which you will not hear;—his vain, fond, wondering witness to the things you will not see;—his far away perception of things that he could accomplish if he had but peace, and time, all unapproachable and vanishing from him, because no one will leave him peace or grant him time: all his friends falling back from him; those whom he would most reverently obey rebuking and paralysing him; and last and worst of all, those who believe in him the most faithfully suffering by him the most bitterly;—the wife's eyes, in their sweet ambition, shining brighter as the cheek wastes away; and the little lips at his side parched and pale, which one day, he knows, though he may never see it, will quiver so proudly when they name his name, calling him "our father." You deprive[Pg 70] yourselves, by your large expenditure for pictures of mark, of the power of relieving and redeeming this distress; you injure the painter whom you pay so largely;—and what, after all, have you done for yourselves, or got for yourselves? It does not in the least follow that the hurried work of a fashionable painter will contain more for your money than the quiet work of some unknown man. In all probability, you will find, if you rashly purchase what is popular at a high price, that you have got one picture you don't care for, for a sum which would have bought twenty you would have delighted in. For remember always that the price of a picture by a living artist, never represents, never can represent, the quantity of labour or value in it. Its price represents, for the most part, the degree of desire which the rich people of the country have to possess it. Once get the wealthy classes to imagine that the possession of pictures by a given artist adds to their "gentility," and there is no price which his work may not immediately reach, and for years maintain; and in buying at that price, you are not getting value for your money, but merely disputing for victory in a contest of ostentation. And it is hardly possible to spend your money in a worse or more wasteful way; for though you may not be doing it for ostentation yourself, you are, by your pertinacity, nourishing the ostentation of others; you meet them in their game of wealth, and continue it for them; if they had not found an opposite player, the game would have been done; for a proud man can find no enjoyment in possessing himself of what nobody disputes with him. So that by every farthing you give for a picture beyond its fair price—that is to say, the price which will pay the painter for his time—you are not only cheating yourself and buying vanity, but you are stimulating the vanity of others; paying literally, for the cultivation of pride. You may consider every pound that you spend above the just price of a work of art, as an investment in a cargo of mental quick-lime or guano, which, being laid on the fields of human nature, is to grow a harvest of pride. You are in fact ploughing and harrowing, in a most valuable part of your land, in order to reap the whirlwind; you are setting your hand stoutly to Job's agriculture, "Let thistles grow instead of wheat, and cockle instead of barley."[Pg 71]

That, then, is the impact you have on the well-known painter and on the lesser artists in his circle. But you do worse than that; by spending so much on trendy artwork, you deprive yourselves of the ability to support the emerging young talent. Let’s say, for the sake of argument—if you're not convinced by what I've said—that paying the great artist well does no harm; yet it certainly doesn't do him any real good. His reputation is solid, and he’s made his fortune; he couldn’t care less if you buy or not. He figures he’s doing you a favor by allowing you to have one of his pieces. The only benefit you provide him is to help him buy a new set of carriage horses; meanwhile, with that same amount of money you waste, you could have uplifted and supported the dreams and health of twenty young painters. And if among those twenty you happened upon one with genuine potential stifled by poverty, just think of the far-reaching good you could have achieved with that fortunate investment. I say, "Think about it," in vain; you can’t truly grasp the emotional struggle a sensitive young painter faces as he fights through his initial obscurity—his awareness of a strong voice within him that you can’t hear—his futile, affectionate, wondering observations of the things you’ll never see—his distant vision of what he could achieve if only he had peace and time, which are both unreachable and fading away from him because no one will give him peace or time: all his friends drifting away from him; those he would most respect reprimanding and stifling him; and worst of all, those who believe in him the most suffering the most profoundly because of him—his wife’s eyes, shining with sweet ambition, growing brighter as her face loses its color; and the little lips beside him, parched and pale, which one day, he knows, even if he never sees it, will tremble proudly when they say his name, calling him "our father." You deprive[Pg 70] yourselves, by your excessive spending on fashionable artwork, of the ability to alleviate and transform this suffering; you harm the painter you pay so much;—and what, in the end, have you done for yourselves or gained for yourselves? It doesn’t follow that the rushed work of a popular painter is worth more than the thoughtful work of an unknown artist. In all likelihood, if you hastily buy something that’s trending at a high price, you’ll end up with a painting you don’t care for, despite the fact you could have bought twenty pieces you would have loved for the same amount. Always remember that the price of a painting by a living artist never indicates, and can never represent, the amount of effort or value in it. Its price mostly reflects how much desire wealthy people have to own it. Once you get the affluent classes to believe that owning artwork by a certain artist boosts their "status," there’s no price that piece can’t reach and hold for years; and when you buy it at that price, you’re not getting value for your money but merely fighting for triumph in an exhibition of wealth. It’s almost impossible to spend your money in a worse, more wasteful manner; even if you’re not showing off yourself, you’re fueling the show-off tendencies of others; you engage with them in their wealth game and keep it going for them; without an opponent, their game would be over; because a proud person finds no joy in possessing something that no one else contests him for. So by every penny you spend on a painting beyond its fair price—that is, the amount which compensates the artist for his time—you are not just cheating yourself and buying into vanity, but you are also feeding the vanity of others; literally paying for the growth of pride. Consider every pound you spend above the fair price of a work of art as an investment in a shipment of mental quicklime or fertilizer, which, when applied to the fields of human nature, will produce a crop of pride. You are essentially tilling and harrowing a very valuable part of your land to reap the whirlwind; you're actively trying to cultivate a mess, "Let thistles grow instead of wheat, and cockle instead of barley."[Pg 71]

Well, but you will say, there is one advantage in high prices, which more than counterbalances all this mischief, namely, that by great reward we both urge and enable a painter to produce rather one perfect picture than many inferior ones: and one perfect picture (so you tell us, and we believe it) is worth a great number of inferior ones.

Well, you might say that there is one advantage to high prices that more than makes up for all this trouble, which is that by offering big rewards, we encourage and allow a painter to create one perfect piece instead of several mediocre ones. And one perfect piece (as you tell us, and we believe) is worth many mediocre ones.

It is so; but you cannot get it by paying for it. A great work is only done when the painter gets into the humour for it, likes his subject, and determines to paint it as well as he can, whether he is paid for it or not; but bad work, and generally the worst sort of bad work, is done when he is trying to produce a showy picture, or one that shall appear to have as much labour in it as shall be worth a high price.[14]

It’s true, but you can’t buy it. A great piece of art is created when the artist is in the right mood for it, enjoys the subject, and decides to do the best job possible, whether they’re getting paid or not. However, poor work—often the worst kind of poor work—happens when the artist is just trying to make an impressive picture or one that looks like it took a lot of effort so it can command a high price.[14]

There is however, another point, and a still more important one, bearing on this matter of purchase, than the keeping down of prices to a rational standard. And that is, that you pay your prices into the hands of living men, and do not pour them into coffins.

There is, however, another point, and an even more important one, regarding this issue of buying, beyond just keeping prices at a reasonable level. And that is, that you are paying your prices to living people, not pouring them into coffins.

For observe that, as we arrange our payment of pictures at present, no artist's work is worth half its proper value while he is alive. The moment he dies, his pictures, if they are good, reach double their former value; but, that rise of price represents simply a profit made by the intelligent dealer or purchaser on his past purchases. So that the real facts of the matter are, that the British public, spending a certain sum annually in art, [Pg 72] determines that, of every thousand it pays, only five hundred shall go to the painter, or shall be at all concerned in the production of art; and that the other five hundred shall be paid merely as a testimonial to the intelligent dealer, who knew what to buy. Now, testimonials are very pretty and proper things, within due limits; but testimonial to the amount of a hundred per cent. on the total expenditure is not good political economy. Do not therefore, in general, unless you see it to be necessary for its preservation, buy the picture of a dead artist. If you fear that it may be exposed to contempt or neglect, buy it; its price will then, probably, not be high: if you want to put it into a public gallery, buy it; you are sure, then, that you do not spend your money selfishly: or, if you loved the man's work while he was alive, and bought it then, buy it also now, if you can see no living work equal to it. But if you did not buy it while the man was living, never buy it after he is dead: you are then doing no good to him, and you are doing some shame to yourself. Look around you for pictures that you really like, and in buying which you can help some genius yet unperished—that is the best atonement you can make to the one you have neglected—and give to the living and struggling painter at once wages, and testimonial.

For notice that, as we handle payments for art today, no artist's work is worth even half its true value while they are alive. The moment they pass away, their artwork, if it’s good, can double in value; however, that increase just signifies profit for the smart dealer or buyer from their previous purchases. So the reality is that the British public, spending a certain amount each year on art, [Pg 72] decides that out of every thousand they spend, only five hundred goes to the artist, or is involved in creating art; the other five hundred is simply a reward for the savvy dealer who knew what to buy. Now, rewards are nice and proper within reasonable limits, but a reward amounting to a hundred percent of the total expenditure is not wise economic practice. Therefore, in general, unless you see it necessary for preservation, don't buy a painting by a dead artist. If you worry it might be neglected or disrespected, buy it; its price likely won't be high then. If you want to display it in a public gallery, go ahead; you can be sure you’re spending your money for the right reasons. Or, if you loved their work while they were alive and bought it then, get it now if you can't find any living artist whose work matches it. But if you didn't buy it while the artist was alive, never buy it after they’ve died: you're not helping them, and you're bringing shame on yourself. Look for pieces you genuinely love, and in purchasing them, you can support some still-living genius—that's the best way to make amends for someone you’ve overlooked—and provide the living artist with both income and recognition.

So far, then, of the motives which should induce us to keep down the prices of modern art, and thus render it, as a private possession, attainable by greater numbers of people than at present. But we should strive to render it accessible to them in other ways also—chiefly by the permanent decoration of public buildings; and it is in this field that I think we may look for the profitable means of providing that constant employment for young painters of which we were speaking last evening.

So far, then, about the reasons that should motivate us to lower the prices of modern art, making it a personal possession that more people can access than currently. But we should also work to make it available to them in other ways—mainly through the lasting decoration of public buildings; and I believe that in this area, we can find effective ways to provide the ongoing employment for young painters that we discussed last evening.

The first and most important kind of public buildings which we are always sure to want, are schools: and I would ask you to consider very carefully, whether we may not wisely introduce some great changes in the way of school decoration. Hitherto, as far as I know, it has either been so difficult to give all the education we wanted to our lads, that we have been obliged to do it, if at all, with cheap furniture in bare walls; or else we have considered that cheap furniture and bare walls are[Pg 73] a proper part of the means of education; and supposed that boys learned best when they sat on hard forms, and had nothing but blank plaster about and above them whereupon to employ their spare attention; also, that it was as well they should be accustomed to rough and ugly conditions of things, partly by way of preparing them for the hardships of life, and partly that there might be the least possible damage done to floors and forms, in the event of their becoming, during the master's absence, the fields or instruments of battle. All this is so far well and necessary, as it relates to the training of country lads, and the first training of boys in general. But there certainly comes a period in the life of a well educated youth, in which one of the principal elements of his education is, or ought to be, to give him refinement of habits; and not only to teach him the strong exercises of which his frame is capable, but also to increase his bodily sensibility and refinement, and show him such small matters as the way of handling things properly, and treating them considerately. Not only so, but I believe the notion of fixing the attention by keeping the room empty, is a wholly mistaken one: I think it is just in the emptiest room that the mind wanders most; for it gets restless, like a bird, for want of a perch, and casts about for any possible means of getting out and away. And even if it be fixed, by an effort, on the business in hand, that business becomes itself repulsive, more than it need be, by the vileness of its associations; and many a study appears dull or painful to a boy when it is pursued on a blotted deal desk, under a wall with nothing on it but scratches and pegs, which would have been pursued pleasantly enough in a curtained corner of his father's library, or at the lattice window of his cottage. Nay, my own belief is, that the best study of all is the most beautiful; and that a quiet glade of forest, or the nook of a lake shore, are worth all the schoolrooms in Christendom, when once you are past the multiplication table; but be that as it may, there is no question at all but that a time ought to come in the life of a well trained youth, when he can sit at a writing table without wanting to throw the inkstand at his neighbour; and when also he will feel more capable of certain efforts of mind with beautiful and refined forms about him than with ugly ones. When[Pg 74] that time comes, he ought to be advanced into the decorated schools; and this advance ought to be one of the important and honourable epochs of his life.

The first and most essential type of public building we always need is schools. I would like you to think carefully about whether we should implement significant changes in how we decorate schools. Until now, as far as I know, we've either struggled to provide all the education our students need, resulting in using cheap furniture and bare walls, or we've thought that this simplicity is appropriate for education. Many believe that boys learn best while sitting on hard benches in empty spaces, which gives them blank walls to distract themselves with, and that it's good for them to get used to rough and unattractive environments. This is somewhat necessary for rural boys and the initial training of all boys. However, there comes a point in a young person's education where a crucial aspect is refining their habits. It’s important not just to teach them physical skills but also to enhance their sensitivity and show them how to handle and treat things with care. I also think the idea that an empty room keeps attention focused is completely wrong; in fact, the emptiest rooms make minds wander. Like restless birds looking for a perch, they try to find ways to escape. Even if someone manages to stay focused, the dullness of the surroundings can make the task at hand seem worse than it actually is. Many subjects could be enjoyable if studied in a pleasant setting, like a cozy corner of their father's library or by the lattice window of their cottage. Personally, I believe the best study environments are the most beautiful ones; a peaceful forest clearing or a lakeside spot is far better than any schoolroom once you have mastered the basics. Regardless, there’s no doubt that a well-educated young person should eventually be able to sit at a writing desk without wanting to throw their ink at someone else and will feel more mentally capable when surrounded by beautiful objects instead of ugly ones. When that time comes, they should move into more decorated schools, and this transition should be a significant and honorable moment in their life.

I have not time, however, to insist on the mere serviceableness to our youth of refined architectural decoration, as such; for I want you to consider the probable influence of the particular kind of decoration which I wish you to get for them, namely, historical painting. You know we have hitherto been in the habit of conveying all our historical knowledge, such as it is, by the ear only, never by the eye; all our notions of things being ostensibly derived from verbal description, not from sight. Now, I have no doubt that, as we grow gradually wiser—and we are doing so every day—we shall discover at last that the eye is a nobler organ than the ear; and that through the eye we must, in reality, obtain, or put into form, nearly all the useful information we are to have about this world. Even as the matter stands, you will find that the knowledge which a boy is supposed to receive from verbal description is only available to him so far as in any underhand way he gets a sight of the thing you are talking about. I remember well that, for many years of my life, the only notion I had of the look of a Greek knight was complicated between recollection of a small engraving in my pocket Pope's Homer, and reverent study of the Horse Guards. And though I believe that most boys collect their ideas from more varied sources, and arrange them more carefully than I did; still, whatever sources they seek must always be ocular: if they are clever boys, they will go and look at the Greek vases and sculptures in the British Museum, and at the weapons in our armouries—they will see what real armour is like in lustre, and what Greek armour was like in form, and so put a fairly true image together, but still not, in ordinary cases, a very living or interesting one. Now, the use of your decorative painting would be, in myriads of ways, to animate their history for them, and to put the living aspect of past things before their eyes as faithfully as intelligent invention can; so that the master shall have nothing to do but once to point to the schoolroom walls, and for ever afterwards the meaning of any word would be fixed in a boy's mind in the best possible way. Is it a question of classical dress[Pg 75]—what a tunic was like, or a chlamys, or a peplus? At this day, you have to point to some vile woodcut, in the middle of a dictionary page, representing the thing hung upon a stick, but then, you would point to a hundred figures, wearing the actual dress, in its fiery colours, in all actions of various stateliness or strength; you would understand at once how it fell round the people's limbs as they stood, how it drifted from their shoulders as they went, how it veiled their faces as they wept, how it covered their heads in the day of battle. Now, if you want to see what a weapon is like, you refer, in like manner, to a numbered page, in which there are spear-heads in rows, and sword-hilts in symmetrical groups; and gradually the boy gets a dim mathematical notion how one scymitar is hooked to the right and another to the left, and one javelin has a knob to it and another none: while one glance at your good picture would show him,—and the first rainy afternoon in the schoolroom would for ever fix in his mind,—the look of the sword and spear as they fell or flew; and how they pierced, or bent, or shattered—how men wielded them, and how men died by them. But far more than all this, is it a question not of clothes or weapons, but of men? how can we sufficiently estimate the effect on the mind of a noble youth, at the time when the world opens to him, of having faithful and touching representations put before him of the acts and presences of great men—how many a resolution, which would alter and exalt the whole course of his after-life, might be formed, when in some dreamy twilight he met, through his own tears, the fixed eyes of those shadows of the great dead, unescapable and calm, piercing to his soul; or fancied that their lips moved in dread reproof or soundless exhortation. And if but for one out of many this were true—if yet, in a few, you could be sure that such influence had indeed changed their thoughts and destinies, and turned the eager and reckless youth, who would have cast away his energies on the race-horse or the gambling-table, to that noble life-race, that holy life-hazard, which should win all glory to himself and all good to his country—would not that, to some purpose, be "political economy of art?"

I don’t have time to focus on just how useful refined architectural decoration is for our youth. Instead, I want you to think about the potential impact of the specific type of decoration I wish for them, which is historical painting. You see, we’ve mostly taught our historical knowledge through listening, never through seeing; all our ideas come from words, not from images. I’m sure that, as we become wiser – and we are getting smarter every day – we’ll eventually realize that our eyes are more important than our ears, and that through our eyes we can truly gather and organize most of the important information we need about the world. Even now, the knowledge a boy gets from verbal explanations is only useful if he somehow manages to see the thing you’re describing. I remember that for many years, my only idea of what a Greek knight looked like came from a small engraving in my pocket Pope's Homer and my careful observation of the Horse Guards. While I believe most boys gather ideas from more diverse sources and organize them better than I did, whatever sources they choose must still rely on sight: if they’re smart, they’ll visit the British Museum to look at Greek vases and sculptures and check out weapons in armories—they’ll learn what actual armor looks like in shine and what Greek armor looks like in shape, putting together a fairly accurate picture, but still not one that's very lively or engaging. The purpose of your decorative painting would be, in countless ways, to bring their history to life and to present the vibrant aspects of the past as faithfully as intelligent design can; so that all the teacher has to do is point to the classroom walls, and from then on, the meaning of any word will be clearly etched in a boy's mind in the best possible way. Is it about classical clothing—what a tunic, chlamys, or peplus looked like? Right now, you have to point to some awful woodcut in the middle of a dictionary page showing the item hanging from a stick, but with the paintings, you could point to multiple figures wearing the actual clothing in vivid colors, showing them poised in various dignified or powerful poses; he would instantly understand how it draped around their bodies as they stood, how it flowed from their shoulders as they walked, how it covered their faces as they cried, and how it shielded their heads in battle. Now, if you want to showcase what a weapon looks like, you refer to a numbered page filled with rows of spearheads and neatly grouped sword hilts, and gradually the boy might get a vague idea of how one scimitar curves to the right while another curves to the left, or how one javelin has a knob and another does not; yet, a single glance at your good picture would show him—and that first rainy afternoon in the classroom would engrave it in his mind—what a sword and spear look like when they fall or fly, and how they pierced, bent, or shattered—how men wielded them and how men fell by them. But even more than clothes or weapons, is it about men? How can we truly grasp the impact on a noble youth at the time when the world is opening up for him, of being shown faithful and moving representations of the actions and presence of great men—how many decisions, which could transform and elevate the entire course of his life, might arise when in a reflective moment he encounters, through his own tears, the steady gaze of those shadows of the great dead, unyielding and calm, reaching into his soul; or imagines that their lips quivered in silent reprimand or voiceless encouragement. And if this were true for even one among many—if, in a few cases, we could be certain that such influence had genuinely shifted their thoughts and paths, turning an eager and reckless youth, who might have wasted his energies on horse racing or gambling, toward that noble pursuit, that sacred challenge of life, which would bring him all honor and benefit his country—would that not be a kind of "political economy of art"?

And observe, there could be no monotony, no exhaustibleness, in the scenes required to be thus pourtrayed. Even if[Pg 76] there were, and you wanted for every school in the kingdom, one death of Leonidas; one battle of Marathon; one death of Cleobis and Bito; there need not therefore be more monotony in your art than there was in the repetition of a given cycle of subjects by the religious painters of Italy. But we ought not to admit a cycle at all. For though we had as many great schools as we have great cities (one day I hope we shall have), centuries of painting would not exhaust, in all the number of them, the noble and pathetic subjects which might be chosen from the history of even one noble nation. But, besides this, you will not, in a little while, limit your youths' studies to so narrow fields as you do now. There will come a time—I am sure of it—when it will be found that the same practical results, both in mental discipline, and in political philosophy, are to be attained by the accurate study of mediæval and modern as of ancient history; and that the facts of mediæval and modern history are, on the whole, the most important to us. And among these noble groups of constellated schools which I foresee arising in our England, I foresee also that there will be divided fields of thought; and that while each will give its scholars a great general idea of the world's history, such as all men should possess—each will also take upon itself, as its own special duty, the closer study of the course of events in some given place or time. It will review the rest of history, but it will exhaust its own special field of it; and found its moral and political teaching on the most perfect possible analysis of the results of human conduct in one place, and at one epoch. And then, the galleries of that school will be painted with the historical scenes belonging to the age which it has chosen for its special study.

And look, there should be no monotony or exhaustion in the scenes that need to be depicted. Even if there were, and you required for every school in the kingdom one death of Leonidas, one battle of Marathon, and one death of Cleobis and Bito; there shouldn’t be more monotony in your art than there was in the repeated themes of the religious painters of Italy. But we shouldn’t even accept a cycle at all. For even if we had as many great schools as we have great cities (and I hope we will one day), centuries of painting would not run out of the noble and moving subjects that could be chosen from the history of even one great nation. Moreover, soon, you won’t limit your students' studies to such narrow fields as you do now. There will come a time—I’m sure of it—when it will be recognized that the same practical outcomes, both in mental discipline and in political philosophy, can be achieved by studying medieval and modern history as well as ancient history; and that the facts of medieval and modern history are, overall, the most relevant to us. Among these great networks of thriving schools that I foresee emerging in our England, I also anticipate that there will be specialized areas of thought; and while each will provide its students with a broad understanding of world history, which everyone should have, each will also take it as its own special mission to closely study the events of a specific place or time. It will review the rest of history but will exhaust its own special field; and base its moral and political teachings on the most thorough possible analysis of human actions in one place and at one time. Then, the galleries of that school will be filled with paintings of the historical scenes that belong to the period it has chosen for its focused study.

So far, then, of art as you may apply it to that great series of public buildings which you devote to the education of youth. The next large class of public buildings in which we should introduce it, is one which I think a few years more of national progress will render more serviceable to us than they have been lately. I mean, buildings for the meetings of guilds of trades.

So far, we’ve talked about how art relates to the group of public buildings you dedicate to educating young people. The next major category of public buildings where we should incorporate art is one that I believe, with a few more years of national progress, will become more useful to us than they have been recently. I’m referring to buildings for trade guild meetings.

And here, for the last time, I must again interrupt the course of our chief inquiry, in order to state one other principle of political economy, which is perfectly simple and indisputable;[Pg 77] but which, nevertheless, we continually get into commercial embarrassments for want of understanding; and not only so, but suffer much hindrance in our commercial discoveries, because many of our business men do not practically admit it.

And now, for the final time, I need to pause our main discussion to mention another principle of political economy, which is really straightforward and undeniable;[Pg 77] yet, we often find ourselves in financial trouble due to a lack of understanding of it. Not only that, but we face significant obstacles in our business ventures because many of our entrepreneurs fail to recognize it in practice.

Supposing half a dozen or a dozen men were cast ashore from a wreck on an uninhabited island and left to their own resources, one of course, according to his capacity, would be set to one business and one to another; the strongest to dig and to cut wood, and to build huts for the rest: the most dexterous to make shoes out of bark and coats out of skins; the best educated to look for iron or lead in the rocks, and to plan the channels for the irrigation of the fields. But though their labours were thus naturally severed, that small group of shipwrecked men would understand well enough that the speediest progress was to be made by helping each other,—not by opposing each other; and they would know that this help could only be properly given so long as they were frank and open in their relations, and the difficulties which each lay under properly explained to the rest. So that any appearance of secresy or separateness in the actions of any of them would instantly, and justly, be looked upon with suspicion by the rest, as the sign of some selfish or foolish proceeding on the part of the individual. If, for instance, the scientific man were found to have gone out at night, unknown to the rest, to alter the sluices, the others would think, and in all probability rightly think, that he wanted to get the best supply of water to his own field; and if the shoemaker refused to show them where the bark grew which he made the sandals of, they would naturally think, and in all probability rightly think, that he didn't want them to see how much there was of it, and that he meant to ask from them more corn and potatoes in exchange for his sandals than the trouble of making them deserved. And thus, although each man would have a portion of time to himself in which he was allowed to do what he chose without let or inquiry,—so long as he was working in that particular business which he had undertaken for the common benefit, any secresy on his part would be immediately supposed to mean mischief; and would require to be accounted for, or put an end to: and this all the more because, whatever the work might be, certainly[Pg 78] there would be difficulties about it which, when once they were well explained, might be more or less done away with by the help of the rest; so that assuredly every one of them would advance with his labour not only more happily, but more profitably and quickly, by having no secrets, and by frankly bestowing, and frankly receiving, such help as lay in his way to get or to give.

Suppose six or twelve men are washed ashore from a shipwreck on a deserted island and left to fend for themselves. Naturally, each person would take on a role suited to their skills: the strongest would dig, chop wood, and build huts for everyone else; the most skilled would make shoes from bark and clothing from animal hides; and the best educated would search for iron or lead in the rocks and plan irrigation channels for crops. Even though their tasks are divided, this small group of shipwrecked men would understand that they could make the best progress by helping each other rather than competing against each other. They would realize that this assistance could only be effective as long as they remained honest and open with one another, clearly explaining the challenges each faced. Consequently, any hint of secrecy or isolation in anyone's actions would be quickly and rightly viewed with suspicion by the others, seen as a sign of selfishness or foolishness. For example, if the scientist was found sneaking out at night to adjust the water controls without telling anyone, the others would likely assume he was trying to ensure the best water supply for his own crops. Similarly, if the shoemaker refused to reveal where he found the bark for his sandals, they would naturally think he wanted to keep the supply hidden so he could demand more corn and potatoes in exchange for his work than it was worth. So, while each man would have some time to himself to do as he pleased without interference—as long as he worked on the task he had taken on for the group’s benefit—any secrecy on his part would immediately be assumed to indicate wrongdoing and would need to be explained or stopped. This was especially true because whatever the work involved, there would definitely be challenges that could more or less be solved with the support of the others once properly explained. Thus, each person would make progress not only more happily but also more profitably and swiftly by having no secrets and openly giving and receiving help where they could.

And, just as the best and richest result of wealth and happiness to the whole of them, would follow on their perseverance in such a system of frank communication and of helpful labour;—so precisely the worst and poorest result would be obtained by a system of secresy and of enmity; and each man's happiness and wealth would assuredly be diminished in proportion to the degree in which jealousy and concealment became their social and economical principles. It would not, in the long run, bring good, but only evil, to the man of science, if, instead of telling openly where he had found good iron, he carefully concealed every new bed of it, that he might ask, in exchange for the rare ploughshare, more corn from the farmer, or in exchange for the rude needle, more labour from the sempstress: and it would not ultimately bring good, but only evil, to the farmers, if they sought to burn each other's cornstacks, that they might raise the value of their grain, or if the sempstresses tried to break each other's needles, that each might get all the stitching to herself.

And just like the best and most rewarding outcomes of wealth and happiness for everyone would come from sticking to a system of open communication and cooperative work, the exact opposite would happen with a system of secrecy and hostility; each person's happiness and wealth would definitely decrease in line with how much jealousy and concealment became their social and economic values. In the long run, it wouldn't benefit the scientist at all if he carefully hid where he found good iron, trying to trade the rare ploughshare for more corn from the farmer, or trying to get more work from the seamstress in exchange for the basic needle. And it wouldn't ultimately benefit the farmers either if they tried to burn each other's corn stacks to drive up the price of their grain, or if the seamstresses tried to break each other's needles to take all the sewing work for themselves.

Now, these laws of human action are precisely as authoritative in their application to the conduct of a million of men, as to that of six or twelve. All enmity, jealousy, opposition, and secresy are wholly, and in all circumstances, destructive in their nature—not productive; and all kindness, fellowship, and communicativeness are invariably productive in their operation,—not destructive; and the evil principles of opposition and exclusiveness are not rendered less fatal, but more fatal, by their acceptance among large masses of men; more fatal, I say, exactly in proportion as their influence is more secret. For though the opposition does always its own simple, necessary, direct quantity of harm, and withdraws always its own simple, necessary, measurable quantity of wealth from the sum possessed by the community, yet, in proportion to the[Pg 79] size of the community, it does another and more refined mischief than this, by concealing its own fatality under aspects of mercantile complication and expediency, and giving rise to multitudes of false theories based on a mean belief in narrow and immediate appearances of good done here and there by things which have the universal and everlasting nature of evil. So that the time and powers of the nation are wasted, not only in wretched struggling against each other, but in vain complaints, and groundless discouragements, and empty investigations, and useless experiments in laws, and elections, and inventions; with hope always to pull wisdom through some new-shaped slit in a ballot-box, and to drag prosperity down out of the clouds along some new knot of electric wire; while all the while Wisdom stands calling at the corners of the streets, and the blessing of heaven waits ready to rain down upon us, deeper than the rivers and broader than the dew, if only we will obey the first plain principles of humanity, and the first plain precepts of the skies; "Execute true judgment, and show mercy and compassion, every man to his brother; and let none of you imagine evil against his brother in your heart."[15]

Now, these laws of human behavior are just as relevant when applied to the actions of a million people as they are to those of six or twelve. All hatred, jealousy, conflict, and secrecy are completely destructive in nature—not productive; while all kindness, friendship, and openness are consistently productive in their effects—not destructive. The harmful ideas of opposition and exclusivity don't become less deadly in large groups of people; in fact, they become more dangerous, especially when their effects are hidden. Although opposition always causes its own specific harm and takes away a definite amount of wealth from the community, it also does a subtler kind of damage, especially when it's not apparent. This damage appears in complex economic scenarios and gives rise to many false theories based on a narrow and short-term view of some good that seems to come from actions with a fundamentally harmful nature. Consequently, the resources and time of the nation are squandered not only in struggling against each other, but also in pointless complaints, baseless discouragements, futile investigations, ineffective laws, elections, and inventions; all while hoping to uncover wisdom through a new approach to voting or to pull prosperity down from the sky with some innovative technology. Meanwhile, wisdom calls out at street corners, and the blessings of heaven are ready to pour down on us, deeper than rivers and broader than dew, if only we would follow the basic principles of humanity and the simple commands of the skies: "Execute true judgment, and show mercy and compassion, each person to their brother; and let none of you harbor evil thoughts against your brother in your heart."

Therefore, I believe most firmly, that as the laws of national prosperity get familiar to us, we shall more and more cast our toil into social and communicative systems; and that one of the first means of our doing so, will be the re-establishing guilds of every important trade in a vital, not formal, condition;—that there will be a great council or government house for the members of every trade, built in whatever town of the kingdom occupies itself principally in such trade, with minor council [Pg 80] halls in other cities; and to each council-hall, officers attached, whose first business may be to examine into the circumstances of every operative, in that trade, who chooses to report himself to them when out of work, and to set him to work, if he is indeed able and willing, at a fixed rate of wages, determined at regular periods in the council-meetings; and whose next duty may be to bring reports before the council of all improvements made in the business, and means of its extension: not allowing private patents of any kind, but making all improvements available to every member of the guild, only allotting, after successful trial of them, a certain reward to the inventors.

Therefore, I firmly believe that as we become more familiar with the laws of national prosperity, we will increasingly invest our efforts into social and communication systems. One of the first ways we will do this is by re-establishing guilds for every important trade in a meaningful way, not just formally. There will be a main council or government house for members of each trade, built in the town that primarily engages in that trade, along with smaller council halls in other cities. Each council hall will have officers whose main job will be to assess the situation of every worker in that trade who chooses to report to them when they are out of work, and to find them work if they are able and willing, at a fixed wage that will be set at regular council meetings. Their next responsibility will be to present reports to the council on all improvements made in the business and strategies for its growth, ensuring that no private patents exist, so all improvements are accessible to every guild member, with a certain reward allotted to the inventors after successful trials.

For these, and many other such purposes, such halls will be again, I trust, fully established, and then, in the paintings and decorations of them, especial effort ought to be made to express the worthiness and honourableness of the trade for whose members they are founded. For I believe one of the worst symptoms of modern society to be, its notion of great inferiority, and ungentlemanliness, as necessarily belonging to the character of a tradesman. I believe tradesmen may be, ought to be—often are, more gentlemen than idle and useless people: and I believe that art may do noble work by recording in the hall of each trade, the services which men belonging to that trade have done for their country, both preserving the portraits, and recording the important incidents in the lives, of those who have made great advances in commerce and civilization. I cannot follow out this subject, it branches too far, and in too many directions; besides, I have no doubt [Pg 81]you will at once see and accept the truth of the main principle, and be able to think it out for yourselves. I would fain also have said something of what might be done, in the same manner, for almshouses and hospitals, and for what, as I shall try to explain in notes to this lecture, we may hope to see, some day, established with a different meaning in their name than that they now bear—workhouses; but I have detained you too long already, and cannot permit myself to trespass further on your patience except only to recapitulate, in closing, the simple principles respecting wealth which we have gathered during the course of our inquiry; principles which are nothing more than the literal and practical acceptance of the saying, which is in all good men's mouths; namely, that they are stewards or ministers of whatever talents are entrusted to them. Only, is it not a strange thing, that while we more or less accept the meaning of that saying, so long as it is considered metaphorical, we never accept its meaning in its own terms? You know the lesson is given us under the form of a story about money. Money was given to the servants to make use of: the unprofitable servant dug in the earth, and hid his Lord's money. Well, we, in our poetical and spiritual application of this, say, that of course money doesn't mean money, it means wit, it means intellect, it means influence in high quarters, it means everything in the world except itself. And do not you see what a pretty and pleasant come-off there is for most of us, in this spiritual application? Of course, if we had wit, we would use it for the good of our fellow-creatures. But we haven't wit. Of course, if we had influence with the bishops, we would use it for the good of the Church; but we haven't any influence with the bishops. Of course, if we had political power, we would use it for the good of the nation; but we have no political power; we have no talents entrusted to us of any sort or kind. It is true we have a little money, but the parable can't possibly mean anything so vulgar as money; our money's our own.

For these and many other reasons, I hope that such halls will be fully established again, and then, in their paintings and decorations, we should make a special effort to showcase the value and respectability of the trade for which they are created. I believe one of the worst signs of modern society is its view that tradesmen are inherently inferior and lacking in gentlemanly qualities. I believe tradesmen can, and often are, more honorable than idle and useless people: and I believe art can play a vital role by showcasing, in the hall of each trade, the contributions that its members have made to their country, preserving portraits and recording important events in the lives of those who have significantly advanced commerce and civilization. I can't delve deeper into this subject as it branches in too many directions; also, I'm sure [Pg 81] you will immediately understand and accept the truth of the main idea and can contemplate it on your own. I would also like to discuss what could be done in the same way for almshouses and hospitals, and what we might one day hope to see established with a different meaning from what they currently represent—workhouses; but I’ve already taken up too much of your time and can't overstay my welcome except to briefly recap the simple principles about wealth that we've discussed during our inquiry; principles that are simply the straightforward and practical interpretation of the saying that's familiar to all good people: that they are stewards or servants of whatever talents they are entrusted with. Yet, isn't it curious that while we generally accept the meaning of this saying as long as it’s viewed metaphorically, we never take it literally? You know the lesson is framed as a story about money. Money was given to the servants to use: the unproductive servant buried it in the ground and hid his master's money. Well, in our poetic and spiritual interpretation of this, we say that money doesn't actually mean money, it stands for intellect, it stands for influence among powerful people, it represents everything except itself. And don't you see how convenient that is for most of us in this spiritual interpretation? Of course, if we had intellect, we would use it for the benefit of others. But we don’t have intellect. Of course, if we had influence with the bishops, we would use it for the good of the Church; but we have no influence with the bishops. Of course, if we had political power, we would use it for the good of the nation; but we have no political power; we have no talents entrusted to us at all. It’s true we have a little money, but the parable can’t possibly refer to something so crude as money; our money belongs to us.

I believe, if you think seriously of this matter, you will feel that the first and most literal application is just as necessary a one as any other—that the story does very specially mean what it says—plain money; and that the reason we don't at once[Pg 82] believe it does so, is a sort of tacit idea that while thought, wit, and intellect, and all power of birth and position, are indeed given to us, and, therefore, to be laid out for the Giver,—our wealth has not been given to us; but we have worked for it, and have a right to spend it as we choose. I think you will find that is the real substance of our understanding in this matter. Beauty, we say, is given by God—it is a talent; strength is given by God—it is a talent; position is given by God—it is a talent; but money is proper wages for our day's work—it is not a talent, it is a due. We may justly spend it on ourselves, if we have worked for it.

I believe that if you seriously think about this issue, you'll realize that the most straightforward interpretation is just as essential as any other—that the story really does mean what it says—straight-up cash; and the reason we don't immediately[Pg 82] accept this is because of an underlying assumption that while thought, wit, intellect, and all the advantages of birth and status are indeed given to us, and therefore should be used for the Giver—our wealth hasn't been given to us; we've earned it, and we have the right to spend it however we want. I think you'll find that's the core of our understanding in this issue. We say beauty is a gift from God—it’s a talent; strength is a gift from God—it’s a talent; status is a gift from God—it’s a talent; but money is simply the fair payment for our labor—it’s not a talent, it’s a right. We can justly spend it on ourselves if we’ve worked for it.

And there would be some shadow of excuse for this, were it not that the very power of making the money is itself only one of the applications of that intellect or strength which we confess to be talents. Why is one man richer than another? Because he is more industrious, more persevering, and more sagacious. Well, who made him more persevering or more sagacious than others? That power of endurance, that quickness of apprehension, that calmness of judgment, which enable him to seize the opportunities that others lose, and persist in the lines of conduct in which others fail—are these not talents?—are they not, in the present state of the world, among the most distinguished and influential of mental gifts? And is it not wonderful, that while we should be utterly ashamed to use a superiority of body, in order to thrust our weaker companions aside from some place of advantage, we unhesitatingly use our superiorities of mind to thrust them back from whatever good that strength of mind can attain? You would be indignant if you saw a strong man walk into a theatre or a lecture-room, and, calmly choosing the best place, take his feeble neighbour by the shoulder, and turn him out of it into the back seats, or the street. You would be equally indignant if you saw a stout fellow thrust himself up to a table where some hungry children were being fed, and reach his arm over their heads and take their bread from them. But you are not the least indignant if, when a man has stoutness of thought and swiftness of capacity, and, instead of being long-armed only, has the much greater gift of being long-headed—you think it perfectly just that he should use his intellect[Pg 83] to take the bread out of the mouths of all the other men in the town who are of the same trade with him; or use his breadth and sweep of sight to gather some branch of the commerce of the country into one great cobweb, of which he is himself to be the central spider, making every thread vibrate with the points of his claws, and commanding every avenue with the facets of his eyes. You see no injustice in this.

And there would be some justification for this if it weren't for the fact that the very ability to make money is just one application of that intellect or strength that we recognize as talents. Why is one person wealthier than another? Because they are more hardworking, more persistent, and more astute. So, who made them more persistent or more astute than others? That ability to endure, that speed of understanding, that calm judgment which allows them to seize opportunities that others miss, and stick to paths where others fail—are these not talents? Aren't they, in today’s world, among the most prominent and impactful mental gifts? And isn't it amazing that while we would be completely ashamed to use physical superiority to shove our weaker peers out of a place of advantage, we readily use our mental advantages to push them away from any benefits that our intellect can achieve? You would be outraged if you saw a strong person walk into a theater or lecture hall, casually pick the best seat, grab their weaker neighbor by the shoulder, and shove them into the back rows or outside. You would feel the same if you saw a robust guy push himself to a table where hungry kids were being served and reach over their heads to take their bread. But you feel no outrage at all if a person with sharp thinking and quick perception, instead of just having long arms, possesses the much greater ability of being far-sighted—you think it's completely fair for them to use their intellect[Pg 83] to take the bread from the mouths of all the other people in the same town who work in the same field; or to use their broad vision to sweep a segment of the country's commerce into one big web, positioning themselves as the central spider, making every thread vibrate with their movements and controlling every pathway with their awareness. You see no injustice in this.

But there is injustice; and, let us trust, one of which honourable men will at no very distant period disdain to be guilty. In some degree, however, it is indeed not unjust; in some degree it is necessary and intended. It is assuredly just that idleness should be surpassed by energy; that the widest influence should be possessed by those who are best able to wield it; and that a wise man, at the end of his career, should be better off than a fool. But for that reason, is the fool to be wretched, utterly crushed down, and left in all the suffering which his conduct and capacity naturally inflict?—Not so. What do you suppose fools were made for? That you might tread upon them, and starve them, and get the better of them in every possible way? By no means. They were made that wise people might take care of them. That is the true and plain fact concerning the relations of every strong and wise man to the world about him. He has his strength given him, not that he may crush the weak, but that he may support and guide them. In his own household he is to be the guide and the support of his children; out of his household he is still to be the father, that is, the guide and support of the weak and the poor; not merely of the meritoriously weak and the innocently poor, but of the guiltily and punishably poor; of the men who ought to have known better—of the poor who ought to be ashamed of themselves. It is nothing to give pension and cottage to the widow who has lost her son; it is nothing to give food and medicine to the workman who has broken his arm, or the decrepit woman wasting in sickness. But it is something to use your time and strength to war with the waywardness and thoughtlessness of mankind; to keep the erring workman in your service till you have made him an unerring one; and to direct your fellow-merchant to the opportunity which his dullness would have lost. This is much;[Pg 84] but it is yet more, when you have fully achieved the superiority which is due to you, and acquired the wealth which is the fitting reward of your sagacity, if you solemnly accept the responsibility of it, as it is the helm and guide of labour far and near. For you who have it in your hands, are in reality the pilots of the power and effort of the State.[16] It is entrusted to you as an authority to be used for good or evil, just as completely as kingly authority was ever given to a prince, or military command to a captain. And, according to the quantity of it that you have in your hands you are the arbiters of the will and work of England; and the whole issue, whether the work of the State shall suffice for the State or not, depends upon you. You may stretch out your sceptre over the heads of the English labourers, and say to them, as they stoop to its waving, "Subdue this obstacle that has baffled our fathers, put away this plague that consumes our children; water these dry places, plough these desert ones, carry this food to those who are in hunger; carry this light to those who are in darkness; carry this life to those who are in death;" or on the other side you may say to her labourers: "Here am I; this power is in my hand; come, build a mound here for me to be throned upon, high and wide; come, make crowns for my head, that men may see them shine from far away; come, weave tapestries for my feet, that I may tread softly on the silk and purple;[17] come, dance before me, that I may be gay; and sing sweetly to me, that I may slumber; so shall I live in joy, and die in honour." And better than such an honourable death, it were that the day had perished wherein we were born, and the night in which it was said there is a child conceived.

But there is injustice; and, let's hope, one that honorable people will soon refuse to commit. In some ways, it's not entirely unjust; in some ways, it's necessary and deliberate. It's definitely just that hard work should overcome idleness; that the greatest influence should belong to those who can handle it best; and that a wise person, at the end of their life, should be better off than a fool. But does that mean the fool should be miserable, completely beaten down, and left to suffer because of their choices and abilities?—Not at all. What do you think fools are here for? So you can walk all over them, starve them, and always outsmart them? Absolutely not. They exist so that wise people can take care of them. That's the simple truth about how every strong and wise person relates to the world around them. Their strength is given not to crush the weak, but to support and guide them. At home, they should guide and support their children; outside, they should still act as a father, meaning guiding and supporting the weak and the poor; not just the deserving weak and the innocent poor, but even the guilty and punishable poor; those who should have known better—those who ought to be ashamed of themselves. It doesn't mean much to give a pension and a cottage to a widow who lost her son; it doesn't mean much to provide food and medicine to a worker who broke his arm, or to an elderly woman suffering from illness. But it does matter to spend your time and energy fighting against the waywardness and thoughtlessness of people; to keep the mistaken worker in your service until you’ve made him reliable; and to guide your fellow merchant to the opportunities his dullness would have caused him to miss. This is significant; but even more so, when you’ve fully earned the superiority that’s rightfully yours, and gained the wealth that’s the appropriate reward for your insight, if you wholeheartedly accept the responsibility that comes with it, as it is the steering wheel and guide of labor both near and far. Because those of you who have it are, in reality, the pilots of the State's power and efforts. It is placed in your hands as an authority to be used for good or ill, just as completely as royal authority was ever given to a prince, or military command to a captain. And, as much as you possess, you are the ones determining the will and actions of England; and the entire outcome of whether the State's work will serve the State or not depends on you. You may extend your influence over the heads of the English laborers and say to them, as they bow to it, "Overcome this challenge that has challenged our ancestors, eliminate this plague that harms our children; irrigate these dry areas, cultivate these barren lands, deliver food to those in need; bring light to those in darkness; bring life to those facing death;" or alternatively, you might say to the laborers, "Here I stand; this power is in my hands; come, build a grand mound for me to sit upon, vast and commanding; come, create crowns for my head that will shine brightly from far away; come, weave tapestries for my feet, so I may tread softly on silk and purple; come, dance before me, so I may rejoice; and sing sweetly to me, so I may peacefully rest; thus shall I live in joy, and die in honor." And better than such an honorable death, it would have been better if the day we were born had never come, and the night in which it was said that a child was conceived.

I trust, that in a little while, there will be few of our rich men who, through carelessness or covetousness, thus forfeit the glorious office which is intended for their hands. I said, just now, that wealth ill used was as the net of the spider, entangling and destroying: but wealth well used, is as the net of the sacred fisher who gathers souls of men out of the deep. A time will come—I do not think even now it is far from us—when this golden net of the world's wealth will be spread abroad [Pg 85] as the flaming meshes of morning cloud are over the sky; bearing with them the joy of light and the dew of the morning, as well as the summons to honourable and peaceful toil. What less can we hope from your wealth than this, rich men of England, when once you feel fully how, by the strength of your possessions—not, observe, by the exhaustion, but by the administration of them and the power—you can direct the acts,—command the energies,—inform the ignorance,—prolong the existence, of the whole human race; and how, even of worldly wisdom, which man employs faithfully, it is true, not only that her ways are pleasantness, but that her paths are peace; and that, for all the children of men, as well as for those to whom she is given, Length of days are in her right hand, as in her left hand Riches and Honour?

I believe that soon there will be few wealthy individuals who, through carelessness or greed, jeopardize the important role that is meant for them. I just mentioned that misusing wealth is like a spider's web, trapping and destroying; but using wealth wisely is like the net of a sacred fisherman who brings souls up from the depths. A time will come—I don’t think it’s too far off—when this golden net of the world’s wealth will be spread out [Pg 85] like the glowing threads of morning clouds in the sky; carrying with it the joy of light and the morning dew, as well as the call to honorable and peaceful work. What more can we expect from your wealth than this, wealthy individuals of England, once you truly recognize how, through the strength of your possessions—not by exhausting them, but by managing and wielding them—you can influence actions, energize efforts, enlighten ignorance, and extend the existence of all humanity? And even in worldly wisdom, which people faithfully utilize, it is indeed true that her ways are pleasantness and her paths are peace; and that, for all mankind, as well as for those who embrace her, Length of days are in her right hand, and Riches and Honour are in her left hand?

FOOTNOTES:

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

[12] The reader can hardly but remember Mrs. Browning's beautiful appeal for Italy, made on the occasion of the first great Exhibition of Art in England:—

"O Magi of the east and of the west,
Your incense, gold, and myrrh are excellent!—
What gifts for Christ, then, bring ye with the rest?
Your hands have worked well. Is your courage spent
In handwork only? Have you nothing best,
Which generous souls may perfect and present,
And He shall thank the givers for? no light
Of teaching, liberal nations, for the poor,
Who sit in darkness when it is not night?
No cure for wicked children? Christ,—no cure,
No help for women, sobbing out of sight
Because men made the laws? no brothel-lure
Burnt out by popular lightnings? Hast thou found
No remedy, my England, for such woes?
No outlet, Austria, for the scourged and bound,
No call back for the exiled? no repose,
Russia, for knouted Poles worked underground,
And gentle ladies bleached among the snows?
No mercy for the slave, America?
No hope for Rome, free France, chivalric France?
Alas, great nations have great shames, I say.
No pity, O world, no tender utterance
Of benediction, and prayers stretched this way
For poor Italia, baffled by mischance?
O gracious nations, give some ear to me!
You all go to your Fair, and I am one
Who at the roadside of humanity
Beseech your alms,—God's justice to be done.
So, prosper!"

[12] The reader can hardly forget Mrs. Browning's beautiful appeal for Italy, made during the first major Art Exhibition in England:—

"O Magi from both the east and west,
Your incense, gold, and myrrh are amazing!—
What gifts for Christ, then, do you bring with you?
Your hands have done a great job. Have you run out of courage?
Are you only working with your hands? Don't you aspire for something greater?
That generous people can improve and showcase,
And He will thank the givers for? no clarity
From liberal countries for the disadvantaged,
Who sits in darkness even during the day?
No cure for naughty kids? Seriously, no solution.
No support for women, weeping out of sight.
Is it because men created the laws? There’s no desire for change.
Shut down by the people's selfish perspectives? Have you discovered
No solution, my England, for such pain?
No way out, Austria, for those who are beaten and shackled,
No return for the exiled? No peace,
Russia, for the suffering Poles hiding underground,
And ladies struggling in the snow?
No mercy for the slave, America?
Is there no hope for Rome, free France, noble France?
Unfortunately, powerful nations have significant regrets, I say.
No compassion, oh world, no kind words
Of blessings and prayers aimed this way
For poor Italy, battling against bad luck?
Oh, noble nations, hear me!
You all are going to your fair, and I'm one.
Who stands with humanity
Please show your generosity—let God's justice prevail.
So, thrive!

[13] It would be a great point gained towards the preservation of pictures if it were made a rule that at every operation they underwent, the exact spots in which they have been re-painted should be recorded in writing.

[13] It would be a significant step forward for preserving artworks if a rule were established that required detailed written records of the exact areas that have been repainted during each restoration process.

[14] When this lecture was delivered, I gave here some data for approximate estimates of the average value of good modern pictures of different classes; but the subject is too complicated to be adequately treated in writing, without introducing more detail than the reader will have patience for. But I may state, roughly, that prices above a hundred guineas are in general extravagant for water-colours, and above five hundred for oils. An artist almost always does wrong who puts more work than these prices will remunerate him for into any single canvass—his talent would be better employed in painting two pictures than one so elaborate. The water-colour painters also are getting into the habit of making their drawings too large, and in a measure attaching their price rather to breadth and extent of touch than to thoughtful labour. Of course marked exceptions occur here and there, as in the case of John Lewis, whose drawings are wrought with unfailing precision throughout, whatever their scale. Hardly any price can be remunerative for such work.

[14] When I gave this lecture, I provided some data for rough estimates of the average value of good modern artwork across different categories. However, the topic is too complex to cover thoroughly in writing without overwhelming the reader with too many details. I can say, generally, that prices over a hundred guineas are usually excessive for watercolors, and anything above five hundred for oils. An artist typically makes a mistake by putting more effort into a single canvas than these prices can justify—his skills would be better used in creating two paintings rather than one so intricate. Watercolor artists are also starting to create their works too large, often pricing them based more on size and the breadth of strokes rather than on careful craftsmanship. Of course, there are notable exceptions, like John Lewis, whose drawings maintain consistent precision regardless of their size. It's hard to find a price that fairly compensates for such work.

[15] It would be well if, instead of preaching continually about the doctrine of faith and good works, our clergymen would simply explain to their people a little what good works mean. There is not a chapter in all the Book we profess to believe, more specially and directly written for England, than the second of Habakkuk, and I never in all my life heard one of its practical texts preached from. I suppose the clergymen are all afraid, and know that their flocks, while they will sit quite politely to hear syllogisms out of the epistle to the Romans, would get restive directly if they ever pressed a practical text home to them. But we should have no mercantile catastrophes, and no distressful pauperism, if we only read often, and took to heart, those plain words:—"Yea, also, because he is a proud man, neither keepeth at home, who enlargeth his desire as hell, and cannot be satisfied,—Shall not all these take up a parable against him, and a taunting proverb against him, and say, 'Woe to him that increaseth that which is not his: and to him that ladeth himself with thick clay.'" (What a glorious history, in one metaphor, of the life of a man greedy of fortune.) "Woe to him that coveteth an evil covetousness that he may set his nest on high. Woe to him that buildeth a town with blood, and stablisheth a city by iniquity. Behold, is it not of the Lord of Hosts that the people shall labour in the very fire, and the people shall weary themselves for very vanity."

[15] It would be better if, instead of constantly preaching about faith and good deeds, our clergy would simply explain to their congregation what good deeds actually mean. There's not a chapter in the entire Book we claim to believe that is more specifically and directly written for England than the second of Habakkuk, and I've never heard any of its practical messages preached in my life. I guess the clergy are all afraid, knowing that their congregations will sit patiently to hear arguments from the epistle to the Romans but will become restless if they ever emphasize a practical message. But we wouldn’t face financial disasters or widespread poverty if we just read often and really considered those straightforward words:—"Yes, also, because he is a proud man, neither keeps at home, who enlarges his desire as hell and cannot be satisfied,—Shall not all these take up a parable against him, and a taunting proverb against him, and say, 'Woe to him that increases that which is not his: and to him that loads himself with thick clay.'" (What a powerful metaphor for the life of a man greedy for wealth.) "Woe to him that covets an evil greed so he can set his nest on high. Woe to him that builds a town with blood and establishes a city through wrongdoing. Behold, is it not from the Lord of Hosts that the people shall labor in the very fire, and the people shall tire themselves for nothing."

The Americans, who have been sending out ships with sham bolt-heads on their timbers, and only half their bolts, may meditate on that "buildeth a town with blood."

The Americans, who have been sending out ships with fake bolt heads on their timber and only half their bolts, might think about that "buildeth a town with blood."

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ See __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.


ADDENDA.

Note, p. 19.—"Fatherly authority."

This statement could not, of course, be heard without displeasure by a certain class of politicians; and in one of the notices of these lectures given in the Manchester journals at the time, endeavour was made to get quit of it by referring to the Divine authority, as the only Paternal power with respect to which men were truly styled "brethren." Of course it is so, and, equally of course, all human government is nothing else than the executive expression of this Divine authority. The moment government ceases to be the practical enforcement of Divine law, it is tyranny; and the meaning which I attach to the words, "paternal government," is, in more extended terms, simply this—"The executive fulfilment, by formal human methods, of the will of the Father of mankind respecting His children." I could not give such a definition of Government as this in a popular lecture; and even in written form, it will necessarily suggest many objections, of which I must notice and answer the most probable.

This statement, of course, couldn't be taken well by certain politicians. In one of the reviews of these lectures published in the Manchester newspapers at the time, an attempt was made to dismiss it by referencing Divine authority as the only paternal power under which people are truly called "brothers." This is indeed the case, and equally, all human governance is just the practical expression of that Divine authority. The moment government stops being the active enforcement of Divine law, it becomes tyranny; and what I mean by "paternal government" is, in broader terms, simply this—"The active fulfillment, through established human means, of the will of our Creator regarding His children." I couldn't present such a definition of government in a public lecture; and even in writing, it will inevitably raise several objections, of which I need to address the most likely ones.

Only, in order to avoid the recurrence of such tiresome phrases as "it may be answered in the second place," and "it will be objected in the third place," etc., I will ask the reader's leave to arrange the discussion in the form of simple dialogue, letting O. stand for objector, and R. for response.

Only, to avoid repeating cumbersome phrases like "it could be answered next," and "an objection could be raised after that," etc., I’ll ask the reader’s permission to structure the discussion as a straightforward dialogue, with O. representing the objector, and R. representing the responder.

O.—You define your paternal government to be the executive fulfilment, by formal human methods, of the Divine will. But, assuredly, that will cannot stand in need of aid or expression from human laws. It cannot fail of its fulfilment.

O.—You define your paternal government as the execution of the Divine will through established human methods. However, it’s clear that this will does not require support or expression from human laws. It will inevitably be fulfilled.

R.—In the final sense it cannot; and in that sense, men who are committing murder and stealing are fulfilling the will of God as much as the best and kindest people in the world.[Pg 87] But in the limited and present sense, the only sense with which we have anything to do, God's will concerning man is fulfilled by some men, and thwarted by others. And those men who either persuade or enforce the doing of it, stand towards those who are rebellious against it exactly in the position of faithful children in a family, who, when the father is out of sight, either compel or persuade the rest to do as their father would have them, were he present; and in so far as they are expressing and maintaining, for the time, the paternal authority, they exercise, in the exact sense in which I mean the phrase to be understood, paternal government over the rest.

R.—In the ultimate sense, it can't; and in that regard, people who commit murder and theft are fulfilling God's will just as much as the kindest and best individuals in the world.[Pg 87] However, in a more limited and present sense, which is the only one we are concerned with, God's will regarding humanity is fulfilled by some people and hindered by others. Those individuals who either encourage or enforce this will are like obedient children in a family who, when their father is not around, either compel or persuade the others to act as he would want if he were there; and to the extent that they are expressing and upholding parental authority in that moment, they are exercising, in the exact way I intend the phrase to be understood, parental governance over the others.

O.—But, if Providence has left a liberty to man in many things in order to prove him, why should human law abridge that liberty, and take upon itself to compel what the great Lawgiver does not compel?

O.—But if Providence has given people the freedom to make many choices to test them, why should human law restrict that freedom and try to enforce what the great Lawgiver does not?

R.—It is confessed, in the enactment of any law whatsoever, that human lawgivers have a right to do this. For, if you have no right to abridge any of the liberty which Providence has left to man, you have no right to punish any one for committing murder or robbery. You ought to leave them to the punishment of God and Nature. But if you think yourself under obligation to punish, as far as human laws can, the violation of the will of God by those great sins, you are certainly under the same obligation to punish, with proportionately less punishment, the violation of His will in less sins.

R.—It's acknowledged that when creating any law, human lawmakers have the right to do so. If you don’t have the right to limit any of the freedom that Providence has granted to humanity, then you cannot rightfully punish anyone for crimes like murder or robbery. You should leave those matters to the judgment of God and Nature. However, if you believe you are obligated to punish such violations of God's will through laws, then you are equally obligated to impose, albeit with lesser consequences, penalties for the violation of His will in less serious offenses.

O.—No; you must not attempt to punish less sins by law, because you cannot properly define nor ascertain them. Everybody can determine whether murder has been committed or not, but you cannot determine how far people have been unjust or cruel in minor matters, and therefore cannot make or execute laws concerning minor matters.

No.—You shouldn't try to punish lesser sins with the law, because you can't clearly define or measure them. Everyone can tell if murder has happened, but you can't figure out how unjust or cruel people have been in smaller issues, so you can't create or enforce laws about those.

R.—If I propose to you to punish faults which cannot be defined, or to execute laws which cannot be made equitable, reject the laws I propose. But do not generally object to the principle of law.

R.—If I suggest punishing faults that can't be clearly defined, or enforcing laws that can't be made fair, then reject the laws I'm proposing. However, don't dismiss the fundamental idea of law itself.

O.—Yes; I generally object to the principle of law as applied to minor things; because, if you could succeed (which you cannot) in regulating the entire conduct of men by law in[Pg 88] little things as well as great, you would take away from human life all its probationary character, and render many virtues and pleasures impossible. You would reduce virtue to the movement of a machine, instead of the act of a spirit.

O.—Yes; I usually disagree with the idea of law being applied to small matters; because, if you could manage (which you can't) to control every aspect of people's behavior by law in[Pg 88] both minor and major issues, you would strip human life of its trial and error nature, making many virtues and joys unattainable. You would turn virtue into a mechanical operation, rather than an expression of the spirit.

R.—You have just said, parenthetically, and I fully and willingly admit it, that it is impossible to regulate all minor matters by law. Is it not probable, therefore, that the degree in which it is possible to regulate them by it, is also the degree in which it is right to regulate them by it? Or what other means of judgment will you employ, to separate the things which ought to be formally regulated from the things which ought not. You admit that great sins should be legally repressed; but you say that small sins should not be legally repressed. How do you distinguish between great and small sins; and how do you intend to determine, or do you in practice of daily life determine, on what occasions you should compel people to do right, and on what occasions you should leave them the option of doing wrong?

R.—You just mentioned, almost as an aside, and I completely agree, that it's not feasible to regulate every minor issue by law. Isn’t it likely, then, that the extent to which these issues can be regulated by law is also the extent to which it’s appropriate to regulate them? What other criteria will you use to distinguish between things that should be formally regulated and those that shouldn’t? You acknowledge that serious offenses should be legally addressed; however, you believe that minor offenses shouldn’t be. How do you differentiate between serious and minor offenses, and how do you plan to figure out, or do you already figure out in your daily life, when to enforce what’s right and when to allow people the choice to do wrong?

O.—I think you cannot make any accurate or logical distinction in such matters; but that common sense and instinct have, in all civilized nations, indicated certain crimes of great social harmfulness, such as murder, theft, adultery, slander, and such like, which it is proper to repress legally; and that common sense and instinct indicate also the kind of crimes which it is proper for laws to let alone, such as miserliness, ill-natured speaking, and many of those commercial dishonesties which I have a notion you want your paternal government to interfere with.

O.—I don’t think you can make a clear or logical distinction in matters like this; however, common sense and instinct have pointed out, in all civilized societies, certain crimes that cause significant harm, like murder, theft, adultery, slander, and similar offenses, which should be legally punished. Common sense and instinct also suggest the kinds of crimes that laws should ignore, like being stingy, rude remarks, and various forms of commercial dishonesty that I believe you want your government to step in on.

R.—Pray do not alarm yourself about what my paternal government is likely to interfere with, but keep to the matter in hand. You say that "common sense and instinct" have, in all civilized nations, distinguished between the sins that ought to be legally dealt with and that ought not. Do you mean that the laws of all civilized nations are perfect?

R.—Please don’t worry about what my father’s government might get involved in, but let’s focus on the topic at hand. You say that "common sense and instinct" have, in all civilized nations, differentiated between the sins that should be legally addressed and those that shouldn’t. Are you suggesting that the laws of all civilized nations are flawless?

O.—No; certainly not.

Nope; definitely not.

R.—Or that they are perfect at least in their discrimination of what crimes they should deal with, and what crimes they should let alone?

R.—Or that they're at least really good at figuring out which crimes they should address and which ones they should ignore?

O.—No; not exactly.[Pg 89]

No, not really.

R.—What do you mean, then?

R.—What do you mean?

O.—I mean that the general tendency is right in the laws of civilized nations; and that, in due course of time, natural sense and instinct point out the matters they should be brought to bear upon. And each question of legislation must be made a separate subject of inquiry as it presents itself: you cannot fix any general principles about what should be dealt with legally, and what should not.

O.—I mean that the overall direction of the laws of civilized nations is correct; and that, over time, common sense and instinct highlight the issues that need attention. Each legislative question must be examined as it comes up: you can’t establish any broad principles about what should be addressed legally and what shouldn’t.

R.—Supposing it to be so, do you think there are any points in which our English legislation is capable of amendment, as it bears on commercial and economical matters, in this present time?

R.—If that's the case, do you think there are any areas where our English laws could be improved regarding commercial and economic issues today?

O.—Of course I do.

O.—Of course I do.

R.—Well, then, let us discuss these together quietly; and if the points that I want amended seem to you incapable of amendment, or not in need of amendment, say so: but don't object, at starting, to the mere proposition of applying law to things which have not had law applied to them before. You have admitted the fitness of my expression, "paternal government:" it only has been, and remains, a question between us, how far such government should extend. Perhaps you would like it only to regulate, among the children, the length of their lessons; and perhaps I should like it also to regulate the hardness of their cricket-balls: but cannot you wait quietly till you know what I want it to do, before quarrelling with the thing itself?

R.—Alright, let’s talk about this calmly together; and if the points I want to change seem impossible to change or not even necessary, just let me know. But please, don’t reject the idea of applying the law to things that haven’t had law applied to them before right from the start. You’ve agreed that my term, “paternal government,” is appropriate; the question between us has just been how far that government should go. Maybe you think it should only manage things like the length of the children’s lessons, and maybe I think it should also control the hardness of their cricket balls. But can you hold off on arguing until you fully understand what I want it to do?

O.—No; I cannot wait quietly: in fact I don't see any use in beginning such a discussion at all, because I am quite sure from the first, that you want to meddle with things that you have no business with, and to interfere with healthy liberty of action in all sorts of ways; and I know that you can't propose any laws that would be of real use.[18]

No.—I can't sit back and wait: honestly, I don't see the point in starting this discussion at all because I'm sure from the beginning that you want to interfere with things that aren't your concern and disrupt people's freedom to act in various ways; and I know you can't suggest any rules that would actually be helpful.[18]

R.—If[Pg 90] you indeed know that, you would be wrong to hear me any farther. But if you are only in painful doubt about me, which makes you unwilling to run the risk of wasting your time, I will tell you beforehand what I really do think about this same liberty of action, namely, that whenever we can make a perfectly equitable law about any matter, or even a law securing, on the whole, more just conduct than unjust, we ought to make that law; and that there will yet, on these conditions, always remain a number of matters respecting which legalism and formalism are impossible; enough, and more than enough, to exercise all human powers of individual judgment, and afford all kinds of scope to individual character. I think this; but of course it can only be proved by separate examination of the possibilities of formal restraint in each given field of action; and these two lectures are nothing more than a sketch of such a detailed examination in one field, namely, that of art. You will find, however, one or two other remarks on such possibilities in the next note.

R.—If[Pg 90] you really know that, you’d be mistaken to listen to me any further. But if you’re just in painful doubt about me, which makes you hesitant to risk wasting your time, I’ll tell you upfront what I truly think about this idea of liberty of action: whenever we can create a completely fair law about any issue, or even a law that generally leads to more just behavior than unjust behavior, we should establish that law. However, even under these circumstances, there will always be many issues where strict legalism and formalism won’t work; there will be more than enough to challenge all human capacities for individual judgment and provide plenty of space for personal character. This is my belief, but it can only be backed up by a detailed examination of the potential for formal restrictions in each specific area of action; and these two lectures are just an outline of such a thorough exploration in one area, which is art. You will, however, find a few other comments on these possibilities in the next note.

Note 2nd, p. 21.—"Right to public support."

It did not appear to me desirable, in the course of the spoken lecture, to enter into details or offer suggestions on the questions of the regulation of labour and distribution of relief, as it would have been impossible to do so without touching in many disputed or disputable points, not easily handled before a general audience. But I must now supply what is wanting to make my general statement clear.

It didn’t seem appropriate to me during the lecture to get into details or suggest solutions regarding labor regulation and distribution of aid, as it would have been impossible to do so without addressing many debated or controversial issues that aren't easy to discuss in front of a general audience. However, I now need to provide the missing information to clarify my overall statement.

I believe, in the first place, that no Christian nation has any business to see one of its members in distress without helping him, though, perhaps, at the same time punishing him: help, of course—in nine cases out of ten—meaning guidance, much more than gift, and, therefore, interference with liberty. When a peasant mother sees one of her careless children fall into a ditch, her first proceeding is to pull him out; her second, to box his ears; her third, ordinarily, to lead him carefully a little way by the hand, or send him home for the rest of the day. The child usually cries, and very often would clearly prefer remaining in the ditch; and if he understood any of the terms of politics, would certainly express resentment at[Pg 91] the interference with his individual liberty: but the mother has done her duty. Whereas the usual call of the mother nation to any of her children, under such circumstances, has lately been nothing more than the foxhunter's,—"Stay still there; I shall clear you." And if we always could clear them, their requests to be left in muddy independence might be sometimes allowed by kind people, or their cries for help disdained by unkind ones. But we can't clear them. The whole nation is, in fact, bound together, as men are by ropes on a glacier—if one falls, the rest must either lift him or drag him along with them[19] as dead weight, not without much increase of danger to themselves. And the law of right being manifestly in this, as, whether manifestly or not, it is always, the law of prudence, the only question is, how this wholesome help and interference are to be administered.[Pg 92]

I believe, first of all, that no Christian nation should ignore one of its members in distress without offering help, even if that also involves some punishment. Typically, help here means guidance rather than just giving, which can interfere with a person's freedom. When a mother sees one of her careless kids fall into a ditch, her first action is to pull him out; her second is to scold him; and her third is usually to either guide him a bit by the hand or send him home for the rest of the day. The child usually cries and might even prefer to stay in the ditch; if he understood anything about politics, he would definitely complain about being interfered with in his personal freedom. But the mother has done her duty. On the other hand, the usual response from a mother nation to any of her children in such situations has recently been nothing more than a foxhunter's call: "Just stay there; I’ll get you out." And if we could always pull them out, their requests to remain in their muddy independence might sometimes be granted by kind people, or their cries for help ignored by unkind ones. But we can’t always pull them out. The whole nation is, in essence, tied together, like people on a glacier – if one falls, the others must either lift him up or drag him along with them as dead weight, which increases the danger for everyone. And because the law of what’s right is clearly tied to this, as it always is, the question becomes how to administer this helpful interference wisely.

The first interference should be in education. In order that men may be able to support themselves when they are grown, their strength must be properly developed while they are young; and the state should always see to this—not allowing their health to be broken by too early labour, nor their powers to be wasted for want of knowledge. Some questions connected with this matter are noticed farther on under the head "Trial Schools:" one point I must notice here, that I believe all youths of whatever rank, ought to learn some manual trade thoroughly; for it is quite wonderful how much a man's views of life are cleared by the attainment of the capacity of doing any one thing well with his hands and arms. For a long time, what right life there was in the upper classes of Europe depended in no small degree on the necessity which each man was under of being able to fence; at this day, the most useful things which boys learn at public schools, are, I believe, riding, rowing, and cricketing. But it would be far better that members of Parliament should be able to plough straight, and make a horseshoe, than only to feather oars neatly or point their toes prettily in stirrups. Then, in literary and scientific teaching, the great point of economy is to give the discipline of it through knowledge which will immediately bear on practical life. Our literary work has long been economically useless to us because too much concerned with dead languages; and our scientific work will yet, for some time, be a good deal lost, because scientific men are too fond or too vain of their systems, and waste the student's time in endeavouring to give him large views, and make him perceive interesting connections of facts; when there is not one student, no, nor one man, in a thousand, who can feel the beauty of a system, or even take it clearly into his head; but nearly all men can understand, and most will be interested in, the facts which bear on daily life. Botanists have discovered some wonderful connection between nettles and figs, which a cowboy who will never see a ripe fig in his life need not be at all troubled about; but it will be interesting to him to know what effect nettles have on hay, and what taste they will give to porridge; and it will give him nearly a new life if he can be got but once, in a spring time, to look well at the beautiful circlet of the white nettle blossom, and work out with his schoolmaster the curves of its petals, and the way it is set on its central mast. So, the principle of chemical equivalents, beautiful as it is, matters far less to a peasant boy, and even to most sons of gentlemen, than their knowing how to find whether the water is wholesome in the back-kitchen cistern, or whether the seven-acre field wants sand or chalk.

The first area that needs attention is education. For people to support themselves as adults, their strength should be properly developed while they’re young, and the government should ensure this—preventing their health from being harmed by excessive early work and making sure they don’t lose their potential due to a lack of knowledge. Some related issues are discussed further under “Trial Schools,” but I want to highlight here that I believe all young people, regardless of their background, should learn a manual trade well; it’s amazing how much clearer a person's perspective on life becomes when they can do something skillfully with their hands. For a long time, the quality of life for the upper classes in Europe was largely dependent on every man being able to fence; nowadays, I believe the most valuable skills boys learn in public schools are riding, rowing, and playing cricket. However, it would be much better if Members of Parliament could plow straight and make a horseshoe rather than just row well or look good in the saddle. Then, in terms of literature and science education, the main focus should be on practical knowledge that directly applies to everyday life. Our literary studies have long been economically useless because they've focused too much on dead languages, and our scientific efforts will also be largely ineffective for a while because scientists often get too caught up in their theories, wasting students’ time trying to give them broad perspectives or making them see interesting connections between facts. In truth, there isn’t one student, nor one person in a thousand, who can appreciate the elegance of a system or even grasp it clearly; but almost everyone can understand and will be interested in facts that relate to everyday life. Botanists may find fascinating links between nettles and figs, but a cowboy who will never see a ripe fig should not be concerned about that; instead, it’s more relevant for him to know the effects of nettles on hay and what flavor they add to porridge. It could significantly enrich his life if he had the opportunity one spring to really look at the lovely circle of white nettle flowers and, with his teacher, explore the curves of their petals and how they sit on their central stem. Similarly, while the principle of chemical equivalents is beautiful, it matters far less to a peasant boy, or even many gentlemen’s sons, than knowing how to determine if the water is safe to drink from the back kitchen cistern or whether the seven-acre field needs sand or chalk.

Having, then, directed the studies of our youth so as to make them practically serviceable men at the time of their entrance into life, that entrance should always be ready for them in cases where their private circumstances present no opening. There ought to be government establishments for every trade, in which all youths who desired it should be received as apprentices on their leaving school; and men thrown out of work received at all times. At these government manufactories the discipline should be strict, and the wages steady, not varying at all in proportion to the demand for the article, but only in proportion to the price of food; the commodities[Pg 93] produced being laid up in store to meet sudden demands, and sudden fluctuations in prices prevented:—that gradual and necessary fluctuation only being allowed which is properly consequent on larger or more limited supply of raw material and other natural causes. When there was a visible tendency to produce a glut of any commodity, that tendency should be checked by directing the youth at the government schools into other trades; and the yearly surplus of commodities should be the principal means of government provision for the poor. That provision should be large, and not disgraceful to them. At present there are very strange notions in the public mind respecting the receiving of alms: most people are willing to take them in the form of a pension from government, but unwilling to take them in the form of a pension from their parishes. There may be some reason for this singular prejudice, in the fact of the government pension being usually given as a definite acknowledgment of some service done to the country;—but the parish pension is, or ought to be, given precisely on the same terms. A labourer serves his country with his spade, just as a man in the middle ranks of life serves it with his sword, pen, or lancet: if the service is less, and therefore the wages during health less, then the reward, when health is broken, may be less, but not, therefore, less honourable; and it ought to be quite as natural and straightforward a matter for a labourer to take his pension from his parish, because he has deserved well of his parish, as for a man in higher rank to take his pension from his country, because he has deserved well of his country. If there be any disgrace in coming to the parish, because it may imply improvidence in early life, much more is there disgrace in coming to the government: since improvidence is far less justifiable in a highly educated than in an imperfectly educated man; and far less justifiable in a high rank, where extravagance must have been luxury, than in a low rank, where it may only have been comfort. So that the real fact of the matter is, that people will take alms delightedly, consisting of a carriage and footmen, because those do not look like alms to the people in the street; but they will not take alms consisting only of bread and water and coals, because everybody would understand what those meant.[Pg 94] Mind, I do not want any one to refuse the carriage who ought to have it; but neither do I want them to refuse the coals. I should indeed be sorry if any change in our views on these subjects involved the least lessening of self-dependence in the English mind: but the common shrinking of men from the acceptance of public charity is not self-dependence, but mere base and selfish pride. It is not that they are unwilling to live at their neighbours' expense, but that they are unwilling to confess they do: it is not dependence they wish to avoid, but gratitude. They will take places in which they know there is nothing to be done—they will borrow money they know they cannot repay—they will carry on a losing business with other people's capital—they will cheat the public in their shops, or sponge on their friends at their houses; but to say plainly they are poor men, who need the nation's help, and go into an almshouse—this they loftily repudiate, and virtuously prefer being thieves to being paupers.

Having guided the education of our youth to make them useful members of society when they start their careers, that transition should always be prepared for them, especially when their personal situations offer no opportunities. There should be government programs for every trade, where any young person who wants a spot can be accepted as an apprentice upon finishing school; and people out of work should be welcomed at all times. At these government factories, discipline should be strict, and wages steady, not fluctuating based on the demand for the products, but only reflecting the cost of food; the goods produced[Pg 93] should be stored to meet sudden needs, and unexpected price changes should be avoided:—only allowing the gradual and necessary fluctuations that naturally arise from changes in the supply of raw materials and other natural factors. When there's a clear risk of producing an oversupply of any product, that risk should be addressed by redirecting youth at government schools into different trades; and the yearly surplus of goods should primarily fund government aid for the less fortunate. This assistance should be substantial and respectful. Currently, there are some odd views regarding accepting aid: most people are fine with receiving it as a government pension but hesitant to accept it as a parish pension. There might be some reason for this odd bias, as government pensions are typically seen as rewards for services rendered to the nation;—but parish pensions should be granted on the same basis. A laborer contributes to their country with their work, just as someone in a higher position contributes with their skills or knowledge: if the laborer's contribution is seen as lesser, resulting in lower pay when healthy, then their reward when they can no longer work may be smaller, but it’s still as honorable; and it should be just as normal and straightforward for a laborer to receive their pension from their parish, since they have served it well, as it is for someone in a higher position to receive their pension from the country for their service. If there is some shame in seeking help from the parish, as it might suggest poor planning in their early life, then the shame is even greater in approaching the government; since it's far less justifiable for someone well-educated to be irresponsible than for someone less educated; and much less justifiable for someone in a high position, where overspending is often viewed as luxury, than for someone in a lower position, where it may only be seen as seeking comfort. The truth is that people are happy to accept generous help that looks like wealth, with a carriage and footmen, because that doesn’t seem like charity to those observing; but they shy away from accepting help that’s just bread, water, and coal, because everyone would see what that really means.[Pg 94] Now, I don't want anyone to turn down the carriage they deserve; but I also don’t want them to reject the coal. I would genuinely feel bad if any shift in our attitudes about these issues meant even a slight reduction in self-reliance among the English people: but the common discomfort people have in accepting public aid isn’t about self-reliance, but rather a base and selfish pride. It’s not that they don’t want to benefit from others’ support; they just don’t want to admit they do. They’re trying to avoid dependence, but more than that, they want to escape feeling grateful. They’ll take jobs knowing there’s nothing to do—they’ll borrow money they can’t pay back—they’ll keep running a losing business with someone else’s money—they’ll deceive the public in their stores, or take advantage of their friends at home; but to openly acknowledge they are poor and need national assistance, and go into a care home—this they proudly reject and would rather be thieves than be considered paupers.

I trust that these deceptive efforts of dishonest men to appear independent, and the agonizing efforts of unfortunate men to remain independent, may both be in some degree checked by a better administration and understanding of laws respecting the poor. But the ordinances for relief and the ordinances for labour must go together; otherwise distress caused by misfortune will always be confounded, as it is now, with distress caused by idleness, unthrift, and fraud. It is only when the state watches and guides the middle life of men, that it can, without disgrace to them, protect their old age, acknowledging in that protection that they have done their duty, or at least some portion of their duty, in better days.

I hope that these deceptive tactics of dishonest people trying to seem independent, along with the desperate struggles of unfortunate people trying to stay independent, can both be somewhat curbed by a better approach to managing the laws concerning the poor. However, the rules for providing help and the rules for work must go hand in hand; otherwise, the hardship from misfortune will always be mixed up, as it is now, with the hardship from laziness, carelessness, and deceit. The state can only protect people's old age, without shaming them, when it supervises and supports their working lives, recognizing that they have fulfilled their duties, or at least part of their duties, during better times.

I know well how strange, fanciful, or impracticable these suggestions will appear to most of the business men of this day; men who conceive the proper state of the world to be simply that of a vast and disorganized mob, scrambling each for what he can get, trampling down its children and old men in the mire, and doing what work it finds must be done with any irregular squad of labourers it can bribe or inveigle together, and afterwards scatter to starvation. A great deal may, indeed, be done in this way by a nation strong-elbowed and[Pg 95] strong-hearted as we are—not easily frightened by pushing, nor discouraged by falls. But it is still not the right way of doing things for people who call themselves Christians. Every so named soul of man claims from every other such soul, protection and education in childhood—help or punishment in middle life—reward or relief, if needed, in old age; all of these should be completely and unstintingly given; and they can only be given by the organization of such a system as I have described.

I understand how odd, unrealistic, or impractical these suggestions may seem to many businesspeople today; individuals who view the ideal world as a massive, chaotic crowd, each person scrambling for what they can obtain, trampling on the vulnerable like children and the elderly in the mud, and doing whatever work they can manage with any loosely organized group of workers they can bribe or convince to assemble, only to disperse them into hardship later. A lot can indeed be achieved this way by a nation as resilient and determined as we are—not easily intimidated by pushing, nor discouraged by setbacks. However, this isn’t the right approach for people who call themselves Christians. Every individual deserves, from one another, protection and education in childhood—support or discipline in adulthood—judgment or assistance, if necessary, in old age; all of which should be provided fully and generously; and this can only be accomplished through the organization of a system like the one I’ve outlined.

Note 3rd, p. 24.—"Trial Schools."

It may be seriously questioned by the reader how much of painting talent we really lose on our present system,[20] and how [Pg 96] much we should gain by the proposed trial schools. For it might be thought, that as matters stand at present, we have more painters than we ought to have, having so many bad ones, and that all youths who had true painters' genius forced their way out of obscurity.

It’s worth considering how much artistic talent we actually miss out on with our current system,[20] and how much we could gain from the suggested trial schools. One might think that, given the current situation, we have more painters than we need, especially since there are so many poor ones, and that any young people with genuine artistic talent have managed to rise from obscurity.

This is not so. It is difficult to analyse the characters of mind which cause youths to mistake their vocation, and to endeavour to [Pg 97] become artists, when they have no true artist's gift. But the fact is, that multitudes of young men do this, and that by far the greater number of living artists are men who have mistaken their vocation. The peculiar circumstances of modern life, which exhibit art in almost every form to the sight of the youths in our great cities, have a natural tendency to fill their imaginations with borrowed ideas, and their minds with imperfect science; the mere dislike of mechanical employments, either felt to be irksome, or believed to be degrading, urges numbers of young men to become painters, in the same temper in which they would enlist or go to sea; others, the sons of engravers or artists, taught the business of the art by their parents, and having no gift for it themselves, follow it as the means of livelihood, in an ignoble patience; or, if ambitious, seek to attract regard, or distance rivalry, by fantastic, meretricious, or unprecedented applications of their mechanical skill; while finally, many men earnest in feeling, and conscientious in principle, mistake their desire to be useful for a love of art, and their quickness of emotion for its capacity, and pass their lives in painting moral and instructive pictures, which might almost justify us in thinking nobody could be a painter but a rogue. On the other hand, I believe that much of the best artistical intellect is daily lost in other avocations. Generally, the temper which would make an admirable artist is humble and observant, capable of taking much interest in little things, and of entertaining itself pleasantly in the dullest circumstances. Suppose, added to these characters, a steady conscientiousness which seeks to do its duty wherever it may be placed, and the power, denied to few artistical minds, of ingenious invention in almost any practical department of human skill, and it can hardly be doubted that the very humility and conscientiousness which would have perfected the painter, have in many instances prevented his becoming one; and that in the quiet life of our steady craftsmen—sagacious manufacturers and uncomplaining clerks—there may frequently be concealed more genius than ever is raised to the direction of our public works, or to be the mark of our public praises.

This isn’t true. It’s hard to analyze the mindset that leads young people to confuse their calling and try to become artists when they lack genuine artistic talent. Yet, the reality is that many young men do this, and the vast majority of living artists are those who have misjudged their vocation. The unique circumstances of modern life, which showcase art in nearly every form to youths in our big cities, tend to fill their imaginations with borrowed ideas and their minds with incomplete knowledge; the simple aversion to mechanical jobs—either seen as boring or considered beneath them—drives many young men to pursue painting, just as they might enlist in the military or go to sea. Others, the children of engravers or artists, are taught the craft by their parents and, lacking talent themselves, follow it as a way to earn a living, in a tiresome resignation; or, if they are ambitious, they try to gain attention or outshine others with flashy or unconventional uses of their mechanical skills. Many sincere individuals, earnest in their beliefs, confuse their desire to be helpful with a passion for art, and their sensitivity for artistic ability, spending their lives creating moral and educational artwork, leading one to think that only rogues could truly be painters. Conversely, I believe much of the best artistic talent is wasted in other jobs. Typically, the temperament suited to make an outstanding artist is humble and observant, able to find great interest in small things and to keep itself entertained even in the dullest situations. If we add to these traits a steady sense of responsibility that strives to fulfill its duties wherever it may find itself, along with the rare ability for inventive thinking found in many artistic minds across various practical fields, it’s undeniable that the very humility and conscientiousness that could have made someone a great painter have, in many cases, prevented them from becoming one; and that in the quiet lives of our dependable workers—wise manufacturers and silent clerks—there might often lie more genius than ever reaches the forefront of our public projects or earns our public accolades.

It is indeed probable, that intense disposition for art will[Pg 98] conquer the most formidable obstacles, if the surrounding circumstances are such as at all to present the idea of such conquest, to the mind; but we have no ground for concluding that Giotto would ever have been more than a shepherd, if Cimabue had not by chance found him drawing; or that among the shepherds of the Apennines there were no other Giottos, undiscovered by Cimabue. We are too much in the habit of considering happy accidents as what are called "special Providences;" and thinking that when any great work needs to be done, the man who is to do it will certainly be pointed out by Providence, be he shepherd or sea-boy; and prepared for his work by all kinds of minor providences, in the best possible way. Whereas all the analogies of God's operations in other matters prove the contrary of this; we find that "of thousand seeds, He often brings but one to bear," often not one; and the one seed which He appoints to bear is allowed to bear crude or perfect fruit according to the dealings of the husbandman with it. And there cannot be a doubt in the mind of any person accustomed to take broad and logical views of the world's history, that its events are ruled by Providence in precisely the same manner as its harvests; that the seeds of good and evil are broadcast among men, just as the seeds of thistles and fruits are; and that according to the force of our industry, and wisdom of our husbandry, the ground will bring forth to us figs or thistles. So that when it seems needed that a certain work should be done for the world, and no man is there to do it, we have no right to say that God did not wish it to be done, and therefore sent no man able to do it. The probability (if I wrote my own convictions, I should say certainty) is, that He sent many men, hundreds of men, able to do it; and that we have rejected them, or crushed them; by our previous folly of conduct or of institution, we have rendered it impossible to distinguish, or impossible to reach them; and when the need for them comes, and we suffer for the want of them, it is not that God refuses to send us deliverers, and specially appoints all our consequent sufferings; but that He has sent, and we have refused, the deliverers; and the pain is then wrought out by His eternal law, as surely as famine is wrought out by eternal law for a nation which will[Pg 99] neither plough nor sow. No less are we in error in supposing, as we so frequently do, that if a man be found, he is sure to be in all respects fitted for the work to be done, as the key is to the lock; and that every accident which happened in the forging him, only adapted him more truly to the wards. It is pitiful to hear historians beguiling themselves and their readers, by tracing in the early history of great men, the minor circumstances which fitted them for the work they did, without ever taking notice of the other circumstances which as assuredly unfitted them for it; so concluding that miraculous interposition prepared them in all points for everything and that they did all that could have been desired or hoped for from them: whereas the certainty of the matter is that, throughout their lives, they were thwarted and corrupted by some things as certainly as they were helped and disciplined by others; and that, in the kindliest and most reverent view which can justly be taken of them, they were but poor mistaken creatures, struggling with a world more profoundly mistaken than they;—assuredly sinned against, or sinning in thousands of ways, and bringing out at last a maimed result—not what they might or ought to have done, but all that could be done against the world's resistance, and in spite of their own sorrowful falsehood to themselves.

It is very likely that a strong passion for art will[Pg 98] overcome the toughest obstacles, as long as the surrounding circumstances at least hint at the possibility of such a triumph; however, we have no reason to think that Giotto would have become anything more than a shepherd if Cimabue hadn't accidentally discovered him drawing. We often tend to view happy accidents as "special Providences," believing that when a significant task needs to be accomplished, the person chosen for it—whether a shepherd or a sailor—will surely be indicated by Providence and prepared through various small fortunities in the best way possible. Yet, all the analogies of God's dealings in other areas suggest the opposite: we see that "of a thousand seeds, He often brings forth only one," and sometimes none at all; and the single seed that He chooses to thrive may yield raw or perfected fruit depending on how the farmer tends to it. Anyone who takes a broad and logical perspective on history can clearly see that events are directed by Providence in the same way as harvests; the seeds of good and evil are sown among people just like thistles and fruits; and based on our effort and the wisdom of our farming practices, the land will yield us figs or thistles. Therefore, when it seems necessary for a particular task to be carried out in the world and no one is available to do it, we have no right to claim that God didn’t want it to happen and thus sent no capable person. The likelihood (though I would say certainty based on my beliefs) is that He sent many individuals—hundreds—who were capable, and that we either ignored or undermined them; through our past foolish actions or systems, we have made it impossible to recognize or reach them; and when the need arises and we suffer from their absence, it is not that God has chosen not to send us helpers or intentionally appoints our resulting hardships; rather, He has sent, and we have rejected, the deliverers. The suffering we face is then brought about by His eternal law, just as famine occurs through eternal law for a nation that will[Pg 99] neither plough nor sow. Furthermore, we are also mistaken in believing, as we often do, that if a person is found, they will certainly be perfectly suited for the task at hand, much like a key fits a lock; and that every event in their development has only made them more fitting for the challenges. It’s disheartening to hear historians fooling themselves and their readers by tracking the minor events in the early lives of great individuals that prepared them for their roles, without ever acknowledging the other circumstances that just as surely hindered them; ultimately concluding that miraculous intervention ensured they were fully prepared for everything and that they delivered all that could reasonably be expected of them. In reality, they were continually thwarted and corrupted by certain factors just as surely as they were aided and refined by others; and even when taking the most compassionate and respectful view of them, they were ultimately flawed beings struggling against a world that was even more confused than themselves—certainly wronged or sinning in countless ways, producing in the end an imperfect outcome—not what they might or should have achieved, but rather all that could be accomplished in defiance of the world's opposition and despite their own troubling self-deceptions.

And this being so, it is the practical duty of a wise nation, first to withdraw, as far as may be, its youth from destructive influences;—then to try its material as far as possible, and to lose the use of none that is good. I do not mean by "withdrawing from destructive influences" the keeping of youths out of trials; but the keeping them out of the way of things purely and absolutely mischievous. I do not mean that we should shade our green corn in all heat, and shelter it in all frost, but only that we should dyke out the inundation from it, and drive the fowls away from it. Let your youth labour and suffer; but do not let it starve, nor steal, nor blaspheme.

And given this, it's the responsibility of a wise nation to first protect its young people from harmful influences as much as possible. Then, it should test them in every way and make sure not to waste any of their potential. By "protecting from harmful influences," I don't mean keeping young people sheltered from challenges; rather, I mean shielding them from things that are purely and utterly harmful. I don’t suggest that we should shield our crops from every bit of heat or frost, but rather that we should keep floodwaters away and protect them from birds. Let your youth work hard and face difficulties, but don’t let them go hungry, resort to theft, or act disrespectfully.

It is not, of course, in my power here to enter into details of schemes of education; and it will be long before the results of experiments now in progress will give data for the solution of the most difficult questions connected with the subject, of[Pg 100] which the principal one is the mode in which the chance of advancement in life is to be extended to all, and yet made compatible with contentment in the pursuit of lower avocations by those whose abilities do not qualify them for the higher. But the general principle of trial schools lies at the root of the matter—of schools, that is to say, in which the knowledge offered and discipline enforced shall be all a part of a great assay of the human soul, and in which the one shall be increased, the other directed, as the tried heart and brain will best bear, and no otherwise. One thing, however, I must say, that in this trial I believe all emulation to be a false motive, and all giving of prizes a false means. All that you can depend upon in a boy, as significative of true power, likely to issue in good fruit, is his will to work for the work's sake, not his desire to surpass his schoolfellows; and the aim of the teaching you give him ought to be, to prove to him and strengthen in him his own separate gift, not to puff him into swollen rivalry with those who are everlastingly greater than he: still less ought you to hang favours and ribands about the neck of the creature who is the greatest, to make the rest envy him. Try to make them love him and follow him, not struggle with him.

It’s not really in my power to go into the details of education plans here, and it will take a while before the results of current experiments provide information that can help answer the toughest questions related to this topic, of[Pg 100] which the main one is how to give everyone a chance to improve their lives while also ensuring that those who aren’t cut out for higher roles can find satisfaction in their simpler jobs. But the idea behind trial schools is central to this—these are schools where the knowledge offered and discipline enforced are part of a larger examination of the human spirit, where both can grow and be directed in a way that suits each individual’s tested heart and mind. However, I believe that competition is a misguided motivation, and giving out prizes is an ineffective approach. What you can truly rely on in a boy, as a sign of real potential likely to yield positive results, is his willingness to work for the sake of the work itself, not his urge to outdo his classmates. The goal of the education you provide should be to help him recognize and strengthen his unique talents, rather than inflating his ego through rivalry with those who are inevitably more accomplished than he is. Even less should you reward the top performer with favors and accolades to provoke envy in the others. Aim to foster a sense of admiration and camaraderie among them, rather than competition.

There must, of course, be examination to ascertain and attest both progress and relative capacity; but our aim should be to make the students rather look upon it as a means of ascertaining their own true positions and powers in the world, than as an arena in which to carry away a present victory. I have not, perhaps, in the course of the lecture, insisted enough on the nature of relative capacity and individual character, as the roots of all real value in Art. We are too much in the habit, in these days, of acting as if Art worth a price in the market were a commodity which people could be generally taught to produce, and as if the education of the artist, not his capacity, gave the sterling value to his work. No impression can possibly be more absurd or false. Whatever people can teach each other to do, they will estimate, and ought to estimate, only as common industry; nothing will ever fetch a high price but precisely that which cannot be taught, and which nobody can do but the man from whom[Pg 101] it is purchased. No state of society, nor stage of knowledge, ever does away with the natural pre-eminence of one man over another; and it is that pre-eminence, and that only, which will give work high value in the market, or which ought to do so. It is a bad sign of the judgment, and bad omen for the progress, of a nation, if it supposes itself to possess many artists of equal merit. Noble art is nothing less than the expression of a great soul; and great souls are not common things. If ever we confound their work with that of others, it is not through liberality, but through blindness.

There has to be some assessment to determine and confirm both progress and relative ability; however, our goal should be for students to see it more as a way to understand their true place and potential in the world, rather than as a competition to achieve immediate success. I may not have emphasized enough during the lecture the importance of relative ability and individual character as the foundation of all genuine value in Art. Nowadays, we often act as if Art that has a market value is simply a product that can be widely taught how to create, and as if the education of the artist, rather than their ability, is what gives their work true value. This notion is utterly absurd and false. Anything that people can teach each other to do will be valued, and should only be valued, as common work; only that which cannot be taught and which only the individual artist can create will ever command a high price. No society or level of knowledge can eliminate the natural superiority of one person over another; it is that superiority, and only that, which will assign high market value to work, or should do so. It reflects poorly on the judgment of a nation, and is a bad sign for its progress, if it believes it has many artists of equal talent. Great art is nothing less than the expression of a great soul; and great souls aren’t common. If we ever confuse their work with that of others, it’s not out of generosity, but out of ignorance.

Note 4th, p. 24.—"Public favour."

There is great difficulty in making any short or general statement of the difference between great and ignoble minds in their behaviour to the "public." It is by no means universally the case that a mean mind, as stated in the text, will bend itself to what you ask of it: on the contrary, there is one kind of mind, the meanest of all, which perpetually complains of the public, contemplates and proclaims itself as a "genius," refuses all wholesome discipline or humble office, and ends in miserable and revengeful ruin; also, the greatest minds are marked by nothing more distinctly than an inconceivable humility, and acceptance of work or instruction in any form, and from any quarter. They will learn from everybody, and do anything that anybody asks of them, so long as it involves only toil, or what other men would think degradation. But the point of quarrel, nevertheless, assuredly rises some day between the public and them, respecting some matter, not of humiliation, but of Fact. Your great man always at last comes to see something the public don't see. This something he will assuredly persist in asserting, whether with tongue or pencil, to be as he sees it, not as they see it; and all the world in a heap on the other side will not get him to say otherwise. Then, if the world objects to the saying, he may happen to get stoned or burnt for it, but that does not in the least matter to him; if the world has no particular objection to the saying, he may get leave to mutter it to himself till he dies, and be merely taken for an idiot; that [Pg 102] also does not matter to him—mutter it he will, according to what he perceives to be fact, and not at all according to the roaring of the walls of Red sea on the right hand or left of him. Hence the quarrel, sure at some time or other to be started between the public and him; while your mean man, though he will spit and scratch spiritedly at the public, while it does not attend to him, will bow to it for its clap in any direction, and say anything when he has got its ear, which he thinks will bring him another clap; and thus, as stated in the text, he and it go on smoothly together.

It's really challenging to make a simple or general statement about how great minds differ from lesser minds in their behavior towards the "public." It's definitely not true that a lesser mind, as mentioned in the text, will always conform to your demands. In fact, there's one type of mind—the least commendable of all—that constantly complains about the public, sees itself as a "genius," rejects any meaningful discipline or humble position, and ultimately ends up in a sad and bitter downfall. On the other hand, the greatest minds are often characterized by extraordinary humility; they are willing to accept work or guidance in any form and from anyone. They will learn from everyone and do whatever is asked of them, as long as it only involves hard work or what others would consider degrading. However, it's certain that one day a conflict arises between the public and these great individuals regarding some issue—not one of humiliation, but of truth. A great person inevitably comes to realize something the public doesn’t see. They will insist on expressing what they perceive to be true, whether through speech or writing, as they see it, and not how the public sees it. No amount of resistance from the masses will change their stance. If the public objects to what they say, they might get ostracized or even punished for it, but that won’t bother them at all. If the public has no strong objection, they might be allowed to quietly hold their opinion until they pass away, only to be regarded as foolish; that too doesn't concern them—they will insist on expressing what they see as truth, regardless of the loud opinions surrounding them. Thus, a certain conflict is destined to arise between the public and them; while a lesser individual might passionately criticize the public as long as it's ignoring them, they will eagerly comply for any applause and say whatever they think will earn them more approval, leading to a smooth relationship between them as stated in the text.

