This is a modern-English version of Reconstruction in Philosophy, originally written by Dewey, John.
It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling,
and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If
you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.
Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.
RECONSTRUCTION IN
PHILOSOPHY
BY
JOHN DEWEY
Professor of Philosophy in Columbia University
NEW YORK.
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
1920
Copyright, 1920,
BY
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
The Quinn & Boden Company
BOOK MANUFACTURERS
RAHWAY NEW JERSEY
PREFATORY NOTE
Being invited to lecture at the Imperial University of Japan in Tokyo during February and March of the present year, I attempted an interpretation of the reconstruction of ideas and ways of thought now going on in philosophy. While the lectures cannot avoid revealing the marks of the particular standpoint of their author, the aim is to exhibit the general contrasts between older and newer types of philosophic problems rather than to make a partisan plea in behalf of any one specific solution of these problems. I have tried for the most part to set forth the forces which make intellectual reconstruction inevitable and to prefigure some of the lines upon which it must proceed.
Being invited to give lectures at the Imperial University of Japan in Tokyo during February and March of this year, I attempted to interpret the shift in ideas and ways of thinking currently happening in philosophy. While the lectures inevitably show the perspective of their author, the goal is to highlight the general differences between older and newer types of philosophical problems rather than to advocate for any one specific solution to these issues. I have mostly aimed to outline the forces that make intellectual reconstruction unavoidable and to anticipate some of the directions it should take.
Any one who has enjoyed the unique hospitality of Japan will be overwhelmed with confusion if he endeavors to make an acknowledgment in any way commensurate to the kindnesses he received. Yet I must set down in the barest of black and white my grateful appreciation of them, and in particular record my ineffaceable impressions of the courtesy and help of the members of the department of philosophy of Tokyo University, and of my dear friends Dr. Ono and Dr. Nitobe.
Anyone who has experienced the distinct hospitality of Japan will feel completely baffled if they try to express their gratitude in a way that matches the kindness they've received. Still, I have to write down in plain text my heartfelt appreciation for it all, especially noting my unforgettable impressions of the courtesy and support from the members of the philosophy department at Tokyo University, as well as from my dear friends Dr. Ono and Dr. Nitobe.
J. D.
J.D.
September, 1919.
September 1919.
CONTENTS
CHAPTER | PAGE | |
I | Changing Ideas About Philosophy | 1 |
Origin of philosophy in desire and imagination. Influence of community traditions and authority. Simultaneous development of matter-of-fact knowledge. Incongruity and conflict of the two types. Respective values of each type.... Classic philosophies (i) compensatory, (ii) dialectically formal, and (iii) concerned with "superior" Reality. Contemporary thinking accepts primacy of matter-of-fact knowledge and assigns to philosophy a social function rather than that of absolute knowledge. | ||
II | Some Historical Factors in Philosophical Reconstruction | 28 |
Francis Bacon exemplifies the newer spirit.... He conceived knowledge as power. As dependent upon organized cooperative research.... As tested by promotion of social progress. The new thought reflected actual social changes, industrial, political, religious.... The new idealism. | ||
III | The Scientific Element in the Reconstruction of Philosophy | 53 |
Science has revolutionized our conception of Nature. Philosophy has to be transformed because no longer depending upon a science which accepts a closed, finite world. Or, fixed species. Or, superiority or rest to change and motion. Contrast of feudal with democratic conceptions. Elimination of final causes. Mechanical science and the possibility of control of nature. Respect for matter. New temper of imagination. Influence thus far technical rather than human and moral. | ||
IV | Changed Ideas About Experience and Reason | 77 |
Traditional conception of nature of experience. Limits of ancient civilization. Effect of classic idea on modern empiricism. Why a different conception is now possible. Psychological change emphasizes vital factor using environment. Effect upon traditional ideas of sensation and knowledge. Factor of organization. Socially, experience is now more inventive and regulative.... Corresponding change in idea of Reason. Intelligence is hypothetical and inventive. Weakness of historic Rationalism. Kantianism. Contrast of German and British philosophies. Reconstruction of empirical liberalism. | ||
V | Changed Views of the Ideal and the Real | 103 |
Idealization rooted in aversion to the disagreeable.... This fact has affected philosophy.... True reality is ideal, and hence changeless, complete. Hence contemplative knowledge is higher than experimental. Contrast with the modern practise of knowledge.... Significance of change.... The actual or realistic signifies conditions effecting change.... Ideals become methods rather than goals. Illustration from elimination of distance. Change in conception of philosophy.... The significant problems for philosophy.... Social understanding and conciliation. The practical problem of real and ideal. | ||
VI | The Importance of Logical Reconstruction | 132 |
Present confusion as to logic. Logic is regulative and normative because empirical. Illustration from mathematics. Origin of thinking in conflicts. Confrontation with fact. Response by anticipation or prediction. Importance of hypotheses. Impartial inquiry. Importance of deductive function. Organization and classification. Nature of truth. Truth is adverbial, not a thing. | ||