There are, however, times when the obstinacy of the mean man looks very like the obstinacy of the great one; but if you look closely into the matter, you will always see that the obstinacy of the first is in the pronunciation of "I;" and of the second, in the pronunciation of "It."

There are, however, times when the stubbornness of the petty person seems very much like the stubbornness of the powerful one; but if you take a closer look, you'll always notice that the stubbornness of the first is focused on the word "I," while the second's is centered around the word "It."

Note 5th, p. 38.—"Invention of new wants."

It would have been impossible for political economists long to have endured the error spoken of in the text,[21] had [Pg 103] they not been confused by an idea, in part well founded, that the energies and refinements, as well as the riches of civilized life arose from imaginary wants. It is quite true, that the savage who knows no needs but those of food, shelter, and sleep, and after he has snared his venison and patched the rents of his hut, passes the rest of his time in animal repose, is in a lower state than the man who labours incessantly that he may procure for himself the luxuries of civilization; and true also, that the difference between one and another nation in progressive power depends in great part on vain desires; but these idle motives are merely to be considered as giving exercise to the national body and mind; they are not sources of wealth, except so far as they give the habits of industry and acquisitiveness. If a boy is clumsy and lazy, we shall do good if we can persuade him to carve cherrystones and fly kites; and this use of his fingers and limbs may eventually be the cause of his becoming a wealthy and happy man; but we must not therefore argue that cherrystones are valuable property, or that kite-flying is a profitable mode of passing time. In like manner, a nation always wastes its time and labour directly, when it invents a new want of a frivolous kind, and yet the invention of such a want may be the sign of a healthy activity, and the labour undergone to satisfy the new want may lead, indirectly, to useful discoveries or to noble arts; so that a nation is not to be discouraged in its fancies when it is either too weak or foolish [Pg 104] to be moved to exertion by anything but fancies, or has attended to its serious business first. If a nation will not forge iron, but likes distilling lavender, by all means give it lavender to distil; only do not let its economists suppose that lavender is as profitable to it as oats, or that it helps poor people to live, any more than the schoolboy's kite provides him his dinner. Luxuries, whether national or personal, must be paid for by labour withdrawn from useful things; and no nation has a right to indulge in them until all its poor are comfortably housed and fed.

It would have been impossible for political economists to tolerate the mistake mentioned in the text,[21] if they hadn't been misled by a partly valid idea that the energy and sophistication, as well as the wealth of civilized life, come from imaginary needs. It's true that the person who only cares about food, shelter, and sleep—who, after catching his deer and fixing his hut, spends the rest of his time in idleness—is in a worse position than the person who works hard to enjoy the luxuries of civilization. It's also true that the difference in a nation’s progress depends largely on superficial desires; however, these trivial motivations should only be seen as exercises for the nation's body and mind and are not actual sources of wealth, except in the way they foster habits of hard work and a desire to acquire. If a boy is clumsy and lazy, it would be beneficial to get him to carve cherry stones and fly kites; this might eventually lead to him becoming a wealthy and happy man, but we shouldn't conclude that cherry stones have real value or that kite-flying is a worthwhile way to spend time. Similarly, a nation directly wastes its time and resources when it creates a new, frivolous desire, yet the creation of such a desire might indicate healthy activity. The effort put into fulfilling this new desire could indirectly lead to useful innovations or great arts; thus, a nation shouldn't be discouraged by its whims when it is too weak or foolish to be motivated by anything other than whims or has already taken care of its more serious matters. If a nation prefers distilling lavender over forging iron, then it should absolutely distill lavender; just don't let its economists think that lavender is as valuable as oats, or that it helps poor people survive any more than a schoolboy’s kite provides him with food. Luxuries, whether for a nation or an individual, must be earned by diverting labor from more useful activities; and no nation has the right to indulge in them until all its poor are adequately housed and fed.

The enervating influence of luxury, and its tendencies to increase vice, are points which I keep entirely out of consideration in the present essay; but, so far as they bear on any question discussed, they merely furnish additional evidence on the side which I have taken. Thus, in the present case, I assume that the luxuries of civilized life are in possession harmless, and in acquirement, serviceable as a motive for exertion; and even on these favourable terms, we arrive at the conclusion that the nation ought not to indulge in them except under severe limitations. Much less ought it to indulge in them if the temptation consequent on their possession, or fatality incident to their manufacture, more than counterbalances the good done by the effort to obtain them.

The draining effect of luxury and how it can lead to more vice are topics I’m not focusing on in this essay; however, when relevant, they just provide extra support for my argument. In this case, I assume that the luxuries of modern life are harmless once in possession and can serve as motivation for hard work when trying to acquire them. Even under these positive assumptions, we conclude that the nation shouldn't indulge in luxuries without strict limits. It should definitely avoid indulging in them if the temptation that comes with owning them or the dangers connected to their production outweigh the benefits gained from striving to obtain them.

Note 6th, p. 48.—"Economy of Literature."

I have been much impressed lately by one of the results of the quantity of our books; namely, the stern impossibility of getting anything understood, that required patience to understand. I observe always, in the case of my own writings, that if ever I state anything which has cost me any trouble to ascertain, and which, therefore, will probably require a minute or two of reflection from the reader before it can be accepted,—that statement will not only be misunderstood, but in all probability taken to mean something very nearly the reverse of what it does mean. Now, whatever faults there may be in my modes of expression, I know that the words I use will always be found, by Johnson's dictionary, to bear, first of all, the[Pg 105] sense I use them in; and that the sentences, whether awkwardly turned or not, will, by the ordinary rules of grammar, bear no other interpretation than that I mean them to bear; so that the misunderstanding of them must result, ultimately, from the mere fact that their matter sometimes requires a little patience. And I see the same kind of misinterpretation put on the words of other writers, whenever they require the same kind of thought.

I’ve been really struck lately by one of the outcomes of the large number of our books: the harsh reality that it’s nearly impossible to get anything properly understood that needs patience to comprehend. I always notice that when I write something that took me a while to figure out and will likely need a minute or two of thought from the reader before it can be accepted, that statement will not only be misunderstood but probably twisted to mean something almost the opposite of what I actually intended. Now, no matter what flaws there may be in how I express myself, I know that the words I choose will always be found, according to Johnson's dictionary, to have, first and foremost, the[Pg 105] meaning I intend; and that the sentences, whether they’re awkwardly phrased or not, will, according to standard grammar rules, have no other meaning than what I mean them to have. So, any misunderstanding must ultimately stem from the fact that the content sometimes needs a bit of patience. I see the same kind of misinterpretation happen with other writers’ words whenever they require similar thought.

I was at first a little despondent about this; but, on the whole, I believe it will have a good effect upon our literature for some time to come; and then, perhaps, the public may recover its patience again. For certainly it is excellent discipline for an author to feel that he must say all he has to say in the fewest possible words, or his reader is sure to skip them; and in the plainest possible words, or his reader will certainly misunderstand them. Generally, also, a downright fact may be told in a plain way; and we want downright facts at present more than any thing else. And though I often hear moral people complaining of the bad effects of want of thought, for my part, it seems to me that one of the worst diseases to which the human creature is liable is its disease of thinking. If it would only just look[22] at a thing instead of thinking what it must be like, or do a thing, instead of thinking it cannot be done, we should all get on far better.

I was initially a bit down about this; however, overall, I believe it will positively impact our literature for some time to come; and then, maybe, the public will regain its patience. For sure, it's great training for an author to know they must express everything they want to say in the fewest words possible, or their reader will likely skip over them; and in the simplest words possible, or their reader will definitely misunderstand them. Usually, a straightforward fact can be communicated plainly; and right now, we need straightforward facts more than anything else. Although I often hear morally-minded people complaining about the negative effects of a lack of thought, it seems to me that one of the worst issues people face is overthinking. If only we would just look[22] at something instead of assuming what it must be like, or do something instead of thinking it can't be done, we would all do much better.

Note 7th, p. 84.—"Pilots of the State."

While, however, undoubtedly, these responsibilities attach to every person possessed of wealth, it is necessary both to avoid any stringency of statement respecting the benevolent modes of spending money, and to admit and approve so much liberty of spending it for selfish pleasures as may distinctly make wealth a personal reward for toil, and secure in the minds of all men the right of property. For although, without doubt, the purest pleasures it can procure are not selfish, it is only as a means of personal gratification that it will be desired by a large majority of workers; and it would be no less false ethics than false policy to check their energy by any forms of public opinion which bore hardly against the wanton expenditure of honestly got wealth. It would be hard if a man who had passed the greater part of his life at the desk or counter could not at last innocently gratify a caprice; and all the best and most sacred ends of almsgiving would be at once disappointed, if the idea of a moral claim took the place of affectionate gratitude in the mind of the receiver.

While it's true that everyone with wealth has responsibilities, we should avoid being too strict about how people choose to spend their money and recognize that it's okay to spend some of it on personal enjoyment. This can make wealth a personal reward for hard work and reinforce everyone's right to own property. Although the most meaningful pleasures that money can buy are often selfless, most workers will primarily want wealth for their personal satisfaction. It would be both unethical and bad policy to discourage their drive by fostering public opinion that harshly judges the extravagant spending of honestly earned money. It would be unfair if a person who has spent most of their life working couldn’t treat themselves to a little indulgence. Moreover, all the good intentions behind charitable giving would be undermined if the recipient felt a sense of moral obligation instead of genuine gratitude.

Some distinction is made by us naturally in this respect between earned and inherited wealth; that which is inherited appearing to involve the most definite responsibilities, especially when consisting in revenues derived from the soil. The form of taxation which constitutes rental of lands places annually a certain portion of the national wealth in the hands of the nobles, or other proprietors of the soil, under conditions peculiarly calculated to induce them to give their best care to its efficient administration. The want of instruction in even the simplest principles of commerce and economy, which hitherto has disgraced our schools and universities, has indeed been the cause of ruin or total inutility of life to multitudes of our men of estate; but this deficiency in our public education cannot exist much longer, and it appears to be highly advantageous for the State that a certain number of persons distinguished by race should be permitted to set examples of wise expenditure, whether in the advancement of science, or in patronage of art and literature; only they must see to it that they take their right standing more firmly than they have done[Pg 107] hitherto, for the position of a rich man in relation to those around him is, in our present real life, and is also contemplated generally by political economists as being, precisely the reverse of what it ought to be. A rich man ought to be continually examining how he may spend his money for the advantage of others: at present, others are continually plotting how they may beguile him into spending it apparently for his own. The aspect which he presents to the eyes of the world is generally that of a person holding a bag of money with a staunch grasp, and resolved to part with none of it unless he is forced, and all the people about him are plotting how they may force him; that is to say, how they may persuade him that he wants this thing or that; or how they may produce things that he will covet and buy. One man tries to persuade him that he wants perfumes; another that he wants jewellery; another that he wants sugarplums; another that he wants roses at Christmas. Anybody who can invent a new want for him is supposed to be a benefactor to society: and thus the energies of the poorer people about him are continually directed to the production of covetable, instead of serviceable things; and the rich man has the general aspect of a fool, plotted against by all the world. Whereas the real aspect which he ought to have is that of a person wiser than others, entrusted with the management of a larger quantity of capital, which he administers for the profit of all, directing each man to the labour which is most healthy for him, and most serviceable for the community.

We naturally make a distinction between earned and inherited wealth; inherited wealth seems to carry more clear responsibilities, especially when it's derived from land. The taxation system that acts as rental for lands transfers a portion of national wealth each year into the hands of nobles or other landowners, in a way that encourages them to manage it effectively. The lack of education in even basic concepts of commerce and economics, which has been a shame in our schools and universities, has led to the ruin or complete uselessness of many wealthy individuals’ lives. However, this gap in our public education can’t last much longer, and it seems beneficial for the state to allow some individuals distinguished by their lineage to set examples of wise spending, whether in advancing science or supporting art and literature; they just need to ensure they take their rightful place more firmly than they have until now[Pg 107]. The role of a rich person in relation to others is, in our current reality, seen by political economists as the opposite of what it should be. A wealthy person should constantly think about how to spend their money for the benefit of others; instead, others are always scheming to trick them into spending it as if it were for their own benefit. The image they present to the world is usually that of someone clutching a bag of money tightly, unwilling to part with any without being forced, while everyone around them is trying to figure out how to influence them; that is, how to make them feel like they need this or that, or how to create things they’ll desire and buy. One person tries to convince them they need perfumes; another says they need jewelry; another suggests they want sweets; yet another promotes roses at Christmas. Anyone who can create a new desire for them is seen as a benefactor to society. Consequently, the efforts of the poorer individuals around them are constantly directed toward creating desirable things rather than useful ones, and the rich person tends to seem like a fool, surrounded by schemers. In reality, they should give off the impression of someone wiser, entrusted with managing a larger amount of capital for the benefit of everyone, guiding each person toward the most fulfilling work for themselves and the community.

Note 8th, p. 84.—"Silk and Purple."

In various places throughout these lectures I have had to allude to the distinction between productive and unproductive labour, and between true and false wealth. I shall here endeavour, as clearly as I can, to explain the distinction I mean.

In different parts of these lectures, I have had to mention the difference between productive and unproductive labor, as well as between real and fake wealth. Here, I will try my best to explain the distinction I mean clearly.

Property may be divided generally into two kinds; that which produces life, and that which produces the objects of life. That which produces or maintains life consists of food, in so far as it is nourishing; of furniture and clothing, in so far as they are protective or cherishing; of fuel; and of all land, instruments, or materials, necessary to produce food,[Pg 108] houses, clothes and fuel. It is specially and rightly called useful property.

Property can generally be divided into two types: things that support life and things that provide for life's needs. Those that support life include nourishing food; furniture and clothing that protect or provide comfort; fuel; and all land, tools, or materials needed to produce food, houses, clothing, and fuel. This type is specifically and accurately referred to as useful property.[Pg 108]

The property which produces the objects of life consists of all that gives pleasure or suggests and preserves thought: of food, furniture, and land, in so far as they are pleasing to the appetite or the eye, of luxurious dress; and all other kinds of luxuries; of books, pictures, and architecture. But the modes of connection of certain minor forms of property with human labour render it desirable to arrange them under more than these two heads. Property may therefore be conveniently considered as of five kinds.

The property that creates the essentials of life includes everything that brings joy or inspires and maintains thought: food, furniture, and land, as long as they appeal to our taste or aesthetics, luxurious clothing, and all other types of luxuries, as well as books, art, and architecture. However, the ways in which certain lesser forms of property relate to human labor make it useful to categorize them in more than just these two groups. Therefore, property can be effectively classified into five types.

1st. Property necessary to life, but not producible by labour, and therefore belonging of right, in a due measure, to every human being as soon as he is born, and morally unalienable. As, for instance, his proper share of the atmosphere, without which he cannot breathe, and of water, which he needs to quench his thirst. As much land as he needs to feed from is also inalienable; but in well regulated communities this quantity of land may often be represented by other possessions, or its need supplied by wages and privileges.

1st. Resources essential for life, which cannot be produced by labor, rightfully belong to everyone in a fair amount as soon as they are born, and cannot be morally taken away. For example, everyone has a rightful share of the air, without which they can't breathe, and of water, which they need to satisfy their thirst. The amount of land needed for sustenance is also irreplaceable; however, in well-organized societies, this portion of land can often be substituted with other assets, or its necessity can be met through wages and privileges.

2. Property necessary to life, but only producible by labour, and of which the possession is morally connected with labour, so that no person capable of doing the work necessary for its production has a right to it until he has done that work:—"he that will not work, neither should he eat." It consists of simple food, clothing, and habitation, with their seeds and materials, or instruments and machinery, and animals used for necessary draught or locomotion, etc. It is to be observed of this kind of property, that its increase cannot usually be carried beyond a certain point, because it depends not on labour only, but on things of which the supply is limited by nature. The possible accumulation of corn depends on the quantity of corn-growing land possessed or commercially accessible; and that of steel, similarly, on the accessible quantity of coal and ironstone. It follows from this natural limitation of supply that the accumulation of property of this kind in large masses at one point, or in one person's hands, commonly involves, more or less, the scarcity of it at another point and in other persons' hands; so that[Pg 109] the accidents or energies which may enable one man to procure a great deal of it, may, and in all likelihood will partially prevent other men procuring a sufficiency of it, however willing they may be to work for it; therefore, the modes of its accumulation and distribution need to be in some degree regulated by law and by national treaties, in order to secure justice to all men.

2. Property that is essential for life, but can only be produced through labor, and whose ownership is morally tied to that labor, means that no one who is able to do the work necessary to produce it has the right to it until they have done that work:—“He who doesn’t work, shouldn't eat.” This includes basic food, clothing, and shelter, along with their seeds and materials, tools and machinery, and animals used for essential work or transportation, etc. It’s important to note that this type of property cannot usually be increased beyond a certain limit because it not only depends on labor but also on resources that are naturally limited. The potential accumulation of grain is dependent on the amount of land available for growing grain or commercially accessible; similarly, the accumulation of steel depends on the available supply of coal and iron ore. This natural limitation of supply means that having a large amount of this type of property gathered in one place or in one person's control often leads to it being scarce in other places and for other people; thus, the factors or resources that allow one individual to acquire a lot of it are likely to hinder others from obtaining enough, even if they are willing to work for it. Therefore, the ways in which this property is accumulated and distributed need to be somewhat regulated by law and national agreements to ensure justice for everyone.

Another point requiring notice respecting this sort of property is, that no work can be wasted in producing it, provided only the kind of it produced be preservable and distributable, since for every grain of such commodities we produce we are rendering so much more life possible on earth.[23] But though we are sure, thus, that we are employing people well, we cannot be sure we might not have employed them better; for it is possible to direct labour to the production of life, until little or none is left for that of the objects of life, and thus to increase population at the expense of civilization, learning, and morality: on the other hand, it is just as possible—and the error is one to which the world is, on the whole, more liable—to direct labour to the objects of life till too little is left for life, and thus to increase luxury or learning at the expense of population. Right political economy holds its aim poised justly between the two extremes, desiring neither to crowd its dominions with a race of savages, nor to found courts and colleges in the midst of a desert.

Another point worth noting about this type of property is that no effort is wasted in producing it, as long as what is produced can be preserved and distributed. For every grain of these commodities we create, we are making more life possible on earth.[23] However, while we can be certain that we are employing people effectively, we can't guarantee that we couldn't have employed them better; it's possible to focus labor on producing life to the extent that there's hardly any left for creating the necessities of life, which can lead to a population increase at the cost of civilization, education, and ethics. On the flip side, it's also very possible—and in fact, the world tends to fall into this error more often—to direct labor towards the necessities of life until there's too little left for sustaining life itself, resulting in an increase in luxury or education at the cost of population. Proper political economy aims to find a balance between these two extremes, avoiding the creation of a society of savages or establishing courts and universities in a barren wasteland.

3.[Pg 110] The third kind of property is that which conduces to bodily pleasures and conveniences, without directly tending to sustain life; perhaps sometimes indirectly tending to destroy it. All dainty (as distinguished from nourishing) food, and means of producing it; all scents not needed for health; substances valued only for their appearance and rarity (as gold and jewels); flowers of difficult culture; animals used for delight (as horses for racing), and such like, form property of this class; to which the term "luxury, or luxuries," ought exclusively to belong.

3.[Pg 110] The third type of property is that which contributes to physical pleasures and comforts, without necessarily keeping us alive; it might sometimes even lead to harm. This includes all fancy (as opposed to nutritious) food and the means to produce it; all fragrances that aren’t essential for health; items prized only for their beauty and rarity (like gold and jewels); flowers that are hard to grow; animals kept for enjoyment (like racehorses), and similar things, which should be exclusively referred to as "luxury" or "luxuries."

Respecting which we have to note first, that all such property is of doubtful advantage even to its possessor. Furniture tempting to indolence, sweet odours, and luscious food, are more or less injurious to health: while jewels, liveries, and other such common belongings of wealthy people, certainly convey no pleasure to their owners proportionate to their cost.

It's important to acknowledge that such possessions are often more trouble than they're worth, even for those who own them. Comfortable furniture, enticing scents, and rich food can be harmful to your health. Meanwhile, jewels, fancy clothes, and other typical symbols of wealth don't bring their owners joy that matches their expense.

Farther, such property, for the most part, perishes in the using. Jewels form a great exception—but rich food, fine dresses, horses and carriages, are consumed by the owner's use. It ought much oftener to be brought to the notice of rich men what sums of interest of money they are paying towards the close of their lives, for luxuries consumed in the middle of them. It would be very interesting, for instance, to know the exact sum which the money spent in London for ices, at its desserts and balls, during the last twenty years, had it been saved and put out at compound interest, would at this moment have furnished for useful purposes.

Moreover, most of that wealth tends to diminish with use. Jewelry is a major exception—but rich food, fancy clothes, horses, and carriages are all consumed by their owners. Wealthy individuals should be reminded more often of how much interest they’re essentially paying at the end of their lives for luxuries indulged in earlier. It would be fascinating, for example, to know the total amount that money spent in London on ice cream at its parties and balls over the last twenty years would have yielded if it had been saved and invested at compound interest for useful purposes today.

Also, in most cases, the enjoyment of such property is wholly selfish, and limited to its possessor. Splendid dress and equipage, however, when so arranged as to produce real beauty of effect, may often be rather a generous than a selfish channel of expenditure. They will, however, necessarily in such case involve some of the arts of design; and therefore take their place in a higher category than that of luxuries merely.[Pg 111]

Also, in most cases, the enjoyment of such property is completely selfish and limited to the owner. However, when fancy clothes and accessories are styled to create true beauty, they can often be a more generous way to spend money than a selfish one. In such cases, they will naturally involve some aspects of design; thus, they belong in a higher category than just luxuries.[Pg 111]

4. The fourth kind of property is that which bestows intellectual or emotional pleasure, consisting of land set apart for purposes of delight more than for agriculture, of books, works of art, and objects of natural history.

4. The fourth type of property is one that provides intellectual or emotional enjoyment, including land dedicated more for pleasure than for farming, along with books, artworks, and natural history items.

It is, of course, impossible to fix an accurate limit between property of the last class and of this class, since things which are a mere luxury to one person are a means of intellectual occupation to another. Flowers in a London ball-room are a luxury; in a botanical garden, a delight of the intellect; and in their native fields, both; while the most noble works of art are continually made material of vulgar luxury or of criminal pride; but, when rightly used, property of this fourth class is the only kind which deserves the name of real property; it is the only kind which a man can truly be said to "possess." What a man eats, or drinks, or wears, so long as it is only what is needful for life, can no more be thought of as his possession than the air he breathes. The air is as needful to him as the food; but we do not talk of a man's wealth of air; and what food or clothing a man possesses more than he himself requires, must be for others to use (and, to him, therefore, not a real property in itself, but only a means of obtaining some real property in exchange for it). Whereas the things that give intellectual or emotional enjoyment may be accumulated and do not perish in using; but continually supply new pleasures and new powers of giving pleasures to others. And these, therefore, are the only things which can rightly be thought of as giving "wealth" or "well being." Food conduces only to "being," but these to "well being." And there is not any broader general distinction between lower and higher orders of men than rests on their possession of this real property. The human race may be properly divided by zoologists into "men who have gardens, libraries, or works of art; and who have none;" and the former class will include all noble persons, except only a few who make the world their garden or museum; while the people who have not, or, which is the same thing, do not care for gardens or libraries, but care for nothing but money or luxuries, will include none but ignoble persons: only it is necessary to understand that I mean by the term "garden"[Pg 112] as much the Carthusian's plot of ground fifteen feet square between his monastery buttresses, as I do the grounds of Chatsworth or Kew; and I mean by the term "art" as much the old sailor's print of the Arethusa bearing up to engage the Belle Poule, as I do Raphael's "Disputa," and even rather more; for when abundant, beautiful possessions of this kind are almost always associated with vulgar luxury, and become then anything but indicative of noble character in their possessors. The ideal of human life is a union of Spartan simplicity of manners with Athenian sensibility and imagination, but in actual results, we are continually mistaking ignorance for simplicity, and sensuality for refinement.

It’s impossible to set a clear boundary between the last class of property and this one, since what is just a luxury for one person can be a source of intellectual engagement for another. Flowers at a London ballroom are a luxury; in a botanical garden, they offer intellectual delight; and in their natural fields, they serve both purposes. Meanwhile, the most revered works of art can often become mere symbols of vulgar luxury or pride, but when used correctly, property in this fourth class is the only type that genuinely deserves the title of real property; it's the only kind a person can be said to truly "own." What someone eats, drinks, or wears, as long as it’s just what’s necessary for life, shouldn't be considered their possession any more than the air they breathe. The air is just as essential as food; however, we don’t refer to a person's wealth of air. Any food or clothing someone has beyond their needs must be used by others (and for them, therefore, it's not real property in itself, but merely a means to acquire some real property in trade). In contrast, things that provide intellectual or emotional enjoyment can be accumulated and don’t diminish with use; they continually offer new pleasures and enhance the ability to delight others. Thus, these are the only things that can accurately be considered as contributing to "wealth" or "well-being." Food only contributes to "being," while these contribute to "well being." There’s no broader general distinction between lower and higher classes of people than based on their possession of this real property. Zoologists might categorize humanity as "people who have gardens, libraries, or art; and those who don’t;" and the first group encompasses all noble individuals, except for a few who treat the world as their garden or museum. Those who lack interest in gardens or libraries and only focus on money or luxuries will consist solely of ignoble individuals. It’s important to note that by "garden" [Pg 112] I refer to anything from a Carthusian monk’s small plot of land between monastery walls to the grounds of Chatsworth or Kew; and by "art," I mean everything from the old sailor’s print of the Arethusa preparing to engage with the Belle Poule to Raphael’s "Disputa," and perhaps even more so; because when they are plentiful and beautiful, such possessions are often linked with vulgar luxury and fail to signify noble character in their owners. The ideal of human life blends Spartan simplicity with Athenian sensitivity and imagination, but in reality, we often confuse ignorance with simplicity and sensuality with refinement.

5. The fifth kind of property is representative property, consisting of documents or money, or rather documents only, for money itself is only a transferable document, current among societies of men, giving claim, at sight, to some definite benefit or advantage, most commonly to a certain share of real property existing in those societies. The money is only genuine when the property it gives claim to is real, or the advantages it gives claim to certain; otherwise, it is false money, and may be considered as much "forged" when issued by a government, or a bank, as when by an individual. Thus, if a dozen of men, cast ashore on a desert island, pick up a number of stones, put a red spot on each stone, and pass a law that every stone marked with a red spot shall give claim to a peck of wheat;—so long as no wheat exists, or can exist, on the island, the stones are not money. But the moment as much wheat exists as shall render it possible for the society always to give a peck for every spotted stone, the spotted stones would become money, and might be exchanged by their possessors for whatever other commodities they chose, to the value of the peck of wheat which the stones represented. If more stones were issued than the quantity of wheat could answer the demand of, the value of the stone coinage would be depreciated, in proportion to its increase above the quantity needed to answer it.

5. The fifth type of property is representative property, which includes documents or money, or rather just documents, because money itself is just a transferable document that's accepted by societies, giving a claim at first glance to some specific benefit or advantage, most often a certain share of real property in those societies. Money is considered genuine only when the property it claims is real, or the benefits it represents are certain; otherwise, it’s fake money and can be regarded as “forged” whether it’s issued by a government, a bank, or an individual. So, if a dozen people wash up on a deserted island, find some stones, mark each one with a red spot, and establish a law that every stone marked with a red spot represents a claim to a peck of wheat—then as long as there’s no wheat on the island or it can't be produced there, those stones aren't money. But the moment there’s enough wheat to ensure that the society can always provide a peck for every spotted stone, the marked stones would become money, and their owners could trade them for any other goods they liked, up to the value of the peck of wheat that the stones represented. If more stones are created than the available wheat can support, the value of the stone currency would decrease in line with the surplus above the necessary amount.

Again, supposing a certain number of the men so cast ashore were set aside by lot, or any other convention, to do the rougher labour necessary for the whole society, they themselves being[Pg 113] maintained by the daily allotment of a certain quantity of food, clothing, etc. Then, if it were agreed that the stones spotted with red should be signs of a Government order for the labour of these men; and that any person presenting a spotted stone at the office of the labourers, should be entitled to a man's work for a week or a day, the red stones would be money; and might—probably would—immediately pass current in the island for as much food, or clothing, or iron, or any other article as a man's work for the period secured by the stone was worth. But if the Government issued so many spotted stones that it was impossible for the body of men they employed to comply with the orders; as, suppose, if they only employed twelve men, and issued eighteen spotted stones daily, ordering a day's work each, then the six extra stones would be forged or false money; and the effect of this forgery would be the depreciation of the value of the whole coinage by one-third, that being the period of shortcoming which would, on the average, necessarily ensue in the execution of each order. Much occasional work may be done in a state or society, by help of an issue of false money (or false promises) by way of stimulants; and the fruit of this work, if it comes into the promiser's hands, may sometimes enable the false promises at last to be fulfilled: hence the frequent issue of false money by governments and banks, and the not unfrequent escapes from the natural and proper consequences of such false issues, so as to cause a confused conception in most people's minds of what money really is. I am not sure whether some quantity of such false issue may not really be permissible in a nation, accurately proportioned to the minimum average produce of the labour it excites; but all such procedures are more or less unsound; and the notion of unlimited issue of currency is simply one of the absurdest and most monstrous that ever came into disjointed human wits.

Again, let's say a certain number of the men cast ashore were chosen by random chance, or some other agreement, to do the harder work needed for the whole community, with their needs being[Pg 113] met by a daily supply of food, clothing, etc. Then, if it was agreed that stones marked with red would signify a government order for the labor of these men; and that anyone presenting a marked stone at the laborers' office would be entitled to a man's work for a week or a day, the red stones would function as money; and likely—would—immediately be exchanged on the island for as much food, clothing, iron, or any other item as a man's labor for the time specified by the stone was worth. But if the government issued so many marked stones that it was impossible for the group of men they employed to meet the demands; for instance, if they only employed twelve men but issued eighteen marked stones daily, ordering a day's work for each, then the six extra stones would be considered counterfeit or fake money; and the result of this counterfeiting would be a drop in the value of the whole currency by one-third, since that would be the expected shortfall in fulfilling each order. A significant amount of occasional work can be done in a state or society through the issuance of counterfeit money (or false promises) as a way to motivate; and if the results of this work end up in the hands of the one who made the promises, it may sometimes allow those false promises to finally be kept: hence the frequent issuance of counterfeit money by governments and banks, and the not uncommon avoidance of the natural and proper consequences of such counterfeits, leading to a muddled understanding in most people's minds about what money really is. I'm not sure whether issuing some amount of such counterfeit money could be acceptable in a nation, as long as it is accurately matched to the minimum average output of the labor it stimulates; but all such actions are somewhat unstable; and the idea of unlimited currency issuance is simply one of the most ridiculous and outrageous concepts that ever entered disjointed human thinking.

The use of objects of real or supposed value for currency, as gold, jewellery, etc., is barbarous; and it always expresses either the measure of the distrust in the society of its own government, or the proportion of distrustful or barbarous nations with whom it has to deal. A metal not easily corroded or imitated, is a desirable medium of currency for the sake of[Pg 114] cleanliness and convenience, but were it possible to prevent forgery, the more worthless the metal itself, the better. The use of worthless media, unrestrained by the use of valuable media, has always hitherto involved, and is therefore supposed to involve necessarily, unlimited, or at least improperly extended, issue; but we might as well suppose that a man must necessarily issue unlimited promises because his words cost nothing. Intercourse with foreign nations must, indeed, for ages yet to come, at the world's present rate of progress, be carried on by valuable currencies; but such transactions are nothing more than forms of barter. The gold used at present as a currency is not, in point of fact, currency at all, but the real property[24] which the currency gives claim to, stamped to measure its quantity, and mingling with the real currency occasionally by barter.

The use of valuable or supposedly valuable items as currency, like gold or jewelry, is primitive. It reflects either the level of distrust people have in their own government or the amount of distrustful or uncivilized nations they interact with. A metal that doesn't easily corrode or can be easily forged is a practical choice for currency because of its cleanliness and convenience, but if forgery could be completely prevented, the less valuable the metal, the better. Using worthless forms of money without the balance of valuable forms has always led to, and is believed to lead to, excessive or improperly managed issuance. It's as illogical as saying that a person must issue endless promises just because their words cost nothing. Trade with other countries will indeed have to rely on valuable currencies for a long time, given the world’s current pace of development, but these transactions are just different forms of bartering. The gold that we currently use as currency isn’t actually currency at all; it's just real property that the currency gives a claim to, marked to measure how much there is, and sometimes exchanged with real currency through bartering.

[Pg 115]The evils necessarily resulting from the use of baseless currencies have been terribly illustrated while these sheets have been passing through the press; I have not had time to examine the various conditions of dishonest or absurd trading which have led to the late "panic" in America and England; this only I know, that no merchant deserving the name ought to be more liable to "panic" than a soldier should; for his name should never be on more paper than he can at any instant meet the call of, happen what will. I do not say this without feeling at the same time how difficult it is to mark, in existing commerce, the just limits between the spirit of enterprise and of speculation. Something of the same temper which makes the English soldier do always all that is possible, and attempt more than is possible, joins its influence with that of mere avarice in tempting the English merchant into risks which he cannot justify, and efforts which he cannot sustain; and the same passion for adventure which our travellers gratify every summer on perilous snow wreaths, and cloud-encompassed precipices, surrounds with a romantic fascination the glittering of a hollow investment, and gilds the clouds that curl round gulfs of ruin. Nay, a higher and a more serious feeling frequently mingles in the motley temptation; and men apply themselves to the task of growing rich, as to a labour of providential appointment, from which they cannot pause without culpability, nor retire without dishonour. Our large trading cities bear to me very nearly the aspect of monastic establishments in which the roar of the mill-wheel and the crane takes the place of other devotional music; and in which the worship of Mammon or Moloch is conducted with a tender reverence and an exact propriety; the merchant rising to his Mammon matins with the self-denial of an anchorite, and expiating the frivolities into which he may be beguiled, in the course of the day by late attendance at Mammon vespers. But, with every allowance that can be made for these conscientious and romantic persons, the fact remains the same, that by far the greater number of the transactions which lead to these times of commercial embarrassment may be ranged simply under two great heads,—gambling and stealing; and both of these in their most culpable form, namely, gambling with money which is not ours, and stealing from those who trust us. I have sometimes thought a day might come, when the nation would perceive that a well-educated man who steals a hundred thousand pounds, involving the entire means of subsistence of a hundred families, deserves, on the whole, as severe a punishment as an ill-educated man who steals a purse from a pocket, or a mug from a pantry. But without hoping for this excess of clearsightedness, we may at least labour for a system of greater honesty and kindness in the minor commerce of our daily life; since the great dishonesty of the great buyers and sellers is nothing more than the natural growth and outcome from the little dishonesty of the little buyers and sellers. Every person who tries to buy an article for less than its proper value, or who[Pg 116] tries to sell it at more than its proper value—every consumer who keeps a tradesman waiting for his money, and every tradesman who bribes a consumer to extravagance by credit, is helping forward, according to his own measure of power, a system of baseless and dishonourable commerce, and forcing his country down into poverty and shame. And people of moderate means and average powers of mind would do far more real good by merely carrying out stern principles of justice and honesty in common matters of trade, than by the most ingenious schemes of extended philanthropy, or vociferous declarations of theological doctrine. There are three weighty matters of the law—justice, mercy, and truth; and of these the Teacher puts truth last, because that cannot be known but by a course of acts of justice and love. But men put, in all their efforts, truth first, because they mean by it their own opinions; and thus, while the world has many people who would suffer martyrdom in the cause of what they call truth, it has few who will suffer even a little inconvenience, in that of justice and mercy.

[Pg 115]The problems that arise from using unreliable currencies have been starkly shown while this writing was being finalized; I haven't had time to look into the various dishonest or ridiculous trading practices that led to the recent "panic" in America and England. What I do know is that no merchant worthy of the title should be more susceptible to "panic" than a soldier should be; because he should never have more on paper than he can afford to settle at any moment, regardless of what happens. I don’t say this without recognizing how difficult it is to define the boundaries between the spirit of enterprise and speculation in today’s commerce. There's something in the English soldier's nature that makes him do everything possible and attempt more than he can manage, which combines with mere greed and lures the English merchant into unjustifiable risks and unsustainable efforts. The same adventurous spirit that our travelers indulge every summer on risky snowy terrains and cloud-covered cliffs also adds a romantic allure to the sparkle of a risky investment, decorating the dangers that lead to financial ruin. Moreover, a deeper, more serious motive often mingles in this tangled temptation; people pursue wealth as if it were a divine duty, feeling they can't pause without guilt or withdraw without disgrace. To me, our major trading cities resemble monastic establishments where the noise of the mill and cranes replaces traditional devotional music; and where the worship of wealth is performed with a certain reverence and precise decorum. The merchant begins his day for Mammon with the self-denial of a monk and atones for the distractions he may fall into during the day by showing up late for Mammon's evening service. However, no matter how sympathetic we might be toward these earnest and romantic individuals, the reality is that most transactions that lead to these economic troubles can simply be categorized into two main types: gambling and stealing; and both of these in their worst forms—gambling with money that isn't ours, and stealing from those who place their trust in us. I've sometimes thought there might come a day when society realizes that a well-educated person who steals a hundred thousand pounds, affecting the livelihoods of a hundred families, deserves, overall, as harsh a punishment as an uneducated person who picks a pocket or takes a dish from a kitchen. But even without hoping for such clarity, we can at least work toward a more honest and kind system in our everyday exchanges; since the significant dishonesty of the large brokers and sellers is just a natural result of the small dishonesty seen among the lesser buyers and sellers. Every individual who attempts to buy something for less than it's worth, or tries to sell it for more than it's worth—every customer who makes a merchant wait for payment, and every merchant who entices a customer to overindulgence through credit, is contributing, according to his own capabilities, to a system of unreliable and disgraceful commerce, dragging his country down into poverty and shame. People of average means and reasonable intellect would do far more genuine good by strictly adhering to principles of justice and honesty in regular trades than by engaging in complex philanthropic schemes or loud declarations of belief. There are three fundamental matters of the law—justice, mercy, and truth; and of these, the Teacher places truth last, because it can only be understood through acts of justice and love. Yet people, in their pursuits, place truth first, as they interpret it to mean their own opinions; and thus, while the world has many who would endure martyrdom for what they call truth, it has few who will even tolerate mild inconvenience for the sake of justice and mercy. [Pg 116]

FOOTNOTES:

[18] If the reader is displeased with me for putting this foolish speech into his mouth, I entreat his pardon; but he may be assured that it is a speech which would be made by many people, and the substance of which would be tacitly felt by many more, at this point of the discussion. I have really tried, up to this point, to make the objector as intelligent a person as it is possible for an author to imagine anybody to be, who differs with him.

[18] If you're upset with me for putting this silly speech in your mouth, I ask for your forgiveness; but you can be sure that it’s a speech many people would say, and the main ideas would be understood by many more at this point in the discussion. I've genuinely tried, up to now, to make the critic as smart as anyone could possibly imagine someone to be who disagrees with him.

[19] It is very curious to watch the efforts of two shopkeepers to ruin each other, neither having the least idea that his ruined neighbour must eventually be supported at his own expense, with an increase of poor rates; and that the contest between them is not in reality which shall get everything for himself, but which shall first take upon himself and his customers the gratuitous maintenance of the other's family.

[19] It's quite interesting to see how two shopkeepers try to sabotage each other, with neither realizing that their destroyed rival will ultimately be a burden on their own shoulders, resulting in higher taxes for the poor. The real competition between them isn't about who can take everything for themselves, but rather who will first end up having to support the other’s family at their own cost.

[20] It will be observed that, in the lecture, it is assumed that works of art are national treasures; and that it is desirable to withdraw all the hands capable of painting or carving from other employments, in order that they may produce this kind of wealth. I do not, in assuming this, mean that works of art add to the monetary resources of a nation, or form part of its wealth, in the vulgar sense. The result of the sale of a picture in the country itself is merely that a certain sum of money is transferred from the hands of B. the purchaser, to those of A. the producer; the sum ultimately to be distributed remaining the same, only A. ultimately spending it instead of B., while the labour of A. has been in the meantime withdrawn from productive channels; he has painted a picture which nobody can live upon, or live in, when he might have grown corn or built houses; when the sale therefore is effected in the country itself, it does not add to, but diminishes, the monetary resources of the country, except only so far as it may appear probable, on other grounds, that A. is likely to spend the sum he receives for his picture more rationally and usefully than B. would have spent it. If, indeed, the picture, or other work of art, be sold in foreign countries, either the money or the useful products of the foreign country being imported in exchange for it, such sale adds to the monetary resources of the selling, and diminishes those of the purchasing nation. But sound political economy, strange as it may at first appear to say so, has nothing whatever to do with separations between national interests. Political economy means the management of the affairs of citizens; and it either regards exclusively the administration of the affairs of one nation, or the administration of the affairs of the world considered as one nation. So when a transaction between individuals which enriches A., impoverishes B. in precisely the same degree, the sound economist considers it an unproductive transaction between the individuals; and if a trade between two nations which enriches one, impoverishes the other in the same degree, the sound eoonomist considers it an unproductive trade between the nations. It is not a general question of political economy, but only a particular question of local expediency, whether an article in itself valueless, may bear a value of exchange in transactions with some other nation. The economist considers only the actual value of the thing done or produced; and if he sees a quantity of labour spent, for instance, by the Swiss, in producing woodwork for sale to the English, he at once sets the commercial impoverishment of the English purchaser against the commercial enrichment of the Swiss seller; and considers the whole transaction productive only so far as the woodwork itself is a real addition to the wealth of the world. For the arrangement of the laws of a nation so as to procure the greatest advantages to itself, and leave the smallest advantages to other nations, is not a part of the science of political economy, but merely a broad application of the science of fraud. Considered thus in the abstract, pictures are not an addition to the monetary wealth of the world, except in the amount of pleasure or instruction to be got out of them day by day: but there is a certain protective effect on wealth exercised by works of high art which must always be included in the estimate of their value. Generally speaking, persons who decorate their houses with pictures, will not spend so much money in papers, carpets, curtains, or other expensive and perishable luxuries as they would otherwise. Works of good art, like books, exercise a conservative effect on the rooms they are kept in; and the wall of the library or picture gallery remains undisturbed, when those of other rooms are re-papered or re-panelled. Of course, this effect is still more definite when the picture is on the walls themselves, either on canvass stretched into fixed shapes on their panels, or in fresco; involving, of course, the preservation of the building from all unnecessary and capricious alteration. And generally speaking, the occupation of a large number of hands in painting or sculpture in any nation may be considered as tending to check the disposition to indulge in perishable luxury. I do not, however, in my assumption that works of art are treasures, take much into consideration this collateral monetary result. I consider them treasures, merely as permanent means of pleasure and instruction; and having at other times tried to show the several ways in which they can please and teach, assume here that they are thus useful; and that it is desirable to make as many painters as we can.

[20] In the lecture, it's taken for granted that works of art are national treasures and that it's important to shift all artists away from other jobs so they can create this kind of wealth. I don't mean to imply that works of art contribute to a country's financial resources or are part of its wealth in the usual sense. When a painting is sold in the same country, it simply transfers a specific amount of money from B, the buyer, to A, the artist; the total amount available stays the same, with A spending it instead of B. Meanwhile, A's work has been taken away from productive activities; they've created something that can't provide for basic needs when they could have been farming or building houses. So, a sale made within the country doesn't increase, but rather decreases, the nation's monetary resources, unless we believe that A will spend that money more wisely and effectively than B would have. If the artwork is sold to foreign countries, then either money or useful goods from that country is brought back in exchange, which does add to the selling country's financial resources and reduces those of the purchasing nation. However, sound economic principles, surprisingly as it might seem, are not concerned with dividing national interests. Political economy focuses on managing the affairs of **citizens**; it either looks at the administration of one nation alone or considers the whole world as one nation. So, when a transaction makes A richer and B poorer by the same amount, a true economist sees it as an unproductive deal between those individuals; similarly, if trade between two nations enriches one while impoverishing the other equally, it’s regarded as unproductive trade between those nations. The economic question isn't about politics in general, but rather a local consideration of usefulness, such as whether something deemed worthless can have exchange value in trade with another nation. Economists look strictly at the actual value of what is done or produced; for example, if Swiss labor is dedicated to creating woodwork for British buyers, they weigh the financial loss for the British against the gain for the Swiss and label the entire exchange productive only if the woodwork genuinely adds value to global wealth. Crafting national laws to maximize its own benefits while minimizing those of other countries isn't part of political economy; it’s more like applying the principles of deceit. Viewed in this light, artworks do not *add* to the world’s monetary wealth, except for the pleasure or knowledge they provide daily. However, significant works of art offer a protective influence on wealth, which is essential to assess their true worth. Generally, people who fill their homes with art spend less on things like decorative papers, carpets, curtains, or other pricey, fleeting luxuries than they would otherwise. Good art, like literature, helps preserve the integrity of the spaces in which it's displayed; the walls of a library or art gallery remain untouched when other rooms are redecorated. This effect is even clearer when the artwork is part of the walls themselves, whether painted directly or in fresco, which helps preserve the building from unnecessary changes. Moreover, having many people engaged in painting or sculpture within any nation can reduce the urge to indulge in temporary luxuries. Still, when I refer to works of art as treasures, I don't weigh this financial factor heavily. I see them as treasures purely for their lasting capacity to provide enjoyment and learning; having previously explored the various ways they can educate and entertain, I assert here that they are indeed useful, and that we should strive to create as many artists as possible.

[21] I have given the political economists too much credit in saying this. Actually, while these sheets are passing through the press, the blunt, broad, unmitigated fallacy is enunciated, formally and precisely, by the Common Councilmen of New York, in their report on the present commercial crisis. Here is their collective opinion, published in the Times of November 23rd, 1857:—"Another erroneous idea is that luxurious living, extravagant dressing, splendid turn-outs and fine houses, are the cause of distress to a nation. No more erroneous impression could exist. Every extravagance that the man of 100,000 or 1,000,000 dollars indulges in adds to the means, the support, the wealth of ten or a hundred who had little or nothing else but their labour, their intellect, or their taste. If a man of 1,000,000 dollars spends principal and interest in ten years, and finds himself beggared at the end of that time, he has actually made a hundred who have catered to his extravagance, employers or employed, so much richer by the division of his wealth. He may be ruined, but the nation is better off and richer, for one hundred minds and hands, with 10,000 dollars apiece, are far more productive than one with the whole."

[21] I have given the political economists too much credit by saying this. In fact, while these sheets are going to press, the blunt, straightforward fallacy is being stated clearly and precisely by the Common Council members of New York in their report on the current economic crisis. Here’s their collective opinion, published in the Times on November 23rd, 1857:—"Another mistaken idea is that luxurious living, extravagant clothing, lavish carriages, and beautiful homes are the cause of a nation’s distress. No misconception could be more wrong. Every extravagance that a person with $100,000 or $1,000,000 indulges in increases the resources, support, and wealth of ten or a hundred people who have little or nothing besides their labor, intellect, or taste. If a person with $1,000,000 spends both principal and interest in ten years, and finds himself broke at the end of that time, he has actually enriched a hundred who catered to his extravagance, whether as employers or employees, by the distribution of his wealth. He may be ruined, but the nation is better off and richer, as one hundred minds and hands with $10,000 each are far more productive than one with it all."

Yes, gentlemen of the Common Council! but what has been doing in the time of the transfer? The spending of the fortune has taken a certain number of years (suppose ten), and during that time 1,000,000 dollars' worth of work has been done by the people, who have been paid that sum for it. Where is the product of that work? By your own statement, wholly consumed; for the man for whom it has been done is now a beggar. You have given, therefore, as a nation, 1,000,000 dollars' worth of work, and ten years of time, and you have produced, as ultimate result, one beggar! Excellent economy, gentlemen! and sure to conduce, in due sequence, to the production of more than one beggar. Perhaps the matter may be made clearer to you, however, by a more familiar instance. If a schoolboy goes out in the morning with five shillings in his pocket, and comes home at night penniless, having spent his all in tarts; principal and interest are gone, and fruiterer and baker are enriched. So far so good. But suppose the schoolboy, instead, has bought a book and a knife; principal and interest are gone, and bookseller and cutler are enriched. But the schoolboy is enriched also, and may help his schoolfellows next day with knife and book, instead of lying in bed and incurring a debt to the doctor.

Yes, gentlemen of the Common Council! But what has happened during the transfer? Spending the fortune has taken several years (let's say ten), and in that time, $1,000,000 worth of work has been done by the people, who have been paid that amount for it. Where is the result of that work? By your own statement, it has been completely consumed; the person for whom it was done is now a beggar. You have, therefore, as a nation, given away $1,000,000 worth of work and ten years of time, resulting in a single beggar! Excellent economy, gentlemen! This is sure to lead, inevitably, to the creation of more than one beggar. However, perhaps the matter will be clearer to you with a more familiar example. If a schoolboy goes out in the morning with five shillings in his pocket and comes home at night without a penny, having spent it all on tarts; both his principal and interest are gone, and the fruit seller and baker profit. So far so good. But if the schoolboy instead buys a book and a knife; both his principal and interest are gone, and the bookseller and cutler benefit. But the schoolboy also benefits, as he can help his classmates the next day with the knife and book instead of staying in bed and running up a bill with the doctor.

[22] There can be no question, however, of the mischievous tendency of the hurry of the present day, in the way people undertake this very looking. I gave three years' close and incessant labour to the examination of the chronology of the architecture of Venice; two long winters being wholly spent in the drawing of details on the spot: and yet I see constantly that architects who pass three or four days in a gondola going up and down the Grand Canal, think that their first impressions are just as likely to be true as my patiently wrought conclusions. Mr. Street, for instance, glances hastily at the façade of the Ducal Palace—so hastily that he does not even see what its pattern is, and misses the alternation of red and black in the centres of its squares—and yet he instantly ventures on an opinion on the chronology of its capitals, which is one of the most complicated and difficult subjects in the whole range of Gothic archæology. It may, nevertheless, be ascertained with very fair probability of correctness by any person who will give a month's hard work to it, but it can be ascertained no otherwise.

[22] There’s no doubt about the problematic speed of today's world, especially in how people approach this very looking. I spent three years working hard and consistently to study the timeline of Venice's architecture, dedicating two long winters just to drawing details on-site. Yet, I constantly see architects who spend only three or four days in a gondola cruising the Grand Canal believe that their initial impressions are just as valid as my carefully developed conclusions. Mr. Street, for example, quickly glances at the façade of the Ducal Palace—so quickly that he doesn’t even notice the pattern and misses the red and black alternation in the center of its squares. Still, he boldly expresses an opinion on the chronology of its capitals, which is one of the most complex and challenging topics in all of Gothic archaeology. While it can be figured out with a fair chance of accuracy by anyone willing to put in a month of hard work, that’s the only way to truly determine it.

[23] This point has sometimes been disputed; for instance, opening Mill's "Political Economy" the other day, I chanced on a passage in which he says that a man who makes a coat, if the person who wears the coat does nothing useful while he wears it, has done no more good to society than the man who has only raised a pineapple. But this is a fallacy induced by endeavour after too much subtlety. None of us have a right to say that the life of a man is of no use to him, though it may be of no use to us; and the man who made the coat, and thereby prolonged another man's life, has done a gracious and useful work, whatever may come of the life so prolonged. We may say to the wearer of the coat, "You who are wearing coats, and doing nothing in them, are at present wasting your own life and other people's;" but we have no right to say that his existence, however wasted, is wasted away. It may be just dragging itself on, in its thin golden line, with nothing dependent upon it, to the point where it is to strengthen into good chain cable, and have thousands of other lives dependent on it. Meantime, the simple fact respecting the coat-maker is, that he has given so much life to the creature, the results of which he cannot calculate; they may be—in all probability will be—infinite results in some way. But the raiser of pines, who has only given a pleasant taste in the mouth to some one, may see with tolerable clearness to the end of the taste in the mouth, and of all conceivable results therefrom.

[23] This point has been debated at times; for example, when I opened Mill's "Political Economy" the other day, I came across a passage where he says that a man who makes a coat has done no more good for society than the man who has just grown a pineapple, if the person wearing the coat isn’t doing anything useful while wearing it. But that's a flawed argument caused by trying to think too deeply. None of us can claim that a man’s life is useless to him, even if it’s useless to us; and the man who made the coat, by helping another man live longer, has accomplished something valuable, regardless of what happens with that extended life. We can tell the person wearing the coat, "You who are wearing coats and not doing anything in them are wasting your life and others’ right now;" but we can't say that his existence, however wasted, is completely wasted away. It might just be continuing on, in its thin golden line, with nothing resting on it, until it becomes strong enough to turn into a good chain, supporting thousands of other lives. In the meantime, the simple truth regarding the coat-maker is that he has contributed life to the individual, the effects of which he cannot measure; they may be—in all likelihood will be—endless effects in some way. But the person who grows pineapples, having only provided someone with a nice taste, can see quite clearly when that taste will end and all the possible consequences of it.

[24] Or rather, equivalent, to such real property, because everybody has been accustomed to look upon it as valuable: and therefore everybody is willing to give labour or goods for it. But real property does ultimately consist only in things that nourish body or mind; gold would be useless to us if we could not get mutton or books for it. Ultimately all commercial mistakes and embarrassments result from people expecting to get goods without working for them, or wasting them after they have got them. A nation which labours, and takes care of the fruits of labour, would be rich and happy; though there were no gold in the universe. A nation which is idle, and wastes the produce of what work it does, would be poor and miserable, though all its mountains were of gold, and had glens filled with diamonds instead of glacier.

[24] Or rather, equivalent to such real property, because everyone tends to see it as valuable: and so everyone is willing to trade labor or goods for it. But real property ultimately consists only of things that nourish the body or mind; gold would be useless to us if we couldn't exchange it for mutton or books. In the end, all commercial mistakes and problems come from people expecting to receive goods without working for them, or from wasting what they do acquire. A nation that works hard and takes care of the fruits of its labor would be rich and happy, even if there were no gold in the universe. A nation that is lazy and squanders the results of its labor would be poor and miserable, even if all its mountains were made of gold and its valleys were filled with diamonds instead of glaciers.

 


UNTO THIS LAST:

Four Essays on the Fundamental Principles of Political Economy.


"FRIEND, I DO THEE NO WRONG. DID'ST NOT THOU AGREE WITH ME FOR A PENNY? TAKE THAT THINE IS, AND GO THY WAY. I WILL GIVE UNTO THIS LAST EVEN AS UNTO THEE."

"Friend, I'm not doing you any wrong. Didn't you agree with me for a penny? Take what’s yours and go your way. I will give to this last just as I gave to you."


"IF YE THINK GOOD, GIVE ME MY PRICE; AND IF NOT, FORBEAR. SO THEY WEIGHED FOR MY PRICE THIRTY PIECES OF SILVER."

"IF YOU THINK IT'S FAIR, GIVE ME MY PRICE; AND IF NOT, BACK OFF. SO THEY WEIGHED OUT THIRTY PIECES OF SILVER FOR MY PRICE."


 

PREFACE.

The four following essays were published eighteen months ago in the Cornhill Magazine, and were reprobated in a violent manner, as far as I could hear, by most of the readers they met with.

The four essays that follow were published eighteen months ago in the Cornhill Magazine and were harshly criticized, as far as I could tell, by most of the readers who encountered them.

Not a whit the less, I believe them to be the best, that is to say, the truest, rightest-worded, and most serviceable things I have ever written; and the last of them, having had especial pains spent on it, is probably the best I shall ever write.

Not at all less, I believe they are the best, meaning the truest, most accurately worded, and most useful things I've ever written; and the last one, having had special care put into it, is probably the best I'll ever write.

"This," the reader may reply, "it might be, yet not therefore well written." Which, in no mock humility, admitting, I yet rest satisfied with the work, though with nothing else that I have done; and purposing shortly to follow out the subjects opened in these papers, as I may find leisure, I wish the introductory statements to be within the reach of any one who may care to refer to them. So I republish the essays as they appeared. One word only is changed, correcting the estimate of a weight; and no word is added.

"This," the reader might respond, "could be true, but that doesn't mean it's well written." While I acknowledge this without any false humility, I am still content with the work, even if I'm not with anything else I've done. I plan to explore the topics introduced in these papers when I have the time, and I want the introductory statements to be accessible to anyone who wants to refer to them. So, I'm reissuing the essays as they originally appeared. The only change I've made is to correct a measurement, and no additional words have been included.

Although, however, I find nothing to modify in these papers, it is a matter of regret to me that the most startling of all the statements in them—that respecting the necessity of the organization of labour, with fixed wages,—should have found its way into the first essay; it being quite one of the least important, though by no means the least certain, of the positions to be defended. The real gist of these papers, their central meaning and aim, is to give, as I believe for the first[Pg 122] time in plain English—it has often been incidentally given in good Greek by Plato and Xenophon, and good Latin by Cicero and Horace,—a logical definition of WEALTH: such definition being absolutely needed for a basis of economical science. The most reputed essay on that subject which has appeared in modern times, after opening with the statement that "writers on political economy profess to teach, or to investigate,[25] the nature of wealth," thus follows up the declaration of its thesis—"Every one has a notion, sufficiently correct for common purposes, of what is meant by wealth." ... "It is no part of the design of this treatise to aim at metaphysical nicety of definition."[26]

Although I don't find anything to change in these papers, I regret that the most shocking statement in them—the one about the need for organizing labor with set wages—ended up in the first essay. It's actually one of the less important points to defend, even if it's definitely certain. The real core of these papers, their main meaning and goal, is to present a logical definition of WEALTH in plain English for what I believe is the first time. This concept has often been indirectly expressed in good Greek by Plato and Xenophon, and in quality Latin by Cicero and Horace. A solid definition is absolutely necessary as a foundation for economic science. The most well-known essay on this topic in recent times starts by stating that "writers on political economy claim to teach, or to investigate,[25] the nature of wealth," and then it continues with the thesis declaration—"Everyone has a notion, sufficiently correct for everyday use, of what is meant by wealth." ... "It's not the aim of this treatise to strive for a precise metaphysical definition."[26]

Metaphysical nicety, we assuredly do not need; but physical nicety, and logical accuracy, with respect to a physical subject, we as assuredly do.

We definitely don't need metaphysical precision; however, we certainly do need physical precision and logical accuracy when it comes to a physical subject.

Suppose the subject of inquiry, instead of being House-law (Oikonomia), had been Star-law (Astronomia), and that, ignoring distinction between stars fixed and wandering, as here between wealth radiant and wealth reflective, the writer had begun thus: "Every one has a notion, sufficiently correct for common purposes, of what is meant by stars. Metaphysical nicety in the definition of a star is not the object of this treatise;"—the essay so opened might yet have been far more true in its final statements, and a thousand-fold more serviceable to the navigator, than any treatise on wealth, which founds its conclusions on the popular conception of wealth, can ever become to the economist.

Suppose the topic of discussion, instead of being House-law (Oikonomia), was Star-law (Astronomia), and that, disregarding the distinction between fixed stars and wandering stars, as we do between radiant wealth and reflective wealth, the writer started with: "Everyone has a general idea, good enough for everyday use, of what a star is. Getting into the precise definition of a star isn't the goal of this essay;"—this introduction might have ultimately been much more accurate in its conclusions and a thousand times more helpful to navigators than any examination of wealth, which bases its findings on the common understanding of wealth, could ever be for economists.


It was, therefore, the first object of these following papers to give an accurate and stable definition of wealth. Their [Pg 123] second object was to show that the acquisition of wealth was finally possible only under certain moral conditions of society, of which quite the first was a belief in the existence and even, for practical purposes, in the attainability of honesty.

It was, therefore, the main goal of the following papers to provide a clear and consistent definition of wealth. Their [Pg 123] second goal was to demonstrate that acquiring wealth is ultimately only possible under certain moral conditions in society, the most important of which is a belief in the existence and, for practical purposes, the attainability of honesty.

Without venturing to pronounce—since on such a matter human judgment is by no means conclusive—what is, or is not, the noblest of God's works, we may yet admit so much of Pope's assertion as that an honest man is among His best works presently visible, and, as things stand, a somewhat rare one; but not an incredible or miraculous work; still less an abnormal one. Honesty is not a disturbing force, which deranges the orbits of economy; but a consistent and commanding force, by obedience to which—and by no other obedience—those orbits can continue clear of chaos.

Without trying to declare what is or isn't the greatest of God's creations—since human judgment on this matter is hardly definitive—we can agree with Pope's statement that an honest person is one of His best creations currently evident, and, as it stands, a bit of a rarity; but not an unbelievable or miraculous creation; even less an abnormal one. Honesty is not a disruptive force that throws the economy off balance; rather, it is a steady and powerful force, and only through following it—rather than any other—you can keep those systems from falling into chaos.

It is true, I have sometimes heard Pope condemned for the lowness, instead of the height, of his standard:—"Honesty is indeed a respectable virtue; but how much higher may men attain! Shall nothing more be asked of us than that we be honest?"

It’s true, I’ve heard people criticize Pope for focusing on the low bar instead of aiming higher: “Sure, honesty is a respectable virtue, but how much more can we achieve? Is being honest the only expectation of us?”

For the present, good friends, nothing. It seems that in our aspirations to be more than that, we have to some extent lost sight of the propriety of being so much as that. What else we may have lost faith in, there shall be here no question; but assuredly we have lost faith in common honesty, and in the working power of it. And this faith, with the facts on which it may rest, it is quite our first business to recover and keep: not only believing, but even by experience assuring ourselves, that there are yet in the world men who can be restrained from fraud otherwise than by the fear of losing employment;[27] nay that it is even accurately in proportion to the number of such men in any State, that the said State does or can prolong its existence.

For now, dear friends, nothing. It seems that in our desire to be more than just friends, we’ve somewhat lost sight of the importance of simply being that. Whatever else we may have lost faith in, let’s not get into that here; but it’s clear we have lost faith in basic honesty and its effectiveness. And this belief, along with the facts that support it, is our top priority to regain and maintain: not just believing, but also proving to ourselves through experience that there are still people in the world who can be held back from cheating beyond just the fear of losing a job;[27] and in fact, the number of such individuals in any society directly influences that society's ability to endure.

[Pg 124]To these two points, then, the following essays are mainly directed. The subject of the organization of labour is only casually touched upon; because, if we once can get a sufficient quantity of honesty in our captains, the organization of labour is easy, and will develop itself without quarrel or difficulty; but if we cannot get honesty in our captains, the organization of labour is for evermore impossible.

[Pg 124]So, these two points are the main focus of the following essays. The topic of how to organize labor is only briefly mentioned because, once we achieve a good level of honesty in our leaders, organizing labor becomes simple and will grow naturally, without conflict or hassle. However, if we can't ensure honesty in our leaders, organizing labor will always remain impossible.

The several conditions of its possibility I purpose to examine at length in the sequel. Yet, lest the reader should be alarmed by the hints thrown out during the following investigation of first principles, as if they were leading him into unexpectedly dangerous ground, I will, for his better assurance, state at once the worst of the political creed at which I wish him to arrive.

The various conditions for its possibility will be examined in detail later. However, to avoid alarming the reader with the initial hints during this exploration of fundamental principles, which might suggest he’s entering unexpectedly risky territory, I will reassure him by stating upfront the worst aspect of the political beliefs I want him to reach.

1. First,—that there should be training schools for youth established, at Government cost,[28] and under Government discipline, over the whole country; that every child born in the country should, at the parent's wish, be permitted (and, in certain cases, be under penalty required) to pass through them; and that, in these schools, the child should (with other minor pieces of knowledge hereafter to be considered) imperatively be taught, with the best skill of teaching that the country could produce, the following three things:—

1. First, there should be training schools for youth set up at the government's expense,[28] and under government supervision, across the entire country. Every child born in the country should, at the parent's request, be allowed (and in some cases, required under penalty) to attend these schools. In these schools, each child should be taught, with the best teaching methods available in the country, the following three essential subjects:—

(a) the laws of health, and the exercises enjoined by them;

(a) the principles of health and the recommended exercises;

(b) habits of gentleness and justice; and

(b) habits of kindness and fairness; and

(c) the calling by which he is to live.

(c) the calling he will live by.

2. Secondly,—that,[Pg 125] in connection with these training schools, there should be established, also entirely under Government regulation, manufactories and workshops, for the production and sale of every necessary of life, and for the exercise of every useful art. And that, interfering no whit with private enterprise, nor setting any restraints or tax on private trade, but leaving both to do their best, and beat the Government if they could,—there should, at these Government manufactories and shops, be authoritatively good and exemplary work done, and pure and true substance sold; so that a man could be sure, if he chose to pay the Government price, that he got for his money bread that was bread, ale that was ale, and work that was work.

2. Secondly,—that,[Pg 125] alongside these training schools, there should be established, also completely under Government regulation, factories and workshops for producing and selling essential goods and for practicing every useful craft. And that, without interfering with private businesses, nor imposing any restrictions or taxes on private trade, but allowing both to operate freely and outperform the Government if they could,—there should be high-quality and exemplary work produced and genuine products sold at these Government factories and shops; so that a person could be confident, if they chose to pay the Government price, that they were getting real bread for their money, real ale for their money, and real work for their money.

3. Thirdly,—that any man, or woman, or boy, or girl, out of employment, should be at once received at the nearest Government school, and set to such work as it appeared, on trial, they were fit for, at a fixed rate of wages determinable every year:—that, being found incapable of work through ignorance, they should be taught, or being found incapable of work through sickness, should be tended; but that being found objecting to work, they should be set, under compulsion of the strictest nature, to the more painful and degrading forms of necessary toil, especially to that in mines and other places of danger (such danger being, however, diminished to the utmost by careful regulation and discipline) and the due wages of such work be retained—cost of compulsion first abstracted—to be at the workman's command, so soon as he has come to sounder mind respecting the laws of employment.

3. Thirdly, any man, woman, boy, or girl who is out of work should be welcomed at the nearest government school and assigned to tasks that seem suitable for them after a trial period, at a fixed wage determined annually. If they are found unable to work due to ignorance, they should be taught; if they cannot work due to illness, they should be cared for. However, if they refuse to work, they should be compelled to take on more difficult and degrading forms of necessary labor, especially in mines and other hazardous environments (with precautions taken to minimize the danger through careful regulation and discipline). The wages earned from such work should be withheld—after deducting the cost of enforcement—and made available to the worker as soon as they have a clearer understanding of the laws of employment.

4. Lastly,—that for the old and destitute, comfort and home should be provided; which provision, when misfortune had been by the working of such a system sifted from guilt, would be honourable instead of disgraceful to the receiver. For (I repeat this passage out of my Political Economy of Art, to which the[Pg 126] reader is referred for farther detail[29]) "a labourer serves his country with his spade, just as a man in the middle ranks of life serves it with sword, pen, or lancet: if the service is less, and, therefore the wages during health less, then the reward, when health is broken, may be less, but not, therefore, less honourable; and it ought to be quite as natural and straightforward a matter for a labourer to take his pension from his parish, because he has deserved well of his parish, as for a man in higher rank to take his pension from his country, because he has deserved well of his country."

4. Lastly, for the elderly and those in need, there should be support and a place to call home. When unfortunate circumstances arise, and this support is given without guilt, it becomes something to be proud of rather than ashamed of for the person receiving it. As I mention in my Political Economy of Art, which the reader can refer to for more details[Pg 126][29]), "a laborer contributes to his country with his spade, just like someone in a higher position contributes with a sword, pen, or scalpel: if the labor is considered less important, and therefore the pay during health is lower, then the compensation when health fails may be less as well, but that doesn’t make it any less honorable. It should be just as natural and straightforward for a laborer to receive his pension from his parish, because he has served his parish well, as it is for someone of higher status to receive a pension from his country for having served it well."

To which statement, I will only add, for conclusion, respecting the discipline and pay of life and death, that, for both high and low, Livy's last words touching Valerius Publicola, "de publico est elatus,"[30] ought not to be a dishonourable close of epitaph.

To that statement, I just want to add in conclusion, regarding the rules and compensation of life and death, that for everyone, whether high or low, Livy's last words about Valerius Publicola, "de publico est elatus,"[30] should not be seen as a dishonorable end to an epitaph.

These things, then, I believe, and am about, as I find power, to explain and illustrate in their various bearings; following out also what belongs to them of collateral inquiry. Here I state them only in brief, to prevent the reader casting about in alarm for my ultimate meaning; yet requesting him, for the present to remember, that in a science dealing with so subtle elements as those of human nature, it is only possible to answer for the final truth of principles, not for the direct success of plans: and that in the best of these last, what can be immediately accomplished is always questionable, and what can be finally accomplished, inconceivable.

These things, then, I believe, and I am about to explain and illustrate in their various perspectives, also exploring related inquiries. Here, I’ll briefly state them to prevent the reader from worrying about my ultimate meaning; however, I ask that for now, you keep in mind that in a field dealing with the complex aspects of human nature, it’s only possible to guarantee the ultimate truth of principles, not the immediate success of plans: and that even in the best of these, what can be achieved right away is always uncertain, and what can ultimately be achieved is unimaginable.

    Denmark Hill, 10th May, 1862.

Denmark Hill, May 10, 1862.

FOOTNOTES:

[25] Which? for where investigation is necessary, teaching is impossible.

[25] Which? where investigation is needed, teaching is not possible.

[26] "Principles of Political Economy." By J. S. Mill. Preliminary remarks, p. 2.

[26] "Principles of Political Economy." By J. S. Mill. Preliminary remarks, p. 2.

[27] "The effectual discipline which is exercised over a workman is not that of his corporation, but of his customers. It is the fear of losing their employment which restrains his frauds, and corrects his negligence" (Wealth of Nations, Book I. chap. 10).

[27] "The real discipline a worker faces doesn't come from their company, but from their customers. It's the fear of losing their job that keeps them honest and makes them pay attention to their work" (Wealth of Nations, Book I. chap. 10).

[28] It will probably be inquired by near-sighted persons, out of what funds such schools could be supported. The expedient modes of direct provision for them I will examine hereafter; indirectly, they would be far more than self-supporting. The economy in crime alone (quite one of the most costly articles of luxury in the modern European market), which such schools would induce, would suffice to support them ten times over. Their economy of labour would be pure gain, and that too large to be presently calculable.

[28] People with limited vision might wonder where the funding for such schools would come from. I will discuss practical ways to provide for them later; however, they would likely be more than self-sustaining in other ways. The savings from reduced crime alone (which is one of the most expensive issues in the modern European economy) would be enough to fund them ten times over. The efficiency in labor would also be a significant benefit, and it’s too large to calculate right now.

[29] "The Political Economy of Art:" Addenda, p. 93.

[29] "The Political Economy of Art:" Addenda, p. 93.

[30] "P. Valerius, omnium consensu princeps belli pacisque artibus, anno post moritur; gloriâ ingenti, copiis familiaribus adeo exiguis, ut funeri sumtus deesset: de publico est elatus. Luxêre matronæ ut Brutum."—Lib. II. c. xvi.

[30] "P. Valerius, the leading figure in the arts of war and peace agreed upon by all, passes away a year later; with immense glory but family resources so meager that the funeral expenses fell short: he was honored by the state. The women wept for Brutus."—Lib. II. c. xvi.


ESSAY I.

THE ROOTS OF HONOUR.

Among the delusions which at different periods have possessed themselves of the minds of large masses of the human race, perhaps the most curious—certainly the least creditable—is the modern soi-disant science of political economy, based on the idea that an advantageous code of social action may be determined irrespectively of the influence of social affection.

Among the misconceptions that have taken hold of large groups of people at various times, perhaps the most interesting—and definitely the least respectable—is the modern so-called science of political economy, which is based on the belief that an effective system of social behavior can be established without considering the impact of social relationships.

Of course, as in the instances of alchemy, astrology, witchcraft, and other such popular creeds, political economy has a plausible idea at the root of it. "The social affections," says the economist, "are accidental and disturbing elements in human nature; but avarice and the desire of progress are constant elements. Let us eliminate the inconstants, and, considering the human being merely as a covetous machine, examine by what laws of labour, purchase, and sale, the greatest accumulative result in wealth is obtainable. Those laws once determined, it will be for each individual afterwards to introduce as much of the disturbing affectionate element as he chooses, and to determine for himself the result on the new conditions supposed."

Of course, like alchemy, astrology, witchcraft, and other popular beliefs, political economy has a convincing idea at its core. "The social feelings," says the economist, "are random and disruptive parts of human nature; but greed and the desire for progress are constant factors. Let’s remove the inconsistencies and, viewing humans purely as greedy machines, explore the laws of labor, buying, and selling that yield the greatest accumulation of wealth. Once we identify those laws, it will be up to each individual to add as much of the disruptive emotional element as they want and to figure out the outcome based on the new conditions."

This would be a perfectly logical and successful method of analysis, if the accidentals afterwards to be introduced were of the same nature as the powers first examined. Supposing a body in motion to be influenced by constant and inconstant forces, it is usually the simplest way of examining its course to trace it first under the persistent conditions, and afterwards introduce the causes of variation. But the disturbing elements in the social problem are not of the same nature as the constant[Pg 128] ones; they alter the essence of the creature under examination the moment they are added; they operate, not mathematically, but chemically, introducing conditions which render all our previous knowledge unavailable. We made learned experiments upon pure nitrogen, and have convinced ourselves that it is a very manageable gas: but behold! the thing which we have practically to deal with is its chloride; and this, the moment we touch it on our established principles, sends us and our apparatus through the ceiling.

This would be a perfectly logical and effective way to analyze things if the variables introduced later were similar to the initial forces examined. When considering a moving object influenced by both constant and variable forces, the simplest approach is usually to first study it under steady conditions and then introduce the factors that cause change. However, the disruptive elements in social issues aren’t the same as the constant ones; they change the nature of what we’re studying as soon as they’re added. They work more like chemicals than like math, introducing conditions that make all our previous knowledge useless. We conducted careful experiments on pure nitrogen and convinced ourselves it’s a manageable gas: but the reality we actually deal with is its chloride, and as soon as we apply our established principles to it, we find ourselves and our equipment flying through the ceiling.

Observe, I neither impugn nor doubt the conclusions of the science, if its terms are accepted. I am simply uninterested in them, as I should be in those of a science of gymnastics which assumed that men had no skeletons. It might be shown, on that supposition, that it would be advantageous to roll the students up into pellets, flatten them into cakes, or stretch them into cables; and that when these results were effected, the re-insertion of the skeleton would be attended with various inconveniences to their constitution. The reasoning might be admirable, the conclusions true, and the science deficient only in applicability. Modern political economy stands on a precisely similar basis. Assuming, not that the human being has no skeleton, but that it is all skeleton, it founds an ossifiant theory of progress on this negation of a soul; and having shown the utmost that may be made of bones, and constructed a number of interesting geometrical figures with death's-heads and humeri, successfully proves the inconvenience of the reappearance of a soul among these corpuscular structures. I do not deny the truth of this theory: I simply deny its applicability to the present phase of the world.

Look, I neither challenge nor doubt the conclusions of science, if we accept its terms. I’m just not interested in them, like I wouldn’t care about a sports science that assumed people had no skeletons. It could be argued, under that assumption, that it would be beneficial to roll students into balls, flatten them into pancakes, or stretch them into cables; and when these changes were made, re-inserting the skeleton would come with various issues for their bodies. The reasoning could be excellent, the conclusions accurate, and the science just lacking in real-world application. Modern political economy rests on a similar foundation. Instead of assuming humans have no skeleton, it assumes humans are entirely skeleton, building a rigid theory of progress on the denial of a soul; and after showing everything that can be done with bones, creating various interesting geometric shapes with skulls and upper arm bones, it demonstrates the problems that arise when a soul tries to come back into these tiny structures. I don’t dispute the truth of this theory: I only challenge its relevance to the current state of the world.

This inapplicability has been curiously manifested during the embarrassment caused by the late strikes of our workmen. Here occurs one of the simplest cases, in a pertinent and positive form, of the first vital problem which political economy has to deal with (the relation between employer and employed); and at a severe crisis, when lives in multitudes, and wealth in masses, are at stake, the political economists are helpless—practically mute; no demonstrable solution of the difficulty can be given by them, such as may convince or calm the opposing parties. Obstinately the masters take one view of[Pg 129] the matter; obstinately the operatives another; and no political science can set them at one.

This issue has been strangely highlighted during the recent strikes by our workers. We see one of the most straightforward examples of the key problem that political economy needs to address (the relationship between employers and employees); and during a serious crisis, when many lives and significant wealth are on the line, political economists seem powerless—essentially silent. They can't provide a clear solution to the problem that would satisfy or calm both sides. The employers stubbornly hold one perspective, while the workers firmly cling to another, and no political theory can reconcile their differences.

It would be strange if it could, it being not by "science" of any kind that men were ever intended to be set at one. Disputant after disputant vainly strives to show that the interests of the masters are, or are not, antagonistic to those of the men: none of the pleaders ever seeming to remember that it does not absolutely or always follow that the persons must be antagonistic because their interests are. If there is only a crust of bread in the house, and mother and children are starving, their interests are not the same. If the mother eats it, the children want it; if the children eat it, the mother must go hungry to her work. Yet it does not necessarily follow that there will be "antagonism" between them, that they will fight for the crust, and that the mother, being strongest, will get it, and eat it. Neither, in any other case, whatever the relations of the persons may be, can it be assumed for certain that, because their interests are diverse, they must necessarily regard each other with hostility, and use violence or cunning to obtain the advantage.

It would be odd if it could, since it's not through any kind of "science" that people were ever meant to align. Each debater tries in vain to argue whether the interests of the powerful are, or are not, opposed to those of the workers: none of the advocates seem to remember that it doesn't always mean people must be in conflict just because their interests differ. If there's only one piece of bread in the house and the mother and children are hungry, their interests aren’t aligned. If the mother eats it, the children want it; if the children eat it, the mother will go hungry for work. Yet it doesn't necessarily mean there will be "conflict" between them, that they will fight over the bread, and that the mother, being stronger, will take it and eat it. Similarly, in any other situation, no matter the relationships involved, it can't be assumed that just because their interests are different, they must view each other with hostility and resort to violence or deception to gain the upper hand.

Even if this were so, and it were as just as it is convenient to consider men as actuated by no other moral influences than those which affect rats or swine, the logical conditions of the question are still indeterminable. It can never be shown generally either that the interests of master and labourer are alike, or that they are opposed; for, according to circumstances, they may be either. It is, indeed, always the interest of both that the work should be rightly done, and a just price obtained for it; but, in the division of profits, the gain of the one may or may not be the loss of the other. It is not the master's interest to pay wages so low as to leave the men sickly and depressed, nor the workman's interest to be paid high wages if the smallness of the master's profit hinders him from enlarging his business, or conducting it in a safe and liberal way. A stoker ought not to desire high pay if the company is too poor to keep the engine-wheels in repair.

Even if that were true, and it was just as convenient to think of people as driven by no more moral influences than those that affect rats or pigs, the logical aspects of the issue are still unclear. It can never be generally proven that the interests of the employer and the employee are the same or that they are in conflict; depending on the situation, they can be either. It is always in both parties’ interest for the work to be done well and for a fair price to be achieved; however, in the profit-sharing, one person's gain might not necessarily mean the other person's loss. It’s not in the employer's interest to pay wages so low that the workers become sickly and unhappy, nor is it in the worker's interest to receive high wages if the employer's limited profits prevent them from expanding the business or managing it in a safe and generous way. A stoker shouldn't want high pay if the company is too broke to keep the engine in good condition.

And the varieties of circumstance which influence these reciprocal interests are so endless, that all endeavour to deduce rules of action from balance of expediency is in vain. And[Pg 130] it is meant to be in vain. For no human actions ever were intended by the Maker of men to be guided by balances of expediency, but by balances of justice. He has therefore rendered all endeavours to determine expediency futile for evermore. No man ever knew or can know, what will be the ultimate result to himself, or to others, of any given line of conduct. But every man may know, and most of us do know, what is a just and unjust act. And all of us may know also, that the consequences of justice will be ultimately the best possible, both to others and ourselves, though we can neither say what is best, or how it is likely to come to pass.

The different circumstances that affect these mutual interests are so vast that trying to derive rules of action from a balance of convenience is pointless. And[Pg 130] it is meant to be pointless. The Creator intended that human actions be guided not by convenience but by justice. As a result, all attempts to determine what is convenient are doomed to fail forever. No one has ever known or can know what the final outcome will be for themselves or others based on any specific course of action. However, everyone can understand what is fair and what is unfair. We can also agree that the outcomes of justice will ultimately be the best for everyone, even though we can't specify what is best or how it will come about.

I have said balances of justice, meaning, in the term justice, to include affection,—such affection as one man owes to another. All right relations between master and operative, and all their best interests, ultimately depend on these.

I have mentioned the balances of justice, which means that, in the context of justice, I also include love—specifically, the kind of love one person owes to another. All proper relationships between a master and a worker, along with all their best interests, ultimately rely on these.

We shall find the best and simplest illustration of the relations of master and operative in the position of domestic servants.

We will find the best and simplest example of the relationship between employer and employee in the role of domestic workers.

We will suppose that the master of a household desires only to get as much work out of his servants as he can, at the rate of wages he gives. He never allows them to be idle; feeds them as poorly and lodges them as ill as they will endure, and in all things pushes his requirements to the exact point beyond which he cannot go without forcing the servant to leave him. In doing this, there is no violation on his part of what is commonly called "justice." He agrees with the domestic for his whole time and service, and takes them;—the limits of hardship in treatment being fixed by the practice of other masters in his neighbourhood; that is to say, by the current rate of wages for domestic labour. If the servant can get a better place, he is free to take one, and the master can only tell what is the real market value of his labour, by requiring as much as he will give.

Let's say the head of a household wants to get as much work as possible out of his servants for the wages he pays. He never lets them be idle; he feeds them as frugally and houses them as poorly as they can tolerate, pushing his demands to the limit just before they would feel compelled to leave. In doing this, he's not violating what people usually think of as "justice." He makes a deal with the domestic worker for their full time and services, based on what others in his area provide; in other words, according to the going rate for domestic labor. If the servant finds a better job, they can take it, and the master can only gauge the true market value of their labor by asking for as much as they'll give.

This is the politico-economical view of the case, according to the doctors of that science; who assert that by this procedure the greatest average of work will be obtained from the servant, and therefore, the greatest benefit to the community, and through the community, by reversion, to the servant himself.

This is the political and economic perspective on the situation, according to the experts in that field. They argue that this approach will yield the highest average output from the worker, resulting in the most benefit for the community, which ultimately returns to the worker as well.

That, however, is not so. It would be so if the servant were[Pg 131] an engine of which the motive power was steam, magnetism, gravitation, or any other agent of calculable force. But he being, on the contrary, an engine whose motive power is a Soul, the force of this very peculiar agent, as an unknown quantity, enters into all the political economist's equations, without his knowledge, and falsifies every one of their results. The largest quantity of work will not be done by this curious engine for pay, or under pressure, or by help of any kind of fuel which may be supplied by the chaldron. It will be done only when the motive force, that is to say, the will or spirit of the creature, is brought to its greatest strength by its own proper fuel; namely, by the affections.

That, however, is not the case. It would be if the servant were an engine powered by steam, magnetism, gravitation, or any other measurable force. But since he is, in fact, an engine powered by a Soul, the influence of this unique force, as an unknown variable, affects all the political economist's calculations without his awareness, skewing every one of their outcomes. The most work won’t be done by this strange engine for money, under pressure, or with any kind of fuel that can be measured in bulk. It will only happen when the driving force, which is the creature's will or spirit, is maximized by its own natural fuel; that is, by emotions.

It may indeed happen, and does happen often, that if the master is a man of sense and energy, a large quantity of material work may be done under mechanical pressure, enforced by strong will and guided by wise method; also it may happen, and does happen often, that if the master is indolent and weak (however good-natured), a very small quantity of work, and that bad, may be produced by the servant's undirected strength, and contemptuous gratitude. But the universal law of the matter is that, assuming any given quantity of energy and sense in master and servant, the greatest material result obtainable by them will be, not through antagonism to each other, but through affection for each other; and that if the master, instead of endeavouring to get as much work as possible from the servant, seeks rather to render his appointed and necessary work beneficial to him, and to forward his interests in all just and wholesome ways, the real amount of work ultimately done, or of good rendered, by the person so cared for, will indeed be the greatest possible.

It often happens that if the leader is sensible and energetic, a significant amount of work can be accomplished through mechanical pressure, driven by strong will and guided by sound methods. Conversely, if the leader is lazy and weak (even if well-meaning), only a small amount of poor-quality work may come from the servant's unfocused efforts and grudging gratitude. However, the overarching principle is that, given the same amount of energy and intelligence from both the leader and the servant, the best results will come not from conflict, but from mutual respect and care. If the leader focuses on making the servant's necessary work truly beneficial and supports their interests in fair and healthy ways, the actual amount of work done or good achieved by that cared-for individual will indeed be the highest possible.

Observe, I say, "of good rendered," for a servant's work is not necessarily or always the best thing he can give his master. But good of all kinds, whether in material service, in protective watchfulness of his master's interest and credit, or in joyful readiness to seize unexpected and irregular occasions of help.

Observe, I say, "of good provided," because a servant's work isn't always the best thing he can offer his master. But good can come in many forms, whether it's through practical service, being vigilantly aware of his master's interests and reputation, or being eager to take advantage of unexpected opportunities to help.

Nor is this one whit less generally true because indulgence will be frequently abused, and kindness met with ingratitude. For the servant who, gently treated, is ungrateful, treated[Pg 132] ungently, will be revengeful; and the man who is dishonest to a liberal master will be injurious to an unjust one.

Nor is this any less true just because indulgence can often be misused, and kindness can be met with ingratitude. A servant who is treated kindly and is ungrateful, when treated harshly, will seek revenge; and a person who is dishonest with a generous master will also be harmful to an unfair one.

In any case, and with any person, this unselfish treatment will produce the most effective return. Observe, I am here considering the affections wholly as a motive power; not at all as things in themselves desirable or noble, or in any other way abstractedly good. I look at them simply as an anomalous force, rendering every one of the ordinary political economist's calculations nugatory; while, even if he desired to introduce this new element into his estimates, he has no power of dealing with it; for the affections only become a true motive power when they ignore every other motive and condition of political economy. Treat the servant kindly, with the idea of turning his gratitude to account, and you will get, as you deserve, no gratitude, nor any value for your kindness; but treat him kindly without any economical purpose, and all economical purposes will be answered; in this, as in all other matters, whosoever will save his life shall lose it, whoso loses it shall find it.[31]

In any case, and with any person, this selfless treatment will lead to the most effective outcome. Note that I am discussing feelings purely as a driving force; not as things that are inherently desirable or noble, or in any abstract way good. I view them simply as an unusual force, making all of the typical political economist's calculations worthless; while, even if he wanted to include this new factor in his estimates, he lacks the ability to manage it; because feelings only become a true driving force when they disregard every other motive and condition of political economy. If you treat the servant well with the intention of gaining their gratitude, you will receive, as you deserve, no gratitude and no value for your kindness; but if you treat them well without any economic goal, all economic goals will be achieved; in this, as in all other situations, whoever seeks to save their life will lose it, and whoever loses it will find it.[31]

The next clearest and simplest example of relation between master and operative is that which exists between the commander of a regiment and his men.

The next clearest and simplest example of the relationship between a leader and their team is the one between a regiment's commander and their soldiers.

[Pg 133]Supposing the officer only desires to apply the rules of discipline so as, with least trouble to himself, to make the regiment most effective, he will not be able, by any rules, or administration of rules, on this selfish principle, to develop the full strength of his subordinates. If a man of sense and firmness, he may, as in the former instance, produce a better result than would be obtained by the irregular kindness of a weak officer; but let the sense and firmness be the same in both cases, and assuredly the officer who has the most direct personal relations with his men, the most care for their interests, and the most value for their lives, will develop their effective strength, through their affection for his own person, and trust in his character, to a degree wholly unattainable by other means. The law applies still more stringently as the numbers concerned are larger; a charge may often be successful, though the men dislike their officers; a battle has rarely been won, unless they loved their general.

[Pg 133]If the officer only wants to enforce the rules of discipline in a way that minimizes his effort while maximizing the regiment's effectiveness, he won't be able to fully tap into his subordinates' strength through mere rules or a strict administration of those rules. If he's sensible and strong, he might achieve better results than a weak officer who shows random kindness; but if both are equally sensible and strong, the officer who builds direct personal connections with his men, cares about their wellbeing, and values their lives will unlock their true potential. This is due to their affection for him and trust in his character, which can't be matched by other approaches. This principle is even more crucial when dealing with larger groups; a charge can succeed even if the men dislike their officers, but a battle is rarely won unless the soldiers love their general.

Passing from these simple examples to the more complicated relations existing between a manufacturer and his workmen, we are met first by certain curious difficulties, resulting, apparently, from a harder and colder state of moral elements. It is easy to imagine an enthusiastic affection existing among soldiers for the colonel, not so easy to imagine an enthusiastic affection among cotton-spinners for the proprietor of the mill. A body of men associated for purposes of robbery (as a Highland clan in ancient times) shall be animated by perfect affection, and every member of it be ready to lay down his life for the life of his chief. But a band of men associated for purposes of legal production and accumulation is usually animated, it appears, by no such emotions, and none of them are in anywise willing to give his life for the life of his chief. Not only are we met by this apparent anomaly, in moral matters, but by others connected with it, in administration [Pg 134]of system. For a servant or a soldier is engaged at a definite rate of wages, for a definite period; but a workman at a rate of wages variable according to the demand for labour, and with the risk of being at any time thrown out of his situation by chances of trade. Now, as, under these contingencies, no action of the affections can take place, but only an explosive action of disaffections, two points offer themselves for consideration in the matter.

Moving from these straightforward examples to the more complex relationships between a manufacturer and his workers, we encounter some interesting challenges that seem to stem from a tougher and colder set of moral factors. It's easy to envision soldiers having strong loyalty to their colonel, but it's not as easy to picture cotton-spinners feeling that same loyalty towards the owner of the mill. A group of men banded together for robbery (like a Highland clan in ancient times) can have genuine affection for one another, and each member might be willing to sacrifice their life for their leader. However, a group of men working together for legal production and profit typically doesn't share those same feelings, and none of them are likely to risk their life for their boss. Not only do we face this moral paradox, but we also see other related issues in management [Pg 134]of systems. A servant or a soldier is hired at a fixed wage for a set period; on the other hand, a worker is paid a wage that fluctuates based on labor demand and faces the risk of being laid off at any time due to market changes. Since, under these circumstances, emotional bonds don’t form and instead only resentments arise, two key points warrant consideration in this situation.

The first—How far the rate of wages may be so regulated as not to vary with the demand for labour.

The first—How can the wage rate be set in a way that it doesn't change with the demand for labor?

The second—How far it is possible that bodies of workmen may be engaged and maintained at such fixed rate of wages (whatever the state of trade may be), without enlarging or diminishing their number, so as to give them permanent interest in the establishment with which they are connected, like that of the domestic servants in an old family, or an esprit de corps, like that of the soldiers in a crack regiment.

The second—How likely is it that groups of workers can be hired and kept at a fixed wage (regardless of the state of the market), without increasing or decreasing their numbers, to ensure they have a lasting stake in the organization they work for, similar to the domestic staff in an old family, or a sense of unity, like that of soldiers in a prestigious regiment.

The first question is, I say, how far it may be possible to fix the rate of wages irrespectively of the demand for labour.

The first question is, I ask, how much it might be possible to set the wage rate regardless of the demand for labor.

Perhaps one of the most curious facts in the history of human error is the denial by the common political economist of the possibility of thus regulating wages; while, for all the important, and much of the unimportant, labour on the earth, wages are already so regulated.

Perhaps one of the most interesting facts in the history of human error is the refusal by the typical political economist to acknowledge the possibility of regulating wages in this way; while, for nearly all significant, and much of the less significant, work on Earth, wages are already regulated.

We do not sell our prime-ministership by Dutch auction; nor, on the decease of a bishop, whatever may be the general advantages of simony, do we (yet) offer his diocese to the clergyman who will take the episcopacy at the lowest contract. We (with exquisite sagacity of political economy!) do indeed sell commissions, but not, openly, generalships: sick, we do not inquire for a physician who takes less than a guinea; litigious, we never think of reducing six-and-eightpence to four-and-sixpence; caught in a shower, we do not canvass the cabmen, to find one who values his driving at less than a sixpence a mile.

We don’t sell our prime minister position through a Dutch auction; nor, when a bishop passes away, no matter the overall benefits of simony, do we (yet) offer his diocese to the clergyman who will accept the role at the lowest price. We (with a keen sense of political economy!) do sell commissions, but not, openly, generalship: when sick, we don’t look for a doctor who charges less than a guinea; when dealing with legal issues, we never think about lowering six-and-eightpence to four-and-sixpence; caught in the rain, we don’t shop around for cab drivers, trying to find one who values their service at less than a sixpence a mile.

It is true that in all these cases there is, and in every conceivable case there must be, ultimate reference to the presumed difficulty of the work, or number of candidates for the office. If it were thought that the labour necessary to make a good[Pg 135] physician would be gone through by a sufficient number of students with the prospect of only half-guinea fees, public consent would soon withdraw the unnecessary half-guinea. In this ultimate sense, the price of labour is indeed always regulated by the demand for it; but so far as the practical and immediate administration of the matter is regarded, the best labour always has been, and is, as all labour ought to be, paid by an invariable standard.

It's true that in all these instances, and in every potential situation, there must be a final reference to the expected difficulty of the work or the number of candidates for the position. If people believed that enough students would put in the effort needed to become good[Pg 135] physicians for just half a guinea, public approval would quickly eliminate the unnecessary half-guinea fee. In this ultimate sense, the price of labor is indeed always determined by demand; but when it comes to the practical and immediate management of the situation, the best labor has always been, and should be, compensated by a consistent standard.

"What!" the reader, perhaps, answers amazedly: "pay good and bad workmen alike?"

"What!" the reader might respond in disbelief: "You pay both good and bad workers the same?"

Certainly. The difference between one prelate's sermons and his successor's,—or between one physician's opinion and another's,—is far greater, as respects the qualities of mind involved, and far more important in result to you personally, than the difference between good and bad laying of bricks (though that is greater than most people suppose). Yet you pay with equal fee, contentedly, the good and bad workmen upon your soul, and the good and bad workmen upon your body; much more may you pay, contentedly, with equal fees, the good and bad workmen upon your house.

Sure. The difference between one preacher's sermons and his successor's—or between one doctor's opinion and another's—is much greater, in terms of the qualities of mind involved, and is far more significant for you personally than the difference between good and bad bricklaying (though that difference is greater than most people realize). Yet you willingly pay the same fee to both the skilled and unskilled workers on your soul, as well as to those working on your body; and even more, you easily pay the same fees to both the good and bad workers on your house.

"Nay, but I choose my physician and (?) my clergyman, thus indicating my sense of the quality of their work." By all means, also, choose your bricklayer; that is the proper reward of the good workman, to be "chosen." The natural and right system respecting all labour is, that it should be paid at a fixed rate, but the good workman employed, and the bad workmen unemployed. The false, unnatural, and destructive system is, when the bad workman is allowed to offer his work at half-price, and either take the place of the good, or force him by his competition to work for an inadequate sum.

"No, I choose my doctor and my clergyman, which shows I appreciate the quality of their work." Of course, you should also choose your bricklayer; that's the proper reward for a skilled worker, to be "chosen." The natural and correct system for all labor is that it should be paid at a fixed rate, with skilled workers employed and unskilled workers unemployed. The false, unnatural, and harmful system occurs when unskilled workers can offer their services for half the price, taking jobs from skilled workers or forcing them to work for less.

This equality of wages, then, being the first object towards which we have to discover the directest available road; the second is, as above stated, that of maintaining constant numbers of workmen in employment, whatever may be the accidental demand for the article they produce.

This equal pay, then, is the first goal we need to find the quickest way to achieve; the second, as mentioned above, is to keep a steady number of workers employed, regardless of the fluctuating demand for the products they make.

I believe the sudden and extensive inequalities of demand which necessarily arise in the mercantile operations of an active nation, constitute the only essential difficulty which has to be overcome in a just organization of labour. The[Pg 136] subject opens into too many branches to admit of being investigated in a paper of this kind; but the following general facts bearing on it may be noted.

I think the sudden and significant inequalities in demand that naturally occur in the business operations of a bustling nation are the only major challenge that needs to be addressed for a fair organization of labor. The[Pg 136] topic has too many aspects to be thoroughly explored in a paper like this, but here are some general facts related to it worth mentioning.

The wages which enable any workman to live are necessarily higher, if his work is liable to intermission, than if it is assured and continuous; and however severe the struggle for work may become, the general law will always hold, that men must get more daily pay if, on the average, they can only calculate on work three days a week, than they would require if they were sure of work six days a week. Supposing that a man cannot live on less than a shilling a day, his seven shillings he must get, either for three days' violent work, or six days' deliberate work. The tendency of all modern mercantile operations is to throw both wages and trade into the form of a lottery, and to make the workman's pay depend on intermittent exertion, and the principal's profit on dexterously used chance.

The wages that allow any worker to get by are naturally higher if their work is inconsistent compared to when it is steady and ongoing. No matter how tough the job market gets, the basic rule remains that people need to earn more per day if they can normally expect to work only three days a week than if they had a guaranteed six days of work. If we assume a person can't survive on less than a shilling a day, then they have to earn their seven shillings, either from three days of hard labor or six days of steady work. The trend in modern businesses is to turn both wages and trade into a sort of lottery, making a worker's pay depend on sporadic effort, while the employer's profit relies on skillful chance.

In what partial degree, I repeat, this may be necessary, in consequence of the activities of modern trade, I do not here investigate; contenting myself with the fact, that in its fatallest aspects it is assuredly unnecessary, and results merely from love of gambling on the part of the masters, and from ignorance and sensuality in the men. The masters cannot bear to let any opportunity of gain escape them, and frantically rush at every gap and breach in the walls of Fortune, raging to be rich, and affronting, with impatient covetousness, every risk of ruin; while the men prefer three days of violent labour, and three days of drunkenness, to six days of moderate work and wise rest. There is no way in which a principal, who really desires to help his workmen, may do it more effectually than by checking these disorderly habits both in himself and them; keeping his own business operations on a scale which will enable him to pursue them securely, not yielding to temptations of precarious gain; and, at the same time, leading his workmen into regular habits of labour and life, either by inducing them rather to take low wages in the form of a fixed salary, than high wages, subject to the chance of their being thrown out of work; or, if this be impossible, by discouraging the system of violent exertion for nominally high[Pg 137] day wages, and leading the men to take lower pay for more regular labour.

In what limited way, I repeat, this may be necessary because of the activities of modern trade, I'm not going to explore here; I’m just acknowledging that, in its most harmful aspects, it’s definitely unnecessary and stems mainly from the desire to gamble on the part of the owners, and from ignorance and hedonism in the workers. The owners can’t stand to miss any chance to make money, and they rush towards every opportunity for profit, desperate to get rich, ignoring every potential risk of ruin because of their impatient greed. Meanwhile, the workers would rather work hard for three days and then spend three days partying than put in six days of steady work and sensible rest. A manager who genuinely wants to help his workers can do so most effectively by curbing these disordered habits in both himself and them; maintaining his business operations at a level that allows him to manage them safely, avoiding the lure of risky profits; and, at the same time, encouraging his workers to develop consistent work and life habits, either by persuading them to accept lower wages in the form of a stable salary rather than higher wages that carry the risk of unemployment, or, if that’s not possible, by discouraging the practice of intense effort for comparatively high daily wages, and guiding the workers to accept lower pay for more consistent work.

In effecting any radical changes of this kind, doubtless there would be great inconvenience and loss incurred by all the originators of movement. That which can be done with perfect convenience and without loss, is not always the thing that most needs to be done, or which we are most imperatively required to do.

In making any major changes like this, it’s likely that the people who started the movement will face a lot of inconvenience and loss. What can be done easily and without any loss isn’t always the most necessary thing to do, or what we absolutely need to do.

I have already alluded to the difference hitherto existing between regiments of men associated for purposes of violence, and for purposes of manufacture; in that the former appear capable of self-sacrifice—the latter, not; which singular fact is the real reason of the general lowness of estimate in which the profession of commerce is held, as compared with that of arms. Philosophically, it does not, at first sight, appear reasonable (many writers have endeavoured to prove it unreasonable) that a peaceable and rational person, whose trade is buying and selling, should be held in less honour than an unpeaceable and often irrational person, whose trade is slaying. Nevertheless, the consent of mankind has always, in spite of the philosophers, given precedence to the soldier.

I have already pointed out the difference that has existed between groups of men banded together for violence and those united for manufacturing; the former seem capable of self-sacrifice, while the latter do not. This unique fact is the true reason why the profession of commerce is generally viewed as lesser compared to that of the military. Philosophically, it doesn’t seem reasonable at first glance (many writers have tried to argue against this) that a peaceful and rational person whose profession involves buying and selling should be considered less honorable than an unpeaceful and often irrational person whose job is to kill. Nevertheless, despite what philosophers say, the general consensus has always favored the soldier.

And this is right.

And this is correct.

For the soldier's trade, verily and essentially, is not slaying, but being slain. This, without well knowing its own meaning, the world honours it for. A bravo's trade is slaying; but the world has never respected bravos more than merchants: the reason it honours the soldier is, because he holds his life at the service of the State. Reckless he may be—fond of pleasure or of adventure—all kinds of bye-motives and mean impulses may have determined the choice of his profession, and may affect (to all appearance exclusively) his daily conduct in it; but our estimate of him is based on this ultimate fact—of which we are well assured—that, put him in a fortress breach, with all the pleasures of the world behind him, and only death and his duty in front of him, he will keep his face to the front; and he knows that this choice may be put to him at any moment, and has beforehand taken his part—virtually takes such part continually—does, in reality, die daily.

For soldiers, the real job isn’t killing, but getting killed. The world honors this idea without fully understanding it. A hired killer's job is to kill; however, the world has never respected hired killers more than merchants. The reason we respect soldiers is that they offer their lives for the State. They may be reckless, enjoy pleasure or adventure, and various ulterior motives and selfish impulses may have influenced their choice of profession and their daily actions; but our view of them is rooted in one fundamental fact—we know that if you put them at a breach in a fortress, with all the pleasures of the world behind them and only death and duty ahead, they will face forward. They understand that this choice could come up at any moment, and they have already made their decision—they essentially make that decision every day and, in reality, die a little bit each day.

Not less is the respect we pay to the lawyer and physician,[Pg 138] founded ultimately on their self-sacrifice. Whatever the learning or acuteness of a great lawyer, our chief respect for him depends on our belief that, set in a judge's seat, he will strive to judge justly, come of it what may. Could we suppose that he would take bribes, and use his acuteness and legal knowledge to give plausibility to iniquitous decisions, no degree of intellect would win for him our respect. Nothing will win it, short of our tacit conviction, that in all important acts of his life justice is first with him; his own interest, second.

We show just as much respect for lawyers and doctors,[Pg 138] which ultimately comes from their selflessness. No matter how knowledgeable or skilled a great lawyer may be, our main respect for him is based on our belief that when in a judge's seat, he will try to judge fairly, no matter the consequences. If we thought he would accept bribes and apply his skills and legal knowledge to support unjust decisions, no level of intelligence would earn our respect. The only thing that will earn it is our shared belief that in all significant actions in his life, justice is his top priority; his own interests come second.

In the case of a physician, the ground of the honour we render him is clearer still. Whatever his science, we should shrink from him in horror if we found him regard his patients merely as subjects to experiment upon; much more, if we found that, receiving bribes from persons interested in their deaths, he was using his best skill to give poison in the mask of medicine.

In the case of a doctor, the reason we show him respect is even clearer. No matter what his expertise is, we would be horrified if we saw him treating his patients merely as test subjects; even more so if we discovered that, taking bribes from people who benefit from their deaths, he was using his medical knowledge to disguise poison as medicine.

Finally, the principle holds with utmost clearness as it respects clergymen. No goodness of disposition will excuse want of science in a physician, or of shrewdness in an advocate; but a clergyman, even though his power of intellect be small, is respected on the presumed ground of his unselfishness and serviceableness.

Finally, the principle is very clear when it comes to clergymen. No kindness of character can make up for a lack of knowledge in a doctor or a lack of cleverness in a lawyer; however, a clergyman, even if his intellect is limited, is respected because he is presumed to be selfless and helpful.

Now there can be no question but that the tact, foresight, decision, and other mental powers, required for the successful management of a large mercantile concern, if not such as could be compared with those of a great lawyer, general, or divine, would at least match the general conditions of mind required in the subordinate officers of a ship, or of a regiment, or in the curate of a country parish. If, therefore, all the efficient members of the so-called liberal professions are still, somehow, in public estimate of honour, preferred before the head of a commercial firm, the reason must lie deeper than in the measurement of their several powers of mind.

Now, there’s no doubt that the skills, foresight, decision-making, and other mental abilities needed to successfully run a large business, although not directly comparable to those of a top lawyer, general, or clergyman, would at least be on par with the overall mental demands of the subordinate officers of a ship, a regiment, or a rural parish clergy. Therefore, if all the key members of what are called liberal professions are still, for some reason, held in higher regard than the heads of commercial firms, the reason must go deeper than just comparing their mental abilities.

And the essential reason for such preference will be found to lie in the fact that the merchant is presumed to act always selfishly. His work may be very necessary to the community; but the motive of it is understood to be wholly personal. The merchant's first object in all his dealings must be (the public believe) to get as much for himself, and leave as little to his neighbour (or customer) as possible. Enforcing this[Pg 139] upon him, by political statute, as the necessary principle of his action; recommending it to him on all occasions, and themselves reciprocally adopting it; proclaiming vociferously, for law of the universe, that a buyer's function is to cheapen, and a seller's to cheat,—the public, nevertheless, involuntarily condemn the man of commerce for his compliance with their own statement, and stamp him for ever as belonging to an inferior grade of human personality.

And the main reason for this preference comes from the belief that merchants always act out of self-interest. Their work might be essential to the community, but it's widely understood that their motives are purely personal. People think that the merchant's primary goal in all their transactions is to get as much as possible for themselves and to leave as little as they can for their neighbor (or customer). By enshrining this idea[Pg 139] in political law as the guiding principle of their actions, promoting it at every chance, and adopting it themselves, society loudly asserts that a buyer's job is to drive down prices, while a seller's role is to deceive. Yet, the public inadvertently condemns the merchant for following their own beliefs and labels him as belonging to a lower class of human beings.

This they will find, eventually, they must give up doing. They must not cease to condemn selfishness; but they will have to discover a kind of commerce which is not exclusively selfish. Or, rather, they will have to discover that there never was, or can be, any other kind of commerce; that this which they have called commerce was not commerce at all, but cozening; and that a true merchant differs as much from a merchant according to laws of modern political economy, as the hero of the Excursion from Autolycus. They will find that commerce is an occupation which gentlemen will every day see more need to engage in, rather than in the businesses of talking to men, or slaying them; that, in true commerce, as in true preaching, or true fighting, it is necessary to admit the idea of occasional voluntary loss; that sixpences have to be lost, as well as lives, under a sense of duty; that the market may have its martyrdoms as well as the pulpit; and trade its heroisms, as well as war.

They will eventually realize that they have to give this up. They shouldn’t stop condemning selfishness; however, they need to find a way of doing business that isn't just about self-interest. Or, rather, they will have to recognize that there never was, and can never be, any other kind of business; that what they have labeled as business was not business at all, but trickery; and that a true merchant is as different from a merchant defined by the principles of modern economics as the hero of the Excursion is from Autolycus. They will discover that commerce is a profession that gentlemen will increasingly feel the need to pursue, instead of just engaging in discussions or conflicts; that, in genuine commerce, like in true preaching or true fighting, it’s essential to accept the idea of occasional voluntary losses; that sixpences must be lost just as lives may be, all under a sense of duty; that the market can have its sacrifices just like the pulpit can; and that trade can have its acts of heroism, just like war.

May have—in the final issue, must have—and only has not had yet, because men of heroic temper have always been misguided in their youth into other fields, not recognizing what is in our days, perhaps, the most important of all fields; so that, while many a zealous person loses his life in trying to teach the form of a gospel, very few will lose a hundred pounds in showing the practice of one.

May have—in the final issue, must have—and only hasn't had yet, because men of heroic spirit have always been misled in their youth into other pursuits, not realizing what is, perhaps, the most important field of all in our times; so that, while many enthusiastic individuals lose their lives trying to teach the principles of a gospel, very few will risk a hundred pounds to demonstrate the practice of one.

The fact is, that people never have had clearly explained to them the true functions of a merchant with respect to other people. I should like the reader to be very clear about this.

The reality is that people have never really had the true roles of a merchant in relation to others clearly explained to them. I want the reader to understand this very clearly.

Five great intellectual professions, relating to daily necessities of life, have hitherto existed—three exist necessarily, in every civilized nation:

Five important intellectual professions, connected to the everyday needs of life, have always existed—three are essential in every civilized society:

The Soldier's profession is to defend it.[Pg 140]

The Soldier's job is to defend it.[Pg 140]

The Pastor's, to teach it.

The Pastor's, to teach it.

The Physician's, to keep it in health.

The Doctor's, to keep it healthy.

The Lawyer's, to enforce justice in it.

The Lawyer's, to enforce justice in it.

The Merchant's, to provide for it.

The Merchant's, to provide for it.

And the duty of all these men is, on due occasion, to die for it.

And the responsibility of all these men is, when the time comes, to die for it.

"On due occasion," namely:—

"At the right time," namely:—

The Soldier, rather than leave his post in battle.

The Soldier, instead of abandoning his position during the fight.

The Physician, rather than leave his post in plague.

The doctor, instead of abandoning his position during the plague.

The Pastor, rather than teach Falsehood.

The Pastor, instead of promoting Falsehood.

The Lawyer, rather than countenance Injustice.

The Lawyer, instead of tolerating Injustice.

The Merchant—What is his "due occasion" of death? It is the main question for the merchant, as for all of us. For, truly, the man who does not know when to die, does not know how to live.

The Merchant—What is his "right moment" for death? This is the key question for the merchant, just like for all of us. Because, honestly, a person who doesn’t know when to die doesn’t know how to live.

Observe, the merchant's function (or manufacturer's, for in the broad sense in which it is here used the word must be understood to include both) is to provide for the nation. It is no more his function to get profit for himself out of that provision than it is a clergyman's function to get his stipend. The stipend is a due and necessary adjunct, but not the object, of his life, if he be a true clergyman, any more than his fee (or honorarium) is the object of life to a true physician. Neither is his fee the object of life to a true merchant. All three, if true men, have a work to be done irrespective of fee—to be done even at any cost, or for quite the contrary of fee; the pastor's function being to teach, the physician's to heal, and the merchant's, as I have said, to provide. That is to say, he has to understand to their very root the qualities of the thing he deals in, and the means of obtaining or producing it; and he has to apply all his sagacity and energy to the producing or obtaining it in perfect state, and distributing it at the cheapest possible price where it is most needed.

Look, the role of the merchant (or the manufacturer, since in this broad sense the term includes both) is to serve the nation. It's not his job to make a profit for himself from that service, just like it's not a clergyman's job to simply collect his salary. The salary is a necessary and rightful part of his life, but not its purpose if he's a genuine clergyman, just as a physician's fee isn't the main goal for a true doctor. Similarly, a true merchant doesn't see profit as the primary aim. All three, if they are honest individuals, have work to do that goes beyond money—work that they should be willing to perform at any cost or even without payment; the pastor’s role is to teach, the physician’s is to heal, and the merchant’s, as I mentioned, is to provide. This means he must deeply understand the qualities of what he deals with and how to obtain or produce it; he must direct all his intelligence and effort toward producing or obtaining it in the best possible condition and distributing it at the lowest price where it's most needed.

And because the production or obtaining of any commodity involves necessarily the agency of many lives and hands, the merchant becomes in the course of his business the master and governor of large masses of men in a more direct, though less confessed way, than a military officer or pastor; so that on him falls, in great part, the responsibility for the kind of life[Pg 141] they lead: and it becomes his duty, not only to be always considering how to produce what he sells in the purest and cheapest forms, but how to make the various employments involved in the production, or transference of it, most beneficial to the men employed.

And since producing or acquiring any product necessarily involves the efforts of many individuals, the merchant, in the course of his business, becomes a leader and overseer of large groups of people in a more direct, though less acknowledged way than a military officer or a pastor. This places on him a significant portion of the responsibility for the quality of life[Pg 141] that they experience. It is his duty not only to continually consider how to offer his products in the purest and most affordable forms but also to ensure that the various jobs involved in production or distribution are as beneficial as possible for the workers.

And as into these two functions, requiring for their right exercise the highest intelligence, as well as patience, kindness, and tact, the merchant is bound to put all his energy, so for their just discharge he is bound, as soldier or physician is bound, to give up, if need be, his life, in such way as it may be demanded of him. Two main points he has in his providing function to maintain: first, his engagements (faithfulness to engagements being the real root of all possibilities in commerce); and, secondly, the perfectness and purity of the thing provided; so that, rather than fail in any engagement, or consent to any deterioration, adulteration, or unjust and exorbitant price of that which he provides, he is bound to meet fearlessly any form of distress, poverty, or labour, which may, through maintenance of these points, come upon him.

And just like in these two roles that require the highest level of intelligence, as well as patience, kindness, and tact, the merchant has to invest all his energy. To fulfill these responsibilities properly, he must be willing to sacrifice, if necessary, his life, just like a soldier or a doctor would. He has two main points to uphold in his role as a provider: first, his commitments (being faithful to commitments is the real foundation of all possibilities in business); and second, the quality and integrity of the goods he provides. He should be ready to face any form of hardship, poverty, or hard work that may arise from upholding these principles, rather than fail to meet a commitment or accept any decline in quality, adulteration, or unfairly high prices for what he provides.

Again: in his office as governor of the men employed by him, the merchant or manufacturer is invested with a distinctly paternal authority and responsibility. In most cases, a youth entering a commercial establishment is withdrawn altogether from home influence; his master must become his father, else he has, for practical and constant help, no father at hand: in all cases the master's authority, together with the general tone and atmosphere of his business, and the character of the men with whom the youth is compelled in the course of it to associate, have more immediate and pressing weight than the home influence, and will usually neutralize it either for good or evil; so that the only means which the master has of doing justice to the men employed by him is to ask himself sternly whether he is dealing with such subordinate as he would with his own son, if compelled by circumstances to take such a position.

Once again: in his role as governor of the men working for him, the merchant or manufacturer holds a clearly paternal authority and responsibility. Most often, a young person starting out in a business is completely removed from home influence; his boss has to step in as a father figure, otherwise, he lacks any practical and consistent support from a father. The authority of the boss, along with the overall tone and environment of his business, and the character of the men the youth must interact with, have more immediate and significant impact than the home influence, often overshadowing it either positively or negatively. Therefore, the only way for the boss to treat his employees fairly is to seriously consider whether he would treat them as he would his own son if he had to take on such a role.

Supposing the captain of a frigate saw it right, or were by any chance obliged, to place his own son in the position of a common sailor; as he would then treat his son, he is bound always to treat every one of the men under him. So, also;[Pg 142] supposing the master of a manufactory saw it right, or were by any chance obliged, to place his own son in the position of an ordinary workman; as he would then treat his son, he is bound always to treat every one of his men. This is the only effective true, or practical Rule which can be given on this point of political economy.

Suppose the captain of a frigate saw it as right, or was somehow required, to put his own son in the role of a common sailor; he would have to treat his son the same way he is required to treat every one of the men under him. Similarly, [Pg 142] if the master of a factory saw it as right, or was by any chance obligated, to assign his own son to the position of a regular worker; he must treat his son the same way he ought to treat all of his workers. This is the only truly effective and practical Rule that can be offered on this matter of political economy.

And as the captain of a ship is bound to be the last man to leave his ship in case of wreck, and to share his last crust with the sailors in case of famine, so the manufacturer, in any commercial crisis or distress, is bound to take the suffering of it with his men, and even to take more of it for himself than he allows his men to feel; as a father would in a famine, shipwreck, or battle, sacrifice himself for his son.

And just like a ship captain must be the last one to leave if the ship sinks and share his last piece of food with the crew during a famine, a manufacturer, during any business crisis or tough times, is expected to endure the hardship alongside his workers and even take on more of the burden than he lets his employees experience; just like a father would sacrifice himself for his son in times of famine, shipwreck, or battle.

All which sounds very strange: the only real strangeness in the matter being, nevertheless, that it should so sound. For all this is true, and that not partially nor theoretically, but everlastingly and practically: all other doctrine than this respecting matters political being false in premises, absurd in deduction, and impossible in practice, consistently with any progressive state of national life; all the life which we now possess as a nation showing itself in the resolute denial and scorn, by a few strong minds and faithful hearts, of the economic principles taught to our multitudes, which principles, so far as accepted, lead straight to national destruction. Respecting the modes and forms of destruction to which they lead, and, on the other hand, respecting the farther practical working of true polity, I hope to reason further in a following paper.

All of this sounds very strange: the only real oddity is that it sounds that way at all. Because everything here is true, and not just partially or theoretically, but in a lasting and practical sense. Any other beliefs about politics are false in their assumptions, irrational in their conclusions, and unworkable in practice, especially in any advancing stage of national life. The life we currently have as a nation is clearly demonstrated in the strong denial and disdain by a few insightful individuals and dedicated advocates toward the economic principles that have been taught to the masses. Those principles, if accepted, lead directly to national ruin. Regarding the ways and forms of this destruction, as well as the further practical implementations of true governance, I plan to discuss more in a future paper.

FOOTNOTES:

[31] The difference between the two modes of treatment, and between their effective material results, may be seen very accurately by a comparison of the relations of Esther and Charlie in Bleak House, with those of Miss Brass and the Marchioness in Master Humphrey's Clock.

[31] You can clearly see the difference between the two treatment methods and their actual outcomes by comparing the relationships of Esther and Charlie in Bleak House with those of Miss Brass and the Marchioness in Master Humphrey's Clock.

The essential value and truth of Dickens's writings have been unwisely lost sight of by many thoughtful persons, merely because he presents his truth with some colour of caricature. Unwisely, because Dickens's caricature, though often gross, is never mistaken. Allowing for his manner of telling them, the things he tells us are always true. I wish that he could think it right to limit his brilliant exaggeration to works written only for public amusement; and when he takes up a subject of high national importance, such as that which he handled in Hard Times, that he would use severer and more accurate analysis. The usefulness of that work (to my mind, in several respects, the greatest he has written) is with many persons seriously diminished because Mr. Bounderby is a dramatic monster, instead of a characteristic example of a worldly master; and Stephen Blackpool a dramatic perfection, instead of a characteristic example of an honest workman. But let us not lose the use of Dickens's wit and insight, because he chooses to speak in a circle of stage fire. He is entirely right in his main drift and purpose in every book he has written; and all of them, but especially Hard Times, should be studied with close and earnest care by persons interested in social questions. They will find much that is partial, and, because partial, apparently unjust; but if they examine all the evidence on the other side, which Dickens seems to overlook, it will appear, after all their trouble, that his view was the finally right one, grossly and sharply told.

The essential value and truth in Dickens's writings have been overlooked by many thoughtful people, just because he presents his truth with some exaggeration. This is unfortunate because Dickens's caricature, while often extreme, is never mistaken. Setting aside his storytelling style, the things he shares are always true. I wish he would limit his brilliant exaggeration to works meant only for public entertainment; when he addresses an important national issue, like the one in Hard Times, he should use a more serious and precise analysis. The usefulness of that work (which I believe is one of the greatest he has written) is seriously reduced for many people because Mr. Bounderby is an exaggerated villain, rather than a typical example of a worldly boss; and Stephen Blackpool is an exaggerated ideal, rather than a typical honest worker. But let's not overlook Dickens's wit and insight just because he chooses to communicate in a theatrical way. He is completely right in his main message and purpose in every book he's written; all of them, especially Hard Times, should be studied carefully and earnestly by those interested in social issues. They will find things that seem one-sided, and therefore apparently unjust; but if they examine all the evidence on the other side, which Dickens seems to miss, they will find that his view was ultimately the correct one, presented in a rough and sharp manner.


ESSAY II.

THE VEINS OF WEALTH.

The answer which would be made by any ordinary political economist to the statements contained in the preceding paper, is in few words as follows:—

The response that any typical political economist would give to the statements in the previous paper can be summarized in just a few words:—

"It is indeed true that certain advantages of a general nature may be obtained by the development of social affections. But political economists never professed, nor profess, to take advantages of a general nature into consideration. Our science is simply the science of getting rich. So far from being a fallacious or visionary one, it is found by experience to be practically effective. Persons who follow its precepts do actually become rich, and persons who disobey them become poor. Every capitalist of Europe has acquired his fortune by following the known laws of our science, and increases his capital daily by an adherence to them. It is vain to bring forward tricks of logic, against the force of accomplished facts. Every man of business knows by experience how money is made, and how it is lost."

"It’s definitely true that developing social connections can lead to some general benefits. But political economists have never claimed, nor do they claim now, to focus on general benefits. Our field is simply about making money. Far from being a misguided or unrealistic pursuit, it’s shown to be effective in practice. People who follow its principles really do get wealthy, while those who ignore them end up poor. Every capitalist in Europe has built their wealth by adhering to our established rules, and they continue to grow their capital each day by sticking to them. It’s pointless to argue with logical tricks when faced with the reality of proven outcomes. Every businessperson knows from experience how money is earned and lost."

Pardon me. Men of business do indeed know how they themselves made their money, or how, on occasion, they lost it. Playing a long-practised game, they are familiar with the chances of its cards, and can rightly explain their losses and gains. But they neither know who keeps the bank of the gambling-house, nor what other games may be played with the same cards, nor what other losses and gains, far away among the dark streets, are essentially, though invisibly, dependent on theirs in the lighted rooms. They have learned a few, and only a few, of the laws of mercantile economy; but not one of those of political economy.[Pg 144]

Excuse me. Businesspeople really do understand how they made their money, or sometimes how they lost it. They’ve been playing this long-standing game and know the odds of their cards, so they can explain their wins and losses fairly accurately. However, they don’t know who runs the gambling house, what other games might be played with the same cards, or what other losses and gains, far out in the dark streets, are fundamentally, though unseen, tied to theirs in the bright rooms. They’ve grasped a few of the principles of mercantile economy, but not a single one of political economy.[Pg 144]

Primarily, which is very notable and curious, I observe that men of business rarely know the meaning of the word "rich." At least if they know, they do not in their reasonings allow for the fact that it is a relative word, implying its opposite "poor" as positively as the word "north" implies its opposite "south." Men nearly always speak and write as if riches were absolute, and it were possible, by following certain scientific precepts, for everybody to be rich. Whereas riches are a power like that of electricity, acting only through inequalities or negations of itself. The force of the guinea you have in your pocket depends wholly on the default of a guinea in your neighbour's pocket. If he did not want it, it would be of no use to you; the degree of power it possesses depends accurately upon the need or desire he has for it,—and the art of making yourself rich, in the ordinary mercantile economist's sense, is therefore equally and necessarily the art of keeping your neighbour poor.

Primarily, what stands out and is quite interesting is that business people rarely grasp the meaning of the word "rich." Even if they understand it, they don't seem to consider that it's a relative term, which implies its opposite "poor" as directly as "north" implies "south." People almost always speak and write as if wealth were absolute, and that, by following certain scientific principles, everyone could be wealthy. However, wealth is a force like electricity, only functioning through inequalities or its lack. The value of the guinea you have in your pocket entirely relies on the absence of a guinea in your neighbor's pocket. If they didn't want it, it would be useless to you; its power relies on their need or desire for it. So, the skill of making yourself wealthy, in the conventional economist's view, is essentially and necessarily the skill of keeping your neighbor poor.

I would not contend in this matter (and rarely in any matter), for the acceptance of terms. But I wish the reader clearly and deeply to understand the difference between the two economies, to which the terms "Political" and "Mercantile" might not unadvisably be attached.

I wouldn't argue about this (and hardly ever about anything), for the acceptance of terms. But I want the reader to clearly and deeply understand the difference between the two economies, which could rightly be called "Political" and "Mercantile."

Political economy (the economy of a State, or of citizens) consists simply in the production, preservation, and distribution, at fittest time and place, of useful or pleasurable things. The farmer who cuts his hay at the right time; the shipwright who drives his bolts well home in sound wood; the builder who lays good bricks in well-tempered mortar; the housewife who takes care of her furniture in the parlour, and guards against all waste in her kitchen; and the singer who rightly disciplines, and never overstrains her voice: are all political economists in the true and final sense; adding continually to the riches and well-being of the nation to which they belong.

Political economy (the economy of a State, or of citizens) is simply about the production, preservation, and distribution of useful or enjoyable things at the right time and place. The farmer who cuts his hay at the perfect moment; the shipbuilder who secures his bolts properly in solid wood; the contractor who lays quality bricks in well-mixed mortar; the homemaker who maintains her furniture in the living room and prevents waste in her kitchen; and the singer who carefully trains her voice without straining it: are all political economists in the truest sense, continually contributing to the wealth and well-being of their nation.

But mercantile economy, the economy of "merces" or of "pay," signifies the accumulation, in the hands of individuals, of legal, or moral claim upon, or power over, the labour of others; every such claim implying precisely as much poverty or debt on one side, as it implies riches or right on the other.

But a mercantile economy, which is the economy of "merces" or "pay," means the accumulation, in the hands of individuals, of a legal or moral claim to, or control over, the labor of others; each such claim implying just as much poverty or debt on one side as it implies wealth or entitlement on the other.

It does not, therefore, necessarily involve an addition to[Pg 145] the actual property, or well-being, of the State in which it exists. But since this commercial wealth, or power over labour, is nearly always convertible at once into real property, while real property is not always convertible at once into power over labour, the idea of riches among active men in civilized nations, generally refers to commercial wealth; and in estimating their possessions, they rather calculate the value of their horses and fields by the number of guineas they could get for them, than the value of their guineas by the number of horses and fields they could buy with them.

It doesn't necessarily add to[Pg 145] the actual resources or well-being of the State it belongs to. However, since this commercial wealth, or control over labor, can usually be quickly turned into real property, while real property doesn’t always convert back into control over labor right away, when people think of wealth in active, civilized societies, they typically mean commercial wealth. In evaluating their assets, they tend to assess the worth of their horses and land based on the number of guineas they could sell them for, rather than the worth of their guineas in terms of the horses and land they could purchase with them.

There is, however, another reason for this habit of mind; namely, that an accumulation of real property is of little use to its owner, unless, together with it, he has commercial power over labour. Thus, suppose any person to be put in possession of a large estate of fruitful land, with rich beds of gold in its gravel, countless herds of cattle in its pastures; houses, and gardens, and storehouses full of useful stores; but suppose, after all, that he could get no servants? In order that he may be able to have servants, some one in his neighbourhood must be poor, and in want of his gold—or his corn. Assume that no one is in want of either, and that no servants are to be had. He must, therefore, bake his own bread, make his own clothes, plough his own ground, and shepherd his own flocks. His gold will be as useful to him as any other yellow pebbles on his estate. His stores must rot, for he cannot consume them. He can eat no more than another man could eat, and wear no more than another man could wear. He must lead a life of severe and common labour to procure even ordinary comforts; he will be ultimately unable to keep either houses in repair, or fields in cultivation; and forced to content himself with a poor man's portion of cottage and garden, in the midst of a desert of waste land, trampled by wild cattle, and encumbered by ruins of palaces, which he will hardly mock at himself by calling "his own."

There is, however, another reason for this way of thinking; that is, having a lot of property is of little use to its owner unless he also has the ability to hire help. So, imagine someone who inherits a large estate with fertile land, rich deposits of gold, countless herds of cattle, houses, gardens, and storage filled with useful supplies; but suppose he can’t find any servants? To have help, someone in his area must be poor and in need of his gold or grain. If no one needs either, and no servants are available, he will have to bake his own bread, make his own clothes, plow his own fields, and tend to his own flocks. His gold will be as useful to him as any other yellow stones on his property. His supplies will rot because he cannot use them. He can eat no more than anyone else could eat, and wear no more than anyone else could wear. He will have to live a life of hard, everyday work just to achieve basic comforts; eventually, he won’t be able to keep either his houses repaired or his fields cultivated, and he will have to settle for a poor man's share of a cottage and garden amid a wasteland, overrun by wild cattle, and cluttered with the ruins of palaces that he would hardly dare to call “his own.”

The most covetous of mankind would, with small exultation, I presume, accept riches of this kind on these terms. What is really desired, under the name of riches, is, essentially, power over men; in its simplest sense, the power of obtaining for our own advantage the labour of servant, tradesman, and[Pg 146] artist; in wider sense, authority of directing large masses of the nation to various ends (good, trivial, or hurtful, according to the mind of the rich person). And this power of wealth of course is greater or less in direct proportion to the poverty of the men over whom it is exercised, and in inverse proportion to the number of persons who are as rich as ourselves, and who are ready to give the same price for an article of which the supply is limited. If the musician is poor, he will sing for small pay, as long as there is only one person who can pay him; but if there be two or three, he will sing for the one who offers him most. And thus the power of the riches of the patron (always imperfect and doubtful, as we shall see presently, even when most authoritative) depends first on the poverty of the artist, and then on the limitation of the number of equally wealthy persons, who also wants seats at the concert. So that, as above stated, the art of becoming "rich," in the common sense, is not absolutely nor finally the art of accumulating much money for ourselves, but also of contriving that our neighbours shall have less. In accurate terms, it is "the art of establishing the maximum inequality in our own favour."

The most greedy people would, with a little bit of pleasure, I think, accept wealth like this under these conditions. What we really want, when we talk about wealth, is basically power over others; in the simplest terms, it's the ability to benefit from the labor of servants, tradespeople, and[Pg 146] artists. In a broader sense, it’s the authority to direct large groups of people in the nation toward various goals (whether good, trivial, or harmful, depending on the wealthy person's mindset). This power that comes from wealth is naturally greater or lesser based on how poor the people we control are and in the opposite proportion to how many others are as rich as we are, who are willing to pay the same price for something in limited supply. If a musician is poor, they will perform for a small fee as long as there’s only one person who can pay them; but if there are two or three, they’ll sing for the one who offers the most. Therefore, the power of the wealth of the patron (which is always flawed and uncertain, as we will see soon, even when it seems most authoritative) relies first on the artist's poverty, and then on the few wealthy individuals who also want tickets to the concert. So, as mentioned earlier, the skill of becoming "rich," in the usual sense, isn’t just about accumulating a lot of money for ourselves, but also about ensuring that our neighbors have less. To put it accurately, it’s "the skill of creating the maximum inequality in our own favor."

Now the establishment of such inequality cannot be shown in the abstract to be either advantageous or disadvantageous to the body of the nation. The rash and absurd assumption that such inequalities are necessarily advantageous, lies at the root of most of the popular fallacies on the subject of political economy. For the eternal and inevitable law in this matter is, that the beneficialness of the inequality depends, first, on the methods by which it was accomplished, and, secondly, on the purposes to which it is applied. Inequalities of wealth, unjustly established, have assuredly injured the nation in which they exist during their establishment; and, unjustly directed, injure it yet more during their existence. But inequalities of wealth justly established, benefit the nation in the course of their establishment; and, nobly used, aid it yet more by their existence. That is to say, among every active and well-governed people, the various strength of individuals, tested by full exertion and specially applied to various need, issues in unequal, but harmonious results, receiving[Pg 147] reward or authority according to its class and service;[32] while, in the inactive or ill-governed nation, the gradations of decay and the victories of treason work out also their own rugged system of subjection and success; and substitute, for the melodious inequalities of concurrent power, the iniquitous dominances and depressions of guilt and misfortune.

Now, the establishment of such inequality can't easily be shown to be either beneficial or harmful to the nation as a whole. The reckless and ridiculous belief that these inequalities are always advantageous is at the core of many common misunderstandings about political economy. The fundamental and unavoidable rule here is that the benefits of inequality depend first on how it was created and second on the ways it is used. Unjustly created wealth inequalities have certainly harmed the nation in which they arise during their establishment, and if directed unjustly, they harm it even more while they persist. On the other hand, justly established wealth inequalities benefit the nation during their creation and, if used nobly, help it even more through their existence. In other words, in every active and well-ruled society, the varying strengths of individuals, tested by full effort and specifically applied to different needs, result in unequal but harmonious outcomes, receiving rewards or authority according to their class and service; while in an inactive or poorly governed nation, the levels of decay and the victories of betrayal create their own harsh system of subjugation and success, replacing the harmonious inequalities of shared power with the unjust dominance and oppression of guilt and misfortune.

Thus the circulation of wealth in a nation resembles that of the blood in the natural body. There is one quickness of the current which comes of cheerful emotion or wholesome exercise; and another which comes of shame or of fever. There is a flush of the body which is full of warmth and life; and another which will pass into putrefaction.

Thus the flow of wealth in a nation is like the flow of blood in a living body. There’s a vibrant current that comes from positive emotions or healthy activity, and another that results from shame or illness. There’s a flush in the body that's filled with warmth and vitality, and another that can decay into rot.

The analogy will hold, down even to minute particulars. For as diseased local determination of the blood involves depression of the general health of the system, all morbid local action of riches will be found ultimately to involve a weakening of the resources of the body politic.

The analogy still applies, even in small details. Just as a local blood condition can lower the overall health of the body, any harmful local effects of wealth will eventually weaken the resources of the political system.

[Pg 148]The mode in which this is produced may be at once understood by examining one or two instances of the development of wealth in the simplest possible circumstances.

[Pg 148]You can grasp how this happens by looking at one or two examples of how wealth grows in the most basic situations.

Suppose two sailors cast away on an uninhabited coast, and obliged to maintain themselves there by their own labour for a series of years.

Suppose two sailors are stranded on a deserted coast and have to survive there through their own hard work for several years.

If they both kept their health, and worked steadily, and in amity with each other, they might build themselves a convenient house, and in time come to possess a certain quantity of cultivated land, together with various stores laid up for future use. All these things would be real riches or property; and, supposing the men both to have worked equally hard, they would each have right to equal share or use of it. Their political economy would consist merely in careful preservation and just division of these possessions. Perhaps, however, after some time one or other might be dissatisfied with the results of their common farming; and they might in consequence agree to divide the land they had brought under the spade into equal shares, so that each might thenceforward work in his own field and live by it. Suppose that after this arrangement had been made, one of them were to fall ill, and be unable to work on his land at a critical time—say of sowing or harvest.

If they both stayed healthy, worked consistently, and got along with each other, they could build themselves a nice house and eventually own a good amount of cultivated land, along with various supplies saved for the future. All these things would be real wealth or property; and, assuming both men worked equally hard, they would each have the right to an equal share or use of it. Their economy would just be about taking care of and sharing these possessions fairly. However, after a while, one of them might become unhappy with how their joint farming was going; and as a result, they might decide to split the land they had cultivated into equal parts so that each could work on his own field and make a living from it. Now, imagine that after this arrangement, one of them got sick and couldn't work on his land during a critical time—like sowing or harvest.

He would naturally ask the other to sow or reap for him.

He would naturally ask the other person to plant or harvest for him.

Then his companion might say, with perfect justice, "I will do this additional work for you; but if I do it, you must promise to do as much for me at another time. I will count how many hours I spend on your ground, and you shall give me a written promise to work for the same number of hours on mine, whenever I need your help, and you are able to give it."

Then his friend might say, fairly enough, "I’ll do this extra work for you; but if I do, you have to promise to return the favor another time. I’ll keep track of how many hours I spend working on your property, and you need to give me a written guarantee that you’ll work for the same number of hours on mine whenever I need your help and you can provide it."

Suppose the disabled man's sickness to continue, and that under various circumstances, for several years, requiring the help of the other, he on each occasion gave a written pledge to work, as soon as he was able, at his companion's orders, for the same number of hours which the other had given up to him.[Pg 149] What will the positions of the two men be when the invalid is able to resume work?

Suppose the disabled man's illness goes on, and that for several years, under different circumstances, he needs assistance from the other person. Each time, he writes an agreement to work, as soon as he can, at his companion's direction, for the same number of hours that his companion had given up for him.[Pg 149] What will the situations of the two men be when the invalid can go back to work?

Considered as a "Polis," or state, they will be poorer than they would have been otherwise: poorer by the withdrawal of what the sick man's labour would have produced in the interval. His friend may perhaps have toiled with an energy quickened by the enlarged need, but in the end his own land and property must have suffered by the withdrawal of so much of his time and thought from them; and the united property of the two men will be certainly less than it would have been if both had remained in health and activity.

Considered as a "Polis," or state, they will be worse off than they would have been otherwise: worse off due to the loss of what the sick man’s work could have generated during that time. His friend might have worked harder out of a greater necessity, but ultimately, his own land and possessions would have taken a hit because of how much time and attention he had to pull away from them; and the combined assets of the two men will definitely be less than if both had stayed healthy and engaged.

But the relations in which they stand to each other are also widely altered. The sick man has not only pledged his labour for some years, but will probably have exhausted his own share of the accumulated stores, and will be in consequence for some time dependent on the other for food, which he can only "pay" or reward him for by yet more deeply pledging his own labour.

But the relationships between them have also changed a lot. The sick man has not only promised his work for a few years, but he will likely have used up his own share of the saved resources, and as a result, he will be dependent on the other person for food for a while, which he can only "pay" or repay him for by further committing his own labor.

Supposing the written promises to be held entirely valid (among civilized nations their validity is secured by legal measures[33]), the person who had hitherto worked for both might now, if he chose, rest altogether, and pass his time in idleness, not only forcing his companion to redeem all the engagements he had already entered into, but exacting from him pledges for further labour, to an arbitrary amount, for what food he had to advance to him.

Assuming the written promises are completely valid (and their validity is guaranteed by legal measures among civilized nations[33]), the person who had previously worked for both could now choose to do nothing and spend his time being idle. He could not only compel his partner to fulfill all the commitments he had already made, but also demand additional guarantees for further work, based on whatever amount of food he had to provide him.

[Pg 150]There might not, from first to last, be the least illegality (in the ordinary sense of the word) in the arrangement; but if a stranger arrived on the coast at this advanced epoch of their political economy, he would find one man commercially Rich; the other commercially Poor. He would see, perhaps with no small surprise, one passing his days in idleness; the other labouring for both, and living sparely, in the hope of recovering his independence, at some distant period.

[Pg 150]There might not be any illegality (in the usual sense) in the arrangement from beginning to end; but if a stranger arrived on the coast at this later stage of their political economy, he would see one man financially wealthy and the other financially struggling. He would likely be surprised to see one person spending his days doing nothing, while the other works hard for both and lives modestly, hoping to regain his independence at some point in the future.

This is, of course, an example of one only out of many ways in which inequality of possession may be established between different persons, giving rise to the Mercantile forms of Riches and Poverty. In the instance before us, one of the men might from the first have deliberately chosen to be idle, and to put his life in pawn for present ease; or he might have mismanaged his land, and been compelled to have recourse to his neighbour for food and help, pledging his future labour for it. But what I want the reader to note especially is the fact, common to a large number of typical cases of this kind, that the establishment of the mercantile wealth which consists in a claim upon labour, signifies a political diminution of the real wealth which consists in substantial possessions.

This is just one example of the many ways that inequality in possessions can arise between different people, leading to the commercial forms of wealth and poverty. In this case, one man might have deliberately chosen to be lazy and sacrificed his future for immediate comfort; or he could have poorly managed his land and ended up relying on his neighbor for food and support, promising to work in exchange. However, what I want the reader to pay special attention to is the fact that is common in many typical situations like this: the creation of commercial wealth, which relies on claims to labor, represents a political reduction in the actual wealth that comes from tangible possessions.

Take another example, more consistent with the ordinary course of affairs of trade. Suppose that three men, instead of two, formed the little isolated republic, and found themselves obliged to separate in order to farm different pieces of land at some distance from each other along the coast; each estate furnishing a distinct kind of produce, and each more or less in need of the material raised on the other. Suppose that the third man, in order to save the time of all three, undertakes simply to superintend the transference of commodities from one farm to the other; on condition of receiving some sufficiently remunerative share of every parcel of goods conveyed, or of some other parcel received in exchange for it.

Take another example, one that aligns more closely with how business usually works. Imagine that instead of two, three men formed a small, isolated community and had to split up to farm different plots of land situated some distance apart along the coast; each farm producing a unique type of crop and each being somewhat dependent on the goods produced by the others. Now, let’s say the third man takes it upon himself to oversee the transfer of goods between the farms to save time for all three of them, with the understanding that he receives a fair share from every shipment of goods he manages or from another shipment he gets in return.

If this carrier or messenger always brings to each estate, from the other, what is chiefly wanted, at the right time, the operations of the two farmers will go on prosperously, and the largest possible result in produce, or wealth, will be attained by the little community. But suppose no intercourse between the landowners is possible, except through the travelling agent; and that, after a time, this agent, watching the course of each[Pg 151] man's agriculture, keeps back the articles with which he has been entrusted until there comes a period of extreme necessity for them, on one side or other, and then exacts in exchange for them all that the distressed farmer can spare of other kinds of produce; it is easy to see that by ingeniously watching his opportunities, he might possess himself regularly of the greater part of the superfluous produce of the two estates, and at last, in some year of severest trial or scarcity, purchase both for himself, and maintain the former proprietors thenceforward as his labourers or servants.

If this carrier or messenger always delivers what each farmer needs from the other at the right time, both farmers will thrive, and the little community will achieve the best possible harvest or wealth. But imagine that the landowners can only communicate through this traveling agent, and after a while, this agent, observing each farmer's agricultural practices, holds back the items he was supposed to deliver until a time of extreme need arises on either side. Then, he demands all that the desperate farmer can spare in exchange for those items. It’s easy to see how, by cleverly seizing his chances, he could end up regularly taking the majority of the extra produce from both farms and, in a year of great hardship or scarcity, end up acquiring both properties for himself, forcing the original owners to become his laborers or servants from then on.

This would be a case of commercial wealth acquired on the exactest principles of modern political economy. But more distinctly even than in the former instance, it is manifest in this that the wealth of the State, or of the three men considered as a society, is collectively less than it would have been had the merchant been content with juster profit. The operations of the two agriculturists have been cramped to the utmost; and the continual limitations of the supply of things they wanted at critical times, together with the failure of courage consequent on the prolongation of a struggle for mere existence, without any sense of permanent gain, must have seriously diminished the effective results of their labour; and the stores finally accumulated in the merchant's hands will not in anywise be of equivalent value to those which, had his dealings been honest, would have filled at once the granaries of the farmers and his own.

This would be an example of commercial wealth obtained through the strictest principles of modern economics. However, even more clearly than in the previous case, it shows that the wealth of the State, or of the three men viewed as a society, is collectively less than it could have been if the merchant had settled for fairer profits. The activities of the two farmers have been severely limited; the ongoing restrictions on the supply of the things they needed at crucial times, combined with the diminishing courage resulting from a prolonged struggle for mere survival without any prospect of lasting gain, must have significantly reduced the effectiveness of their labor. The goods ultimately gathered in the merchant's possession will not be remotely equivalent in value to those that, had his dealings been fair, would have filled both the farmers' granaries and his own.

The whole question, therefore, respecting not only the advantage, but even the quantity, of national wealth, resolves itself finally into one of abstract justice. It is impossible to conclude, of any given mass of acquired wealth, merely by the fact of its existence, whether it signifies good or evil to the nation in the midst of which it exists. Its real value depends on the moral sign attached to it, just as sternly as that of a mathematical quantity depends on the algebraical sign attached to it. Any given accumulation of commercial wealth may be indicative, on the one hand, of faithful industries, progressive energies, and productive ingenuities; or, on the other, it may be indicative of mortal luxury, merciless tyranny, ruinous chicane. Some treasures are heavy with human[Pg 152] tears, as an ill-stored harvest with untimely rain; and some gold is brighter in sunshine than it is in substance.

The whole question about not just the benefit but also the amount of national wealth ultimately comes down to issues of fairness. You can't determine whether a certain amount of wealth is good or bad for a nation just by its existence. Its true worth relies on the moral implications attached to it, just like a mathematical value depends on its sign. A specific accumulation of wealth could represent, on one hand, hardworking industries, innovative progress, and productive creativity; or, on the other, it could signify excessive luxury, ruthless oppression, and destructive dishonesty. Some riches carry the weight of human[Pg 152] tears, much like a poorly harvested crop suffers from unexpected rain; and some gold shines brighter in daylight than it does in reality.

And these are not, observe, merely moral or pathetic attributes of riches, which the seeker of riches may, if he chooses, despise; they are, literally and sternly, material attributes of riches, depreciating or exalting, incalculably, the monetary signification of the sum in question. One mass of money is the outcome of action which has created,—another, of action which has annihilated,—ten times as much in the gathering of it; such and such strong hands have been paralysed, as if they had been numbed by nightshade: so many strong men's courage broken, so many productive operations hindered; this and the other false direction given to labour, and lying image of prosperity set up, on Dura plains dug into seven-times-heated furnaces. That which seems to be wealth may in verity be only the gilded index of far-reaching ruin; a wrecker's handful of coin gleaned from the beach to which he has beguiled an argosy; a camp-follower's bundle of rags unwrapped from the breasts of goodly soldiers dead; the purchase-pieces of potter's fields, wherein shall be buried together the citizen and the stranger.

And these are not just moral or sad characteristics of wealth that someone chasing after riches might choose to ignore; they are, in a very real and serious way, material characteristics of wealth that drastically change the monetary value of the amount in question. One pile of money comes from actions that have created wealth—another comes from actions that have destroyed ten times that amount in the process of accumulating it. Some strong hands have been rendered powerless, as if numbed by poison; the courage of many strong men has been broken, and many productive efforts have been blocked. This has led to misguided labor and a false image of prosperity, built on land dug into intensely heated furnaces. What appears to be wealth may actually just be a shiny sign of widespread destruction; a salvager's handful of coins picked up from the shore where he lured a ship to its doom; a camp-follower's collection of rags taken from the chests of brave soldiers who have died; the burial plots of potter's fields where both the citizen and the outsider will rest together.

And therefore, the idea that directions can be given for the gaining of wealth, irrespectively of the consideration of its moral sources, or that any general and technical law of purchase and gain can be set down for national practice, is perhaps the most insolently futile of all that ever beguiled men through their vices. So far as I know, there is not in history record of anything so disgraceful to the human intellect as the modern idea that the commercial text, "Buy in the cheapest market and sell in the dearest," represents, or under any circumstances could represent, an available principle of national economy. Buy in the cheapest market?—yes; but what made your market cheap? Charcoal may be cheap among your roof timbers after a fire, and bricks may be cheap in your streets after an earthquake; but fire and earthquake may not therefore be national benefits. Sell in the dearest?—yes, truly; but what made your market dear? You sold your[Pg 153] bread well to-day; was it to a dying man who gave his last coin for it, and will never need bread more, or to a rich man who to-morrow will buy your farm over your head; or to a soldier on his way to pillage the bank in which you have put your fortune?

And so, the idea that you can get tips on how to make money without thinking about where that wealth comes from, or that there are any universal rules for buying and selling that should be applied nationally, is probably the most ridiculously pointless notion that has ever tricked people into indulging their vices. As far as I know, there's nothing in history more shameful to human thinking than the modern belief that the commercial saying, "Buy in the cheapest market and sell in the dearest," symbolizes, or ever could symbolize, a valid principle of national economics. Buy in the cheapest market?—sure; but what makes your market cheap? Charcoal might be cheap under your roof beams after a fire, and bricks might be cheap in your streets after an earthquake; but fire and earthquakes aren’t exactly advantages for the nation. Sell in the dearest?—absolutely; but what makes your market expensive? You sold your[Pg 153] bread for a good price today; was it to a dying man who spent his last coin on it and will never need bread again, or to a wealthy guy who will buy your farm tomorrow, or to a soldier heading out to rob the bank where you’ve saved your money?

None of these things you can know. One thing only you can know, namely, whether this dealing of yours is a just and faithful one, which is all you need concern yourself about respecting it; sure thus to have done your own part in bringing about ultimately in the world a state of things which will not issue in pillage or in death. And thus every question concerning these things merges itself ultimately in the great question of justice, which, the ground being thus far cleared for it, I will enter upon in the next paper, leaving only, in this, three final points for the reader's consideration.

You can't know any of these things. The only thing you can know is whether your actions are fair and honest, which is all you should focus on; that way, you're doing your part to help create a world that won’t lead to plunder or death. So every question about these issues ultimately relates to the bigger question of justice, which I will address in the next paper. For now, I’ll leave you with three final points to think about.

It has been shown that the chief value and virtue of money consists in its having power over human beings; that, without this power, large material possessions are useless, and, to any person possessing such power, comparatively unnecessary. But power over human beings is attainable by other means than by money. As I said a few pages back, the money power is always imperfect and doubtful; there are many things which cannot be reached with it, others which cannot be retained by it. Many joys may be given to men which cannot be bought for gold, and many fidelities found in them which cannot be rewarded with it.

It has been shown that the main value and advantage of money comes from its ability to influence people. Without this influence, having a lot of material wealth is pointless, and for anyone who has that influence, it’s relatively unnecessary. However, you can gain power over people through means other than money. As I mentioned a few pages ago, the influence that money provides is often limited and uncertain; there are many things it can't achieve, and there are others it can't hold onto. Many joys can be given to people that you can’t buy with gold, and there are many loyalties in people that can’t be rewarded with it.

Trite enough,—the reader thinks. Yes: but it is not so trite,—I wish it were,—that in this moral power, quite inscrutable and immeasurable though it be, there is a monetary value just as real as that represented by more ponderous currencies. A man's hand may be full of invisible gold, and the wave of it, or the grasp, shall do more than another's with a shower of bullion. This invisible gold, also, does not necessarily diminish in spending. Political economists will do well some day to take heed of it, though they cannot take measure.

Trite enough, the reader thinks. Yes, but it’s not as trite as I wish it were—this moral power, though completely mysterious and immeasurable, has a tangible value just as real as that of heavier currencies. A person’s hand can be filled with invisible gold, and the impact of that or the grip will accomplish more than someone else’s with a pile of cash. This invisible gold also doesn’t necessarily decrease with use. Political economists would be wise to pay attention to it someday, even though they can’t quantify it.

But farther. Since the essence of wealth consists in its authority over men, if the apparent or nominal wealth fail in this power, it fails in essence; in fact, ceases to be wealth at all.[Pg 154] It does not appear lately in England, that our authority over men is absolute. The servants show some disposition to rush riotously upstairs, under an impression that their wages are not regularly paid. We should augur ill of any gentleman's property to whom this happened every other day in his drawing-room.

But further. Since the core of wealth lies in its power over people, if the visible or nominal wealth lacks this power, it essentially loses its identity; in fact, it stops being wealth altogether.[Pg 154] Recently in England, it seems that our power over people is not absolute. The servants seem inclined to charge upstairs in a frenzy, believing that their wages aren’t being paid on time. We should be concerned for any gentleman's property if this occurred every other day in his living room.

So also, the power of our wealth seems limited as respects the comfort of the servants, no less than their quietude. The persons in the kitchen appear to be ill-dressed, squalid, half-starved. One cannot help imagining that the riches of the establishment must be of a very theoretical and documentary character.

So too, the power of our wealth seems limited when it comes to the comfort of the staff, just as much as their peace of mind. The people in the kitchen look poorly dressed, dirty, and half-starved. One can't help but think that the riches of this place are more about appearances and paperwork than reality.

Finally. Since the essence of wealth consists in power over men, will it not follow that the nobler and the more in number the persons are over whom it has power, the greater the wealth? Perhaps it may even appear after some consideration, that the persons themselves are the wealth—that these pieces of gold with which we are in the habit of guiding them, are, in fact, nothing more than a kind of Byzantine harness or trappings, very glittering and beautiful in barbaric sight, wherewith we bridle the creatures; but that if these same living creatures could be guided without the fretting and jingling of the byzants in their mouths and ears, they might themselves be more valuable than their bridles. In fact, it may be discovered that the true veins of wealth are purple—and not in Rock, but in Flesh—perhaps even that the final outcome and consummation of all wealth is in the producing as many as possible full-breathed, bright-eyed, and happy-hearted human creatures. Our modern wealth, I think, has rather a tendency the other way;—most political economists appearing to consider multitudes of human creatures not conducive to wealth, or at best conducive to it only by remaining in a dim-eyed and narrow-chested state of being.

Finally. Since the essence of wealth is about power over people, doesn't it follow that the more noble and numerous the individuals under that power, the greater the wealth? It might even seem, upon reflection, that the individuals themselves *are* the wealth—that the gold we use to control them is merely a kind of flashy adornment, very shiny and impressive in a barbaric way, with which we restrain these beings; but if these living beings could be managed without the irritation and clamor of coins in their mouths and ears, they might actually be more valuable than their adornments. In fact, it might be revealed that the true sources of wealth are not found in material things, but in people—perhaps the ultimate goal of all wealth is to create as many fully alive, bright-eyed, and joyful human beings as possible. Our modern notion of wealth, I think, leans in the opposite direction; most economists seem to view large numbers of human beings as a hindrance to wealth, or at best beneficial only if they remain dim-eyed and narrow-chested.

Nevertheless, it is open, I repeat, to serious question, which I leave to the reader's pondering, whether, among national manufactures, that of Souls of a good quality may not at last turn out a quite leadingly lucrative one? Nay, in some faraway and yet undreamt-of hour, I can even imagine that England may cast all thoughts of possessive wealth back to[Pg 155] the barbaric nations among whom they first arose; and that, while the sands of the Indus and adamant of Golconda may yet stiffen the housings of the charger, and flash from the turban of the slave, she, as a Christian mother, may at last attain to the virtues and the treasures of a Heathen one, and be able to lead forth her Sons, saying—

Nevertheless, it’s worth seriously questioning, and I leave that for the reader to think about, whether, among national industries, producing high-quality Souls might eventually become a major source of profit? In fact, in some distant and yet unimaginable future, I can even see England setting aside all thoughts of wealth and turning back to the barbaric nations where they first emerged; and that, while the sands of the Indus and the diamonds of Golconda might still adorn the gear of the horse and sparkle from the turban of the slave, she, as a Christian mother, might finally embrace the virtues and the treasures of a pagan one, and be able to lead her Sons, saying—

"These are MY gems."

FOOTNOTES:

[32] I have been naturally asked several times, with respect to the sentence in the first of these papers, "the bad workmen unemployed," "But what are you to do with your bad unemployed workmen?" Well, it seems to me the question might have occurred to you before. Your housemaid's place is vacant—you give twenty pounds a year—two girls come for it, one neatly dressed, the other dirtily; one with good recommendations, the other with none. You do not, under these circumstances, usually ask the dirty one if she will come for fifteen pounds, or twelve; and, on her consenting, take her instead of the well-recommended one. Still less do you try to beat both down by making them bid against each other, till you can hire both, one at twelve pounds a year, and the other at eight. You simply take the one fittest for the place, and send away the other, not perhaps concerning yourself quite as much as you should with the question which you now impatiently put to me, "What is to become of her?" For all that I advise you to do, is to deal with workmen as with servants; and verily the question is of weight: "Your bad workman, idler, and rogue—what are you to do with him?"

[32] I've been asked several times about the phrase in the first of these papers, "the bad workmen unemployed," "But what do you do with your bad unemployed workmen?" Well, it seems to me that you should have thought about this before. Your housemaid's position is open—you offer twenty pounds a year—two girls apply for it, one neatly dressed and the other dirty; one has good references, the other has none. In this situation, you wouldn’t usually ask the dirty one if she would accept fifteen pounds or twelve; and if she agrees, you wouldn’t choose her over the one with great references. You certainly wouldn’t try to force both to lower their price by having them compete against each other until you could hire one for twelve pounds a year and the other for eight. You simply choose the one best suited for the job and send the other away, probably not worrying as much as you should about the question you now impatiently ask me: "What will happen to her?" All I advise is to treat workmen like you do servants; and indeed, the question is significant: "What do you do with your bad worker, slacker, and troublemaker?"

We will consider of this presently: remember that the administration of a complete system of national commerce and industry cannot be explained in full detail within the space of twelve pages. Meantime, consider whether, there being confessedly some difficulty in dealing with rogues and idlers, it may not be advisable to produce as few of them as possible. If you examine into the history of rogues, you will find they are as truly manufactured articles as anything else, and it is just because our present system of political economy gives so large a stimulus to that manufacture that you may know it to be a false one. We had better seek for a system which will develop honest men, than for one which will deal cunningly with vagabonds. Let us reform our schools, and we shall find little reform needed in our prisons.

We’ll address this soon: remember that explaining a complete system of national commerce and industry in detail can’t be done in just twelve pages. In the meantime, think about whether, given the undeniable challenge of dealing with con artists and lazy people, it might be best to produce as few of them as possible. If you look into the history of con artists, you’ll see they're as much a product of their environment as anything else, and it’s exactly because our current system of political economy encourages that production that it’s clearly flawed. We’d be better off looking for a system that produces honest individuals rather than one that cleverly manages the dishonest. Let’s improve our schools, and we’ll find that not much needs changing in our prisons.

[33] The disputes which exist respecting the real nature of money arise more from the disputants examining its functions on different sides, than from any real dissent in their opinions. All money, properly so called, is an acknowledgment of debt; but as such, it may either be considered to represent the labour and property of the creditor, or the idleness and penury of the debtor. The intricacy of the question has been much increased by the (hitherto necessary) use of marketable commodities, such as gold, silver, salt, shells, etc., to give intrinsic value or security to currency; but the final and best definition of money is that it is a documentary promise ratified and guaranteed by the nation to give or find a certain quantity of labour on demand. A man's labour for a day is a better standard of value than a measure of any produce, because no produce ever maintains a consistent rate of productibility.

[33] The disagreements about what money really is come more from people looking at its functions from different perspectives rather than any true disagreement in their views. All money, in the truest sense, is a recognition of debt; but as such, it can be seen as reflecting either the labor and assets of the creditor or the neglect and poverty of the debtor. The complexity of the issue has been significantly increased by the (so far necessary) use of marketable goods like gold, silver, salt, shells, etc., to add inherent value or security to currency. However, the clearest and best definition of money is that it is a written promise backed by the government to provide or obtain a specific amount of labor upon request. A person’s labor for a day is a better measure of value than any amount of goods because no goods ever have a consistent rate of productivity.


ESSAY III.

"QUI JUDICATIS TERRAM."

Some centuries before the Christian era, a Jew merchant, largely engaged in business on the Gold Coast, and reported to have made one of the largest fortunes of his time (held also in repute for much practical sagacity), left among his ledgers some general maxims concerning wealth, which have been preserved, strangely enough, even to our own days. They were held in considerable respect by the most active traders of the middle ages, especially by the Venetians, who even went so far in their admiration as to place a statue of the old Jew on the angle of one of their principal public buildings. Of late years these writings have fallen into disrepute, being opposed in every particular to the spirit of modern commerce. Nevertheless, I shall reproduce a passage or two from them here, partly because they may interest the reader by their novelty; and chiefly because they will show him that it is possible for a very practical and acquisitive tradesman to hold, through a not unsuccessful career, that principle of distinction between well-gotten and ill-gotten wealth, which, partially insisted on in my last paper, it must be our work more completely to examine in this.

Some centuries before the Christian era, a Jewish merchant, heavily involved in business on the Gold Coast and known to have made one of the largest fortunes of his time (also respected for his practical wisdom), left behind some general principles about wealth among his ledgers, which have somehow been preserved even to this day. They were held in high regard by the most active traders of the Middle Ages, especially the Venetians, who admired him so much that they placed a statue of the old Jew on the corner of one of their main public buildings. In recent years, these writings have fallen out of favor, as they go against the spirit of modern commerce. However, I will share a passage or two from them here, partly because they may interest the reader with their novelty; and mainly because they will demonstrate that it’s possible for a very pragmatic and profit-driven tradesman to maintain, throughout a successful career, a clear distinction between wealth that is earned through good means and wealth that is not, a principle I briefly touched upon in my last paper and that we will need to explore more thoroughly in this one.

He says, for instance, in one place: "The getting of treasures by a lying tongue is a vanity tossed to and fro of them that seek death:" adding in another, with the same meaning (he has a curious way of doubling his sayings): "Treasures of wickedness profit nothing: but justice delivers from death." Both these passages are notable for their assertion of death as the only real issue and sum of attainment by any unjust scheme of wealth. If we read, instead of "lying tongue,"[Pg 157] "lying label, title, pretence, or advertisement," we shall more clearly perceive the bearing of the words on modern business. The seeking of death is a grand expression of the true course of men's toil in such business. We usually speak as if death pursued us, and we fled from him; but that is only so in rare instances. Ordinarily, he masks himself—makes himself beautiful—all-glorious; not like the King's daughter, all-glorious within, but outwardly: his clothing of wrought gold. We pursue him frantically all our days, he flying or hiding from us. Our crowning success at three-score and ten is utterly and perfectly to seize, and hold him in his eternal integrity—-robes, ashes, and sting.

He says, for example, in one part: "Getting treasures through a lying tongue is just a pointless pursuit for those who seek death:" and adds in another with the same idea (he has a unique way of repeating his phrases): "Treasure gained through wickedness doesn’t benefit anyone: but justice saves you from death." Both of these passages are important because they highlight death as the only real outcome of any dishonest scheme for wealth. If we read, instead of "lying tongue,"[Pg 157] "lying label, title, pretense, or advertisement," we’ll better understand how these words relate to modern business. The pursuit of death is a powerful expression of how men toil in such ventures. We usually talk as if death is chasing us and we’re fleeing from him; but that’s only true in rare cases. Most of the time, he hides himself—makes himself attractive—glorious on the outside; not like the King’s daughter, who is glorious within, but outwardly: wearing clothing made of gold. We chase after him desperately throughout our lives, while he eludes or conceals himself from us. Our ultimate success at seventy years is simply to capture and hold him in his eternal reality—his robes, ashes, and sting.

Again: the merchant says, "He that oppresseth the poor to increase his riches, shall surely come to want." And again, more strongly: "Rob not the poor because he is poor; neither oppress the afflicted in the place of business. For God shall spoil the soul of those that spoiled them."

Again: the merchant says, "Anyone who takes advantage of the poor to get richer will definitely end up in need." And again, more firmly: "Don't rob the poor just because they're poor; don't mistreat those who are suffering in the workplace. Because God will ruin the lives of those who have harmed them."

This "robbing the poor because he is poor" is especially the mercantile form of theft, consisting in taking advantage of a man's necessities in order to obtain his labour or property at a reduced price. The ordinary highwayman's opposite form of robbery—of the rich, because he is rich—does not appear to occur so often to the old merchant's mind; probably because, being less profitable and more dangerous than the robbery of the poor, it is rarely practised by persons of discretion.

This "stealing from the poor because they are poor" is especially the business-focused version of theft, where someone takes advantage of a person's needs to get their labor or possessions for less than they're worth. The usual type of robbery—stealing from the rich because they are rich—doesn't seem to come to the old merchant's mind as often; likely because it's less profitable and more dangerous than taking from the poor, so sensible people rarely do it.

But the two most remarkable passages in their deep general significance are the following:—

But the two most notable sections in their overall importance are these:—

"The rich and the poor have met. God is their maker."

"The rich and the poor have come together. God created them both."

"The rich and the poor have met. God is their light."

"The rich and the poor have come together. God is their light."

They "have met:" more literally, have stood in each other's way, (obviaverunt). That is to say, as long as the world lasts, the action and counteraction of wealth and poverty, the meeting, face to face, of rich and poor, is just as appointed and necessary a law of that world as the flow of stream to sea, or the interchange of power among the electric clouds:—"God is their maker." But, also, this action may be either gentle and just, or convulsive and destructive: it may be by rage of devouring flood, or by lapse of serviceable wave;—in blackness of thunderstroke, or continual force of vital fire,[Pg 158] soft, and shapeable into love-syllables from far away. And which of these it shall be depends on both rich and poor knowing that God is their light; that in the mystery of human life, there is no other light than this by which they can see each other's faces, and live;—light, which is called in another of the books among which the merchant's maxims have been preserved, the "sun of justice,"[34] of which it is promised that it shall rise at last with "healing" (health-giving or helping, making whole or setting at one) in its wings. For truly this healing is only possible by means of justice; no love, no faith, no hope will do it; men will be unwisely fond—vainly faithful, unless primarily they are just; and the mistake of the best men through generation after generation, has been that great one of thinking to help the poor by almsgiving, and by preaching of patience or of hope, and by every other means, emollient or consolatory, except the one thing which God orders for them, justice. But this justice, with its accompanying holiness or helpfulness, being even by the best men denied in its trial time, is by the mass of men hated wherever it appears: so that, when the choice was one day fairly put to them, they denied the Helpful One and the Just;[35] and desired a murderer, sedition-raiser, and robber, to be granted to them;—the murderer instead of the Lord of Life, the sedition-raiser instead of the Prince of Peace, and the robber instead of the Just Judge of all the world.

They "have met": more literally, they've crossed paths, (obviaverunt). This means that as long as the world exists, the interaction between wealth and poverty, the face-to-face encounter of rich and poor, is just as essential and inevitable a law of the world as the flow of rivers to the sea or the exchange of power among electric clouds:—"God is their maker." However, this interaction can be either gentle and fair or chaotic and destructive: it could be like a raging flood or a gentle wave;—in the darkness of a thunderstorm or the consistent warmth of vital fire,[Pg 158] soft and able to transform into expressions of love from a distance. Whether it leans one way or the other depends on both the rich and poor understanding that God is their guide; that in the mystery of human existence, there is no other light but this one that allows them to see each other's faces and coexist;—a light that is referred to in another book among those preserving the merchant's principles as the "sun of justice,"[34] promised to rise eventually with "healing" (restorative or supportive, making whole or bringing together) in its wings. Because truly, this healing is only possible through justice; no love, faith, or hope can achieve it; people will foolishly be overly attached—vainly loyal, unless they are primarily just; and the mistake of the best people for generations has been the significant error of trying to help the poor through charity, preaching patience or hope, and using every other softening or comforting means, except the one thing that God orders for them, justice. But this justice, along with its holiness or helpfulness, is often denied in its testing time by even the best individuals and is hated by most people wherever it appears: so that when they were given a fair choice one day, they rejected the Helpful One and the Just;[35] and instead chose a murderer, rebel-rouser, and thief;—the murderer instead of the Lord of Life, the rebel-rouser instead of the Prince of Peace, and the thief instead of the Just Judge of the entire world.

[Pg 159]I have just spoken of the flowing of streams to the sea as a partial image of the action of wealth. In one respect it is not a partial, but a perfect image. The popular economist thinks himself wise in having discovered that wealth, or the forms of property in general, must go where they are required; that where demand is, supply must follow. He farther declares that this course of demand and supply cannot be forbidden by human laws. Precisely in the same sense, and with the same certainty, the waters of the world go where they are required. Where the land falls, the water flows. The course neither of clouds nor rivers can be forbidden by human will. But the disposition and administration of them can be altered by human forethought. Whether the stream shall be a curse or a blessing, depends upon man's labour, and administrating intelligence. For centuries after centuries, great districts of the world, rich in soil, and favoured in climate, have lain desert under the rage of their own rivers; not only desert, but plague-struck. The stream which, rightly directed, would have flowed in soft irrigation from field to field—would have purified the air, given food to man and beast, and carried their burdens for them on its bosom—now overwhelms the plain, and poisons the wind; its breath pestilence, and its work famine. In like manner this wealth "goes where it is required." No human laws can withstand its flow. They can only guide it: but this, the leading trench and limiting mound can do so thoroughly, that it shall become water of life—the riches of the hand of wisdom;[36] or, on the contrary, by leaving it to its own lawless flow, they may make it, what it has been too often, the last and deadliest of national plagues: water of Marah—the water which feeds the roots of all evil.

[Pg 159]I just mentioned how streams flow to the sea as a partial representation of wealth. In one way, it's not a partial but a perfect representation. The everyday economist believes they are clever for realizing that wealth, or property in general, must go where it’s needed; that supply must follow demand. They assert that human laws can’t stop this flow of demand and supply. In exactly the same way, the world’s waters go where required. Where the land slopes down, the water flows. Neither clouds nor rivers can be controlled by human will. But we can change how they are managed and utilized with human foresight. Whether a stream is a blessing or a curse depends on human labor and management. For centuries, vast areas of the world, rich in soil and blessed with a good climate, have remained barren and afflicted by their own rivers; not just barren but plagued. The stream that, if properly directed, could gently irrigate fields—purifying the air, providing food for people and animals, and carrying their burdens—now floods the land and pollutes the atmosphere; its breath brings disease, and its actions cause famine. In a similar way, this wealth "goes where it is required." No human laws can stop its course. They can only direct it: and this guiding channel and controlling dam can do so effectively that it becomes a source of life—the riches created by wisdom; [36] or, if left to flow chaotically, it may turn into what it has often been, the worst of national disasters: water of Marah—the water that nurtures all evil’s roots.

[Pg 160]The necessity of these laws of distribution or restraint is curiously overlooked in the ordinary political economist's definition of his own "science." He calls it, shortly, the "science of getting rich." But there are many sciences, as well as many arts, of getting rich. Poisoning people of large estates was one employed largely in the middle ages; adulteration of food of people of small estates is one employed largely now. The ancient and honourable Highland method of black mail; the more modern and less honourable system of obtaining goods on credit, and the other variously improved methods of appropriation—which, in major and minor scales of industry, down to the most artistic pocket-picking, we owe to recent genius,—all come under the general head of sciences, or arts, of getting rich.

[Pg 160]The need for laws of distribution or restraint is oddly ignored in the typical political economist's definition of their own "science." They often refer to it simply as the "science of getting rich." However, there are many different sciences, as well as many arts, of acquiring wealth. Back in the Middle Ages, one method was to poison wealthy individuals; today, a common approach is the adulteration of food aimed at those with smaller estates. The ancient and respectable Highland practice of blackmail, along with the more modern and less honorable tactic of buying goods on credit, as well as other variously refined methods of appropriation—ranging from significant industrial practices to the most skillful pickpocketing—all fall under the broad category of sciences, or arts, of getting wealthy.

So that it is clear the popular economist, in calling his science the science par excellence of getting rich, must attach some peculiar ideas of limitation to its character. I hope I do not misrepresent him, by assuming that he means his science to be the science of "getting rich by legal or just means." In this definition, is the word "just," or "legal," finally to stand? For it is possible among certain nations, or under certain rulers, or by help of certain advocates, that proceedings may be legal which are by no means just. If, therefore, we leave at last only the word "just" in that place of our definition, the insertion of this solitary and small word will make a notable difference in the grammar of our science. For then it will follow that, in order to grow rich scientifically we must grow rich justly; and, therefore, know what is just; so that our economy will no longer depend merely on prudence, but on jurisprudence—and that of divine, not human law. Which prudence is indeed of no mean order, holding itself, as it were, high in the air of heaven, and gazing for ever on the light of the sun of justice; hence the souls which have excelled in it are represented by Dante as stars forming in heaven for ever the figure of the eye of an eagle: they having been in life the discerners of light from darkness; or to the whole human race, as the light of the body, which is the eye; while those souls which form the wings of the bird (giving power and dominion to justice, "healing in its wings") trace also in light the inscription in heaven: "DILIGITE JUSTITIAM QUI JUDICATIS TERRAM." "Ye who judge the earth, give" (not, observe, merely love, but) "diligent love to justice:" the love which seeks diligently, that is to say, choosingly, and by preference to all things else. Which judging or doing judgment in the earth is, according[Pg 161] to their capacity and position, required not of judges only, nor of rulers only, but of all men:[37] a truth sorrowfully lost sight of even by those who are ready enough to apply to themselves passages in which Christian men are spoken of as called to be "saints" (i.e., to helpful or healing functions); and "chosen to be kings" (i.e., to knowing or directing functions); the true meaning of these titles having been long lost through the pretences of unhelpful and unable persons to saintly and kingly character; also through the once popular idea that both the sanctity and royalty are to consist in wearing long robes and high crowns, instead of in mercy and judgment; whereas all true sanctity is saving power, as all true royalty is ruling power; and injustice is part and parcel of the denial of such power, which "makes men as the creeping things, as the fishes of the sea, that have no ruler over them."[38]

To make it clear, when the popular economist refers to his field as the science of getting rich, he must have some specific limitations in mind. I hope I'm not misrepresenting him by thinking that he means his field is the science of "getting rich through legal or fair means." In this definition, should we ultimately keep the word "just" or "legal"? Because in some countries, or under certain leaders, or with the help of particular advocates, some actions may be legal but not just at all. Thus, if we finally settle on just the word "just" in our definition, adding this small word will significantly change the meaning of our field. It will imply that to get rich scientifically, we must also get rich justly; therefore, we need to understand what is just, meaning our economy will depend not just on being prudent, but on understanding the law—specifically divine law, rather than human law. This kind of prudence, indeed, has great value, as it reaches towards the heavenly light of justice. Those who excel in this are depicted by Dante as stars forever creating the figure of an eagle's eye in heaven, having been able in life to distinguish light from darkness; or as the light of the body, which is the eye to the entire human race. Meanwhile, the souls that form the wings of the bird (which empower and support justice, "healing in its wings") also trace the inscription in the sky: "DILIGITE JUSTITIAM QUI JUDICATIS TERRAM." "You who judge the earth, give" (note, not just love, but "diligent love to justice"): a love that seeks thoroughly, meaning selectively and preferentially above all else. This judging or enacting justice on earth is, according to one's ability and position, required not only of judges and rulers but of all people:[37] a truth sadly forgotten even by those who quickly apply to themselves passages that describe Christian men as called to be "saints" (i.e., to helpful or healing roles); and "chosen to be kings" (i.e., to knowledge or leadership roles); the real meaning of these titles has long been obscured by the pretensions of those who lack both helpfulness and ability in claiming saintly and kingly characteristics; and through the once widespread belief that both sanctity and royalty consist of wearing long robes and high crowns, rather than embodying mercy and justice; whereas all true sanctity is about saving power, and all true royalty is about ruling power; and injustice is inherently part of denying such power, which "makes men like creeping things, like the fish of the sea, that have no ruler over them."[38]

Absolute justice is indeed no more attainable than absolute truth; but the righteous man is distinguished from the unrighteous by his desire and hope of justice, as the true man from the false by his desire and hope of truth. And though absolute justice be unattainable, as much justice as we need for all practical use is attainable by all those who make it their aim.

Absolute justice is just as unreachable as absolute truth; however, the righteous person is set apart from the unrighteous by their desire and hope for justice, just as the honest person is distinguished from the dishonest by their desire and hope for truth. And while absolute justice may be beyond our grasp, the amount of justice necessary for all practical purposes is achievable for anyone who aims for it.

We have to examine, then, in the subject before us, what are the laws of justice respecting payment of labour—no small part, these, of the foundations of all jurisprudence.

We need to look into the laws of justice regarding payment for labor in this subject we're discussing—these are an important part of the foundations of all law.

I reduced, in my last paper, the idea of money payment to its simplest or radical terms. In those terms its nature, and the conditions of justice respecting it, can be best ascertained.

I simplified the concept of money payment in my last paper to its most basic terms. In those terms, we can best understand its nature and the conditions of justice related to it.

[Pg 162]Money payment, as there stated, consists radically in a promise to some person working for us, that for the time and labour he spends in our service to-day we will give or procure equivalent time and labour in his service at any future time when he may demand it.[39]

[Pg 162]Money payment, as mentioned, is essentially a promise to someone working for us that in exchange for the time and effort they spend helping us today, we will provide or arrange equivalent time and effort in their service whenever they request it in the future.[39]

If we promise to give him less labour than he has given us, we under-pay him. If we promise to give him more labour than he has given us, we over-pay him. In practice, according to the laws of demand and supply, when two men are ready to do the work, and only one man wants to have it done, the two men under-bid each other for it; and the one who gets it to do, is under-paid. But when two men want the work done, and there is only one man ready to do it, the two men who want it done over-bid each other, and the workman is over-paid.

If we promise to give him less work than he has given us, we’re under-paying him. If we promise to give him more work than he has done for us, we’re over-paying him. In reality, based on the laws of supply and demand, when two people are willing to do the job but only one person wants to hire someone, the two applicants will bid lower than each other for it, and the one who gets hired ends up being under-paid. However, when there are two people who want the job done and only one person available to do it, the two who want it will bid higher than each other, and the worker gets over-paid.

I will examine these two points of injustice in succession, but first I wish the reader to clearly understand the central principle lying between the two, of right or just payment.

I will look at these two points of injustice one after the other, but first I want the reader to clearly understand the main principle connecting them, which is fair or just payment.

When we ask a service of any man, he may either give it us freely, or demand payment for it. Respecting free gift of service, there is no question at present, that being a matter of affection—not of traffic. But if he demand payment for it, and we wish to treat him with absolute equity, it is evident that this equity can only consist in giving time for time, strength for strength, and skill for skill. If a man works an hour for us, and we only promise to work half an hour for him in return, we obtain an unjust advantage. If, on the contrary, we promise to work an hour and a half for him in return, he has an unjust advantage. The justice consists in absolute exchange; or, if there be any respect to the stations of the parties, it will not be in favour of the employer: there is certainly no equitable reason in a man's being poor, that if he give me a pound of bread to-day, I should return him less than a pound of bread to-morrow; or any equitable reason in a man's being uneducated, that if he uses a certain quantity of skill and knowledge in my service, I should use a less quantity of skill and knowledge in his. Perhaps, ultimately, it may appear desirable, or, to say the least, gracious, that I should give in return somewhat more than I received. But at present, we are concerned on the law of justice only, which is that of perfect and accurate exchange;—one circumstance only interfering with the simplicity of this radical idea of just payment—that inasmuch as labour (rightly directed) is fruitful just as seed is, the fruit (or "interest" as it is called) of the labour first given, or "advanced," ought to be taken into account, and balanced by an additional quantity of labour in the subsequent repayment. Supposing the repayment to take place at the end of a year, or of any other given time, this calculation could be approximately made; but as money (that is to say, cash) payment involves no reference to time (it being optional with the person paid to spend what he receives at once or after any number of years), we can only assume, generally, that some slight advantage must in equity be allowed to the person who advances the labour, so that the typical form of bargain will be: If you give me an hour to-day, I will give you an hour and five minutes on demand. If you give me a pound of bread to-day, I will give you seventeen ounces on demand, and so on. All that is necessary for the reader to note is, that the amount returned is at least in equity not to be less than the amount given.

When we ask anyone for a service, they can either provide it freely or expect payment for it. Regarding the free gift of service, there’s no debate currently, as it’s based on goodwill—not a transaction. However, if they ask for payment and we want to treat them fairly, it’s clear that fairness consists in giving back time for time, effort for effort, and expertise for expertise. If someone works an hour for us and we only offer to work half an hour in return, we gain an unfair advantage. Conversely, if we agree to work an hour and a half in return, they have an unfair advantage. Fairness lies in complete exchange; if there’s consideration of the positions of the parties involved, it won’t favor the employer. There’s certainly no fair reason that if a person is poor, and they give me a pound of bread today, I should return less than a pound of bread tomorrow. Likewise, there’s no fair reason that if someone is less educated—and uses a certain amount of skill and knowledge in my service—I should use less skill and knowledge in theirs. Ultimately, it might seem preferable, or at least polite, for me to give back more than I received. But for now, we are only focused on the principle of justice, which is that of perfect and precise exchange—one factor complicating this straightforward idea of fair payment is that since labor (when properly directed) is productive like seeds, the results (or "interest" as it’s called) of the initial labor should be considered and balanced with an extra amount of labor in the following repayment. Assuming the repayment occurs after a year or another set time, we could roughly calculate this; however, since cash payment doesn’t involve timing (the person receiving it can either spend it right away or after several years), we can only generally assume that a slight benefit should be given to the individual who performed the labor. Thus, the typical arrangement would be: If you give me an hour today, I’ll give you an hour and five minutes when you ask. If you give me a pound of bread today, I’ll give you seventeen ounces when you ask, and so on. All the reader needs to remember is that the amount returned must, at the very least, not be less than the amount given.

[Pg 163]The abstract idea, then, of just or due wages, as respects the labourer, is that they will consist in a sum of money which will at any time procure for him at least as much labour as he has given, rather more than less. And this equity or justice of payment is, observe, wholly independent of any reference to the number of men who are willing to do the work. I want a horseshoe for my horse. Twenty smiths, or twenty thousand smiths, may be ready to forge it; their number does not in one atom's weight affect the question of the equitable payment[Pg 164] of the one who does forge it. It costs him a quarter of an hour of his life, and so much skill and strength of arm to make that horseshoe for me. Then at some future time I am bound in equity to give a quarter of an hour, and some minutes more, of my life (or of some other person's at my disposal), and also as much strength of arm and skill, and a little more, in making or doing what the smith may have need of.

[Pg 163]The basic idea of fair wages for workers is that they should receive enough money to allow them to get at least as much labor as they put in, preferably more. This fairness in payment is completely unaffected by how many people are willing to do the work. I need a horseshoe for my horse. Whether there are twenty blacksmiths or twenty thousand ready to make it, their numbers don’t change what is fair to pay the one who actually makes it. It takes him a quarter of an hour of his life, along with his skill and strength, to create that horseshoe for me. Later on, I have a moral obligation to give back a quarter of an hour, plus a few extra minutes, of my own life (or someone else's time that I can use), along with my own skill and strength, and a bit more, to provide for whatever the blacksmith needs. [Pg 164]

Such being the abstract theory of just remunerative payment, its application is practically modified by the fact that the order for labour, given in payment, is general, while the labour received is special. The current coin or document is practically an order on the nation for so much work of any kind; and this universal applicability to immediate need renders it so much more valuable than special labour can be, that an order for a less quantity of this general toil will always be accepted as a just equivalent for a greater quantity of special toil. Any given craftsman will always be willing to give an hour of his own work in order to receive command over half an hour, or even much less, of national work. This source of uncertainty, together with the difficulty of determining the monetary value of skill,[40] renders the ascertainment (even approximate) of the proper wages of any given labour in terms of currency, matter of considerable complexity. But they do not affect the principle of exchange. The worth of the work may not be easily known; but it has a worth, just as fixed and real as the specific gravity of a substance, though such specific gravity may not be easily ascertainable when the substance is united with many others. Nor is there so much difficulty or chance in determining it as in determining the ordinary maxima and minima of vulgar political economy. There are few bargains in which the buyer can ascertain with anything like precision that the seller would have taken no less;—or the seller acquire more than a comfortable faith that the purchaser would have given no more. This impossibility of precise knowledge prevents neither from striving to attain the desired point of greatest vexation and injury to the other, nor from accepting it for a scientific principle that he is to buy for the least and sell for the most possible, though what the real least or most may be he cannot tell. In like manner, a just person lays it down for a scientific principle that he is to pay a just price, and, without being able precisely to ascertain the limits of such a price, will nevertheless strive to attain the closest possible approximation to them. A practically serviceable approximation he can obtain. It is [Pg 165] easier to determine scientifically what a man ought to have for his work, than what his necessities will compel him to take for it. His necessities can only be ascertained by empirical, but his due by analytical, investigation. In the one case, you try your answer to the sum like a puzzled schoolboy—till you find one that fits; in the other, you bring out your result within certain limits, by process of calculation.

Such is the abstract theory of fair compensation, but its application is practically affected by the fact that the payment for labor is general, while the labor received is specific. The current currency or document is essentially an order to the nation for a certain amount of work of any type; this universal applicability to immediate needs makes it much more valuable than specialized labor. Therefore, an order for a smaller amount of this general work will always be seen as a fair equivalent for a larger amount of specialized work. Any specific craftsman will always prefer to spend an hour of their own work to gain control over half an hour, or even much less, of national work. This uncertainty, along with the challenge of determining the monetary value of skill, makes it quite complicated to figure out (even approximately) the appropriate wages for any given labor in terms of currency. However, this does not change the principle of exchange. The value of work may not be easily determined, but it does have value, as fixed and real as the specific gravity of a substance, even though that specific gravity may not be easily determined when the substance is mixed with others. It is not as difficult or random to determine as figuring out the ordinary highs and lows of basic political economy. There are few deals where the buyer can precisely know that the seller would have accepted no less—or the seller can be more than reasonably sure that the buyer would have offered no more. This inability to know precisely does not stop either party from trying to reach the point of maximum discomfort and loss for the other, nor does it prevent them from accepting as a principle that they should buy at the lowest and sell at the highest price, even though they cannot identify what the true lowest or highest is. Similarly, a fair-minded person operates under the principle that they should pay a fair price, and while they may not be able to exactly pinpoint the limits of such a price, they will nonetheless aim for the closest approximation. A practically useful approximation is obtainable. It is easier to scientifically determine what someone should receive for their work than to figure out what their needs will force them to accept. Their needs can only be assessed empirically, whereas what they are owed can be calculated analytically. In one scenario, you try to solve the equation like a confused schoolboy until you find an answer that works; in the other, you arrive at your result within certain limits through calculation.

Supposing, then, the just wages of any quantity of given labour to have been ascertained, let us examine the first results of just and unjust payment, when in favour of the purchaser or employer; i.e., when two men are ready to do the work, and only one wants to have it done.

Supposing that the fair wages for a certain amount of labor have been determined, let’s look at the initial outcomes of fair and unfair payments, especially when they benefit the buyer or employer; i.e., when two men are willing to do the work, but only one wants it completed.

The unjust purchaser forces the two to bid against each other till he has reduced their demand to its lowest terms. Let us assume that the lowest bidder offers to do the work at half its just price.

The unfair buyer makes the two compete against each other until they've driven their demand down to the lowest possible point. Let's say that the lowest bidder is willing to do the work for half of what it should really cost.

The purchaser employs him, and does not employ the other. The first or apparent result, is, therefore, that one of the two men is left out of employ, or to starvation, just as definitely as by the just procedure of giving fair price to the best workman. The various writers who endeavoured to invalidate the positions of my first paper never saw this, and assumed that the unjust hirer employed both. He employs both no more than the just hirer. The only difference (in the outset) is that the just man pays sufficiently, the unjust man insufficiently, for the labour of the single person employed.

The buyer hires him and not the other. So, the first or obvious result is that one of the two men is left without a job or facing starvation, just as clearly as if the employer was paying a fair price to the best worker. The various writers who tried to dispute the points I made in my first paper never recognized this and assumed that the unfair employer hired both. He doesn’t hire both any more than the fair employer does. The only difference (from the start) is that the fair person pays a fair wage, while the unfair person pays too little for the work of the one person he hires.

I say, in "the outset;" for this first or apparent difference is not the actual difference. By the unjust procedure, half the proper price of the work is left in the hands of the employer. This enables him to hire another man at the same unjust rate on some other kind of work; and the final result is that he has two men working for him at half-price, and two are out of employ.

I say, at the beginning; because this first or obvious difference isn't the real difference. Due to the unfair practices, half of the fair price for the work is kept by the employer. This allows him to hire another person at the same unfair rate for a different type of work; and the end result is that he has two people working for him at half price, while two others are left unemployed.

By the just procedure, the whole price of the first piece of work goes into the hands of the man who does it. No surplus being left in the employer's hands, he cannot hire another man for another piece of labour. But by precisely so much as his power is diminished, the hired workman's power is increased; that is to say, by the additional half of the price he has received; which additional half he has the power of using to employ another man in his service. I will suppose, for the moment, the least favourable, though quite probable,[Pg 167] case—that, though justly treated himself, he yet will act unjustly to his subordinate; and hire at half-price, if he can. The final result will then be, that one man works for the employer, at just price; one for the workman, at half-price; and two, as in the first case, are still out of employ. These two, as I said before, are out of employ in both cases. The difference between the just and unjust procedure does not lie in the number of men hired, but in the price paid to them, and the persons by whom it is paid. The essential difference, that which I want the reader to see clearly, is, that in the unjust case, two men work for one, the first hirer. In the just case, one man works for the first hirer, one for the person hired, and so on, down or up through the various grades of service; the influence being carried forward by justice, and arrested by injustice. The universal and constant action of justice in this matter is therefore to diminish the power of wealth, in the hands of one individual, over masses of men, and to distribute it through a chain of men. The actual power exerted by the wealth is the same in both cases; but by injustice it is put all into one man's hands, so that he directs at once and with equal force the labour of a circle of men about him; by the just procedure, he is permitted to touch the nearest only, through whom, with diminished force, modified by new minds, the energy of the wealth passes on to others, and so till it exhausts itself.

By a fair process, the entire payment for the first piece of work goes to the person who does it. Since no extra money is left with the employer, he cannot hire someone else for additional work. However, as much as the employer's ability to hire decreases, the hired worker's ability increases; specifically, from the extra half of the payment he has received, which he can use to hire someone else for his own service. Let's assume, for a moment, the least favorable yet plausible case—that, although treated fairly himself, he still chooses to treat his subordinate unfairly and hires someone at half the price, if possible. The end result will be that one person works for the employer at the full price; another for the worker at half price; and two remain unemployed, just like in the first scenario. These two, as mentioned earlier, are unemployed in both situations. The difference between the fair and unfair approach isn't about how many people are hired, but about the wages paid to them, and by whom they are paid. The main distinction, which I want the reader to clearly understand, is that in the unfair case, two people are working for one, the first employer. In the fair case, one person works for the first employer, another for the second employer, and so on, through various levels of service; the influence is carried forward by fairness and hindered by unfairness. Thus, the ongoing and consistent action of fairness in this matter is to lessen the control of wealth in the hands of one individual over many people, and to distribute it through a network of individuals. The actual power wielded by the wealth is the same in both situations; but through unfairness, it is concentrated entirely in one person’s hands, allowing him to simultaneously and equally direct the labor of a group around him. Through fair practices, he can only influence those closest to him, through whom, with lessened impact, shaped by new perspectives, the power of the wealth continues on to others, until it is fully depleted.

The immediate operation of justice in this respect is, therefore, to diminish the power of wealth, first in acquisition of luxury, and, secondly, in exercise of moral influence. The employer cannot concentrate so multitudinous labour on his own interests, nor can he subdue so multitudinous mind to his own will. But the secondary operation of justice is not less important. The insufficient payment of the group of men working for one, places each under a maximum of difficulty in rising above his position. The tendency of the system is to check advancement. But the sufficient or just payment, distributed through a descending series of offices or grades of labour,[41] gives each subordinated person fair and sufficient means of rising in the social scale, if he chooses to use them; and thus not only diminishes the immediate power of wealth, but removes the worst disabilities of poverty.

The immediate role of justice in this regard is to reduce the power of wealth, first in acquiring luxury and, second, in exerting moral influence. Employers cannot focus so much labor solely on their own interests, nor can they compel so many minds to conform to their will. However, the secondary role of justice is equally significant. Inadequate pay for a group of workers places each person at a maximum disadvantage in trying to improve their situation. The system tends to hinder advancement. In contrast, fair or just pay, distributed across various levels of jobs, [41] provides each subordinate with reasonable and adequate means to move up the social ladder if they choose to take advantage of them. This not only lessens the immediate power of wealth but also alleviates the harshest burdens of poverty.

[Pg 168]It is on this vital problem that the entire destiny of the labourer is ultimately dependent. Many minor interests may sometimes appear to interfere with it, but all branch from it. For instance, considerable agitation is often caused in the minds of the lower classes when they discover the share which they nominally, and to all appearance, actually, pay out of their wages in taxation (I believe thirty-five or forty per cent.). This sounds very grievous; but in reality the labourer does not pay it, but his employer. If the workman had not to pay it, his wages would be less by just that sum: competition would still reduce them to the lowest rate at which life was possible. Similarly the lower orders agitated for the repeal of the corn laws,[42] thinking they would be better off if bread were cheaper; never perceiving that as soon as bread was permanently cheaper, wages would permanently fall in precisely that proportion. The corn laws were rightly repealed; not, however, because they directly oppressed the poor, but because they indirectly oppressed them in causing a large quantity of their labour to be consumed unproductively. So also unnecessary taxation oppresses them, through destruction of capital, but the destiny of the poor depends primarily always on this one question of dueness of wages. Their distress (irrespectively of that caused by sloth, minor error, or crime) arises on the grand scale from the two reacting forces of competition and oppression. There is not yet, nor will yet for ages be, any real over-population in the world; but a local over-population, or, more accurately, a degree of [Pg 169] population locally unmanageable under existing circumstances for want of forethought and sufficient machinery, necessarily shows itself by pressure of competition; and the taking advantage of this competition by the purchaser to obtain their labour unjustly cheap, consummates at once their suffering and his own; for in this (as I believe in every other kind of slavery) the oppressor suffers at last more than the oppressed, and those magnificent lines of Pope, even in all their force, fall short of the truth—

[Pg 168]The entire future of workers ultimately hinges on this critical issue. There may be minor concerns that seem to interfere with it, but they all stem from this main issue. For example, significant unrest often arises among lower classes when they realize the portion of their earnings taken as taxes (I believe it’s around thirty-five to forty percent). This seems extremely unfair; however, in reality, the worker isn’t the one paying it—it's their employer. If the worker didn’t have to pay it, their wages would be reduced by that same amount since competition would still push wages to the lowest level necessary for survival. Likewise, the lower classes pushed for the repeal of the corn laws,[42] believing they would benefit from cheaper bread; they failed to recognize that once bread became permanently cheaper, wages would also permanently drop by the same amount. The corn laws were rightly repealed, not because they directly harmed the poor, but because they indirectly did so by wasting a significant portion of their labor. Unnecessary taxation also harms them through the destruction of capital, but the fate of the poor primarily depends on the crucial issue of fair wages. Their suffering (aside from that caused by laziness, minor mistakes, or crime) mainly stems from the two opposing forces of competition and oppression. There is not, nor will there be for a long time, any actual overpopulation in the world; however, local overpopulation, or more accurately, a level of population that becomes unmanageable under current conditions due to a lack of foresight and adequate resources, manifests as competitive pressure. When buyers exploit this competition to obtain labor at an unfairly low cost, it not only increases their own suffering but ultimately harms them more than the oppressed; as the magnificent lines of Pope suggest, even at their most powerful, they fall short of the truth—

"Still, to be fair to these unfortunate men of wealth,
Each only HATE HIS NEIGHBOUR AS HIMSELF:
Condemned to the mines, the same fate awaits. "The slave who digs it and the slave who hides it."

[Pg 170]The collateral and reversionary operations of justice in this matter I shall examine hereafter (it being needful first to define the nature of value); proceeding then to consider within what practical terms a juster system may be established; and ultimately the vexed question of the destinies of the unemployed workmen.[43] Lest, however, the reader should be alarmed at some of the issues to which our investigations seem to be tending, as if in their bearing against the power of wealth they had something in common with those of socialism, I wish him to know, in accurate terms, one or two of the main points which I have in view.

[Pg 170]I'll look into the collateral and future implications of justice in this matter later (since it's important first to clarify what value really means); then I'll consider how we can establish a fairer system in practical terms; and finally, I'll tackle the complex issue of what should happen to the unemployed workers.[43] However, I want to reassure the reader that although some of the topics we will explore may seem to challenge the influence of wealth and share similarities with socialist ideas, I want to clearly outline a couple of key points that I have in mind.

Whether socialism has made more progress among the army and navy (where payment is made on my principles), or among the manufacturing operatives (who are paid on my opponents' principles), I leave it to those opponents to ascertain and declare. Whatever their conclusions may be, I think it necessary to answer for myself only this: that if there be any one point insisted on throughout my works more frequently than another, that one point is the impossibility of Equality. My continual aim has been to show the eternal superiority of some men to others, sometimes even of one man to all others; and to show also the advisability of appointing such persons or person to guide, to lead, or on occasion even to compel and subdue, their inferiors, according to their own better knowledge and wiser will. My principles of Political Economy were all involved in a single phrase spoken three years ago at Manchester: "Soldiers of the Ploughshare as well as Soldiers of the Sword:" and they were all summed in a single sentence in the last volume of Modern Painters—"Government and co-operation are in all things the Laws of Life; Anarchy and competition the Laws of Death."

Whether socialism has made more progress within the army and navy (where payment is made based on my principles), or among the manufacturing workers (who are paid according to my opponents' principles), I leave it to those opponents to determine and announce. Regardless of their conclusions, I feel it's necessary to assert for myself this: that if there is one point emphasized throughout my works more than any other, it is the impossibility of Equality. My ongoing aim has been to demonstrate the enduring superiority of some individuals over others, sometimes even of one individual over all others; and to also highlight the need to appoint such individuals to guide, lead, or occasionally even compel and control their inferiors, based on their better knowledge and wiser judgment. My principles of Political Economy were encapsulated in a single phrase I spoke three years ago in Manchester: "Farmers as well as Soldiers:" and they were all summarized in a single sentence from the last volume of Modern Painters—"Government and cooperation are in all things the Laws of Life; Anarchy and competition the Laws of Death."

And with respect to the mode in which these general principles affect the secure possession of property, so far am I from invalidating such security, that the whole gist of these papers will be found ultimately to aim at an extension in its range; and whereas it has long been known and declared that the poor have no right to the property of the rich, I wish it also to be known and declared that the rich have no right to the property of the poor.

And regarding how these general principles influence the secure ownership of property, I'm not trying to undermine that security at all; the main focus of these papers is actually to broaden its scope. While it’s long been understood and stated that the poor don’t have a claim to the property of the rich, I’d like it to be recognized and stated that the rich also don’t have a claim to the property of the poor.

But that the working of the system which I have undertaken to develop would in many ways shorten the apparent [Pg 172]and direct, though not the unseen and collateral, power, both of wealth, as the Lady of Pleasure, and of capital, as the Lord of Toil, I do not deny: on the contrary, I affirm it in all joyfulness; knowing that the attraction of riches is already too strong, as their authority is already too weighty, for the reason of mankind. I said in my last paper that nothing in history had ever been so disgraceful to human intellect as the acceptance among us of the common doctrines of political economy as a science. I have many grounds for saying this, but one of the chief may be given in few words. I know no previous instance in history of a nation's establishing a systematic disobedience to the first principles of its professed religion. The writings which we (verbally) esteem as divine, not only denounce the love of money as the source of all evil, and as an idolatry abhorred of the Deity, but declare mammon service to be the accurate and irreconcileable opposite of God's service; and, whenever they speak of riches absolute, and poverty absolute, declare woe to the rich, and blessing to the poor. Whereupon we forthwith investigate a science of becoming rich, as the shortest road to national prosperity.

But I believe that the system I’m working on will, in many ways, shorten the apparent [Pg 172]and direct, though not the unseen and collateral, influence of both wealth, represented by the Lady of Pleasure, and capital, represented by the Lord of Toil. I joyfully affirm this; I understand that the allure of wealth is already too strong, and its authority too imposing, for human reason. In my last article, I said that nothing in history has been more shameful to human intellect than our acceptance of the common beliefs of political economy as a science. I have many reasons for saying this, but one of the main ones can be explained briefly. I’m not aware of any previous instance in history where a nation established a systematic disobedience to the fundamental principles of its professed religion. The writings we (verbally) regard as divine not only condemn the love of money as the root of all evil and as an idolatry that God detests, but also state that serving wealth is the direct and irreconcilable opposite of serving God; and whenever they mention absolute wealth and absolute poverty, they declare woe to the rich and blessings to the poor. Yet, despite this, we immediately start investigating the science of getting rich as the quickest path to national prosperity.

"Tai Cristian will befriend the Ethiopian,
When the two colleges depart,
"One is forever rich, and the other is poor."

FOOTNOTES:

[34] More accurately, Sun of Justness; but, instead of the harsh word "Justness," the old English "Righteousness" being commonly employed, has, by getting confused with "godliness," or attracting about it various vague and broken meanings, prevented most persons from receiving the force of the passages in which it occurs. The word "righteousness" properly refers to the justice of rule, or right, as distinguished from "equity," which refers to the justice of balance. More broadly, Righteousness is King's justice; and Equity, Judge's justice; the King guiding or ruling all, the Judge dividing or discerning between opposites (therefore, the double question, "Man, who made me a ruler—δικαστὴς—or a divider—μεριστὴς—over you?") Thus, with respect to the Justice of Choice (selection, the feebler and passive justice), we have from lego,—lex, legal, loi, and loyal; and with respect to the Justice of Rule (direction, the stronger and active justice), we have from rego,—rex, regal, roi, and royal.

[34] More accurately, Sun of Justness; but, instead of the harsh word "Justness," the old English "Righteousness" being commonly used, has, by getting confused with "godliness," or attracting various vague and broken meanings, prevented most people from grasping the significance of the passages in which it appears. The word "righteousness" properly refers to the justice of rule, or what is right, as opposed to "equity," which refers to the justice of balance. More broadly, Righteousness is the King's justice; and Equity, the Judge's justice; the King guiding or ruling all, the Judge dividing or discerning between opposites (therefore, the double question, "Man, who made me a ruler—δικαστὴς—or a divider—μεριστὴς—over you?") Thus, regarding the Justice of Choice (selection, the weaker and passive justice), we have from lego,—lex, legal, loi, and loyal; and regarding the Justice of Rule (direction, the stronger and active justice), we have from rego,—rex, regal, roi, and royal.

[35] In another place written with the same meaning, "Just, and having salvation."

[35] In another instance conveying the same idea, "Fair, and possessing salvation."

[36] "Length of days in her right hand; in her left, riches and honour."

[36] "Long life is in her right hand; in her left, wealth and honor."

[37] I hear that several of our lawyers have been greatly amused by the statement in the first of these papers that a lawyer's function was to do justice. I did not intend it for a jest; nevertheless it will be seen that in the above passage neither the determination nor doing of justice are contemplated as functions wholly peculiar to the lawyer. Possibly, the more our standing armies, whether of soldiers, pastors, or legislators (the generic term "pastor" including all teachers, and the generic term "lawyer" including makers as well as interpreters of law), can be superseded by the force of national heroism, wisdom, and honesty, the better it may be for the nation.

[37] I've heard that a number of our lawyers found it quite funny when it was stated in the first of these papers that a lawyer's job is to do justice. I didn't mean it as a joke; however, it’s clear from the passage that the pursuit and execution of justice aren't exclusive responsibilities of lawyers. Perhaps the more we can replace our standing armies—whether they consist of soldiers, pastors, or legislators (with "pastor" referring to all educators and "lawyer" encompassing both creators and interpreters of law)—with the strength of national heroism, wisdom, and integrity, the better it will be for our country.

[38] It being the privilege of the fishes, as it is of rats and wolves, to live by the laws of demand and supply; but the distinction of humanity, to live by those of right.

[38] Just like fish, rats, and wolves can thrive by the laws of supply and demand, humans have the unique ability to live by principles of rights.

[39] It might appear at first that the market price of labour expressed such an exchange: but this is a fallacy, for the market price is the momentary price of the kind of labour required, but the just price is its equivalent of the productive labour of mankind. This difference will be analysed in its place. It must be noted also that I speak here only of the exchangeable value of labour, not of that of commodities. The exchangeable value of a commodity is that of the labour required to produce it, multiplied into the force of the demand for it. If the value of the labour = x and the force of demand = y, the exchangeable value of the commodity is xy, in which if either x = 0, or y = 0, xy = 0.

[39] At first glance, it might seem like the market price of labor reflects such an exchange, but that's a misconception. The market price is just the current price for the type of labor needed, while the fair price is its equivalent in productive labor from people. This difference will be examined later. It's important to mention that I'm only discussing the exchangeable value of labor, not that of goods. The exchangeable value of a good is determined by the amount of labor needed to produce it, multiplied by the strength of its demand. If the value of the labor equals x and the demand equals y, then the exchangeable value of the good is xy, where if either x = 0 or y = 0, then xy = 0.

[40] Under the term "skill" I mean to include the united force of experience, intellect, and passion in their operation on manual labour: and under the term "passion," to include the entire range and agency of the moral feelings; from the simple patience and gentleness of mind which will give continuity and fineness to the touch, or enable one person to work without fatigue, and with good effect, twice as long as another, up to the qualities of character which render science possible—(the retardation of science by envy is one of the most tremendous losses in the economy of the present century)—and to the incommunicable emotion and imagination which are the first and mightiest sources of all value in art.

[40] By "skill," I mean the combined influence of experience, intellect, and passion when applied to manual labor. When I say "passion," I refer to the full range of moral feelings, from simple patience and a gentle mindset that allow for continuous and precise work, enabling one person to labor effectively for twice as long as another without tiring, to the character traits that make scientific progress possible—(the hindrance of science by envy is one of the biggest losses in the economy of our time)—and the deeply personal emotions and imagination that are the primary and strongest sources of value in art.

It is highly singular that political economists should not yet have perceived, if not the moral, at least the passionate element, to be an inextricable quantity in every calculation. I cannot conceive, for instance, how it was possible that Mr. Mill should have followed the true clue so far as to write,—"No limit can be set to the importance—even in a purely productive and material point of view—of mere thought," without seeing that it was logically necessary to add also, "and of mere feeling." And this the more, because in his first definition of labour he includes in the idea of it "all feelings of a disagreeable kind connected with the employment of one's thoughts in a particular occupation." True; but why not also, "feelings of an agreeable kind?" It can hardly be supposed that the feelings which retard labour are more essentially a part of the labour than those which accelerate it. The first are paid for as pain, the second as power. The workman is merely indemnified for the first; but the second both produce a part of the exchangeable value of the work, and materially increase its actual quantity.

It’s quite unusual that political economists still haven’t recognized, if not the moral aspect, at least the emotional element as an essential part of every calculation. I can’t understand, for example, how Mr. Mill got so close to the truth in writing, “No limit can be set to the importance—even from a purely productive and material perspective—of mere thought,” without realizing it was also necessary to include, “and of mere feeling.” This is especially true since in his initial definition of labor, he incorporates “all feelings of a disagreeable kind associated with using one’s thoughts in a specific job.” That’s true, but why not include “feelings of an agreeable kind” too? It seems unlikely that the emotions that hinder work are more fundamentally a part of the labor than those that enhance it. The first are compensated as pain; the second as power. The worker is only reimbursed for the first, but the second both contribute to the exchangeable value of the work and significantly increase its actual quantity.

"Fritz is with us. He is worth fifty thousand men." Truly, a large addition to the material force;—consisting, however, be it observed, not more in operations carried on in Fritz's head, than in operations carried on in his armies' heart. "No limit can be set to the importance of mere thought." Perhaps not! Nay, suppose some day it should turn out that "mere" thought was in itself a recommendable object of production, and that all Material production was only a step towards this more precious Immaterial one?

"Fritz is with us. He is worth fifty thousand men." Truly, a significant boost to our military strength;—but it's important to note that its value lies not just in what Fritz thinks, but in how his armies feel. "There’s no limit to the importance of mere thought." Maybe that’s true! Imagine if one day we find out that "mere" thought is actually a valuable form of creation on its own, and that all physical production is just a means to achieve this more valuable immaterial goal?

[41] I am sorry to lose time by answering, however curtly, the equivocations of the writers who sought to obscure the instances given of regulated labour in the first of these papers, by confusing kinds, ranks, and quantities of labour with its qualities. I never said that a colonel should have the same pay as a private, nor a bishop the same pay as a curate. Neither did I say that more work ought to be paid as less work (so that the curate of a parish of two thousand souls should have no more than the curate of a parish of five hundred). But I said that, so far as you employ it at all, bad work should be paid no less than good work; as a bad clergyman yet takes his tithes, a bad physician takes his fee, and a bad lawyer his costs. And this, as will be farther shown in the conclusion, I said, and say, partly because the best work never was, nor ever will be, done for money at all; but chiefly because, the moment people know they have to pay the bad and good alike, they will try to discern the one from the other, and not use the bad. A sagacious writer in the Scotsman asks me if I should like any common scribbler to be paid by Messrs. Smith, Elder and Co. [the original publishers of this work] as their good authors are. I should, if they employed him—but would seriously recommend them, for the scribbler's sake, as well as their own, not to employ him. The quantity of its money which the country at present invests in scribbling is not, in the outcome of it, economically spent; and even the highly ingenious person to whom this question occurred, might perhaps have been more beneficially employed than in printing it.

[41] I apologize for taking the time to respond, even briefly, to the misleading claims of the writers who tried to blur the facts about regulated labor in the first of these papers by mixing up types, levels, and amounts of labor with its quality. I never claimed that a colonel should earn the same as a private, nor that a bishop should earn the same as a curate. I also didn’t say that more work should pay the same as less work (so that a curate for a parish of two thousand should earn no more than a curate for a parish of five hundred). What I did say is that, as long as you pay for it, bad work should be compensated the same as good work; just as a bad clergyman still collects his tithes, a bad doctor takes his fee, and a bad lawyer gets paid his charges. As I will explain further in the conclusion, I said this, and I stand by it, partly because the best work has never been, nor will it ever be, done purely for money; but mainly because, once people realize they have to pay both bad and good the same, they will seek to tell them apart and will avoid the bad. A thoughtful writer in the Scotsman asked me if I’d want some random writer to be paid by Messrs. Smith, Elder and Co. [the original publishers of this work] just like their good authors are. I would, if they decided to hire him—but I would strongly advise them, for both the scribbler’s benefit and their own, not to hire him. The amount of money the country currently invests in writing isn’t spent wisely in the long run; and even the highly clever person who posed this question might have been better off doing something else than printing it.

[42] I have to acknowledge an interesting communication on the subject of free trade from Paisley (for a short letter from "A Well-wisher" at ——, my thanks are yet more due). But the Scottish writer will, I fear, be disagreeably surprised to hear, that I am, and always have been, an utterly fearless and unscrupulous free trader. Seven years ago, speaking of the various signs of infancy in the European mind (Stones of Venice, vol. iii. p. 168), I wrote: "The first principles of commerce were acknowledged by the English parliament only a few months ago, in its free trade measures, and are still so little understood by the million, that no nation dares to abolish its custom-houses."

[42] I want to acknowledge an interesting message about free trade from Paisley (and I’m especially grateful for the brief letter from "A Well-wisher" at ——). However, the Scottish writer might be unpleasantly surprised to learn that I am, and always have been, a completely unyielding and unrepentant advocate of free trade. Seven years ago, while discussing the various signs of immaturity in European thought (Stones of Venice, vol. iii. p. 168), I stated: "The basic principles of commerce were only recently recognized by the English parliament in its free trade measures, and they are still so poorly understood by the general public that no nation dares to get rid of its customs offices."

It will be observed that I do not admit even the idea of reciprocity. Let other nations, if they like, keep their ports shut; every wise nation will throw its own open. It is not the opening them, but a sudden, inconsiderate, and blunderingly experimental manner of opening them, which does harm. If you have been protecting a manufacture for a long series of years, you must not take the protection off in a moment, so as to throw every one of its operatives at once out of employ, any more than you must take all its wrappings off a feeble child at once in cold weather, though the cumber of them may have been radically injuring its health. Little by little, you must restore it to freedom and to air.

You’ll notice that I don’t even entertain the idea of reciprocity. Other countries can keep their ports shut if they want; every smart nation will open its own. It’s not about opening them, but about doing it suddenly, carelessly, and through trial and error that causes problems. If you’ve been protecting an industry for a long time, you can’t just remove that protection all at once and leave all its workers without jobs, any more than you can strip a weak child of all its layers in cold weather, even if those layers have been hurting its health. You have to gradually restore its freedom and exposure to the air.

Most people's minds are in curious confusion on the subject of free trade, because they suppose it to imply enlarged competition. On the contrary, free trade puts an end to all competition. "Protection" (among various other mischievous functions) endeavours to enable one country to compete with another in the production of an article at a disadvantage. When trade is entirely free, no country can be competed with in the articles for the production of which it is naturally calculated; nor can it compete with any other, in the production of articles for which it is not naturally calculated. Tuscany, for instance, cannot compete with England in steel, nor England with Tuscany in oil. They must exchange their steel and oil. Which exchange should be as frank and free as honesty and the sea-winds can make it. Competition, indeed, arises at first, and sharply, in order to prove which is strongest in any given manufacture possible to both: this point once ascertained, competition is at an end.

Most people are confused about free trade because they think it means more competition. In fact, free trade eliminates all competition. "Protection" (among other harmful effects) tries to help one country compete with another when producing a product under less favorable conditions. When trade is completely free, no country can be outcompeted in the products it naturally excels at producing; nor can it compete with others in products it isn't suited to produce. For example, Tuscany can't compete with England in steel, and England can't compete with Tuscany in oil. They need to trade their steel and oil. This exchange should be as open and straightforward as honesty and the sea winds can allow. Competition does arise initially and intensely to determine which country is stronger in any manufacturing that both can undertake; once this point is established, competition comes to an end.

[43] I should be glad if the reader would first clear the ground for himself so far as to determine whether the difficulty lies in getting the work or getting the pay for it. Does he consider occupation itself to be an expensive luxury, difficult of attainment, of which too little is to be found in the world? or is it rather that, while in the enjoyment even of the most athletic delight, men must nevertheless be maintained, and this maintenance is not always forthcoming? We must be clear on this head before going farther, as most people are loosely in the habit of talking of the difficulty of "finding employment." Is it employment that we want to find, or support during employment? Is it idleness we wish to put an end to, or hunger? We have to take up both questions in succession, only not both at the same time. No doubt that work is a luxury, and a very great one. It is, indeed, at once a luxury and a necessity; no man can retain either health of mind or body without it. So profoundly do I feel this, that, as will be seen in the sequel, one of the principal objects I would recommend to benevolent and practical persons, is to induce rich people to seek for a larger quantity of this luxury than they at present possess. Nevertheless, it appears by experience that even this healthiest of pleasures may be indulged in to excess, and that human beings are just as liable to surfeit of labour as to surfeit of meat; so that, as on the one hand, it may be charitable to provide, for some people, lighter dinner, and more work,—for others, it may be equally expedient to provide lighter work, and more dinner.

[43] I would appreciate it if the reader could first clarify whether the challenge lies in securing the work itself or getting paid for it. Does he view work as an expensive luxury that is hard to come by, of which there is too little in the world? Or is it that, even in the pursuit of the most exhilarating activities, people still need to be supported, and that support isn’t always available? We need to be clear about this before moving on, as most people casually discuss the challenge of "finding employment." Are we looking to find a job, or are we actually seeking financial support while working? Is it the boredom we want to eliminate, or is it hunger? We have to tackle both issues one at a time, but not simultaneously. It's true that work is a luxury, and a significant one at that. It serves as both a luxury and a necessity; no one can maintain their mental or physical health without it. I feel strongly about this, and as will be highlighted later, one of my main suggestions for kind and practical individuals is to encourage wealthy people to pursue a greater amount of this luxury than they currently have. However, experience shows that even this healthiest of pleasures can be overindulged, and that humans are just as prone to overwork as to overeating; thus, while it may be helpful to provide some people with lighter meals and more work, for others it might be equally wise to offer lighter work and more meals.


ESSAY IV.

AD VALOREM.

In the last paper we saw that just payment of labour consisted in a sum of money which would approximately obtain equivalent labour at a future time: we have now to examine the means of obtaining such equivalence. Which question involves the definition of Value, Wealth, Price, and Produce.

In the last paper, we learned that fair payment for labor is a sum of money that would likely secure similar labor in the future. Now, we need to look into how to achieve that equivalence. This question requires us to define Value, Wealth, Price, and Produce.

None of these terms are yet defined so as to be understood by the public. But the last, Produce, which one might have thought the clearest of all, is, in use, the most ambiguous; and the examination of the kind of ambiguity attendant on its present employment will best open the way to our work.

None of these terms are defined in a way that the public can understand. However, the last term, Produce, which you might think is the clearest of all, is actually the most ambiguous in practice. Examining the type of ambiguity associated with how it's currently used will best pave the way for our work.

In his Chapter on Capital,[44] Mr. J. S. Mill instances, as a capitalist, a hardware manufacturer, who, having intended to spend a certain portion of the proceeds of his business in buying plate and jewels, changes his mind, and "pays it as wages to additional workpeople." The effect is stated by Mr. Mill to be that "more food is appropriated to the consumption of productive labourers."

In his Chapter on Capital,[44] Mr. J. S. Mill discusses a hardware manufacturer who, planning to spend part of his business profits on plates and jewels, changes his mind and instead "pays it as wages to additional workers." Mr. Mill notes that the result is that "more food is allocated to the consumption of productive laborers."

Now I do not ask, though, had I written this paragraph, it would surely have been asked of me, What is to become of the silversmiths? If they are truly unproductive persons, we will acquiesce in their extinction. And though in another part of the same passage, the hardware merchant is supposed also to dispense with a number of servants, whose "food is thus set free for productive purposes," I do not inquire what will be the effect, painful or otherwise, upon the servants, of this emancipation of their food. But I very seriously inquire [Pg 174] why ironware is produce, and silverware is not? That the merchant consumes the one, and sells the other, certainly does not constitute the difference, unless it can be shown (which, indeed, I perceive it to be becoming daily more and more the aim of tradesmen to show) that commodities are made to be sold, and not to be consumed. The merchant is an agent of conveyance to the consumer in one case, and is himself the consumer in the other:[45] but the labourers are in either case equally productive, since they have produced goods to the same value, if the hardware and the plate are both goods.

Now, I'm not asking, but if I had written this paragraph, it definitely would have been asked of me, What will happen to the silversmiths? If they are truly unproductive, we will accept their disappearance. And while in another part of the same passage, the hardware merchant is also supposed to let go of several servants, whose "food is then available for productive purposes," I won’t ask what the impact, whether painful or not, will be on those servants due to this release of their food. However, I seriously want to know why ironware is produced, but silverware is not? Just because the merchant uses one and sells the other doesn’t really explain the difference, unless it can be demonstrated (which I see is increasingly becoming the goal of merchants to show) that goods are made to be sold, not consumed. The merchant acts as a conduit to the consumer in one case and is the consumer in the other: [45] but the workers are equally productive in both cases, since they have produced goods of the same value, if both hardware and silverware are considered goods.

And what distinction separates them? It is indeed possible that in the "comparative estimate of the moralist," with which Mr. Mill says political economy has nothing to do (III. i. 2), a steel fork might appear a more substantial production than a silver one: we may grant also that knives, no less than forks, are good produce; and scythes and ploughshares serviceable articles. But, how of bayonets? Supposing the hardware merchant to effect large sales of these, by help of the "setting free" of the food of his servants and his silversmith,—is he still employing productive labourers, or, in Mr. Mill's words, labourers who increase "the stock of permanent means of enjoyment" (I. iii. 4)? Or if, instead of bayonets, he supply bombs, will not the absolute and final "enjoyment" of even these energetically productive articles (each of which costs ten pounds[46]) be dependent on a proper choice of time [Pg 175] and place for their enfantement; choice, that is to say, depending on those philosophical considerations with which political economy has nothing to do?[47]

And what makes them different? It’s possible that in the "comparative judgment of the moralist," which Mr. Mill claims has nothing to do with political economy (III. i. 2), a steel fork might seem like a more significant product than a silver one. We can also agree that knives, just like forks, are good products; and scythes and ploughshares are useful items. But what about bayonets? If the hardware merchant sells a lot of these, thanks to the "setting free" of the food for his workers and his silversmith—does this still mean he is using productive laborers, or, in Mr. Mill's words, workers who enhance "the stock of permanent means of enjoyment" (I. iii. 4)? Or if, instead of bayonets, he sells bombs, will the ultimate "enjoyment" of even these highly productive items (each costing ten pounds[46]) rely on choosing the right time and place for their enfantement; a choice that, in essence, hinges on those philosophical issues that political economy doesn’t concern itself with?[47]

I should have regretted the need of pointing out inconsistency in any portion of Mr. Mill's work, had not the value of his work proceeded from its inconsistencies. He deserves honour among economists by inadvertently disclaiming the principles which he states, and tacitly introducing the moral considerations with which he declares his science has no connection. Many of his chapters, are, therefore, true and valuable; and the only conclusions of his which I have to dispute are those which follow from his premises.

I would have regretted needing to point out inconsistencies in any part of Mr. Mill's work if the value of his work didn't come from those inconsistencies. He deserves recognition among economists for unintentionally rejecting the principles he presents while quietly bringing in the moral considerations he claims are unrelated to his science. Many of his chapters are therefore true and valuable; the only conclusions of his that I need to challenge are those that stem from his premises.

Thus, the idea which lies at the root of the passage we have just been examining, namely, that labour applied to produce luxuries will not support so many persons as labour applied to produce useful articles, is entirely true; but the instance given fails—and in four directions of failure at once—because Mr. Mill has not defined the real meaning of usefulness. The definition which he has given—"capacity to satisfy a desire, or serve a purpose" (III. i. 2)—applies equally to the iron and silver; while the true definition,—which he has not given, but which nevertheless underlies the false verbal definition in his mind, and comes out once or twice by accident (as in the words "any support to life or strength" in I. i. 5)—applies to some articles of iron, but not to others, and to some articles of silver, but not to others. It applies to ploughs, but not to bayonets; and to forks, but not to filigree.[48]

So, the main idea behind the passage we've just looked at, which is that labor spent on producing luxury items won't support as many people as labor spent on producing useful goods, is completely true. However, the example given falls short in four ways because Mr. Mill hasn't defined what usefulness really means. The definition he provides— "the ability to satisfy a desire or serve a purpose" (III. i. 2)—fits both iron and silver; however, the true definition—which he hasn't provided but is hinted at in his mind and comes up accidentally once or twice (like in the phrase "any support to life or strength" in I. i. 5)—applies to some types of iron but not others, and some types of silver but not others. It applies to plows, but not to bayonets; and to forks, but not to filigree.[48]

The eliciting of the true definition will give us the reply to our first question, "What is value?" respecting which, however, we must first hear the popular statements.

The true definition will answer our first question, "What is value?" but first, we need to consider the common viewpoints on the topic.

[Pg 176]"The word 'value,' when used without adjunct, always means, in political economy, value in exchange" (Mill, III. i. 3). So that, if two ships cannot exchange their rudders, their rudders are, in politico-economic language, of no value to either.

[Pg 176]"The term 'value,' when used on its own, always refers to exchange value in political economy" (Mill, III. i. 3). Therefore, if two ships cannot trade their rudders, then their rudders have no value to either ship in political and economic terms.

But "the subject of political economy is wealth."—(Preliminary remarks, page 1.)

But "the subject of political economy is wealth."—(Preliminary remarks, page 1.)

And wealth "consists of all useful and agreeable objects which possess exchangeable value."—(Preliminary remarks, page 10.)

And wealth "includes all useful and enjoyable things that have exchangeable value."—(Preliminary remarks, page 10.)

It appears then, according to Mr. Mill, that usefulness and agreeableness underlie the exchange value, and must be ascertained to exist in the thing, before we can esteem it an object of wealth.

It seems that, according to Mr. Mill, usefulness and pleasure are the basis of exchange value and need to be confirmed as present in something before we can consider it a valuable asset.

Now, the economical usefulness of a thing depends not merely on its own nature, but on the number of people who can and will use it. A horse is useless, and therefore unsaleable, if no one can ride,—a sword if no one can strike, and meat, if no one can eat. Thus every material utility depends on its relative human capacity.

Now, the economic value of something depends not just on what it is, but on how many people can and will use it. A horse is useless, and therefore unsellable, if no one can ride it—just like a sword is useless if no one can wield it, and meat is useless if no one can eat it. So, every practical utility is based on its relative usefulness to people.

Similarly: The agreeableness of a thing depends not merely on its own likeableness, but on the number of people who can be got to like it. The relative agreeableness, and therefore saleableness, of "a pot of the smallest ale," and of "Adonis painted by a running brook," depends virtually on the opinion of Demos, in the shape of Christopher Sly. That is to say, the agreeableness of a thing depends on its relative human disposition.[49] Therefore, political economy, being a science of [Pg 177] wealth, must be a science respecting human capacities and dispositions. But moral considerations have nothing to do with political economy (III. i. 2). Therefore, moral considerations have nothing to do with human capacities and dispositions.

Similarly: How appealing something is doesn’t just depend on its inherent likability, but also on how many people can be convinced to like it. The relative appeal, and thus marketability, of "a pot of the smallest ale" versus "Adonis painted by a running brook" practically hinges on the opinion of the public, represented by Christopher Sly. In other words, how agreeable something is is influenced by people's preferences. [49] Therefore, political economy, as a study of wealth, must also concern itself with human abilities and attitudes. However, ethical considerations have no relevance to political economy (III. i. 2). Thus, ethical considerations are unrelated to human abilities and attitudes.

I do not wholly like the look of this conclusion from Mr. Mill's statements:—let us try Mr. Ricardo's.

I’m not entirely comfortable with the conclusion drawn from Mr. Mill's statements:—let’s take a look at Mr. Ricardo's.

"Utility is not the measure of exchangeable value, though it is absolutely essential to it."—(Chap. 1. sect. i.) Essential to what degree, Mr. Ricardo? There may be greater and less degrees of utility. Meat, for instance, may be so good as to be fit for any one to eat, or so bad as to be fit for no one to eat. What is the exact degree of goodness which is "essential" to its exchangeable value, but not "the measure" of it? How good must the meat be, in order to possess any exchangeable value; and how bad must it be—(I wish this were a settled question in London markets)—in order to possess none?

"Utility isn’t the measure of exchangeable value, but it’s absolutely essential to it."—(Chap. 1. sect. i.) Essential to what extent, Mr. Ricardo? There can be varying degrees of utility. For example, meat can be good enough for anyone to eat or so bad that no one can eat it. What’s the exact degree of quality that’s "essential" to its exchangeable value but not "the measure" of it? How good does the meat have to be to have any exchangeable value, and how bad does it have to be—(I wish this were a settled question in London markets)—to have none?

There appears to be some hitch, I think, in the working even of Mr. Ricardo's principles; but let him take his own example. "Suppose that in the early stages of society the bows and arrows of the hunter were of equal value with the implements of the fisherman. Under such circumstances the value of the deer, the produce of the hunter's day's labour, would be exactly" (italics mine) "equal to the value of the fish, the product of the fisherman's day's labour. The comparative value of the fish and game would be entirely regulated by the quantity of labour realized in each." (Ricardo, chap. iii. On Value.)

There seems to be some issue, I think, in the application of Mr. Ricardo's principles; but let's consider his own example. "Imagine that in the early days of society, the bows and arrows of the hunter were valued the same as the tools of the fisherman. In this case, the value of the deer, which is the result of the hunter's day's work, would be exactly" (italics mine) "equal to the value of the fish, the outcome of the fisherman's day's work. The relative value of the fish and game would be completely determined by the amount of labor invested in each." (Ricardo, chap. iii. On Value.)

Indeed! Therefore, if the fisherman catches one sprat, and the huntsman one deer, one sprat will be equal in value to one deer; but if the fisherman catches no sprat, and the huntsman two deer, no sprat will be equal in value to two deer?

Indeed! So, if the fisherman catches one sprat and the huntsman catches one deer, one sprat is equal in value to one deer; but if the fisherman catches no sprat and the huntsman catches two deer, no sprat is equal in value to two deer?

Nay; but—Mr. Ricardo's supporters may say—he means, on an average;—if the average product of a day's work of [Pg 178]fisher and hunter be one fish and one deer, the one fish will always be equal in value to the one deer.

No; but—Mr. Ricardo's supporters might argue—he means, on average;—if the average output of a day's work of [Pg 178] a fisherman and a hunter is one fish and one deer, then one fish will always be worth the same as one deer.

Might I inquire the species of fish. Whale? or whitebait?[50]

Might I ask what kind of fish it is? A whale? Or whitebait?[50]

It would be waste of time to pursue these fallacies farther; we will seek for a true definition.

It would be a waste of time to pursue these false ideas any further; we will look for a true definition.

Much store has been set for centuries upon the use of our English classical education. It were to be wished that our [Pg 179] well-educated merchants recalled to mind always this much of their Latin schooling,—that the nominative of valorem (a word already sufficiently familiar to them) is valor; a word which, therefore, ought to be familiar to them. Valor, from valere, to be well, or strong (ὑγιαίνω);—strong, in life (if a man), or valiant; strong, for life (if a thing), or valuable. To be "valuable," therefore, is to "avail towards life." A truly valuable or availing thing is that which leads to life with its whole strength. In proportion as it does not lead to life, or as its strength is broken, it is less valuable; in proportion as it leads away from life, it is unvaluable or malignant.

For centuries, a lot of importance has been placed on our English classical education. It would be great if our [Pg 179] well-educated merchants constantly remembered this part of their Latin lessons—that the nominative of valorem (a term they should already know well) is valor; a word that should be familiar to them. Valor, derived from valere, meaning to be well or strong (ὑγιαίνω);—strong, in life (if referring to a person), or brave; strong, for life (if referring to a thing), or valuable. Thus, to be "valuable" means to "contribute to life." Something that is truly valuable is what promotes life with all its strength. The less it promotes life or the more its strength is diminished, the less valuable it becomes; and the more it leads away from life, the more it is worthless or harmful.

The value of a thing, therefore, is independent of opinion, and of quantity. Think what you will of it, gain how much you may of it, the value of the thing itself is neither greater nor less. For ever it avails, or avails not; no estimate can raise, no disdain depress, the power which it holds from the Maker of things and of men.

The value of something, then, is not dependent on opinion or amount. No matter what you think about it or how much you acquire, the actual value of the thing remains unchanged. It either holds value or it doesn’t; no amount of praise can increase it, and no amount of disdain can reduce it, as its worth comes from the Creator of all things and people.

The real science of political economy, which has yet to be distinguished from the bastard science, as medicine from witchcraft, and astronomy from astrology, is that which teaches nations to desire and labour for the things that lead to life; and which teaches them to scorn and destroy the things that lead to destruction. And if, in a state of infancy, they suppose indifferent things, such as excrescences of shellfish, and pieces of blue and red stone, to be valuable, and spend large measure of the labour which ought to be employed for the extension and ennobling of life, in diving or digging for them, and cutting them into various shapes,—or if, in the same state of infancy, they imagine precious and beneficent things, such as air, light, and cleanliness, to be valueless,—or if, finally, they imagine the conditions of their own existence, by which alone they can truly possess or use anything, such, for instance, as peace, trust, and love, to be prudently exchangeable, when the market offers, for gold, iron, or excrescences of shells—the great and only science of Political Economy teaches them, in all these cases, what is vanity, and what substance; and how the service of Death, the Lord of Waste, and of eternal emptiness, differs from the service of Wisdom, the Lady of Saving, and of eternal fulness; she who[Pg 180] has said, "I will cause those that love me to inherit Substance; and I will Fill their treasures."

The true science of political economy, which still needs to be differentiated from its lesser version, just like medicine is different from witchcraft and astronomy from astrology, is that which teaches countries to want and work towards things that promote life; and to reject and eliminate things that bring about destruction. If, in a naive state, they mistakenly value trivial things like bits of shell or pieces of colored stone and waste a lot of effort that should go into improving and enriching life by searching for and shaping those items— or if they think that precious and beneficial things like air, light, and cleanliness have no value— or if, in this same naive state, they wrongly believe that their own fundamental needs like peace, trust, and love can be wisely traded for gold, iron, or bits of shell when the market is right— the great and essential science of Political Economy teaches them in all these instances what is meaningless and what is real; and how the service of Death, the Lord of Waste, and eternal emptiness, differs from the service of Wisdom, the Lady of Saving, and eternal fullness; she who[Pg 180] has declared, "I will make those who love me inherit Content; and I will Fill their treasures."

The "Lady of Saving," in a profounder sense than that of the savings' bank, though that is a good one: Madonna della Salute,—Lady of Health—which, though commonly spoken of as if separate from wealth, is indeed a part of wealth. This word, "wealth," it will be remembered, is the next we have to define.

The "Lady of Saving," in a deeper way than just a savings bank, though that's a solid concept: Madonna della Salute—Lady of Health—which, while usually mentioned as if it's separate from wealth, is actually a part of wealth. This word, "wealth," as we should recall, is the next one we need to define.

"To be wealthy," says Mr. Mill, is "to have a large stock of useful articles."

"To be wealthy," says Mr. Mill, is "to have a lot of useful stuff."

I accept this definition. Only let us perfectly understand it. My opponents often lament my not giving them enough logic: I fear I must at present use a little more than they will like; but this business of Political Economy is no light one, and we must allow no loose terms in it.

I accept this definition. But let’s make sure we fully understand it. My opponents often complain that I don’t provide them with enough logic: I’m afraid I have to use a bit more logic than they’d prefer right now; however, the subject of Political Economy is not a trivial matter, and we cannot afford to use vague terms in it.

We have, therefore, to ascertain in the above definition, first, what is the meaning of "having," or the nature of Possession. Then, what is the meaning of "useful," or the nature of Utility.

We need to figure out, from the definition above, first, what "having" means, or what Possession really is. Then, we need to understand what "useful" means, or what Utility is all about.

And first of possession. At the crossing of the transepts of Milan Cathedral has lain, for three hundred years, the embalmed body of St. Carlo Borromeo. It holds a golden crosier, and has a cross of emeralds on its breast. Admitting the crosier and emeralds to be useful articles, is the body to be considered as "having" them? Do they, in the politico-economical sense of property, belong to it? If not, and if we may, therefore, conclude generally that a dead body cannot possess property, what degree and period of animation in the body will render possession possible?

And first, let's talk about possession. At the intersection of the transepts of Milan Cathedral lies, for three hundred years, the embalmed body of St. Carlo Borromeo. It holds a golden staff and has a cross of emeralds on its chest. If we accept that the staff and emeralds are useful items, can we consider the body as "having" them? Do they, in the context of political and economic property, belong to it? If not, and if we can generally conclude that a dead body cannot possess property, what level and duration of life in the body would make possession possible?

As thus: lately in a wreck of a Californian ship, one of the passengers fastened a belt about him with two hundred pounds of gold in it, with which he was found afterwards at the bottom. Now, as he was sinking—had he the gold? or had the gold him?[51]

As it happened, recently a shipwreck occurred off the coast of California, and one of the passengers fastened a belt around himself that held two hundred pounds of gold. He was later discovered at the bottom of the ocean. Now, as he was sinking—did he have the gold, or did the gold have him?[51]

And if, instead of sinking him in the sea by its weight, the gold had struck him on the forehead, and thereby caused incurable disease—suppose palsy or insanity,—would the gold[Pg 181] in that case have been more a "possession" than in the first? Without pressing the inquiry up through instances of gradually increasing vital power over the gold (which I will, however, give, if they are asked for), I presume the reader will see that possession, or "having," is not an absolute, but a gradated, power; and consists not only in the quantity or nature of the thing possessed, but also (and in a greater degree) in its suitableness to the person possessing it, and in his vital power to use it.

And if, instead of sinking him in the sea with its weight, the gold had hit him on the forehead and caused an incurable disease—say paralysis or madness—would the gold[Pg 181] then be more of a "possession" than before? Without diving deeper into examples of progressively greater influence of the gold (which I can provide if needed), I assume the reader understands that possession, or "having," isn't absolute but rather a spectrum; it involves not just the amount or type of what is possessed, but also (and more importantly) how suitable it is for the person owning it, and their ability to utilize it.

And our definition of Wealth, expanded, becomes: "The possession of useful articles, which we can use." This is a very serious change. For wealth, instead of depending merely on a "have," is thus seen to depend on a "can." Gladiator's death, on a "habet"; but soldier's victory, and state's salvation, on a "quo plurimum posset." (Liv. VII. 6.) And what we reasoned of only as accumulation of material, is seen to demand also accumulation of capacity.

And our definition of wealth, updated, becomes: "The possession of useful items, that we can actually use." This is a significant shift. Wealth is now understood not just in terms of what you "have," but also in terms of what you "can" do. The death of a gladiator is about what he "has"; but a soldier's victory and a state's survival depend on what they "can do." (Liv. VII. 6.) What we previously considered only as the accumulation of material goods is now seen to also require the accumulation of skills.

So much for our verb. Next for our adjective. What is the meaning of "useful?"

So much for our verb. Next, let's look at our adjective. What does "useful" mean?

The inquiry is closely connected with the last. For what is capable of use in the hands of some persons, is capable, in the hands of others, of the opposite of use, called commonly, "from-use," or "ab-use." And it depends on the person, much more than on the article, whether its usefulness or ab-usefulness will be the quality developed in it. Thus, wine, which the Greeks, in their Bacchus, made, rightly, the type of all passion, and which, when used, "cheereth god and man" (that is to say, strengthens both the divine life, or reasoning power, and the earthly, or carnal power, of man); yet, when abused, becomes "Dionusos," hurtful especially to the divine part of man, or reason. And again, the body itself, being equally liable to use and to abuse, and, when rightly disciplined, serviceable to the State, both for war and labour;—but when not disciplined, or abused, valueless to the State, and capable only of continuing the private or single existence of the individual (and that but feebly)—the Greeks called such a body an "idiotic" or "private" body, from their word signifying a person employed in no way directly useful[Pg 182] to the State: whence, finally, our "idiot," meaning a person entirely occupied with his own concerns.

The inquiry is closely tied to the last. For what is useful in the hands of some people can be harmful in the hands of others, commonly referred to as "misuse" or "abuse." Whether something is beneficial or detrimental depends more on the person than the item itself. Take wine, for example, which the Greeks, in their Bacchus, rightly viewed as a symbol of passion. When used properly, it "cheers both god and man" (that is, it enhances both the divine, or rational, and earthly, or physical, aspects of humanity); however, when abused, it becomes "Dionusos," damaging especially to the rational part of people. Additionally, the body itself is equally subject to use and abuse; when properly trained, it can serve the State well in both war and labor, but when neglected or abused, it becomes worthless to the State, only capable of sustaining the private existence of the individual (and even that poorly). The Greeks termed such a body an "idiotic" or "private" body, deriving from their word for a person who is not directly useful to the State: hence, our term "idiot," referring to someone focused solely on their own affairs.[Pg 182]

Hence, it follows, that if a thing is to be useful, it must be not only of an availing nature, but in availing hands. Or, in accurate terms, usefulness is value in the hands of the valiant; so that this science of wealth being, as we have just seen, when regarded as the science of Accumulation, accumulative of capacity as well as of material,—when regarded as the science of Distribution, is distribution not absolute, but discriminate; not of every thing to every man, but of the right thing to the right man. A difficult science, dependent on more than arithmetic.

Therefore, it follows that for something to be useful, it must not only be effective but also in capable hands. In precise terms, usefulness is value in the hands of those who are brave; thus, this study of wealth, as we've just discussed, when viewed as the study of Accumulation, involves accumulating both skills and resources—when viewed as the study of Distribution, it is not just distribution for everyone, but a careful distribution; not giving everything to everyone, but the right thing to the right person. It’s a complex field that relies on more than just numbers.

Wealth, therefore, is "THE POSSESSION OF THE VALUABLE BY THE VALIANT;" and in considering it as a power existing in a nation, the two elements, the value of the thing, and the valour of its possessor, must be estimated together. Whence it appears that many of the persons commonly considered wealthy, are in reality no more wealthy than the locks of their own strong boxes are; they being inherently and eternally incapable of wealth; and operating for the nation, in an economical point of view, either as pools of dead water, and eddies in a stream (which, so long as the stream flows, are useless, or serve only to drown people, but may become of importance in a state of stagnation, should the stream dry); or else, as dams in a river, of which the ultimate service depends not on the dam, but the miller; or else, as mere accidental stays and impediments, acting, not as wealth, but (for we ought to have a correspondent term) as "illth," causing various devastation and trouble around them in all directions; or lastly, act not at all, but are merely animated conditions of delay (no use being possible of anything they have until they are dead), in which last condition they are nevertheless often useful as delays, and "impedimenta," if a nation is apt to move too fast.

Wealth is therefore "THE POSSESSION OF THE VALUABLE BY THE VALIANT;" and when we look at it as a force within a nation, we need to consider together two elements: the value of the item and the courage of its owner. This shows that many people who are commonly seen as wealthy are actually no wealthier than the contents of their own vaults; they are inherently and permanently incapable of generating wealth. From an economic perspective, they function for the nation either as stagnant pools and eddies in a stream (which, while the stream flows, are useless or potentially dangerous, but could become significant if the stream dries up); or as dams in a river, where the value depends not on the dam itself, but on the miller; or as mere accidental barriers and obstacles, acting not as wealth but, for lack of a better term, as "illth," causing various damage and chaos around them; or finally, they may not act at all but simply serve as delays (nothing they have can be used until they pass), and in this last state, they can still be somewhat beneficial as delays and "impedimenta" if a nation is prone to moving too quickly.

This being so, the difficulty of the true science of Political Economy lies not merely in the need of developing manly character to deal with material value, but in the fact, that while the manly character and material value only form wealth by their conjunction, they have nevertheless a mutually[Pg 183] destructive operation on each other. For the manly character is apt to ignore, or even cast away, the material value:—whence that of Pope:—

This being the case, the challenge of the true science of Political Economy is not just about cultivating strong character to handle material value, but also about the fact that while strong character and material value only create wealth together, they also tend to undermine each other. Strong character often tends to overlook or even reject material value:—whence that of Pope:—

"Sure, qualities that deserve praise
"More people ruin their fortunes than improve them."

And on the other hand, the material value is apt to undermine the manly character; so that it must be our work, in the issue, to examine what evidence there is of the effect of wealth on the minds of its possessors; also, what kind of person it is who usually sets himself to obtain wealth, and succeeds in doing so; and whether the world owes more gratitude to rich or to poor men, either for their moral influence upon it, or for chief goods, discoveries, and practical advancements. I may, however, anticipate future conclusions so far as to state that in a community regulated only by laws of demand and supply, but protected from open violence, the persons who become rich are, generally speaking, industrious, resolute, proud, covetous, prompt, methodical, sensible, unimaginative, insensitive, and ignorant. The persons who remain poor are the entirely foolish, the entirely wise,[52] the idle, the reckless, the humble, the thoughtful, the dull, the imaginative, the sensitive, the well-informed, the improvident, the irregularly and impulsively wicked, the clumsy knave, the open thief, and the entirely merciful, just, and godly person.

And on the other hand, material wealth tends to weaken a person's character; so it’s our job to look into how wealth affects the minds of those who have it; what kind of person usually goes after wealth and manages to get it; and whether the world should be more grateful to rich people or poor people, either for their moral impact or for their key contributions, discoveries, and practical progress. I can, however, hint at future conclusions by saying that in a community driven only by supply and demand, but safe from outright violence, the people who get rich are usually hardworking, determined, proud, greedy, quick, organized, practical, unimaginative, insensitive, and uninformed. The people who stay poor are either completely foolish, completely wise, the lazy, the reckless, the humble, the thoughtful, the dull, the imaginative, the sensitive, the knowledgeable, the careless, the randomly wicked, the clumsy crook, the blatant thief, and the completely merciful, fair, and righteous person.

Thus far then of wealth. Next, we have to ascertain the nature of Price; that is to say, of exchange value, and its expression by currencies.

Thus far then of wealth. Next, we need to determine the nature of Cost; that is to say, exchange value, and how it's represented by currencies.

Note first, of exchange, there can be no profit in it. It is only in labour there can be profit—that is to say a "making in advance," or "making in favour of" (from proficio). In exchange, there is only advantage, i.e., a bringing of vantage or power to the exchanging persons. Thus, one man, by sowing and reaping, turns one measure of corn into two measures. That is Profit. Another by digging and forging, turns one spade into two spades. That is Profit. But the man who has two measures of corn wants sometimes to dig; and [Pg 184] the man who has two spades wants sometimes to eat:—They exchange the gained grain for the gained tool; and both are the better for the exchange; but though there is much advantage in the transaction, there is no profit. Nothing is constructed or produced. Only that which had been before constructed is given to the person by whom it can be used. If labour is necessary to effect the exchange, that labour is in reality involved in the production, and, like all other labour, bears profit. Whatever number of men are concerned in the manufacture, or in the conveyance, have share in the profit; but neither the manufacture nor the conveyance are the exchange, and in the exchange itself there is no profit.

First, note that there can be no profit in exchange. Profit only comes from labor, meaning a "making in advance" or "making in favor of" (from proficio). In exchange, there is only advantage, i.e., a transfer of benefit or power to the people involved. One person, by sowing and reaping, converts one measure of corn into two measures. That is profit. Another person, by digging and forging, turns one spade into two spades. That is profit. However, the person who has two measures of corn sometimes wants to dig; and the person who has two spades sometimes wants to eat:—They exchange some of the grain for the tool, and both benefit from the trade; but while there is much advantage in the transaction, there is no profit. Nothing new is made or produced. Only what was already made is given to someone who can use it. If labor is needed to complete the exchange, that labor is essentially part of the production process, and, like all other labor, generates profit. Any number of people involved in the manufacturing or transportation share in the profit; however, neither the manufacturing nor the transportation is the exchange itself, and in the exchange, there is no profit.

There may, however, be acquisition, which is a very different thing. If, in the exchange, one man is able to give what cost him little labour for what has cost the other much, he "acquires" a certain quantity of the produce of the other's labour. And precisely what he acquires, the other loses. In mercantile language, the person who thus acquires is commonly said to have "made a profit;" and I believe that many of our merchants are seriously under the impression that it is possible for everybody, somehow, to make a profit in this manner. Whereas, by the unfortunate constitution of the world we live in, the laws both of matter and motion have quite rigorously forbidden universal acquisition of this kind. Profit, or material gain, is attainable only by construction or by discovery; not by exchange. Whenever material gain follows exchange, for every plus there is a precisely equal minus.

There might, however, be acquisition, which is a completely different matter. If, in the exchange, one person is able to give something that cost them little effort in return for something that cost the other a lot, they "acquire" a certain amount of the other person's labor's output. What one person acquires, the other loses. In business terms, the person who acquires this way is often said to have "made a profit;" and I believe that many of our merchants genuinely think it's possible for everyone to somehow make a profit like this. However, due to the unfortunate setup of the world we live in, the laws of matter and motion strictly prohibit universal attainment of this kind. Profit, or material gain, can only be achieved through construction or discovery, not through exchange. Whenever material gain results from an exchange, for every plus there is a precisely equal minus.

Unhappily for the progress of the science of Political Economy, the plus quantities, or—if I may be allowed to coin an awkward plural—the pluses, make a very positive and venerable appearance in the world, so that every one is eager to learn the science which produces results so magnificent; whereas the minuses have, on the other hand, a tendency to retire into back streets, and other places of shade,—or even to get themselves wholly and finally put out of sight in graves: which renders the algebra of this science peculiar, and difficultly legible; a large number of its negative signs being written by the account-keeper in a kind of red ink, which starvation[Pg 185] thins, and makes strangely pale, or even quite invisible ink, for the present.

Unfortunately for the advancement of Political Economy, the positive figures—or if I may create an awkward plural, the positives—stand out prominently in the world, making everyone eager to learn this science that yields such impressive results; meanwhile, the negatives tend to retreat into side streets and other shady spots, or even become completely hidden away in graves. This makes the algebra of this science unique and hard to read, as many of its negative signs are recorded by the accountant in a type of red ink that starvation thins out, rendering it strangely pale, or even completely invisible at present.[Pg 185]

The science of Exchange, or, as I hear it has been proposed to call it, of "Catallactics," considered as one of gain, is, therefore, simply nugatory; but considered as one of acquisition, it is a very curious science, differing in its data and basis from every other science known. Thus:—If I can exchange a needle with a savage for a diamond, my power of doing so depends either on the savage's ignorance of social arrangements in Europe, or on his want of power to take advantage of them, by selling the diamond to any one else for more needles. If, farther, I make the bargain as completely advantageous to myself as possible, by giving to the savage a needle with no eye in it (reaching, thus, a sufficiently satisfactory type of the perfect operation of catallactic science), the advantage to me in the entire transaction depends wholly upon the ignorance, powerlessness, or heedlessness of the person dealt with. Do away with these, and catallactic advantage becomes impossible. So far, therefore as the science of exchange relates to the advantage of one of the exchanging persons only, it is founded on the ignorance or incapacity of the opposite person. Where these vanish, it also vanishes. It is therefore a science founded on nescience, and an art founded on artlessness. But all other sciences and arts, except this, have for their object the doing away with their opposite nescience and artlessness. This science, alone of sciences, must, by all available means, promulgate and prolong its opposite nescience; otherwise the science itself is impossible. It is, therefore, peculiarly and alone, the science of darkness; probably a bastard science—not by any means a divina scientia, but one begotten of another father, that father who, advising his children to turn stones into bread, is himself employed in turning bread into stones, and who, if you ask a fish of him (fish not being producible on his estate), can but give you a serpent.

The science of exchange, or what some are suggesting to call "Catallactics," when viewed as a way to gain, is essentially pointless; however, when seen as a means of acquiring, it becomes a fascinating field that stands apart from all other sciences. For example: If I can trade a needle with a tribal person for a diamond, my ability to do so relies either on the tribal person's lack of knowledge about social arrangements in Europe or their inability to take advantage of that knowledge by selling the diamond to someone else for more needles. Furthermore, if I structure the deal to benefit myself as much as possible by giving the tribal person a needle that doesn’t have a hole in it (thus reaching a satisfactory example of effective catallactic practice), the benefit I gain from the entire transaction hinges entirely on the ignorance, helplessness, or carelessness of the other party involved. Remove these factors, and the advantage in catallactics disappears. Thus, the science of exchange, when it pertains to just one party’s benefit, is based on the other person's ignorance or incapacity. When these disappear, so does the advantage. Therefore, it is a science rooted in ignorance and an art reliant on simplicity. Unlike all other sciences and arts, which aim to eliminate their opposing ignorance and simplicity, this particular science must, through every means possible, promote and sustain its own opposing ignorance; otherwise, the science itself cannot exist. It is, therefore, uniquely the science of darkness; likely a bastard science—not a divine science—but one born of a different lineage, that lineage which, while advising its children to turn stones into bread, is busy transforming bread into stones, and who, if you ask for a fish (since fish can’t be found on its land), can only hand you a serpent.

The general law, then, respecting just or economical exchange, is simply this:—There must be advantage on both sides (or if only advantage on one, at least no disadvantage on the other) to the persons exchanging; and just payment[Pg 186] for his time, intelligence, and labour, to any intermediate person effecting the transaction (commonly called a merchant): and whatever advantage there is on either side, and whatever pay is given to the intermediate person, should be thoroughly known to all concerned. All attempt at concealment implies some practice of the opposite, or undivine science, founded on nescience. Whence another saying of the Jew merchant's—"As a nail between the stone joints, so doth sin stick fast between buying and selling." Which peculiar riveting of stone and timber, in men's dealing with each other, is again set forth in the house which was to be destroyed—timber and stones together—when Zechariah's roll (more probably "curved sword") flew over it: "the curse that goeth forth over all the earth upon every one that stealeth and holdeth himself guiltless," instantly followed by the vision of the Great Measure;—the measure "of the injustice of them in all the earth" (αὔτη ἡ ἀδικία αὐτῶν ἐν πάσῇ τῇ γῃ), with the weight of lead for its lid, and the woman, the spirit of wickedness, within it;—that is to say, Wickedness hidden by Dulness, and formalized, outwardly, into ponderously established cruelty. "It shall be set upon its own base in the land on Babel."[53]

The basic rule about fair or efficient exchange is this: there should be benefits for both parties involved (or if only one benefits, the other shouldn't suffer). There needs to be a fair payment for the time, knowledge, and effort of anyone facilitating the exchange (usually called a merchant). Everyone involved should clearly understand the advantages on each side and the payment given to the middleman. Any attempt to hide this information suggests some form of dishonesty, rooted in ignorance. This is reflected in the saying of the Jewish merchant: "Just as a nail gets stuck between the joints of stone, sin gets caught between buying and selling." This specific connection between stone and timber in how people interact with one another is also illustrated in the house that was meant to be destroyed—timber and stones together—when Zechariah's scroll (or more likely "curved sword") flew over it: "the curse that travels across the earth against everyone who steals and believes they are innocent," immediately followed by the vision of the Great Measure;—the measure "of the injustice of them in all the earth" (αὔτη ἡ ἀδικία αὐτῶν ἐν πάσῇ τῇ γῃ), with a lead weight as its lid, and within it, a woman representing evil;—which means, evil hidden by ignorance, and formally transformed, outwardly, into heavy, established cruelty. "It shall be established on its own foundation in the land of Babel."

I have hitherto carefully restricted myself, in speaking of exchange, to the use of the term "advantage;" but that term includes two ideas: the advantage, namely, of getting what we need, and that of getting what we wish for. Three-fourths of the demands existing in the world are romantic; founded on visions, idealisms, hopes, and affections; and the regulation of the purse is, in its essence, regulation of the imagination and the heart. Hence, the right discussion of the nature of price is a very high metaphysical and psychical problem; sometimes to be solved only in a passionate manner, as by David in his counting the price of the water of the well by the gate of Bethlehem; but its first conditions are the following:—The price of anything is the quantity of labour given by the person desiring it, in order to obtain possession of it. This price depends on four variable quantities. A. The quantity of wish the purchaser has for the thing; opposed [Pg 187] to α, the quantity of wish the seller has to keep it. B. The quantity of labour the purchaser can afford, to obtain the thing; opposed to β, the quantity of labour the seller can afford, to keep it. These quantities are operative only in excess; i.e., the quantity of wish (A) means the quantity of wish for this thing, above wish for other things; and the quantity of work (B) means the quantity which can be spared to get this thing from the quantity needed to get other things.

I have so far carefully limited my discussion of exchange to the term "advantage," but that term covers two concepts: the advantage of getting what we need and the advantage of getting what we want. Most of the demands we see in the world are romantic, based on dreams, ideals, hopes, and emotions; managing our finances is essentially managing our imagination and feelings. Therefore, understanding the nature of price is a complex philosophical and psychological issue, sometimes only approachable with deep emotion, like David counting the price of the water from the well by the gate of Bethlehem. But the basic conditions are as follows: The price of anything is the amount of labor the person wanting it is willing to invest to obtain it. This price depends on four variable factors. A. The level of desire the buyer has for the item, opposed to α, the level of desire the seller has to keep it. B. The amount of labor the buyer can afford to spend to get the item, opposed to β, the amount of labor the seller can afford to keep it. These factors only come into play when in excess; i.e., the level of desire (A) refers to the desire for this item over the desire for other items; and the amount of labor (B) refers to what can be spared to acquire this item from the total needed to acquire other items.

Phenomena of price, therefore, are intensely complex, curious, and interesting—too complex, however, to be examined yet; every one of them, when traced far enough, showing itself at last as a part of the bargain of the Poor of the Flock (or "flock of slaughter"), "If ye think good, give ME my price, and if not, forbear"—Zech. xi. 12; but as the price of everything is to be calculated finally in labour, it is necessary to define the nature of that standard.

The concept of price is incredibly complex, intriguing, and interesting—too complex to dive into just yet; each instance, when followed far enough, ultimately revealing itself as part of the deal made by the Poor of the Flock (or "flock of slaughter"), "If you think it's a good idea, give ME my price, and if not, don't bother"—Zech. xi. 12; but since the price of everything must ultimately be measured in labor, it's essential to clarify what that standard means.

Labour is the contest of the life of man with an opposite:—the term "life" including his intellect, soul, and physical power, contending with question, difficulty, trial, or material force.

Labour is the struggle of a person's life against something opposing:—the term "life" encompasses their intellect, soul, and physical strength, fighting against questions, challenges, trials, or physical forces.

Labour is of a higher or lower order, as it includes more or fewer of the elements of life: and labour of good quality, in any kind, includes always as much intellect and feeling as will fully and harmoniously regulate the physical force.

Labour can be seen as having a higher or lower value, depending on how many of the essential qualities of life it involves. High-quality work, in any form, always includes a significant amount of intellect and emotion that effectively and harmoniously manages physical effort.

In speaking of the value and price of labour, it is necessary always to understand labour of a given rank and quality, as we should speak of gold or silver of a given standard. Bad (that is, heartless, inexperienced, or senseless) labour cannot be valued; it is like gold of uncertain alloy, or flawed iron.[54]

When talking about the value and cost of labor, it's important to always consider labor of a specific rank and quality, just like we would discuss gold or silver of a certain standard. Poor (meaning heartless, inexperienced, or foolish) labor can't be valued; it's like gold of uncertain mix or defective iron.[54]

The quality and kind of labour being given, its value, like that of all other valuable things, is invariable. But the [Pg 188] quantity of it which must be given for other things is variable: and in estimating this variation, the price of other things must always be counted by the quantity of labour; not the price of labour by the quantity of other things.

The quality and type of labor provided, its value, like that of all other valuable things, remains constant. However, the amount of it that must be exchanged for other things varies. When assessing this variation, the price of other items should always be measured by the amount of labor; not the price of labor by the amount of other items.

Thus, if we want to plant an apple sapling in rocky ground, it may take two hours' work; in soft ground, perhaps only half an hour. Grant the soil equally good for the tree in each case. Then the value of the sapling planted by two hours' work is nowise greater than that of the sapling planted in half an hour. One will bear no more fruit than the other. Also, one half-hour of work is as valuable as another half-hour; nevertheless the one sapling has cost four such pieces of work, the other only one. Now the proper statement of this fact is, not that the labour on the hard ground is cheaper than on the soft; but that the tree is dearer. The exchange value may, or may not, afterwards depend on this fact. If other people have plenty of soft ground to plant in, they will take no cognizance of our two hours' labour, in the price they will offer for the plant on the rock. And if, through want of sufficient botanical science, we have planted an upas-tree instead of an apple, the exchange value will be a negative quantity; still less proportionate to the labour expended.

So, if we want to plant an apple sapling in rocky soil, it might take two hours of work; in softer soil, maybe only half an hour. Assume the soil is just as good for the tree in both situations. Then the value of the sapling planted with two hours of work is not greater than that of the sapling planted in half an hour. One won't produce more fruit than the other. Also, one half-hour of work is as valuable as another half-hour; still, one sapling has taken four of those half-hours, while the other only took one. The real takeaway here is not that labor in the hard soil is cheaper than in the soft; it's that the tree is more expensive. The market value could depend on this later on. If other people have plenty of soft ground to use, they won’t consider our two hours of labor when deciding how much to pay for the plant on the rocky site. And if, due to a lack of sufficient botanical knowledge, we mistakenly plant an upas tree instead of an apple tree, the market value will be negative; even less in line with the labor put in.

What is commonly called cheapness of labour, signifies, therefore, in reality, that many obstacles have to be overcome by it; so that much labour is required to produce a small result. But this should never be spoken of as cheapness of labour, but as dearness of the object wrought for. It would be just as rational to say that walking was cheap, because we had ten miles to walk home to our dinner, as that labour was cheap, because we had to work ten hours to earn it.

What we usually refer to as cheap labor actually means that there are many challenges that it has to deal with; thus, a lot of work is needed to achieve a small outcome. However, this shouldn’t be described as cheap labor, but rather as the high cost of the thing being produced. It would be just as sensible to claim that walking is cheap just because we have to walk ten miles home for dinner, as it is to say that labor is cheap because we need to work ten hours to earn it.

The last word which we have to define is "Production."

The final term we need to define is "Production."

I have hitherto spoken of all labour as profitable; because it is impossible to consider under one head the quality or value of labour, and its aim. But labour of the best quality may be various in aim. It may be either constructive [Pg 189]("gathering," from con and struo), as agriculture; nugatory, as jewel-cutting; or destructive ("scattering," from de and struo), as war. It is not, however, always easy to prove labour, apparently nugatory, to be actually so;[55] generally, the formula holds good, "he that gathereth not, scattereth;" thus, the jeweller's art is probably very harmful in its ministering to a clumsy and inelegant pride. So that, finally, I believe nearly all labour may be shortly divided into positive and negative labour: positive, that which produces life; negative, that which produces death; the most directly negative labour being murder, and the most directly positive, the bearing and rearing of children: so that in the precise degree in which murder is hateful, on the negative side of idleness, in that exact degree child-rearing is admirable, on the positive side of idleness. For which reason, and because of the honour that there is in rearing[56] children, while the wife is said to be as the vine (for cheering), the children are as the olive-branch, for praise; nor for praise only, but for peace (because large families can only be reared in times of peace): though since, in their spreading and voyaging in various directions, they distribute strength, they are, to the home strength, as arrows in the hand of the giant—striking here and there, far away.

I’ve talked about all work being valuable so far; because it’s impossible to group together the quality or value of work and its purpose. But high-quality work can have different goals. It can be constructive [Pg 189] (like agriculture); unproductive, like jewel-cutting; or destructive (like war). However, it's not always easy to prove that seemingly unproductive work is truly so; generally, the saying holds, “he who doesn’t gather, scatters;” thus, the craft of jewel-making may actually contribute to unrefined pride. So in the end, I think most work can be broadly categorized into positive and negative labor: positive work creates life; negative work causes death, with murder being the most extreme form of negative labor and raising children the most commendable form of positive labor. In this way, the more we detest murder, which represents the negative side of idleness, the more we admire child-rearing, which is on the positive side. That’s why, because of the honor associated with raising children, while the wife is compared to a vine (for support), children are like olive branches, symbolizing praise; not just for praise, but for peace (since large families can only thrive in peaceful times); and as they spread out and travel in different directions, they distribute strength, acting like arrows in the hand of a giant—striking far and wide.

Labour being thus various in its result, the prosperity of [Pg 190] any nation is in exact proportion to the quantity of labour which it spends in obtaining and employing means of life. Observe,—I say, obtaining and employing; that is to say, not merely wisely producing, but wisely distributing and consuming. Economists usually speak as if there were no good in consumption absolute.[57] So far from this being so, consumption absolute is the end, crown, and perfection of production; and wise consumption is a far more difficult art than wise production. Twenty people can gain money for one who can use it; and the vital question, for individual and for nation, is, never "how much do they make?" but "to what purpose do they spend?"

Labour varies in its outcomes, so the prosperity of any nation directly relates to the amount of labour it invests in obtaining and using resources for living. Notice, I mean obtaining and using; that is, not just producing wisely, but also distributing and consuming wisely. Economists often talk as if consumption has no real value. In reality, consumption is the ultimate goal, the peak, and the completion of production; and consuming wisely is a much more challenging skill than producing wisely. Twenty people can earn money for every one who knows how to use it; the crucial question for individuals and nations isn't "how much do they make?" but "how do they spend it?"

The reader may, perhaps, have been surprised at the slight reference I have hitherto made to "capital," and its functions. It is here the place to define them.

The reader might be a bit surprised by the minimal mention I've made so far about "capital" and what it does. This is the right moment to clarify those terms.

Capital signifies "head, or source, or root material"—it is material by which some derivative or secondary good is produced. It is only capital proper (caput vivum, not caput mortuum) when it is thus producing something different from itself. It is a root, which does not enter into vital function till it produces something else than a root; namely, fruit. That fruit will in time again produce roots; and so all living capital issues in reproduction of capital; but capital which produces nothing but capital is only root producing root; bulb issuing in bulb, never in tulip; seed issuing in seed, never in bread. The Political Economy of Europe has hitherto devoted itself wholly to the multiplication, or (less even) the aggregation, of bulbs. It never saw, nor conceived such a thing as a tulip. Nay, boiled bulbs they might have been—glass bulbs—Prince Rupert's drops, consummated in powder (well, if it were glass-powder and not gunpowder), for any end or meaning the economists had in defining the laws of aggregation. We will try and get a clearer notion of them.

Capital means "head, source, or root material"—it's the material used to create some kind of secondary good. It is considered true capital (caput vivum, not caput mortuum) only when it produces something different from itself. It's like a root that doesn't serve a purpose until it generates something beyond a root; specifically, fruit. Over time, that fruit will again produce roots; so all living capital leads to the reproduction of capital. However, capital that only creates more capital is simply a root growing roots; a bulb producing a bulb, but never a tulip; a seed yielding a seed, but never bread. The Political Economy of Europe has so far focused entirely on the increase, or even less so, the gathering, of bulbs. It has never recognized or imagined something like a tulip. In fact, they might as well have been boiled bulbs—glass bulbs—Prince Rupert's drops, ultimately reduced to powder (ideally glass powder, not gunpowder), considering the purpose or meaning the economists had in outlining the laws of aggregation. We will attempt to clarify this further.

The best and simplest general type of capital is a well-made ploughshare. Now, if that ploughshare did nothing but beget[Pg 191] other ploughshares, in a polypous manner,—however the great cluster of polypous plough might glitter in the sun, it would have lost its function of capital. It becomes true capital only by another kind of splendour,—when it is seen "splendescere sulco," to grow bright in the furrow; rather with diminution of its substance, than addition, by the noble friction. And the true home question, to every capitalist and to every nation, is not, "how many ploughs have you?" but, "where are your furrows?" not—"how quickly will this capital reproduce itself?"—but, "what will it do during reproduction?" What substance will it furnish, good for life? what work construct, protective of life? if none, its own reproduction is useless—if worse than none (for capital may destroy life as well as support it), its own reproduction is worse than useless; it is merely an advance from Tisiphone, on mortgage—not a profit by any means.

The best and simplest kind of capital is a well-made ploughshare. Now, if that ploughshare only produced[Pg 191] other ploughshares, in a never-ending cycle—no matter how impressive the group of ploughs might look in the sun, it would have lost its purpose as capital. It truly becomes capital only through another kind of brilliance—when it is seen "shining in the furrow," growing brighter in the soil; rather through a reduction of its material than an increase, from the noble wear and tear. The key question for every capitalist and every nation is not, "how many ploughs do you have?" but, "where are your furrows?" not—"how quickly will this capital replicate itself?"—but, "what will it accomplish during that process?" What tangible benefits will it provide for life? What work will it create to protect life? If it offers nothing, its reproduction is pointless—if it does more harm than good (because capital can harm life as well as support it), its reproduction is worse than pointless; it's just a loan from Tisiphone on credit—not a profit by any means.

Not a profit, as the ancients truly saw, and showed in the type of Ixion;—for capital is the head, or fountain head, of wealth—the "well-head" of wealth, as the clouds are the well-heads of rain: but when clouds are without water, and only beget clouds, they issue in wrath at last, instead of rain, and in lightning instead of harvest; whence Ixion is said first to have invited his guests to a banquet, and then made them fall into a pit filled with fire; which is the type of the temptation of riches issuing in imprisoned torment,—torment in a pit (as also Demas' silver mine), after which, to show the rage of riches passing from lust of pleasure to lust of power, yet power not truly understood, Ixion is said to have desired Juno, and instead, embracing a cloud (or phantasm), to have begotten the Centaurs; the power of mere wealth being, in itself, as the embrace of a shadow,—comfortless (so also "Ephraim feedeth on wind and followeth after the east wind"; or "that which is not"—Prov. xxiii. 5; and again Dante's Geryon, the type of avaricious fraud, as he flies, gathers the air up with retractile claws,—"l'aer a se raccolse"[58]), but in its offspring, [Pg 192] a mingling of the brutal with the human nature: human in sagacity—using both intellect and arrow; but brutal in its body and hoof, for consuming, and trampling down. For which sin Ixion is at last bound upon a wheel—fiery and toothed, and rolling perpetually in the air;—the type of human labour when selfish and fruitless (kept far into the middle ages in their wheel of fortune); the wheel which has in it no breath or spirit, but is whirled by chance only; whereas of all true work the Ezekiel vision is true, that the Spirit of the living creature is in the wheels, and where the angels go, the wheels go by them; but move no otherwise.

Not a profit, as the ancients rightly understood and demonstrated in the figure of Ixion; for capital is the source, or fountainhead, of wealth—the "well-head" of wealth, just as clouds are the well-heads of rain. But when clouds lack water and only produce more clouds, they ultimately lead to anger instead of rain, and to lightning rather than harvest. This is why Ixion is said to have invited his guests to a feast, only to have them fall into a pit filled with fire; this symbolizes the temptation of wealth resulting in trapped torment—torment in a pit, like Demas' silver mine. Then to illustrate the fury of wealth shifting from the desire for pleasure to the desire for power, though a power that isn’t truly understood, Ixion is said to have desired Juno and instead embraced a cloud (or illusion), resulting in the birth of the Centaurs. The power of mere wealth is, in essence, like embracing a shadow—comfortless (also like "Ephraim feeds on wind and follows after the east wind," or "that which is not"—Prov. xxiii. 5; and again Dante's Geryon, the embodiment of greedy fraud, as he flies, gathers the air with retractable claws,—"l'aer a se raccolse"[58]). Yet in its offspring, there is a mixture of the brutal with human nature: human in cunning—using both intellect and arrows; but brutal in its body and hooves, for consuming and trampling. For this sin, Ixion is ultimately bound to a fiery, toothed wheel, continually rolling through the air; a symbol of human effort when selfish and fruitless (further perpetuated into the Middle Ages in their wheel of fortune); a wheel that contains no breath or spirit, but is only spun by chance. In contrast, true work aligns with Ezekiel's vision, where the Spirit of the living creature is in the wheels, and wherever the angels go, the wheels follow them; but they do not move in any other way.

This being the real nature of capital, it follows that there are two kinds of true production, always going on in an active State; one of seed, and one of food; or production for the Ground, and for the Mouth; both of which are by covetous persons thought to be production only for the granary; whereas the function of the granary is but intermediate and conservative, fulfilled in distribution; else it ends in nothing but mildew, and nourishment of rats and worms. And since production for the Ground is only useful with future hope of harvest, all essential production is for the Mouth; and is finally measured by the mouth; hence, as I said above, consumption is the crown of production; and the wealth of a nation is only to be estimated by what it consumes.

This is the true nature of capital, so it's clear that there are two types of real production constantly happening in an active state: one for seeds and one for food; or production for the ground and for consumption. Greedy individuals often see this as production only for the granary, but the granary's role is just to act as a temporary storage and distribution point. If not managed properly, it leads to nothing but rot and becomes a source for pests. And since production for the ground is only valuable if there's a hope for future harvest, all essential production is ultimately for consumption; it is measured by what is consumed. Therefore, as I mentioned earlier, consumption is the ultimate goal of production, and a nation's wealth should be evaluated based on its consumption.

The want of any clear sight of this fact is the capital error, issuing in rich interest and revenue of error among the political economists. Their minds are continually set on money-gain, not on mouth-gain; and they fall into every sort of net and snare, dazzled by the coin-glitter as birds by the fowler's glass; or rather (for there is not much else like birds in them) they [Pg 193]are like children trying to jump on the heads of their own shadows; the money-gain being only the shadow of the true gain, which is humanity.

The lack of any clear understanding of this fact is the main mistake, leading to significant errors and misguided profits among economists. Their focus is constantly on making money, not on real nourishment; and they get caught in all kinds of traps, dazzled by the shine of coins, just like birds are by the hunter's glass; or rather (since they aren't really much like birds), they are like children trying to jump on the heads of their own shadows; the money they chase is only the shadow of the true benefit, which is humanity.

The final object of political economy, therefore, is to get good method of consumption, and great quantity of consumption: in other words, to use everything, and to use it nobly; whether it be substance, service, or service perfecting substance. The most curious error in Mr. Mill's entire work (provided for him originally by Ricardo) is his endeavour to distinguish between direct and indirect service, and consequent assertion that a demand for commodities is not demand for labour (I. v. 9, et seq.). He distinguishes between labourers employed to lay out pleasure grounds, and to manufacture velvet; declaring that it makes material difference to the labouring classes in which of these two ways a capitalist spends his money; because the employment of the gardeners is a demand for labour, but the purchase of velvet is not.[59] Error colossal as well as strange. It will, indeed, make a difference to the labourer whether we bid him swing his scythe in the spring winds, or drive the loom in pestilential air; but, so far as his pocket is concerned, it makes to him absolutely no difference whether we order him to make green velvet, with seed and a scythe, or red velvet, with silk and scissors. Neither does it anywise concern him whether, [Pg 194] when the velvet is made, we consume it by walking on it, or wearing it, so long as our consumption of it is wholly selfish. But if our consumption is to be in any wise unselfish, not only our mode of consuming the articles we require interests him, but also the kind of article we require with a view to consumption. As thus (returning for a moment to Mr. Mill's great hardware theory[60]): it matters, so far as the labourer's immediate profit is concerned, not an iron filing whether I employ him in growing a peach, or forging a bombshell; but my probable mode of consumption of those articles matters seriously. Admit that it is to be in both cases "unselfish," and the difference, to him, is final, whether when his child is ill, I walk into his cottage and give it the peach, or drop the shell down his chimney, and blow his roof off.

The main goal of political economy is to figure out the best way to consume goods and to consume a lot of them. In other words, it’s about using everything well, whether it’s a product, a service, or a service that enhances a product. One of the most puzzling mistakes in Mr. Mill's entire work (initially pointed out by Ricardo) is his attempt to differentiate between direct and indirect services, leading him to claim that demand for goods isn’t the same as demand for labor (I. v. 9, et seq.). He makes a distinction between workers who design parks and those who produce velvet, arguing that it significantly affects laborers which way a capitalist spends his money; because hiring gardeners represents a demand for labor, while buying velvet does not.[59] This is a colossal and strange error. It definitely matters to a laborer whether we tell him to work in the fields on a nice spring day or in a stuffy room at a factory; but when it comes to his earnings, it doesn’t make a difference whether we ask him to create green velvet with seeds and a scythe or red velvet with silk and scissors. It also doesn’t matter to him whether, once the velvet is produced, we use it by walking on it or wearing it, as long as our usage is purely self-serving. However, if our consumption is to be in any way generous, not only does the way we use the items we need matter to him, but also the type of item we choose for consumption. To illustrate this (returning for a moment to Mr. Mill's main hardware theory[60]): in terms of immediate profit for the laborer, it doesn’t matter at all whether I have him grow a peach or manufacture a bombshell; but my likely method of consuming those items does matter quite a bit. If we admit that the consumption in both cases is “unselfish,” then it makes a significant difference to him whether, when his child is sick, I enter his home and hand him the peach or drop the bombshell down his chimney and blow off his roof.

The worst of it, for the peasant, is, that the capitalist's consumption of the peach is apt to be selfish, and of the shell, distributive;[61] but, in all cases, this is the broad and general fact, that on due catallactic commercial principles, somebody's [Pg 195] roof must go off in fulfilment of the bomb's destiny. You may grow for your neighbour, at your liking, grapes or grapeshot; he will also, catallactically, grow grapes or grapeshot for you, and you will each reap what you have sown.

The worst part for the peasant is that the capitalist's enjoyment of the peach tends to be selfish, while the shell's is shared; [61] but, in all circumstances, this is the clear and overarching truth: based on proper commercial principles, someone's [Pg 195] roof has to come off to fulfill the bomb's purpose. You can grow grapes or grapeshot for your neighbor, as you prefer; he will also, commercially, grow grapes or grapeshot for you, and you will both reap what you have planted.

It is, therefore, the manner and issue of consumption which are the real tests of production. Production does not consist in things laboriously made, but in things serviceably consumable; and the question for the nation is not how much labour it employs, but how much life it produces. For as consumption is the end and aim of production, so life is the end and aim of consumption.

It’s, therefore, the way and the results of consumption that are the real measures of production. Production isn’t just about things being made with effort; it’s about things that are useful for consumption. The question for the nation isn’t how much labor it uses, but how much life it creates. Just as consumption is the purpose of production, life is the purpose of consumption.

I left this question to the reader's thought two months ago, choosing rather that he should work it out for himself than have it sharply stated to him. But now, the ground being sufficiently broken (and the details into which the several questions, here opened, must lead us, being too complex for discussion in the pages of a periodical, so that I must pursue them elsewhere), I desire, in closing the series of introductory papers, to leave this one great fact clearly stated. There is no Wealth but Life. Life, including all its powers of love, of joy, and of admiration. That country is the richest which nourishes the greatest number of noble and happy human beings; that man is richest who, having perfected the functions of his own life to the utmost, has also the widest helpful influence, both personal and by means of his possessions, over the lives of others.

I left this question for the reader to ponder two months ago, preferring that they figure it out themselves rather than have it bluntly laid out for them. However, now that the groundwork has been established (and the details surrounding the various questions raised are too intricate to discuss in a periodical, so I'll address them elsewhere), I want to conclude this series of introductory papers by clearly stating one important fact. Wealth is nothing without life. Life, which includes all its capacities for love, joy, and admiration. The richest country is the one that nurtures the largest number of noble and happy individuals; the richest person is the one who, having maximized their own life's potential, also has the broadest positive impact—both personally and through their resources—on the lives of others.

A strange political economy; the only one, nevertheless, that ever was or can be: all political economy founded on self-interest[62] being but the fulfilment of that which once brought schism into the Policy of angels, and ruin into the Economy of Heaven.

A strange political economy; the only one that ever was or can be: all political economy based on self-interest[62] is just a reflection of what once caused division in the policy of angels and destruction in the economy of heaven.

"The greatest number of human beings noble and happy." But is the nobleness consistent with the number? Yes, not only consistent with it, but essential to it. The maximum of life can only be reached by the maximum of virtue. In this respect the law of human population differs wholly from [Pg 196] that of animal life. The multiplication of animals is checked only by want of food, and by the hostility of races; the population of the gnat is restrained by the hunger of the swallow, and that of the swallow by the scarcity of gnats. Man, considered as an animal, is indeed limited by the same laws: hunger, or plague, or war, are the necessary and only restraints upon his increase,—effectual restraints hitherto,—his principal study having been how most swiftly to destroy himself, or ravage his dwelling-places, and his highest skill directed to give range to the famine, seed to the plague, and sway to the sword. But, considered as other than an animal, his increase is not limited by these laws. It is limited only by the limits of his courage and his love. Both of these have their bounds; and ought to have: his race has its bounds also; but these have not yet been reached, nor will be reached for ages.

"The greatest number of human beings noble and happy." But is nobleness aligned with the number? Yes, it’s not only aligned with it but crucial to it. The highest level of life can only be achieved through the highest level of virtue. In this sense, the law of human population is completely different from that of animal life. The growth of animal populations is limited only by the lack of food and by competition between species; for example, the population of gnats is limited by the hunger of swallows, and that of swallows by the shortage of gnats. When we think of humans as animals, they are indeed subject to the same laws: hunger, disease, or war are the necessary and only restrictions on their growth—effective restrictions so far—since their main focus has often been on how to quickly destroy themselves or devastate their environments, with their greatest skills aimed at exacerbating famine, sowing disease, and wielding weapons. However, when we think of humans as more than just animals, their growth is not constrained by these laws. It is limited only by their courage and their love. Both of these have their limits; and they should. Humanity also has its limits; however, these have not yet been reached, nor will they be for a long time.

In all the ranges of human thought I know none so melancholy as the speculations of political economists on the population question. It is proposed to better the condition of the labourer by giving him higher wages. "Nay," says the economist, "if you raise his wages, he will either drag people down to the same point of misery at which you found him, or drink your wages away." He will. I know it. Who gave him this will? Suppose it were your own son of whom you spoke, declaring to me that you dared not take him into your firm, nor even give him his just labourer's wages, because if you did, he would die of drunkenness, and leave half a score of children to the parish. "Who gave your son these dispositions?"—I should inquire. Has he them by inheritance or by education? By one or other they must come; and as in him, so also in the poor. Either these poor are of a race essentially different from ours, and unredeemable (which, however often implied, I have heard none yet openly say), or else by such care as we have ourselves received, we may make them continent and sober as ourselves—wise and dispassionate as we are—models arduous of imitation. "But," it is answered, "they cannot receive education." Why not? That is precisely the point at issue. Charitable persons suppose the worst fault of the rich is to refuse the people meat; and the[Pg 197] people cry for their meat, kept back by fraud, to the Lord of Multitudes.[63] Alas! it is not meat of which the refusal is cruelest, or to which the claim is validest. The life is more than the meat. The rich not only refuse food to the poor; they refuse wisdom; they refuse virtue; they refuse salvation. Ye sheep without shepherd, it is not the pasture that has been shut from you, but the presence. Meat! perhaps your right to that may be pleadable; but other rights have to be pleaded first. Claim your crumbs from the table, if you will; but claim them as children, not as dogs; claim your right to be fed, but claim more loudly your right to be holy, perfect, and pure.

In all the areas of human thought, I can't think of any that are as sad as the discussions of political economists about population. They suggest improving workers' lives by raising their wages. "No," says the economist, "if you increase his wages, he will either drag others down to the same level of misery he’s at, or drink away your money." He will. I know it. Who gave him this will? Imagine if it were your own son you were talking about, saying you couldn't hire him or even pay him what he deserves because if you did, he would drink himself to death and leave behind several children for the state to support. "Who gave your son these tendencies?"—I would ask. Did he inherit them or learn them? They have to come from one of those; and just like him, so do the poor. Either these poor people are fundamentally different from us and beyond saving (which I've heard implied but never openly stated), or with the same care we received, we can teach them to be sober and disciplined like us—wise and rational figures worth emulating. "But," it’s replied, "they can’t be educated." Why not? That’s exactly what we’re debating. Well-meaning people think the biggest problem with the rich is that they deny the poor food; and the poor cry out for their food, held back by deceit, to the Lord of Multitudes. Alas! the cruelest refusal isn’t of food, nor is it the most legitimate claim. Life is more important than food. The rich not only deny the poor nourishment; they deny them wisdom; they deny them virtue; they deny them salvation. You sheep without a shepherd, it’s not just the food that’s been kept from you, but the connection. Food! Maybe you can argue your right to that; but other rights must be claimed first. Demand your scraps from the table if you must; but ask as children, not as dogs; demand your right to be fed, but more loudly demand your right to be holy, perfect, and pure.

Strange words to be used of working people: "What! holy; without any long robes nor anointing oils; these rough-jacketed, rough-worded persons set to nameless and dishonoured service? Perfect!—these, with dim eyes and cramped limbs, and slowly wakening minds? Pure!—these, [Pg 198] with sensual desire and grovelling thought; foul of body, and coarse of soul?" It may be so; nevertheless, such as they are, they are the holiest, perfectest, purest persons the earth can at present show. They may be what you have said; but if so, they yet are holier than we, who have left them thus.

Strange words to describe working people: "What! Holy; without any long robes or anointing oils; these rough-coated, rough-talking individuals assigned to nameless and dishonorable jobs? Perfect!—these, with dull eyes and stiff limbs, and slowly waking minds? Pure!—these, with lustful desires and lowly thoughts; dirty bodies, and coarse souls?" It might be true; still, just as they are, they are the holiest, most perfect, and purest people the earth has to offer right now. They may be what you’ve said; but if that’s the case, they are still holier than us, who have abandoned them.

But what can be done for them? Who can clothe—who teach—who restrain their multitudes? What end can there be for them at last, but to consume one another?

But what can be done for them? Who can provide clothes—who can teach—who can control their masses? What can their ultimate fate be, if not to devour one another?

I hope for another end, though not, indeed, from any of the three remedies for over-population commonly suggested by economists.

I hope for a different solution, but not from any of the three remedies for overpopulation that economists usually suggest.

These three are, in brief—Colonization; Bringing in of waste lands; or Discouragement of Marriage.

These three are, in short—Colonization; Reclaiming wastelands; or Discouraging Marriage.

The first and second of these expedients merely evade or delay the question. It will, indeed, be long before the world has been all colonized, and its deserts all brought under cultivation. But the radical question is not how much habitable land is in the world, but how many human beings ought to be maintained on a given space of habitable land.

The first and second of these solutions just dodge or postpone the issue. It will certainly take a long time before everything in the world has been colonized and all the barren areas cultivated. But the fundamental question isn't about how much livable land exists in the world; it's about how many people should be supported in a specific area of habitable land.

Observe, I say, ought to be, not how many can be. Ricardo, with his usual inaccuracy, defines what he calls the "natural rate of wages" as "that which will maintain the labourer." Maintain him! yes; but how?—the question was instantly thus asked of me by a working girl, to whom I read the passage. I will amplify her question for her. "Maintain him, how?" As, first, to what length of life? Out of a given number of fed persons how many are to be old—how many young; that is to say, will you arrange their maintenance so as to kill them early—say at thirty or thirty-five on the average, including deaths of weakly or ill-fed children?—or so as to enable them to live out a natural life? You will feed a greater number, in the first case,[64] by rapidity of succession; probably a happier number in the second: which does Mr. Ricardo mean to be their natural state, and to which state belongs the natural rate of wages?

Look, I say, ought to be, not how many can be. Ricardo, with his usual inaccuracy, defines what he calls the "natural rate of wages" as "that which will sustain the worker." Sustain him! Yes; but how?—this question was immediately raised by a working girl to whom I read the passage. I'll expand her question for her. "Sustain him, how?" First, to what age? Out of a certain number of fed people, how many will be old—how many young; in other words, will you arrange their support in a way that causes early deaths—let's say at thirty or thirty-five on average, including deaths of weakly or poorly-fed children?—or in a way that allows them to live a full life? You will feed a larger number in the first scenario,[64] through quick succession; probably a happier number in the second: which state does Mr. Ricardo consider to be their natural state, and to which state does the natural rate of wages belong?

Again: A piece of land which will only support ten idle, ignorant, and improvident persons, will support thirty or forty [Pg 199] intelligent and industrious ones. Which of these is their natural state, and to which of them belongs the natural rate of wages?

Again: A piece of land that can only sustain ten lazy, uninformed, and careless people can support thirty or forty [Pg 199] smart and hardworking individuals. Which of these is their natural condition, and to which of them does the natural wage rate belong?

Again: If a piece of land support forty persons in industrious ignorance; and if, tired of this ignorance, they set apart ten of their number to study the properties of cones, and the sizes of stars; the labour of these ten, being withdrawn from the ground, must either tend to the increase of food in some transitional manner, or the persons set apart for sidereal and conic purposes must starve, or some one else starve instead of them. What is, therefore, the natural rate of wages of the scientific persons, and how does this rate relate to, or measure, their reverted or transitional productiveness?

Again: If a piece of land can support forty people in hardworking ignorance, and if, fed up with this ignorance, they assign ten of them to study the properties of cones and the sizes of stars; the work of these ten, being taken away from farming, must either lead to increased food production in some way, or the people studying stars and shapes will starve, or someone else will starve in their place. So, what is the natural wage rate for these scientists, and how does this rate connect to or reflect their temporary or eventual productivity?

Again: If the ground maintains, at first, forty labourers in a peaceable and pious state of mind, but they become in a few years so quarrelsome and impious that they have to set apart five, to meditate upon and settle their disputes; ten, armed to the teeth with costly instruments, to enforce the decisions; and five to remind everybody in an eloquent manner of the existence of a God;—what will be the result upon the general power of production, and what is the "natural rate of wages" of the meditative, muscular, and oracular labourers?

Again: If the land supports, at first, forty workers in a calm and devout state of mind, but they become so argumentative and irreverent in a few years that they need to set aside five to reflect on and resolve their conflicts; ten, fully armed with expensive tools, to enforce the decisions; and five to eloquently remind everyone about the existence of God;—what will be the impact on overall productivity, and what is the "natural rate of wages" for the reflective, strong, and persuasive workers?

Leaving these questions to be discussed, or waived, at their pleasure, by Mr. Ricardo's followers, I proceed to state the main facts bearing on that probable future of the labouring classes which has been partially glanced at by Mr. Mill. That chapter and the preceding one differ from the common writing of political economists in admitting some value in the aspect of nature, and expressing regret at the probability of the destruction of natural scenery. But we may spare our anxieties, on this head. Men can neither drink steam, nor eat stone. The maximum of population on a given space of land implies also the relative maximum of edible vegetable, whether for men or cattle; it implies a maximum of pure air; and of pure water. Therefore: a maximum of wood, to transmute the air, and of sloping ground, protected by herbage from the extreme heat of the sun, to feed the streams. All England may, if it so chooses, become one manufacturing[Pg 200] town; and Englishmen, sacrificing themselves to the good of general humanity, may live diminished lives in the midst of noise, of darkness, and of deadly exhalation. But the world cannot become a factory, nor a mine. No amount of ingenuity will ever make iron digestible by the million, nor substitute hydrogen for wine. Neither the avarice nor the rage of men will ever feed them, and however the apple of Sodom and the grape of Gomorrah may spread their table for a time with dainties of ashes, and nectar of asps,—so long as men live by bread, the far away valleys must laugh as they are covered with the gold of God, and the shouts of His happy multitudes ring round the winepress and the well.

Leaving these questions to be discussed or ignored as Mr. Ricardo's followers see fit, I will now lay out the key facts regarding the likely future of the working classes, which Mr. Mill has partially touched upon. That chapter and the one before it stand apart from the typical works of political economists by acknowledging some value in the beauty of nature and expressing regret over the expected loss of natural scenery. However, we can ease our worries about this. People can't drink steam or eat stone. The maximum population that can thrive on a piece of land also means there’s a limit to the amount of edible plants available for both people and animals; it means there’s a limit on clean air and pure water. Thus, there’s also a cap on the amount of wood to purify the air, and on sloping land, which, shielded by grass from the sun's extreme heat, nourishes the streams. All of England could, if it wanted, turn into one massive manufacturing city; and the English could give up their own well-being for the sake of humanity, living reduced lives amid noise, darkness, and harmful fumes. But the world can’t be just a factory or a mine. No matter how creative people get, they can’t make iron edible for millions, nor can they replace wine with hydrogen. Neither greed nor anger will ever provide sustenance; and just as the apple of Sodom and the grape of Gomorrah may temporarily offer a feast of ashes and nectar of asps, as long as people rely on bread, the distant valleys will continue to flourish under the blessings of God, while the joyful voices of His happy crowds resound around the winepress and the well.

Nor need our more sentimental economists fear the too wide spread of the formalities of a mechanical agriculture. The presence of a wise population implies the search for felicity as well as for food; nor can any population reach its maximum but through that wisdom which "rejoices" in the habitable parts of the earth. The desert has its appointed place and work; the eternal engine, whose beam is the earth's axle, whose beat is its year, and whose breath is its ocean, will still divide imperiously to their desert kingdoms, bound with unfurrowable rock, and swept by unarrested sand, their powers of frost and fire: but the zones and lands between, habitable, will be loveliest in habitation. The desire of the heart is also the light of the eyes. No scene is continually and untiringly loved, but one rich by joyful human labour; smooth in field; fair in garden; full in orchard; trim, sweet, and frequent in homestead; ringing with voices of vivid existence. No air is sweet that is silent; it is only sweet when full of low currents of under sound—triplets of birds, and murmur and chirp of insects, and deep-toned words of men, and wayward trebles of childhood. As the art of life is learned, it will be found at last that all lovely things are also necessary:—the wild flower by the wayside, as well as the tended corn; and the wild birds and creatures of the forest, as well as the tended cattle; because man doth not live by bread only, but also by the desert manna; by every wondrous word and unknowable work of God. Happy, in that he knew them not, nor did his[Pg 201] fathers know; and that round about him reaches yet into the infinite, the amazement of his existence.

Nor should our more sentimental economists worry about the extensive use of the formalities of a mechanical agriculture. The presence of an insightful population suggests a pursuit of happiness as well as sustenance; no population can reach its fullest potential without that wisdom which "rejoices" in the livable areas of the earth. The desert has its designated role and purpose; the eternal mechanism, whose beam is the earth's axis, whose rhythm is its year, and whose breath is its ocean, will still demand that their desert territories, bound by unyielding rock and swept by unrestrained sand, receive their forces of frost and fire: but the zones and lands in between, which can be inhabited, will be most beautiful for living in. The desires of the heart are also the light of the eyes. No scene is endlessly and tirelessly loved, but one enriched by joyful human effort; smooth in fields; beautiful in gardens; abundant in orchards; neat, sweet, and welcoming in homes; ringing with the sounds of vibrant life. No air is sweet when it's silent; it becomes sweet only when filled with soft sounds—trills of birds, the murmur and chirp of insects, the deep-toned voices of people, and the playful notes of children. As the skill of living is mastered, it will eventually be realized that all beautiful things are also essential: the wildflower by the roadside, as well as the cultivated crops; the wild birds and creatures of the forest, as well as the domesticated livestock; because man does not live by bread alone, but also by the manna of the desert; by every marvelous word and unfathomable work of God. He is fortunate, in that he did not know them, nor did his[Pg 201] ancestors know; and that around him still reaches into the infinite, the wonder of his existence.

Note, finally, that all effectual advancement towards this true felicity of the human race must be by individual, not public effort. Certain general measures may aid, certain revised laws guide, such advancement; but the measure and law which have first to be determined are those of each man's home. We continually hear it recommended by sagacious people to complaining neighbours (usually less well placed in the world than themselves), that they should "remain content in the station in which Providence has placed them." There are perhaps some circumstances of life in which Providence has no intention that people should be content. Nevertheless, the maxim is on the whole a good one; but it is peculiarly for home use. That your neighbour should, or should not, remain content with his position, is not your business; but it is very much your business to remain content with your own. What is chiefly needed in England at the present day is to show the quantity of pleasure that may be obtained by a consistent, well-administered competence, modest, confessed, and laborious. We need examples of people who, leaving Heaven to decide whether they are to rise in the world, decide for themselves that they will be happy in it, and have resolved to seek—not greater wealth, but simpler pleasure; not higher fortune, but deeper felicity; making the first of possessions, self-possession; and honouring themselves in the harmless pride and calm pursuits of peace.

Note, finally, that all effective progress towards true happiness for humanity must come from individuals, not collective efforts. Some general initiatives may help, and some updated laws may guide such progress; however, the measures and laws that first need to be established are those for each person’s home. We often hear wise people advising complaining neighbors (usually those who are less fortunate) to "stay content in the position where Providence has placed them." There may be certain life circumstances where Providence doesn’t intend for people to be content. Still, the saying is generally a good one; but it’s especially meant for personal situations. Whether your neighbor should or shouldn’t be satisfied with his position is not your concern; instead, it’s essential for you to be satisfied with your own. What is primarily needed in England today is to demonstrate how much happiness can be gained from a steady, well-managed lifestyle that is modest, acknowledged, and hard-working. We need examples of people who, leaving it to fate to decide if they will advance in life, choose to be happy where they are and have made the decision to seek—not greater wealth, but simpler joys; not higher status, but deeper happiness; making self-control the most valuable possession; and respecting themselves in the innocent pride and peaceful pursuits of a fulfilling life.

Of which lowly peace it is written that "justice and peace have kissed each other;" and that the fruit of justice is "sown in peace of them that make peace"; not "peace-makers" in the common understanding—reconcilers of quarrels; (though that function also follows on the greater one;) but peace-Creators; Givers of Calm. Which you cannot give, unless you first gain; nor is this gain one which will follow assuredly on any course of business, commonly so called. No form of gain is less probable, business being (as is shown in the language of all nations—πωλεῖν from πέλω, πρᾶσις from περάω, venire, vendre, and venal, from venio, etc.) essentially restless—and probably contentious;—having a raven-like [Pg 202] mind to the motion to and fro, as to the carrion food; whereas the olive-feeding and bearing birds look for rest for their feet: thus it is said of Wisdom that she "hath builded her house, and hewn out her seven pillars;" and even when, though apt to wait long at the doorposts, she has to leave her house and go abroad, her paths are peace also.

Of the humble peace it is said that "justice and peace have kissed each other;" and that the result of justice is "sown in the peace of those who make peace"; not "peace-makers" in the usual sense—settlers of disputes; (though that role also follows from the greater one;) but peace-Creators; Givers of Calm. You cannot give this unless you first possess it; and this possession is not something that will definitely follow from any typical business endeavor. No type of profit is less likely, business being (as demonstrated in the language of all nations—πωλεῖν from πέλω, πρᾶσις from περάω, venire, vendre, and venal, from venio, etc.) fundamentally restless—and likely contentious;—having a raven-like [Pg 202] mind, constantly moving back and forth, as if drawn to the carcass; while the olive-eating and bearing birds seek rest for their feet: thus it is said of Wisdom that she "has built her house and hewn out her seven pillars;" and even when, although she may wait long at the door, she has to leave her house and venture out, her paths are peace as well.

For us, at all events, her work must begin at the entry of the doors: all true economy is "Law of the house." Strive to make that law strict, simple, generous: waste nothing, and grudge nothing. Care in nowise to make more of money, but care to make much of it; remembering always the great, palpable, inevitable fact—the rule and root of all economy—that what one person has, another cannot have; and that every atom of substance, of whatever kind, used or consumed, is so much human life spent; which, if it issue in the saving present life, or gaining more, is well spent, but if not, is either so much life prevented, or so much slain. In all buying, consider, first, what condition of existence you cause in the producers of what you buy; secondly, whether the sum you have paid is just to the producer, and in due proportion lodged in his hands;[65] thirdly, to how much clear use, for food, knowledge, or joy, this that you have bought can be put; and fourthly, to whom and in what way it can be most speedily and serviceably distributed: in all dealings whatsoever insisting on entire openness and stern fulfilment; and in all doings, on perfection and loveliness of accomplishment; especially on fineness and purity of all marketable commodity: watching at the same time for all ways of gaining, or teaching, powers of simple pleasure; and of showing "hoson en asphodelph geg honeiar"—the sum of enjoyment depending not on the quantity of things tasted, but on the vivacity and patience of taste.

For us, her work must start at the entrance of the doors: all true economy is "Law of the house." Aim to make that law strict, simple, and generous: waste nothing and resent nothing. Don’t focus on making money as much as on making the most out of it; always remember the important, clear, and unavoidable fact—the rule and foundation of all economy—that what one person has, another cannot have; and that every bit of material consumed is a portion of human life spent; which, if it leads to saving present life or gaining more, is well spent, but if not, is either life prevented or life lost. In every purchase, first consider what kind of existence you create for the producers of what you buy; second, whether the amount you paid is fair to the producer and properly placed in their hands; third, how much practical use, for food, knowledge, or joy, the item you bought can provide; and fourth, to whom and how it can be quickly and effectively distributed: in all dealings, insisting on total transparency and strict adherence; and in all actions, on perfection and beauty of achievement; especially on the quality and purity of all marketable goods: at the same time, looking for all ways to gain or teach the power of simple pleasure; and showing "hoson en asphodelph geg honeiar"—the essence of enjoyment depending not on the quantity of things experienced, but on the depth and patience of taste.

[Pg 203]And if, on due and honest thought over these things, it seems that the kind of existence to which men are now summoned by every plea of pity and claim of right, may, for some time at least, not be a luxurious one:—consider whether, even, supposing it guiltless, luxury would be desired by any of us, if we saw clearly at our sides the suffering which accompanies it in the world. Luxury is indeed possible in the future—innocent and exquisite: luxury for all, and by the help of all; but luxury at present can only be enjoyed by the ignorant; the cruelest man living could not sit at his feast, unless he sat blindfold. Raise the veil boldly; face the light; and if, as yet, the light of the eye can only be through tears, and the light of the body through sackcloth, go thou forth weeping, bearing precious seed, until the time come, and the kingdom, when Christ's gift of bread, and bequest of peace shall be Unto this last as unto thee; and when, for earth's severed multitudes of the wicked and the weary, there shall be holier reconciliation than that of the narrow home, and calm economy, where the Wicked cease—not from trouble, but from troubling—and the Weary are at rest.

[Pg 203]And if, after careful consideration of these matters, it seems that the kind of life that people are being urged towards by every plea for compassion and claim for rights may, at least for a while, not be a comfortable one:—think about whether, even if it were guiltless, any of us would actually want luxury if we could clearly see the suffering that accompanies it in the world. Luxury is indeed possible in the future—pure and delightful: luxury for everyone, with the help of everyone; but right now, it can only be enjoyed by those who are unaware. The cruelest person alive couldn’t enjoy a feast unless they turned a blind eye. Lift the veil boldly; confront the truth; and if, for now, the light of vision can only come through tears, and the light of the body through rough cloth, go out weeping, sowing precious seeds, until the time comes, and the kingdom, when Christ's gift of bread, and promise of peace shall be for everyone equally; and when, for the countless suffering and troubled people, there will be a holier reconciliation than that of a narrow home, where the wicked don’t stop being troubled, but stop causing trouble—and the weary find rest.

FOOTNOTES:

[44] Book I. chap. iv. s. 1. To save space, my future references to Mr. Mill's work will be by numerals only, as in this instance, I. iv. 1. Ed. in 2 vols. 8vo, Parker, 1848.

[44] Book I. chap. iv. s. 1. To keep it brief, I will refer to Mr. Mill's work by numbers only from now on, like in this case, I. iv. 1. Ed. in 2 vols. 8vo, Parker, 1848.

[45] If Mr. Mill had wished to show the difference in result between consumption and sale, he should have represented the hardware merchant as consuming his own goods instead of selling them; similarly, the silver merchant as consuming his own goods instead of selling them. Had he done this, he would have made his position clearer, though less tenable; and perhaps this was the position he really intended to take, tacitly involving his theory, elsewhere stated, and shown in the sequel of this paper to be false, that demand for commodities is not demand for labour. But by the most diligent scrutiny of the paragraph now under examination, I cannot determine whether it is a fallacy pure and simple, or the half of one fallacy supported by the whole of a greater one; so that I treat it here on the kinder assumption that it is one fallacy only.

[45] If Mr. Mill wanted to illustrate the difference in outcomes between consumption and sale, he should have shown the hardware merchant consuming his own goods instead of selling them; likewise, the silver merchant should have been depicted consuming his own goods instead of selling them. If he had done this, it would have clarified his position, even though it would be harder to defend; and perhaps this was the stance he truly intended to take, subtly connecting to his theory, previously stated and proven false in this paper's later sections, that demand for commodities isn't the same as demand for labor. However, after closely examining the paragraph in question, I can’t tell if it’s simply a fallacy or if it’s part of a larger fallacy supported by a more significant one; therefore, I will approach it with the more charitable assumption that it's just one fallacy.

[46] I take Mr. [afterwards Sir A.] Helps' estimate in his essay on War.

[46] I'm using Mr. [later Sir A.] Helps' assessment in his essay on War.

[47] Also when the wrought silver vases of Spain were dashed to fragments by our custom-house officers, because bullion might be imported free of duty, but not brains, was the axe that broke them productive?—the artist who wrought them unproductive? Or again. If the woodman's axe is productive, is the executioner's? as also, if the hemp of a cable be productive, does not the productiveness of hemp in a halter depend on its moral more than on its material application?

[47] When our customs officers smashed the beautiful silver vases from Spain because while bullion could be imported duty-free, but not ideas, was the axe that destroyed them productive?—was the artist who created them unproductive? Or consider this: if the woodcutter's axe is productive, is the executioner's axe? Similarly, if hemp is productive for making a cable, does the usefulness of hemp in a noose depend more on its moral implications than on its physical use?

[48] Filigree: that is to say, generally, ornament dependent on complexity, not on art.

[48] Filigree: in other words, it’s usually ornamentation based on complexity rather than on artistic value.

[49] These statements sound crude in their brevity; but will be found of the utmost importance when they are developed. Thus, in the above instance, economists have never perceived that disposition to buy is a wholly moral element in demand: that is to say, when you give a man half-a-crown, it depends on his disposition whether he is rich or poor with it—whether he will buy disease, ruin, and hatred, or buy health, advancement, and domestic love. And thus the agreeableness or exchange value of every offered commodity depends on production, not merely of the commodity, but of buyers of it; therefore on the education of buyers, and on all the moral elements by which their disposition to buy this, or that, is formed. I will illustrate and expand into final consequences every one of these definitions in its place: at present they can only be given with extremest brevity; for in order to put the subject at once in a connected form before the reader, I have thrown into one, the opening definitions of four chapters; namely, of that on Value ("Ad Valorem"); on Price ("Thirty Pieces"); on Production ("Demeter"); and on Economy ("The Law of the House").

[49] These statements may seem blunt in their simplicity, but they are crucial once fully explained. In this instance, economists have often overlooked that the willingness to purchase is entirely a moral factor in demand: that is, when you give someone a half-crown, their wealth depends on their attitude towards it—whether they choose to spend it on harm, despair, and animosity, or on health, progress, and love at home. Thus, the desirability or market value of any given product is determined by production, not just of the product itself, but also of those who wish to buy it; therefore, it relies on the education of buyers and all the moral factors shaping their willingness to purchase this or that item. I will explain and elaborate on the implications of each of these definitions in detail: for now, they can only be presented briefly; to give the reader a cohesive overview, I've combined the introductory definitions from four chapters: Value ("Ad Valorem"), Price ("Thirty Pieces"), Production ("Demeter"), and Economy ("The Law of the House").

[50] Perhaps it may be said, in farther support of Mr. Ricardo, that he meant, "when the utility is constant or given, the price varies as the quantity of labour." If he meant this, he should have said it; but, had he meant it, he could have hardly missed the necessary result, that utility would be one measure of price (which he expressly denies it to be); and that, to prove saleableness, he had to prove a given quantity of utility, as well as a given quantity of labour: to wit, in his own instance, that the deer and fish would each feed the same number of men, for the same number of days, with equal pleasure to their palates. The fact is, he did not know what he meant himself. The general idea which he had derived from commercial experience, without being able to analyse it, was, that when the demand is constant, the price varies as the quantity of labour required for production; or,—using the formula I gave in last paper—when y is constant, xy varies as x. But demand never is, nor can be, ultimately constant, if x varies distinctly; for, as price rises, consumers fall away; and as soon as there is a monopoly (and all scarcity is a form of monopoly; so that every commodity is affected occasionally by some colour of monopoly), y becomes the most influential condition of the price. Thus the price of a painting depends less on its merit than on the interest taken in it by the public; the price of singing less on the labour of the singer than the number of persons who desire to hear him; and the price of gold less on the scarcity which affects it in common with cerium or iridium, than on the sun-light colour and unalterable purity by which it attracts the admiration and answers the trust of mankind.

[50] It might be said, to further support Mr. Ricardo, that he meant, "when the utility is constant or established, the price changes with the quantity of labor." If that's what he meant, he should have stated it clearly; however, if he did mean that, he would have hardly overlooked the crucial conclusion that utility would be one measure of price (which he explicitly denies). To demonstrate salability, he needed to establish both a given quantity of utility and a given quantity of labor; for example, he should have shown that the deer and fish would each be able to feed the same number of people for the same number of days, providing equal enjoyment to their taste buds. The truth is, he didn’t even understand his own argument. The general concept he gathered from his business experience, without being able to analyze it, was that when demand is steady, the price varies according to the amount of labor needed for production; or—in the formula I provided in the last paper—when y is constant, xy varies with x. But demand cannot remain constant if x changes significantly; as prices rise, consumers stop buying; and as soon as there’s a monopoly (and every scarcity is a kind of monopoly; so all products occasionally experience some form of monopoly), y becomes the key factor affecting the price. Therefore, the price of a painting depends less on its quality and more on how much interest the public has in it; the price of a performance relies less on the singer’s effort and more on how many people want to hear him; and the price of gold is influenced less by its scarcity, similar to cerium or iridium, and more by its appealing color and enduring purity, which earn the admiration and trust of people.

It must be kept in mind, however, that I use the word "demand" in a somewhat different sense from economists usually. They mean by it "the quantity of a thing sold." I mean by it "the force of the buyer's capable intention to buy." In good English, a person's "demand" signifies, not what he gets, but what he asks for.

It’s important to note, though, that I use the term "demand" in a slightly different way than economists typically do. They define it as "the quantity of a thing sold." I define it as "the strength of the buyer's genuine intention to purchase." In plain English, a person's "demand" represents not what they receive, but what they request.

Economists also do not notice that objects are not valued by absolute bulk or weight, but by such bulk and weight as is necessary to bring them into use. They say, for instance, that water bears no price in the market. It is true that a cupful does not, but a lake does; just as a handful of dust does not, but an acre does. And were it possible to make even the possession of the cupful or handful permanent (i.e., to find a place for them), the earth and sea would be bought up by handfuls and cupfuls.

Economists also overlook the fact that objects aren't valued by their total size or weight, but by the size and weight needed to actually use them. They claim, for example, that water has no market price. That might be true for a cup of water, but it definitely isn’t for a lake; similarly, a handful of dirt has no value, but an acre does. If it were possible to make the ownership of that cup or handful permanent (i.e., to find a place for them), then the earth and sea could be bought up in handfuls and cupfuls.

[51] Compare George Herbert, The Church Porch, Stanza 28.

[51] Compare George Herbert, The Church Porch, Stanza 28.

[52] "ὁ Ζεὺς δήπου πένεται."—Arist. Plut.. 582. It would but weaken the grand words to lean on the preceding ones:—"ὅτι τοῦ Πλούτου παρέχω βελτίονας ἄνδρας, καὶ τὴν γνώμην, καὶ τὴν ἰδέαν."

[52] "ὁ Ζεὺς δήπου πένεται."—Arist. Plut.. 582. It would weaken the powerful words to rely on the previous ones:—"ὅτι τοῦ Πλούτου παρέχω βελτίονας ἄνδρας, καὶ τὴν γνώμην, καὶ τὴν ἰδέαν."

[53] Zech. v. 11. See note on the passage, at pp. 191-2.

[53] Zech. v. 11. See the note on this passage at pages 191-2.

[54] Labour which is entirely good of its kind, that is to say, effective, or efficient, the Greeks called "weighable," or ἄξιος, translated usually "worthy," and because thus substantial and true, they called its price τιμή, the "honourable estimate" of it (honorarium): this word being founded on their conception of true labour as a divine thing, to be honoured with the kind of honour given to the gods; whereas the price of false labour, or of that which led away from life, was to be, not honour, but vengeance; for which they reserved another word, attributing the exaction of such price to a peculiar goddess called Tisiphone, the "requiter (or quittance-taker) of death;" a person versed in the highest branches of arithmetic, and punctual in her habits; with whom accounts current have been opened also in modern days.

[54] Labor that is entirely good, meaning effective or efficient, was referred to by the Greeks as "weighable," or ἄξιος, which is usually translated as "worthy." Because it was considered substantial and genuine, they termed its price τιμή, which means the "honourable estimate" of it (honorarium). This word is based on their belief in true labor as a divine thing deserving of the same honor given to the gods. In contrast, the price of false labor, or that which detracted from life, was not honor but vengeance. For this, they had another term, as they ascribed the collection of such a price to a specific goddess named Tisiphone, the "requiter (or quittance-taker) of death." She was skilled in the highest forms of arithmetic and punctual in her duties; accounts with her have also been kept in modern times.

[55] The most accurately nugatory labour is, perhaps, that of which not enough is given to answer a purpose effectually, and which, therefore, has all to be done over again. Also, labour which fails of effect through non-cooperation. The curé of a little village near Bellinzona, to whom I had expressed wonder that the peasants allowed the Ticino to flood their fields, told me that they would not join to build an effectual embankment high up the valley, because everybody said "that would help his neighbours as much as himself." So every proprietor built a bit of low embankment about his own field; and the Ticino, as soon as it had a mind, swept away and swallowed all up together.

[55] The most pointless work is probably the kind where not enough effort is put in to achieve a goal effectively, resulting in everything having to be redone. This also includes work that fails due to lack of collaboration. The priest of a small village near Bellinzona, to whom I expressed my surprise that the farmers let the Ticino flood their fields, told me they refused to cooperate in building a proper embankment further up the valley because everyone thought "that would benefit his neighbors just as much as him." So, each landowner built a small embankment around his own field, and whenever the Ticino felt like it, it washed everything away.

[56] Observe, I say, "rearing," not "begetting." The praise is in the seventh season, not in σπορητός, nor in φυταλιὰ, but in ὀπώρα. It is strange that men always praise enthusiastically any person who, by a momentary exertion, saves a life; but praise very hesitatingly a person who, by exertion and self-denial prolonged through years, creates one. We give the crown "ob civem servatum,"—why not "ob civem natum"? Born, I mean, to the full, in soul as well as body. England has oak enough, I think, for both chaplets.

[56] Look, I say "rearing," not "begetting." The praise is in the seventh season, not in σπορητός, nor in φυταλιὰ, but in ὀπώρα. It's odd that people always enthusiastically commend someone who saves a life with a quick act; yet they are much more hesitant to praise someone who, through years of effort and sacrifice, creates a life. We award the crown "ob civem servatum,"—so why not "ob civem natum"? Born, I mean, fully, in both soul and body. England has enough oak, I think, for both wreaths.

[57] When Mr. Mill speaks of productive consumption, he only means consumption which results in increase of capital, or material wealth. See I. iii. 4, and I. iii. 5.

[57] When Mr. Mill talks about productive consumption, he is referring to consumption that leads to an increase in capital or material wealth. See I. iii. 4, and I. iii. 5.

[58] So also in the vision of the women bearing the ephah, before quoted, "the wind was in their wings," not wings "of a stork," as in our version; but "milvi," of a kite, in the Vulgate, or perhaps more accurately still in the Septuagint, "hoopoe," a bird connected typically with the power of riches by many traditions, of which that of its petition for a crest of gold is perhaps the most interesting. The "Birds" of Aristophanes, in which its part is principal, is full of them; note especially the "fortification of the air with baked bricks, like Babylon," l. 550; and, again, compare the Plutus of Dante, who (to show the influence of riches in destroying the reason) is the only one of the powers of the Inferno who cannot speak intelligibly; and also the cowardliest; he is not merely quelled or restrained, but literally "collapses" at a word; the sudden and helpless operation of mercantile panic being all told in the brief metaphor, "as the sails, swollen with the wind, fall, when the mast breaks."

[58] In the vision of the women carrying the ephah, as mentioned earlier, "the wind was in their wings," not "wings of a stork," like in our version; instead, it's "milvi," which means kite, in the Vulgate, or possibly even more accurately "hoopoe" in the Septuagint. This bird is often associated with wealth in many traditions, one of the most intriguing being its request for a crest of gold. In Aristophanes' "Birds," where the hoopoe has a central role, there are many references to this. Pay particular attention to the “fortification of the air with baked bricks, like Babylon,” line 550; and also compare it to Dante's "Plutus," who (to illustrate how wealth can corrupt reason) is the only one of the infernal powers who can’t speak clearly; he is not just overwhelmed or silenced, but literally "collapses" at a word. The sudden and helpless effect of commercial panic is captured in the simple metaphor, "as the sails, swollen with the wind, fall when the mast breaks."

[59] The value of raw material, which has, indeed, to be deducted from the price of the labour, is not contemplated in the passages referred to, Mr. Mill having fallen into the mistake solely by pursuing the collateral results of the payment of wages to middlemen. He says:—"The consumer does not, with his own funds, pay the weaver for his day's work." Pardon me; the consumer of the velvet pays the weaver with his own funds as much as he pays the gardener. He pays, probably, an intermediate ship-owner, velvet merchant, and shopman; pays carriage money, shop rent, damage money, time money, and care money; all these are above and beside the velvet price (just as the wages of a head gardener would be above the grass price); but the velvet is as much produced by the consumer's capital, though he does not pay for it till six months after production, as the grass is produced by his capital, though he does not pay the man who mowed and rolled it on Monday, till Saturday afternoon. I do not know if Mr. Mill's conclusion—"the capital cannot be dispensed with, the purchasers can"—has yet been reduced to practice in the City on any large scale.

[59] The cost of raw materials, which needs to be deducted from labor costs, isn’t addressed in the mentioned passages. Mr. Mill made this mistake by focusing only on the indirect effects of paying wages to middlemen. He states: “The consumer does not pay the weaver for his day’s work with his own money.” Actually, the consumer of the velvet pays the weaver with his own money just like he pays the gardener. He likely pays an intermediary shipper, a velvet merchant, and a shopkeeper; he pays for transportation, shop rent, damages, time, and care—all of which are additional to the cost of the velvet (similar to how a head gardener’s wages are separate from the price of grass). But the velvet is as much a result of the consumer's capital, even if he doesn't pay for it until six months post-production, as the grass results from his capital, even though he doesn’t pay the worker who cut and rolled it until Saturday afternoon. I’m not sure if Mr. Mill's conclusion—“capital cannot be eliminated, but buyers can”—has been put into practice widely in the City yet.

[60] Which, observe, is the precise opposite of the one under examination. The hardware theory required us to discharge our gardeners and engage manufacturers; the velvet theory requires us to discharge our manufacturers and engage gardeners.

[60] Notice that this is the exact opposite of what we're looking at. The hardware theory had us let go of our gardeners and hire manufacturers; the velvet theory has us let go of our manufacturers and hire gardeners.

[61] It is one very awful form of the operation of wealth in Europe that it is entirely capitalists' wealth which supports unjust wars. Just wars do not need so much money to support them; for most of the men who wage such, wage them gratis; but for an unjust war, men's bodies and souls have both to be bought; and the best tools of war for them besides; which makes such war costly to the maximum; not to speak of the cost of base fear, and angry suspicion, between nations which have not grace nor honesty enough in all their multitudes to buy an hour's peace of mind with: as, at present, France and England, purchasing of each other ten millions sterling worth of consternation annually (a remarkably light crop, half thorns and half aspen leaves,—sown, reaped, and granaried by "the science" of the modern political economist, teaching covetousness instead of truth). And all unjust war being supportable, if not by pillage of the enemy, only by loans from capitalists, these loans are repaid by subsequent taxation of the people, who appear to have no will in the matter, the capitalists' will being the primary root of the war; but its real root is the covetousness of the whole nation, rendering it incapable of faith, frankness, or justice, and bringing about, therefore, in due time, his own separate loss and punishment to each person.

[61] One terrible aspect of wealth in Europe is that it is entirely capitalists' wealth that funds unjust wars. Just wars don't require as much money to sustain them; most individuals fighting them do so voluntarily. However, for an unjust war, both lives and souls need to be bought, along with the best weapons, which makes such conflicts extremely expensive. Not to mention the costs of fear and suspicion between nations that lack the grace and honesty to secure even an hour's peace of mind—take, for example, France and England, spending ten million pounds a year on mutual anxiety (an exceptionally small price, consisting mainly of thorns and aspen leaves—cultivated and harvested by "the science" of modern political economy, which promotes greed instead of truth). Moreover, while unjust wars can be funded through enemy plunder or loans from capitalists, these loans are ultimately repaid by taxing the people, who seem to have no say in the matter. The capitalists' will is the main cause of the war, but the deeper issue lies in the nation's greed, which prevents it from being faithful, honest, or just, ultimately leading to loss and punishment for each individual in due time.

[62] "In all reasoning about prices, the proviso must be understood, 'supposing all parties to take care of their own interest.'"—Mill, III. i. 5.

[62] "When discussing prices, it’s important to assume that everyone is looking out for their own interests."—Mill, III. i. 5.

[63] James v. 4. Observe, in these statements I am not taking up, nor countenancing one whit, the common socialist idea of division of property; division of property is its destruction; and with it the destruction of all hope, all industry, and all justice: it is simply chaos—a chaos towards which the believers in modern political economy are fast tending, and from which I am striving to save them. The rich man does not keep back meat from the poor by retaining his riches; but by basely using them. Riches are a form of strength; and a strong man does not injure others by keeping his strength, but by using it injuriously. The socialist, seeing a strong man oppress a weak one, cries out—"Break the strong man's arms"; but I say, "Teach him to use them to better purpose." The fortitude and intelligence which acquire riches are intended, by the Giver of both, not to scatter, nor to give away, but to employ those riches in the service of mankind; in other words, in the redemption of the erring and aid of the weak—that is to say, there is first to be the work to gain money; then the Sabbath of use for it—the Sabbath, whose law is, not to lose life, but to save. It is continually the fault or the folly of the poor that they are poor, as it is usually a child's fault if it falls into a pond, and a cripple's weakness that slips at a crossing; nevertheless, most passers-by would pull the child out, or help up the cripple. Put it at the worst, that all the poor of the world are but disobedient children, or careless cripples, and that all rich people are wise and strong, and you will see at once that neither is the socialist right in desiring to make everybody poor, powerless, and foolish as he is himself, nor the rich man right in leaving the children in the mire.

[63] James v. 4. In these statements, I’m not endorsing the typical socialist idea of dividing property; dividing property leads to its destruction and, with it, the loss of all hope, hard work, and justice. It creates nothing but chaos—a chaos that those who believe in modern political economy are quickly heading toward, and I am trying to save them from. A wealthy person doesn’t deny food to the poor by keeping their wealth; rather, they do so by misusing it. Wealth is a form of power, and a strong person doesn’t hurt others by retaining their power, but by using it harmfully. The socialist, seeing a strong person oppressing a weaker one, shouts—“Break the strong person’s arms”; but I say, “Teach them to use their strength for good.” The courage and intelligence that lead to wealth are meant, by the Creator of both, not to be scattered or given away, but to use that wealth in service to humanity; in other words, there should first be work done to earn money; then a purpose for its use—the purpose being not to waste life, but to save it. It is often the fault or folly of the poor that they are poor, just as it can be a child's fault if they fall into a pond, or a disabled person’s weakness that causes them to stumble. However, most passersby would pull the child out or help the disabled person. Even if we assume that all the poor people in the world are just disobedient children or careless disabled individuals, and all wealthy people are wise and strong, it becomes clear that neither the socialist is correct in wanting to make everyone poor, powerless, and foolish like themselves, nor is the wealthy person justified in leaving the children in the mud.

[64] The quantity of life is the same in both cases; but it is differently allotted.

[64] The amount of life is the same in both situations; but it's distributed differently.

[65] The proper offices of middlemen, namely, overseers (or authoritative workmen), conveyancers (merchants, sailors, retail dealers, etc.), and order-takers (persons employed to receive directions from the consumer), must, of course, be examined before I can enter farther into the question of just payment of the first producer. But I have not spoken of them in these introductory papers, because the evils attendant on the abuse of such intermediate functions result not from any alleged principle of modern political economy, but from private carelessness or iniquity.

[65] The roles of middlemen, like overseers (or skilled workers), conveyancers (merchants, sailors, retail sellers, etc.), and order-takers (people who take instructions from customers), need to be considered before I can discuss fair payment for the primary producer. However, I haven't addressed them in these introductory papers because the problems caused by the misuse of these intermediary roles arise not from any supposed principle of modern political economy, but from individual negligence or wrongdoing.

 


ESSAYS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY:

CONTRIBUTED TO "FRASER'S MAGAZINE" IN 1862 AND 1863, BEING A SEQUEL TO PAPERS WHICH APPEARED IN THE "CORNHILL MAGAZINE," UNDER THE TITLE OF "UNTO THIS LAST."


 

ESSAYS ON POLITICAL ECONOMY


I.

MAINTENANCE OF LIFE; WEALTH, MONEY, AND RICHES.

As domestic economy regulates the acts and habits of a household, political economy regulates those of a society or State, with reference to its maintenance.

As household economy manages the actions and habits of a home, political economy oversees those of a society or state, focusing on its sustainability.

Political economy is neither an art nor a science,[66] but a system of conduct and legislature, founded on the sciences, directing the arts, and impossible, except under certain conditions of moral culture.

Political economy is not just an art or a science,[66] but a system of behavior and laws, based on the sciences, guiding the arts, and only possible under specific conditions of moral development.

By the "maintenance" of a State is to be understood the support of its population in healthy and happy life; and the increase of their numbers, so far as that increase is consistent with their happiness. It is not the object of political economy to increase the numbers of a nation at the cost of common health or comfort; nor to increase indefinitely the comfort of individuals, by sacrifice of surrounding lives, or possibilities of life.

By “maintenance” of a State, we mean supporting its population so they can live healthy and happy lives, along with increasing their numbers as long as that boost aligns with their happiness. The goal of political economy isn’t to grow a nation’s population at the expense of overall health or comfort, nor to indefinitely improve individual comfort at the cost of the well-being or potential lives of others.

The assumption which lies at the root of nearly all erroneous reasoning on political economy—namely, that its object is to accumulate money or exchangeable property—may be shown in few words to be without foundation. For no economist would admit national economy to be legitimate which proposed to itself only the building of a pyramid of gold. He would declare the gold to be wasted, were it to remain in the monumental form, and would say it ought to be employed. But to what end? Either it must be used only to gain more gold, and build a larger pyramid, or to some purpose other than the gaining of gold. And this other purpose, however at first apprehended, will be found to resolve itself finally into the service of man—that is to say, the extension, defence, or comfort of his life. The golden pyramid may perhaps be providently built, perhaps improvidently; but, at all events, the wisdom or folly of the accumulation can only be determined by our having first clearly stated the aim of all economy, namely, the extension of life.

The basic misunderstanding behind most flawed reasoning in political economy—specifically that its goal is just to gather money or assets—can be briefly disproven. No economist would consider a national economy legitimate if its only goal was to create a giant pile of gold. They would say the gold is wasted if it just sits there as a monument and should be put to use. But what for? Either it has to be used solely to acquire more gold and create a bigger pile, or for something beyond just gaining gold. This other purpose, no matter how it's initially perceived, ultimately turns into serving humanity—that is, enhancing, protecting, or improving life. The golden pyramid might be built wisely or foolishly, but regardless, whether the accumulation is smart or not can only be judged once we clearly define the purpose of all economy, which is to enhance life.

If the accumulation of money, or of exchangeable property, were a certain means of extending existence, it would be useless, in discussing economical questions, to fix our attention upon the more distant object—life—instead of the immediate one—money. But it is not so. Money may sometimes be accumulated at the cost of life, or by limitations of it; that is to say, either by hastening the deaths of men, or preventing their births. It is therefore necessary to keep clearly in view the ultimate object of economy, and to determine the expediency of minor operations with reference to that ulterior end. It has been just stated that the object of political economy is the continuance not only of life, but of healthy and happy life. But all true happiness is both a consequence and cause of life; it is a sign of its vigour, and means of its continuance. All true suffering is in like manner a consequence and cause of death. I shall therefore, in future, use the word "Life" singly: but let it be understood to include in its signification the happiness and power of the entire human nature, body and soul.

If accumulating money or valuable property were a guaranteed way to prolong life, it wouldn't make sense to focus on the broader idea of life when discussing economic issues, instead of the immediate concern of money. However, that's not the case. Sometimes, money can be accumulated at the expense of life or through restrictions on it; in other words, by speeding up people’s deaths or preventing their births. It's essential to keep the ultimate goal of the economy in mind and assess smaller actions based on that ultimate goal. It's already been mentioned that the aim of political economy is not just to sustain life, but to maintain a healthy and happy life. True happiness is both a result of and a contributor to life; it reflects vitality and is a means for its continuation. Similarly, true suffering is both a result of and a contributor to death. Therefore, from now on, I will use the term "Life" on its own, but it should be understood to encompass the happiness and well-being of the whole human being, both body and soul.

That human nature, as its Creator made it, and maintains it wherever His laws are observed, is entirely harmonious.[Pg 209] No physical error can be more profound, no moral error more dangerous than that involved in the monkish doctrine of the opposition of body to soul. No soul can be perfect in an imperfect body; no body perfect without perfect soul. Every right action and true thought sets the seal of its beauty on person and face; every wrong action and foul thought its seal of distortion; and the various aspects of humanity might be read as plainly as a printed history, were it not that the impressions are so complex that it must always in some cases—and, in the present state of our knowledge, in all cases—be impossible to decipher them completely. Nevertheless, the face of a consistently just, and of a consistently unjust person, may always be rightly discerned at a glance; and if the qualities are continued by descent through a generation or two, there arises a complete distinction of race. Both moral and physical qualities are communicated by descent, far more than they can be developed by education (though both may be destroyed for want of education), and there is as yet no ascertained limit to the nobleness of person and mind which the human creature may attain, by persevering observance of the laws of God respecting its birth and training. We must therefore yet farther define the aim of political economy to be "the multiplication of human life at the highest standard." It might at first seem questionable whether we should endeavour to maintain a small number of persons of the highest type of beauty and intelligence, or a larger number of an inferior class. But I shall be able to show in the sequel, that the way to maintain the largest number is first to aim at the highest standard. Determine the noblest type of man, and aim simply at maintaining the largest possible number of persons of that class, and it will be found that the largest possible number of every healthy subordinate class must necessarily be produced also.

Human nature, as its Creator designed it and keeps it intact wherever His laws are followed, is completely harmonious.[Pg 209] No physical flaw can be more profound, and no moral flaw more dangerous, than the monkish belief that the body and soul are opposed to each other. No soul can be perfect in an imperfect body, and no body can be perfect without a perfect soul. Every right action and true thought enhances the beauty of a person and their face; every wrong action and corrupt thought distorts it. The different aspects of humanity could be read as clearly as a printed history if it weren't for the complexity of these impressions, making it impossible to fully understand them in most cases—and, given our current knowledge, it’s impossible in all cases. Nevertheless, the face of a consistently just person and that of a consistently unjust person can always be recognized at a glance. If these traits are passed down through one or two generations, a clear distinction of race emerges. Both moral and physical traits are inherited much more than they can be shaped by education (although both can be ruined without education). There is still no known limit to the greatness of character and mind that a human being can achieve through the consistent adherence to God's laws regarding their birth and upbringing. Therefore, we must further clarify the goal of political economy as "the multiplication of human life at the highest standard." At first, it may seem debatable whether we should strive to maintain a small number of individuals of the highest beauty and intelligence or a larger group of those who are less refined. However, I will demonstrate later that the way to sustain the largest number is to first aim for the highest standard. Define the noblest type of person and make it your goal to maintain the largest possible number of that group, and you will see that the greatest number of every healthy subordinate group will also naturally arise.

The perfect type of manhood, as just stated, involves the perfections (whatever we may hereafter determine these to be) of his body, affections, and intelligence. The material things, therefore, which it is the object of political economy to produce and use (or accumulate for use), are things which serve either to sustain and comfort the body, or exercise[Pg 210] rightly the affections and form the intelligence.[67] Whatever truly serves either of these purposes is "useful" to man, wholesome, healthful, helpful, or holy. By seeking such things, man prolongs and increases his life upon the earth.

The ideal type of manhood, as mentioned earlier, includes the qualities (whatever we might define those to be) of his body, emotions, and intellect. The material goods that political economy aims to produce and use (or gather for use) are items that either support and comfort the body or properly engage the emotions and develop the intellect.[Pg 210][67] Anything that truly serves either of these purposes is "useful" to people, beneficial, healthy, supportive, or sacred. By pursuing such things, individuals extend and enrich their lives on Earth.

On the other hand, whatever does not serve either of these purposes,—much more whatever counteracts them,—is in like manner useless to man, unwholesome, unhelpful, or unholy; and by seeking such things man shortens and diminishes his life upon the earth. And neither with respect to things useful or useless can man's estimate of them alter their nature. Certain substances being good for his food, and others noxious to him, what he thinks or wishes respecting them can neither change their nature, nor prevent their power. If he eats corn, he will live; if nightshade, he will die. If he produce or make good and beautiful things, they will "recreate" him (note the solemnity and weight of the word); if bad and ugly things, they will "corrupt" or break in pieces—that is, in the exact degree of their power, kill him. For every [Pg 211] hour of labour, however enthusiastic or well intended, which he spends for that which is not bread, so much possibility of life is lost to him. His fancies, likings, beliefs, however brilliant, eager, or obstinate, are of no avail if they are set on a false object. Of all that he has laboured for, the eternal law of heaven and earth measures out to him for reward, to the utmost atom, that part which he ought to have laboured for, and withdraws from him (or enforces on him, it may be) [Pg 212] inexorably that part which he ought not to have laboured for. The dust and chaff are all, to the last speck, winnowed away, and on his summer threshing-floor stands his heap of corn; little or much, not according to his labour, but to his discretion. No "commercial arrangements," no painting of surfaces nor alloying of substances, will avail him a pennyweight. Nature asks of him calmly and inevitably, What have you found, or formed—the right thing or the wrong? By the right thing you shall live; by the wrong you shall die.

On the other hand, anything that doesn’t serve these purposes—or even worse, anything that goes against them—is also useless to people: unhealthy, unhelpful, or immoral. By pursuing such things, people shorten their lives on earth. Moreover, a person's view of what is useful or useless doesn’t change what those things actually are. Some substances are good for food, while others are harmful; what a person thinks or wishes about them can’t change their properties or prevent their effects. If he eats corn, he’ll live; if he eats nightshade, he’ll die. If he creates good and beautiful things, they will "rejuvenate" him (note the seriousness of the term); if he makes bad and ugly things, they will "corrupt" or shatter him—that is, to the exact extent of their impact, they will harm him. For every [Pg 211] hour of work, no matter how passionate or well-meaning, that he spends on things that aren’t necessary, he loses a portion of life. His thoughts, preferences, and beliefs, no matter how bright, enthusiastic, or stubborn, mean nothing if they’re focused on something misleading. Out of all that he has worked for, the eternal laws of heaven and earth reward him exactly with what he should have worked for, while they take away (or impose upon him) [Pg 212] without mercy what he shouldn’t have pursued. The useless parts are entirely sorted out, and on his summer threshing floor lies his pile of grain; little or much, not based on his effort, but on his judgment. No "business deals," no surface-level improvements or mixing of substances will earn him even the slightest gain. Nature asks him plainly and inevitably, What have you found or created—the right thing or the wrong? By the right thing, you will live; by the wrong, you will perish.

To thoughtless persons it seems otherwise. The world looks to them as if they could cozen it out of some ways and means of life. But they cannot cozen IT; they can only cozen their neighbours. The world is not to be cheated of a grain; not so much as a breath of its air can be drawn surreptitiously. For every piece of wise work done, so much life is granted; for every piece of foolish work, nothing; for every piece of wicked work, so much death. This is as sure as the courses of day and night. But when the means of life are once produced, men, by their various struggles and industries of accumulation or exchange, may variously gather, waste, restrain, or distribute them; necessitating, in proportion to the waste or restraint, accurately so much more death. The rate and range of additional death is measured by the rate and range of waste, and is inevitable;—the only question (determined mostly by fraud in peace, and force in war) is, Who is to die, and how?

To careless people, it seems different. The world appears to them as if they can trick it into providing some ways to survive. But they can't trick IT; they can only deceive their neighbors. The world won't be cheated out of even a little; not even a breath of its air can be taken secretly. For every wise action taken, life is granted; for every foolish action, nothing; and for every wicked action, there’s death. This is as certain as the cycle of day and night. Once the means of living are produced, people can go about collecting, wasting, saving, or sharing them through their various struggles and efforts. The more they waste or hold back, the more death is necessary, proportionally. The rate and extent of additional death is determined by how much is wasted, and it's unavoidable; the only question (mostly decided by deceit in peace and force in war) is, Who will die, and how?

Such being the everlasting law of human existence, the essential work of the political economist is to determine what are in reality useful and life-giving things, and by what degrees and kinds of labour they are attainable and distributable. This investigation divides itself under three great heads—first, of Wealth; secondly, of Money; and thirdly, of Riches.

Such is the constant rule of human life, the main task of a political economist is to identify what truly benefits and sustains life, and the different levels and types of work required to acquire and share them. This study breaks down into three main categories: first, Wealth; second, Money; and third, Riches.

These terms are often used as synonymous, but they signify entirely different things. "Wealth," consists of things in themselves valuable; "Money," of documentary claims to the possession of such things; and "Riches" is a relative term, expressing the magnitude of the possessions of one person or society as compared with those of other persons or societies.[Pg 213]

These terms are often used interchangeably, but they actually mean different things. "Wealth" refers to things that are valuable in themselves; "Money" is about the documented claims to owning those things; and "Riches" is a relative term that indicates how much one person or society possesses compared to others.[Pg 213]

The study of Wealth is a province of natural science:—it deals with the essential properties of things.

The study of wealth is a branch of natural science—it focuses on the fundamental qualities of things.

The study of Money is a province of commercial science:—it deals with conditions of engagement and exchange.

The study of money is a field of business science: it focuses on the conditions of involvement and trade.

The study of Riches is a province of moral science:—it deals with the due relations of men to each other in regard of material possessions; and with the just laws of their association for purposes of labour.

The study of wealth is a field of moral science: it focuses on the appropriate relationships between people concerning material possessions and the fair laws governing their collaboration for work.

I shall in this paper shortly sketch out the range of subjects which will come before us as we follow these three branches of inquiry.

I will briefly outline the topics we will explore as we examine these three areas of research in this paper.


Section I.—MONEY.

Wealth, it has been said, consists of things essentially valuable. We now, therefore, need a definition of "value."

Wealth, as they've pointed out, is made up of things that are fundamentally valuable. So, we now need to define what "value" means.

Value signifies the strength or "availing" of anything towards the sustaining of life, and is always twofold; that is to say, primarily, Intrinsic, and, secondarily, Effectual.

Value represents the importance or "usefulness" of something in sustaining life and has two aspects; that is to say, first, Inherent, and second, Effective.

The reader must, by anticipation, be warned against confusing value with cost, or with price. Value is the life-giving power of anything; cost, the quantity of labour required to produce it; price, the quantity of labour which its possessor will take in exchange for it. Cost and price are commercial conditions, to be studied under the head of Money.

The reader should be warned in advance not to confuse value with cost or price. Value is the essential worth of something; cost is the amount of labor needed to produce it; price is the amount of labor that the owner will accept in trade for it. Cost and price are economic factors, which need to be examined in the context of Money.

Intrinsic value is the absolute power of anything to support life. A sheaf of wheat of given quality and weight has in it a measurable power of sustaining the substance of the body; a cubic foot of pure air, a fixed power of sustaining its warmth; and a cluster of flowers of given beauty, a fixed power of enlivening or animating the senses and heart.

Intrinsic value is the true ability of anything to support life. A bundle of wheat of a certain quality and weight has a measurable ability to nourish the body; a cubic foot of pure air has a specific ability to maintain warmth; and a bunch of flowers with a certain beauty has a definite ability to uplift the senses and heart.

It does not in the least affect the intrinsic value of the wheat, the air, or the flowers, that men refuse or despise them. Used or not, their own power is in them, and that particular power is in nothing else.

It doesn't change the inherent value of the wheat, air, or flowers at all that people reject or look down on them. Whether used or not, their true essence lies within them, and that unique essence is found nowhere else.

But in order that this value of theirs may become effectual, a certain state is necessary in the recipient of it. The digesting, the breathing, and perceiving functions must be perfect in the human creature before the food, air, or flowers can become their full value to it. The production of effectual value, therefore, always involves two needs; first, the production of a thing essentially useful; then the production of the capacity to use it. Where the intrinsic value and[Pg 215] acceptant capacity come together there is Effectual value, or wealth. Where there is either no intrinsic value, or no acceptant capacity, there is no effectual value; that is to say, no wealth. A horse is no wealth to us if we cannot ride, nor a picture if we cannot see, nor can any noble thing be wealth, except to a noble person. As the aptness of the user increases, the effectual value of the thing used increases; and in its entirety can co-exist only with perfect skill of use, or harmony of nature. The effectual value of a given quantity of any commodity existing in the world at any moment is therefore a mathematical function of the capacity existing in the human race to enjoy it. Let its intrinsic value be represented by x, and the recipient faculty by y; its effectual value is x y, in which the sum varies as either co-efficient varies, is increased by either's increase,[68] and cancelled by either's absence.

But for this value to be effective, the recipient must be in a certain state. The processes of digestion, breathing, and perception need to be functioning perfectly in a person before food, air, or flowers can provide their full benefit. Therefore, creating effective value always requires two things: first, producing something that is fundamentally useful; second, producing the ability to use it. Where intrinsic value and the capacity to accept it meet, there is effective value, or wealth. If there’s no intrinsic value or no capacity to accept it, there is no effective value; in other words, no wealth. A horse is not valuable to us if we can’t ride it, nor is a painting if we can’t see it, nor can any noble thing be valuable, except to someone noble. As the skill of the user increases, the effective value of the item used also increases; and it can only fully coexist with perfect skill of use or natural harmony. The effective value of any given amount of a commodity in the world at any moment is therefore a mathematical function of the human capacity to enjoy it. If we represent its intrinsic value as x, and the recipient's capacity as y; its effective value is x y, where the total changes as either of the factors changes, increases when either increases, and disappears if either is absent.[68]

Valuable material things may be conveniently referred to five heads:—

Valuable material things can be conveniently classified into five categories:—

1. Land, with an associated air, water, and organisms.

1. Land, along with its air, water, and living organisms.

2. Houses, furniture, and instruments.

2. Homes, furniture, and tools.

3. Stored or prepared food and medicine, and articles of bodily luxury, including clothing.

3. Stored or prepared food and medicine, and items of personal luxury, including clothing.

4. Books.

Books.

5. Works of art.

Artworks.

We shall enter into separate inquiry as to the conditions of value under each of these heads. The following sketch of the entire subject may be useful for future reference:—

We will look into the different factors of value for each of these areas. The outline of the whole topic below might be helpful for future reference:—

1. Land. Its value is twofold—

1. Land. Its value is twofold—

A. As producing food and mechanical power.
B. As an object of sight and thought, producing intellectual power.

A. By creating food and mechanical power.
B. As something to see and think about, generating intellectual power.

[Pg 216]A. Its value, as a means of producing food and mechanical power, varies with its form (as mountain or plain), with its substance (in soil or mineral contents), and with its climate. All these conditions of intrinsic value, in order to give effectual value, must be known and complied with by the men who have to deal with it; but at any given time, or place, the intrinsic value is fixed; such and such a piece of land, with its associated lakes and seas, rightly treated in surface and substance, can produce precisely so much food and power, and no more. Its surface treatment (agriculture) and substance treatment (practical geology and chemistry), are the first roots of economical science. By surface treatment, however, I mean more than agriculture as commonly understood; I mean land and sea culture;—dominion over both the fixed and the flowing fields;—perfect acquaintance with the laws of climate, and of vegetable and animal growth in the given tracts of earth or ocean, and of their relations regulating especially the production of those articles of food which, being in each particular spot producible in the highest perfection, will bring the best price in commercial exchanges.

[Pg 216]A. Its value, as a source of food and mechanical power, depends on its form (like mountains or plains), its content (in terms of soil or minerals), and its climate. All these factors of intrinsic value need to be understood and managed by the people who interact with it to create effective value. However, at any specific time or place, the intrinsic value is set; a particular piece of land, along with its lakes and seas, if properly managed in terms of surface and substance, can yield a certain amount of food and power, and nothing more. Surface management (agriculture) and substance management (practical geology and chemistry) are the foundational aspects of economic science. By surface management, though, I mean more than just agriculture in the typical sense; I mean both land and sea cultivation—control over both the fixed and flowing resources—thorough knowledge of climate laws, and the growth patterns of plants and animals in specific areas of land or sea, as well as the relationships that especially influence the production of food items that can be grown in optimal quality at each particular location, ensuring the best price in commercial exchanges.

B. The second element of value in land is its beauty, united with such conditions of space and form as are necessary for exercise, or pleasant to the eye, associated with vital organism.

B. The second element of value in land is its beauty, combined with the necessary conditions of space and shape that are good for exercise or pleasant to look at, associated with living organisms.

Land of the highest value in these respects is that lying in temperate climates, and boldly varied in form; removed from unhealthy or dangerous influences (as of miasm or volcano); and capable of sustaining a rich fauna and flora. Such land, carefully tended by the hand of man, so far as to remove from it unsightlinesses and evidences of decay; guarded from violence, and inhabited, under man's affectionate protection, by every kind of living creature that can occupy it in peace, forms the most precious "property" that human beings can possess.

Land that is most valuable in these ways is located in temperate climates and has a diverse landscape; it is free from unhealthy or dangerous influences (like swamps or volcanoes) and can support a rich variety of animal and plant life. When such land is carefully maintained by people to eliminate ugliness and signs of decay; protected from harm, and home to every kind of living creature that can thrive there in peace, it becomes the most treasured "property" that humans can own.

The determination of the degree in which these two elements of value can be united in land, or in which either element must, or should, in particular cases, be sacrificed to the other, forms the most important branch of economical inquiry respecting preferences of things.[Pg 217]

The assessment of how much these two elements of value can be combined in land, or when one element must or should, in specific cases, give way to the other, represents the most crucial area of economic study regarding preferences for different things.[Pg 217]

2. Buildings, furniture, and instruments.

Buildings, furniture, and equipment.

The value of buildings consists—A, in permanent strength, with convenience of form, of size, and of position; so as to render employment peaceful, social intercourse easy, temperature and air healthy. The advisable or possible magnitude of cities and mode of their distribution in squares, streets, courts, etc., the relative value of sites of land, and the modes of structure which are healthiest and most permanent, have to be studied under this head.

The value of buildings lies in their lasting strength, along with their convenience in shape, size, and location; this ensures a peaceful work environment, easy social interactions, and healthy temperature and air quality. The recommended or feasible size of cities and how they are organized into squares, streets, courts, etc., the relative worth of land sites, and the construction methods that are healthiest and most durable need to be examined in this context.

B. The value of buildings consists, secondarily, in historical association and architectural beauty, of which we have to examine the influence on manners and life.

B. The value of buildings also lies in their historical significance and architectural beauty, which we need to explore in terms of their impact on behavior and lifestyle.

The value of instruments consists—

The value of instruments is—

A. In their power of shortening labour, or otherwise accomplishing (as ships) what human strength unaided could not. The kinds of work which are severally best accomplished by hand or by machine;—the effect of machinery in gathering and multiplying population, and its influence on the minds and bodies of such population; together with the conceivable uses of machinery on a colossal scale in accomplishing mighty and useful works, hitherto unthought of, such as the deepening of large river channels;—changing the surface of mountainous districts;—irrigating tracts of desert in the torrid zone;—breaking up, and thus rendering capable of quicker fusion edges of ice in the northern and southern Arctic seas, etc., so rendering parts of the earth habitable which hitherto have not been so, are to be studied under this head.

A. In their ability to reduce labor or achieve what human strength alone cannot (like ships). The types of tasks that are best done by hand or by machine; the impact of machinery on gathering and increasing population, and its effect on the minds and bodies of that population; along with the potential uses of machinery on a massive scale for accomplishing incredible and useful projects that have never been imagined before, like deepening large river channels; transforming the landscape of mountainous areas; irrigating desert regions in hot climates; and breaking up ice edges in the northern and southern Arctic seas so that previously uninhabitable parts of the earth can become livable, should be explored under this topic.

B. The value of instruments is, secondarily, in their aid to abstract sciences. The degree in which the multiplication of such instruments should be encouraged, so as to make them, if large, easy of access to numbers (as costly telescopes), or so cheap as that they might, in a serviceable form, become a common part of the furniture of households, is to be considered under this head.

B. The value of tools is, secondly, in how they assist abstract sciences. The extent to which we should promote the increase of such tools, making them easily available to many (like expensive telescopes), or making them so affordable that they could be a common part of household items, should be considered in this context.

3. Food, medicine, and articles of luxury. Under this head we shall have to examine the possible methods of obtaining pure and nourishing food in such security and equality[Pg 218] of supply as to avoid both waste and famine; then the economy of medicine and just range of sanitary law; finally, the economy of luxury, partly an aesthetic and partly an ethical question.

3. Food, medicine, and luxury items. In this section, we will explore the ways to obtain clean and nourishing food while ensuring a secure and equal supply to prevent both waste and famine; then we’ll consider the efficiency of medicine and the appropriate scope of health laws; finally, we’ll look at the economics of luxury, which is both an aesthetic and ethical issue.

4. Books. The value of these consists—

4. Books. The value of these consists—

A. In their power of preserving and communicating the knowledge of facts.

A. In their ability to preserve and share knowledge of facts.

B. In their power of exciting vital or noble emotion and intellectual action. They have also their corresponding negative powers of disguising and effacing the memory of facts, and killing the noble emotions, or exciting base ones. Under these two heads we have to consider the economical and educational value, positive and negative, of literature;—the means of producing and educating good authors, and the means and advisability of rendering good books generally accessible, and directing the reader's choice to them.

B. They have the ability to stir up strong emotions and inspire intellectual activity. They also have the opposite effect of masking and erasing memories of facts, suppressing noble feelings, or inciting lower ones. Under these two categories, we need to evaluate the economic and educational value, both positive and negative, of literature—how to create and nurture good authors, as well as how to make good books widely accessible and guide readers toward them.

5. Works of art. The value of these is of the same nature as that of books, but the laws of their production and possible modes of distribution are very different, and require separate examination.

5. Works of art. Their value is similar to that of books, but the processes of creating them and the ways they can be distributed are quite different and need to be looked at individually.


Section II.—CASH.

Under this head, we shall have to examine the laws of currency and exchange; of which I will note here the first principles.

Under this topic, we will need to look into the laws of currency and exchange; I will outline the basic principles here.

Money has been inaccurately spoken of as merely a means of circulation. It is, on the contrary, an expression of right. It is not wealth, being the sign[69] of the relative quantities of it, to which, at a given time, persons or societies are entitled.

Money has often been incorrectly described as just a way to exchange goods. In reality, it's a representation of rights. It's not wealth itself, but a symbol[69] of the relative amounts of it that individuals or societies are entitled to at any given time.

If all the money in the world, notes and gold, were destroyed in an instant, it would leave the world neither richer nor poorer than it was. But it would leave the individual inhabitants of it in different relations.

If all the money in the world, including cash and gold, were wiped out in a flash, it wouldn't make the world any richer or poorer. However, it would change how each person relates to one another.

Money is, therefore, correspondent in its nature to the title-deed of an estate. Though the deed be burned, the estate still exists, but the right to it has become disputable.

Money is, therefore, similar in nature to the title deed of a property. Even if the deed is destroyed, the property still exists, but the right to it becomes open to dispute.

The worth of money remains unchanged, as long as the proportion of the quantity of existing money to the quantity of existing wealth, or available labour which it professes to represent, remains unchanged.

The value of money stays the same as long as the ratio of the total amount of money to the total amount of wealth or available labor that it claims to represent remains constant.

If the wealth increases, but not the money, the worth of the money increases; if the money increases, but not the wealth, the worth of the money diminishes.

If wealth goes up but money doesn’t, the value of the money goes up; if money goes up but wealth doesn’t, the value of the money goes down.

Money, therefore, cannot be arbitrarily multiplied, any more than title-deeds can. So long as the existing wealth or available labour is not fully represented by the currency, the currency may be increased without diminution of the assigned worth of its pieces. But when the existing wealth, or available labour, is once fully represented, every piece of money thrown into circulation diminishes the worth of every [Pg 220] other existing piece, in the proportion it bears to the number of them, provided the new piece be received with equal credit; if not, the depreciation of worth takes place exclusively in the new piece, according to the inferiority of its credit.

Money cannot be randomly multiplied, just like property titles can't be. As long as the current wealth or available labor isn’t fully represented by the currency, the currency can be increased without reducing the value of its individual units. But once the existing wealth or available labor is fully represented, adding more money into circulation reduces the value of every other existing piece in proportion to the total number of pieces, as long as the new piece is accepted with the same trust; if not, the decrease in value happens only in the new piece, based on how much less credit it has.

When, however, new money, composed of some substance of supposed intrinsic value (as of gold), is brought into the market, or when new notes are issued which are supposed to be deserving of credit, the desire to obtain money will, under certain circumstances, stimulate industry; an additional quantity of wealth is immediately produced, and if this be in proportion to the new claims advanced, the value of the existing currency is undepreciated. If the stimulus given be so great as to produce more goods than are proportioned to the additional coinage, the worth of the existing currency will be raised.

When new money, which is made of something believed to have real value (like gold), is introduced into the market, or when new notes are issued that are thought to be trustworthy, the desire to acquire money can, under certain conditions, boost industry. This leads to an immediate increase in wealth, and if this increase matches the new claims made, the value of the current currency remains stable. However, if the boost is significant enough to create more goods than the new money can support, the value of the existing currency will rise.

Arbitrary control and issues of currency affect the production of wealth, by acting on the hopes and fears of men; and are, under certain circumstances, wise. But the issue of additional currency to meet the exigencies of immediate expense, is merely one of the disguised forms of borrowing or taxing.

Arbitrary control and currency issues impact the generation of wealth by influencing people's hopes and fears; and, in some situations, this can be reasonable. However, creating more currency to cover immediate expenses is just another hidden way of borrowing or taxing.

It is, however, in the present low state of economical knowledge, often possible for Governments to venture on an issue of currency, when they could not venture on an additional loan or tax, because the real operation of such issue is not understood by the people, and the pressure of it is irregularly distributed, and with an unperceived gradation. Finally, the use of substances of intrinsic value as the materials of a currency, is a barbarism;—a remnant of the conditions of barter, which alone can render commerce possible among savage nations. It is, however, still necessary, partly as a mechanical check on arbitrary issues; partly as a means of exchanges with foreign nations. In proportion to the extension of civilization, and increase of trustworthiness in Governments, it will cease. So long as it exists, the phenomena of the cost and price of the articles used for currency, are mingled with those of currency itself, in an almost inextricable manner; and the worth of money in the market is affected by multitudinous accidental circumstances, which[Pg 221] have been traced, with more or less success, by writers on commercial operations; but with these variations the true political economist has no more to do than an engineer fortifying a harbour of refuge against Atlantic tide, has to concern himself with the cries or quarrels of children who dig pools with their fingers for its ebbing currents among the sand.

It is, however, in today's limited understanding of economics, often possible for governments to issue currency when they wouldn’t be able to take on more loans or taxes, because the actual impact of such issuance is not well understood by the public, and the effects are unevenly distributed and not obvious. Additionally, using materials of intrinsic value as currency is outdated—a leftover from barter systems that are only necessary for trade among less developed nations. However, it remains important, partly as a control against arbitrary issuance and partly for trade with other countries. As civilization advances and government trustworthiness grows, this practice will diminish. While it exists, the price and value of items used as currency become entangled with the currency itself in an almost impossible way; the value of money in the market is influenced by countless random factors, which[Pg 221] have been explored, with varying degrees of success, by those studying commerce; but these fluctuations have no more relevance to a true political economist than an engineer concerned with fortifying a safe harbor against the Atlantic tide has to do with the noises or disputes of children digging pools in the sand to catch the receding water.


Section III.—WEALTH.

According to the various industry, capacity, good fortune, and desires of men, they obtain greater or smaller share of, and claim upon, the wealth of the world.

According to different industries, abilities, luck, and people's desires, they get a bigger or smaller share of, and stake in, the world's wealth.

The inequalities between these shares, always in some degree just and necessary, may be either restrained by law (or circumstance) within certain limits; or may increase indefinitely.

The differences between these shares, which are always somewhat fair and necessary, can either be limited by laws (or situations) to a certain extent or can grow without bounds.

Where no moral or legal restraint is put upon the exercise of the will and intellect of the stronger, shrewder, or more covetous men, these differences become ultimately enormous. But as soon as they become so distinct in their extremes as that, on one side, there shall be manifest redundance of possession, and on the other manifest pressure of need,—the terms "riches" and "poverty" are used to express the opposite states; being contrary only in the manner of the terms "warmth" and "cold"; which neither of them imply an actual degree, but only a relation to other degrees, of temperature.

Where there are no moral or legal limits on the actions and intelligence of stronger, smarter, or more greedy people, these differences grow significantly. However, once these disparities become so pronounced that one side clearly has an abundance of resources while the other faces a clear struggle for necessities, we use the terms "riches" and "poverty" to describe these opposing conditions; they are contrary in the same way as "warmth" and "cold," which do not indicate a specific level but rather a relationship to other levels of temperature.

Respecting riches, the economist has to inquire, first, into the advisable modes of their collection; secondly, into the advisable modes of their administration. Respecting the collection of national riches, he has to inquire, first, whether he is justified in calling the nation rich; if the quantity of money it possesses relatively to that possessed by other nations be large, irrespectively of the manner of its distribution. Or does the mode of distribution in any wise affect the nature of the riches? Thus, if the king alone be rich—suppose Crœsus or Mausolus—are the Lydians and Carians therefore a rich nation? Or if one or two slave-masters be rich, and the nation be otherwise composed of slaves, is it to be called a rich nation? For if not, and the ideas of a certain mode of[Pg 223] distribution or operation in the riches, and of a certain degree of freedom in the people, enter into our idea of riches as attributed to a people, we shall have to define the degree of fluency or circulative character which is essential to their vitality; and the degree of independence of action required in their possessors. Questions which look as if they would take time in answering. And farther. Since there are two modes in which the inequality, which is indeed the condition and constituent of riches, may be established—namely, by increase of possession on the one side, and by decrease of it on the other—we have to inquire, with respect to any given state of riches, precisely in what manner the correlative poverty was produced; that is to say, whether by being surpassed only, or being depressed, what are the advantages, or the contrary, conceivable in the depression. For instance, it being one of the commonest advantages of being rich to entertain a number of servants, we have to inquire, on the one side, what economical process produced the poverty of the persons who serve him; and what advantage each (on his own side) derives from the result.

When it comes to wealth, the economist needs to look into two main things: first, the best ways to gather it; second, the best ways to manage it. Regarding the gathering of national wealth, he must first ask whether it’s fair to say the nation is wealthy. Is the amount of money it has significant compared to what other nations possess, regardless of how it's distributed? Or does the way wealth is distributed affect how we define it? For example, if the king is the only wealthy one—like Croesus or Mausolus—does that mean the Lydians and Carians are a wealthy nation? Or if just one or two slave owners are rich while the rest of the nation consists of slaves, should it still be labeled a rich nation? If not, and if our idea of wealth as applied to a society includes certain distribution methods or a certain level of freedom for the people, we need to define how much flow or circulation is essential for wealth to thrive, as well as the level of independence necessary for those who hold that wealth. These are questions that might take some time to answer. Moreover, since there are two ways the inequality— which is actually a prerequisite for wealth—can occur: either through an increase in individual wealth on one side or a decrease on the other, we need to investigate how any particular situation of wealth has resulted in corresponding poverty. Specifically, we need to determine if poverty arises from being outdone or from being pushed down, and consider what benefits—if any—come from that poverty. For example, since one of the most common benefits of being wealthy is the ability to employ many servants, we need to examine what economic processes led to the poverty of those who serve, and what each person gains (from their perspective) as a result of this arrangement.

These being the main questions touching the collection of riches, the next, or last, part of the inquiry is into their administration.

These are the main questions about collecting wealth, so the next, or final, part of the inquiry is about how to manage it.

They have in the main three great economical powers which require separate examination: namely, the powers of selection, direction, and provision.

They mainly have three major economic powers that need to be looked at separately: the powers of selection, direction, and provision.

A. Their power of Selection relates to things of which the supply is limited (as the supply of best things is always). When it becomes matter of question to whom such things are to belong, the richest person has necessarily the first choice, unless some arbitrary mode of distribution be otherwise determined upon. The business of the economist is to show how this choice may be a Wise one.

A. Their ability to Choose relates to things that have a limited supply (since the supply of the best things is always limited). When it comes to deciding who should have these things, the richest person naturally has the first pick, unless some random method of allocation is decided instead. The economist's job is to demonstrate how this choice can be a smart one.

B. Their power of Direction arises out of the necessary relation of rich men to poor, which ultimately, in one way or another, involves the direction of, or authority over, the labour of the poor; and this nearly as much over their mental as[Pg 224] their bodily labour. The business of the economist is to show how this direction may be a Just one.

B. Their ability to Direct comes from the essential relationship between rich people and poor people, which, in one way or another, includes the direction of, or authority over, the labor of the poor; and this applies nearly as much to their mental work as[Pg 224] their physical labor. The role of the economist is to demonstrate how this direction can be fair.

C. Their power of Provision or "preparatory sight" (for pro-accumulation is by no means necessarily pro-vision), is dependent upon their redundance; which may of course by active persons be made available in preparation for future work or future profit; in which function riches have generally received the name of capital; that is to say, of head- or source-material. The business of the economist is to show how this provision may be a Distant one.

C. Their ability to supply or "preparatory sight" (since pro-accumulation doesn't always mean pro-vision) relies on their surplus. This surplus can be utilized by proactive individuals to prepare for future tasks or profits. In this role, wealth is commonly referred to as capital, meaning it is the primary or foundational resource. The economist's job is to demonstrate how this provision can be made for the long term.

The examination of these three functions of riches will embrace every final problem of political economy;—and, above, or before all, this curious and vital problem,—whether, since the wholesome action of riches in these three functions will depend (it appears) on the Wisdom, Justice, and Far-sightedness of the holders; and it is by no means to be assumed that persons primarily rich, must therefore be just and wise,—it may not be ultimately possible so, or somewhat so, to arrange matters, as that persons primarily just and wise, should therefore be rich.

The study of these three roles of wealth will cover every key issue in political economy; and above all, there's this interesting and important question—whether the positive impact of wealth in these three roles relies (it seems) on the wisdom, fairness, and foresight of those who possess it. It shouldn't be taken for granted that wealthy individuals are necessarily just or wise; and it might not ultimately be feasible to set things up in a way that ensures that those who are just and wise will also be wealthy.

Such being the general plan of the inquiry before us, I shall not limit myself to any consecutive following of it, having hardly any good hope of being able to complete so laborious a work as it must prove to me; but from time to time, as I have leisure, shall endeavour to carry forward this part or that, as may be immediately possible; indicating always with accuracy the place which the particular essay will or should take in the completed system.

Given this general outline for our investigation, I won't restrict myself to a strict sequence, as I have little hope of completing such a demanding task. Instead, whenever I have the time, I will try to work on different sections as I can, always clearly indicating where each particular essay fits into the overall plan.

FOOTNOTES:

[66] The science which in modern days had been called Political Economy is in reality nothing more than the investigation of the phenomena of commercial operations. It has no connexion with political economy, as understood and treated of by the great thinkers of past ages; and as long as it is allowed to pass under the same name, every word written by those thinkers—and chiefly the words of Plato, Xenophon, Cicero, and Bacon—must be either misunderstood or misapplied. The reader must not, therefore, be surprised at the care and insistence with which I have retained the literal and earliest sense of all important terms used in these papers; for a word is usually well made at the time it is first wanted; its youngest meaning has in it the full strength of its youth; subsequent senses are commonly warped or weakened; and as a misused word always is liable to involve an obscured thought, and all careful thinkers, either on this or any other subject, are sure to have used their words accurately, the first condition, in order to be able to avail ourselves of their sayings at all, is a firm definition of terms.

[66] The field that we now call Political Economy is really just the study of commercial activities. It doesn't have any connection to the political economy as discussed by the great thinkers of earlier times. As long as it keeps sharing the same name, everything written by those thinkers—especially by Plato, Xenophon, Cicero, and Bacon—will likely be misunderstood or misapplied. Therefore, the reader shouldn't be surprised by my careful attention to maintaining the original and earliest meanings of all important terms in these papers; a word is usually best defined when it’s first used, and its earliest meaning carries its full significance. Later meanings can often be twisted or weakened. Since a misused word can obscure a thought, and serious thinkers on any topic are careful with their word choice, the first step to understanding their ideas is to have clear definitions of the terms.

[67] It may be observed, in anticipation of some of our future results, that while some conditions of the affections are aimed at by the economist as final, others are necessary to him as his own instruments: as he obtains them in greater or less degree his own farther work becomes more or less possible. Such, for instance, are the fortifying virtues, which the wisest men of all time have, with more or less distinctness, arranged under the general heads of Prudence, or Discretion (the spirit which discerns and adopts rightly); Justice (the spirit which rules and divides rightly); Fortitude (the spirit which persists and endures rightly); and Temperance (the spirit which stops and refuses rightly); or in shorter terms still, the virtues which teach how to consist, assist, persist, and desist. These outermost virtues are not only the means of protecting and prolonging life itself, but they are the chief guards or sources of the material means of life, and are the visible governing powers and princes of economy. Thus (reserving detailed statements for the sequel) precisely according to the number of just men in a nation, is their power of avoiding either intestine or foreign war. All disputes may be peaceably settled, if a sufficient number of persons have been trained to submit to the principles of justice. The necessity for war is in direct ratio to the number of unjust persons who are incapable of determining a quarrel but by violence. Whether the injustice take the form of the desire of dominion, or of refusal to submit to it, or of lust of territory, or lust of money, or of mere irregular passion and wanton will, the result is economically the same;—loss of the quantity of power and life consumed in repressing the injustice, as well as of that requiring to be repressed, added to the material and moral destruction caused by the fact of war. The early civil wars of England, and the existing war in America, are curious examples—these under monarchical, this under republican institutions—of the results of the want of education of large masses of nations in principles of justice. This latter war, especially, may perhaps at least serve for some visible, or if that be impossible (for the Greeks told us that Plutus was blind, as Dante that he was speechless), some feelable proof that true political economy is an ethical, and by no means a commercial business. The Americans imagined themselves to know somewhat of money-making; bowed low before their Dollar, expecting Divine help from it; more than potent—even omnipotent. Yet all the while this apparently tangible, was indeed an imaginary Deity;—and had they shown the substance of him to any true economist, or even true mineralogist, they would have been told, long years ago,—"Alas, gentlemen, this that you are gaining is not gold,—not a particle of it. It is yellow, and glittering, and like enough to the real metal,—but see—it is brittle, cat-gold, 'iron firestone.' Out of this, heap it as high as you will, you will get so much steel and brimstone—nothing else; and in a year or two, when (had you known a little of right economy) you might have had quiet roof-trees over your heads, and a fair account at your banker's, you shall instead have to sleep a-field, under red tapestries, costliest, yet comfortless; and at your banker's find deficit at compound interest." But the mere dread or distrust resulting from the want of inner virtues of Faith and Charity among nations, is often no less costly than war itself. The fear which France and England have of each other costs each nation about fifteen millions sterling annually, besides various paralyses of commerce; that sum being spent in the manufacture of means of destruction instead of means of production. There is no more reason in the nature of things that France and England should be hostile to each other than that England and Scotland should be, or Lancashire and Yorkshire; and the reciprocal terrors of the opposite sides of the English Channel are neither more necessary, more economical, nor more virtuous than the old riding and reiving on opposite flanks of the Cheviots, or than England's own weaving for herself of crowns of thorn from the stems of her Red and White Roses.

[67] It's worth noting, looking ahead to some of our future findings, that while some aspects of social issues are seen by economists as goals, others are essential tools for them. The extent to which they acquire these tools makes their further work more or less feasible. For example, these tools include the strengthening virtues that wise men throughout history have categorized under the broader themes of Prudence (the ability to discern and make the right choices), Justice (the ability to rule and distribute rightly), Fortitude (the ability to persevere and endure rightly), and Temperance (the ability to stop and say no rightly). In simpler terms, these virtues teach us how to stand firm, help, persevere, and refrain. These overarching virtues not only protect and extend life itself but also serve as the primary safeguards or sources of the material means of living and are the visible powers that govern the economy. Consequently (keeping detailed discussions for later), a nation's ability to avoid civil or foreign war directly correlates with the number of just individuals within it. All conflicts can be resolved peacefully if a sufficient number of people are trained to adhere to justice principles. The need for war increases in direct proportion to the number of unjust individuals who can only settle disputes through violence. Whether this injustice arises from the desire for power, resistance to it, greed for land, greed for wealth, or uncontrolled passion, the economic outcome is the same: a loss of power and life spent quelling the injustice, along with the material and moral devastation caused by war itself. The early civil wars in England and the ongoing war in America serve as intriguing examples—one under monarchy and the other under republican systems—of the consequences of a lack of education among large populations in justice principles. This latter conflict, in particular, may perhaps provide some visible, or, if that's not feasible (as the Greeks said, Plutus was blind, and Dante said he was speechless), some tangible evidence that true political economy is an ethical matter, not simply a commercial one. Americans believed they understood money-making; they worshipped their Dollar, expecting it to provide divine assistance, more powerful than anything—even omnipotent. All the while, this seemingly concrete entity was actually an imaginary deity; had they presented it to any genuine economist or even true mineralogist, they would have been informed long ago, "Sorry, gentlemen, what you are gaining is not gold—not a single particle of it. It looks yellow and shiny, similar to the real metal—but look—it’s brittle, fool’s gold, ‘iron firestone.’ No matter how high you pile it, you’ll only get steel and brimstone—nothing more; and in a year or two, when (if you’d understood proper economics) you could have enjoyed comfortable homes and a decent bank account, you will instead end up sleeping outdoors, under luxurious yet uncomfortable tapestries; and at your bank, you’ll find deficits with compounded interest." However, the simple fear or distrust arising from the lack of inner virtues like Faith and Charity among nations often costs as much as war itself. The mutual fear between France and England costs each nation around fifteen million pounds annually, along with various disruptions to trade; that amount is spent on creating means of destruction instead of production. There’s no inherent reason in the nature of things that France and England should be hostile towards each other any more than England and Scotland should be, or Lancashire and Yorkshire; and the mutual fears across the English Channel are neither more necessary, economical, nor virtuous than the past raids along the Cheviots, or England's own tradition of weaving crowns of thorns from her Red and White Roses.

[68] With this somewhat strange and ungeometrical limitation, however, which, here expressed for the moment in the briefest terms, we must afterwards trace in detail—that x y may be indefinitely increased by the increase of y only; but not by the increase of x, unless y increases also in a fixed proportion.

[68] With this somewhat strange and non-geometric limitation, which we will later explore in detail, we can say in the simplest terms that x y can continue to grow with the increase of y alone; however, it cannot grow with the increase of x unless y also increases by a consistent ratio.

[69] Always, and necessarily, an imperfect sign; but capable of approximate accuracy if rightly ordered.

[69] Always an imperfect sign, but it can be fairly accurate if organized correctly.


II.

NATURE OF WEALTH, VARIATIONS OF VALUE, THE NATIONAL STORE, NATURE OF LABOUR, VALUE AND PRICE, THE CURRENCY.

The last paper having consisted of little more than definition of terms, I purpose, in this, to expand and illustrate the given definitions, so as to avoid confusion in their use when we enter into the detail of our subject.

The last paper was mainly about defining terms, so in this one, I plan to elaborate on and clarify those definitions to prevent confusion when we dive into the specifics of our topic.

The view which has been taken of the nature of wealth, namely, that it consists in an intrinsic value developed by a vital power, is directly opposed to two nearly universal conceptions of wealth. In the assertion that value is primarily intrinsic, it opposes the idea that anything which is an object of desire to numbers, and is limited in quantity, may be called, or virtually become, wealth. And in the assertion that value is secondarily dependent upon power in the possessor, it opposes the idea that wealth consists of things exchangeable at rated prices. Before going farther, we will make these two positions clearer.

The view of wealth as something that has intrinsic value created by a vital force stands in stark contrast to two almost universally accepted ideas about wealth. First, the claim that value is mainly intrinsic challenges the belief that anything that many people desire and is limited in supply can be considered wealth, or can effectively become wealth. Second, the claim that value relies on the power of the possessor denies the notion that wealth consists of items that can be exchanged at established prices. Before we continue, let’s clarify these two points.

 

First. All wealth is intrinsic, and is not constituted by the judgment of men. This is easily seen in the case of things affecting the body; we know that no force of fantasy will make stones nourishing, or poison innocent; but it is less apparent in things affecting the mind. We are easily—perhaps willingly—misled by the appearance of beneficial results obtained by industries addressed wholly to the gratification of fanciful desire; and apt to suppose that whatever is widely coveted, dearly bought, and pleasurable in possession, must be included in our definition of wealth. It is the more difficult to quit ourselves of this error because many things which are true wealth in moderate use, yet become false wealth in immoderate; and many things are mixed of good and evil,—as, mostly, books and works of art,—out of which[Pg 226] one person will get the good, and another the evil; so that it seems as if there were no fixed good or evil in the things themselves, but only in the view taken, and use made of them. But that is not so. The evil and good are fixed in essence and in proportion. They are separable by instinct and judgment, but not interchangeable; and in things in which evil depends upon excess, the point of excess, though indefinable, is fixed; and the power of the thing is on the hither side for good, and on the farther side for evil. And in all cases this power is inherent, not dependent on opinion or choice. Our thoughts of things neither make, nor mar their eternal force; nor—which is the most serious point for future consideration—can they prevent the effect of it upon ourselves.

First. All wealth is intrinsic and isn't determined by people's opinions. This is clearly seen in matters affecting the body; we know that no amount of imagination will turn stones into food or make poison harmless. However, it's less obvious when it comes to things that impact the mind. We can easily—perhaps willingly—be misled by the appearance of beneficial outcomes from industries focused solely on satisfying fanciful desires, leading us to believe that anything that's widely desired, expensive, and enjoyable to possess must be considered wealthy. It's harder to free ourselves from this misconception because many things that are true wealth in moderation become false wealth in excess; and many things are a mix of good and evil—like most books and works of art—where one person benefits while another suffers, making it seem like there’s no fixed good or evil within the things themselves, only in our perspective and usage of them. But that's not the case. Good and evil are fixed in their essence and proportion. They can be distinguished by instinct and judgment, but they aren’t interchangeable; and with things where evil stems from excess, the threshold for excess, although not clearly defined, is set; and the power of the thing aligns on this side for good and on the other side for evil. In all situations, this power is inherent and not reliant on opinion or choice. Our thoughts about things neither create nor destroy their eternal power; nor—this is the crucial point for future thought—can they stop its effects on us.

Therefore, the object of special analysis of wealth into which we have presently to enter will be not so much to enumerate what is serviceable, as to distinguish what is destructive; and to show that it is inevitably destructive; that to receive pleasure from an evil thing is not to escape from, or alter the evil of it, but to be altered by it; that is, to suffer from it to the utmost, having our own nature, in that degree, made evil also. And it will be shown farther that, through whatever length of time or subtleties of connexion the harm is accomplished (being also less or more according to the fineness and worth of the humanity on which it is wrought), still, nothing but harm ever comes of a bad thing.

Therefore, the focus of our special analysis of wealth will not be so much on listing what is beneficial, but rather on identifying what is harmful; and to demonstrate that it is inevitably harmful. Taking pleasure in something bad doesn't mean we escape or change the badness of it, but rather that we are changed by it; in other words, we endure its negative effects to the fullest, having our own nature made worse in the process. It will also be shown that regardless of how long it takes or the complexities involved in the harm, whether it's more or less depending on the quality and value of the person affected, bad things only result in harm.

So that, finally, wealth is not the accidental object of a morbid desire, but the constant object of a legitimate one.[70] By the fury of ignorance, and fitfulness of caprice, large interests may be continually attached to things unserviceable or hurtful; if their nature could be altered by our passions, the science of Political Economy would be but as the weighing [Pg 227] of clouds, and the portioning out of shadows. But of ignorance there is no science; and of caprice no law. Their disturbing forces interfere with the operations of economy, but have nothing in common with them; the calm arbiter of national destiny regards only essential power for good in all it accumulates, and alike disdains the wanderings of imagination and the thirsts of disease.

So, in the end, wealth isn't just something we randomly desire; it's a continuous goal worth pursuing. By the chaos of ignorance and the unpredictability of whims, significant investments can often get attached to things that are useless or harmful. If we could change their nature based on our emotions, the field of Political Economy would be like measuring clouds and dividing shadows. But there’s no real science in ignorance, and no law in whims. Their disruptive forces affect economic operations but aren't related to them; the steady judge of a nation's destiny focuses only on the true power for good in what it gathers, dismissing both flights of fancy and unhealthy cravings.

 

Secondly. The assertion that wealth is not only intrinsic, but dependent, in order to become effectual, on a given degree of vital power in its possessor, is opposed to another popular view of wealth;—namely, that though it may always be constituted by caprice, it is, when so constituted, a substantial thing, of which given quantities may be counted as existing here, or there, and exchangeable at rated prices.

Secondly. The claim that wealth is not only inherent but also relies on a certain level of vitality in its owner to be effective goes against another common belief about wealth; specifically, that while it may often be determined by whims, once established, it is a tangible asset, with specific amounts that can be counted as existing in certain places and traded at set prices.

In this view there are three errors. The first and chief is the overlooking the fact that all exchangeableness of commodity, or effective demand for it, depends on the sum of capacity for its use existing, here or elsewhere. The book we cannot read, or picture we take no delight in, may indeed be called part of our wealth, in so far as we have power of exchanging either for something we like better. But our power of effecting such exchange, and yet more, of effecting it to advantage, depends absolutely on the number of accessible persons who can understand the book, or enjoy the painting, and who will dispute the possession of them. Thus the [Pg 228]actual worth of either, even to us, depends no less on their essential goodness than on the capacity consisting somewhere for the perception of it; and it is vain in any completed system of production to think of obtaining one without the other. So that, though the great political economist knows that co-existence of capacity for use with temporary possession cannot be always secured, the final fact, on which he bases all action and administration, is that, in the whole nation, or group of nations, he has to deal with, for every grain of intrinsic value produced he must with exactest chemistry produce its twin grain of governing capacity, or in the degrees of his failure he has no wealth. Nature's challenge to us is in earnest, as the Assyrian's mock, "I will give you two thousand horses, if thou be able on thy part to set riders upon them." Bavieca's paces are brave, if the Cid backs him; but woe to us, if we take the dust of capacity, wearing the armour of it, for capacity itself, for so all procession, however goodly in the show of it, is to the tomb.

In this view, there are three mistakes. The first and most important is ignoring the fact that the ability to exchange a commodity, or its effective demand, relies on the total capacity to use it, whether here or elsewhere. A book we can’t read or a painting we don’t enjoy can be considered part of our wealth only to the extent that we can trade either for something we prefer more. However, our ability to make such exchanges, and even more importantly, to do so advantageously, completely depends on the number of people available who can understand the book or appreciate the painting, and who will compete for them. Therefore, the actual value of either, even to us, depends not just on their inherent quality but also on the existence of people somewhere capable of recognizing that quality; it’s futile in any comprehensive production system to think of achieving one without the other. So, while a great economist understands that the coexistence of the capacity for use and temporary possession cannot always be guaranteed, the ultimate fact on which he bases all actions and management is that, in the entire nation or group of nations he is dealing with, for every unit of intrinsic value produced, he must precisely create its equivalent unit of governing capacity, or the extent of his failure means there is no wealth. Nature’s challenge to us is serious, like the Assyrian's taunt, "I will give you two thousand horses if you can provide riders for them." Bavieca’s speed is impressive if the Cid rides him; but woe to us if we mistake the dust of capacity, adorned as if it were capacity itself, for true capacity, because then all our processes, no matter how splendid they appear, lead only to the grave.

The second error in this popular view of wealth is that, in estimating property which we cannot use as wealth, because it is exchangeable, we in reality confuse wealth with money. The land we have no skill to cultivate, the book which is sealed to us, or dress which is superfluous, may indeed be exchangeable, but as such are nothing more than a cumbrous form of bank-note, of doubtful and slow convertibility. As long as we retain possession of them, we merely keep our bank-notes in the shape of gravel or clay, of book leaves, or of embroidered tissue. Circumstances may perhaps render such forms the safest, or a certain complacency may attach to the exhibition of them;—into both these advantages we shall inquire afterwards; I wish the reader only to observe here, that exchangeable property which we cannot use is, to us personally, merely one of the forms of money, not of wealth.

The second mistake in this common perspective on wealth is that when we evaluate property that we can't use as wealth because it can be exchanged, we actually confuse wealth with money. The land we can't cultivate, the book we can't read, or the clothing we don't need may be exchangeable, but they are really just cumbersome forms of banknotes, which are questionable and slow to convert. As long as we own them, we're just holding our banknotes in the shape of dirt or clay, book pages, or fancy fabric. Sometimes, these forms might be the safest option, or we might feel a sense of satisfaction from showing them off; we will explore both of these points later. For now, I want the reader to notice that exchangeable property we can't use is, for us personally, simply another form of money, not real wealth.

The third error in the popular view is the confusion of guardianship with possession; the real state of men of property being, too commonly that of curators, not possessors of wealth. For a man's power of Use, Administration, Ostentation, Destruction, or Bequest; and possession is in use only, which for each man is sternly limited; so that such things,[Pg 229] and so much of them, are well for him, or Wealth; and more of them, or any other things, are ill for him, or Illth. Plunged to the lips in Orinoco, he shall drink to his thirst measure,—more, at his peril; with a thousand oxen on his lands, he shall eat to his hunger measure,—more, at his peril. He cannot live in two houses at once; a few bales of silk or wool will suffice for the fabric of all the clothes he can ever wear, and a few books will probably hold all the furniture good for his brain.[71] Beyond these, in the best of us but narrow, [Pg 230] capacities, we have but the power of administering, or if for harm, mal-administering, wealth (that is to say, distributing, lending, or increasing it);—of exhibiting it (as in magnificence of retinue or furniture), of destroying, or, finally, of bequeathing it. And with multitudes of rich men, administration degenerates into curatorship; they merely hold their property in charge, as Trustees, for the benefit of some person or persons to whom it is to be delivered upon their death; and the position, explained in clear terms, would hardly seem a covetable one. What would be the probable decision of a youth on his entrance into life, to whom the career hoped for him was proposed in terms such as these: "You must work unremittingly, and with your utmost intelligence, during all your available years; you will thus accumulate wealth to a large amount; but you must touch none of it, beyond what is needful for your support. Whatever sums you may gain beyond those required for your decent and moderate maintenance shall be properly taken care of, and on your death-bed you shall have the power of determining to whom they shall belong, or to what purposes be applied?"

The third mistake in the common belief is confusing guardianship with ownership; the true situation for property owners is often that of caretakers, not actual possessors of wealth. A person's ability to Use, Manage, Show Off, Destroy, or Leave behind their possessions is limited; thus, the right amount of such things[Pg 229] is beneficial for him, or Wealth, while having too much, or anything else, is harmful for him, or Illth. Dipped into the Orinoco river, he should drink just enough to quench his thirst—any more would be dangerous; with a thousand cattle on his land, he should eat just enough to satisfy his hunger—more would be risky. He can't live in two houses at the same time; a few bales of silk or wool are enough for all the clothes he could ever wear, and a few books will likely provide all the knowledge suitable for his mind.[71] Beyond these, even in the best among us, our capacities are limited,[Pg 230] and we can only manage, or mismanage, wealth (that is, distribute, lend, or grow it); we can show it off (like with displays of luxury or possessions), destroy it, or ultimately, leave it behind. With many wealthy individuals, managing turns into mere caretaking; they simply look after their assets as Trustees, for the benefit of some person or people who will receive it upon their death; and explained clearly, this role hardly seems desirable. What do you think a young person starting out in life would decide if their future was presented like this: "You must work tirelessly and to the best of your abilities for all your available years; you will therefore accumulate a significant amount of wealth; but you cannot touch any of it beyond what is necessary for your living. Any money you earn beyond what's needed for your respectful and modest living will be properly managed, and on your deathbed, you will have the power to decide who it belongs to or what it should be used for?"

The labour of life, under such conditions, would probably be neither zealous nor cheerful; yet the only difference between this position and that of the ordinary capitalist is the power which the latter delights in supposing himself to possess, and which is attributed to him by others, of spending his money at any moment. This pleasure, taken in the imagination of power to part with that which we have no intention of parting with, is one of the most curious though commonest forms of Eidolon, or Phantasm of Wealth. But the political economist has nothing to do with this idealism, and looks only to the practical issue of it,—namely, that the holder of wealth, in such temper, may be regarded simply as a mechanical means of collection; or as a money-chest with a slit in it,[72] set in the public thoroughfare;—chest of which [Pg 231] only Death has the key, and probably Chance the distribution of contents. In his function of lender (which, however, is one of administration, not use, as far as he is himself concerned), the capitalist takes, indeed, a more interesting aspect; but even in that function, his relations with the state are apt to degenerate into a mechanism for the convenient contraction of debt;—a function the more mischievous, because a nation invariably appeases its conscience with respect to an unjustifiable expense by meeting it with borrowed funds,—expresses its repentance of a foolish piece of business by letting its tradesmen wait for their money,—and always leaves its descendants to pay for the work which will be of the least service to them.[73]

The work of life, in such circumstances, would likely be neither enthusiastic nor happy; yet the only difference between this situation and that of the typical capitalist is the power that the latter enjoys imagining he has, and which others attribute to him, of spending his money at any given moment. This enjoyment, rooted in the illusion of power to give away things we're not actually willing to part with, is one of the most interesting yet common forms of a fantasy about wealth. However, the political economist isn't concerned with this idealism and focuses only on the real outcome of it—that the holder of wealth, in such a state of mind, can merely be viewed as a mechanical means of gathering money; or like a cash box with a slot,[72] placed in a public space;—a box that only Death has the key to, and probably Chance has the role of distributing what’s inside. In his role as a lender (which, however, is more about management than actual use, as far as he is concerned), the capitalist appears a bit more interesting; but even in that role, his connections with the state often turn into a method for easily accumulating debt—a role that becomes more harmful because a nation always eases its conscience regarding an unjustifiable expense by settling it with borrowed money—shows its regret over a foolish decision by making its vendors wait for their payments—and constantly leaves its future generations to cover the costs of projects that will offer them the least benefit.[73]

Quit of these three sources of misconception, the reader will have little farther difficulty in apprehending the real nature of Effectual value. He may, however, at first not without surprise, perceive the consequences involved in the acceptance of our definition. For if the actual existence of wealth be dependent on the power of its possessor, it follows that the sum of wealth held by the nation, instead of being constant or calculable, varies hourly, nay, momentarily, with the number and character of its holders; and that in changing hands, it changes in quantity. And farther, since the worth of the currency is proportioned to the sum of material wealth which it represents, if the sum of the wealth changes, the worth of the currency changes. And thus both the sum of the property, and power of the currency, of the State, vary momentarily, as the character and number of the holders. And not only so, but a different rate and manner of variation is caused by the character of the holders of different kinds of wealth. The transitions of value caused by the character of the holders of land differ in mode from those caused by character in holders of works of art; and these again from those caused by character in holders of machinery or other working capital. But we cannot examine these [Pg 232]special phenomena of any kind of wealth until we have a clear idea of the way in which true currency expresses them; and of the resulting modes in which the cost and price of any article are related to its value. To obtain this we must approach the subject in its first elements.

Once we clear up these three sources of misunderstanding, the reader will have little trouble grasping the true nature of Effectual value. However, at first, they may be surprised by the implications of accepting our definition. If the actual existence of wealth depends on the power of its possessor, it means that the total wealth held by the nation isn't fixed or predictable; it changes every hour, even every moment, based on who holds it and their characteristics. When wealth changes hands, its quantity also changes. Furthermore, since the value of currency is tied to the amount of material wealth it represents, if the total wealth fluctuates, the value of the currency does too. Therefore, both the total property and the power of the currency of the State change constantly as the characteristics and numbers of the holders shift. Moreover, different types of wealth are affected by the nature of their holders in distinct ways. The changes in value caused by landholders differ from those caused by holders of art, and again from those caused by holders of machinery or other productive assets. However, we cannot explore these [Pg 232]special phenomena of any kind of wealth until we have a clear understanding of how true currency reflects them and how the resulting costs and prices of various items relate to their value. To achieve this, we must start from the basics.

Let us suppose a national store of wealth, real or imaginary (that is to say, composed of material things either useful, or believed to be so), presided over by a Government,[74] and that every workman, having produced any article involving labour in its production, and for which he has no immediate use, [Pg 233] brings it to add to this store, receiving, from the Government, in exchange an order either for the return of the thing itself, or of its equivalent in other things,[75] such as he may choose out of the store at any time when he needs them. Now, supposing that the labourer speedily uses this general order, or, in common language, "spends the money," he has neither changed the circumstances of the nation nor his own, except in so far as he may have produced useful and consumed useless articles, or vice versa. But if he does not use, or uses in part only, the order he receives, and lays aside some portion of it; and thus every day bringing his contribution to the national store, lays by some percentage of the order received in exchange for it, he increases the national wealth daily by as much as he does not use of the received order, and to the same amount accumulates a monetary claim on the Government. It is of course always in his power, as it is his legal right, to bring forward this accumulation of claim, and at once to consume, to destroy, or distribute, the sum of his wealth. Supposing he never does so, but dies, leaving his claim to others, he has enriched the State during his life by the quantity of wealth over which that claim extends, or has, in other words, rendered [Pg 234] so much additional life possible in the State, of which additional life he bequeaths the immediate possibility to those whom he invests with his claim, he would distribute this possibility of life among the nation at large.

Let’s imagine a national store of wealth, whether real or imagined (meaning it’s made up of things that are useful or thought to be useful), managed by the Government,[74] and that every worker, after creating an item that took labor to make and isn’t immediately needed by them, [Pg 233] brings it to add to this store, receiving from the Government an order in return for either the item itself or its equivalent in other items,[75] which they can choose from the store whenever they need. Now, if the worker quickly uses this general order, or in simpler terms, "spends the money," their situation and that of the country hasn’t changed except for whether they’ve created something useful and consumed something useless, or the other way around. But if they don’t use, or only partially use, the order they receive and set aside some of it; by consistently contributing to the national store while saving a portion of the order they received, they are increasing the national wealth daily by the amount they don’t use from the order, and accumulating a monetary claim against the Government. It’s always within their power, as it’s their legal right, to cash in this growing claim and immediately spend, destroy, or distribute their wealth. If they never do so and pass away, leaving their claim to others, they have increased the State’s wealth during their lifetime by the amount of wealth that claim represents, that is to say, they’ve made [Pg 234] additional life possible in the State, and they bequeath this potential for life to those they pass their claim to, thus distributing this possibility of life across the nation.

We hitherto consider the Government itself as simply a conservative power, taking charge of the wealth entrusted to it.

We now see the Government as just a conservative authority, responsible for managing the wealth entrusted to it.

But a Government may be far other than a conservative power. It may be on the one hand constructive, on the other destructive.

But a government can be much more than just a conservative force. It can, on one hand, be constructive, and on the other, be destructive.

If a constructive, or improving power, using all the wealth entrusted to it to the best advantage, the nation is enriched in root and branch at once, and the Government is enabled for every order presented, to return a quantity of wealth greater than the order was written for, according to the fructification obtained in the interim.[76]

If a constructive or improving force uses all the wealth entrusted to it wisely, the nation benefits significantly, and the Government can provide a greater amount of wealth than what was requested, based on the growth achieved in the meantime.[76]

This ability may be either concealed, in which case the currency does not completely represent the wealth of the country, or it may be manifested by the continual payment of the excess of value on each order, in which case there is (irrespectively, observe, of collateral results afterwards to be examined) a perpetual rise in the worth of the currency, that is to say, a fall in the price of all articles represented by it.

This ability can either be hidden, meaning the currency doesn't fully reflect the country's wealth, or it can be shown through the ongoing payment of the extra value on each order. In this case, there is, regardless of the collateral consequences that will be looked at later, a constant increase in the value of the currency, which means a decrease in the price of all items it represents.

But if the Government be destructive, or a consuming power, it becomes unable to return the value received on the presentation of the order.

But if the government is harmful or exploitative, it can't give back the value received when the order is presented.

This inability may either (A), be concealed by meeting demands to the full, until it issue in bankruptcy, or in some form of national debt;—or (B), it may be concealed during oscillatory movements between destructiveness and productiveness, which result on the whole in stability;—or (C), it may be manifested by the consistent return of less than value received on each presented order, in which case there is a consistent fall in the worth of the currency, or rise in the price of the things represented by it.

This inability may either (A) be hidden by fully meeting demands until it leads to bankruptcy or some form of national debt; —or (B) it may be concealed during fluctuations between destruction and production that ultimately result in stability; —or (C) it may be shown by the consistent return of less value than what was received for each order, in which case there is a steady decline in the value of the currency or an increase in the price of the things it represents.

Now, if for this conception of a central Government, we substitute that of another body of persons occupied in [Pg 235] industrial pursuits, of whom each adds in his private capacity to the common store: so that the store itself, instead of remaining a public property of ascertainable quantity, for the guardianship of which a body of public men are responsible, becomes disseminated private property, each man giving in exchange for any article received from another, a general order for its equivalent in whatever other article the claimant may desire (such general order being payable by any member of the society in whose possession the demanded article may be found), we at once obtain an approximation to the actual condition of a civilized mercantile community from which approximation we might easily proceed into still completer analysis. I purpose, however, to arrive at every result by the gradual expansion of the simpler conception; but I wish the reader to observe, in the meantime, that both the social conditions thus supposed (and I will by anticipation say also all possible social conditions) agree in two great points; namely, in the primal importance of the supposed national store or stock, and in its destructibility or improvability by the holders of it.

Now, if we replace the idea of a central Government with that of another group of people engaged in [Pg 235] industrial activities, where each individual contributes to the common pool in their personal capacity, we find that the pool itself, instead of being a public asset of a fixed amount managed by a group of public officials, becomes distributed private property. Each person exchanges a general order for something they receive from someone else for its equivalent in any other item they want (that general order can be fulfilled by any member of society who has the requested item). This gives us a close representation of the actual state of a civilized commercial community, which we could easily analyze more deeply from there. My goal is to reach every conclusion by gradually expanding on this simpler idea; however, I want the reader to notice, in the meantime, that both of these assumed social conditions (and I will also say all potential social conditions) share two major points: the fundamental importance of the assumed national store or stock, and its ability to be destroyed or improved by its holders.

I. Observe that in both conditions, that of central Government-holding, and diffused private-holding, the quantity of stock is of the same national moment. In the one case, indeed, its amount may be known by examination of the persons to whom it is confided; in the other it cannot be known but by exposing the private affairs of every individual. But, known or unknown, its significance is the same under each condition. The riches of the nation consist in the abundance, and their wealth depends on the nature of this store.

I. Note that in both situations, whether the government holds central control or private ownership is spread out, the amount of stock is equally important for the nation. In one scenario, you can determine the amount by looking at the individuals it’s entrusted to; in the other, you can only find out by revealing the private matters of each person. However, whether it's known or unknown, its importance remains the same in both cases. The nation's wealth comes from the abundance, and their prosperity relies on the quality of this resource.

II. In the second place, both conditions (and all other possible ones) agree in the destructibility or improvability of the store by its holders. Whether in private hands, or under Government charge, the national store may be daily consumed, or daily enlarged, by its possessors; and while the currency remains apparently unaltered, the property it represents may diminish or increase.[Pg 236]

II. Secondly, both conditions (and all other possible ones) share the characteristic that the store can be destroyed or improved by its holders. Whether it's in private ownership or managed by the government, the national store can be used up or increased every day by its owners; and while the currency seems unchanged, the value of the property it represents can decrease or grow.[Pg 236]

The first question, then, which we have to put under our simple conception of central Government, namely, "What store has it?" is one of equal importance, whatever may be the constitution of the State; while the second question—namely, "Who are the holders of the store?"—involves the discussion of the constitution of the State itself.

The first question we need to consider about our straightforward idea of central government is, "What resources does it have?" This is equally important, regardless of the structure of the state; while the second question—"Who controls these resources?"—requires us to discuss the structure of the state itself.

The first inquiry resolves itself into three heads:

The first inquiry divides into three parts:

1. What is the nature of the store?

1. What is the nature of the store?

2. What is its quantity in relation to the population?

2. What is its amount compared to the population?

3. What is its quantity in relation to the currency?

3. What is its amount compared to the currency?

The second inquiry, into two:

The second inquiry, regarding two:

1. Who are the Holders of the store, and in what proportions?

1. Who owns the store, and in what shares?

2. Who are the Claimants of the store (that is to say, the holders of the currency), and in what proportions?

2. Who are the Claimants of the store (that is to say, the holders of the currency), and in what proportions?

We will examine the range of the first three questions in the present paper; of the two following, in the sequel.

We will look at the first three questions in this paper; the next two will be addressed later.

Question First. What is the nature of the store? Has the nation hitherto worked for and gathered the right thing or the wrong? On that issue rest the possibilities of its life.

Question First. What is the nature of the store? Has the nation been working for and gathering the right things or the wrong ones? The possibilities for its future depend on that issue.

For example, let us imagine a society, of no great extent, occupied in procuring and laying up store of corn, wine, wool, silk, and other such preservable materials of food and clothing; and that it has a currency representing them. Imagine farther, that on days of festivity, the society, discovering itself to derive satisfaction from pyrotechnics, gradually turns its attention more and more to the manufacture of gunpowder; so that an increasing number of labourers, giving what time they can spare to this branch of industry, bring increasing quantities of combustibles into the store, and use the general orders received in exchange to obtain such wine, wool, or corn as they may have need of. The currency remains the same, and represents precisely the[Pg 237] same amount of material in the store, and of labour spent in producing it. But the corn and wine gradually vanish, and in their place, as gradually, appear sulphur and saltpetre; till at last, the labourers who have consumed corn and supplied nitre, presenting on a festal morning some of their currency to obtain materials for the feast, discover that no amount of currency will command anything Festive, except Fire. The supply of rockets is unlimited, but that of food limited in a quite final manner; and the whole currency in the hands of the society represents an infinite power of detonation, but none of existence.

For example, let's picture a small society focused on gathering and storing corn, wine, wool, silk, and other food and clothing materials that can be preserved; and imagine it has a currency that represents these goods. Now, envision that on festive days, this society realizes it enjoys fireworks and gradually shifts its focus toward producing gunpowder. As a result, more and more workers dedicate their spare time to this industry, bringing in larger amounts of explosives to their stockpile and using the general orders they receive in exchange to get whatever wine, wool, or corn they need. The currency remains the same and still accurately represents the[Pg 237] equivalent amount of goods in storage and the labor that went into producing them. However, the corn and wine slowly disappear, and gradually, sulphur and saltpeter take their place. Eventually, on a festive morning, the workers who have consumed the corn and provided the saltpeter realize that no amount of currency can buy anything festive except fire. The supply of rockets is limitless, but food is scarce to the point of extinction; the entire currency held by the society reflects an infinite potential for explosions but none for survival.

The statement, caricatured as it may seem, is only exaggerated in assuming the persistence of the folly to extremity, unchecked, as in reality it would be, by the gradual rise in price of food. But it falls short of the actual facts of human life in expression of the depth and intensity of the folly itself. For a great part (the reader would not believe how great until he saw the statistics in detail) of the most earnest and ingenious industry of the world is spent in producing munitions of war; gathering that is to say the materials, not of festive, but of consuming fire; filling its stores with all power of the instruments of pain, and all affluence of the ministries of death. It was no true Trionfo della Morte which men have seen and feared (sometimes scarcely feared) so long;—wherein he brought them rest from their labours. We see and share another and higher form of his triumph now. Task-master instead of Releaser, he rules the dust of the arena no less than of the tomb; and, content once in the grave whither man went, to make his works cease and his devices to vanish,—now, in the busy city and on the serviceable sea, makes his work to increase, and his devices to multiply.

The statement, as exaggerated as it may seem, only overstates the idea of foolishness going unchecked to extremes, which in reality would be moderated by the gradual increase in food prices. However, it doesn't fully capture the true extent and intensity of that foolishness. A significant portion (you wouldn’t believe how much until you see the detailed statistics) of the world’s most dedicated and clever work is spent on producing weapons of war; gathering materials not for celebrations but for destruction; stocking up on all the tools of suffering and all the means of death. It wasn’t a true Triumph of Death that people have witnessed and feared (sometimes barely feared) for so long, which offered them relief from their struggles. We are now experiencing a different and more profound form of his triumph. As a taskmaster rather than a liberator, he governs both the dust of the arena and the grave; and while once content to bring men to rest in the grave, where their labors would cease and their creations would disappear—now, in the bustling city and on the busy sea, he drives their work to grow and their inventions to flourish.

To this doubled loss, or negative power of labour, spent in producing means of destruction, we have to add in our estimate of the consequences of human folly, whatever more insidious waste of toil there is in the production of unnecessary luxury. Such and such an occupation (it is said) supports so many labourers, because so many obtain wages in following it; but it is never considered that unless there be a supporting power in the product of the occupation, the wages given to[Pg 238] one man are merely withdrawn from another. We cannot say of any trade that it maintains such and such a number of persons, unless we know how and where the money, now spent in the purchase of its produce, would have been spent, if that produce had not been manufactured. The purchasing funds truly support a number of people in making This; but (probably) leave unsupported an equal number who are making, or could have made That. The manufacturers of small watches thrive in Geneva;—it is well;—but where would the money spent on small watches have gone, had there been no small watches to buy?

To this doubled loss, or negative impact of labor spent on creating means of destruction, we also need to consider the consequences of human foolishness, along with any hidden waste of effort in producing unnecessary luxury. People say that certain jobs support a number of workers because many get paid for them; but it’s never taken into account that unless the products of these jobs have supporting value, the wages paid to one person are just taken from another. We can’t claim that any trade supports a specific number of people unless we know how and where the money currently spent on its products would have been spent if those products hadn’t been made. The funds used for purchases genuinely support several people in making This; but (likely) leave an equal number unsupported who are making, or could have made That. The makers of small watches succeed in Geneva—that’s good—but where would the money spent on small watches have gone if there were no small watches to buy?

If the so frequently uttered aphorism of mercantile economy—"labour is limited by capital"—were true, this question would be a definite one. But it is untrue; and that widely. Out of a given quantity of wages, more or less labour is to be had, according to the quantity of will with which we can inspire the workman; and the true limit of labour is only in the limit of this moral stimulus of the will, and the bodily power. In an ultimate, but entirely practical sense, labour is limited by capital, as it is by matter—that is to say, where there is no material, there can be no work—but in the practical sense, labour is limited only by the great original capital[77] of Head, Heart, and Hand. Even in the most artificial relations of commerce, it is to capital as fire to fuel: out of so much fuel you shall have so much fire—not in proportion to the mass of combustibles, but to the force of wind that fans and water that quenches; and the appliance of both. And labour is furthered, as conflagration is, not so much by added fuel, as by admitted air.

If the often repeated saying in business—"labor is limited by capital"—were true, this would be a clear-cut question. But it's not true; and that’s a big misconception. From a set amount of wages, you can get more or less labor depending on how much motivation we can give the worker; and the real limit of labor only lies in the limits of this moral motivation and physical ability. Ultimately, but in a practical sense, labor is limited by capital, just like it's limited by materials—that is, where there is no material, there can be no work—but in practical terms, labor is limited only by the fundamental capital of Mind, Heart, and Hand. Even in the most complex business relationships, capital is like fire to fuel: with a certain amount of fuel, you get a certain amount of fire—not based on the mass of combustibles, but on the strength of the wind that fans it and the water that puts it out; and the application of both. Labor is also boosted, like a fire, not just by adding more fuel, but by allowing in more air.

For which reasons, I had to insert, above, the qualifying "probably"; for it can never be said positively that the purchase money, or wages fund of any trade is withdrawn from some other trade. The object itself may be the stimulus of the production of the money which buys it; that is to say, the work by which the purchaser obtained the means of buying it would not have been done by him, unless he had [Pg 239] wanted that particular thing. And the production of any article not intrinsically (nor in the process of manufacture) injurious, is useful, if the desire of it causes productive labour in other directions.

For which reasons, I had to add the word "probably" above; because it can never be said for sure that the money from a purchase or wages from any job is taken away from another job. The object itself might inspire the production of the money that buys it; in other words, the work the buyer did to earn the money to buy it wouldn’t have happened unless he wanted that specific thing. And producing any item that's not harmful in itself (or during its manufacturing) is beneficial, as long as the desire for it leads to productive work in other areas.

In the national store, therefore, the presence of things intrinsically valueless does not imply an entirely correlative absence of things valuable. We cannot be certain that all the labour spent on vanity has been diverted from reality, and that for every bad thing produced, a precious thing has been lost. In great measure, the vain things represent the results of roused indolence; they have been carved, as toys, in extra time; and, if they had not been made, nothing else would have been made. Even to munitions of war this principle applies; they partly represent the work of men who, if they had not made spears, would never have made pruning-hooks, and who are incapable of any activities but those of contest.

In the national store, the presence of things that have no real value doesn’t necessarily mean there’s a complete lack of valuable things. We can’t be sure that all the time spent on vanity has taken away from reality, or that for every bad product created, a valuable one has been lost. In many ways, these vanity items reflect the outcomes of awakened laziness; they’ve been crafted, like toys, during spare time, and if they hadn’t been made, nothing else would have been created. This principle even applies to weapons of war; they partly represent the efforts of people who, if they hadn’t made spears, would never have made pruning-hooks, and who can only engage in activities centered around conflict.

Thus, then, finally, the nature of the store has to be considered under two main lights, the one, that of its immediate and actual utility; the other, that of the past national character which it signifies by its production, and future character which it must develop by its uses. And the issue of this investigation will be to show us that Economy does not depend merely on principles of "demand and supply," but primarily on what is demanded, and what is supplied.

Thus, the nature of the store must be considered from two main perspectives: one, its immediate and practical utility; and the other, the historical national character it represents through its production, as well as the future character it will shape through its uses. The outcome of this investigation will demonstrate that the economy doesn't solely rely on the principles of "demand and supply," but primarily on what is actually demanded and what is supplied.

Question Second. What is the quantity of the store in relation to the population? It follows from what has been already stated that the accurate form in which this question has to be put is—"What quantity of each article composing the store exists in proportion to the real need for it by the population?" But we shall for the time assume, in order to keep all our terms at the simplest, that the store is wholly composed of useful articles, and accurately proportioned to the several needs of them.

Question Second. What is the quantity of the store in relation to the population? It follows from what has been stated that the precise way to ask this question is—"What quantity of each item in the store exists in relation to the actual need for it by the population?" However, for simplicity’s sake, we will assume for now that the store consists entirely of useful items and is perfectly proportioned to the various needs for them.

Now it does not follow, because the store is large in proportion to the number of people, that the people must be in comfort, nor because it is small, that they must be in distress. An active and economical race always produces[Pg 240] more than it requires, and lives (if it is permitted to do so) in competence on the produce of its daily labour. The quantity of its store, great or small, is therefore in many respects indifferent to it, and cannot be inferred by its aspect. Similarly an inactive and wasteful population, which cannot live by its daily labour, but is dependent, partly or wholly, on consumption of its store, may be (by various difficulties hereafter to be examined, in realization of getting at such store) retained in a state of abject distress, though its possessions may be immense. But the results always involved in the magnitude of store are, the commercial power of the nation, its security, and its mental character. Its commercial power, in that according to the quantity of its store, may be the extent of its dealings; its security, in that according to the quantity of its store are its means of sudden exertion or sustained endurance; and its character, in that certain conditions of civilization cannot be attained without permanent and continually accumulating store, of great intrinsic value, and of peculiar nature.

Now, just because the store is large compared to the number of people doesn’t mean the people have to be comfortable, and just because it’s small doesn’t mean they must be suffering. A hardworking and resourceful population usually produces more than it needs and, if allowed to, lives comfortably on the fruits of its daily efforts. The amount of its store, whether large or small, is largely irrelevant and can’t be judged by its appearance. In contrast, a lazy and wasteful population that can’t sustain itself through its daily labor and relies either partially or completely on consuming its store may find itself in severe distress, even if it has substantial possessions. However, the size of the store always affects a nation’s commercial power, security, and overall character. Its commercial power relates to how much it can trade based on its store, its security refers to its capacity for quick action or sustained resilience based on its store, and its character suggests that certain levels of civilization can’t be reached without a consistently accumulating store of significant and unique value.

Now, seeing that these three advantages arise from largeness of store in proportion to population, the question arises immediately, "Given the store—is the nation enriched by diminution of its numbers? Are a successful national speculation and a pestilence, economically the same thing?"

Now, since these three benefits come from having a large supply in relation to the population, the question immediately arises: "Given the supply—is the nation richer if its population decreases? Are a successful national investment and a plague, economically equivalent?"

This is in part a sophistical question; such as it would be to ask whether a man was richer when struck by disease which must limit his life within a predicable period than he was when in health. He is enabled to enlarge his current expenses, and has for all purposes a larger sum at his immediate disposal (for, given the fortune, the shorter the life the larger the annuity); yet no man considers himself richer because he is condemned by his physician. The logical reply is that, since Wealth is by definition only the means of life, a nation cannot be enriched by its own mortality. Or in shorter words, the life is more than the meat; and existence itself more wealth than the means of existence. Whence, of two nations who have equal store, the more numerous is to be considered the richer, provided the type of the inhabitant be as high (for, though the relative bulk of their store be less, its relative[Pg 241] efficiency, or the amount of effectual wealth, must be greater). But if the type of the population be deteriorated by increase of its numbers, we have evidence of poverty in its worst influence; and then, to determine whether the nation in its total may still be justifiably esteemed rich, we must set or weigh the number of the poor against that of the rich.

This question is somewhat misleading; it's like asking if a person is richer when they are diagnosed with a disease that limits their lifespan compared to when they are healthy. They can spend more right now and have more money available at the moment (since, given the same wealth, a shorter life means a larger annuity); yet nobody considers themselves richer just because their doctor has given them a bad prognosis. The logical answer is that, since wealth is defined as the means to live, a nation cannot become richer through its own mortality. In simpler terms, life is worth more than mere sustenance; and existence itself is a greater wealth than just the resources needed for survival. Therefore, between two nations with the same wealth, the one with a larger population is considered richer, assuming the quality of its inhabitants is high (because, although the total amount of their resources might be less, its overall efficiency, or the amount of effective wealth, should be greater). However, if the quality of the population declines due to an increase in numbers, we see signs of poverty at its worst. To determine whether the nation as a whole can still be considered rich, we must compare the number of poor people to the number of wealthy individuals.

To effect which piece of scalework, it is of course necessary to determine, first, who are poor and who are rich; nor this only, but also how poor and how rich they are! Which will prove a curious thermometrical investigation; for we shall have to do for gold and for silver what we have done for quicksilver—determine, namely, their freezing-point, their zero, their temperate and fever-heat points; finally, their vaporescent point, at which riches, sometimes explosively, as lately in America, "make to themselves wings";—and correspondently the number of degrees below zero at which poverty, ceasing to brace with any wholesome cold, burns to the bone.

To carry out this piece of work, we first need to figure out who is poor and who is rich; but not just that, we also need to assess how poor and how rich they are! This will turn out to be an interesting investigation; we’ll have to apply the same analysis to gold and silver that we do for mercury—specifically, determine their freezing point, their baseline, their moderate and extreme temperatures; and finally, their boiling point, where wealth, sometimes explosively like recently in America, "takes flight";—and correspondingly the number of degrees below zero at which poverty, instead of providing any healthy chill, causes intense suffering.

For the performance of these operations, in the strictest sense scientific, we will first look to the existing so-called "science" of Political Economy; we will ask it to define for us the comparatively and superlatively rich, and the comparatively and superlatively poor; and on its own terms—if any terms it can pronounce—examine, in our prosperous England, how many rich and how many poor people there are; and whether the quantity and intensity of the poverty is indeed so overbalanced by the quantity and intensity of wealth, that we may permit ourselves a luxurious blindness to it, and call ourselves, complacently, a rich country. And if we find no clear definition in the existing science, we will endeavour for ourselves to fix the true degrees of the Plutonic scale, and to apply them.

For these operations, in the most scientific sense, we will first refer to the current so-called "science" of Political Economy; we will ask it to define for us the relatively rich and the relatively poor; and based on its own criteria—if it has any—we will examine, in our prosperous England, how many rich people and how many poor people there are; and whether the amount and severity of poverty is truly outweighed by the amount and severity of wealth, so that we can allow ourselves to overlook it and call ourselves, with self-satisfaction, a wealthy country. If we don't find a clear definition in the existing science, we will try to establish for ourselves the proper gradations of the wealth scale and apply them.

Question Third. What is the quantity of the store in relation to the Currency? We have seen that the real worth of the currency, so far as dependent on its relation to the magnitude of the store, may vary within certain limits, without affecting its worth in exchange. The diminution or increase of the represented wealth may be unperceived, and the currency may be taken either for more or less than it is[Pg 242] truly worth. Usually, it is taken for more; and its power in exchange, or credit-power, is thus increased (or retained) up to a given strain upon its relation to existing wealth. This credit-power is of chief importance in the thoughts, because most sharply present to the experience, of a mercantile community; but the conditions of its stability[78] and all other relations of the currency to the material store are entirely simple in principle, if not in action. Far other than simple are the relations of the currency to that "available labour" which by our definition (p. 219) it also represents. For this relation is involved not only with that of the magnitude of the store to the number, but with that of the magnitude of the store to the mind, of the population. Its proportion to their number, and the resulting worth of currency, are calculable; but its proportion to their will for labour is not. The worth of the piece of money which claims a given quantity of the store, is, in exchange, less or greater according to the facility of obtaining the same quantity of the same thing without having recourse to the store. In other words, it depends on the immediate Cost and Price of the thing. We must now, therefore, complete the definition of these terms.

Question Three. What is the relationship between the amount of goods and the Currency? We have observed that the real value of currency, as far as it relates to the amount of goods, can fluctuate within certain limits without affecting its value in exchange. Changes in the represented wealth may go unnoticed, and the currency may be valued at more or less than it actually is[Pg 242]. Typically, it is valued at more, which increases (or maintains) its power in exchange, or credit-power, up to a certain point in relation to the existing wealth. This credit-power is crucial in the minds of a mercantile community as it is most directly related to their experiences; however, the conditions for its stability[78] and all other relationships of currency to the material goods are quite straightforward in principle, if not in practice. The relationships between currency and "available labor," as we defined it (p. 219), are much more complex. This relationship involves not only the amount of goods in relation to the population but also the amount of goods in relation to their mindset. The ratio of goods to their number, and the resulting value of currency, can be calculated; however, the ratio to their willingness to work cannot. The value of a piece of money that corresponds to a certain amount of goods varies in exchange based on how easily one can obtain that same amount of goods without relying on the store. In other words, it depends on the immediate Cost and Price of the item. Therefore, we must now complete the definitions of these terms.

All cost and price are counted in Labour. We must know first, therefore, what is to be counted as Labour.

All costs and prices are calculated in terms of Labor. We need to identify first what should be considered as Labor.

I have already defined labour to be the Contest of the life of man with an opposite.[79] Literally, it is the quantity of "Lapse," loss, or failure of human life caused by any effort. It is usually confused with effort itself, or the application of [Pg 243] power (opera); but there is much effort which is merely a mode of recreation, or of pleasure. The most beautiful actions of the human body and the highest results of the human intelligence, are conditions, or achievements, of quite unlaborious, nay, of recreative, effort. But labour is the suffering in effort. It is the negative quantity, or quantity of de-feat which has to be counted against every Feat, and of de-fect which has to be counted against every Fact, or Deed of men. In brief, it is "that quantity of our toils which we die in."

I have already defined labor as the struggle of human life against something opposing it.[79] Essentially, it represents the amount of "Lapse," loss, or failure of human life that results from any effort. It's often mistaken for effort itself or the application of [Pg 243] power (opera); however, a lot of effort is just a form of recreation or enjoyment. The most beautiful actions of the human body and the greatest achievements of human intelligence can happen under conditions or as a result of efforts that are not laborious, but rather recreative. Labor, on the other hand, is the suffering involved in effort. It is the negative aspect, or the amount of defeat that must be weighed against every accomplishment, and the flaws that must be considered against every action or deed of humanity. In short, it is "that portion of our struggles in which we ultimately perish."

We might, therefore, à priori, conjecture (as we shall ultimately find) that it cannot be bought, nor sold. Everything else is bought and sold for Labour, but labour itself cannot be bought nor sold for anything, being priceless.[80] The idea that it is a commodity to be bought or sold, is the alpha and omega of Politico-Economic fallacy.

We can, therefore, initially guess (as we will ultimately discover) that it can't be bought or sold. Everything else is traded for labor, but labor itself can't be exchanged for anything, as it is invaluable.[80] The notion that it is a commodity to be traded is the beginning and end of the Politico-Economic misconception.

This being the nature of labour, the "Cost" of anything is the quantity of labour necessary to obtain it;—the quantity for which, or at which, it "stands" (constat). It is literally the "Constancy" of the thing;—you shall win it—move it—come at it—for no less than this.

This is the nature of work: the "Cost" of something is the amount of labor needed to get it; the amount for which it "stands." It is essentially the "Constancy" of the item; you will acquire it—move it—get it—for no less than this.

Cost is measured and measurable only in "labor," not in "opera."[81] It does not matter how much power a thing needs to produce it; it matters only how much distress. [Pg 244] Generally the more power it requires, the less the distress; so that the noblest works of man cost less than the meanest.

Cost is measured and measurable only in "labor," not in "work."[81] It doesn’t matter how much power something needs to produce it; what matters is how much distress it causes. [Pg 244] Usually, the more power it requires, the less distress there is; so, the greatest achievements of humanity cost less than the most trivial.

True labour, or spending of life, is either of the body, in fatigue or pain, of the temper or heart (as in perseverance of search for things,—patience in waiting for them,—fortitude or degradation in suffering for them, and the like), or of the intellect. All these kinds of labour are supposed to be included in the general term, and the quantity of labour is then expressed by the time it lasts. So that a unit of labour is "an hour's work" or a day's work, as we may determine.[82]

True work, or how we spend our lives, comes from the body, involving fatigue or pain, from the mind or emotions (like the persistence in searching for things, being patient while waiting for them, or coping with suffering for them), or from our intellect. All these types of work are understood to fall under the general term, and the amount of work is measured by how long it takes. So, a unit of work can be defined as "an hour's work" or "a day's work," depending on how we choose to measure it.[82]

Cost, like value, is both intrinsic and effectual. Intrinsic cost is that of getting the thing in the right way; effectual cost is that of getting the thing in the way we set about it. But intrinsic cannot be made a subject of analytical investigation, being only partially discoverable, and that by long experience. Effectual cost is all that the political economist can deal with; that is to say, the cost of the thing under existing circumstances and by known processes.

Cost, like value, has both an inherent and practical side. Inherent cost refers to obtaining something the right way, while practical cost relates to obtaining it through our chosen methods. However, the inherent aspect can't be analyzed thoroughly, as it can only be partially understood through extensive experience. Practical cost is what political economists can address; in other words, it’s the cost of something based on current situations and established processes.

Cost (irrespectively of any question of demand or supply) varies with the quantity of the thing wanted, and with the number of persons who work for it. It is easy to get a little of some things, but difficult to get much; it is impossible to get some things with few hands, but easy to get them with many.

Cost (regardless of demand or supply) changes with how much of a thing is desired and how many people are working for it. It’s simple to acquire a small amount of some things, but hard to obtain a large quantity; it's impossible to get certain things with just a few people, but easy to get them with many.

The cost and value of things, however difficult to determine accurately, are thus both dependent on ascertainable physical circumstances.[83]

The cost and value of things, although challenging to figure out precisely, both rely on measurable physical conditions.[83]

[Pg 245]But their price is dependent on the human will.

[Pg 245]But their price depends on human desire.

Such and such a thing is demonstrably good for so much. And it may demonstrably be bad for so much.

Such and such a thing is clearly good for a lot. And it can also clearly be bad for a lot.

[Pg 246]But it remains questionable, and in all manner of ways questionable, whether I choose to give so much.[84]

[Pg 246]But it’s still up in the air, and in many different ways up in the air, whether I decide to give so much.[84]

This choice is always a relative one. It is a choice to give a price for this, rather than for that;—a resolution to have the thing, if getting it does not involve the loss of a better thing. Price depends, therefore, not only on the cost of the commodity itself, but on its relation to the cost of every other attainable thing.

This choice is always a relative one. It's about deciding on a price for this instead of that; it’s a decision to go for what you want, as long as getting it doesn’t mean losing something better. So, price depends not just on the cost of the item itself, but on how it compares to the cost of everything else you can get.

Farther. The power of choice is also a relative one. It depends not merely on our own estimate of the thing, but on everybody else's estimate; therefore on the number and force of the will of the concurrent buyers, and on the existing quantity of the thing in proportion to that number and force.

Farther. The power of choice is also a relative thing. It doesn't just rely on our own assessment of something, but on how everyone else views it; so it depends on the number and strength of the willing buyers, and on how much of the item is available compared to that number and strength.

Hence the price of anything depends on four variables.[85]

Hence, the price of anything depends on four factors.[85]

1. Its cost.

Price.

2. Its attainable quantity at that cost.

2. The amount you can get at that price.

3. The number and power of the persons who want it.

3. The number and influence of the people who want it.

4. The estimate they have formed of its desirableness.

4. The judgment they've made about how desirable it is.

(Its value only affects its price so far as it is contemplated in this estimate; perhaps, therefore, not at all.)

(Its value only impacts its price as far as it's considered in this estimate; maybe, therefore, not at all.)

Now, in order to show the manner in which price is expressed in terms of a currency, we must assume these four quantities to be known, and the "estimate of desirableness," commonly called the Demand, to be certain. We will take the number of persons at the lowest. Let A and B be two labourers who "demand," that is to say, have resolved to [Pg 247] labour for, two articles, a and b. Their demand for these articles (if the reader likes better, he may say their need) is to be absolute, existence depending on the getting these two things. Suppose, for instance, that they are bread and fuel in a cold country, and let a represent the least quantity of bread, and b the least quantity of fuel, which will support a man's life for a day. Let a be producible by an hour's labour but b only by two hours' labour; then the cost of a is one hour, and of b two (cost, by our definition, being expressible in terms of time). If, therefore, each man worked both for his corn and fuel, each would have to work three hours a day. But they divide the labour for its greater ease.[86] Then if A works three hours, he produces 3a, which is one a more than both the men want. And if B works three hours, he produces only 1½b, or half of b less than both want. But if A works three hours and B six, A has 3a, and B has 3b, a maintenance in the right proportion for both for a day and a half; so that each might take a half a day's rest. But as B has worked double time, the whole of this day's rest belongs in equity to him. Therefore, the just exchange should be, A, giving two a for one b, has one a and one b;—maintenance for a day. B, giving one b for two a, has two a and two b;—maintenance for two days.

Now, to explain how price is represented in terms of currency, we need to assume that these four quantities are known and that the "estimate of desirability," usually called Demand, is certain. We'll consider the lowest number of people involved. Let A and B be two laborers who "demand," meaning they have decided to work for two items, a and b. Their demand for these items (or their need, if you prefer) is absolute, with their survival depending on obtaining these two things. For example, let’s say they are bread and fuel in a cold climate. Let a be the minimum amount of bread and b be the minimum amount of fuel that can sustain a man for a day. If a can be produced with one hour of labor and b takes two hours, then the cost of a is one hour, and the cost of b is two hours (with cost, by our definition, being expressed in terms of time). Therefore, if each man works for his corn and fuel, each would need to work three hours a day. However, they divide the labor to make it easier.[86] If A works three hours, he produces 3a, which is one a more than both of them need. If B works three hours, he produces only 1½b, or half of b less than what they both want. But if A works three hours and B works six, A has 3a and B has 3b, providing enough for both for a day and a half, allowing each to take half a day's rest. However, since B has worked double the time, he is entitled to the entire day’s rest. Therefore, the fair exchange would be that A, giving two a for one b, ends up with one a and one b, providing maintenance for one day. B, giving one b for two a, ends up with two a and two b, providing maintenance for two days.

But B cannot rest on the second day, or A would be left without the article which B produces. Nor is there any means of making the exchange just, unless a third labourer is called in. Then one workman, A, produces a, and two, B and C, produce b;—A, working three hours, has three a;—B, three hours, 1½b;—C, three hours, 1½b. B and C each give half of b for a, and all have their equal daily maintenance for equal daily work.

But B can't take a day off, or A will be left without the item that B makes. There’s also no way to make the trade fair unless a third worker is brought in. So, one worker, A, produces a, and the two, B and C, produce b;—A works for three hours and makes three a;—B works for three hours and produces 1½b;—C works for three hours and also produces 1½b. B and C each give half of b in exchange for a, and everyone gets their fair share of daily sustenance for their equal daily effort.

To carry the example a single step farther, let three articles, a, b, and c, be needed.

To extend the example just a bit further, let's say we need three items, a, b, and c.

Let a need one hour's work, b two, and c four; then the day's work must be seven hours, and one man in a day's [Pg 248] work can make 7a, or 3½b, or 1¾c. Therefore one A works for a, producing 7a; two B's work for b, producing 7b; four C's work for c, producing 7c.

Let a take one hour of work, b two hours, and c four hours; then the total work for the day must be seven hours, and one person in a day's [Pg 248] work can complete 7a, or 3½b, or 1¾c. So, one A works on a, producing 7a; two B's work on b, producing 7b; four C's work on c, producing 7c.

A has six a to spare, and gives two a for one b, and four a for one c. Each B has 2½b to spare, and gives ½b for one a, and two b for one c. Each C has ¾ of c to spare, and gives ½c for one b, and ¼ of c for one a. And all have their day's maintenance.

A has six a left over, and gives two a for one b, and four a for one c. Each B has 2½ b left over, and gives ½ b for one a, and two b for one c. Each C has ¾ of c left over, and gives ½ c for one b, and ¼ of c for one a. And all have what they need for the day.

Generally, therefore, it follows that, if the demand is constant,[87] the relative prices of things are as their costs, or as the quantities of labour involved in production.

Generally, it follows that if the demand is constant,[87] the relative prices of items are in line with their costs or the amount of labor required for production.

Then, in order to express their prices in terms of a currency, we have only to put the currency into the form of orders for a certain quantity of any given article (with us it is in the form of orders for gold), and all quantities of other articles are priced by the relation they bear to the article which the currency claims.

Then, to express their prices in a currency, we just need to convert the currency into orders for a specific quantity of any item (for us, it's in the form of orders for gold), and all quantities of other items are priced based on how they relate to the item that the currency represents.

But the worth of the currency itself is not in the slightest degree founded more on the worth of the article for which the gold is exchangeable. It is just as accurate to say, "So many pounds are worth an acre of land," as "An acre of land is worth so many pounds." The worth of gold, of land, of houses, and of food, and of all other things, depends at any moment on the existing quantities and relative demands for all and each; and a change in the worth of, or demand for, any one, involves an instantaneously correspondent change in the worth, and demand for, all the rest—a change as inevitable and as accurately balanced (though often in its process as untraceable) as the change in volume of the outflowing river from some vast lake, caused by change in the volume of the inflowing streams, though no eye can trace, no instrument detect motion either on its surface, or in the depth.

But the value of the currency itself isn't really based on the value of the item for which the gold can be exchanged. It's just as accurate to say, "So many pounds are worth an acre of land," as it is to say, "An acre of land is worth so many pounds." The value of gold, land, houses, food, and everything else depends at any moment on the existing quantities and relative demands for each. A change in the value of, or demand for, any one item leads to an immediate corresponding change in the value and demand for all the others—a change that’s as certain and as perfectly balanced (though often untraceable in its process) as the change in the volume of water flowing out of some large lake, caused by a change in the volume of the streams flowing in, even though no eye can see it and no instrument can detect motion either on its surface or in its depths.

Thus, then, the real working power or worth of the currency is founded on the entire sum of the relative estimates formed by the population of its possessions; a change in this estimate in any direction (and therefore every change in the national character), instantly alters the value of money, in its second great function of commanding labour. But [Pg 249] we must always carefully and sternly distinguish between this worth of currency, dependent on the conceived or appreciated value of what it represents, and the worth of it, dependent on the existence of what it represents. A currency is true or false, in proportion to the security with which it gives claim to the possession of land, house, horse, or picture; but a currency is strong or weak, worth much or worth little, in proportion to the degree of estimate in which the nation holds the house, horse, or picture which is claimed. Thus the power of the English currency has been, till of late, largely based on the national estimate of horses and of wine: so that a man might always give any price to furnish choicely his stable, or his cellar, and receive public approval therefor: but if he gave the same sum to furnish his library, he was called mad, or a Bibliomaniac. And although he might lose his fortune by his horses, and his health or life by his cellar, and rarely lost either by his books, he was yet never called a Hippomaniac nor an Oinomaniac; but only Bibliomaniac, because the current worth of money was understood to be legitimately founded on cattle and wine, but not on literature. The prices lately given at sales for pictures and MSS. indicate some tendency to change in the national character in this respect, so that the worth of the currency may even come in time to rest, in an acknowledged manner, somewhat on the state and keeping of the Bedford missal, as well as on the health of Caractacus or Blink Bonny; and old pictures be considered property, no less than old port. They might have been so before now, but it is more difficult to choose the one than the other.

Thus, the true power or value of currency is based on the total amount of relative assessments made by the population of its assets; any change in this assessment in either direction (and consequently, every change in national character) instantly affects the value of money, particularly in its second main role of commanding labor. But [Pg 249] we must always carefully and firmly differentiate between this value of currency, which depends on the perceived or appreciated value of what it represents, and its value, which depends on the actual existence of what it represents. Currency is true or false based on how securely it claims the ownership of land, a house, a horse, or a painting; however, a currency is strong or weak, valuable or worthless, depending on how much the nation values the house, horse, or painting in question. Until recently, the power of the English currency has been largely based on the national value placed on horses and wine: a person could always pay any price to smartly stock their stable or cellar and receive public approval for it; but if they spent the same amount to stock their library, they were deemed insane or a bibliomaniac. Although they might lose their fortune through their horses, and their health or life through their wine, and rarely lost anything through their books, they were never called a hippomaniac or oinomaniac, only bibliomaniac, because the current value of money was considered legitimately based on livestock and wine, but not on literature. The recent prices fetched at auctions for paintings and manuscripts suggest a shift in national values regarding this, so that the value of currency might, over time, come to be recognized as partly based on the condition and preservation of the Bedford missal, just as it is on the health of Caractacus or Blink Bonny; and old paintings could be considered property no less than old port. They might have been recognized as such before, but it is more challenging to select one over the other.

Now, observe, all these sources of variation in the power of the currency exist wholly irrespective of the influences of vice, indolence, and improvidence. We have hitherto supposed, throughout the analysis, every professing labourer to labour honestly, heartily, and in harmony with his fellows. We have now to bring farther into the calculation the effects of relative industry, honour, and forethought, and thus to follow out the bearings of our second inquiry: Who are the holders of the Store and Currency, and in what proportions?

Now, notice that all these sources of variation in the power of the currency exist completely independent of the impacts of vice, laziness, and carelessness. So far in our analysis, we've assumed that every worker claims to work honestly, energetically, and cooperatively with their peers. Now we need to factor in the effects of relative effort, integrity, and planning ahead, and thus continue with the focus of our second question: Who holds the Store and Currency, and in what amounts?

This, however, we must reserve for our next paper,—noticing[Pg 250] here only that, however distinct the several branches of the subject are, radically, they are so interwoven in their issues that we cannot rightly treat any one, till we have taken cognisance of all. Thus the quantity of the currency in proportion to number of population is materially influenced by the number of the holders in proportion to the non-holders; and this again by the number of holders of goods. For as, by definition, the currency is a claim to goods which are not possessed, its quantity indicates the number of claimants in proportion to the number of holders; and the force and complexity of claim. For if the claims be not complex, currency as a means of exchange may be very small in quantity. A sells some corn to B, receiving a promise from B to pay in cattle, which A then hands over to C, to get some wine. C in due time claims the cattle from B; and B takes back his promise. These exchanges have, or might have been, all effected with a single coin or promise; and the proportion of the currency to the store would in such circumstances indicate only the circulating vitality of it—that is to say, the quantity and convenient divisibility of that part of the store which the habits of the nation keep in circulation. If a cattle-breeder is content to live with his household chiefly on meat and milk, and does not want rich furniture, or jewels, or books,—if a wine- and corn-grower maintains himself and his men chiefly on grapes and bread;—if the wives and daughters of families weave and spin the clothing of the household, and the nation, as a whole, remains content with the produce of its own soil and the work of its own hands, it has little occasion for circulating media. It pledges and promises little and seldom; exchanges only so far as exchange is necessary for life. The store belongs to the people in whose hands it is found, and money is little needed either as an expression of right, or practical means of division and exchange.

This, however, we have to save for our next paper,—noting[Pg 250] here only that, even though the different branches of the topic are distinct, they are so interconnected in their outcomes that we can’t properly address one until we consider all of them. Therefore, the amount of currency in relation to the population is significantly affected by the number of people holding it compared to those who don’t; and this is influenced again by the number of goods held. Since, by definition, currency represents a claim to goods not owned, its quantity reflects the number of claimants relative to the number of holders; and the complexity of claims. If the claims are not complicated, the amount of currency used for exchange may be quite small. A sells some corn to B, getting a promise from B to pay in cattle, which A then gives to C to buy some wine. C eventually claims the cattle from B; and B gives back his promise. These exchanges could have all been done with a single coin or promise; and in such cases, the ratio of currency to reserves would merely reveal its circulating vitality—that is, the amount and convenient divisibility of the part of the reserves that people choose to keep in circulation. If a cattle-breeder is happy to live primarily on meat and milk and doesn’t need fancy furniture, jewelry, or books—if a wine- and corn-grower sustains himself and his workers mainly on grapes and bread;—if the wives and daughters of families weave and spin their household clothing, and the nation as a whole is satisfied with what it produces and the work of its own hands, it has little need for a currency. It promises and pledges rarely; exchanges only as much as is essential for living. The reserves belong to the people who possess them, and money is hardly needed as a representation of rights or as a practical means of division and exchange.

But in proportion as the habits of the nation become complex and fantastic (and they may be both, without therefore being civilized), its circulating medium must increase in proportion to its store. If everyone wants a little of everything,—if food must be of many kinds, and dress of many fashions,—if multitudes live by work which, ministering to[Pg 251] fancy, has its pay measured by fancy, so that large prices will be given by one person for what is valueless to another,—if there are great inequalities of knowledge, causing great inequalities of estimate,—and finally, and worst of all, if the currency itself, from its largeness, and the power which the possession of it implies, becomes the sole object of desire with large numbers of the nation, so that the holding of it is disputed among them as the main object of life:—in each and all these cases, the currency enlarges in proportion to the store, and, as a means of exchange and division, as a bond of right, and as an expression of passion, plays a more and more important part in the nation's dealings, character, and life.

But as the habits of the nation become more complex and extravagant (and they can be both without being civilized), the amount of money in circulation must increase in line with its supply. If everyone wants a bit of everything—if food has to come in various types, and clothing in various styles—if many people earn a living by work that caters to different tastes, with pay determined by what’s fashionable, resulting in some people paying high prices for things that are worthless to others—if there are significant gaps in knowledge creating disparities in value assessment—and finally, and most importantly, if having money itself, due to its abundance and the power it represents, becomes the primary goal for many people, leading to intense competition for its possession as the main focus of life:—in all these cases, the currency expands in relation to the supply and, as a means of exchange and division, as a legal bond, and as a reflection of emotion, takes on an increasingly crucial role in the nation's transactions, character, and existence.

Against which part, when, as a bond of Right, it becomes too conspicuous and too burdensome, the popular voice is apt to be raised in a violent and irrational manner, leading to revolution instead of remedy. Whereas all possibility of Economy depends on the clear assertion and maintenance of this bond of right, however burdensome. The first necessity of all economical government is to secure the unquestioned and unquestionable working of the great law of Property—that a man who works for a thing shall be allowed to get it, keep it, and consume it, in peace; and that he who does not eat his cake to-day, shall be seen, without grudging, to have his cake to-morrow. This, I say, is the first point to be secured by social law; without this, no political advance, nay, no political existence, is in any sort possible. Whatever evil, luxury, iniquity, may seem to result from it, this is nevertheless the first of all Equities; and to the enforcement of this, by law and by police-truncheon, the nation must always primarily set its mind—that the cupboard door may have a firm lock to it, and no man's dinner be carried off by the mob, on its way home from the baker's. Which, thus fearlessly asserting, we shall endeavour in the next paper to consider how far it may be practicable for the mob itself, also, in due breadth of dish, to have dinners to carry home.

When a certain right becomes too obvious and too heavy to bear, the public tends to react in a loud and irrational way, often leading to revolution instead of solutions. However, the possibility of economic stability relies on clearly affirming and maintaining this right, no matter how burdensome it may feel. The essential requirement of effective governance is to ensure that the fundamental law of Property is upheld—that a person who works for something should be allowed to obtain it, keep it, and enjoy it in peace; and that someone who saves their cake for tomorrow should be able to do so without any resentment. This is, I argue, the first principle that must be secured by social law; without it, no political progress, or even political existence, is in any way feasible. Regardless of the problems, excess, or injustice that may arise from it, this remains the most basic form of fairness; and the country must always prioritize enforcing this through law and authority, ensuring that the pantry is securely locked and that no one’s dinner is taken by the crowd on its way home from the bakery. With this bold assertion, we will next explore how feasible it might be for the crowd itself to also have meals to take home, in appropriate portions.

FOOTNOTES:

[70] Few passages of the Book which at least some part of the nations at present most advanced in civilization accept as an expression of final truth, have been more distorted than those bearing on Idolatry. For the idolatry there denounced is neither sculpture, nor veneration of sculpture. It is simply the substitution of an "Eidolon," phantasm, or imagination of Good, for that which is real and enduring; from the Highest Living Good, which gives life, to the lowest material good which ministers to it. The Creator, and the things created, which He is said to have "seen good" in creating, are in this their eternal goodness always called Helpful or Holy: and the sweep and range of idolatry extend to the rejection of all or any of these, "calling evil good, or good evil,—putting bitter for sweet, and sweet for bitter," so betraying the first of all Loyalties, to the fixed Law of life, and with resolute opposite loyalty serving our own imagination of good, which is the law, not of the dwelling, but of the Grave (otherwise called the law of error; or "mark missing," which we translate law of "Sin"), these "two masters," between whose services we have to choose, being otherwise distinguished as God and "Mammon," which Mammon, though we narrowly take it as the power of money only, is in truth the great evil spirit of false and fond desire, or "Covetousness, which is Idolatry." So that Iconoclasm—image or likeness-breaking—is easy; but an idol cannot be broken—it must be forsaken, and this is not so easy, either in resolution or persuasion. For men may readily be convinced of the weakness of an image, but not of the emptiness of a phantasm.

[70] Few sections of the Book, which at least some parts of the world's most advanced nations see as a final truth, have been distorted more than those concerning Idolatry. The idolatry being criticized here is not about sculptures or the worship of sculptures. It's merely about replacing a concept, an "Eidolon," a phantom or imagination of what is good, with what is real and lasting; from the Highest Living Good, which gives life, to the lowest material good that serves it. The Creator and the things He created, which He deemed "good," are in their eternal goodness always referred to as Helpful or Holy: and the scope of idolatry extends to rejecting any of these, "calling evil good, or good evil,—putting bitter for sweet, and sweet for bitter," thus betraying the fundamental Loyalty to the unchanging Law of life, and resolutely serving our own imagined version of good, which is the law not of life but of the Grave (known as the law of error, or "mark missing," which we interpret as the law of "Sin"). These "two masters," between whose services we must choose, are distinguished as God and "Mammon," which, even when we focus narrowly on it as the power of money, is actually the great evil spirit of false desires, or "Covetousness, which is Idolatry." So, breaking images is easy; but an idol can't simply be broken—it must be abandoned, and that's not so easy, either in determination or persuasion. People can easily be convinced of the weakness of an image, but not of the emptiness of a phantasm.

[71] I reserve, until the completion and collection of these papers, any support by the authority of other writers of the statements made in them; were, indeed, such authorities wisely sought for and shown, there would be no occasion for my writing at all. Even in the scattered passages referring to this subject in three books of Carlyle's:—"Sartor Resartus"; "Past and Present"; and the "Latter-Day Pamphlets"; all has been said that needs to be said, and far better than I shall ever say it again. But the habit of the public mind at the present is to require everything to be uttered diffusely, loudly, and seven times over, before it will listen; and it has exclaimed against these papers of mine, as if they contained things daring and new, when there is not one assertion in them of which the truth has not been for ages known to the wisest, and proclaimed by the most eloquent of men. It will be a far greater pleasure to me hereafter, to collect their words than add to mine; Horace's clear rendering of the substance of the preceding passages in the text may be found room for at once:—

       Si quis emat citharas, emptas comportet in unum,
       Nec studio citharae, nec Musae deditus ulli;
       Si scalpra et formas, non sutor; nautica vela,
       Aversus mercaturis: delirus et amens
       Undique dicatur merito. Quî discrepat istis,
       Qui nummos aurumque recondit, nescius uti
       Compositis, metuensque velut contingere sacrum?

[71] I will hold off, until I finish and compile these papers, on any endorsements from other writers for the statements I've made in them; if such endorsements were sought and provided wisely, there would be no need for my writing at all. Even in the bits and pieces that reference this subject in three of Carlyle's books: "Sartor Resartus," "Past and Present," and the "Latter-Day Pamphlets," everything that needs to be said has already been said, and far better than I could ever express it again. However, the public mindset today demands that things be said in detail, loudly, and multiple times before it will listen; my papers have been met with criticism, as if they contained bold and novel ideas, when in fact, there isn't a single claim in them that hasn't been known to the wisest for ages and expressed by the most eloquent men. It will give me much greater joy in the future to gather their words rather than add to my own; Horace’s clear interpretation of the essence of the earlier passages can be placed here immediately:—

       Si quis emat citharas, emptas comportet in unum,
       Nec studio citharae, nec Musae deditus ulli;
       Si scalpra et formas, non sutor; nautica vela,
       Aversus mercaturis: delirus et amens
       Undique dicatur merito. Quî discrepat istis,
       Qui nummos aurumque recondit, nescius uti
       Compositis, metuensque velut contingere sacrum?

With which it is perhaps desirable also to give Xenophon's statement, it being clearer than any English one can be, owing to the power of the general Greek term for wealth, "useable things":—

With that in mind, it's probably useful to share Xenophon's statement since it’s clearer than any English version due to the strength of the general Greek word for wealth, "useable things":—

Ταῦτὰ ἄρα ὄντα, τῷ μὲν ἐπισταμένῳ χρῆσθαι αὐτῶν ἑκάστοις χρήματά ἐστι, τῷ δὲ μὴ ἐπισταμένῳ, οὐ χρήματα· ὥσπέρ γε αὐλοὶ τῷ μὲν ἐπισταμένῳ ἀξὶως λόγου αὐλεῖν χρήματά εἰσι, τῷ δἐ μὴ ἐπισταμένῳ οὐδὲν μᾶλλον ἤ ἄχρηστοι λίθοι, εἰ μὴ ἀπσδιδοῖτό γε αὐτούς. * * * Μὴ πωλούμενοι μὲν γὰρ οὐ χρήματά εἰσιν οἱ αὐλοί· (οὐδὲν γὰρ χρήσιμοί εἰσι) πωλούμενοι δὲ χρήματα· Πρὸς ταῦτα δ’ ὁ Σωκράτης εἶπεν, ἢν ἐπίστηταί γε πωλεῖν. Εί δὲ πωλοίη αὗ πρὸς τοὖτον ὃς μὴ ἐπίστηται χρῆσθαι, οὐδὲ πωλούμενοι εἰσὶ χρήματα.

So, for those who know how to use them, these things are valuable, but for those who don’t, they aren’t valuable at all. Just like the flutes: for someone who understands how to play them, they’re worth something; for someone who doesn’t understand it, they are just worthless stones, unless they can actually get something out of them. * * * Flutes that aren’t sold aren’t valuable (since they’re not useful at all), but when sold, they are valuable. To this, Socrates said, if one knows how to sell them. But if they are sold to someone who doesn’t know how to use them, they are not valuable at all.

[72] The orifice being not merely of a receptant, but of a suctional character. Among the types of human virtue and vice presented grotesquely by the lower animals, perhaps none is more curiously definite that that of avarice in the Cephalopod, a creature which has a purse for a body; a hawk's beak for a mouth; suckers for feet and hands; and whose house is its own skeleton.

[72] The opening is not just a receiving one but also has a sucking function. Among the kinds of human virtues and vices represented strangely by lower animals, perhaps none is more distinctly curious than avarice in the Cephalopod, a creature that has a body shaped like a purse, a beak like a hawk's for a mouth, suckers for feet and hands, and whose home is its own skeleton.

[73] It would be well if a somewhat dogged conviction could be enforced on nations as on individuals, that, with few exceptions, what they cannot at present pay for, they should not at present have.

[73] It would be beneficial if a strong belief could be applied to nations just like it is to individuals, that, with few exceptions, what they can't afford right now, they shouldn't have right now.

[74] The reader is to include here in the idea of "Government," any branch of the Executive, or even any body of private persons, entrusted with the practical management of public interests unconnected directly with their own personal ones. In theoretical discussions of legislative interference with political economy, it is usually and of course unnecessarily, assumed that Government must be always of that form and force in which we have been accustomed to see it;—that its abuses can never be less, nor its wisdom greater, nor its powers more numerous. But, practically, the custom in most civilized countries is, for every man to deprecate the interference of Government as long as things tell for his personal advantage, and to call for it when they cease to do so. The request of the Manchester Economists to be supplied with cotton by the Government (the system of supply and demand having, for the time, fallen sorrowfully short of the expectations of scientific persons from it), is an interesting case in point. It were to be wished that less wide and bitter suffering (suffering, too, of the innocent) had been needed to force the nation, or some part of it, to ask itself why a body of men, already confessedly capable of managing matters both military and divine, should not be permitted, or even requested at need to provide in some wise for sustenance as well as for defence, and secure, if it might be (and it might, I think, even the rather be), purity of bodily ailment, as well as of religious conviction? Why, having made many roads for the passage of armies, they may not make a few for the conveyance of food; and after organizing, with applause, various schemes of spiritual instruction for the Public, organize, moreover, some methods of bodily nourishment for them? Or is the soul so much less trustworthy in its instincts than the stomach, that legislation is necessary for the one, but inconvenient to the other?

[74] Readers should understand that "Government" includes any branch of the Executive or any group of private individuals tasked with managing public interests that aren't directly related to their own personal ones. In theoretical debates about legislative interference with political economy, it’s often unnecessarily assumed that Government must always take the same form and exert the same force that we’re used to seeing; that its abuses can never be fewer, nor its wisdom greater, nor its powers more extensive. But in reality, in most civilized countries, people tend to reject Government interference as long as things are going well for them personally and only call for it when their situation changes. The request from the Manchester Economists for the Government to supply them with cotton (since the system of supply and demand had fallen drastically short of expectations) is a relevant example. It would be preferable if less widespread and severe suffering (including that of the innocent) hadn’t compelled the nation—or at least parts of it—to consider why a group of people already acknowledged as capable of managing military and spiritual matters shouldn’t also be allowed to, or even asked to, help provide for basic needs as well as for defense, and ensure, if possible (and I believe it could be), both physical health and spiritual well-being? Why, after building many roads for the movement of armies, can’t they build a few for transporting food? And after successfully organizing various schemes for public spiritual education, why can't they also organize means of physical nourishment? Or is the soul so much less reliable in its instincts than the stomach that legislation is needed for one, but not the other?

There is a strange fallacy running at this time through all talk about free trade. It is continually assumed that every kind of Government interference takes away liberty of trade. Whereas liberty is lost only when interference hinders, not when it helps. You do not take away a man's freedom by showing him his road—nor by making it smoother for him (not that it is always desirable to do so, but it may be); nor even by fencing it for him, if there is an open ditch at the side of it. The real mode in which protection interferes with liberty, and the real evil of it, is not in its "protecting" one person, but in its hindering another; a form of interference which invariably does most mischief to the person it is intended to serve, which the Northern Americans are about discomfortably to discover, unless they think better of it. There is also a ludicrous confusion in many persons' minds between protection and encouragement; they differ materially. "Protection" is saying to the commercial schoolboy, "Nobody shall hit you." "Encouragement," is saying to him, "That's the way to hit."

There’s a weird misconception floating around in discussions about free trade right now. People keep assuming that any kind of government interference takes away trade freedom. But freedom is only lost when interference gets in the way, not when it actually helps. You don’t take away a person’s freedom by showing them the way—or by making that way easier for them (not that it’s always a good idea, but sometimes it might be); nor even by putting up a fence for them if there’s an open ditch next to it. The real way that protection limits freedom—and the true problem with it—is not in "protecting" one person, but in blocking another. This kind of interference usually causes the most harm to the very people it’s supposed to help, something that people in Northern America are about to uncomfortably realize unless they reconsider. There’s also a funny mix-up in many people’s minds between protection and encouragement; they are quite different. "Protection" tells the commercial schoolboy, "Nobody can hit you." "Encouragement" tells him, "This is how to hit."

[75] The question of equivalence (namely, how much wine a man is to receive in return for so much corn, or how much coal in return for so much iron) is a quite separate one, which we will examine presently. For the time let it be assumed that this equivalence has been determined, and that the Government order in exchange for a fixed weight of any article (called, suppose, a), is either for the return of that weight of the article itself, or of another fixed weight of the article b, or another of the article c, and so on.

[75] The question of equivalence (that is, how much wine a person should get in exchange for a certain amount of corn, or how much coal for a given amount of iron) is a separate issue that we will look into shortly. For now, let's assume that this equivalence has been established, and that the Government order in exchange for a specific weight of any item (let's say, a) is either for that same weight of the item itself, or for another fixed weight of item b, or another item c, and so on.

[76] The reader must be warned in advance that the conditions here supposed have nothing to do with the "interest" of money commonly so called.

[76] The reader should be advised from the start that the conditions discussed here have nothing to do with the so-called "interest" of money.

[77] The aphorism, being hurried English for "labour is limited by want of capital," involves also awkward English in its denial, which cannot be helped.

[77] The saying, hurriedly put in English as "work is constrained by lack of funding," also has clumsy phrasing in its refusal, which can't be avoided.

[78] These are nearly all briefly represented by the image used for the force of money by Dante, of mast and sail,—

       "Quali dal vento be gonfiate vele
       Caggiono avvolte, poi chè l'alber fiacca
       Tal cadde a terra la fiera crudele."

[78] These are almost all briefly shown by the image Dante used for the power of money, of mast and sail,—

       "Like sails that swell from the wind
       Fall tangled down when the mast weakens,
       So the fierce beast fell to the ground."

The image may be followed out, like all of Dante's, into as close detail as the reader chooses. Thus the stress of the sail must be proportioned to the strength of mast, and it is only in unforeseen danger that a skilful seaman ever carries all the canvas his spars will bear: states of mercantile languor are like the flap of the sail in a calm,—of mercantile precaution, like taking in reefs; and the mercantile ruin is instant on the breaking of the mast.

The image can be taken further, like all of Dante's work, into as much detail as the reader decides. So, the force of the sail has to match the strength of the mast, and it’s only in unexpected danger that a skilled sailor ever uses all the sail the masts can handle: times of business stagnation are like a sail flapping in a calm, while business caution is like reducing sail; and financial disaster happens immediately when the mast breaks.

[79] That is to say, its only price is its return. Compare "Unto This Last," p. 162 and what follows.

[79] In other words, its only cost is its return. See "Unto This Last," p. 162 and what comes after.

[80] The object of Political Economy is not to buy, nor to sell labour,—but to spare it. Every attempt to buy or sell it is, in the outcome, ineffectual;—so far as successful, it is not sale, but Betrayal; and the purchase money is a part of that typical thirty pieces which bought, first the greatest of labours, and afterwards the burial field of the Stranger; for this purchase-money, being in its very smallness or vileness the exactly measured opposite of "vilis annona amicorum," makes all men strangers to each other.

[80] The goal of Political Economy isn't to buy or sell labor—it's to conserve it. Any effort to buy or sell labor ultimately falls short; when it does succeed, it's not a fair trade but a betrayal. The money spent is part of that infamous thirty pieces which purchased, first, the greatest of labors, and later the burial ground of the Stranger. This price, in its exact smallness or worthlessness, stands in stark contrast to "vilis annona amicorum," making everyone feel like strangers to each other.

[81] Cicero's distinction, "sordidi quæstus, quorum operæ, non quorum artes emuntur," admirable in principle, is inaccurate in expression, because Cicero did not practically know how much operative dexterity is necessary in all the higher arts; but the cost of this dexterity is incalculable. Be it great or small, the "cost" of the mere authority and perfectness of touch in a hammerstroke of Donatello's, or a pencil touch of Correggio's, is inestimable by any ordinary arithmetic. (The best masters themselves usually estimate it at sums varying from two to three or four shillings a day, with wine or soup extra.)

[81] Cicero's point, "base earnings, for which you pay not for their skills," is impressive in principle but misses the mark in its wording. He didn't fully grasp how much skill is required in all the higher arts, and the value of this skill is beyond measure. Whether the cost is high or low, the "value" of the pure authority and perfect execution in a hammer strike by Donatello or a brush stroke by Correggio can't be calculated using ordinary math. (Even the best artists usually value it at amounts ranging from two to three or four shillings a day, with wine or soup being extra.)

[82] Only observe, as some labour is more destructive of life than other labour, the hour or day of the more destructive toil is supposed to include proportionate rest. Though men do not, or cannot, usually take such rest, except in death.

[82] Just notice that some types of work are more harmful to life than others, so the hours or days of the more damaging work are expected to allow for an appropriate amount of rest. However, people often don’t or can’t take that rest, except when they die.

[83] There is, therefore, observe, no such thing as cheapness (in the common use of that term), without some error or injustice. A thing is said to be cheap, not because it is common, but because it is supposed to be sold under its worth. Everything has its proper and true worth at any given time, in relation to everything else; and at that worth should be bought and sold. If sold under it, it is cheap to the buyer by exactly so much as the seller loses, and no more. Putrid meat, at twopence a pound, is not "cheaper" than wholesome meat at sevenpence a pound; it is probably much dearer; but if, by watching your opportunity, you can get the wholesome meat for sixpence a pound, it is cheaper to you by a penny, which you have gained, and the seller has lost. The present rage for cheapness is either, therefore, simply and literally, a rage for badness of all commodities, or it is an attempt to find persons whose necessities will force them to let you have more than you should for your money. It is quite easy to produce such persons, and in large numbers; for the more distress there is in a nation, the more cheapness of this sort you can obtain, and your boasted cheapness is thus merely a measure of the extent of your national distress.

[83] So, there’s no such thing as true cheapness (in the usual sense), without some kind of mistake or unfairness. We call something cheap not because it’s common, but because it seems to be sold for less than it’s actually worth. Everything has its own real and proper value at any moment, in relation to everything else; and that is the price it should be bought and sold at. If it’s sold for less, it’s cheap to the buyer exactly by the amount the seller loses, and no more. Spoiled meat at two pence a pound isn’t “cheaper” than fresh meat at seven pence a pound; it might actually be much more expensive. But if, by seizing the opportunity, you manage to get the fresh meat for six pence a pound, it’s cheaper to you by a penny, which you gain while the seller loses. The current obsession with cheapness is either simply a fixation on the poor quality of all goods, or it’s an effort to find people whose needs will force them to let you get more than you should for your money. It’s quite easy to produce such people, and in large numbers; because the more hardship there is in a country, the greater the availability of this kind of cheapness, and your touted cheapness is merely a reflection of the level of national distress.

There is, indeed, a condition of apparent cheapness, which we confuse, in practice and in reasoning, with the other; namely, the real reduction in cost of articles by right application of labour. But in this case the article is only cheap with reference to its former price, the so-called cheapness is only our expression for the sensation of contrast between its former and existing prices. So soon as the new methods of producing the article are established, it ceases to be esteemed either cheap or dear, at the new price, as at the old one, and is felt to be cheap only when accident enables it to be purchased beneath this new value. And it is to no advantage to produce the article more easily, except as it enables you to multiply your population. Cheapness of this kind is merely the discovery that more men can be maintained on the same ground; and the question, how many you will maintain in proportion to your means, remains exactly in the same terms that it did before.

There is, in fact, a state of seeming cheapness that we often mix up, both in practice and in thought, with another condition; specifically, the genuine reduction in the cost of goods through the proper application of labor. In this situation, the item is only considered cheap compared to its previous price; the so-called cheapness is just our way of expressing the feeling of contrast between its past and current prices. Once the new methods for producing the item are established, it no longer holds the same value as either cheap or expensive at the new price, just as it didn't at the old price. It’s only perceived as cheap when circumstance allows it to be bought for less than this new value. Moreover, there’s no real benefit to producing the item more easily, except that it allows for a larger population. This type of cheapness is simply the realization that more people can be supported on the same land; and the question of how many people you will support in relation to your resources remains exactly the same as it was before.

A form of immediate cheapness results, however, in many cases, without distress, from the labour of a population where food is redundant, or where the labour by which the food is produced leaves much idle time on their hands, which may be applied to the production of "cheap" articles.

A kind of instant affordability often happens, though without hardship, from the work of a population where food is plentiful, or where the effort to produce food leaves them with a lot of free time that can be used to make "cheap" products.

All such phenomena indicate to the political economist places where the labour is unbalanced. In the first case, the just balance is to be effected by taking labourers from the spot where the pressure exists, and sending them to that where food is redundant. In the second, the cheapness is a local accident, advantageous to the local purchaser, disadvantageous to the local producer. It is one of the first duties of commerce to extend the market and thus give the local producer his full advantage.

All these phenomena point to the political economist locations where labor is uneven. In the first case, the right balance is achieved by taking workers from where there’s a surplus of labor and moving them to places where food is plentiful. In the second, the low prices are a local issue, benefiting the local buyer and harming the local seller. One of commerce's primary responsibilities is to expand the market, thereby ensuring that local producers get their fair advantage.

Cheapness caused by natural accidents of harvest, weather, etc., is always counterbalanced, in due time, by natural scarcity similarly caused. It is the part of wise Government, and healthy commerce, so to provide in times and places of plenty for times and places of dearth, as that there shall never be waste, nor famine.

Cheapness caused by natural events like harvest fluctuations and weather changes is eventually balanced out by natural scarcity that happens for similar reasons. It is the responsibility of a wise government and a healthy market to prepare during times and places of abundance for times and places of shortage, ensuring that there is never waste or famine.

Cheapness caused by gluts of the market is merely a disease of clumsy and wanton commerce.

Cheapness caused by market oversupply is simply a problem of careless and reckless business practices.

[84] Price has already been defined (pp. 214, 215) to be the quantity of labour which the possessor of a thing is willing to take for it. It is best to consider the price to be that fixed by the possessor, because the possessor has absolute power of refusing sale, while the purchaser has no absolute power of compelling it; but the effectual or market price is that at which their estimates coincide.

[84] Price has already been defined (pp. 214, 215) as the amount of labor that the owner of an item is willing to accept for it. It's best to think of the price as what the owner sets, since the owner has the ultimate right to refuse to sell, while the buyer cannot force a sale; however, the actual market price is where their valuations align.

[85] The two first of these variables are included in the x, and the two last in they, of the formula given at p. 162 of "Unto This Last," and the four are the radical conditions which regulate the price of things on first production; in their price in exchange, the third and fourth of these divide each into two others, forming the Four which are stated at p. 186 of "Unto This Last."

[85] The first two variables are included in the x, and the last two are in the y of the formula on page 162 of "Unto This Last." These four are the fundamental conditions that determine the price of goods at initial production. In their exchange price, the third and fourth variables split into two additional variables each, forming the four that are listed on page 186 of "Unto This Last."

[86] This "greater ease" ought to be allowed for by a diminution in the times of the divided work; but as the proportion of times would remain the same, I do not introduce this unnecessary complexity into the calculation.

[86] This "greater ease" should be accounted for by reducing the time taken for the divided work; however, since the ratio of times would stay the same, I won't add this unnecessary complexity to the calculation.

[87] Compare "Unto This Last," p. 177, et seq.

[87] See "Unto This Last," p. 177, and following.


III.

THE CURRENCY-HOLDERS AND STORE-HOLDERS. THE DISEASE OF DESIRE.

It will be seen by reference to the last paper that our present task is to examine the relation of holders of store to holders of currency; and of both to those who hold neither. In order to do this, we must determine on which side we are to place substances such as gold, commonly known as bases of currency. By aid of previous definitions the reader will now be able to understand closer statements than have yet been possible.

It will be clear from the last paper that our current task is to look at the relationship between people who hold goods and those who hold money; and both groups in relation to those who hold neither. To do this, we need to decide where to categorize substances like gold, which are commonly known as currency backing. With the help of earlier definitions, the reader will now be able to grasp more detailed statements than have been possible before.

The currency of any country consists of every document acknowledging debt which is transferable in the country.

The currency of any country is made up of all documents that recognize debt and can be transferred within that country.

This transferableness depends upon its intelligibility and credit. Its intelligibility depends chiefly on the difficulty of forging anything like it;—its credit much on national character, but ultimately always on the existence of substantial means of meeting its demand.

This transferability relies on its clarity and trustworthiness. Its clarity mainly hinges on how hard it is to replicate; its trustworthiness largely depends on the national character, but ultimately, it always comes down to having the real resources to meet its demand.

As the degrees of transferableness are variable (some documents passing only in certain places, and others passing, if at all, for less than their inscribed value), both the mass and, so to speak, fluidity, of the currency, are variable. True or perfect currency flows freely, like a pure stream; it becomes sluggish or stagnant in proportion to the quantity of less transferable matter which mixes with it, adding to its bulk, but diminishing its purity. Substances of intrinsic value, such as gold, mingle also with the currency, and increase, while they modify, its power; these are carried by it as stones are carried by a torrent, sometimes momentarily impeding, sometimes concentrating its force, but not affecting its purity.[Pg 253] These substances of intrinsic value may be also stamped or signed so as to become acknowledgments of debt, and then become, so far as they operate independently of their intrinsic value, part of the real currency.

As the ease of transferring currency varies (some documents are only valid in certain locations while others, if valid at all, are worth less than their stated value), both the overall amount and the liquidity of the currency are variable. True or perfect currency flows freely, like a clear stream; it becomes sluggish or stagnant in proportion to the amount of less transferable assets that mix in, increasing its volume but reducing its purity. Items with intrinsic value, like gold, also blend with the currency and enhance, while changing, its power; these items are carried along like stones in a rushing river, sometimes temporarily slowing it down, sometimes concentrating its force, but not affecting its purity.[Pg 253] These items with intrinsic value can also be stamped or signed to serve as acknowledgments of debt, thus becoming, to the extent they operate independently of their intrinsic value, part of the actual currency.

Deferring consideration of minor forms of currency, consisting of documents bearing private signature, we will examine the principle of legally authorized or national currency.

Putting aside minor forms of currency, which include documents with private signatures, we will look at the principle of legally recognized or national currency.

This, in its perfect condition, is a form of public acknowledgment of debt, so regulated and divided that any person presenting a commodity of tried worth in the public market, shall, if he please, receive in exchange for it a document giving him claim for the return of its equivalent, (1) in any place, (2) at any time, and (3) in any kind.

This, in its perfect state, is a way to publicly recognize a debt, organized and divided so that anyone presenting a valuable commodity in the public market can, if they wish, receive a document in exchange that entitles them to get back its equivalent, (1) at any location, (2) at any time, and (3) in any form.

When currency is quite healthy and vital, the persons entrusted with its management are always able to give on demand either—

When currency is strong and vital, the people in charge of managing it can always provide on demand either—

A. The assigning document for the assigned quantity of goods. Or,

A. The document that specifies the assigned quantity of goods. Or,

B. The assigned quantity of goods for the assigning document.

B. The specified amount of goods for the assignment document.

If they cannot give document for goods, the national exchange is at fault.

If they can't provide documents for the goods, the national exchange is at fault.

If they cannot give goods for document, the national credit is at fault.

If they can't provide goods for the document, the national credit is to blame.

The nature and power of the document are therefore to be examined under the three relations which it bears to Place, Time, and Kind.

The nature and power of the document should be examined in relation to Place, Time, and Kind.

1. It gives claim to the return of equivalent wealth in any Place. Its use in this function is to save carriage, so that parting with a bushel of corn in London, we may receive an order for a bushel of corn for the Antipodes, or elsewhere. To be perfect in this use, the substance of currency must be to the maximum portable, credible, and intelligible. Its non-acceptance or discredit results always from some form of ignorance or dishonour: so far as such interruptions rise out of differences in denomination, there is no ground[Pg 254] for their continuance among civilized nations. It may be convenient in one country to use chiefly copper for coinage, in another silver, and in another gold,—reckoning accordingly in centimes, francs, or sequins; but that a French franc should be different in weight from an English shilling, and an Austrian zwanziger vary in weight and alloy from both, is wanton loss of commercial power.

1. It allows for the return of equal value in any location. This function helps save on transportation costs, so when we trade a bushel of corn in London, we can get an order for a bushel of corn for the other side of the world, or anywhere else. For this purpose to work perfectly, the currency must be as portable, trustworthy, and understandable as possible. Its rejection or lack of trust usually comes from some kind of ignorance or dishonor: when these issues arise from differences in currency types, there’s no reason for them to persist among civilized nations. It might be practical for one country to primarily use copper coins, another to use silver, and another to use gold—counting in centimes, francs, or sequins accordingly; but the fact that a French franc is different in weight from an English shilling, and an Austrian zwanziger varies in weight and composition from both, is a waste of commercial potential.

2. It gives claim to the return of equivalent wealth at any Time. In this second use, currency is the exponent of accumulation: it renders the laying up of store at the command of individuals unlimitedly possible;—whereas, but for its intervention, all gathering would be confined within certain limits by the bulk of poverty, or by its decay, or the difficulty of its guardianship. "I will pull down my barns and build greater" cannot be a daily saying; and all material investment is enlargement of care. The national currency transfers the guardianship of the store to many; and preserves to the original producer the right of re-entering on its possession at any future period.

2. It allows for the return of equivalent wealth at any time. In this second use, currency represents accumulation: it makes it possible for individuals to store wealth without limits; without it, all accumulation would be restricted by poverty, decay, or the challenges of keeping it safe. "I will pull down my barns and build greater" can't be a daily mantra; plus, any physical investment requires more responsibility. The national currency shifts the responsibility of protecting the wealth to many people and keeps the original producer's right to reclaim it at any future time.

3. It gives claim (practical, though not legal) to the return of equivalent wealth in any Kind. It is a transferable right, not merely to this or that, but to anything; and its power in this function is proportioned to the range of choice. If you give a child an apple or a toy, you give him a determinate pleasure, but if you give him a penny, an indeterminate one, proportioned to the range of selection offered by the shops in the village. The power of the world's currency is similarly in proportion to the openness of the world's fair, and commonly enhanced by the brilliancy of external aspect, rather than solidity of its wares.

3. It claims a return of equivalent wealth in any form (practical, though not legal). It’s a transferable right, not just for this or that, but for anything; and its effectiveness in this role depends on the range of choices available. If you give a child an apple or a toy, you provide them with a specific pleasure, but if you give them a penny, it offers them an undefined pleasure, based on the variety of options available at the shops in the village. The power of the world’s currency works similarly, correlating to how open the world’s market is, and is often boosted by its external appearance, rather than the actual quality of its goods.

We have said that the currency consists of orders for equivalent goods. If equivalent, their quality must be guaranteed. The kinds of goods chosen for specific claim must, therefore, be capable of test, while, also, that a store may be kept in hand to meet the call of the currency, smallness of bulk, with great relative value, is desirable; and indestructibility, over at least a certain period, essential.

We’ve stated that currency is made up of claims for equivalent goods. If they are equivalent, their quality needs to be assured. The types of goods selected for specific claims must be testable, and it’s important that they can be easily stored to meet the demand for currency. Ideally, these goods should be small in size but have a high relative value, and they must be durable for at least a certain period.

Such indestructibility and facility of being tested are[Pg 255] united in gold; its intrinsic value is great, and its imaginary value is greater; so that, partly through indolence, partly through necessity and want of organization, most nations have agreed to take gold for the only basis of their currencies;—with this grave disadvantage, that its portability enabling the metal to become an active part of the medium of exchange, the stream of the currency itself becomes opaque with gold—half currency and half commodity, in unison of functions which partly neutralize, partly enhance each other's force.

Gold is both incredibly durable and easy to test. Its intrinsic value is significant, and its perceived value is even higher. As a result, many nations, due to laziness, necessity, and lack of organization, have decided to use gold as the sole foundation for their currencies. However, this comes with a serious drawback: because gold is easy to transport, it actively becomes a part of the exchange medium, turning the currency itself into a mix of gold—part currency and part commodity—where their functions both cancel and amplify each other's effects.

They partly neutralize, since in so far as the gold is commodity, it is bad currency, because liable to sale; and in so far as it is currency, it is bad commodity, because its exchange value interferes with its practical use. Especially its employment in the higher branches of the arts becomes unsafe on account of its liability to be melted down for exchange.

They partially cancel each other out because, as a commodity, gold is poor currency due to its ability to be sold, and as currency, it is a poor commodity because its exchange value disrupts its practical use. Its use in advanced arts, in particular, becomes risky because it can be melted down for cash.

Again. They partly enhance, since in so far as the gold has acknowledged intrinsic value, it is good currency, because everywhere acceptable; and in so far as it has legal exchangeable value, its worth as a commodity is increased. We want no gold in the form of dust or crystal; but we seek for it coined because in that form it will pay baker and butcher. And this worth in exchange not only absorbs a large quantity in that use,[88] but greatly increases the effect on the imagination of the quantity used in the arts. Thus, in brief, the force of the functions is increased, but their precision blunted, by their unison.

Again. They partially enhance, since as far as gold has inherent value, it serves as good currency because it's widely accepted; and since it has legal exchange value, its worth as a commodity rises. We don't want gold in the form of dust or crystal; we want it in coins because that form can pay the baker and butcher. This worth in exchange not only absorbs a large quantity in that use,[88] but also greatly amplifies the impact on the imagination of the amount used in the arts. So, in summary, the effectiveness of the functions increases, but their accuracy is dulled by their harmony.

These inconveniences, however, attach to gold as a basis [Pg 256] of currency on account of its portability and preciousness. But a far greater inconvenience attaches to it as the only legal basis of currency. Imagine gold to be only attainable in masses weighing several pounds each, and its value, like that of a malachite or marble, proportioned to its largeness of bulk;—it could not then get itself confused with the currency in daily use, but it might still remain as its basis; and this second inconvenience would still affect it, namely, that its significance as an expression of debt, varies, as that of every other article would, with the popular estimate of its desirableness, and with the quantity offered in the market. My power of obtaining other goods for gold depends always on the strength of public passion for gold, and on the limitation of its quantity, so that when either of two things happen—that the world esteems gold less, or finds it more easily,—my right of claim is in that degree effaced; and it has been even gravely maintained that a discovery of a mountain of gold would cancel the National Debt; in other words, that men may be paid for what costs much in what costs nothing. Now, if it is true that there is little chance of sudden convulsion in this respect, the world will not rapidly increase in wisdom so as to despise gold, and perhaps may even desire it more eagerly the more easily it is obtained; nevertheless the right of debt ought not to rest on a basis of imagination; nor should the frame of a national currency vibrate with every miser's panic and every merchant's imprudence.

These issues, however, are tied to gold as a basis for currency because of its ease of transport and value. But an even bigger problem arises when it is the only legal basis for currency. Imagine if gold could only be obtained in large masses weighing several pounds each, and its value, like that of malachite or marble, depended on its size;—it wouldn't get confused with the currency we use daily, but it could still serve as the basis for it. This brings up a second issue: its significance as a representation of debt fluctuates, just like any other item, based on how desirable it is viewed by the public and the amount available in the market. My ability to acquire other goods for gold always depends on how much people want gold and how limited its supply is. So, if the world starts to value gold less or finds it more readily available, my claim to it is diminished. It has even been seriously argued that discovering a mountain of gold would wipe out the National Debt; in other words, people could be compensated for something valuable with something that costs very little. While it’s unlikely there will be a sudden shift in this regard, the world probably won’t quickly become wise enough to overlook gold, and may even desire it more when it’s easier to find. Nevertheless, the right to debt shouldn't rely on something imaginary; nor should the structure of a national currency be swayed by every miser's fear and every merchant's recklessness.

There are two methods of avoiding this insecurity, which would have been fallen upon long ago if, instead of calculating the conditions of the supply of gold, men had only considered how the world might live and manage its affairs without gold at all.[89] One is to base the currency on substances of [Pg 257] truer intrinsic value; the other, to base it on several substances instead of one. If I can only claim gold, the discovery of a continent of cornfields need not trouble me. If, however, I wish to exchange my bread for other things, a good harvest will for the time limit my power in this respect; but if I can claim either bread, iron, or silk at pleasure, the standard of value has three feet instead of one, and will be proportionally firm. Thus, ultimately the steadiness of currency depends upon the breadth of its base; but the difficulty of organization increasing with this breadth, the discovery of the condition at once safest and most convenient[90] can only be by long analysis which must for the present be deferred. Gold or silver[91] may always be retained in limited use, as a luxury of coinage and questionless standard, of one weight and alloy among nations, varying only in the die. The purity of coinage when metallic, is closely indicative of the honesty of the system of revenue, and even of the general dignity of the State.[92]

There are two ways to avoid this insecurity, which could have been figured out long ago if people had focused on how the world could live and function without gold entirely. [89] One way is to base currency on materials that have real intrinsic value; the other is to use multiple materials instead of just one. If I can only claim gold, then the discovery of a continent full of cornfields won’t concern me. However, if I want to trade my bread for other things, a good harvest will limit my options for a while; but if I can claim bread, iron, or silk whenever I want, the standard of value has three points of reference instead of one, and will be much more stable. Ultimately, the stability of currency relies on the variety of its foundation; however, as the complexity of organization increases with this variety, finding the safest and most convenient solution can only come from long analysis, which must be postponed for now. Gold or silver [91] can always be kept in limited use, serving as a luxury of coinage and a universally accepted standard, with consistent weight and alloy across nations, differing only in the mint. The purity of coinage when metallic closely reflects the integrity of the revenue system, and even the overall dignity of the State. [92]

Whatever the article or articles may be which the national currency promises to pay, a premium on that article indicates bankruptcy of the Government in that proportion, the division of the assets being restrained only by the remaining confidence of the holders of notes in the return of prosperity to the firm. Incontrovertible currencies, those of forced acceptance, or of unlimited issue, are merely various modes of disguising taxation, and delaying its pressure, until it is too late to interfere with its causes. To do away with the possibility of such disguise would have been among the [Pg 258] first results of a true economical science, had any such existed; but there have been too many motives for the concealment, so long as it could by any artifices be maintained, to permit hitherto even the founding of such a science.

Whatever articles the national currency promises to pay, a premium on those articles signals the government's bankruptcy to that extent, with the distribution of assets limited only by the remaining trust of note holders in a return to prosperity. Non-debatable currencies, those that must be accepted or can be issued endlessly, are just different ways to hide taxation and delay its impact until it's too late to address its causes. Eliminating the chance for such deception would have been one of the first results of a true economic science if it had ever existed; however, there have been too many reasons to keep it hidden, as long as it could be maintained through various tricks, preventing even the establishment of such a science thus far.

And, indeed, it is only through evil conduct, wilfully persisted in, that there is any embarrassment either in the theory or the working of currency. No exchequer is ever embarrassed, nor is any financial question difficult of solution, when people keep their practice honest, and their heads cool. But when Governments lose all office of pilotage, protection, scrutiny, and witness; and live only in magnificence of proclaimed larceny, effulgent mendacity, and polished mendicity; or when the people choosing Speculation (the S usual redundant in the spelling) instead of Toil, pursue no dishonesty with chastisement, that each may with impunity take his dishonest turn; and enlarge their lust of wealth through ignorance of its use, making their harlot of the dust, and setting Earth, the Mother, at the mercy of Earth, the Destroyer, so that she has to seek in hell the children she left playing in the meadows,—there are no tricks of financial terminology that will save them; all signature and mintage do but magnify the ruin they retard; and even the riches that remain, stagnant or current, change only from the slime of Avernus to the sand of Phlegethon;—quicksand at the embouchure;—land fluently recommended by recent auctioneers as "eligible for building leases."

And, really, it’s only through bad behavior, deliberately continued, that there’s any trouble in the theory or functioning of currency. No treasury is ever troubled, and no financial issue is hard to solve when people keep their actions honest and their minds calm. But when governments lose all ability to guide, protect, scrutinize, and observe; and they exist only in the grandeur of open theft, dazzling lies, and sleek poverty; or when people choose speculation (the S often redundant in the spelling) over hard work, and there’s no punishment for dishonesty so everyone can take their dishonest turn without consequence; and they grow their greed for wealth through ignorance of how to use it, making a slave of material things, and putting Earth, the Mother, at the mercy of Earth, the Destroyer, so that she has to search in hell for the children she left playing in the meadows,—there are no tricks of financial jargon that will save them; every signature and coinage only amplifies the ruin they delay; and even the wealth that remains, whether stagnant or flowing, merely shifts from the filth of Avernus to the sand of Phlegethon;—quicksand at the mouth;—land enthusiastically promoted by recent auctioneers as "suitable for building leases."

Finally, then, the power of true currency is fourfold.

Finally, the true power of currency is fourfold.

1. Credit power. Its worth in exchange, dependent on public opinion of the stability and honesty of the issuer.

1. Credit power. Its value in trade relies on the public's perception of the issuer's stability and integrity.

2. Real worth. Supposing the gold, or whatever else the currency expressly promises, to be required from the issuer, for all his notes; and that the call cannot be met in full. Then the actual worth of the document (whatever its credit power) would be, and its actual worth at any moment is to be defined as being, what the division of the assets of the issuer, and his subsequent will work, would produce for it.

2. Real worth. Let's say the gold or whatever else the currency explicitly promises needs to be provided by the issuer for all his notes; and that he cannot meet the demand in full. Then the true value of the document (regardless of its credit power) would be based on what could be generated from the issuer's asset division and any future actions he might take.

3. The exchange power of its base. Granting that we can get five pounds in gold for our note, it remains a question how much of other things we can get for five pounds in gold.[Pg 259] The more of other things exist, and the less gold, the greater this power.

3. The exchange power of its base. Assuming we can get five pounds in gold for our note, the real question is how much of other things we can buy for five pounds in gold.[Pg 259] The more of other things there are and the less gold there is, the greater this power becomes.

4. The power over labour, exercised by the given quantity of the base, or of the things to be got for it. The question in this case is, how much work, and (question of questions) whose work, is to be had for the food which five pounds will buy. This depends on the number of the population; on their gifts, and on their dispositions, with which, down to their slightest humours and up to their strongest impulses, the power of the currency varies; and in this last of its ranges,—the range of passion, price, or praise (converso in pretium Deo), is at once least, and greatest.

4. The control over labor, determined by the amount of resources available, or the things that can be obtained with it. The main question here is how much work, and (the most important question) whose work, can be had for the food that five pounds can buy. This depends on the size of the population, their talents, and their attitudes, which can influence everything from their minor quirks to their strongest motivations, and this is where the power of money fluctuates; within this last spectrum—defined by passion, price, or praise (converso in pretium Deo)—it is simultaneously the least and the most significant.

Such being the main conditions of national currency, we proceed to examine those of the total currency, under the broad definition, "transferable acknowledgment of debt";[93] among the many forms of which there are in effect only two, distinctly opposed; namely, the acknowledgments of debts [Pg 260] which will be paid, and of debts which will not. Documents, whether in whole or part, of bad debt, being to those of good debt as bad money to bullion, we put for the present these forms of imposture aside (as in analysing a metal we should wash it clear of dross), and then range, in their exact quantities, the true currency of the country on one side, and the store or property of the country on the other. We place gold, and all such substances, on the side of documents, as far as they operate by signature;—on the side of store as far as they operate by value. Then the currency represents the quantity of debt in the country, and the store the quantity of its possession. The ownership of all the property is divided between the holders of currency and holders of store, and whatever the claiming value of the currency is at any moment, that value is to be deducted from the riches of the store-holders, the deduction being practically made in the payment of rent for houses and lands, of interest on stock, and in other ways to be hereafter examined.

Given the main conditions of national currency, we now look at those of total currency, defined broadly as a "transferable acknowledgment of debt";[93] of which there are really only two distinct forms: acknowledgments of debts that will be paid and those that won’t. Documents representing bad debt are to good debt what counterfeit money is to real bullion, so for now, we set aside these forms of deception (just as we would remove impurities when analyzing a metal), and instead, we categorize the true currency of the country on one side and the property or store of the country on the other. We place gold and similar substances on the side of documents when they function through signature, and on the side of store when they hold value. Therefore, currency reflects the total amount of debt in the country, while the store reflects the total amount of possessions. The ownership of all property is shared between currency holders and store holders, and whatever the current claiming value of the currency is, that value must be deducted from the wealth of the store-holders; this deduction occurs in the form of rent payments for houses and land, interest on stocks, and other methods to be discussed later.

At present I wish only to note the broad relations of the two great classes—the currency-holders and store-holders.[94] Of course they are partly united, most monied men having [Pg 261] possessions of land or other goods; but they are separate in their nature and functions. The currency-holders as a class regulate the demand for labour, and the store-holders the laws of it; the currency-holders determine what shall be produced, and the store-holders the conditions of its production. Farther, as true currency represents by definition debts which will be paid, it represents either the debtor's wealth, or his ability and willingness; that is to say, either wealth existing in his hands transferred to him by the creditor, or wealth which, as he is at some time surely to return it, he is either increasing, or, if diminishing, has the will and strength to reproduce. A sound currency, therefore, as by its increase it represents enlarging debt, represents also enlarging means; but in this curious way, that a certain quantity of it marks the deficiency of the wealth of the country from what it would have been if that currency had not existed.[95] In this respect it is like the detritus of a mountain; assume that it lies at a fixed angle, and the more the detritus, the larger must be the mountain; but it would have been larger still, had there been none.

Right now, I just want to point out the general relationship between the two major groups—the currency-holders and the store-holders.[94] They are connected to some extent, as most wealthy individuals own land or other assets; however, they are distinct in their nature and roles. Currency-holders, as a group, control the demand for labor, while store-holders set the rules for it. Currency-holders decide what gets produced, and store-holders establish the conditions for that production. Moreover, true currency represents, by definition, debts that will be settled, reflecting either the debtor's wealth or their capability and willingness to pay; in other words, it embodies wealth that has been transferred to them by the creditor or wealth that they will eventually return and are either increasing or, if decreasing, have the intention and ability to regenerate. A solid currency, then, as it grows, signifies expanding debt, which also indicates increasing resources; but intriguingly, a certain amount of it illustrates how the country's wealth falls short of what it could have been without that currency.[95] In this sense, it's similar to the debris of a mountain; if we assume it remains at a fixed angle, the more debris there is, the larger the mountain must be; yet it would have been even larger if that debris didn't exist.

Finally, though, as above stated, every man possessing money has usually also some property beyond what is necessary for his immediate wants, and men possessing property usually also hold currency beyond what is necessary for their immediate exchanges, it mainly determines the class to which they belong, whether in their eyes the money is an adjunct of [Pg 262] the property, or the property of the money. In the first case, the holder's pleasure is in his possessions, and in his money subordinately, as the means of bettering or adding to them. In the second, his pleasure is in his money, and in his possessions only as representing it. In the first case, the money is as an atmosphere surrounding the wealth, rising from it and raining back upon it; but in the second, it is a deluge, with the wealth floating, and for the most part perishing in it. The shortest distinction between the men is that the one wishes always to buy and the other to sell.

Finally, as mentioned earlier, every man with money typically also owns some property beyond what he needs for his immediate wants, and those with property generally have extra cash beyond what's necessary for their daily transactions. This mainly decides the class to which they belong, based on whether they see money as an extension of their property or property as a result of their money. In the first scenario, the holder finds joy in his possessions, with money as a secondary tool to enhance or add to them. In the second, he takes pleasure in his money, viewing his possessions merely as representations of it. In the first case, money acts like an atmosphere surrounding wealth, rising from it and falling back onto it; in the second, it becomes a flood, with wealth floating and mostly being lost within it. The simplest distinction between these two types of men is that one always wants to buy, while the other wants to sell.

Such being the great relations of the classes, their several characters are of the highest importance to the nation; for on the character of the store-holders depends the preservation, display, and serviceableness of its wealth;—on that of the currency-holders its nature, and in great part its distribution; and on both its production.

Given the significant connections between the classes, their individual qualities are crucial to the nation; because the character of the store-holders affects the maintenance, visibility, and usefulness of its wealth; — while that of the currency-holders influences its nature and largely its distribution; and both impact its production.

The store-holders are either constructive, or neutral, or destructive; and in subsequent papers we shall, with respect to every kind of wealth, examine the relative power of the store-holder for its improvement or destruction; and we shall then find it to be of incomparably greater importance to the nation in whose hands the thing is put, than how much of it is got; and that the character of the holders may be conjectured by the quality of the store, for such and such a thing; nor only asks for it, but if to be bettered, betters it: so that possession and possessor reciprocally act on each other through the entire sum of national possession. The base nation asking for base things sinks daily to deeper vileness of nature and of use; while the noble nation, asking for noble things, rises daily into diviner eminence in both; the tendency to degradation being surely marked by ἀταξὶα, carelessness as to the hands in which things are put, competition for the acquisition of them, disorderliness in accumulation, inaccuracy in reckoning, and bluntness in conception as to the entire nature of possession.

The store owners can be constructive, neutral, or destructive. In future papers, we will analyze the influence of each type of store owner on different kinds of wealth, considering whether they improve or diminish it. We will discover that the identity of the store owner is far more crucial for the nation than the amount of wealth they possess. You can gauge the character of the owners by the quality of the goods. A good store owner not only seeks valuable items but also improves them when possible. Thus, ownership and the owner influence each other throughout the total wealth of the nation. A corrupt nation that seeks worthless things sinks deeper into moral decay, while a noble nation that seeks valuable items ascends to greater heights in virtue. The signs of degradation are clearly evident in carelessness about who holds the wealth, reckless competition to gain it, disorganized accumulation, inaccuracies in bookkeeping, and a lack of understanding of what true possession means.

Now, the currency-holders always increase in number and influence in proportion to the bluntness of nature and clumsiness of the store-holders; for the less use people can make of things the more they tire of them, and want to change[Pg 263] them for something else, and all frequency of change increases the quantity and power of currency; while the large currency-holder himself is essentially a person who never has been able to make up his mind as to what he will have, and proceeds, therefore, in vague collection and aggregation, with more and more infuriate passion, urged by complacency in progress, and pride in conquest.

Now, the number and influence of currency holders keep growing as nature becomes less practical and storeholders become more clumsy. The less people can make use of things, the more they get tired of them, wanting to swap them for something else. This constant desire for change boosts the amount and power of currency. At the same time, the big currency holder is really just someone who has never figured out what they want, so they keep collecting and accumulating things haphazardly, driven by a mix of satisfaction in their progress and pride in their acquisitions.[Pg 263]

While, however, there is this obscurity in the nature of possession of currency, there is a charm in the absoluteness of it, which is to some people very enticing. In the enjoyment of real property others must partly share. The groom has some enjoyment of the stud, and the gardener of the garden; but the money is, or seems shut up; it is wholly enviable. No one else can have part in any complacencies arising from it.

While there is some uncertainty about the nature of possessing money, its absolute nature can be very appealing to certain people. When it comes to real estate, others have to share in the enjoyment. The groom gets some enjoyment from the horses, and the gardener enjoys the garden; but money feels completely exclusive; it's entirely desirable. No one else can share in the pleasures that come from it.

The power of arithmetical comparison is also a great thing to unimaginative people. They know always they are so much better than they were, in money; so much better than others, in money; wit cannot be so compared, nor character. My neighbour cannot be convinced I am wiser than he is, but he can that I am worth so much more; and the universality of the conviction is no less flattering than its clearness. Only a few can understand, none measure, superiorities in other things; but everybody can understand money, and count it.

The power of comparing numbers is significant for people who lack imagination. They can always see that they're doing better financially than they used to be, and better than others as well; you can't measure wit or character in the same way. My neighbor might not believe I'm wiser than he is, but he definitely recognizes that I'm worth more money; and the fact that so many people share this belief is both flattering and clear. Only a few can grasp or measure superiority in other areas, but everyone understands money and knows how to count it.

Now, these various temptations to accumulation would be politically harmless, if what was vainly accumulated had any fair chance of being wisely spent. For as accumulation cannot go on for ever, but must some day end in its reverse—if this reverse were indeed a beneficial distribution and use, as irrigation from reservoir, the fever of gathering, though perilous to the gatherer, might be serviceable to the community. But it constantly happens (so constantly, that it may be stated as a political law having few exceptions), that what is unreasonably gathered is also unreasonably spent by the persons into whose hands it finally falls. Very frequently it is spent in war, or else in stupefying luxury, twice hurtful, both in being indulged by the rich and witnessed by the poor. So that the mal tener and mal dare are as correlative as complementary colours; and the circulation of wealth, which ought to be[Pg 264] soft, steady, strong, far-sweeping, and full of warmth, like the Gulf Stream, being narrowed into an eddy, and concentrated on a point, changes into the alternate suction and surrender of Charybdis. Which is, indeed, I doubt not, the true meaning of that marvellous fable, "infinite," as Bacon said of it, "in matter of meditation."[96]

Now, these various temptations to accumulate would be politically harmless if what was collected had any real chance of being wisely used. Since accumulation can't go on forever and must eventually lead to its opposite—if this reverse were actually a beneficial distribution and use, like irrigation from a reservoir, then the urge to gather, though risky for the gatherer, could benefit the community. But it often happens (so often that it can be stated as a political law with few exceptions) that what is gathered without reason is also spent without reason by those who finally receive it. Frequently, it's spent on war or excessive luxury, which harms both the rich indulging in it and the poor witnessing it. Thus, the mal tener and mal dare are as related as complementary colors; and the flow of wealth, which should be[Pg 264] smooth, steady, strong, far-reaching, and warm like the Gulf Stream, becomes narrowed into an eddy, focused on a single point, transforming into the alternating suction and release of Charybdis. This, indeed, I believe, captures the true meaning of that marvelously deep fable, "infinite," as Bacon described it, "in matter of meditation."

[Pg 265]This disease of desire having especial relation to the great art of Exchange, or Commerce, we must, in order to complete our code of first principles, shortly state the nature and limits of that art.

[Pg 265]This disease of desire, closely linked to the important practice of Trade or Commerce, requires us to briefly outline the nature and boundaries of that practice to finish our set of fundamental principles.

As the currency conveys right of choice out of many things in exchange for one, so Commerce is the agency by which the power of choice is obtained; and countries producing [Pg 266] only timber can obtain for their timber silk and gold; or, naturally producing only jewels and frankincense, can obtain for them cattle and corn. In this function commerce is of more importance to a country in proportion to the limitations of its products and the restlessness of its fancy;—generally of greater importance towards Northern latitudes.

As money represents the ability to choose from many options in exchange for something, commerce is the way that choice is achieved. Countries that only produce [Pg 266] timber can trade their timber for silk and gold, or those that naturally produce only jewels and frankincense can exchange them for cattle and corn. In this role, commerce matters more to a country when its products are limited and its desires are restless—typically, it's more significant in northern regions.

[Pg 267]Commerce is necessary, however, not only to exchange local products, but local skill. Labour requiring the agency of fire can only be given abundantly in cold countries; labour requiring suppleness of body and sensitiveness of touch only in warm ones; labour involving accurate vivacity of thought only in temperate ones; while peculiar imaginative actions are produced by extremes of heat and cold, and of light and darkness. The production of great art is limited to climates [Pg 268] warm enough to admit of repose in the open air, and cool enough to render such repose delightful. Minor variations in modes of skill distinguish every locality. The labour which at any place is easiest, is in that place cheapest; and it becomes often desirable that products raised in one country should be wrought in another. Hence have arisen discussions [Pg 269] on "International values," which will be one day remembered as highly curious exercises of the human mind. For it will be discovered, in due course of tide and time, that international value is regulated just as inter-provincial or inter-parishional value is. Coals and hops are exchanged between Northumberland and Kent on absolutely the same principles as iron and wine between Lancashire and Spain. The greater breadth of an arm of the sea increases the cost, but does not modify the principle of exchange; and a bargain written in two languages will have no other economical results than a bargain written in one. The distances of nations are measured not by seas, but by ignorances; and their divisions determined, not by dialects, but by enmities.

[Pg 267]Commerce is essential, not just for trading local products but also for exchanging local skills. Work that requires the use of fire is best done in cold regions; work that needs flexibility and sensitivity is suited to warmer areas; work that demands sharp thinking is ideal in temperate climates; while unique creative activities arise from extreme temperatures and varying light levels. The creation of great art is confined to climates that are warm enough to relax outdoors and cool enough to make that relaxation enjoyable. Small differences in skills set each area apart. The labor that is easiest in a location is also the cheapest there, often leading to a situation where products made in one country are processed in another. This has sparked debates about "International values," discussions that will eventually be seen as interesting exercises in human thought. In time, it will become clear that international value is determined just like the value found within regions or communities. Coal and hops are traded between Northumberland and Kent based on the same principles as iron and wine traded between Lancashire and Spain. A wider sea may increase costs, but it does not change how exchanges are made; and a contract written in two languages will have the same economic results as one written in just one. The distances between nations are measured not by the seas that separate them but by their ignorance of each other; and their divisions are defined not by languages but by conflicts. [Pg 268] [Pg 269]

Of course, a system of international values may always be constructed if we assume a relation of moral law to physical geography; as, for instance, that it is right to cheat across a river, though not across a road; or across a lake, though not across a river; or over a mountain, though not across a lake, etc.:—again, a system of such values may be constructed by assuming similar relations of taxation to physical geography; as, for instance, that an article should be taxed in crossing a river, but not in crossing a road; or in being carried over a mountain, but not over a ferry, etc.: such positions are indeed not easily maintained when once put in logical form; but one law of international value is maintainable in any form; namely, that the farther your neighbour lives from you, and the less he understands you, the more you are bound to be true in your dealings with him; because your [Pg 270] power over him is greater in proportion to his ignorance, and his remedy more difficult in proportion to his distance.

Of course, an international value system can always be set up if we link moral law to physical geography; for example, it might be seen as acceptable to cheat across a river but not across a road, or across a lake but not across a river, or over a mountain but not across a lake, etc. Similarly, a system of values could be designed by looking at how taxation relates to physical geography; for instance, you might impose a tax on an item crossing a river, but not when it crosses a road, or when it’s carried over a mountain, but not over a ferry, etc. These positions are indeed not easy to support once they are put into logical form; however, one law of international value holds true regardless of the situation: the farther away your neighbor is and the less he understands you, the more you should strive to be honest in your dealings with him; because your influence over him increases with his ignorance, and his recourse becomes harder the farther away he is.

I have just said the breadth of sea increases the cost of exchange. Exchange or commerce, as such, is always costly; the sum of the value of the goods being diminished by the cost of their conveyance, and by the maintenance of the persons employed in it. So that it is only when there is advantage to both producers (in getting the one thing for the other), greater than the loss in conveyance, that the exchange is expedient. And it is only justly conducted when the porters kept by the producers (commonly called merchants) look only for pay, and not for profit. For in just commerce there are but three parties—the two persons or societies exchanging and the agent or agents of exchange: the value of the things to be exchanged is known by both the exchangers, and each receives equivalent value, neither gaining nor losing (for whatever one gains the other loses). The intermediate agent is paid an equal and known percentage by both, partly for labour in conveyance, partly for care, knowledge, and risk; every attempt at concealment of the amount of the pay indicates either effort on the part of the agent to obtain exorbitant percentage, or effort on the part of the exchangers to refuse him a just one. But for the most part it is the first, namely, the effort on the part of the merchant to obtain larger profit (so called) by buying cheap and selling dear. Some part, indeed, of this larger gain is deserved, and might be openly demanded, because it is the reward of the merchant's knowledge, and foresight of probable necessity; but the greater part of such gain is unjust; and unjust in this most fatal way, that it depends first on keeping the exchangers ignorant of the exchange value of the articles, and secondly, on taking advantage of the buyer's need and the seller's poverty. It is, therefore, one of the essential, and quite the most fatal, forms of usury; for usury means merely taking an exorbitant sum for the use of anything, and it is no matter whether the exorbitance is on loan or exchange, in rent or in price—the essence of the usury being that it is obtained by advantage of opportunity or necessity, and not as due reward for labour. All the great thinkers, therefore, have[Pg 271] held it to be unnatural and impious, in so far as it feeds on the distress of others, or their folly.[97] Nevertheless attempts to repress it by law (in other words, to regulate prices by law so far as their variations depend on iniquity, and not on nature) must for ever be ineffective; though Plato, Bacon, and the First Napoleon—all three of them men who knew somewhat more of humanity than the "British merchant" usually does—tried their hands at it, and have left some (probably) good moderative forms of law, which we will examine in their place. But the only final check upon it must be radical purifying of the national character, for being, as Bacon calls it, "concessum propter duritiem cordis," it is to be done away with by touching the heart only; not, however, without medicinal law—as in the case of the other permission, "propter duritiem." But in this, more than in anything (though much in all, and though in this he would not himself allow of their application, for his own laws against usury are sharp enough), Plato's words are true in the fourth book of the "Polity," that neither drugs, nor charms, nor burnings, will touch a deep-lying political sore, any more than a deep bodily one; but only right and utter change of constitution; and that "they do but lose their labour who think that by any tricks of law they can get the better of these mischiefs of intercourse, and see not that they hew at a Hydra."

I just mentioned that the vastness of the sea raises the cost of trade. Trade or commerce, in general, is always expensive; the value of the items is decreased by the costs of transporting them and by the upkeep of the people involved. Therefore, trade only makes sense when both producers benefit from exchanging one item for another, and this advantage is greater than the transport costs. It’s only considered fair when the carriers employed by the producers (commonly known as merchants) seek payment rather than profit. In fair trade, there are three parties involved: the two individuals or groups exchanging items and the agent or agents facilitating the exchange. Both parties know the value of what they're trading, and each receives something of equal worth, meaning neither party profits or loses (because for every gain one party makes, the other loses the same amount). The intermediary agent is compensated with a known and equitable percentage from both sides, partly for their labor in transportation and partly for their care, expertise, and the risk they take. Any attempt to hide the amount they earn suggests either that the agent is trying to charge an unreasonable percentage or that the exchangers are attempting to deny them fair compensation. Usually, it's the agent trying to make a larger profit by buying low and selling high. Some of this extra profit is deserved and should be openly requested, as it reflects the merchant’s knowledge and foresight regarding supply and demand. However, much of this profit is unjust, primarily due to keeping the exchangers unaware of the item's value and exploiting the buyer’s desperation and the seller’s hardship. Thus, this practice is a harmful form of usury; usury simply means charging an excessive fee for the use of something, regardless of whether the excess comes from lending or trading, rent or price—the core of usury lies in taking advantage of someone's situation or needs rather than providing fair compensation for labor. This is why all the great thinkers have considered it unnatural and immoral, as it preys on the suffering or naiveté of others. Attempts to control this by law—essentially trying to regulate prices based on dishonesty rather than what’s inherent in nature—will always be futile. Although Plato, Bacon, and Napoleon—all of whom understood humanity better than the typical “British merchant”—made attempts to create laws addressing this issue, they left behind only some possibly effective regulations, which we will examine later. The only true solution must be a fundamental change in national character, as Bacon described it, "concessum propter duritiem cordis," which can only be achieved by appealing to the heart; nevertheless, it must be accompanied by regulatory law, similar to the other permissions, "propter duritiem." In these matters, more than any other, and although he would not advocate for their application since his own laws against usury are quite strict, Plato's assertion in the fourth book of the "Polity" holds true: neither drugs, nor charms, nor punishments will resolve a deep-seated political issue any more than they would heal a serious physical ailment. Only a complete and genuine restructuring will do the trick, and those who believe they can outsmart these problems through legal maneuvers will simply waste their efforts, unaware that they are battling a Hydra.

And indeed this Hydra seems so unslayable, and sin sticks so fast between the joinings of the stones of buying and selling, that "to trade" in things, or literally "cross-give" them, has warped itself, by the instinct of nations, into their worst word for fraud; for, because in trade there cannot but be trust, and it seems also that there cannot but also be injury in answer to it, what is merely fraud between enemies becomes treachery among friends: and "trader," "traditor," and "traitor" are but the same word. For which simplicity of language there is more reason than at first appears; for as in true commerce there is no "profit," so in true commerce there is no "sale." The idea of sale is that of an interchange [Pg 272] between enemies respectively endeavouring to get the better of one another; but commerce is an exchange between friends; and there is no desire but that it should be just, any more than there would be between members of the same family. The moment there is a bargain over the pottage, the family relation is dissolved;—typically "the days of mourning for my father are at hand." Whereupon follows the resolve "then will I slay my brother."

And it really seems like this Hydra is impossible to defeat, and sin clings so tightly between the cracks of buying and selling, that "to trade" in things, or literally "to give back and forth," has twisted itself, by the instinct of nations, into their worst word for deception; because in trade there has to be trust, and it also seems like there must be injury in response to it, what is simply fraud between enemies turns into betrayal among friends: and "trader," "traditor," and "traitor" are just different forms of the same word. There’s more logic to this simplicity of language than it seems at first; because in true commerce there’s no "profit," so in true commerce there’s no "sale." The idea of sale implies an exchange between enemies who are each trying to outdo the other; but commerce is an exchange between friends; and there’s no desire for anything other than fairness, just like among family members. The moment there’s a deal made over the stew, the family bond is broken;—typically "the days of mourning for my father are at hand." Then comes the determination "so I will slay my brother."

This inhumanity of mercenary commerce is the more notable because it is a fulfilment of the law that the corruption of the best is the worst. For as, taking the body natural for symbol of the body politic, the governing and forming powers may be likened to the brain and the labouring to the limbs, the mercantile, presiding over circulation and communication of things in changed utilities is symbolized by the heart; which, if it harden, all is lost. And this is the ultimate lesson which the leader of English intellect meant for us (a lesson, indeed, not all his own, but part of the old wisdom of humanity), in the tale of the "Merchant of Venice"; in which the true and incorrupt merchant,—kind and free, beyond every other Shakespearian conception of men,—is opposed to the corrupted merchant, or usurer; the lesson being deepened by the expression of the strange hatred which the corrupted merchant bears to the pure one, mixed with intense scorn—

This cruelty of mercenary trade is especially striking because it shows that the corruption of the best leads to the worst. Just like how the human body represents the political body, the governing and shaping powers can be compared to the brain, while the working class is like the limbs. The mercantile aspect, overseeing the flow and exchange of goods in altered usefulness, is akin to the heart; if it becomes hardened, everything is lost. This is the key lesson that the leader of English thought intended for us (a lesson not entirely his own, but part of humanity's old wisdom) in the story of the "Merchant of Venice"; where the true and incorruptible merchant—kind and free, surpassing every other Shakespearian portrayal of men—is contrasted with the corrupt merchant or usurer; this lesson is heightened by the expression of the strange hatred that the corrupt merchant feels towards the pure one, mixed with deep scorn.

"This is the fool that lent out money gratis; look to him, jailor," (as to lunatic no less than criminal); the enmity, observe, having its symbolism literally carried out by being aimed straight at the heart, and finally foiled by a literal appeal to the great moral law that flesh and blood cannot be weighed, enforced by "Portia" ("Portion"), the type of divine Fortune,[98] found, not in gold, nor in silver, but in lead, that [Pg 273] is to say, in endurance and patience, not in splendour; and finally taught by her lips also, declaring, instead of the law and quality of "merces," the greater law and quality of mercy, which is not strained, but drops as the rain, blessing him that gives and him that takes. And observe that this "mercy" is not the mean "Misericordia," but the mighty "Gratia," answered by Gratitude (observe Shylock's leaning on the, to him detestable, word gratis, and compare the relation of Grace to Equity given in the second chapter of the second book of the "Memorabilia"); that is to say, it is the gracious or loving, instead of the strained, or competing manner, of doing things, answered, not only with "merces" or pay, but with "merci," or thanks. And this is indeed the meaning of the great benediction, "Grace, mercy, and peace," for there can be no peace without grace (not even by help of rifled cannon),[99] nor even without triplicity of graciousness, for the Greeks, who began with but one Grace, had to open their scheme into three before they had done.

"This is the fool who lent money for free; watch him, jailer," (as a madman no less than a criminal); notice how the hostility is symbolically aimed straight at the heart, and ultimately countered by a direct reference to the great moral law that flesh and blood can’t be weighed, enforced by "Portia" ("Portion"), the embodiment of divine Fortune,[98] found, not in gold or silver, but in lead, meaning in endurance and patience, not in splendor; and finally taught by her words, declaring, instead of the law and idea of "merces," the greater law and idea of mercy, which isn’t forced, but falls like rain, blessing both the giver and the receiver. And note that this "mercy" is not the petty "Misericordia," but the powerful "Gratia," answered by Gratitude (notice Shylock's reliance on the, to him abhorrent, word gratis, and compare the connection of Grace to Equity mentioned in the second chapter of the second book of the "Memorabilia"); that is to say, it is the gracious or loving way of doing things, responded to not only with "merces" or payment, but with "merci," or thanks. And this truly captures the essence of the great blessing, "Grace, mercy, and peace," for there can be no peace without grace (not even with the aid of rifled cannons),[99] nor even without a triplicity of graciousness, as the Greeks, who started with just one Grace, had to evolve their concept into three before they were finished.

With the usual tendency of long-repeated thought to take the surface for the deep, we have conceived their goddesses as if they only gave loveliness to gesture; whereas their true function is to give graciousness to deed, the other loveliness arising naturally out of that. In which function Charis becomes Charitas[100] and has a name and praise even greater [Pg 274] than that of Faith or truth, for these may be maintained sullenly and proudly; but Charis[101] is in her countenance always gladdening (Aglaia), and in her service instant and humble; and the true wife of Vulcan, or Labour. And it is not until her sincerity of function is lost, and her mere beauty contemplated, instead of her patience, that she is born again of the foam flake, and becomes Aphrodité; then only capable of joining herself to War and to the enmities of men, instead of to Labour and their services. Therefore the fable of Mars and Venus is, chosen by Homer, picturing himself as Demodocus, to sing at the games in the Court of Alcinous. Phæacia is the Homeric island of Atlantis; an image of noble and wise government, concealed, how slightly! merely by the change of a short vowel for a long one in the name of its queen; yet misunderstood by all later writers, even by Horace in his [Pg 275] "pinguis, Phæaxque," etc. That fable expresses the perpetual error of men, thinking that grace and dignity can only be reached by the soldier, and never by the artizan; so that commerce and the useful arts have had the honour and beauty taken away, and only the Fraud[102] and Pain left to them, with the lucre. Which is, indeed, one great reason of the continual blundering about the offices of government with respect to commerce. The higher classes are ashamed to deal with it; and though ready enough to fight for (or occasionally against) the people,—to preach to them,—or judge them, will not break bread for them; the refined upper servant who has willingly looked after the burnishing of the armoury and ordering of the library, not liking to set foot into the larder.

With the usual tendency for long-held beliefs to confuse appearance with substance, we think of their goddesses as if they only added beauty to movement; when in reality, their true role is to bring grace to actions, with the other beauty flowing naturally from that. In this role, Charis becomes Charitas[100], and her name and acclaim are even greater than those of Faith or Truth, because these can be held onto with bitterness and pride; but Charis[101] is always joyful in her expression (Aglaia), and in her service, she is both quick and humble; she is the true wife of Vulcan, or Work. And it’s only when her genuine purpose is forgotten, and her mere beauty is focused on instead of her patience, that she is reborn from the sea foam and becomes Aphrodité; only then can she align herself with War and human conflicts, rather than with Work and their contributions. Thus, the story of Mars and Venus is chosen by Homer, depicting himself as Demodocus, to sing at the games in the Court of Alcinous. Phæacia is the Homeric island of Atlantis; a symbol of noble and wise governance, disguised so subtly! merely by swapping a short vowel for a long one in the name of its queen; yet completely misunderstood by all later writers, even by Horace in his [Pg 275] "pinguis, Phæaxque," etc. That story illustrates the persistent mistake of men, believing that grace and dignity can only be achieved by soldiers, never by artisans; resulting in commerce and the useful arts being stripped of honor and beauty, leaving only Deceit[102] and Pain, along with profit. This is, indeed, one major reason for the ongoing misunderstandings in government regarding commerce. The upper classes are ashamed to engage with it; and while they are ready to fight for (or sometimes against) the people, to preach to them, or judge them, they will not share a meal with them; the refined upper servant who has willingly cared for the polishing of the armory and organizing of the library avoids entering the pantry.

Farther still. As Charis becomes Charitas on the one side, she becomes—better still—Chara, Joy, on the other; or rather this is her very mother's milk and the beauty of her childhood; for God brings no enduring Love, nor any other good, out of [Pg 276] pain, nor out of contention; but out of joy and harmony.[103] And in this sense, human and divine, music and gladness, and the measures of both, come into her name; and Cher becomes full-vowelled Cheer, and Cheerful; and Chara, companioned, opens into Choir and Choral.

Farther still. As Charis transforms into Charitas on one side, she also becomes—better yet—Chara, Joy, on the other; or rather, this is the essence of her mother's nurturing and the beauty of her childhood; for God brings no lasting Love, nor any other good, from pain or conflict; only from joy and harmony.[Pg 276] And in this way, both human and divine, music and happiness, along with their rhythms, become part of her name; and Cher evolves into fully expressive Cheer, and Cheerful; while Chara, in companionship, expands into Choir and Choral.

And lastly. As Grace passes into Freedom of action, Charis becomes Eleutheria, or liberality; a form of liberty quite curiously and intensely different from the thing usually understood by "Liberty" in modern language; indeed, much more like what some people would call slavery; for a Greek always understood, primarily, by liberty, deliverance from the law of his own passions (or from what the Christian writers call bondage of corruption), and this a complete liberty: not having to resist the passion, but making it fawn upon, and follow him—(this may be again partly the meaning of the fawning beasts about the Circean cave; so, again, George Herbert—

And finally, as Grace enters into Freedom of action, Charis becomes Eleutheria, or generosity; a type of freedom that is quite intriguingly and intensely different from what we typically think of as "Liberty" today. In fact, it’s more similar to what some might refer to as slavery; because for a Greek, liberty primarily meant liberation from the dictates of one's own desires (or from what Christian writers call the bondage of corruption), and this is a complete freedom: not having to fight against desires, but having them submit to and follow him—(this might also partially explain the fawning beasts around the Circean cave; and then, again, George Herbert—

Control your passion's anger;
Then may the creatures lead you to joyful light)—

not being merely safe from the Siren, but also unbound from the mast. And it is only in such generosity that any man becomes capable of so governing others as to take true part in any system of national economy. Nor is there any other eternal distinction between the upper and lower classes than this form of liberty, Eleutheria, or benignity, in the one, and its opposite of slavery, Douleia, or malignity, in the other; the separation of these two orders of men, and the firm government of the lower by the higher, being the first conditions of possible wealth and economy in any state,—the Gods giving it no greater gift than the power to discern its freemen, and "malignum spernere vulgus."

not just being safe from the Siren, but also free from the mast. It's only through such generosity that anyone can truly manage others and participate meaningfully in any national economy. Moreover, the only lasting difference between the upper and lower classes is this kind of freedom, Eleutheria, or kindness, in one, and its counterpart of slavery, Douleia, or cruelty, in the other; the division of these two groups of people, along with the firm governance of the lower by the higher, are the fundamental requirements for potential wealth and economy in any state—the Gods bestowing no greater gift than the ability to recognize its free citizens, and "malignum spernere vulgus."

[Pg 277]The examination of this form of Charis must, therefore, lead us into the discussion of the principles of government in general, and especially of that of the poor by the rich, discovering how the Graciousness joined with the Greatness, or Love with Majestas, is the true Dei Gratia, or Divine Right, of every form and manner of King; i.e., specifically, of the thrones, dominations, princedoms, virtues, and powers of the earth;—of the thrones, stable, or "ruling," literally right-doing powers ("rex eris, recte si facies:") of the dominations, lordly, edifying, dominant, and harmonious powers; chiefly domestic, over the "built thing," domus, or house; and inherently twofold, Dominus and Domina; Lord and Lady: of the Princedoms, pre-eminent, incipient, creative, and demonstrative powers; thus poetic and mercantile, in the "princeps carmen deduxisse" and the merchant-prince: of the Virtues or Courages; militant, guiding, or Ducal powers; and finally of the Strengths and Forces pure; magistral powers, of the more over the less, and the forceful and free over the weak and servile elements of life.

[Pg 277]Examining this form of Charis must lead us to discuss the principles of government in general, particularly the relationship between the rich and the poor. We need to uncover how Graciousness paired with Greatness, or Love combined with Authority, represents the true Divine Right of every type of King; specifically, regarding the thrones, dominations, princedoms, virtues, and powers of the earth. This includes stable or "ruling" powers that uphold justice ("you will be a king if you act justly"), the lordly and harmonious powers over the household, embodying both Lord and Lady roles; the pre-eminent and creative powers represented by princes, both in poetic and mercantile senses, as seen in the "princeps carmen deduxisse" and the merchant-prince; the courageous and guiding powers of the Virtues; and finally, the pure Strengths and Forces, which are authoritative powers over the weak and subservient aspects of life.

Subject enough for the next paper involving "economical" principles of some importance, of which, for theme, here is a sentence, which I do not care to translate, for it would sound harsh in English, though, truly, it is one of the tenderest ever uttered by man; which may be meditated over, or rather through, in the meanwhile, by any one who will take the pains:—

Subject enough for the next paper involving "economic" principles of some importance, of which, for theme, here is a sentence that I don't want to translate, because it would sound harsh in English, although, truly, it is one of the most tender things ever said by a person; which can be contemplated, or rather thought through, in the meantime, by anyone who cares to put in the effort:—

Ἆῥ οὖν, ὥσπερ ἵππος τῷ ἀνεπιστήμονι μὲν ἐγχειροῦντι δὲ χρῆσθαι ζημία ἐστὶν, οὕτω καὶ ἀδελφὸς ὅταν τις αὐτῷ μὴ ἐπιστάμενος ἐγχειρῆ χρῆσθαι, ζημία ἐστί;

So, just as a horse can cause damage when used by someone who doesn't understand how to handle it, in the same way, if a brother tries to use something without knowing how, is that also harmful?

FOOTNOTES:

[88] The waste of labour in obtaining the gold, though it cannot be estimated by help of any existing data, may be understood in its bearing on entire economy by supposing it limited to transactions between two persons. If two farmers in Australia have been exchanging corn and cattle with each other for years, keeping their accounts of reciprocal debt in any simple way, the sum of the possessions of either would not be diminished, though the part of it which was lent or borrowed were only reckoned by marks on a stone, or notches on a tree; and the one counted himself accordingly, so many scratches, or so many notches, better than the other. But it would soon be seriously diminished if, discovering gold in their fields, each resolved only to accept golden counters for a reckoning; and accordingly, whenever he wanted a sack of corn or a cow, was obliged to go and wash sand for a week before he could get the means of giving a receipt for them.

[88] The waste of effort in getting gold, even though it can't be measured using any existing data, can be understood in its impact on the overall economy by imagining it limited to transactions between two people. If two farmers in Australia have been swapping corn and cattle for years, keeping track of their mutual debts in a simple way, the total possessions of either would not decrease, even if the part that was lent or borrowed was only noted by scratches on a stone or notches in a tree; and each would count themselves according to how many scratches or notches they had compared to the other. However, their possessions would quickly start to diminish if, upon discovering gold in their fields, they both decided to only accept golden coins for transactions; thus, every time one wanted a sack of corn or a cow, they would have to spend a week washing sand just to have the means to make a payment.

[89] It is difficult to estimate the curious futility of discussions such as that which lately occupied a section of the British Association, on the absorption of gold, while no one can produce even the simplest of the data necessary for the inquiry. To take the first occurring one,—What means have we of ascertaining the weight of gold employed this year in the toilettes of the women of Europe (not to speak of Asia); and, supposing it known, what means of conjecturing the weight by which, next year, their fancies, and the changes of style among their jewellers, will diminish or increase it?

[89] It’s hard to grasp the strange pointlessness of discussions like the one that recently took place at a section of the British Association about the absorption of gold, especially when no one can provide even the simplest data needed for the inquiry. To start with—how can we determine the amount of gold used this year in the jewelry of women in Europe (not to mention Asia)? And even if we did know, how could we guess what amount would change next year based on their preferences and the shifting styles from their jewelers?

[90] See, in Pope's epistle to Lord Bathurst, his sketch of the difficulties and uses of a currency literally "pecuniary "—

[90] Check out Pope's letter to Lord Bathurst, where he outlines the challenges and purposes of a currency that's literally "money-related"—

        "His Grace will game—to White's a bull he led," etc.

"His Grace will play—he led a bull to White's," etc.

[91] Perhaps both; perhaps silver only. It may be found expedient ultimately to leave gold free for use in the arts. As a means of reckoning, the standard might be, and in some cases has already been, entirely ideal.—See Mill's "Political Economy," book iii., chap. 7, at beginning.

[91] Maybe both; maybe just silver. It could be more practical in the end to keep gold available for artistic use. As a way of measuring value, the standard could be, and in some cases already has been, completely theoretical.—See Mill's "Political Economy," book iii., chap. 7, at beginning.

[92] The purity of the drachma and sequin were not without significance of the state of intellect, art, and policy, both in Athens and Venice;—a fact first impressed upon me ten years ago, when, in daguerreotypes of Venetian architecture, I found no purchasable gold pure enough to gild them with, but that of the old Venetian sequin.

[92] The quality of the drachma and sequin reflected the state of intellect, art, and politics in both Athens and Venice. I realized this ten years ago when I looked at daguerreotypes of Venetian architecture and discovered that there was no gold available that was pure enough to gild them, except for the old Venetian sequin.

[93] Under which term, observe, we include all documents of debt which, being honest, might be transferable, though they practically are not transferred; while we exclude all documents which are in reality worthless, though in fact transferred temporarily as bad money is. The document of honest debt, not transferred, is merely to paper currency as gold withdrawn from circulation is to that of bullion. Much confusion has crept into the reasoning on this subject from the idea that withdrawal from circulation is a definable state, whereas it is a gradated state, and indefinable. The sovereign in my pocket is withdrawn from circulation as long as I choose to keep it there. It is no otherwise withdrawn if I bury it, nor even if I choose to make it, and others, into a golden cup, and drink out of them; since a rise in the price of the wine, or of other things, may at any time cause me to melt the cup and throw it back into currency; and the bullion operates on the prices of the things in the market as directly, though not as forcibly, while it is in the form of a cup, as it does in the form of a sovereign. No calculation can be founded on my humour in any ease. If I like to handle rouleaus, and therefore keep a quantity of gold, to play with, in the form of jointed basaltic columns, it is all one in its effect on the market as if I kept it in the form of twisted filigree, or steadily amicus lamnæ, beat the narrow gold pieces into broad ones, and dined off them. The probability is greater that I break the rouleau than that I melt the plate; but the increased probability is not calculable. Thus, documents are only withdrawn from the currency when cancelled, and bullion when it is so effectually lost as that the probability of finding it is no greater than that of finding new gold in the mine.

[93] Here, we refer to all legitimate debt documents that might be transferable, even if they aren't actually transferred; we exclude worthless documents that are temporarily passed around like bad money. A legitimate debt document that isn't transferred is like paper money compared to gold that’s taken out of circulation. There's been a lot of confusion about this topic because people think withdrawal from circulation is a clear state, when really it’s a gradated and unclear situation. The coin in my pocket is out of circulation as long as I choose to keep it there. It remains out of circulation if I bury it, or even if I turn it—and others—into a gold cup to drink from; if the price of wine or other goods goes up, I might decide to melt the cup and put it back into circulation. The gold still influences market prices even in the form of a cup, although not as strongly, just like it does as a coin. I can’t base any calculations on my whims. Whether I keep gold as jointed basaltic columns for fun or in another decorative form, it affects the market the same way. I’m more likely to break the stack of coins than to melt the gold plates, but the chance isn’t predictable. So, documents are only considered out of circulation when they’re canceled, and bullion when it’s so thoroughly lost that the likelihood of finding it is the same as discovering new gold in a mine.

[94] They are (up to the amount of the currency) simply creditors and debtors—the commercial types of the two great sects of humanity which those words describe; for debt and credit are of course merely the mercantile forms of the words "duty" and "creed," which give the central ideas: only it is more accurate to say "faith" than "creed," because creed has been applied carelessly to mere forms of words. Duty properly signifies whatever in substance or act one person owes to another, and faith the other's trust in his rendering it. The French "devoir" and "foi" are fuller and clearer words than ours; for, faith being the passive of fact, foi comes straight through fides from fio; and the French keep the group of words formed from the infinitive—fieri, "se fier," "se défier," "défiance," and the grand following "défi." Our English "affiance," "defiance," "confidence," "diffidence," retain accurate meanings; but our "faithful" has become obscure, from being used for "faithworthy," as well as "full of faith." "His name that sat on him was called Faithful and True."

[94] They are (up to the amount of the currency) simply creditors and debtors—the commercial types of the two main groups of humanity that those terms refer to; because debt and credit are really just the business versions of the words "duty" and "faith," which provide the key concepts: it's actually more accurate to say "faith" than "creed," since "creed" has often been used improperly to describe just superficial expressions. Duty correctly means whatever in substance or action one person owes to another, while faith is the trust that the other person has in fulfilling that obligation. The French words "devoir" and "foi" are clearer and more complete than ours; because, with faith being the passive form of fact, "foi" comes directly from "fides" via "fio"; and the French maintain the group of words created from the infinitive—"fieri," "se fier," "se défier," "défiance," and the notable "défi." Our English words "affiance," "defiance," "confidence," "diffidence," keep their precise meanings; but our term "faithful" has become unclear, as it’s been used to mean both "worthy of faith" and "full of faith." "His name that sat on him was called Faithful and True."

Trust is the passive of true saying, as faith is the passive of due doing; and the right learning of these etymologies, which are in the strictest sense only to be learned "by heart," is of considerably more importance to the youth of a nation than its reading and ciphering.

Trust is the passive form of true saying, just as faith is the passive form of proper doing; understanding these origins, which can only be fully grasped "by heart," is much more important for the youth of a nation than simply reading and doing math.

[95] For example, suppose an active peasant, having got his ground into good order and built himself a comfortable house, finding still time on his hands, sees one of his neighbours little able to work, and ill lodged, and offers to build him also a house, and to put his land in order, on condition of receiving for a given period rent for the building and tithe of the fruits. The offer is accepted, and a document given promissory of rent and tithe. This note is money. It can only be good money if the man who has incurred the debt so far recovers his strength as to be able to take advantage of the help he has received, and meet the demand of the note; if he lets his house fall to ruin, and his field to waste, his promissory note will soon be valueless: but the existence of the note at all is a consequence of his not having worked so stoutly as the other. Let him gain as much as to be able to pay back the entire debt; the note is cancelled and we have two rich store-holders and no currency.

[95] For example, imagine an active farmer who has gotten his land in good shape and built a comfortable house. Finding that he still has some free time, he notices one of his neighbors is struggling to work and lives in poor conditions. He offers to build a house for this neighbor and help organize his land in exchange for rent for the building and a share of the crops for a certain period. The neighbor agrees, and they create a document promising to pay the rent and the crop share. This note serves as money. It will only be valuable if the person who took on the debt is able to recover and benefit from the help they received to fulfill the promise in the note. If they let their house fall apart and allow their land to go to waste, the promissory note will quickly lose its value. However, the existence of the note is a direct result of the borrower not working as hard as the farmer. If the neighbor manages to earn enough to repay the entire debt, the note is voided, and now we have two wealthy landowners with no currency in circulation.

[96] It is a strange habit of wise humanity to speak in enigmas only, so that the highest truths and usefullest laws must be hunted for through whole picture-galleries of dreams, which to the vulgar seem dreams only. Thus Homer, the Greek tragedians, Plato, Dante, Chaucer, Shakespeare, and Goethe, have hidden all that is chiefly serviceable in their work, and in all the various literature they absorbed and re-embodied, under types which have rendered it quite useless to the multitude. What is worse, the two primal declarers of moral discovery, Homer and Plato, are partly at issue; for Plato's logical power quenched his imagination, and he became incapable of understanding the purely imaginative element either in poetry or painting; he therefore somewhat overrates the pure discipline of passionate art in song and music, and misses that of meditative art. There is, however, a deeper reason for his distrust of Homer. His love of justice, and reverently religious nature made him dread as death, every form of fallacy; but chiefly, fallacy respecting the world to come (his own myths being only symbolic exponents of a rational hope). We shall perhaps now every day discover more clearly how right Plato was in this, and feel ourselves more and more wonderstruck that men such as Homer and Dante (and, in an inferior sphere, Milton), not to speak of the great sculptors and painters of every age, have permitted themselves, though full of all nobleness and wisdom, to coin idle imaginations of the mysteries of eternity, and mould the faiths of the families of the earth by the courses of their own vague and visionary arts: while the indisputable truths respecting human life and duty, respecting which they all have but one voice, lie hidden behind these veils of phantasy, unsought and often unsuspected. I will gather carefully, out of Dante and Homer, what of this kind bears on our subject, in its due place; the first broad intention of their symbols may be sketched at once. The rewards of a worthy use of riches, subordinate to other ends, are shown by Dante in the fifth and sixth orbs of Paradise; for the punishment of their unworthy use, three places are assigned; one for the avaricious and prodigal whose souls are lost ("Hell": Canto 7); one for the avaricious and prodigal whose souls are capable of purification ("Purgatory": Canto 19); and one for the usurers, of whom none can be redeemed ("Hell": Canto 17). The first group, the largest in all hell (gente piu che altrove troppa), meet in contrary currents, as the waves of Charybdis, casting weights at each other from opposite sides. This weariness of contention is the chief element of their torture; so marked by the beautiful lines, beginning, Or puoi, figliuol, etc. (but the usurers, who made their money inactively, sit on the sand, equally without rest, however, "Di qua, di la soccorrien," etc.). For it is not avarice but contention for riches, leading to this double misuse of them, which, in Dante's sight, is the unredeemable sin. The place of its punishment is guarded by Plutus, "the great enemy," and "la fièra crudele," a spirit quite different from the Greek Plutus, who, though old and blind, is not cruel, and is curable, so as to become far-sighted (οὑ τυφλὸς ἀλλ’ ὀξὺ βλέπων—Plato's epithets in first book of the Laws). Still more does this Dantesque type differ from the resplendent Plutus of Goethe in the second part of "Faust," who is the personified power of wealth for good or evil; not the passion for wealth; and again from the Plutus of Spenser, who is the passion of mere aggregation. Dante's Plutus is specially and definitely the spirit of Contention and Competition, or Evil Commerce; and because, as I showed in my last paper, this kind of commerce "makes all men strangers," his speech is unintelligible, and no single soul of all those ruined by him has recognizable features.

       (La sconescente vita—
       Ad ogni conoscenza or li fa bruni).

[96] It's a strange habit of wise humanity to speak only in riddles, forcing us to search through entire galleries of dreams for the highest truths and most useful laws, which appear to the average person as just dreams. So, Homer, the Greek tragedians, Plato, Dante, Chaucer, Shakespeare, and Goethe have concealed all that is truly valuable in their work, as well as in all the various literature they've absorbed and transformed, under symbols that make it essentially useless to the masses. Worse still, the two primary voices of moral discovery, Homer and Plato, are partly at odds; Plato's logical rigor stifled his imagination, preventing him from grasping the purely imaginative aspect found in poetry or painting. Consequently, he somewhat overvalues the strict discipline of passionate art in song and music while overlooking that of reflective art. However, there is a deeper reason for his distrust of Homer. His passion for justice and devout nature made him fear every kind of falsehood; especially concerning the afterlife (his own myths being merely symbolic representations of a rational hope). Perhaps we will increasingly recognize how right Plato was in this, and continue to be amazed that men like Homer and Dante (and, in a lesser scope, Milton), not to mention the great sculptors and painters through time, allowed themselves—despite their nobility and wisdom—to create fanciful notions about the mysteries of eternity and shape the beliefs of families worldwide through their vague and visionary arts. Meanwhile, the undeniable truths regarding human life and duty, which they all unanimously agree on, lie concealed behind these layers of fantasy, often unnoticed and unexamined. I will carefully compile, from Dante and Homer, what applies to our topic in due course; however, the main intention behind their symbols can be outlined now. Dante illustrates the rewards for a rightful use of wealth, subordinate to other purposes, in the fifth and sixth spheres of Paradise; for the punishment of its improper use, there are three designated places: one for the greedy and wasteful whose souls are lost ("Hell": Canto 7); one for the greedy and wasteful whose souls can be purified ("Purgatory": Canto 19); and one for the usurers, from whom no one can be redeemed ("Hell": Canto 17). The first group, the largest in all of hell (gente piu che altrove troppa), clash like the waves of Charybdis, throwing burdens at one another from opposing sides. This exhaustion from conflict is their primary torment, beautifully captured in the lines beginning, Or puoi, figliuol, etc. (but the usurers, who passively made their money, sit on the sand, equally restless, however, "Di qua, di la soccorrien," etc.). It’s not avarice but the fight for wealth that leads to this double misuse, which in Dante’s view is the unforgivable sin. The place of its punishment is guarded by Plutus, "the great enemy," and "la fièra crudele," a spirit entirely different from the Greek Plutus, who, though old and blind, is not cruel and can be healed to gain insight (οὑ τυφλὸς ἀλλ’ ὀξὺ βλέπων—Plato's descriptions in the first book of the Laws). Even more, this Dantesque version greatly differs from Goethe's radiant Plutus in the second part of "Faust," who embodies the force of wealth for both good and evil; not the desire for wealth; and again from Spenser's Plutus, who embodies mere accumulation. Dante's Plutus is specifically and explicitly the spirit of Conflict and Competition, or Evil Commerce; and because, as I demonstrated in my last paper, this type of commerce "makes all men strangers," his speech is incomprehensible, and no soul ruined by him has distinct features.

       (La sconescente vita—
       Ad ogni conoscenza or li fa bruni).

On the other hand, the redeemable sins of avarice and prodigality are, in Dante's sight, those which are without deliberate or calculated operation. The lust, or lavishness, of riches can be purged, so long as there has been no servile consistency of dispute and competition for them. The sin is spoken of as that of degradation by the love of earth; it is purified by deeper humiliation—the souls crawl on their bellies; their chant, "my soul cleaveth unto the dust." But the spirits here condemned are all recognizable, and even the worst examples of the thirst for gold, which they are compelled to tell the histories of during the night, are of men swept by the passion of avarice into violent crime, but not sold to its steady work. The precept given to each of these spirits for its deliverance is—Turn thine eyes to the lucre (lure) which the Eternal King rolls with the mighty wheels: otherwise, the wheels of the "Greater Fortune," of which the constellation is ascending when Dante's dream begins. Compare George Herbert,—

"Lift up thy head;
       Take stars for money; stars, not to be told
       By any art, yet to be purchased."

On the other hand, Dante sees the redeemable sins of greed and extravagance as those that lack intent or calculated thought. The desire for or excess of wealth can be cleansed, as long as there's no ongoing, desperate struggle for it. This sin is described as a fall into the love of the material world; it is purified through deeper humiliation—souls crawl on their bellies, singing, "my soul cleaveth unto the dust." However, the spirits condemned here are all recognizable, and even the worst instances of the craving for gold, which they are forced to recount during the night, are of people driven by greed into violent crimes, but not completely consumed by it. The advice given to each of these spirits for their redemption is—Look towards the treasure that the Eternal King rolls with mighty wheels; otherwise, you'll remain with the wheels of "Greater Fortune," symbolized by the constellation rising when Dante's dream begins. Compare George Herbert,—

"Lift up your head;"
       Take stars for money; stars, not to be told
       By any art, yet to be purchased."

And Plato's notable sentence in the third book of "Polity":—"Tell them they have divine gold and silver in their souls for ever; that they need no money stamped of men—neither may they otherwise than impiously mingle the gathering of the divine with the mortal treasure, for through that which the law of the multitude has coined, endless crimes have been done and suffered; but in theirs is neither pollution nor sorrow." At the entrance of this place of punishment an evil spirit is seen by Dante, quite other than the "Gran Nemico." The great enemy is obeyed knowingly and willingly; but this spirit—feminine—and called a Siren—is the "Deceitfulness of riches," ἀπάτη πλοῦτου of the gospels, winning obedience by guile. This is the Idol of Riches, made doubly phantasmal by Dante's seeing her in a dream. She is lovely to look upon, and enchants by her sweet singing, but her womb is loathsome. Now, Dante does not call her one of the Sirens carelessly, any more than he speaks of Charybdis carelessly, and though he had only got at the meaning of the Homeric fable through Virgil's obscure tradition of it, the clue he has given us is quite enough. Bacon's interpretation, "the Sirens, or pleasures," which has become universal since his time, is opposed alike to Plato's meaning and Homer's. The Sirens are not pleasures, but Desires: in the Odyssey they are the phantoms of vain desire; but in Plato's vision of Destiny, phantoms of constant Desire; singing each a different note on the circles of the distaff of Necessity, but forming one harmony, to which the three great Fates put words. Dante, however, adopted the Homeric conception of them, which was that they were demons of the Imagination, not carnal (desire of the eyes; not lust of the flesh); therefore said to be daughters of the Muses. Yet not of the muses, heavenly or historical, but of the muse of pleasure; and they are at first winged, because even vain hope excites and helps when first formed; but afterwards, contending for the possession of the imagination with the muses themselves, they are deprived of their wings, and thus we are to distinguish the Siren power from the Power of Circe, who is no daughter of the muses, but of the strong elements, Sun and Sea; her power is that of frank and full vital pleasure, which, if governed and watched, nourishes men; but, unwatched, and having no "moly," bitterness or delay mixed with it, turns men into beasts, but does not slay them, leaves them, on the contrary, power of revival. She is herself indeed an Enchantress;—pure Animal life; transforming—or degrading—but always wonderful (she puts the stores on board the ship invisibly, and is gone again, like a ghost); even the wild beasts rejoice and are softened around her cave; to men, she gives no rich feast, nothing but pure and right nourishment,—Pramnian wine, cheese and flour; that is corn, milk, and wine, the three great sustainers of life—it is their own fault if these make swine of them; and swine are chosen merely as the type of consumption; as Plato's ὑῶν πόλις in the second book of the "Polity," and perhaps chosen by Homer with a deeper knowledge of the likeness of nourishment, and internal form of body. "Et quel est, s'il vous plaît, cet audacieux animal qui se permet d'être bâti au dedans comme une jolie petite fille?"

And Plato's famous line in the third book of "Polity":—"Tell them they have divine gold and silver in their souls forever; that they don’t need any money made by humans—nor should they mix the gathering of the divine with mortal wealth, because through the currency of the masses, endless crimes have been committed and endured; but theirs is free from pollution or sorrow." At the entrance to this place of punishment, Dante sees an evil spirit, completely different from the "Great Enemy." The great enemy is obeyed knowingly and willingly; but this spirit—a feminine one—called a Siren—is the "Deceitfulness of riches," ἀπάτη πλοῦτου from the gospels, gaining obedience through trickery. This is the Idol of Riches, made even more ghostly by Dante’s vision of her in a dream. She is beautiful to behold, enchanting with her sweet singing, but her belly is repulsive. Dante doesn’t call her one of the Sirens carelessly, just as he doesn’t mention Charybdis without thought, and even though he only grasped the meaning of the Homeric tale through Virgil's vague account, the hint he gives us is quite sufficient. Bacon's interpretation, "the Sirens, or pleasures," which has become popular since his time, contradicts both Plato's and Homer's meanings. The Sirens aren’t pleasures; they are Desires: in the Odyssey, they are the illusions of empty desire; but in Plato's vision of Destiny, they are illusions of constant Desire; each singing a different note in the circles of the spinning wheel of Necessity, yet together creating one harmony, which the three great Fates articulate. Dante, however, embraced the Homeric view of them, seeing them as demons of the Imagination, not physical (desire of the eyes, not lust of the flesh); hence, they are said to be daughters of the Muses. Yet, they aren’t of the heavenly or historical muses, but of the muse of pleasure; and at first, they have wings, as even vain hope elevates and assists at its inception; but later, as they compete for the imagination’s attention against the muses themselves, they lose their wings, distinguishing the Siren's power from that of Circe, who is not a daughter of the muses but of the strong elements, Sun and Sea; her power is that of genuine, full-bodied pleasure, which, if managed and monitored, nourishes people; but if neglected, and without any "moly," bitterness, or delay mixed in, turns people into beasts, but doesn’t kill them; rather, it leaves them with the potential for revival. She is indeed an Enchantress;—pure Animal life; transforming—or degrading—but always fascinating (she secretly supplies the ship and vanishes, like a ghost); even the wild beasts rejoice and are softened around her cave; to humans, she offers no lavish feast, only pure and wholesome nourishment—Pramnian wine, cheese, and flour; that is corn, milk, and wine, the three essential sustainers of life—it is their own fault if these turn them into swine; and swine are merely chosen as a symbol of consumption; like Plato's ὑῶν πόλις in the second book of the "Polity," possibly chosen by Homer with a deeper understanding of the relationship between nourishment and the internal structure of the body. "And what is, if you please, this daring creature that dares to be built inside like a pretty little girl?"

"Hélas! chère enfant, j'ai honte de le nommer, et il ne foudra pas m'en vouloir. C'est ... c'est le cochon. Ce n'est pas précisément flatteur pour vous; mais nous en sommes tous là, et si cela vous contrarie par trop, il faut aller vous plaindre au bon Dieu qui a voulu que les choses fussent arrangées ainsï: seulement le cochon, qui ne pense qu' à manger, a l'estomac bien plus vaste que nous, et c'est toujours une consolation." ("Histoire d'une Bouchée de Pain," Lettre ix.) But the deadly Sirens are all things opposed to the Circean power. They promise pleasure, but never give it. They nourish in no wise; but slay by slow death. And whereas they corrupt the heart and the head, instead of merely betraying the senses, there is no recovery from their power; they do not tear nor snatch, like Scylla, but the men who have listened to them are poisoned, and waste away. Note that the Sirens' field is covered, not merely with the bones, but with the skins of those who have been consumed there. They address themselves, in the part of the song which Homer gives, not to the passions of Ulysses, but to his vanity, and the only man who ever came within hearing of them, and escaped untempted, was Orpheus, who silenced the vain imaginations by singing the praises of the gods.

"Hélas! dear child, I'm ashamed to say it, and I hope you won't hold it against me. It’s... it’s the pig. It’s not exactly flattering for you; but we’re all in this together, and if it bothers you too much, you should take it up with God, who decided things should be this way: only the pig, which only thinks about eating, has a much larger stomach than we do, and that’s always a comfort." ("Histoire d'une Bouchée de Pain," Lettre ix.) But the deadly Sirens are entirely opposed to the Circean power. They promise pleasure but never deliver. They don’t nourish at all; instead, they kill slowly. And while they corrupt both the heart and the mind, rather than just deceiving the senses, there is no escape from their influence; they don’t tear away like Scylla, but the men who have listened to them are poisoned and fade away. Note that the Sirens’ area is covered not just with bones, but also with the skins of those consumed there. They address themselves, in the part of the song that Homer provides, not to Ulysses’ passions, but to his vanity, and the only man who ever heard them and escaped untempted was Orpheus, who quieted the vain thoughts by singing the praises of the gods.

It is, then, one of these Sirens whom Dante takes as the phantasm or deceitfulness of riches; but note further, that she says it was her song that deceived Ulysses. Look back to Dante's account of Ulysses' death, and we find it was not the love of money, but pride of knowledge, that betrayed him; whence we get the clue to Dante's complete meaning: that the souls whose love of wealth is pardonable have been first deceived into pursuit of it by a dream of its higher uses, or by ambition. His Siren is therefore the Philotimé of Spenser, daughter of Mammon—

       "Whom all that folk with such contention
       Do flock about, my deare, my daughter is—
       Honour and dignitie from her alone
       Derived are."

It is, then, one of these Sirens that Dante sees as the illusion or deceitfulness of riches; but note that she claims her song deceived Ulysses. If we look back at Dante's account of Ulysses' death, we find it wasn't the love of money, but the pride of knowledge, that caused his downfall; this gives us insight into Dante's full meaning: that the souls whose love for wealth can be excused were first misled into chasing it by a vision of its greater purposes, or by ambition. His Siren is therefore the Philotimé from Spenser, daughter of Mammon—

       "Whom all that folk with such contention
       Do flock about, my dear, my daughter is—
       Honour and dignity from her alone
       Derived are."

By comparing Spenser's entire account of this Philotimé with Dante's of the Wealth-Siren, we shall get at the full meaning of both poets; but that of Homer lies hidden much more deeply. For his Sirens are indefinite, and they are desires of any evil thing; power of wealth is not specially indicated by him, until, escaping the harmonious danger of imagination, Ulysses has to choose between two practical ways of life, indicated by the two rocks of Scylla and Charybdis. The monsters that haunt them are quite distinct from the rocks themselves, which, having many other subordinate significations, are in the main Labour and Idleness, or getting and spending; each with its attendant monster, or betraying demon. The rock of gaining has its summit in the clouds, invisible and not to be climbed; that of spending is low, but marked by the cursed fig-tree, which has leaves but no fruit. We know the type elsewhere; and there is a curious lateral allusion to it by Dante when Jacopo di Sant' Andrea, who had ruined himself by profusion and committed suicide, scatters the leaves of the bush of Lotto degli Agli, endeavouring to hide himself among them. We shall hereafter examine the type completely; here I will only give an approximate rendering of Homer's words, which have been obscured more by translation than even by tradition—

By comparing Spenser's entire narrative about Philotimé with Dante's depiction of the Wealth-Siren, we can grasp the full meaning of both poets; however, Homer's meaning is much more deeply concealed. His Sirens are vague, representing desires for any kind of evil; the power of wealth isn't specifically pointed out until Ulysses has to choose between two practical life paths, represented by the two rocks of Scylla and Charybdis. The monsters that lurk around them are quite different from the rocks themselves, which symbolize various subordinate meanings but primarily represent Labor and Idleness, or gaining and spending; each with its own accompanying monster or treacherous influence. The rock of gaining looms high in the clouds, out of sight and impossible to scale; the rock of spending is low, marked by the cursed fig tree, which has leaves but no fruit. We recognize this type elsewhere; there's an interesting indirect reference to it in Dante when Jacopo di Sant' Andrea, who squandered his wealth and took his own life, hides among the leaves of the Lotto degli Agli bush. We'll explore this type further later; for now, I'll provide a rough translation of Homer's words, which have become more obscured by translation than by tradition—

"They are overhanging rocks. The great waves of blue water break round them; and the blessed Gods call them the Wanderers.

"They are overhanging rocks. The huge blue waves crash around them, and the blessed Gods call them the Wanderers."

"By one of them no winged thing can pass—not even the wild doves that bring ambrosia to their father Jove—but the smooth rock seizes its sacrifice of them." (Not even ambrosia to be had without Labour. The word is peculiar—as a part of anything offered for sacrifice; especially used of heave-offering.) "It reaches the wide heaven with its top, and a dark-blue cloud rests on it, and never passes; neither does the clear sky hold it in summer nor in harvest. Nor can any man climb it—not if he had twenty feet and hands, for it is smooth as though it were hewn.

"By one of them, nothing with wings can get through—not even the wild doves that bring ambrosia to their father Jove—but the smooth rock takes its sacrifice from them." (Not even ambrosia is free of effort. The word is unique—as a part of anything offered for sacrifice; especially used for heave-offering.) "It reaches the vast sky with its peak, and a dark-blue cloud sits on it, never moving; neither does the clear sky touch it in summer or during harvest. No one can climb it—not even if he had twenty feet and hands, because it’s as smooth as if it were carved."

"And in the midst of it is a cave which is turned the way of hell. And therein dwells Scylla, whining for prey: her cry, indeed, is no louder than that of a newly-born whelp: but she herself is an awful thing—nor can any creature see her face and be glad; no, though it were a god that rose against her. For she has twelve feet, all fore-feet, and six necks, and terrible heads on them; and each has three rows of teeth, full of black death.

"And in the middle of it is a cave that leads to hell. Inside it lives Scylla, lamenting for prey: her cry is really no louder than that of a newborn puppy: but she herself is a horrifying sight—no creature can look upon her face and feel happy; not even if a god confronted her. She has twelve feet, all front legs, and six necks, each with terrifying heads; and each head has three rows of teeth, filled with dark death."

"But the opposite rock is lower than this, though but a bow-shot distant; and upon it there is a great fig-tree, full of leaves; and under it the terrible Charybdis sucks it down, and thrice casts it up again; be not thou there when she sucks down, for Neptune himself could not save thee."

"But the opposite rock is lower than this one, even though it's only a short distance away; and on it, there’s a huge fig tree, full of leaves; and underneath it, the fearsome Charybdis pulls everything down and spits it up three times; don’t be there when she pulls things down, because even Neptune himself couldn't save you."

The reader will find the meaning of these types gradually elicited as we proceed.

The reader will see the meaning of these types come out gradually as we move forward.

[97] Hence Dante's companionship of Cahors, Inf., canto xi., supported by the view taken of the matter throughout the middle ages, in common with the Greeks.

[97] Therefore, Dante's partnership with Cahors, Inf., canto xi., aligns with the perspective held during the Middle Ages, shared by the Greeks.

[98] Shakespeare would certainly never have chosen this name had he been forced to retain the Roman spelling. Like Perdita, "lost lady," or "Cordelia," "heart-lady," Portia is "fortune-lady." The two great relative groups of words, Fortune, fero, and fors—Portio, porto, and pars (with the lateral branch, op-portune, im-portune, opportunity, etc.), are of deep and intrinsic significance; their various senses of bringing, abstracting, and sustaining, being all centralized by the wheel (which bears and moves at once), or still better, the ball (spera) of Fortune,—"Volve sua spera, e beata si gode:" the motive power of this wheel distinguishing its goddess from the fixed majesty of Necessitas with her iron nails; or ἀνάγκη, with her pillar of fire and iridescent orbits, fixed at the centre. Portus and porta, and gate in its connexion with gain, form another interesting branch group; and Mors, the concentration of delaying, is always to be remembered with Fors, the concentration of bringing and bearing, passing on into Fortis and Fortitude.

[98] Shakespeare definitely would not have picked this name if he had to stick to the Roman spelling. Like Perdita, meaning "lost lady," or Cordelia, meaning "heart-lady," Portia means "fortune-lady." The two main groups of related words, Fortune, fero, and fors—Portio, porto, and pars (along with the related words op-portune, im-portune, opportunity, etc.)—are very meaningful; their different meanings of bringing, abstracting, and sustaining all come together around the wheel (which both carries and moves at the same time), or even better, the ball (spera) of Fortune—"Volve sua spera, e beata si gode:" the driving force of this wheel sets its goddess apart from the fixed authority of Necessitas with her iron nails; or ἀνάγκη, with her pillar of fire and shimmering orbits, fixed at the center. Portus and porta, along with the idea of a gate in connection with gain, make up another interesting group; and Mors, the essence of delaying, should always be remembered alongside Fors, the essence of bringing and bearing, leading into Fortis and Fortitude.

[99] Out of whose mouths, indeed, no peace was ever promulgated, but only equipoise of panic, highly tremulous on the edge in changes in the wind.

[99] From whose mouths, in fact, no peace was ever declared, only a balance of fear, always shaky at the slightest shift in the breeze.

[100] The reader must not think that any care can be misspent in tracing the connexion and power of the words which we have to use in the sequel. Not only does all soundness of reasoning depend on the work thus done in the outset, but we may sometimes gain more by insistence on the expression of a truth, than by much wordless thinking about it; for to strive to express it clearly is often to detect it thoroughly; and education, even as regards thought, nearly sums itself in making men economise their words, and understand them. Nor is it possible to estimate the harm that has been done, in matters of higher speculation and conduct, by loose verbiage, though we may guess at it by observing the dislike which people show to having anything about their religion said to them in simple words, because then they understand it. Thus congregations meet weekly to invoke the influence of a Spirit of Life and Truth; yet if any part of that character were intelligibly expressed to them by the formulas of the service, they would be offended. Suppose, for instance, in the closing benediction, the clergyman were to give its vital significance to the word "Holy," and were to say, "the Fellowship of the Helpful and Honest Ghost be with you, and remain with you always," what would be the horror of many, first, at the irreverence of so intelligible an expression, and, secondly, at the discomfortable entry of the suspicion that (while throughout the commercial dealings of the week they had denied the propriety of Help, and possibility of Honesty) the Person whose company they had been asking to be blessed with could have no fellowship with knaves.

[100] The reader shouldn't think that any effort is wasted in exploring the connection and power of the words we will use later. The solidity of our reasoning relies heavily on this foundational work, and sometimes we benefit more from clearly expressing a truth than from merely pondering it quietly; striving for clarity helps us understand it better. Education, especially in terms of thought, largely revolves around teaching people to be concise with their words and to grasp their meanings. It’s hard to quantify the damage caused in the realms of deep thought and behavior by vague language, though we can hint at it by noticing how people often resist having their beliefs articulated in straightforward terms—because then it's too clear. Congregations gather each week to seek the influence of a Spirit of Life and Truth; yet, if any aspect of that spirit were simply put into the words of the service, they would react negatively. For instance, if during the closing blessing, the clergyman were to highlight the true meaning of "Holy" and say, "the Fellowship of the Helpful and Honest Spirit be with you, and remain with you always," many would be horrified first by the irreverence of such a clear expression and second by the uncomfortable realization that (while they had neglected the value of Help and the possibility of Honesty in their weekly transactions) the Being they were asking for blessings from could not associate with dishonest people.

[101] As Charis becomes Charitas [see next page], the word "Cher," or "Dear," passes from Shylock's sense of it (to buy cheap and sell dear) into Antonio's sense of it: emphasized with the final i in tender "Cheri," and hushed to English calmness in our noble "Cherish."

[101] As Charis becomes Charitas [see next page], the word "Cher," or "Dear," shifts from Shylock's understanding of it (to buy low and sell high) to Antonio's interpretation: highlighted by the final i in the affectionate "Cheri," and softened to English serenity in our noble "Cherish."

[102] While I have traced the finer and higher laws of this matter for those whom they concern, I have also to note the material law—vulgarly expressed in the proverb, "Honesty is the best policy." That proverb is indeed wholly inapplicable to matters of private interest. It is not true that honesty, as far as material gain is concerned, profits individuals. A clever and cruel knave will, in a mixed society, always be richer than an honest person can be. But Honesty is the best "policy," if policy means practice of State. For fraud gains nothing in a State. It only enables the knaves in it to live at the expense of honest people; while there is for every act of fraud, however small, a loss of wealth to the community. Whatever the fraudulent person gains, some other person loses, as fraud produces nothing; and there is, besides, the loss of the time and thought spent in accomplishing the fraud; and of the strength otherwise obtainable by mutual help (not to speak of the fevers of anxiety and jealousy in the blood, which are a heavy physical loss, as I will show in due time). Practically, when the nation is deeply corrupt, cheat answers to cheat, every one is in turn imposed upon, and there is to the body politic the dead loss of ingenuity, together with the incalculable mischief of the injury to each defrauded person, producing collateral effect unexpectedly. My neighbour sells me bad meat: I sell him in return flawed iron. We neither of us get one atom of pecuniary advantage on the whole transaction, but we both suffer unexpected inconvenience;—my men get scurvy, and his cattle-truck runs off the rails.

[102] I have outlined the deeper laws of this issue for those who care about them, but I also need to highlight the practical law—commonly summed up in the saying, "Honesty is the best policy." That saying, however, doesn’t really apply when it comes to personal gain. It’s not true that honesty leads to material benefit for individuals. A clever and ruthless trickster will always have more wealth than an honest person in a mixed society. But honesty is indeed the best "policy" if we view policy as the practice of government. Fraud doesn’t gain anything for a state; it just lets the dishonest thrive at the expense of honest people. For every act of fraud, no matter how small, the community loses wealth. Whatever the fraudster gains, someone else loses, since fraud creates nothing. Plus, there’s the wasted time and effort spent on executing the fraud, and the loss of the benefits we could have gained through mutual support—not to mention the anxiety and jealousy that can take a heavy toll on our health, as I will demonstrate later. In reality, when a nation is thoroughly corrupt, one cheat meets another, and everyone gets taken advantage of. The result is a dead loss of creativity and the unforeseen consequences of harming each defrauded individual. If my neighbor sells me rotten meat, I retaliate by selling him defective iron. In the end, neither of us gains anything financially from the whole deal, but we both face unexpected problems—my workers get scurvy, and his cattle truck derails.

[103] "τὰ μὲν οὗν ἄλλα ζῶα οὐκ ἔχειν αἴσθησιν τῶν εν ταῖς κινήσεσι ταξεων οὐδὲ ἀταξιῶν, οἷ δὴ ῥυθμὸς ὄνομα καὶ ἁρμονία ἡμῖν δὲ οὔς εἴπομεν τοὺς θεοὺς [Apollo, the Muses, and Bacchus—the grave Bacchus, that is—ruling the choir of age; or Bacchus restraining; 'sæva tene, cum Berecyntio cornu, tympana,' etc.] συγχορὲυτας δέδοσθαι, τούτους εἴναι καὶ τοὺς δεδώκοτας τὴν ἔνρυθμόν τε καὶ ἑναρμόνιον αἴσθησιν μεθ’ ἠδονῆς ... χόρους τε ὠνομακέναι παρὰ τῆς χαρὰς ἔμφυτον ὔνομα."—"Laws," book ii.

[103] "So the other animals do not have the perception of the orderly motions or the chaotic ones, we speak of the rhythm and harmony of the gods. [Apollo, the Muses, and Bacchus—the serious Bacchus, that is—leading the choir of time; or Bacchus holding back; 'sæva tene, with Berecyntian horn, drums,' etc.] They are given to be the chorus, and those who granted the rhythmic and harmonious perception along with pleasure ... that they are named choruses from the joy instilled in them.."—"Laws," book ii.


IV.

LAWS AND GOVERNMENTS: LABOUR AND RICHES.

It remains, in order to complete the series of our definitions, that we examine the general conditions of government, and fix the sense in which we are to use, in future, the terms applied to them.

It’s still necessary to finish our set of definitions by looking at the overall conditions of government and clarifying the meaning of the terms we’ll use moving forward.

The government of a state consists in its customs, laws, and councils, and their enforcements.

The government of a state includes its customs, laws, councils, and how they are enforced.

I.—Customs.

I.—Customs.

As one person primarily differs from another by fineness of nature, and secondarily, by fineness of training, so also, a polite nation differs from a savage one, first by the refinement of its nature, and secondly by the delicacy of its customs.

As one person mainly differs from another by their natural qualities, and secondarily by their level of training, a polite nation also differs from a savage one, first by the refinement of its character and second by the sophistication of its customs.

In the completeness, or accomplishment of custom, which is the nation's self-government, there are three stages—first, fineness in method of doing or of being;—called the manner or moral of acts: secondly, firmness in holding such method after adoption, so that it shall become a habit in the character: i.e., a constant "having" or "behaving"; and, lastly, practice, or ethical power in performance and endurance, which is the skill following on habit, and the ease reached by frequency of right doing.

In the fulfillment of tradition, which represents the nation’s self-governance, there are three stages—first, excellence in how things are done or how one behaves; this is referred to as the style or ethics of actions: second, determination in maintaining this method once it's adopted, allowing it to become a habit in one’s character: i.e., a consistent way of “having” or “acting”; and finally, practice, or moral strength in execution and resilience, which is the expertise that comes from habit and the comfort achieved through regularly doing what is right.

The sensibility of the nation is indicated by the fineness of its customs; its courage, patience, and temperance by its persistence in them.

The character of a nation is shown by the quality of its customs; its bravery, resilience, and self-control are demonstrated by its commitment to them.

By sensibility I mean its natural perception of beauty, fitness, and rightness; or of what is lovely, decent, and just:[Pg 279] faculties dependent much on race, and the primal signs of fine breeding in man; but cultivable also by education, and necessary perishing without it. True education has, indeed, no other function than the development of these faculties, and of the relative will. It has been the great error of modern intelligence to mistake science for education. You do not educate a man by telling him what he knew not, but by making him what he was not.

By sensibility, I mean our natural ability to perceive beauty, appropriateness, and fairness; or what is beautiful, decent, and just: [Pg 279] these abilities depend greatly on one's background and are clear signs of good breeding in people; but they can also be developed through education, which is essential for their survival. True education has, in fact, no other purpose than to enhance these abilities and the related will. A significant mistake of modern thinking is to confuse science with education. You don't educate someone by just telling them things they didn't know, but by transforming them into what they weren't.

And making him what he will remain for ever: for no wash of weeds will bring back the faded purple. And in that dyeing there are two processes—first, the cleansing and wringing out, which is the baptism with water; and then the infusing of the blue and scarlet colours, gentleness and justice, which is the baptism with fire.

And making him what he will always be: because no amount of washing with weeds will restore the faded purple. And in that dyeing, there are two processes—first, the cleaning and wringing out, which is like baptism with water; and then the infusion of blue and scarlet colors, gentleness and justice, which is like baptism with fire.

The customs and manners of a sensitive and highly-trained race are always vital: that is to say, they are orderly manifestations of intense life (like the habitual action of the fingers of a musician). The customs and manners of a vile and rude race, on the contrary, are conditions of decay: they are not, properly speaking, habits, but incrustations; not restraints, or forms, of life; but gangrenes;—noisome, and the beginnings of death. And generally, so far as custom attaches itself to indolence instead of action, and to prejudice instead of perception, it takes this deadly character, so that thus

The customs and behaviors of a sensitive and well-trained society are always essential. In other words, they are structured expressions of vibrant life (like the consistent actions of a musician's fingers). On the other hand, the customs and behaviors of a corrupt and uncivilized society represent decay. They aren't truly habits, but rather layers of buildup; not restraints or forms of life, but infections—harmful and signs of approaching death. Generally, whenever custom is tied to laziness instead of action, and to bias instead of understanding, it adopts this destructive nature, so that thus

"Tradition weighs heavily on us
"Heavy like frost, and deep almost like life."

This power and depth are, however, just what give value to custom, when it works with life, instead of against it.

This power and depth are exactly what give value to custom when it aligns with life, instead of opposing it.

The high ethical training, of a nation being threefold, of body, heart, and practice (compare the statement in the preface to "Unto This Last"), involves exquisiteness in all its perceptions of circumstance,—all its occupations of thought. It implies perfect Grace, Pitifulness, and Peace; it is irreconcilably inconsistent with filthy or mechanical employments,—with the desire of money,—and with mental states of anxiety, jealousy, and indifference to pain. The present insensibility of the upper classes of Europe to the aspects of suffering, uncleanness, and crime, binds them not only into one responsibility with[Pg 280] the sin, but into one dishonour with the foulness, which rot at their thresholds. The crimes daily recorded in the police courts of London and Paris (and much more those which are unrecorded) are a disgrace to the whole body politic;[104] they are, as in the body natural, stains of disease on a face of delicate skin, making the delicacy itself frightful. Similarly, the filth and poverty permitted or ignored in the midst of us are as dishonourable to the whole social body, as in the body natural it is to wash the face, but leave the hands and feet foul. Christ's way is the only true one: begin at the feet; the face will take care of itself. Yet, since necessarily, in the frame of a nation, nothing but the head can be of gold, and the feet, for the work they have to do, must be part of iron, part of clay;—foul or mechanical work is always reduced by a noble race to the minimum in quantity; and, even then, performed and endured, not without sense of degradation, as a fine temper is wounded by the sight of the lower offices of the body. The highest conditions of human society reached hitherto, have cast such work to slaves;—supposing slavery of a politically defined kind to be done away with, mechanical and foul employment must in all highly-organized states take the aspect either of punishment or probation. All criminals should at once be set to the most dangerous and painful forms of it, especially to work in mines and at furnaces,[105] so as to relieve the innocent population as far as possible: of merely rough (not mechanical) manual labour, especially agricultural, a large portion should be done by the upper classes;—bodily health, and sufficient contrast and repose for the mental functions, being unattainable without it; what necessarily inferior labour remains to be done, as especially in manufactures, should, and always will, when the relations of society are reverent and harmonious, fall to the lot of those who, for the time, are fit for nothing better. For as, whatever the perfectness of the educational system, there must remain infinite differences between the natures and capacities of men; and these differing natures are generally rangeable under the two qualities of lordly (or tending towards rule, construction, and harmony) and servile (or tending towards misrule, destruction, and discord); and, since the lordly part is only in a state of profitableness while ruling, and the servile only in a state of redeemableness while serving, the whole health of the state depends on the manifest separation of these two elements of its mind: for, if the servile part be not separated and rendered visible in service, it mixes with and corrupts the entire body of the state; and if the lordly part be not distinguished, and set to rule, it is crushed and lost, being turned to no account, so that the rarest qualities of the nation are all given to it in vain.[106] The effecting of which distinction is the first object, as we shall see presently, of national councils.

The high ethical training of a nation consists of three parts: body, heart, and practice (see the preface to "Unto This Last"). This involves having a refined understanding of circumstances and all kinds of thoughts. It means embodying perfect grace, compassion, and peace, and it is completely incompatible with dirty or mechanical jobs, the pursuit of money, and mental states of anxiety, jealousy, and indifference to pain. The current insensitivity of the upper classes in Europe to suffering, filth, and crime not only ties them to the wrongdoing but also to the disgrace that festers at their doorsteps. The crimes reported daily in the police courts of London and Paris (and even more that go unreported) are a shame for the whole political community; they are like the blemishes of disease on a delicate face, making the delicacy itself horrifying. Similarly, the dirt and poverty that we allow or ignore around us are just as dishonorable to society as it is to wash one's face while leaving hands and feet dirty. Christ's way is the only true path: start with the feet; the face will take care of itself. However, since in a nation, only the head can be made of gold, and the feet, as they do their work, must be part iron and part clay; unclean or menial work is always minimized by a noble society; and, even then, it is done and endured with a sense of degradation, as a sensitive person feels wounded by the sight of the lower functions of the body. The highest states of human society have relegated such work to slaves; assuming that politically defined slavery has been abolished, menial and dirty jobs in all highly organized societies must be seen as either punishment or a chance to improve. All criminals should immediately be assigned to the most dangerous and painful forms of work, especially in mines and at furnaces, to relieve the innocent population as much as possible. A considerable portion of simple (not mechanical) manual labor, especially agricultural work, should be done by the upper classes; since physical well-being and a sufficient contrast for mental relaxation cannot be achieved without it. Any remaining inferior labor, particularly in manufacturing, should, and will always, fall to those who are temporarily suited for nothing better when society is respectful and harmonious. For even with the best educational system, there will always be vast differences between people's natures and abilities; and these different natures can generally be categorized as either lordly (tending towards leadership, creation, and harmony) or servile (tending towards chaos, destruction, and discord). Since the lordly part is only useful when in leadership, and the servile part is redeemable only when in service, the health of the state relies on clearly separating these two aspects of its nature: if the servile part is not separated and shown in its service, it contaminates the entire state; and if the lordly part is not recognized and placed in charge, it is oppressed and wasted, turning its most valuable qualities useless. The establishment of this distinction is the primary goal, as we will see shortly, of national councils.

II.—Laws.

II.—Laws.

These are the definitions and bonds of custom, or, of what the nation desires should become custom.

These are the definitions and connections of tradition, or, of what the nation wants to become tradition.

Law is either archic[107] (of direction), meristic (of division), or critic (of judgment). Archic law is that of appointment and precept: it defines what is and is not to be done. Meristic law is that of balance and distribution: it defines what is and is not to be possessed. Critic law is that of discernment and award: it defines what is and is not to be suffered.

Law is either archic[107] (of direction), meristic (of division), or critic (of judgment). Archic law is about setting rules and guidelines: it defines what should and shouldn’t be done. Meristic law is about balance and distribution: it defines what can and cannot be owned. Critic law is about judgment and evaluation: it defines what can and cannot be tolerated.

If we choose to class the laws of precept and distribution under the general head of "statutes," all law is simply either of statute or judgment; that is, first, the establishment of ordinance, and, secondly, the assignment of the reward or penalty due to its observance or violation.

If we decide to categorize the laws of commands and distribution under the general label of "statutes," then all law is essentially either statutory or based on judgments; that is, first, the creation of rules, and, secondly, the allocation of the reward or punishment that comes from following or breaking them.

[Pg 283]To some extent these two forms of law must be associated, and, with every ordinance, the penalty of disobedience to it be also determined. But since the degrees and guilt of disobedience vary, the determination of due reward and punishment must be modified by discernment of special fact, which is peculiarly the office of the judge, as distinguished from that of the lawgiver and lawsustainer, or king; not but that the two offices are always theoretically and, in early stages, or limited numbers, of society, are often practically, united in the same person or persons.

[Pg 283]To some extent, these two types of law need to be connected, and for every regulation, the consequences of ignoring it should also be defined. However, since the severity and nature of disobedience differ, the determination of appropriate rewards and punishments must take into account specific circumstances, which is primarily the responsibility of the judge, as opposed to that of the lawmaker or the ruler. However, it's important to note that in theory—and often in the early stages or smaller societies—the two roles are frequently combined in the same individual or individuals.

Also, it is necessary to keep clearly in view the distinction between these two kinds of law, because the possible range of law is wider in proportion to their separation. There are many points of conduct respecting which the nation may wisely express its will by a written precept or resolve; yet not enforce it by penalty; and the expedient degree of penalty is always quite a separate consideration from the expedience of the statute, for the statute may often be better enforced by mercy than severity, and is also easier in bearing, and less likely to be abrogated. Farther, laws of precept have reference especially to youth, and concern themselves with training; but laws of judgment to manhood, and concern themselves with remedy and reward. There is a highly curious feeling in the English mind against educational law; we think no man's liberty should be interfered with till he has done irrevocable wrong; whereas it is then just too late for the only gracious and kingly interference, which is to hinder him from doing it. Make your educational laws strict, and your criminal ones may be gentle; but, leave youth its liberty, and you will have to dig dungeons for age. And it is good for a man that he wear the yoke in his youth; for the yoke of youth, if you know how to hold it, may be of silken thread; and there is sweet chime of silver bells at that bridle rein; but, for the captivity of age, you must forge the iron fetter, and cast the passing bell.

Also, it's important to clearly understand the difference between these two types of laws because the potential range of law expands with their separation. There are many aspects of behavior where a nation might wisely express its will through a written rule or resolution; however, it shouldn't enforce it with penalties. The appropriate level of punishment is always a separate issue from the usefulness of the law itself, as a law is often better upheld through mercy rather than harshness. It's also easier to endure and less likely to be overturned. Furthermore, laws of guidance mainly pertain to youth and focus on training, while laws of judgment relate to adulthood and deal with remedies and rewards. There's a peculiar sentiment in the English mindset against educational laws; we believe that a person's freedom shouldn't be interfered with until after they've committed irreversible wrongdoing. But by then, it's too late for the only noble intervention, which is to prevent them from making that mistake. If you establish strict educational laws, your criminal laws can be lenient; however, if you give youth too much freedom, you'll end up having to build prisons for older individuals. It's beneficial for a person to accept some restrictions in their youth; the burden of youth, if managed correctly, can be light and comfortable, accompanied by the sweet sound of silver bells at that reins; but for the bondage of old age, you'll need to create heavy chains and toll the passing bell.

Since no law can be in a final or true sense established, but by right (all unjust laws involving the ultimate necessity of their own abrogation), the law-sustaining power in so far as it is Royal, or "right doing";—in so far, that is, as[Pg 284] it rules, not mis-rules, and orders, not dis-orders, the things submitted to it. Throned on this rock of justice, the kingly power becomes established and establishing, "θεῖος," or divine, and, therefore, it is literally true that no ruler can err, so long as he is a ruler, or ἄρχων οὐδεὶς ἁμαρτάνει τότε ὅταν ἄρχων ᾖ (perverted by careless thought, which has cost the world somewhat, into "the king can do no wrong"). Which is a divine right of kings indeed, and quite unassailable, so long as the terms of it are "God and my Right," and not "Satan and my Wrong," which is apt, in some coinages, to appear on the reverse of the die, under a good lens.

Since no law can truly be established without being just (since all unjust laws must ultimately be repealed), the power of law, as far as it is royal or about "doing what’s right," means that it rules correctly and organizes, rather than misrules and disrupts, the things under its authority. Built on this foundation of justice, royal power becomes established and establishes others, recognized as "divine," and thus, it is accurate to say that no ruler can be wrong as long as they remain a ruler, or ἄρχων οὐδεὶς ἁμαρτάνει τότε ὅταν ἄρχων ᾖ (misinterpreted over time to mean "the king can do no wrong"). This is indeed a divine right of kings and remains utterly unchallengeable, as long as its terms are "God and my Right," not "Satan and my Wrong," which can sometimes, under scrutiny, appear on the opposite side of the coin.

Meristic law, or that of tenure of property, first determines what every individual possesses by right, and secures it to him; and what he possesses by wrong, and deprives him of it. But it has a far higher provisory function: it determines what every man should possess, and puts it within his reach on due conditions; and what he should not possess, and puts this out of his reach conclusively.

Meristic law, or the law of property ownership, first defines what every individual has a right to and protects that right; it also identifies what they have wrongfully acquired and takes it away. However, it has an even more important role: it establishes what each person should own and makes it attainable under certain conditions; conversely, it defines what they should not own and ensures that it remains out of their reach permanently.

Every article of human wealth has certain conditions attached to its merited possession, which, when they are unobserved, possession becomes rapine. The object of meristic law is not only to secure every man his rightful share (the share, that is, which he has worked for, produced, or received by gift from a rightful owner), but to enforce the due conditions of possession, as far as law may conveniently reach; for instance, that land shall not be wantonly allowed to run to waste, that streams shall not be poisoned by the persons through whose properties they pass, nor air be rendered unwholesome beyond given limits. Laws of this kind exist already in rudimentary degree, but needing large development; the just laws respecting the possession of works of art have not hitherto been so much as conceived, and the daily loss of national wealth, and of its use, in this respect, is quite incalculable.[108] While, finally, in certain conditions [Pg 285] of a nation's progress, laws limiting accumulation of property may be found expedient.

Every aspect of human wealth comes with specific conditions for rightful ownership. When these conditions are ignored, possession turns into theft. The purpose of property law is not just to guarantee that everyone gets their fair share—meaning the share they worked for, produced, or received as a gift from a legitimate owner—but also to enforce the necessary conditions for ownership, as much as the law can reasonably manage. For instance, land shouldn't be carelessly left to waste, streams shouldn’t be polluted by those whose properties they flow through, and the air shouldn't be made unhealthy beyond certain limits. Laws of this kind already exist in a basic form, but they need to be significantly developed; just laws regarding the ownership of artworks have yet to be fully formulated, and the daily loss of national wealth and its potential use in this area is immeasurable.[108] Furthermore, during certain phases of a nation's progress, it may be beneficial to impose laws that limit property accumulation.

Critic law determines questions of injury, and assigns due rewards and punishments to conduct.[109]

Critic law addresses issues of harm and assigns appropriate rewards and penalties for actions.[109]

Therefore, in order to true analysis of it, we must understand the real meaning of this word "injury."

Therefore, to properly analyze it, we need to understand the true meaning of the word "injury."

We commonly understand by it any kind of harm done by one man to another; but we do not define the idea of [Pg 286] harm; sometimes we limit it to the harm which the sufferer is conscious of, whereas much the worst injuries are those he is unconscious of; and, at other times, we limit the idea to violence, or restraint, whereas much the worse forms of injury are to be accomplished by carelessness, and the withdrawal of restraint.

We usually think of it as any kind of harm done by one person to another, but we don't really define the concept of [Pg 286] harm. Sometimes we only consider harm that the victim is aware of, even though the most serious injuries are the ones they're not aware of. Other times, we restrict the idea to violence or restraint, while the more harmful injuries often come from negligence and the absence of restraint.

"Injury" is, then, simply the refusal, or violation of any man's right or claim upon his fellows: which claim, much talked of in modern times, under the term "right," is mainly resolvable into two branches: a man's claim not to be hindered from doing what he should; and his claim to be hindered from doing what he should not; these two forms of hindrance being intensified by reward, or help and fortune, or Fors on one side, and punishment, impediment, and even final arrest, or Mors, on the other.

"Injury" is essentially the refusal or violation of any person's rights or claims against others. This concept, often referred to as "rights" today, mainly breaks down into two key areas: a person's right not to be prevented from doing what they should do, and their right to be stopped from doing what they shouldn’t do. These two types of obstacles are heightened by rewards, support, and fortune on one side, and by punishment, hindrance, and even death on the other.

Now, in order to a man's obtaining these two rights, it is clearly needful that the worth of him should be approximately known; as well as the want of worth, which has, unhappily, been usually the principal subject of study for critic law, careful hitherto only to mark degrees of de-merit, instead of merit;—assigning, indeed, to the deficiencies (not always, alas! even to these) just fine, diminution, or (with the broad vowels) damnation; but to the efficiencies, on the other side, which are by much the more interesting, as well as the only profitable part of its subject, assigning in any clear way neither measurement nor aid.

Now, for a man to acquire these two rights, it’s essential that his worth is somewhat understood; along with the lack of worth, which has unfortunately been the main focus of legal criticism, historically concerned only with identifying degrees of demerit instead of merit. It has indeed assigned penalties to deficiencies (not always, sadly, even to these), such as fines, reductions, or (using the broad vowels) damnation; but has failed to clearly measure or support the efficiencies, which are far more interesting and the only truly valuable part of its subject.

Now, it is in this higher and perfect function of critic law, enabling as well as disabling, that it becomes truly kingly or basilican, instead of Draconic (what Providence gave the great, old, wrathful legislator his name?); that is, it becomes the law of man and of life, instead of the law of the worm and of death—both of these laws being set in everlasting poise one against another, and the enforcement of both being the eternal function of the lawgiver, and true claim of every living soul: such claim being indeed as straight and earnest to be mercifully hindered, and even, if need be, abolished, when longer existence means only deeper destruction, as to be mercifully helped and recreated when longer existence and new creation mean nobler life. So that what we vulgarly[Pg 287] term reward and punishment will be found to resolve themselves mainly into help and hindrance, and these again will issue naturally from true recognition of deserving, and the just reverence and just wrath which follow instinctively on such recognition.

Now, it is in this higher and perfect role of law as a critic, enabling as well as disabling, that it truly becomes regal or noble, instead of harsh (what gave the old, wrathful lawgiver his name?); that is, it becomes the law of humanity and life, rather than the law of decay and death—both of these laws existing in eternal balance against each other, and the enforcement of both being the ongoing duty of the lawmaker, and a real claim of every living being: such claim being indeed just as reasonable and serious to be compassionately restrained, and even, if necessary, eliminated, when a longer existence only leads to greater destruction, as it is to be compassionately supported and renewed when a longer existence and new beginnings lead to a greater life. Therefore, what we commonly [Pg 287] call reward and punishment will primarily break down into help and hindrance, which will naturally arise from true acknowledgment of worthiness, and the appropriate respect and justified anger that instinctively follow such acknowledgment.

I say "follow," but in reality they are the recognition. Reverence is but the perceiving of the thing in its entire truth: truth reverted is truth revered (vereor and veritas having clearly the same root), so that Goethe is for once, and for a wonder, wrong in that part of the noble scheme of education in "Wilhelm Meister," in which he says that reverence is not innate, and must be taught. Reverence is as instinctive as anger;—both of them instant on true vision: it is sight and understanding that we have to teach, and these are reverence. Make a man perceive worth, and in its reflection he sees his own relative unworth, and worships thereupon inevitably, not with stiff courtesy, but rejoicingly, passionately, and, best of all, restfully: for the inner capacity of awe and love is infinite in man; and when his eyes are once opened to the sight of beauty and honour, it is with him as with a lover, who, falling at his mistress's feet, would cast himself through the earth, if it might be, to fall lower, and find a deeper and humbler place. And the common insolences and petulances of the people, and their talk of equality, are not irreverence in them in the least, but mere blindness, stupefaction, and fog in the brains,[110] which pass away in the degree that they are raised and purified: the first sign of which raising is, that they gain some power of discerning, and some patience in submitting to their true counsellors and governors; the modes of such discernment forming the real "constitution" of the state, and not the titles or offices of the discerned person; for it is no matter, save in degree of mischief, to what office a man is appointed, if he cannot fulfil it. And this brings us to the third division of our subject.

I say "follow," but really, they are recognition. Reverence is just seeing things in their full truth: when truth is flipped, it's truth revered (with vereor and veritas clearly sharing the same root). So Goethe is, for once, mistaken in that part of the noble education plan in "Wilhelm Meister," where he claims that reverence isn’t innate and needs to be taught. Reverence is as instinctive as anger; both arise from true vision. What we need to teach are sight and understanding, as these are reverence. If you help someone recognize worth, they see their own relative unworthiness in reflection, and they inevitably worship, not with stiff courtesy, but joyfully, passionately, and, best of all, peacefully. The inner capacity for awe and love is infinite in humans; when their eyes are opened to beauty and honor, it's like a lover who, at his mistress's feet, would want to sink through the ground just to find a deeper and humbler place. The common rudeness and impatience of people, and their talk of equality, aren’t irreverence at all, but simple blindness, confusion, and fog in their minds, which fade as they are uplifted and purified. The first sign of this uplift is that they gain some ability to discern and some patience in listening to their true advisors and leaders. The ways of this discernment create the real "constitution" of the state, not the titles or positions of the people being discerned. It doesn't matter much, except in terms of potential harm, what office someone has if they can’t fulfill it. And this brings us to the third part of our topic.

III.—Government by Council.

III.—Council Governance.

This is the determination, by living authority, of the national conduct to be observed under existing circumstances; and the modification or enlargement, abrogation or enforcement, of the code of national law according to present needs or purposes. This government is necessarily always by Council, for though the authority of it may be vested in one person, that person cannot form any opinion on a matter of public interest but by (voluntarily or involuntarily) submitting himself to the influence of others.

This is the decision, made by living authority, about the national behavior to follow under current circumstances; and the changes or expansions, repeal or enforcement, of the national legal code based on present needs or goals. This government always operates through a Council, because even though the authority might be held by one person, that person cannot form an opinion on a public issue without (willingly or unwillingly) being influenced by others.

This government is always twofold—visible and invisible.

This government is always two-sided—seen and unseen.

The visible government is that which nominally carries on the national business; determines its foreign relations, raises taxes, levies soldiers, fights battles, or directs that they be fought, and otherwise becomes the exponent of the national fortune. The invisible government is that exercised by all energetic and intelligent men, each in his sphere, regulating the inner will and secret ways of the people, essentially forming its character, and preparing its fate. Visible governments are the toys of some nations, the diseases of others, the harness of some, the burdens of the more, the necessity of all. Sometimes their career is quite distinct from that of the people, and to write it, as the national history, is as if one should number the accidents which befall a man's weapons and wardrobe, and call the list his biography. Nevertheless a truly noble and wise nation necessarily has a noble and wise visible government, for its wisdom issues in that conclusively. "Not out of the oak, nor out of the rock, but out of the temper of man, is his polity:" where the temper inclines, it inclines as Samson by his pillar, and draws all down with it.

The visible government is the one that officially handles the country's affairs; it manages foreign relations, collects taxes, recruits soldiers, leads battles, or decides how they should be fought, and generally represents the nation's interests. The invisible government is run by all the energetic and intelligent individuals, each in their own field, influencing the inner desires and hidden ways of the people, essentially shaping its character and determining its future. Visible governments can be playthings for some nations, burdens for others, restrictive for some, and essential for all. Sometimes, their actions are completely separate from those of the people, and to document this as national history is like counting the random events that happen to a person's clothes and weapons and calling that their life story. However, a genuinely noble and wise nation will inevitably have a noble and wise visible government since its wisdom manifests through that. "Not from the oak, nor from the rock, but from the character of man comes his government": where the character leans, it falls like Samson pulling down the pillars, bringing everything down with it.

Visible governments are, in their agencies, capable of three pure forms, and of no more than three.

Visible governments have three distinct forms in their agencies, and no more than three.

They are either monarchies, where the authority is vested in one person; oligarchies, when it is vested in a minority; or democracies, when vested in a majority.

They are either monarchies, where power is held by one person; oligarchies, where power is held by a small group; or democracies, where power rests with the majority.

But these three forms are not only, in practice, variously limited and combined, but capable of infinite difference in character and use, receiving specific names according to their[Pg 289] variations; which names, being nowise agreed upon, nor consistently used, either in thought or writing, no man can at present tell, in speaking of any kind of government, whether he is understood, nor in hearing whether he understands. Thus we usually call a just government by one person a monarchy, and an unjust or cruel one, a tyranny; this might be reasonable if it had reference to the divinity of true government; but to limit the term "oligarchy" to government by a few rich people, and to call government by a few wise or noble people "aristocracies," is evidently absurd, unless it were proved that rich people never could be wise, or noble people rich; and farther absurd because there are other distinctions in character, as well as riches or wisdom (greater purity of race, or strength of purpose, for instance), which may give the power of government to the few. So that if we had to give names to every group or kind of minority, we should have verbiage enough. But there is one right name—"oligarchy."

But these three forms are not only limited and combined in different ways in practice, but they also have countless variations in character and use, receiving specific names based on their[Pg 289] differences. These names are not agreed upon or used consistently, either in thought or writing, so no one can clearly tell, when discussing any type of government, whether they are understood, nor can they be sure if they understand what they hear. Generally, we call a fair government led by one person a monarchy, and an unfair or cruel one a tyranny; this might make sense if it related to the ideal of true government. However, limiting the term "oligarchy" to mean government by a few wealthy people and labeling government led by a few wise or noble individuals as "aristocracy" is clearly unreasonable, unless it can be proven that wealthy people can’t be wise, or noble people can’t be rich. Moreover, it's absurd because there are other distinguishing factors, beyond wealth or wisdom (like greater purity of race or strength of purpose, for instance), that could also grant power to a few. So, if we had to name every group or type of minority, we would have more than enough terminology. But there is one accurate name—"oligarchy."

So also the terms "republic" and "democracy" are confused, especially in modern use; and both of them are liable to every sort of misconception. A republic means, properly, a polity in which the state, with its all, is at every man's service, and every man, with his all, at the state's service (people are apt to lose sight of the last condition); but its government may nevertheless be oligarchic (consular, or decemviral, for instance), or monarchic (dictatorial). But a democracy means a state in which the government rests directly with the majority of the citizens. And both these conditions have been judged only by such accidents and aspects of them as each of us has had experience of; and sometimes both have been confused with anarchy, as it is the fashion at present to talk of the "failure of republican institutions in America," when there has never yet been in America any such thing as an institution; neither any such thing as a res-publica, but only a multitudinous res-privata; every man for himself. It is not republicanism which fails now in America; it is your model science of political economy, brought to its perfect practice. There you may see competition, and the "law of demand and supply" (especially in paper), in beautiful and[Pg 290] unhindered operation.[111] Lust of wealth, and trust in it; vulgar faith in magnitude and multitude, instead of nobleness; besides that faith natural to backwoodsmen,—"lucum ligna,"—perpetual self-contemplation, issuing in passionate vanity: total ignorance of the finer and higher arts, and of all that they teach and bestow;[112] and the discontent of energetic minds unoccupied, frantic with hope of uncomprehended change, and progress they know not whither;[113] these are the things that they have "failed" with in America; and yet not altogether failed—it is not collapse, but collision; the greatest railroad accident on record, with fire caught from the furnace, and Catiline's quenching "non aquá, sed ruinâ." But I see not, in any of our talk of them, justice enough done to their erratic strength of purpose, nor any estimate taken of the strength of endurance of domestic sorrow in what their women and children suppose a righteous cause. And out of that endurance and suffering, its own fruit will be born with time; and Carlyle's prophecy of them (June, 1850), as it has now come true in the first clause, will in the last.

The terms "republic" and "democracy" are often mixed up today, and both can be misleading. A republic is, in essence, a system where the state is there to serve everyone, and everyone is there to serve the state (people often overlook the second part). However, its government can be oligarchic (like a consular or decemviral system) or monarchic (like a dictatorship). On the other hand, a democracy is where the government is run directly by the majority of its citizens. Both concepts have been judged based on individual experiences, and sometimes they are confused with anarchy. These days, people talk about the "failure of republican institutions in America," but there has never really been any true institution in America; it's more about many individual interests than a collective public good—everyone for themselves. It isn't republicanism that is failing in America; it's your so-called science of political economy being executed perfectly. You can see competition and the "law of demand and supply" (especially in paper), operating freely and beautifully. The desire for wealth, reliance on it; a superficial belief in size and quantity over quality; combined with the natural beliefs of frontiersmen—"lucum ligna"—constant self-focus leading to vanity; complete ignorance of the finer arts and what they offer; and the restlessness of ambitious minds feeling frustrated and hopeful for change they can't quite grasp—these are the things that represent their "failure" in America. Yet, it isn't a total failure—it’s more of a collision than a collapse; the most significant railroad accident ever recorded, ignited by a furnace fire, with Catiline's response being, "not with water, but with ruin." However, I don't see enough acknowledgment of their unpredictable determination or the strength of the domestic suffering that their women and children associate with a just cause. Out of that endurance and struggle, something will eventually emerge; and Carlyle's prophecy about them (June, 1850), which has already come true in part, will in the end.

America too will find that caucuses, division-lists, stump-oratory and speeches to Buncombe will not carry men to the immortal gods; that the Washington Congress, and constitutional battle of Kilkenny cats is, there as here, naught for such objects; [Pg 291] quite incompetent for such; and, in fine, that said sublime constitutional arrangement will require to be (with terrible throes, and travail such as few expect yet) remodelled, abridged, extended, suppressed; torn asunder, put together again;—not without heroic labour, and effort quite other than that of the Stump-Orator and the Revival Preacher, one day!

America will also realize that caucuses, division lists, campaign speeches, and all that empty talk won't take people to greatness; that the Washington Congress and the pointless constitutional struggles are, as they are here, useless for such aims; [Pg 291] completely unfit for this purpose; and, ultimately, that this impressive constitutional setup will need to be (with great upheaval, and challenges that few anticipate) restructured, shortened, expanded, or even dismantled; ripped apart and then reassembled—certainly not without significant effort and hard work that’s quite different from what the campaign speechmaker and the revival preacher offer!

Understand, then, once for all, that no form of government, provided it be a government at all, is, as such, either to be condemned or praised, or contested for in anywise but by fools. But all forms of government are good just so far as they attain this one vital necessity of policy—that the wise and kind, few or many, shall govern the unwise and unkind; and they are evil so far as they miss of this or reverse it. Nor does the form in any case signify one whit, but its firmness and adaptation to the need; for if there be many foolish persons in a state, and few wise, then it is good that the few govern; and if there be many wise and few foolish, then it is good that many govern; and if many be wise, yet one wiser, then it is good that one should govern; and so on. Thus, we may have "the ants' republic, and the realm of bees," both good in their kind; one for groping, and the other for building; and nobler still, for flying, the Ducal monarchy of those

Understand, then, once and for all, that no form of government, as long as it is a government at all, should be condemned, praised, or argued over by anyone but fools. All forms of government are good to the extent that they achieve this essential policy requirement—namely, that the wise and kind, whether few or many, should govern the unwise and unkind; and they are bad to the degree that they fail to achieve this or turn it upside down. The form itself doesn't matter at all; what really counts is its stability and how well it meets the needs at hand. If there are many foolish people in a society and few wise ones, then it’s best for the few to govern. If there are many wise people and only a few foolish ones, then it’s better for the many to govern. And if there are many wise individuals but one person is wiser than the rest, then it's best for that one to lead. Therefore, we can have "the ants' republic and the realm of bees," both good in their own ways; one for searching and the other for building; and even greater, for flying, the Ducal monarchy of those

"Smart about the seasons, that brings forth
The airy caravan, high above the seas.

Nor need we want examples, among the inferior creatures, of dissoluteness, as well as resoluteness in, government. I once saw democracy finely illustrated by the beetles of North Switzerland, who, by universal suffrage, and elytric acclamation, one May twilight, carried it that they would fly over the Lake of Zug; and flew short, to the great disfigurement of the Lake of Zug—"Κανθάρου λιμήν—over some leagues square, and to the close of the Cockchafer democracy for that year. The old fable of the frogs and the stork finely touches one form of tyranny; but truth will touch it more nearly than fable, for tyranny is not complete when it is only over the idle, but when it is over the laborious and the blind. This description of pelicans and climbing perch which I find quoted in one of our popular natural histories, out of Sir Emerson[Pg 292] Tennent's "Ceylon," comes as near as may be to the true image of the thing:—

Nor do we lack examples, among lesser creatures, of both reckless and determined governance. I once saw democracy perfectly displayed by the beetles of North Switzerland, who, through universal suffrage and enthusiastic cheers, decided one May evening that they would fly over Lake Zug; and they flew just a short distance, greatly marring the beauty of Lake Zug—"Κανθάρου λιμήν—over several leagues, marking the end of that year's Cockchafer democracy. The old fable of the frogs and the stork illustrates one type of tyranny well; however, the truth addresses it more closely, for tyranny isn't complete when it only affects the lazy, but also when it encompasses the hardworking and the oblivious. This description of pelicans and climbing perch, which I found quoted in one of our popular natural histories from Sir Emerson[Pg 292] Tennent's "Ceylon," comes as close as possible to accurately representing the concept:—

Heavy rains came on, and as we stood on the high ground, we observed a pelican on the margin of the shallow pool gorging himself; our people went towards him, and raised a cry of "Fish! fish!" We hurried down, and found numbers of fish struggling upward through the grass, in the rills formed by the trickling of the rain. There was scarcely water to cover them, but nevertheless they made rapid progress up the bank, on which our followers collected about two baskets of them. They were forcing their way up the knoll, and had they not been interrupted, first by the pelican, and afterwards by ourselves, they would in a few minutes have gained the highest point, and descended on the other side into a pool which formed another portion of the tank. In going this distance, however, they must have used muscular exertion enough to have taken them half a mile on level ground; for at these places all the cattle and wild animals of the neighbourhood had latterly come to drink, so that the surface was everywhere indented with footmarks, in addition to the cracks in the surrounding baked mud, into which the fish tumbled in their progress. In those holes which were deep, and the sides perpendicular, they remained to die, and were carried off by kites and crows.

Heavy rains started pouring down, and as we stood on higher ground, we spotted a pelican by the edge of a shallow pool feeding hungrily. Our group moved toward him, shouting, "Fish! Fish!" We rushed down and discovered lots of fish trying to swim upward through the grass in the little streams formed by the rain. There was hardly enough water to cover them, but they were quickly making their way up the bank, where our followers collected about two baskets of them. They were pushing their way up the hill, and if they hadn't been interrupted first by the pelican and then by us, they would have reached the top in just a few minutes and gone down into a pool that was part of the reservoir. However, to cover that distance, they must have exerted enough energy to have traveled half a mile on flat ground; since in those spots, all the local cattle and wild animals had recently come to drink, leaving the surface marked with footprints, along with cracks in the hardened mud where the fish fell as they moved. In the deeper holes with steep sides, they ended up dying, and then they were taken away by kites and crows.

But whether governments be bad or good, one general disadvantage seems to attach to them in modern times—that they are all costly. This, however, is not essentially the fault of the governments. If nations choose to play at war, they will always find their governments willing to lead the game, and soon coming under that term of Aristophanes, "κάπηλοι ἀσπίδων," shield-sellers. And when (πῆμ’ ἐπὶπήματι) the shields take the form of iron ships, with apparatus "for defence against liquid fire"—as I see by latest accounts they are now arranging the decks in English dockyards,—they become costly biers enough for the grey convoy of chief-mourner waves, wreathed with funereal foam, to bear back the dead upon; the massy shoulders of those corpse-bearers being intended for quite other work, and to bear the living, if we would let them.

But whether governments are good or bad, one common drawback seems to apply to them these days—they're all expensive. However, this isn't entirely the fault of the governments. If countries decide to engage in war, they'll always find their governments ready to lead the charge, soon fitting the description of Aristophanes, "κάπηλοι ἀσπίδων," shield-sellers. And when (πῆμ’ ἐπὶπήματι) the shields turn into iron ships, equipped "for protection against liquid fire"—as I hear they're currently setting up in English shipyards—they become heavy coffins to carry back the dead on the grey waves, crowned with mournful foam; the sturdy shoulders of those corpse-bearers are meant for much better things, to support the living, if we just let them.

Nor have we the least right to complain of our governments being expensive so long as we set the government to do precisely the work which brings no return. If our present doctrines of political economy be just, let us trust them to[Pg 293] the utmost; take that war business out of the government's hands, and test therein the principles of supply and demand. Let our future sieges of Sebastopol be done by contract—no capture, no pay—(I am prepared to admit that things might go better so); and let us sell the commands of our prospective battles, with our vicarages, to the lowest bidder; so may we have cheap victories and divinity. On the other hand, if we have so much suspicion of our science that we dare not trust it on military or spiritual business, it would be but reasonable to try whether some authoritative handling may not prosper in matters utilitarian. If we were to set our governments to do useful things instead of mischievous, possibly even the apparatus might in time come to be less costly! The machine, applied to the building of the house, might perhaps pay, when it seems not to pay, applied to pulling it down. If we made in our dockyards ships to carry timber and coals, instead of cannon, and with provision for brightening of domestic solid culinary fire, instead of for the averting of hostile liquid fire, it might have some effect on the taxes? Or if the iron bottoms were to bring us home nothing better than ivory and peacocks, instead of martial glory, we might at least have gayer suppers, and doors of the right material for dreams after them. Or suppose that we tried the experiment on land instead of water carriage; already the government, not unapproved, carries letters and parcels for us; larger packages may in time follow:—parcels;—even general merchandise? Why not, at last, ourselves? Had the money spent in local mistakes and vain private litigation, on the railroads of England, been laid out, instead, under proper government restraint, on really useful railroad work, and had no absurd expense been incurred in ornamenting stations, we might already have had,—what ultimately will be found we must have,—quadruple rails, two for passengers, and two for traffic, on every great line; and we might have been carried in swift safety, and watched and warded by well-paid pointsmen, for half the present fares. "ὧ Δημίδιον, ὁρᾁς τὰ λαγῳ’ ἅ σοι φέρω?" Suppose it should turn out, finally, that a true government set to true work, instead of being a costly engine, was a paying one? that your government, rightly organized, instead [Pg 294] of itself subsisting by an income tax, would produce its subjects some subsistence in the shape of an income dividend!—police and judges duly paid besides, only with less work than the state at present provides for them.

We have no right to complain about our government being expensive as long as we give it tasks that bring no return. If our current ideas about political economy are correct, let's trust them to the fullest; take military matters out of the government's hands and test the principles of supply and demand. Let future sieges of places like Sebastopol be contracted out—no capture, no pay—(I could agree that things might improve that way); and let's auction off the command of our future battles along with our church positions to the lowest bidder; that way we could have cheaper victories and divine results. On the other hand, if we don’t trust our economic principles enough to apply them to military or spiritual matters, it would only make sense to see if some kind of authoritative approach might work better for practical matters. If we tasked our governments with useful jobs instead of harmful ones, maybe the overall expenses would eventually be lower! A machine used for building could turn out to be more beneficial, rather than being used for destruction. If we made ships in our docks to transport timber and coal instead of cannons, and designed them to ensure a cozy, warm fire at home instead of to defend against enemy fire, wouldn’t that affect taxes? Or if those iron ships brought back nothing but ivory and peacocks instead of military honor, at least our dinners would be livelier, and we'd have the right materials for pleasant dreams afterwards. Or consider trying this on land instead of by water; the government already manages to deliver letters and parcels for us (not without some approval); larger packages might follow:—parcels;—even general merchandise? Why not eventually ourselves? Imagine if the money wasted on local failures and pointless private lawsuits concerning the railroads in England had been used, instead, under proper government oversight, on genuinely beneficial railway projects, and if we hadn’t wasted money on fancy train stations, we might already have what we ultimately need—four tracks, two for passengers and two for freight—on every major line; and we could travel swiftly and safely, overseen by well-paid staff, for half the current fares. "ὧ Δημίδιον, ὁρᾁς τὰ λαγῳ’ ἅ σοι φέρω?" What if it turns out that a true government set to do real work, instead of being a costly machine, actually generates profit? That your government, when organized properly, instead of relying on income taxes, could provide its citizens with some income in the form of dividends!—with police and judges being paid too, while doing less work than what the state currently assigns them.

A true government set to true work!—Not easily imagined, still less obtained, but not beyond human hope or ingenuity. Only you will have to alter your election systems somewhat, first. Not by universal suffrage, nor by votes purchasable with beer, is such government to be had. That is to say, not by universal equal suffrage. Every man upwards of twenty, who had been convicted of no legal crime, should have his say in this matter; but afterwards a louder voice, as he grows older, and approves himself wiser. If he has one vote at twenty, he should have two at thirty, four at forty, and ten at fifty. For every one vote which he has with an income of a hundred a year, he should have ten with an income of a thousand (provided you first see to it that wealth is, as nature intended it to be, the reward of sagacity and industry,—not of good luck in a scramble or a lottery.) For every one vote which he had as subordinate in any business, he should have two when he became a master; and every office and authority nationally bestowed, inferring trustworthiness and intellect, should have its known proportional number of votes attached to it. But into the detail and working of a true system in these matters we cannot now enter; we are concerned as yet with definitions only, and statements of first principles, which will be established now sufficiently for our purposes when we have examined the nature of that form of government last on the list in the previous paper,—the purely "Magistral," exciting at present its full share of public notice, under its ambiguous title of "slavery."

A real government focused on actual work!—It’s hard to picture, even harder to achieve, but it’s not out of reach for human hope or creativity. You just need to tweak your voting systems a bit, first. Not through universal voting rights or votes bought with drinks, can such a government be formed. In other words, not through universally equal voting rights. Every man over twenty who hasn’t been convicted of a crime should have a say in this; but as he gets older and proves himself wiser, his voice should carry more weight. If he has one vote at twenty, he should get two at thirty, four at forty, and ten at fifty. For every vote he has with an income of a hundred a year, he should have ten with an income of a thousand (provided you ensure that wealth is, as nature intended, the reward for wisdom and hard work—not just luck in a scramble or a lottery). For every vote he has as an employee, he should get two when he becomes a boss; and every position of trust and authority granted nationally, implying reliability and intelligence, should come with a specific number of votes attached. But we can't dive into the details and functioning of a rightful system just yet; we are still focused on definitions and fundamental principles, which will be adequately established for our needs as we examine the nature of the last form of government mentioned in the previous paper—the purely "Magistral," which is currently drawing significant public attention under its misleading label of "slavery."

I have not, however, been able to ascertain in definite terms, from the declaimers against slavery, what they understand by it. If they mean only the imprisonment or compulsion being in many cases highly expedient, slavery, so defined, would be no evil in itself, but only in its abuse; that is, when men are slaves, who should not be, or masters, who should not be, or under conditions which should not be. It is not, for instance, a necessary condition of slavery,[Pg 295] nor a desirable one, that parents should be separated from children, or husbands from wives; but the institution of war, against which people declaim with less violence, effects such separations—not unfrequently in a higher permanent manner. To press a sailor, seize a white youth by conscription for a soldier, or carry off a black one for a labourer, may all be right, or all wrong, according to needs and circumstances. It is wrong to scourge a man unnecessarily. So it is to shoot him. Both must be done on occasion; and it is better and kinder to flog a man to his work, than to leave him idle till he robs, and flog him afterwards. The essential thing for all creatures is to be made to do right; how they are made to do it—by pleasant promises, or hard necessities, pathetic oratory, or the whip, is comparatively immaterial. To be deceived is perhaps as incompatible with human dignity as to be whipped, and I suspect the last instrument to be not the worst, for the help of many individuals. The Jewish nation throve under it, in the hand of a monarch reputed not unwise; it is only the change of whip for scorpion which is expedient, and yet that change is as likely to come to pass on the side of licence as of law; for the true scorpion whips are those of the nation's pleasant vices, which are to it as St. John's locusts—crown on the head, ravin in the mouth, and sting in the tail. If it will not bear the rule of Athena and her brother, who shepherd without smiting (οὐ πληγῇ νέμοντες), Athena at last calls no more in the corners of the streets; and then follows the rule of Tisiphone, who smites without shepherding.

I still haven't been able to clearly understand what those who criticize slavery mean by it. If they only refer to imprisonment or coercion, which can sometimes be very necessary, then slavery, as defined that way, isn't inherently evil; it's only problematic when abused. That is, it becomes an issue when people are enslaved who shouldn't be or when there are masters who shouldn't be in that role, or when conditions are unjust. For example, it's not a necessary or desirable aspect of slavery that parents must be separated from their children or husbands from wives. However, war—against which people speak less passionately—often causes such separations, often in a more permanent way. Forcing a sailor into service, drafting a young man as a soldier, or taking a Black person for labor can all be right or wrong depending on the needs and circumstances. It's wrong to beat someone unnecessarily, just as it is wrong to shoot him. Both actions may sometimes be required, and it's better and kinder to make someone work through punishment than to leave him idle until he commits theft and then punish him afterward. The most important thing for all beings is to be encouraged to do what's right; how they are motivated—through pleasant promises, harsh necessities, emotional speeches, or punishment—is relatively unimportant. Being deceived might be just as damaging to human dignity as being beaten, and I suspect the latter might even be less harmful for some individuals. The Jewish nation prospered under such conditions, in the hands of a reputedly wise king; the real challenge is changing the method of punishment from a whip to a scorpion. And this change can happen just as easily through lawlessness as through legislation; the true "scorpion whips" are often the nation's tempting vices, which are like St. John's locusts—bringing a crown on the head, destruction in the mouth, and a sting in the tail. If a society can't accept the rule of Athena and her brother, who guide without punishment, Athena will eventually stop calling out in the streets. Then the rule of Tisiphone, who punishes without guidance, will take over.

If, however, slavery, instead of absolute compulsion, is meant the purchase, by money, of the right of compulsion, such purchase is necessarily made whenever a portion of any territory is transferred, for money, from one monarch to another: which has happened frequently enough in history, without its being supposed that the inhabitants of the districts so transferred became their slaves. In this, as in the former case, the dispute seems about the fashion of the thing rather than the fact of it. There are two rocks in mid-sea, on each of which, neglected equally by instructive and commercial powers, a handful of inhabitants live as they may. Two[Pg 296] merchants bid for the two properties, but not in the same terms. One bids for the people, buys them, and sets them to work, under pain of scourge; the other bids for the rock, buys it, and throws the inhabitants into the sea. The former is the American, the latter the English method, of slavery; much is to be said for, and something against, both, which I hope to say in due time and place.

If, however, slavery is interpreted not as complete coercion but as the purchase of the right to coerce through money, then that purchase happens every time a part of any territory is bought and sold from one ruler to another. This has occurred frequently throughout history without anyone thinking that the residents of those transferred areas became slaves. In both cases, the argument seems to focus more on the way it's done rather than the reality of it. There are two rocky islands in the sea, where a small group of people live, neglected by both educational and commercial powers. Two[Pg 296] merchants compete for the two properties, but not in the same way. One bids for the people, buys them, and forces them to work under threat of punishment; the other bids for the rock, buys it, and tosses the residents into the sea. The first approach is the American style of slavery, while the second represents the English method. There's a lot to discuss both for and against each, which I plan to address in due time.

If, however, slavery mean not merely the purchase of the right of compulsion, but the purchase of the body and soul of the creature itself for money, it is not, I think, among the black races that purchases of this kind are most extensively made, or that separate souls of a fine make fetch the highest price. This branch of the inquiry we shall have occasion also to follow out at some length; for in the worst instance of the "Βίων πρᾶσις" we are apt to get only Pyrrhon's answer—τί φῆς;—ἐπριάμην σε; Ἄδηλον.

If, however, slavery means not just the buying of the right to force someone to do something, but the buying of a person's body and soul for money, then I don’t think it’s among the black races that such purchases are most commonly made, or that unique souls command the highest price. We’ll also explore this aspect in detail later; because in the worst case of the "Βίων πρᾶσις", we often only get Pyrrho's response—τί φῆς;—ἐπριάμην σε; Ἄδηλον.

The fact is that slavery is not a political institution at all, but an inherent, natural, and eternal inheritance of a large portion of the human race—to whom the more you give of their own will, the more slaves they will make themselves. In common parlance, we idly confuse captivity with slavery, and are always thinking of the difference between pine-trunks and cowslip bells, or between carrying wood and clothes-stealing, instead of noting the far more serious differences between Ariel and Caliban, and the means by which practically that difference may be brought about.[114]

The truth is that slavery isn't a political system at all; it's an inherent, natural, and lasting part of a large segment of humanity—where the more freedom you give them, the more they will enslave themselves. In everyday language, we lazily mix up captivity with slavery, and we often focus on trivial differences, like between tree trunks and cowslip flowers, or between hauling wood and stealing clothes, instead of recognizing the much more significant differences between Ariel and Caliban, and how that distinction can be practically achieved.[114]

[Pg 297]I should dwell, even in these prefatory papers, at somewhat more length on this matter, had not all I would say, been said (already in vain) by Carlyle, in the first of the "Latter-Day Pamphlets," which I commend to the reader's gravest reading: [Pg 298] together with that as much neglected, and still more immediately needed, on model prisons, and with the great chapter on "Permanence" (fifth of the last section of "Past and Present"), which sums, what is known, and foreshadows,—or rather fore-lights, all that is to be learned, of National Discipline. I have only here farther to examine the nature of one world-wide and everlasting form of slavery, wholesome in use, deadly in abuse—the service of the rich by the poor.

[Pg 297]I should elaborate, even in these introductory sections, a bit more on this topic, except that everything I would like to say has already been expressed (albeit in vain) by Carlyle in the first of the "Latter-Day Pamphlets," which I urge the reader to seriously consider: [Pg 298] along with the much overlooked, and even more urgently needed, discussion on model prisons, and the important chapter on "Permanence" (the fifth chapter of the last section of "Past and Present"), which summarizes what is known and suggests—or rather highlights—all that can be learned about National Discipline. I only need to further analyze the nature of one universal and timeless kind of slavery, beneficial when used properly, but harmful when abused—the service of the wealthy by the less fortunate.

As in all previous discussions of our subject, we must study this relation in its simplest elements in order to reach its first principles. The simplest state of it is, then, this:[115] a wise [Pg 299] and provident person works much, consumes little, and lays by store; an improvident person works little, consumes all the produce, and lays by no store. Accident interrupts the daily work, or renders it less productive; the idle person must then starve, or be supported by the provident one,—who, having him thus at his mercy, may either refuse to maintain him altogether, or, which will evidently be more to his own interest, say to him, "I will maintain you, indeed, but you shall now work hard, instead of indolently, and instead of being allowed to lay by what you save, as you might have done, had you remained independent, I will take all the surplus. You would not lay it up yourself; it is wholly your own fault that has thrown you into my power, and I will force you to work, or starve; yet you shall have no profit, only your daily bread." This mode of treatment has now become so universal that it is supposed the only natural—nay, the only possible one; and the market wages are calmly defined by economists as "the sum which will maintain the labourer."

As in all previous discussions about our topic, we need to examine this relationship in its simplest terms to understand its basic principles. The simplest form is this:[115] a wise and prepared person works a lot, uses little, and saves some; an unprepared person works little, spends everything they earn, and saves nothing. Accidents can disrupt daily work or make it less effective; then, the idle person must either go hungry or be supported by the prepared one—who, having this power over them, may choose either to refuse support altogether or, more beneficial for themselves, say, "I will support you, but you need to work hard now instead of being lazy, and instead of being allowed to save what you earn, which you could have done if you had stayed independent, I will take all the extra. You wouldn't have saved it yourself; it's entirely your fault for putting yourself in this position, and I will make you work or let you starve; yet you will only get your basic needs, nothing more." This way of treating people has become so common that it is thought of as the only natural—indeed, the only possible way; and market wages are calmly defined by economists as "the amount needed to support the laborer."

The power of the provident person to do this is only checked by the correlative power of some neighbour of similarly frugal habits, who says to the labourer—"I will give you a little more than my provident friend:—come and work for me." The power of the provident over the improvident depends thus primarily on their relative numbers; secondarily, on the modes of agreement of the adverse parties with each other. The level of wages is a variable function of the number of provident and idle persons in the world, of the enmity between them as classes, and of the agreement between those of the same class. It depends, from beginning to end, on moral conditions.

The ability of a careful person to do this is only limited by the corresponding ability of a neighbor with similar savings habits, who tells the worker, “I’ll pay you a little more than my careful friend—come work for me.” The influence of the careful over the careless primarily relies on their relative numbers; secondarily, it depends on how the opposing parties agree with each other. The level of wages is a variable factor influenced by the number of careful and lazy individuals in the world, the hostility between these two groups as classes, and the agreements within the same class. It all boils down to moral conditions.

Supposing the rich to be entirely selfish, it is always for their interest that the poor should be as numerous as they can employ and restrain. For, granting the entire population no larger than the ground can easily maintain,—that the classes are stringently divided,—and that there is sense or strength of hand enough with the rich to secure obedience; then, if nine-tenths of a nation are poor, the remaining tenth have the[Pg 300] service of nine persons each;[116] but, if eight-tenths are poor, only of four each; if seven-tenths are poor, of two and a third each; but, practically if the rich strive always to obtain more power over the poor, instead of to raise them,—and if, on the other hand, the poor become continually more vicious and numerous, through neglect and oppression—though the range of the power of the rich increases, its tenure becomes less secure; until, at last, the measure of iniquity being full, revolution, civil war, or the subjection of the state to a healthier or stronger one, closes the moral corruption and industrial disease.

Assuming that the wealthy are completely selfish, it benefits them for the poor to be as numerous as they can manage and control. If we consider a population that doesn’t exceed what the land can easily support—a situation where classes are sharply divided—and the rich have enough power or influence to enforce obedience; then, if nine-tenths of a nation are poor, the remaining tenth have the[Pg 300] service of nine individuals each;[116] but if eight-tenths are poor, they only have four to serve each; if seven-tenths are poor, then just over two each. However, if the rich consistently seek to gain more control over the poor instead of helping to uplift them—and, at the same time, if the poor grow increasingly depraved and numerous due to neglect and oppression—even though the wealthy’s power may widen, its stability becomes less secure; until eventually, when the levels of wrongdoing reach their peak, revolution, civil war, or the subjugation of the state by a healthier or stronger one brings an end to both moral decay and economic illness.

It is rare, however, that things come to this extremity. Kind persons among the rich, and wise among the poor, modify the connexion of the classes: the efforts made to raise and relieve on the one side, and the success and honest toil on the other, bind and blend the orders of society into the confused tissue of half-felt obligation, sullenly-rendered obedience, and variously-directed, or mis-directed, toil, which form the warp of daily life. But this great law rules all the wild design of the weaving; that success (while society is guided by laws of competition) signifies always so much victory over your neighbour as to obtain the direction of his work, and to take the profits of it. This is the real source of all great riches. No man can become largely rich by his personal toil.[117] The work of his own hands, wisely directed, will indeed always maintain himself and his family, and make fitting provision for his age. But it is only by the discovery of some method of taxing the labour of others that he can become opulent. Every increase of his capital enables him to extend this taxation more widely; that is, to invest larger funds in the maintenance [Pg 301] of his labourers—to direct, accordingly, vaster and yet vaster masses of labour; and to appropriate its profits. There is much confusion of idea on the subject of this appropriation. It is, of course, the interest of the employer to disguise it from the persons employed; and for his own comfort and complacency he often desires no less to disguise it from himself. And it is matter of much doubt with me, how far the foolish arguments used habitually on this subject are indeed the honest expressions of foolish convictions,—or rather (as I am sometimes forced to conclude from the irritation with which they are advanced) are resolutely dishonest, wilful sophisms, arranged so as to mask to the last moment the real state of economy, and future duties of men. By taking a simple example, and working it thoroughly out, the subject may be rescued from all but determined misconception.

It's rare for things to get this extreme. Kind people among the rich and wise individuals among the poor help change the connection between classes: the efforts to uplift and support on one side, along with the success and honest work on the other, intertwine social orders into a tangled web of half-felt obligation, grudging obedience, and variously directed—or misdirected—labor, which make up the fabric of daily life. But this fundamental rule governs the chaotic design of the weaving: success (while society operates under competitive laws) always means gaining some victory over your neighbor, allowing you to control their work and take the profits from it. This is the true source of all great wealth. No one can become very wealthy solely through their own labor. The work of their own hands, when directed wisely, can certainly support themselves and their family and provide adequately for their old age. However, it's only by figuring out how to benefit from the labor of others that they can become wealthy. Each increase in their capital allows them to extend this benefit further; that is, to invest more money in the support of their workers—to manage larger and larger groups of labor; and to claim the profits. There's a lot of confusion regarding this appropriation. Naturally, it's in the employer's interest to hide this from the employees; and for their own comfort and peace of mind, they often prefer to obscure it from themselves as well. I'm quite uncertain about how far the foolish arguments typically used on this topic are truly honest expressions of misguided beliefs—or instead (as I sometimes conclude from the irritation with which they are presented) are intentionally deceptive, willful fallacies designed to conceal the real economic situation and the future responsibilities of individuals. By taking a straightforward example and fully exploring it, we can clarify the subject from all but willful misunderstandings.

Let us imagine a society of peasants, living on a river-shore, exposed to destructive inundation at somewhat extended intervals; and that each peasant possesses of this good, but imperilled ground, more than he needs to cultivate for immediate subsistence. We will assume farther (and with too great probability of justice) that the greater part of them indolently keep in tillage just as much land as supplies them with daily food;—that they leave their children idle and untaught; and take no precautions against the rise of the stream. But one of them (we will say only one, for the sake of greater clearness) cultivates carefully all the ground of his estate; makes his children work hard and healthily; uses his spare time and theirs in building a rampart against the river; and at the end of some years has in his storehouses large reserves of food and clothing, and in his stables a well-tended breed of cattle.

Let’s picture a community of farmers living by a riverbank, facing dangerous floods every now and then. Each farmer has more land than they need to grow enough food for themselves. We can also assume (and it’s probably accurate) that most of them lazily farm only what gives them their daily meals; they let their kids be idle and uneducated, and they don’t do anything to prepare for the river’s rising waters. But one of them (let's say just one for clarity) works hard to cultivate all his land; he makes sure his kids are busy and healthy; he uses his extra time and theirs to build a barrier against the river. After several years, he has plenty of food and clothing stored away and well-cared-for livestock in his barn.

The torrent rises at last—sweeps away the harvests and many of the cottages of the careless peasantry, and leaves them destitute. They naturally come for help to the provident one, whose fields are unwasted and whose granaries are full. He has the right to refuse it them; no one disputes his right. But he will probably not refuse it; it is not his interest to do so, even were he entirely selfish and cruel. The only question with him will be on what terms his aid is to be granted.[Pg 302]

The flood finally comes—washes away the crops and many homes of the careless farmers, leaving them in need. They naturally turn to the one who planned ahead, whose fields are untouched and whose grain stores are full. He has every right to deny them help; no one argues with that. But he’s likely to provide assistance; it wouldn’t benefit him to do otherwise, even if he were completely selfish and cruel. The only thing he’ll consider is under what conditions he'll offer his support.[Pg 302]

Clearly not on terms of mere charity. To maintain his neighbours in idleness would be his ruin and theirs. He will require work from them in exchange for their maintenance; and whether in kindness or cruelty, all the work they can give. Not now the three or four hours they were wont to spend on their own land, but the eight or ten hours they ought to have spent. But how will he apply this labour? The men are now his slaves—nothing less. On pain of starvation, he can force them to work in the manner and to the end he chooses. And it is by his wisdom in this choice that the worthiness of his mastership is proved, or its unworthiness. Evidently he must first set them to bank out the water in some temporary way, and to get their ground cleansed and resown; else, in any case, their continued maintenance will be impossible. That done, and while he has still to feed them, suppose he makes them raise a secure rampart for their own ground against all future flood, and rebuild their houses in safer places, with the best material they can find; being allowed time out of their working hours to fetch such material from a distance. And for the food and clothing advanced, he takes security in land that as much shall be returned at a convenient period.

Clearly not just out of charity. Keeping his neighbors idle would ruin both him and them. He’ll expect them to work in exchange for their support, and whether it's out of kindness or harshness, he’ll demand all the work they can give. Not the three or four hours they used to spend on their own land, but the eight or ten hours they actually should have put in. But how will he use this labor? The men are now his slaves—nothing less. Under threat of starvation, he can compel them to work in whatever way and for whatever purpose he decides. It’s through his wisdom in making these choices that the value of his leadership is shown, or its lack. Clearly, he must first get them to temporarily drain the water and clear and replant their land; otherwise, he won't be able to keep providing for them. Once that's done, and while he still needs to feed them, what if he has them build a strong barrier for their land to protect against future floods, and rebuild their houses in safer locations using the best materials they can find? They would be allowed some time outside of working hours to gather these materials from afar. And for the food and clothing he provides, he’ll take security in the land, ensuring that a portion will be returned at a suitable time.

At the end of a few years, we may conceive this security redeemed, and the debt paid. The prudent peasant has sustained no loss; but is no richer than he was, and has had all his trouble for nothing. But he has enriched his neighbours materially; bettered their houses, secured their land, and rendered them, in worldly matters, equal to himself. In all true and final sense, he has been throughout their lord and king.

At the end of a few years, we might see this security redeemed and the debt settled. The careful farmer hasn’t lost anything but isn’t any richer than before and has gone through all this trouble for nothing. However, he has materially improved his neighbors; he’s enhanced their homes, secured their land, and made them, in practical terms, equal to him. In every real sense, he has been their lord and king the whole time.

We will next trace his probable line of conduct, presuming his object to be exclusively the increase of his own fortune. After roughly recovering and cleansing the ground, he allows the ruined peasantry only to build huts upon it, such as he thinks protective enough from the weather to keep them in working health. The rest of their time he occupies first in pulling down and rebuilding on a magnificent scale his own house, and in adding large dependencies to it. This done, he follows the example of the first great Hebrew financier, and in exchange for his continued supply of corn, buys as much of his neighbours![Pg 303] land, as he thinks he can superintend the management of; and makes the former owners securely embank and protect the ceded portion. By this arrangement he leaves to a certain number of the peasantry only as much ground as will just maintain them in their existing numbers: as the population increases, he takes the extra hands, who cannot be maintained on the narrow estates, for his own servants; employs some to cultivate the ground he has bought, giving them of its produce merely enough for subsistence; with the surplus, which, under his energetic and careful superintendence, will be large, he supports a train of servants for state, and a body of workmen, whom he educates in ornamental arts. He now can splendidly decorate his house, lay out its grounds magnificently, and richly supply his table, and that of his household and retinue. And thus, without any abuse of right, we should find established all the phenomena of poverty and riches, which (it is supposed necessarily) accompany modern civilization. In one part of the district, we should have unhealthy land, miserable dwellings and half-starved poor; in another, a well-ordered estate, well-fed servants, and refined conditions of highly-educated and luxurious life.

Next, we'll outline his likely behavior, assuming his goal is solely to boost his own wealth. After roughly clearing and cleaning the land, he lets the devastated farmers build simple huts that he thinks will protect them from the elements enough to keep them able to work. He then spends the rest of his time tearing down and rebuilding his own house on a grand scale, adding large extensions to it. Once that’s done, he follows the example of the first major Hebrew financier and, in exchange for his continued supply of grain, buys as much of his neighbors' land as he thinks he can manage; he also makes the former owners securely embank and protect the land he has taken. With this arrangement, he leaves a certain number of farmers just enough land to sustain their current population: as the population grows, he takes the extra laborers, who can’t be supported on the small estates, to become his servants; he employs some to farm the land he’s purchased, providing them just enough produce to survive; with the surplus, which will be considerable under his diligent supervision, he maintains a group of servants for show and a team of workers whom he trains in decorative arts. He can now lavishly decorate his house, beautifully landscape its grounds, and generously stock his dining table and that of his household and staff. Thus, without any violation of rights, we would observe the emergence of all the signs of poverty and wealth that are believed to inherently accompany modern civilization. In one part of the area, there would be unhealthy land, miserable homes, and starving poor people; in another, a well-managed estate with well-fed servants and the refined lifestyle of the well-educated and luxurious.

I have put the two cases in simplicity, and to some extremity. But though in more complex and qualified operation, all the relations of society are but the expansion of these two typical sequences of conduct and result. I do not say, observe, that the first procedure is entirely right; still less, that the second is wholly wrong. Servants and artists, and splendour of habitation and retinue, have all their use, propriety and office. I only wish the reader to understand clearly what they cost; that the condition of having them is the subjection to you of a certain number of imprudent or unfortunate persons (or, it may be, more fortunate than their master), over whose destinies you exercise a boundless control. "Riches" mean eternally and essentially this; and may heaven send at last a time when those words of our best-reputed economist shall be true, and we shall indeed "all know what it is to be rich;" that is to be slave-master over farthest earth, and over all ways and thoughts of men. Every operative you employ is your true servant: distant or near, subject to your immediate[Pg 304] orders, or ministering to your widely-communicated caprice—for the pay he stipulates, or the price he tempts,—all are alike under this great dominion of the gold. The milliner who makes the dress is as much a servant (more so, in that she uses more intelligence in the service) as the maid who puts it on; the carpenter who smoothes the door, as the footman who opens it; the tradesmen who supply the table, as the labourers and sailors who supply the tradesmen. Why speak of these lower services? Painters and singers (whether of note or rhyme), jesters and story-tellers, moralists, historians, priests—so far as these, in any degree, paint, or sing, or tell their tale, or charm their charm, or "perform" their rite, for pay, in so far they are all slaves; abject utterly, if the service be for pay only; abject less and less in proportion to the degrees of love and wisdom which enter into their duty, or can enter into it, according as their function is to do the bidding and the work of a man;—or to amuse, tempt, and deceive a child.

I’ve simplified the two cases a bit to their extremes. But even though society operates in more complex and nuanced ways, all of its relationships are just expansions of these two typical patterns of behavior and outcome. I’m not saying that the first approach is completely right; even less so that the second is entirely wrong. Servants, artists, lavish homes, and entourages all serve their purpose and have their place. I just want the reader to clearly recognize what they cost: the condition of having them often means exerting control over a certain number of imprudent or unfortunate people (or perhaps people who are more fortunate than their master), whose fates you dominate without limits. "Wealth" essentially means this; may we eventually reach a time when the words of our most respected economist ring true, and we all really know what it means to be rich—that is, to be masters over distant lands and the thoughts and ways of others. Every worker you hire is your true servant: near or far, responding to your immediate orders or catering to your whims for the pay they agree to or the price they’re tempted by—everyone falls under this vast dominion of wealth. The milliner making the dress is as much a servant (even more so, because she uses more skill in her work) as the maid who puts it on; the carpenter who smooths the door is just as much a servant as the footman who opens it; the merchants supplying the table are just as much servants as the workers and sailors supplying the merchants. Why even discuss these lower-level services? Painters and singers (whether they’re famous or just rhyming), jokesters and storytellers, moralists, historians, priests—so far as any of them in some way creates art, sings, tells their stories, enchants, or performs rites for pay, they are all slaves; utterly subservient if their work is solely for payment; somewhat less subservient in proportion to the love and wisdom that they put into their work, depending on whether they’re fulfilling the demands and tasks of a person, or merely entertaining, tempting, and deceiving a child.

There may be thus, and, to a certain extent, there always is, a government of the rich by the poor, as of the poor by the rich; but the latter is the prevailing and necessary one, and it consists, observe, of two distinct functions,—the collection of the profits of labour from those who would have misused them, and the administration of those profits for the service either of the same person in future, or of others; or, as is more frequently the case in modern times, for the service of the collector himself.

There may be, and to some extent, there always is, a government of the rich by the poor, just as there is one of the poor by the rich; but the latter is the dominant and necessary one. This involves, notice, two separate functions: collecting the profits from labor from those who would have wasted them, and managing those profits either for the benefit of the same person in the future or for others; or, as is more often the case today, for the benefit of the collector themselves.

The examination of these various modes of collection and use of riches will form the third branch of our future inquiries; but the key to the whole subject lies in the clear understanding of the difference between selfish and unselfish expenditure. It is not easy, by any course of reasoning, to enforce this on the generally unwilling hearer; yet the definition of unselfish expenditure is brief and simple. It is expenditure which if you are a capitalist, does not pay you, but pays somebody else; and if you are a consumer, does not please you, but pleases somebody else. Take one special instance, in further illustration of the general type given above. I did not invent that type, but spoke of a real river, and of real peasantry, the languid[Pg 305] and sickly race which inhabits, or haunts—for they are often more like spectres than living men—the thorny desolation on the banks of the Arve. Some years ago, a society formed at Geneva offered to embank the river, for the ground which would have been recovered by the operation; but the offer was refused by the (then Sardinian) government. The capitalists saw that this expenditure would have "paid," if the ground saved from the river was to be theirs. But if when the offer that had this aspect of profit was refused, they had nevertheless persisted in the plan and, merely taking security for the return of their outlay, lent the funds for the work, and thus saved a whole race of human souls from perishing in a pestiferous fen (as, I presume, some among them would, at personal risk, have dragged any one drowning creature out of the current of the stream, and not expected payment therefor), such expenditure would have precisely corresponded to the use of his power made, in the first instance, by our supposed richest peasant—it would have been the king's, of grace, instead of the usurer's, for gain.

The exploration of these different ways of gathering and using wealth will be the third part of our future discussions; however, the key to the entire topic lies in clearly understanding the difference between selfish and unselfish spending. It’s not easy to convince a generally reluctant audience of this through reasoning; still, the definition of unselfish spending is brief and straightforward. It’s spending that, if you’re a capitalist, doesn’t benefit you, but benefits someone else; and if you’re a consumer, doesn’t satisfy you, but satisfies someone else. Let’s examine one specific example to further illustrate the general idea mentioned above. I didn’t come up with that idea; I was referring to a real river and real peasants—the weak and sickly people who live, or linger—often like ghosts rather than living beings—among the thorny wasteland along the banks of the Arve. A few years back, a society in Geneva proposed to build a dam on the river to recover the land that would be saved by this effort; however, the (then Sardinian) government declined the offer. The capitalists realized that this spending would have "paid off" if the land saved from the river was going to be theirs. But if, after the profit-oriented offer was rejected, they had continued with the plan and, securing repayment for their investment, lent the money for the project, thereby saving an entire community from dying in a harmful marsh (as I believe some would have, risking their own safety to pull even one drowning person from the current, without expecting payment), that spending would have truly reflected the use of his power by our hypothetical wealthiest peasant—it would have been the king’s generosity instead of the usurer's greed.

"Impossible, absurd, Utopian!" exclaim nine-tenths of the few readers whom these words may find. No, good reader, this is not Utopian: but I will tell you what would have seemed, if we had not seen it, Utopian on the side of evil instead of good: that ever men should have come to value their money so much more than their lives, that if you call upon them to become soldiers, and take chance of bullet, for their pride's sake, they will do it gaily, without thinking twice; but if you ask them for their country's sake to spend a hundred pounds without security of getting back a hundred-and-five[118] they will laugh in your face.

"Impossible, ridiculous, Utopian!" exclaim nine-tenths of the few readers who might encounter these words. No, dear reader, this isn't Utopian: but let me tell you what would have seemed, if we had not witnessed it, Utopian on the side of evil instead of good: that people have come to value their money so much more than their lives, that if you ask them to become soldiers and risk their lives for pride, they will do it eagerly, without a second thought; but if you ask them to spend a hundred pounds for their country without any guarantee of getting back a hundred-and-five, they will laugh in your face.

[Pg 306]Not but that also this game of life-giving-and-taking is, in the end, somewhat more costly than other forms of play might be. Rifle practice is, indeed, a not unhealthy pastime, and a feather on the top of the head is a pleasing appendage; but while learning the stops and fingering of the sweet instrument, does no one ever calculate the cost of an overture? What melody does Tityrus meditate on his tenderly spiral pipe? The leaden seed of it, broad cast, true conical "Dents de Lion" seed—needing leas allowance for the wind than is usual with that kind of herb—what crop are you likely to have of it? Suppose, instead of this volunteer marching and countermarching, you were to do a little volunteer ploughing and counterploughing? It is more difficult to do it straight: the dust of the earth, so disturbed, is more grateful than for merely rhythmic footsteps. Golden cups, also, given for good ploughing would be more suitable in colour (ruby glass, for the wine which "giveth his colour" on the ground, as well as in the cup, might be fitter for the rifle prize in the ladies' hands); or, conceive a little volunteer exercise with the spade, other than such as is needed for moat and breastwork, or even for the burial of the fruit of the leaden avena-seed, subject to the shrill Lemures' criticism—

[Pg 306]But this game of giving life and taking it is, in the end, a bit more expensive than other kinds of play. Target practice is definitely a healthy hobby, and a feather in your cap is a nice touch; but while you’re figuring out how to play the sweet instrument, does anyone ever think about the cost of the performance? What tune is Tityrus playing on his delicate, coiled pipe? The heavy seeds, widely scattered, true conical "Dandelion" seeds—requiring less wind resistance than you usually see with that type of plant—what kind of yield can you expect? Instead of this casual marching around, what if you tried some volunteer plowing? It's harder to do it right: the disturbed earth dust is more rewarding than just rhythmic footsteps. Also, golden cups for good plowing would match the color better (ruby glass for the wine that “gives its color” on the ground as well as in the cup might be more appropriate for the ladies’ rifle prize); or imagine a little volunteer work with a spade, beyond what’s needed for a moat and fortifications, or even for burying the produce of the heavy avena seeds, facing the sharp criticism of the pesky spirits—

"Wer hat das Haus so schlecht gebaut?"

"Who built the house so poorly?"

If you were to embank Lincolnshire now,—more stoutly against the sea? or strip the peat of Solway, or plant Plinlimmon moors with larch—then, in due hour of year, some amateur reaping and threshing?

If you were to build up Lincolnshire now—stronger against the sea? Or clear the peat from Solway, or plant larch on Plinlimmon moors—then, at the right time of year, some hobbyist harvesting and threshing?

"Nay, we reap and thresh by steam in these advanced days."

"Sure, we harvest and process with steam in these modern times."

I know it, my wise and economical friends. The stout arms God gave you to win your bread by, you would fain shoot your neighbours—and God's sweet singers—with;[119] then you invoke the friends to your farm-service, and—

I know it, my smart and thrifty friends. The strong arms that God gave you to earn your living by, you would rather use to shoot your neighbors—and God's lovely singers—with; [119] then you call on your friends for help with the farm, and—

"When the young and the old come out to play
On a toxic vacation,
Tell how the sweet little goblin sweats. (His feast of ashes properly arranged),
And the belching night, where the morning breathed. His dark flail has threshed the corn. That ten-day laborers couldn't finish.

But we will press the example closer. On a green knoll above that plain of the Arve, between Cluses and Bonneville, there was, in the year 1860, a cottage, inhabited by a well-doing family—man and wife, three children, and the grandmother. I call it a cottage but, in truth, it was a large chimney on the ground, wide at the bottom (so that the family might live round the fire), with one broken window in it, and an unclosing door. The family, I say, was "well-doing," at least, it was hopeful and cheerful; the wife healthy, the children, for Savoyards, pretty and active, but the husband threatened with decline, from exposure under the cliffs of the Mont Vergi by day, and to draughts between every plank of his chimney in the frosty nights. "Why could he not plaster the [Pg 308] chinks?" asks the practical reader. For the same reason that your child cannot wash its face and hands till you have washed them many a day for it, and will not wash them when it can, till you force it.

But let's examine the example more closely. On a green hill overlooking the Arve plain, between Cluses and Bonneville, there was, in 1860, a cottage lived in by a hardworking family—a man and woman, three kids, and the grandmother. I call it a cottage, but really, it was more like a big chimney on the ground, wide at the base (so the family could gather around the fire), with one broken window and an unclosable door. The family was "doing well," at least they were hopeful and cheerful; the wife was healthy, the children, for Savoyards, were pretty and lively, but the husband was facing decline, due to exposure under the cliffs of Mont Vergi during the day, and drafts between every plank of his chimney on frosty nights. "Why couldn't he just plaster the gaps?" asks the practical reader. For the same reason that your child can’t wash their face and hands until you’ve done it for them many times, and won’t do it on their own until you make them.

I passed this cottage often in my walks, had its window and door mended, sometimes mended also a little the meal of sour bread and broth, and generally got kind greeting and smile from the face of young or old; which greeting, this year, narrowed itself into the half-recognizing stare of the elder child and the old woman's tears; for the father and mother were both dead,—one of sickness, the other of sorrow. It happened that I passed not alone, but with a companion, a practised English joiner, who, while these people were dying of cold, had been employed from six in the morning to six of the evening for two months, in fitting the panels without nails, of a single door in a large house in London. Three days of his work taken, at the right time, from the oak panels, and applied to the larch timbers, would have saved these Savoyards' lives. He would have been maintained equally (I suppose him equally paid for his work by the owner of the greater house, only the work not consumed selfishly on his own walls;) and the two peasants, and eventually, probably their children, saved.

I often walked past this cottage, had its window and door fixed, sometimes improved the meager meal of stale bread and broth, and generally received a kind greeting and a smile from the faces of the young and old. However, this year, those greetings changed into the half-recognizing stare of the older child and the old woman's tears; the father and mother were both dead—one from illness and the other from grief. I happened to be passing by not alone, but with a skilled English carpenter who, while these people were freezing, had been working from six in the morning to six in the evening for two months, fitting a single door in a large house in London without nails. If he had taken just three days of his labor from the oak panels and used it for the larch timbers at the right time, it would have saved these Savoyard lives. He would still have been supported (I assume he was equally compensated for his work by the owner of the larger house, only he wasn't selfishly using that work for his own walls); and those two peasants, and likely their children as well, would have been saved.

There are, therefore, let me finally enforce and leave with the reader this broad conclusion,—three things to be considered in employing any poor person. It is not enough to give him employment. You must employ him first to produce useful things; secondly, of the several (suppose equally useful) things he can equally well produce, you must set him to make that which will cause him to lead the healthiest life; lastly, of the things produced, it remains a question of wisdom and conscience how much you are to take yourself, and how much to leave to others. A large quantity, remember, unless you destroy it, must always be so left at one time or another; the only questions you have to decide are, not what you will give, and what you will keep, but when, and how, and to whom, you will give. The natural law of human life is, of course, that in youth a man shall labour and lay by store for his old age, and when age comes, should use what he has laid[Pg 309] by, gradually slackening his toil, and allowing himself more frank use of his store, taking care always to leave himself as much as will surely suffice for him beyond any possible length of life. What he has gained, or by tranquil and unanxious toil, continues to gain, more than is enough for his own need, he ought so to administer, while he yet lives, as to see the good of it again beginning in other hands; for thus he has himself the greatest sum of pleasure from it, and faithfully uses his sagacity in its control. Whereas most men, it appears, dislike the sight of their fortunes going out into service again, and say to themselves,—"I can indeed nowise prevent this money from falling at last into the hands of others, nor hinder the good of it, such as it is, from becoming theirs, not mine; but at least let a merciful death save me from being a witness of their satisfaction; and may God so far be gracious to me as to let no good come of any of this money of mine before my eyes." Supposing this feeling unconquerable, the safest way of rationally indulging it would be for the capitalist at once to spend all his fortune on himself, which might actually, in many cases, be quite the rightest as well as the pleasantest thing to do, if he had just tastes and worthy passions. But, whether for himself only, or through the hands and for the sake of others also, the law of wise life is, that the maker of the money should also be the spender of it, and spend it, approximately, all, before he dies; so that his true ambition as an economist should be, to die, not as rich, but as poor, as possible, calculating the ebb tide of possession in true and calm proportion to the ebb tide of life. Which law, checking the wing of accumulative desire in the mid-volley,[120] and leading to peace of possession and fulness of fruition in old age, is also wholesome in that by the freedom of gift, together with present help and counsel, it at once endears and dignifies age in the sight of youth, which then no longer strips the bodies of the dead, but receives the grace of the living. Its chief use would (or will be, for [Pg 310] men are indeed capable of attaining to this much use for their reason), that some temperance and measure will be put to the acquisitiveness of commerce.[121] For as things stand, a man holds it his duty to be temperate in his food, and of his body, but for no duty to be temperate in his riches, and of his mind. He sees that he ought not to waste his youth and his flesh for luxury; but he will waste his age, and his soul, for money, and think it no wrong, nor the delirium tremens of the intellect any evil. But the law of life is, that a man should fix the sum he desires to make annually, as the food he desires to eat daily; and stay when he has reached the limit, refusing increase of business, and leaving it to others, so obtaining due freedom of time for better thoughts. How the gluttony of business is punished, a bill of health for the principals of the richest city houses, issued annually, would show in a sufficiently impressive manner.

There are, therefore, let me finally emphasize and leave with the reader this broad conclusion: three things to consider when hiring any poor person. It’s not enough to just give them a job. First, you need to employ them to create useful things; second, of the various things they can produce that are equally useful, you should have them make those that will help them live the healthiest life; lastly, regarding what is produced, it’s a matter of wisdom and conscience how much you take for yourself and how much you leave for others. Remember, a large quantity must eventually be left for others unless you completely destroy it; the real questions are not what you will give and what you will keep, but when, how, and to whom you will give. The natural law of human life is that, in their youth, a person should work and save for old age, and when old age comes, they should use what they have saved, gradually reducing their work and enjoying their savings, while always ensuring they leave enough for themselves for any possible length of life. What they have earned, or what they continue to earn through steady and worry-free work—more than enough for their own needs—they should manage wisely while they are still alive, allowing the benefits to begin in other hands. This way, they experience the greatest satisfaction from it and wisely manage their resources. However, it seems most people dislike seeing their wealth go to others and tell themselves, “I can’t prevent this money from eventually falling into someone else’s hands, nor can I stop the benefits of it from becoming theirs instead of mine; but at least let a merciful death save me from witnessing their satisfaction, and may God be gracious enough to not let any good come from my money before my eyes.” Assuming this feeling is unchangeable, the safest way to rationally indulge it would be for the wealthy person to spend all their money on themselves immediately, which could, in many cases, be both the best and most enjoyable choice, if they have good tastes and worthy passions. But whether for oneself or for the sake of others, the principle of a wise life is that the person who earns the money should also be the one to spend it, ideally spending it all before they die; therefore, their true goal as an economist should be to die as poor as possible, calculating their possessions in a true and calm proportion to the remaining length of their life. This principle, which tempers the desire for accumulation, leads to peace of possession and fullness of enjoyment in old age, and it also has the benefit of making age more valued and dignified in the eyes of youth, which then doesn’t strip the bodies of the dead but honors the living. Its main purpose would be to ensure some moderation and measure in the greed of commerce. As it stands now, a person feels it’s their duty to be moderate in their food and physical body, but they feel no obligation to be moderate in their wealth or mindset. They recognize they shouldn't waste their youth and health on luxury, but they’ll waste their old age and soul for money, thinking it's not wrong, nor recognizing the harm to their intellect. The law of life is that one should set an annual income goal just as they set a daily food intake limit and stop once they reach it, refusing to take on more business and leaving it for others, thereby gaining the necessary free time for better thoughts. How the greed for business is punished can be clearly shown through an annual health report for the executives of the wealthiest city firms.

I know, of course, that these statements will be received by the modern merchant, as an active Border rider of the sixteenth century would have heard of its being proper for men of the Marches to get their living by the spade instead of the spur. But my business is only to state veracities and necessities; I neither look for the acceptance of the one, nor promise anything for the nearness of the other. Near or distant, the day will assuredly come when the merchants of a state shall be its true "ministers of exchange," its porters, in the double sense of carriers and gate-keepers, bringing all lands into frank and faithful communication, and knowing for their master of guild, Hermes the herald, instead of Mercury the gain-guarder.

I know that these statements will likely be received by today’s merchants like a sixteenth-century Border rider would have reacted to the idea that men from the Marches should make a living with shovels instead of swords. But my job is simply to lay out the truths and necessities; I’m not looking for anyone to accept one or promising anything for the other’s proximity. Whether soon or later, the day will definitely come when the merchants of a state will truly be its “ministers of exchange,” its porters, in both meanings of the word—carriers and gatekeepers—bringing all lands into honest and trustworthy communication, recognizing Hermes the herald as their master of the guild instead of Mercury the profit protector.

And now, finally, for immediate rule to whom it concerns.

And now, finally, for immediate attention to those it concerns.

The distress of any population means that they need food, houseroom, clothes, and fuel. You can never, therefore, be wrong in employing any labourer to produce food, [Pg 311] houseroom, clothes, or fuel: but you are always wrong if you employ him to produce nothing (for then some other labourer must be worked double time to feed him); and you are generally wrong, at present, if you employ him (unless he can do nothing else) to produce works of art, or luxuries; because modern art is mostly on a false basis, and modern luxury is criminally great.[122]

The struggles of any community indicate that they need food, shelter, clothes, and fuel. Therefore, you can’t go wrong by hiring a worker to produce food, shelter, clothes, or fuel: but you are always making a mistake if you hire him to produce nothing (because then another worker has to work extra hours to support him); and you are generally making a mistake right now if you hire him (unless there’s nothing else he can do) to create art or luxury items; because contemporary art is mostly based on a false premise, and modern luxury is excessively extravagant.[Pg 311][122]

The way to produce more food is mainly to bring in fresh ground, and increase facilities of carriage;—to break rock, exchange earth, drain the moist, and water the dry, to mend roads, and build harbours of refuge. Taxation thus spent will annihilate taxation, but spent in war, it annihilates revenue.

The best way to grow more food is mainly to prepare new land and improve transportation. This means breaking up rocks, swapping soil, draining wet areas, watering dry ones, fixing roads, and building safe harbors. Money spent on these projects will effectively eliminate taxes, but money spent on war just reduces income.

The way to produce houseroom is to apply your force first to the humbler dwellings. When your bricklayers are out of employ, do not build splendid new streets, but better the old ones: send your paviours and slaters to the poorest villages, and see that your poor are healthily lodged before you try your hand on stately architecture. You will find its stateliness rise better under the trowel afterwards; and we do [Pg 312] not yet build so well as that we need hasten to display our skill to future ages. Had the labour which has decorated the Houses of Parliament filled, instead, rents in walls and roofs throughout the county of Middlesex; and our deputies met to talk within massive walls that would have needed no stucco for five hundred years,—the decoration might have been better afterwards, and the talk now. And touching even our highly conscientious church building, it may be well to remember that in the best days of church plans, their masons called themselves "logeurs du bon Dieu;" and that since, according to the most trusted reports, God spends a good deal of His time in cottages as well as in churches, He might perhaps like to be a little better lodged there also.

The way to create living space is to focus your efforts on the simpler homes first. When your bricklayers are out of work, don’t build fancy new streets; instead, improve the old ones. Send your pavement workers and roofers to the poorest neighborhoods, and make sure your less fortunate are living in healthy conditions before you tackle grand architecture. You’ll find that the grandeur will look even better later on. We still don’t build so well that we need to rush to show off our skills to future generations. If the work that went into decorating the Houses of Parliament had instead been used to fix the cracks in walls and roofs all over Middlesex; and if our representatives met in sturdy buildings that wouldn’t need any plaster for five hundred years—the decoration could have been even better later on, and the conversations today would be improved too. And when it comes to our very well-meaning church building, it’s worth noting that in the best days of church planning, the masons considered themselves "God’s lodgers;" and since, according to the most reliable sources, God spends a lot of His time in cottages as well as churches, He might appreciate being a bit better accommodated there too.

The way to get more clothes is,—not necessarily, to get more cotton. There were words written twenty years ago which would have saved many of us some shivering had they been minded in time. Shall we read them?

The way to get more clothes isn't just about getting more cotton. There were words written twenty years ago that could have saved many of us from shivering if we had paid attention in time. Should we read them?

"The Continental people, it would seem, are 'importing our machinery, beginning to spin cotton and manufacture for themselves, to cut us out of this market and then out of that!' Sad news indeed; but irremediable;—by no means. The saddest news is, that we should find our National Existence, as I sometimes hear it said, depend on selling manufactured cotton at a farthing an ell cheaper than any other People. A most narrow stand for a great Nation to base itself on! A stand which, with all the Corn-Law Abrogations conceivable, I do not think will be capable of enduring.

"The people in Europe seem to be importing our machinery, starting to spin cotton and manufacture for themselves, aiming to cut us out of this market and then the next! That’s definitely disappointing news, but it’s not hopeless. What’s truly saddening is that our National Existence, as I sometimes hear it put, seems to depend on selling manufactured cotton at a lower price than anyone else. What a weak foundation for a great Nation to rely on! A foundation that, even with all conceivable Corn-Law Abrogations, I don’t think can hold up."

"My friends, suppose we quitted that stand; suppose we came honestly down from it and said: 'This is our minimum cotton-prices. We care not, for the present, to make cotton any cheaper. Do you, if it seem so blessed to you, make cotton cheaper. Fill your lungs with cotton-fuzz, your hearts with copperas-fumes, with rage and mutiny; become ye the general gnomes of Europe, slaves of the lamp!' I admire a Nation which fancies it will die if it do not undersell all other Nations, to the end of the world. Brothers, we will cease to undersell them; we will be content to equal-sell them; to be happy selling equally with them! I do not see the use of underselling them. Cotton-cloth is already two-pence[Pg 313] a yard or lower; and yet bare backs were never more numerous among us. Let inventive men cease to spend their existence incessantly contriving how cotton can be made cheaper; and try to invent, a little, how cotton at its present cheapness could be somewhat justlier divided among us. Let inventive men consider, Whether the Secret of this Universe, and of Man's Life there, does, after all, as we rashly fancy it, consist in making money?... With a Hell which means—'Failing to make money,' I do not think there is any Heaven possible that would suit one well; nor so much as an Earth that can be habitable long! In brief, all this Mammon-Gospel of Supply-and-demand, Competition, Laissez-faire, and Devil take the hindmost" (foremost, is it not, rather, Mr. Carlyle?) "begins to be one of the shabbiest Gospels ever preached." (In the matter of clothes, decidedly.) The way to produce more fuel is first to make your coal mines safer, by sinking more shafts; then set all your convicts to work in them, and if, as is to be hoped, you succeed in diminishing the supply of that sort of labourer, consider what means there may be, first of growing forest where its growth will improve climate; then of splintering the forests which now make continents of fruitful land pathless and poisonous, into faggots for fire;—so gaining at once dominion sunwards and icewards. Your steam power has been given you (you will find eventually) for work such as that; and not for excursion trains, to give the labourer a moment's breath, at the peril of his breath for ever, from amidst the cities which you have crushed into masses of corruption. When you know how to build cities, and how to rule them, you will be able to breathe in their streets, and the "excursion" will be the afternoon's walk or game in the fields round them. Long ago, Claudian's peasant of Verona knew, and we must yet learn, in his fashion, the difference between via and vita. But nothing of this work will pay.

"My friends, let's say we stepped down from our high horse; let’s just say: 'These are our lowest prices for cotton. We’re not interested, for now, in making it any cheaper. If you think it’s so great, go ahead and make cotton cheaper yourself. Fill your lungs with cotton dust, your hearts with anger and rebellion; become the general workers of Europe, slaves to the grind!' I admire a nation that believes it will fail if it doesn’t outprice all other nations, forever. Brothers, we will stop underselling them; we’ll be satisfied to compete with them; to be happy selling on the same level as them! I don’t see the point in underselling them. Cotton fabric is already at two pence[Pg 313] a yard or less, and yet we have more bare backs than ever. Let inventors stop spending their lives tirelessly figuring out how to make cotton cheaper; instead, let them try to figure out how we can share the cotton at its current low price more fairly among us. Let’s ask ourselves, is the secret of this universe, and of our lives, really just about making money? With a Hell that means ‘not making money,’ I don’t believe there’s any Heaven that would truly suit anyone, nor even a livable Earth for long! In short, all this talk about money—supply and demand, competition, free market, and may the devil take the last one left—is becoming one of the most worn-out doctrines ever preached." (Especially regarding clothing.) The way to produce more energy is first to make your coal mines safer by adding more shafts; then put all your prisoners to work in them. If, as we hope, you manage to reduce the number of those laborers, consider how to grow forests where they will improve the climate, then how to split the forests that now make rich land inaccessible and toxic, into firewood—thus gaining control over both the sun and the ice. Your steam power has been given to you (you’ll eventually realize) for work like this, not for pleasure rides that give the worker a brief escape at the risk of his health forever, from the cities you’ve condensed into places of decay. Once you learn how to build and govern cities, you’ll be able to breathe freely in their streets, and a ‘day trip’ will simply be an afternoon stroll or game in the fields around them. Long ago, Claudian's peasant of Verona understood this, and we must learn, in his way, the difference between the road and life. But none of this work will be profitable.

No; no more than it pays to dust your rooms or wash your doorsteps. It will pay; not at first in currency, but in that which is the end and the source of currency,—in life (and in currency richly afterwards). It will pay in that which is more than life,—in "God's first creature, which was light," whose[Pg 314] true price has not yet been reckoned in any currency, and yet into the image of which all wealth, one way or other, must be cast. For your riches must either as the lightning, which,

No; just like it doesn’t make sense to dust your rooms or wash your doorsteps. It will pay off; not right away in money, but in what’s the end and source of money—in life (and eventually in money as well). It will reward you with something even greater than life—in "God's first creation, which was light," whose[Pg 314] true value hasn’t been calculated in any form of currency, and yet all wealth must somehow reflect it. Your riches must either be like lightning, which,

"gave birth but in a cloud,
Though shining brightly and speaking loudly,
As it starts, it finishes its violent race,
"And where it shines, it hurts the spot;"

or else as the lightning of the sacred sign, which shines from one part of the heaven to the other. There is no other choice; you must either take dust for deity, spectre for possession, fettered dream for life, and for epitaph, this reversed verse of the great Hebrew hymn of economy (Psalm cxii.):—"He hath gathered together, he hath stripped the poor, his iniquity remaineth for ever." Or else, having the sun for justice to shine on you, and the sincere substance of good in your possession, and the pure law and liberty of life within you, leave men to write this better legend over your grave: "He hath dispersed abroad. He hath given to the poor. His righteousness remaineth for ever."

or else like the lightning from a sacred sign, which flashes from one side of the sky to the other. There's no other option; you must either accept dust as god, a ghost as wealth, a chained dream as life, and for your tombstone, this twisted version of the great Hebrew hymn of economy (Psalm cxii.):—"He has gathered together, he has stripped the poor, his wrongdoing lasts forever." Or instead, with the sun of justice shining on you, and the genuine goodness in your possession, and the pure law and freedom of life within you, let people write this better message on your grave: "He has given generously. He has given to the poor. His righteousness lasts forever."


The present paper completes the definitions necessary for future service. The next in order will be the first chapter of the body of the work.

The current paper finishes the definitions needed for future reference. Next up is the first chapter of the main text.

These introductory essays are as yet in imperfect form; I suffer them to appear, though they were not intended for immediate publication, for the sake of such chance service as may be found in them.

These introductory essays are not in perfect shape yet; I'm allowing them to be published, even though they weren't meant for immediate release, for whatever benefit they might offer.

[Here the author indicated certain corrections, which have been carried out in this edition. He then went on to say that the note on Charis (p. 274) required a word or two in further illustration, as follows:—]

[Here the author indicated certain corrections, which have been carried out in this edition. He then went on to say that the note on Charis (p. 274) needed a word or two for further clarification, as follows:—]

The derivation of words is like that of rivers: there is one real source, usually small, unlikely, and difficult to find, far up among the hills; then, as the word flows on and comes into service, it takes in the force of other words from other sources, and becomes itself quite another word—even more than one word, after the junction—a word as it were of many waters, sometimes both sweet and bitter. Thus the whole force of our English "charity" depends on the guttural in "Charis" getting confused with the "c" of the Latin "carus;" thenceforward throughout the middle ages, the two ideas ran on together, and both got confused with St. Paul's ὰγάπη, which expresses a different idea in all sorts of ways; our "charity," having not only brought in the entirely foreign sense of almsgiving, but lost the essential sense of [Pg 315] contentment, and lost much more in getting too far away from the "charis," of the final Gospel benedictions. For truly it is fine Christianity we have come to, which professing to expect the perpetual grace of its Founder, has not itself grace enough to save it from overreaching its friends in sixpenny bargains; and which, supplicating evening and morning the forgiveness of its own debts, goes forth in the daytime to take its fellow-servants by the throat, saying—not "Pay me that thou owest," but "Pay me that thou owest me not."

The origin of words is like that of rivers: there’s one real source, usually small, obscure, and hard to find, up in the hills; then, as the word flows and gets used, it gathers influences from other words and sources, becoming something entirely different—even multiple meanings after they merge—a word made up of many streams, sometimes both pleasant and unpleasant. Hence, the full meaning of our English "charity" relies on the guttural sound in "Charis" getting mixed up with the "c" of the Latin "carus;" from that point on, throughout the Middle Ages, the two concepts ran together, becoming confused with St. Paul's ὰγάπη, which conveys different ideas in various ways; our "charity," having not only adopted the completely foreign sense of giving to the poor but also having lost the core meaning of [Pg 315] contentment, lost even more by straying too far from the "charis," of the final blessings in the Gospel. For it truly is remarkable Christianity we've reached, which, while claiming to depend on the constant grace of its Founder, lacks enough grace itself to avoid exploiting its friends over trivial deals; and which, begging for forgiveness of its own debts morning and evening, goes out during the day to choke its fellow servants, saying—not "Pay me what you owe," but "Pay me what you owe me not."

Not but that we sometimes wear Ophelia's rue with a difference, and call it, "Herb o' grace o' Sundays," taking consolation out of the offertory with—"Look, what he layeth out, it shall be paid him again." Comfortable words, indeed, and good to set against the old royalty of Largesse—

Not that we don't sometimes wear Ophelia's rue differently, and call it, "Herb of grace on Sundays," finding comfort in the offertory with—"Look, what he gives, it will be returned to him." Truly reassuring words, and a good counter to the old tradition of generosity—

"Whose greatest joy was, I swear,
When she gave it and said, 'Take this.'

Again: the first root of the word faith being far away in——(compare my note on this force of it in "Modern Painters," vol. v., p. 255), the Latins, as proved by Cicero's derivation of the word, got their "facio," also involved in the idea; and so the word, and the world with it, gradually lose themselves in an arachnoid web of disputation concerning faith and works, no one ever taking the pains to limit the meaning of the term: which in earliest Scriptural use is as nearly as possible our English "obedience." Then the Latin "fides," a quite different word, alternately active and passive in different uses, runs into "foi;" "facere," through "ficare," into "fier," at the end of words; and "fidere," into "fier" absolute; and out of this endless reticulation of thought and word rise still more finely reticulated theories concerning salvation by faith—the things which the populace expected to be saved from, being indeed carved for them in a very graphic manner in their cathedral porches, but the things they were expected to believe being carved for them not so clearly.

Again: the root of the word faith being far away in——(see my note on this aspect in "Modern Painters," vol. v., p. 255), the Latins, as shown by Cicero's explanation of the word, got their "facio," which is also linked to the concept; and so the word, and the world along with it, gradually get lost in a tangled web of debate about faith and works, with no one ever bothering to define the meaning of the term: which in its earliest Scriptural use is almost identical to our English "obedience." Then the Latin "fides," a completely different word, shifts between active and passive meanings, transforming into "foi"; "facere," through "ficare," into "fier" at the end of words; and "fidere," into "fier" absolute; and out of this endless network of thought and language arise increasingly elaborate theories about salvation through faith—the things that the public expected to be saved from being depicted for them in a very vivid way in their cathedral porches, but the things they were expected to believe being represented not so clearly.

Lastly I debated with myself whether to make the note on Homer longer by examining the typical meaning of the shipwreck of Ulysses, and his escape from Charybdis by help of her fig-tree; but as I should have had to go on to the lovely myth of Leucothea's veil, and did not care to spoil this by a hurried account of it, I left it for future examination; and three days after the paper was published, observed that the reviewers, with their usual useful ingenuity, were endeavouring to throw the whole subject back into confusion by dwelling on the single (as they imagined) oversight. I omitted also a note on the sense of the word λυγρὸν, with respect to the pharmacy of Circe, and herb-fields of Helen (compare its use in Odyssey, xvii. 473, etc.), which would further have illustrated the nature of the Circean power. But, not to be led too far into the subtleness of these myths, respecting them all [Pg 316] I have but this to say: Even in very simple parables, it is not always easy to attach indisputable meaning to every part of them. I recollect some years ago, throwing an assembly of learned persons who had met to delight themselves with interpretations of the parable of the prodigal son (interpretations which had up to that moment gone very smoothly) into high indignation, by inadvertently asking who the prodigal son was, and what was to be learned by his example. The leading divine of the company (still one of our great popular preachers) at last explained to me that the unprodigal son was a lay figure, put in for dramatic effect, to make the story prettier, and that no note was to be taken of him. Without, however, admitting that Homer put in the last escape of Ulysses merely to make his story prettier, this is nevertheless true of all Greek myths, that they have many opposite lights and shades: they are as changeful as opal and, like opal, usually have one colour by reflected, and another by transmitted, light. But they are true jewels for all that, and full of noble enchantment for those who can use them; for those who cannot, I am content to repeat the words I wrote four years ago, in the appendix to the "Two Paths"—

Lastly, I struggled with whether to extend the note on Homer by exploring the common interpretation of Ulysses' shipwreck and his escape from Charybdis with the help of her fig tree. However, since I would have had to delve into the beautiful myth of Leucothea's veil and didn’t want to ruin it with a rushed summary, I decided to save it for later analysis. Three days after the paper was published, I noticed that the reviewers, with their typical ingenuity, were trying to throw everything back into confusion by focusing on what they thought was a single oversight. I also left out a note on the meaning of the word λυγρὸν regarding Circe's magic and Helen's herb fields (see its usage in Odyssey, xvii. 473, etc.), which would have further explained the nature of Circean power. But, not wanting to get too deeply into the subtleties of these myths, I can only say this: even in very simple parables, it’s not always easy to pin down a clear meaning for every part. I remember years ago, I unintentionally stirred up a group of scholars who had gathered to enjoy interpreting the parable of the prodigal son (interpretations that had been going quite smoothly) by asking who the prodigal son was and what we could learn from his example. The leading theologian in the group (still one of our prominent preachers) finally told me that the unprodigal son was just a puppet, added for dramatic effect to make the story more appealing, and that we shouldn't pay any attention to him. Without claiming that Homer included Ulysses' last escape just to make his story prettier, it remains true that all Greek myths have many conflicting aspects: they are as variable as opal and, like opal, usually show one color by reflected light and another by transmitted light. But they are still true gems, filled with noble enchantment for those who can appreciate them; for those who can’t, I'm happy to repeat the words I wrote four years ago in the appendix to the "Two Paths"—

"The entire purpose of a great thinker may be difficult to fathom, and we may be over and over again more or less mistaken in guessing at his meaning; but the real, profound, nay, quite bottomless and unredeemable mistake, is the fool's thought, that he had no meaning."

"The full purpose of a great thinker can be hard to understand, and we might repeatedly misinterpret their meaning; however, the truly deep, even endless, and irredeemable mistake is the fool's belief that they have no meaning."

FOOTNOTES:

[104] "The ordinary brute, who flourishes in the very centre of ornate life, tells us of unknown depths on the verge of which we totter, being bound to thank our stars every day we live that there is not a general outbreak and a revolt from the yoke of civilization."—Times leader, Dec. 25th, 1862. Admitting that our stars are to be thanked for our safety, whom are we to thank for the danger?

[104] "The average beast, thriving in the heart of luxurious life, reveals to us the unknown depths we are always on the edge of, making us grateful every day we live that there's not a widespread uprising against the constraints of civilization."—Times leader, Dec. 25th, 1862. Acknowledging that we should be thankful to our lucky stars for our safety, who should we thank for the danger?

[105] Our politicians, even the best of them, regard only the distress caused by the failure of mechanical labour. The degradation caused by its excess is a far more serious subject of thought, and of future fear. I shall examine this part of our subject at length hereafter. There can hardly be any doubt, at present, cast on the truth of the above passages, as all the great thinkers are unanimous on the matter. Plato's words are terrific in their scorn and pity whenever he touches on the mechanical arts. He calls the men employed in them not even human,—but partially and diminutively human, "ανθρωπίσκοι," and opposes such work to noble occupations, not merely as prison is opposed to freedom, but as a convict's[Pg 281] dishonoured prison is to the temple (escape from them being like that of a criminal to the sanctuary), and the destruction caused by them being of soul no less than body.—Rep., vi. 9. Compare "Laws," v. 11. Xenophon dwells on the evil of occupations at the furnace (root of βάναυσος), and especially their "ἀσχολία, want of leisure"—Econ. i. 4. (Modern England, with all its pride of education, has lost that first sense of the word "school," and till it recover that it will find no other rightly.) His word for the harm to the soul is to "break" it, as we say of the heart.—Econ. i. 6. And herein also is the root of the scorn, otherwise apparently most strange and cruel, with which Homer, Dante, and Shakespeare always speak of the populace; for it is entirely true that in great states the lower orders are low by nature as well as by task, being precisely that part of the commonwealth which has been thrust down for its coarseness or unworthiness (by coarseness I mean especially insensibility and irreverence; the "profane" of Horace); and when this ceases to be so, and the corruption and the profanity are in the higher instead of the lower orders, there arises, first, helpless confusion; then, if the lower classes deserve power, ensues swift revolution, and they get it: but if neither the populace nor their rulers deserve it, there follows mere darkness and dissolution, till, out of the putrid elements, some new capacity of order rises, like grass on a grave; if not, there is no more hope, nor shadow of turning, for that nation. Atropos has her way with it.

[105] Our politicians, even the best of them, only acknowledge the suffering caused by the failure of mechanical work. The degradation stemming from its overuse is a far more serious issue to consider and a cause for future concern. I will explore this aspect of our topic in detail later. There’s hardly any doubt about the truth of the above statements, as all the great thinkers agree on this. Plato's words are intense in their disdain and sympathy whenever he addresses mechanical arts. He describes the men working in these fields as not fully human, but rather partially and diminutively human, "ανθρωπίσκοι," contrasting such work with noble occupations—not only as prison compares to freedom, but as a convict’s[Pg 281] degrading prison compares to a temple (where one escapes like a criminal to a sanctuary), with the harm they cause being detrimental to both soul and body.—Rep., vi. 9. See "Laws," v. 11. Xenophon emphasizes the harm of jobs at the furnace (source of βάναυσος), especially their "ἀσχολία, lack of leisure"—Econ. i. 4. (Modern England, with all its pride in education, has lost the original meaning of the word "school," and until it regains that, it won’t find anything else rightly.) His term for the harm to the soul is to "break" it, just as we say of the heart.—Econ. i. 6. This also explains the scorn, which may seem strange and cruel, with which Homer, Dante, and Shakespeare refer to the common people; for it's completely true that in great societies, the lower classes are low by nature as well as by their tasks, being specifically that part of the community which has been pushed down due to its crudeness or unworthiness (by crudeness, I refer particularly to insensitivity and irreverence; the "profane" of Horace); and when this changes, and corruption and disrespect are found among the higher classes instead of the lower, it creates, first, utter confusion; then, if the lower classes deserve power, a swift revolution occurs, and they attain it: but if neither the populace nor their leaders deserve it, what follows is mere darkness and chaos, until from the decayed components, some new order emerges, like grass growing on a grave; if not, there is no more hope or possibility of change for that nation. Atropos has her way with it.

So that the law of national health is like that of a great lake or sea, in perfect but slow circulation, letting the dregs fall continually to the lowest place, and the clear water rise; yet so as that there shall be no neglect of the lower orders, but perfect supervision and sympathy, so that if one member suffer, all members shall suffer with it.

So the law of public health is like a large lake or ocean, constantly but gradually flowing, allowing the impurities to settle at the bottom while the clean water rises; still ensuring that the lower levels are not neglected, but instead receive full oversight and care, so that if one part suffers, all parts suffer together.

[106] "ὀλίγης, καὶ ἄλλως γιγνομένης." The bitter sentence never was so true as at this day.

[106] "ὀλίγης, καὶ ἄλλως γιγνομένης." The harsh saying has never been more accurate than it is today.

[107] Thetic, or Thesmic, would perhaps be a better term than Archic; but liable to be confused with some which we shall want relating to Theoria. The administrators of the three great divisions of law are severally Archons, Merists, and Dicasts. The Archons are the true princes, or beginners of things; or leaders (as of an orchestra); the Merists are properly the Domini, or Lords (law-words) of houses and nations; the Dicasts properly the judges, and that with Olympian justice, which reaches to heaven and hell. The violation of archic law is ἁμαρτία (error) πονηρία (failure), πλημμέλεια (discord). The violation of meristic law is ἀνομία (iniquity). The violation of critic law is ἀδικία (injury). Iniquity is central generic term; for all law is fatal; it is the division to men of their fate; as the fold of their pasture, it is νόμος; as the assigning of their portion, μοῖρα.

[107] Thetic, or Thesmic, might be a better term than Archic; however, it may be confused with some terms we will need regarding Theoria. The leaders of the three main branches of law are Archons, Merists, and Dicasts. The Archons are the true leaders or initiators; like conductors of an orchestra; the Merists are essentially the Lords of homes and nations; the Dicasts are the judges, dispensing a form of justice that extends to both heaven and hell. Violating archic law is ἁμαρτία (error), πονηρία (failure), πλημμέλεια (discord). Breaking meristic law is ἀνομία (iniquity). Violating critic law is ἀδικία (injury). Iniquity serves as a central term since all law is fatal; it distributes fate to people; like the boundaries of their pastures, it is νόμος; in its assignment of their share, it is μοῖρα.

[108] These laws need revision quite as much respecting property in national as in private hands. For instance: the public are under a vague impression, that because they have paid for the contents of the British Museum, every one has an equal right to see and to handle them. But the public have similarly paid for the contents of Woolwich Arsenal; yet do not expect free access to it, or handling of its contents. The British Museum is neither a free circulating library, nor a free school; it is a place for the safe preservation, and exhibition on due occasion, of unique books, unique objects of natural history, and unique works of art; its books can no more be used by everybody than its coins can be handled, or its statues cast. Free libraries there ought to be in every quarter of London, with large and complete reading-rooms attached; so also free educational institutions should be open in every quarter of London, all day long and till late at night, well lighted, well catalogued, and rich in contents both of art and natural history. But neither the British Museum nor National Gallery are schools; they are treasuries; and both should be severely restricted in access and in use. Unless some order is taken, and that soon, in the MSS. department of the Museum (Sir Frederic Madden was complaining of this to me only the other day), the best MSS. in the collection will be destroyed, irretrievably, by the careless and continual handling to which they are now subjected.

[108] These laws need to be updated just as much for public property as for private property. For example, people seem to think that because they contributed to funding the British Museum, everyone has the right to freely view and touch its contents. However, the public also funded the contents of Woolwich Arsenal and doesn’t expect free access to it or the ability to handle its items. The British Museum isn’t just a free circulating library or a free school; it exists to safely preserve and showcase unique books, one-of-a-kind natural history specimens, and exceptional artworks. Its books can't be used by everyone just as its coins can’t be touched or its statues molded. There should be free libraries in every part of London, complete with spacious and well-equipped reading rooms; similarly, every neighborhood should have free educational institutions open all day and late into the night, well-lit, well-organized, and rich in art and natural history resources. But neither the British Museum nor the National Gallery are schools; they are repositories, and access and usage should be strictly limited. If action isn't taken soon regarding the manuscripts in the Museum (Sir Frederic Madden mentioned this to me just the other day), the finest manuscripts in the collection will be irreparably damaged due to the careless and constant handling they currently endure.

[109] Two curious economical questions arise laterally with respect to this branch of law, namely, the cost of crime and the cost of judgment. The cost of crime is endured by nations ignorantly, not being clearly stated in their budgets; the cost of judgment patiently (provided only it can be had pure for the money), because the science, or perhaps we ought rather to say the art, of law, is felt to found a noble profession, and discipline; so that civilized nations are usually glad that a number of persons should be supported by funds devoted to disputation and analysis. But it has not yet been calculated what the practical value might have been, in other directions, of the intelligence now occupied in deciding, through courses of years, what might have been decided as justly, had the date of judgment been fixed, in as many hours. Imagine one half of the funds which any great nation devotes to dispute by law, applied to the determination of physical questions in medicine, agriculture, and theoretic science; and calculate the probable results within the next ten years.

[109] Two interesting economic questions come up regarding this area of law: the cost of crime and the cost of judgment. The cost of crime is unconsciously borne by nations, as it isn't clearly outlined in their budgets; the cost of judgment is accepted patiently (as long as it can be obtained without issues for the price), because the field of law is recognized as a noble profession and discipline. As a result, civilized nations are generally pleased to support people involved in dispute and analysis. However, it hasn't been figured out what the practical value could have been, in other areas, of the intelligence that is currently dedicated to deciding, over many years, what could have been just as fairly decided in just a few hours. Imagine if half of the funds that any major nation spends on legal disputes were directed toward solving physical questions in medicine, agriculture, and theoretical science; consider the potential outcomes over the next ten years.

I say nothing yet, of the more deadly, more lamentable loss, involved in the use of purchased instead of personal justice,—ἐπακτῷ παρ’ ἄλλων—ἀπορίᾳ’ οἰκείων.

I haven’t even mentioned the more devastating and regrettable loss that comes from relying on bought justice instead of personal justice,—ἐπακτῷ παρ’ ἄλλων—ἀπορίᾳ’ οἰκείων.

[110] Compare Chaucer's "villany" (clownishness).

       "Full foul and chorlishe seemed she,
       And eke villanous for to be,
       And little coulde of norture
       To worship any creature."

[110] Compare Chaucer's "villainy" (clownishness).

       "She seemed very ugly and crude,
       And also villainous for sure,
       And knew very little about etiquette
       To honor any creature."

[111] "Supply-and-demand,—alas! For what noble work was there ever any audible 'demand' in that poor sense?" ("Past and Present"). Nay, the demand is not loud even for ignoble work. See "Average earnings of Betty Taylor," in Times, of 4th February, of this year [1863]: "Worked from Monday morning at 8 a.m., to Friday night at 5.30 p.m., for 1s.d."—Laissez faire.

[111] "Supply and demand—unfortunately! When has there ever been a clear 'demand' for any truly admirable work?" ("Past and Present"). In fact, the demand isn't even strong for work that lacks honor. See "Average earnings of Betty Taylor," in Times, from February 4th of this year [1863]: "Worked from Monday morning at 8 a.m. to Friday night at 5:30 p.m. for 1s.d."—Laissez faire.

[112] See Bacon's note in the "Advancement of Learning," on "didicisse fideliter artes" (but indeed the accent had need be upon "fideliter"). "It taketh away vain admiration of anything, which is the root of all weakness: for all things are admired either because they are new, or because they are great," etc.

[112] See Bacon's note in the "Advancement of Learning," on "learning the arts faithfully" (but really the emphasis should be on "faithfully"). "It removes empty admiration for anything, which is the source of all weakness: for things are admired either because they are new, or because they are impressive," etc.

[113] Ames, by report of Waldo Emerson, expressed the popular security wisely, saying, "that a monarchy is a merchantman, which sails well, but will sometimes strike on a rock, and go to the bottom; whilst a republic is a raft, which would never sink, but then your feet are always in the water." Yes, and when the four winds (your only pilots) steer competitively from the four corners, ὡς δ’ ὅτ’ ὀπωρινὸς Βορέης φορέησιν ἀκάνθας, perhaps the wiser mariner may wish for keel and wheel again.

[113] Ames, according to Waldo Emerson, cleverly summed up the common sentiment by saying, "a monarchy is like a big ship that sails well but might hit a rock and sink; meanwhile, a republic is like a raft that never sinks, but your feet are always wet." Yes, and when the four winds (your only navigators) blow unpredictably from all directions, ὡς δ’ ὅτ’ ὀπωρινὸς Βορέης φορέησιν ἀκάνθας, the wiser sailor might find himself wishing for a proper keel and wheel again.

[114] The passage of Plato, referred to in note p. 280, in its context, respecting the slave who, well dressed and washed, aspires to the hand of his master's daughter, corresponds curiously to the attack of Caliban on Prospero's cell, and there is an undercurrent of meaning throughout, in the "Tempest" as well as in the "Merchant of Venice"; referring in this case to government, as in that to commerce. Miranda ("the wonderful," so addressed first by Ferdinand, "Oh, you wonder!") corresponds to Homer's Arete: Ariel and Caliban are respectively the spirits of freedom and mechanical labour. Prospero ("for hope"), a true governor, opposed to Sycorax, the mother of slavery, her name, "Swine-raven," indicating at once brutality and deathfulness; hence the line—"As wicked dew as e'er my mother brushed, with raven's feather,"—etc. For all dreams of Shakespeare, as those of true and strong men must be, are "φαντάσματα θεῖα, καὶ σκιαὶ τῶν ὄντων," phantasms of God, and shadows of things that are. We hardly tell our children, willingly, a fable with no purport in it; yet we think God sends His best messengers only to say fairy tales to us, all fondness and emptiness. The "Tempest" is just like a grotesque in a rich missal, "clasped where paynims pray." Ariel is the spirit of true liberty, in early stages of human society oppressed by ignorance and wild tyranny; venting groans as fast as mill-wheels strike; in shipwreck of states, fearful; so that "all but mariners plunge in the brine, and quit the vessel, then all afire with me," yet having in itself the will and sweetness of truest peace, whence that is especially called "Ariel's" song, "Come unto these yellow sands"—(fenceless, and countless—changing with the sweep of the sea—"vaga arena." Compare Horace's opposition of the sea-sand to the dust of the grave: "numero carentis"—"exigui;" and again compare "animo rotundum percurrisse" with "put a girdle round the earth")—"and then take hands: court'sied when you have, and kiss'd,—the wild waves whist:" (mind it is "courtesia," not "curtsey") and read "quiet" for "whist" if you want the full sense. Then may you indeed foot it featly, and sweet spirits bear the burden for you—with watch in the night, and call in early morning. The power of liberty in elemental transformation follows—"Full fathom five thy father lies, of his bones are coral made." Then, giving rest after labour, it "fetches dew from the still-vex'd Bermoothes, and, with a charm joined to their suffered labour, leaves men asleep." Snatching away the feast of the cruel, it seems to them as a harpy, followed by the utterly vile, who cannot see it in any shape, but to whom it is the picture of nobody, it still gives shrill harmony to their false and mocking catch, "Thought is free," but leads them into briars and foul places, and at last hollas the hounds upon them. Minister of fate against the great criminal, it joins itself with the "incensed seas and shores"—the sword that layeth at it cannot hold, and may, "with bemocked-at stabs as soon kill the still-closing waters, as diminish one dowle that's in my plume." As the guide and aid of true love, it is always called by Prospero "fine" (the French "fine"—not the English), or "delicate"—another long note would be needed to explain all the meaning in this word. Lastly, its work done, and war, it resolves itself to the elements. The intense significance of the last song, "Where the bee sucks," I will examine in its due place. The types of slavery in Caliban are more palpable, and need not be dwelt on now: though I will notice them also, severally, in their proper places;—the heart of his slavery is in his worship: "That's a brave god, and bears celestial liquor." But, in illustration of the sense in which the Latin "benignus" and "malignus," are to be coupled with Eleutheria and Douleia, not that Caliban's torment is always the physical reflection of his own nature—"cramps" and "side-stitches that shall pen thy breath up"—"thou shalt be pinched as thick as honeycomb:" the whole nature of slavery being one cramp and cretinous contraction. Fancy this of Ariel! You may fetter him, but yet set no mark on him; you may put him to hard work and far journey, but you cannot give him a cramp.

[114] The passage from Plato mentioned in note p. 280, about the well-dressed slave wanting to marry his master's daughter, strangely parallels Caliban’s attack on Prospero's cell. There’s a deeper meaning throughout "The Tempest" as well as in "The Merchant of Venice," relating in this case to governance, just like that connects with commerce. Miranda ("the wonderful," first called so by Ferdinand, "Oh, you wonder!") is similar to Homer’s Arete: Ariel and Caliban represent the spirits of freedom and manual labor, respectively. Prospero ("for hope") is a true governor, standing against Sycorax, the mother of slavery; her name, "Swine-raven," reflects brutality and death. Hence the line—"As wicked dew as e'er my mother brushed, with raven's feather,"—etc. All of Shakespeare's dreams, like those of true and strong men, are "φαντάσματα θεῖα, καὶ σκιαὶ τῶν ὄντων," phantasms of God, and shadows of what exists. We hardly tell our children a fable without a purpose; yet we think God sends His best messengers just to tell us fairy tales full of love and emptiness. "The Tempest" is like a grotesque scene in a lavish missal, "clasped where paynims pray." Ariel is the spirit of true freedom, initially oppressed by ignorance and violent tyranny; expressing cries as fast as mill-wheels turn, in the chaos of states, so that "all but mariners plunge in the brine, and quit the vessel, then all afire with me," yet containing within it the will and sweetness of genuine peace, from which comes "Ariel's" song, "Come unto these yellow sands"—(unfenced, and countless—changing with the sea’s sweep—"vaga arena." Compare Horace's contrast of sea-sand with grave dust: "numero carentis"—"exigui;" and further compare "animo rotundum percurrisse" with "put a girdle round the earth")—"and then take hands: court'sied when you have, and kiss'd,—the wild waves whist:" (note it is "courtesia," not "curtsey") and read "quiet" for "whist" if you want the complete sense. Then you may actually dance gracefully, and sweet spirits will carry the load for you—with watch in the night, and call in the early morning. The power of freedom in elemental transformation follows—"Full fathom five thy father lies, of his bones are coral made." Then, giving rest after effort, it "fetches dew from the still-vex'd Bermoothes, and, with a charm joined to their suffered labour, leaves men asleep." Stealing away the feast of the cruel, it appears to them as a harpy, followed by the utterly vile, who cannot see it in any form, but to whom it represents no one, yet still creates shrill harmony to their false and mocking catch, "Thought is free," but leads them into thorns and filthy places, ultimately unleashing the hounds on them. Minister of fate against the great wrongdoer, it aligns with the "incensed seas and shores"—the sword that strikes it cannot prevail, and may, "with bemocked-at stabs as soon kill the still-closing waters, as diminish one dowle that's in my plume." As the guide and aid of true love, it is consistently called by Prospero "fine" (the French "fine"—not the English), or "delicate"—an additional long note would be needed to explain all the significance in this term. Finally, its task complete, and war concluded, it dissolves back into the elements. The deep significance of the last song, "Where the bee sucks," I will discuss in its proper place. The types of slavery in Caliban are more obvious and don’t need detailed exploration now; though I will note them separately in their relevant sections;—the core of his slavery lies in his worship: "That's a brave god, and bears celestial liquor." However, to illustrate the sense in which the Latin "benignus" and "malignus," are to be linked with Eleutheria and Douleia, it's not that Caliban's suffering is merely a physical reflection of his own nature—"cramps" and "side-stitches that shall pen thy breath up"—"thou shalt be pinched as thick as honeycomb:" the entire essence of slavery being one cramped and dull contraction. Think about this for Ariel! You may chain him, but you cannot mark him; you can assign him tough tasks and long journeys, but you cannot constrict his freedom.

Of Shakespeare's names I will afterwards speak at more length: they are curiously—often barbarously—mixed out of various traditions and languages. Three of the clearest in meaning have been already noticed. Desdemona, "δυσδαιμονία," "miserable fortune," is also plain enough. Othello is, I believe, "the careful"; all the calamity of the tragedy arising from the single flaw and error in his magnificently collected strength. Ophelia, "serviceableness," the true lost wife of Hamlet, is marked as having a Greek name by that last word of her, where her gentle preciousness is opposed to the uselessness of the churlish clergy—"A ministering angel shall my sister be when thou liest howling." Hamlet is, I believe, connected in some way with "homely," the entire event of the tragedy turning on betrayal of home duty. Hermione (ἕρμα), "pillar-like" (ἥ εἴδος ἔχε χρυσῆς Ἀφροδίτης). Titania (τιτήνη), "the queen;" Benedict and Beatrice, "blessed and blessing;" Valentine and Proteus, enduring (or strong) (valens) and changeful. Iago and Iachimo have evidently the same root—probably the Spanish Iago, Jacob, "the supplanter." Leonatus, and other such names are interpreted, or played with, in the plays themselves. For the interpretation of Sycorax, and reference to her raven's feather, I am indebted to Mr. John R. Wise.

I'll discuss Shakespeare's names in more detail later; they're interestingly—often awkwardly—blended from different traditions and languages. Three of the most straightforward ones have already been mentioned. Desdemona, "δυσδαιμονία," meaning "miserable fortune," is also quite clear. Othello likely means "the careful"; all the tragedy's turmoil stems from a single flaw in his otherwise impressive strength. Ophelia, which means "serviceableness," is the true lost wife of Hamlet, noted for having a Greek name, where her gentle value contrasts with the ineffectiveness of the rude clergy—"A ministering angel shall my sister be when thou liest howling." I think Hamlet may be linked to the idea of "homely," as the whole tragedy revolves around the betrayal of domestic duty. Hermione (ἕρμα), means "pillar-like" (ἥ εἴδος ἔχε χρυσῆς Ἀφροδίτης). Titania (τιτήνη) means "the queen"; Benedict and Beatrice mean "blessed and blessing"; Valentine and Proteus mean enduring (or strong) (valens) and changeful. Iago and Iachimo clearly share the same root—most likely the Spanish Iago, Jacob, meaning "the supplanter." Leonatus and similar names are interpreted or played with in the plays themselves. For the interpretation of Sycorax and her raven's feather, I'm thankful to Mr. John R. Wise.

[115] In the present general examination I concede so much to ordinary economists as to ignore all innocent poverty. I assume poverty to be always criminal; the conceivable exceptions we will examine afterwards.

[115] In this general overview, I’ll give in to mainstream economists by disregarding all forms of innocent poverty. I’ll assume that poverty is always a result of wrongdoing; we’ll look into any possible exceptions later.

[116] I say nothing yet of the quality of the servants, which, nevertheless, is the gist of the business. Will you have Paul Veronese to paint your ceiling, or the plumber from over the way? Both will work for the same money; Paul, if anything, a little cheaper of the two, if you keep him in good humour; only you have to discern him first, which will need eyes.

[116] I'm not even mentioning the quality of the servants, which is the main point. Would you prefer Paul Veronese to paint your ceiling, or the plumber from down the street? Both will do it for the same price; in fact, Paul might even be a bit cheaper if you keep him happy. But you have to be able to recognize his work first, and that requires some insight.

[117] By his heart he may; but only when its produce, or the sight or hearing of it, becomes a subject of dispute, so as to enable the artist to tax the labour of multitudes highly, in exchange for his own.

[117] He can do so with his heart, but only when what he creates, or the way people see or hear it, becomes a point of contention, allowing the artist to charge a lot for the hard work of many, in return for his own effort.

[118] I have not hitherto touched on the subject of interest of money; it is too complex; and must be reserved for its proper place in the body of the work. (I should be glad if a writer, who sent me some valuable notes on this subject, and asked me to return a letter which I still keep at his service, would send me his address.) The definition of interest (apart from compensation for risk) is, "the exponent of the comfort of accomplished labour, separated from its power;" the power being what is lent: and the French economists who have maintained the entire illegality of interest are wrong; yet by no means so curiously or wildly wrong as the English and French ones opposed to them, whose opinions have been collected by Dr. Whewell at page 41 of his Lectures; it never seeming to occur to the mind of the compiler any more than to the writers whom he quotes, that it is quite possible, and even (according to Jewish proverb) prudent, for men to hoard, as ants and mice do, for use, not usury; and lay by something for winter nights, in the expectation of rather sharing than lending the scrapings. My Savoyard squirrels would pass a pleasant time of it under the snow-laden pine-branches, if they always declined to economize because no one would pay them interest on nuts.

[118] I haven't yet discussed the topic of money interest; it's too complicated and should be addressed in its proper section of the work. (I would appreciate it if a writer who sent me some useful notes on this topic and requested a reply—which I still have on hand—could send me his address.) The definition of interest (aside from compensation for risk) is "the measure of the comfort derived from completed work, separated from its capability"; the capability being what is lent. The French economists who argue that interest is entirely illegal are mistaken, but they're not nearly as bizarrely wrong as the English and French economists who oppose them, whose views have been compiled by Dr. Whewell on page 41 of his Lectures. It never seems to strike either the compiler or the authors he quotes that it's entirely possible—and even, as the Jewish proverb suggests, wise—for people to save, just like ants and mice do, for practical use instead of profit; and to set aside something for the colder months, expecting to share rather than lend what's saved. My Savoyard squirrels would have a lovely time under the snow-covered pine branches if they always refused to save just because no one would pay them interest on nuts.

[119] Compare Chaucer's feeling respecting birds (from Canace's falcon, to the nightingale, singing "Domine labia "—to the Lord of Love) with the usual modern British sentiments on this subject. Or even Cowley's:—

       "What prince's choir of music can excel
       That which within this shade does dwell.
       To which we nothing pay, or give,
       They, like all other poets, live
       Without reward, or thanks for their obliging pains!
       'Tis well if they became not prey."

[119] Compare Chaucer's feelings about birds (from Canace's falcon to the nightingale singing "Domine labia"—to the Lord of Love) with the usual modern British views on this topic. Or even Cowley's:—

       "What prince's choir of music can surpass
       That which lives in this shade?
       We don’t pay anything for it,
       They, like all other poets, exist
       Without reward, or thanks for their generous efforts!
       It’s good if they don’t end up as prey."

Yes; it is better than well; particularly since the seed sown by the wayside has been protected by the peculiar appropriation of part of the church rates in our country parishes. See the remonstrance from a "Country Parson," in the Times of June 4th (or 5th; the letter is dated June 3rd, 1862):—"I have heard at a vestry meeting a good deal of higgling over a few shillings' outlay in cleaning the church; but I have never heard any dissatisfaction expressed on account of the part of the rate which is invested in fifty or 100 dozens of birds' heads."

Yes, it’s not just good; it’s actually better, especially since the seeds sown by the roadside have been safeguarded by the unique allocation of some church funds in our rural parishes. Check out the complaint from a "Country Parson" in the Times from June 4th (or 5th; the letter is dated June 3rd, 1862):—"At a vestry meeting, I’ve heard a lot of fuss over a few shillings spent on cleaning the church; however, I’ve never heard any complaints about the portion of the rate that goes towards fifty or 100 dozen bird heads."

[120] καὶ πενίαν ἡγουμένους εἷναι μὴ τὸ τὴν οὐσίαν ἐλάττω ποιεῖν, ἀλλὰ τὸ τήν ἀπληστίαν πλείω.—"Laws," v. 8.

[120] To be in poverty is not to diminish one's substance, but rather to increase one’s greed.—"Laws," v. 8.

Read the context and compare. "He who spends for all that is noble, and gains by nothing but what is just, will hardly be notably wealthy, or distressfully poor."—"Laws," v. 42.

Read the context and compare. "The person who invests in everything good, and only profits from what is fair, will likely not be very rich, nor extremely poor."—"Laws," v. 42.

[121] The fury of modern trade arises chiefly out of the possibility of making sudden fortune by largeness of transaction, and accident of discovery or contrivance. I have no doubt that the final interest of every nation is to check the action of these commercial lotteries. But speculation absolute, unconnected with commercial effort, is an unmitigated evil in a state, and the root of countless evils beside.

[121] The anger surrounding modern trade mainly comes from the chance to strike it rich through large transactions and unexpected discoveries or inventions. I’m sure that every nation's ultimate goal is to curb the impact of these commercial lotteries. However, pure speculation, unrelated to any commercial effort, is a complete disaster for a society and the source of many other problems.

[122] It is especially necessary that the reader should keep his mind fixed on the methods of consumption and destruction, as the true sources of national poverty. Men are apt to watch rather the exchanges in a state than its damages; but the exchanges are only of importance so far as they bring about these last. A large number of the purchases made by the richer classes are mere forms of interchange of unused property, wholly without effect on national prosperity. It matters nothing to the state, whether if a china pipkin be rated as worth a hundred pounds, A has the pipkin, and B the pounds, or A the pounds and B the pipkin. But if the pipkin is pretty, and A or B breaks it, there is national loss; not otherwise. So again, when the loss has really taken place, no shifting of the shoulders that bear it will do away with the fact of it. There is an intensely ludicrous notion in the public mind respecting the abolishment of debt by denying it. When a debt is denied, the lender loses instead of the borrower, that is all; the loss is precisely, accurately, everlastingly the same. The Americans borrow money to spend in blowing up their own houses. They deny their debt; by one third already, gold being at fifty premium; and will probably deny it wholly. That merely means that the holders of the notes are to be the losers instead of the issuers. The quantity of loss is precisely equal, and irrevocable; it is the quantity of human industry spent in explosion, plus the quantity of goods exploded. Honour only decides who shall pay the sum lost, not whether it is to be paid or not. Paid it must be and to the uttermost farthing.

[122] It's especially important for the reader to focus on the ways we consume and destroy, as these are the real causes of national poverty. People tend to pay more attention to exchanges within a state rather than the losses it incurs; but exchanges only matter as far as they lead to those losses. Many purchases made by wealthier individuals are just trade-offs of unused assets and have no real impact on national prosperity. It doesn't matter to the state whether a china pot valued at a hundred pounds is owned by A or B; what matters is if someone breaks it—then there's a national loss. Likewise, when a loss occurs, merely shifting who feels that loss won’t change the reality of it. There's a comically misguided belief that debt can be erased by simply denying it. When someone denies a debt, the lender is the one who loses instead of the borrower—that’s all that changes; the loss remains the same, forever. Americans borrow money to blow up their own houses. They deny their debt, already by a third, with gold at a fifty percent premium, and will likely deny it completely. This just means that those holding the notes will take the hit instead of those who issued them. The total loss is exactly equal and cannot be undone; it includes the human effort wasted in destruction, plus the value of the goods destroyed. Only honor determines who will cover the lost amount, not whether it will be paid. It has to be paid, down to the last penny.

London: Ward, Lock & Co., Limited.


TRANSCRIBER'S NOTE:

1. Footnotes have been renumbered and moved to the end of the chapters.

1. Footnotes have been renumbered and moved to the end of the chapters.

2. The original text includes some Greek characters, the transliterations for which can be seen with mouse-over popups. Position your cursor over the following Greek text β to see its transliteration.

2. The original text includes some Greek characters, and you can see their transliterations by hovering your mouse over them. Position your cursor over the following Greek text β to view its transliteration.

3. Obvious misprints and punctuation errors have been silently corrected in this HTML version.

3. Obvious typos and punctuation mistakes have been quietly fixed in this HTML version.

4. Other than the changes listed above, printer's inconsistencies in hyphenation and ligature usage have been retained.

4. Aside from the changes mentioned above, we have kept the printer's inconsistencies in hyphenation and ligature usage.

 

 



Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!