VII | Rebuilding Moral Ideas | 161 |
Common factor in traditional theories. Every moral situation unique. Supremacy of the specific or individualized case. Fallacy of general ends. Worth of generalization of ends and rules is intellectual. Harmfulness of division of goods into intrinsic and instrumental. Into natural and moral. Moral worth of natural science. Importance of discovery in morals. Abolishing Phariseeism.... Growth as the end. Optimism and pessimism. Conception of happiness. Criticism of utilitarianism. All life moral in so far as educative. | ||
VIII | Reconstruction's Impact on Social Philosophy | 187 |
Defects of current logic of social thought. Neglect of specific situations. Defects of organic concept of society. Evils of notion of fixed self or individual. Doctrine of interests. Moral and institutional reform. Moral test of social institutions. Social pluralism. Political monism, dogma of National State. Primacy of associations. International humanism. Organization a subordinate conception. Freedom and democracy. Intellectual reconstruction when habitual will affect imagination and hence poetry and religion. | ||
Index | 217 |
RECONSTRUCTION IN PHILOSOPHY
CHAPTER I
CHANGING CONCEPTIONS OF PHILOSOPHY
Man differs from the lower animals because he preserves his past experiences. What happened in the past is lived again in memory. About what goes on today hangs a cloud of thoughts concerning similar things undergone in bygone days. With the animals, an experience perishes as it happens, and each new doing or suffering stands alone. But man lives in a world where each occurrence is charged with echoes and reminiscences of what has gone before, where each event is a reminder of other things. Hence he lives not, like the beasts of the field, in a world of merely physical things but in a world of signs and symbols. A stone is not merely hard, a thing into which one bumps; but it is a monument of a deceased ancestor. A flame is not merely something which warms or burns, but is a symbol of the enduring life of the household, of the abiding source of cheer, nourishment and shelter to which man returns from his casual wanderings. Instead of being a quick fork of fire which may sting and hurt, it is the hearth at which one worships and for which one fights. And all this which marks the difference between bestiality and[Pg 2] humanity, between culture and merely physical nature, is because man remembers, preserving and recording his experiences.
Man is different from lower animals because he remembers his past experiences. What happened before is relived in memory. Today’s events are often overshadowed by thoughts of similar experiences from the past. Animals forget experiences as soon as they happen, and each new action or suffering is isolated. But humans live in a world where each occurrence is filled with echoes and memories of what has happened before, where each event reminds us of other things. Thus, humans don’t just exist in a physical world like the animals do; they exist in a world of signs and symbols. A stone isn’t just a hard object you bump into; it represents a monument to a deceased ancestor. A flame isn’t just something that warms or burns; it symbolizes the enduring life of the home, the consistent source of comfort, nourishment, and shelter that brings us back from our wanderings. Instead of being just a quick spark that can sting and cause pain, it’s the hearth we cherish and fight for. All these distinctions that set humanity apart from animality, and culture apart from mere physical nature, stem from man’s ability to remember, preserving and recording his experiences.
The revivals of memory are, however, rarely literal. We naturally remember what interests us and because it interests us. The past is recalled not because of itself but because of what it adds to the present. Thus the primary life of memory is emotional rather than intellectual and practical. Savage man recalled yesterday's struggle with an animal not in order to study in a scientific way the qualities of the animal or for the sake of calculating how better to fight tomorrow, but to escape from the tedium of today by regaining the thrill of yesterday. The memory has all the excitement of the combat without its danger and anxiety. To revive it and revel in it is to enhance the present moment with a new meaning, a meaning different from that which actually belongs either to it or to the past. Memory is vicarious experience in which there is all the emotional values of actual experience without its strains, vicissitudes and troubles. The triumph of battle is even more poignant in the memorial war dance than at the moment of victory; the conscious and truly human experience of the chase comes when it is talked over and re-enacted by the camp fire. At the time, attention is taken up with practical details and with the strain of uncertainty. Only later do the details compose into a story and fuse[Pg 3] into a whole of meaning. At the time of practical experience man exists from moment to moment, preoccupied with the task of the moment. As he re-surveys all the moments in thought, a drama emerges with a beginning, a middle and a movement toward the climax of achievement or defeat.
The revival of memories is rarely literal. We tend to remember what we find interesting, and it's our interest that drives this recall. The past isn't remembered for its own sake but for how it adds value to the present. So, the main aspect of memory is emotional rather than intellectual or practical. A primitive person would recall yesterday's struggle with a beast not to scientifically study it or plan for a better fight tomorrow, but to escape the monotony of today by reliving the excitement of yesterday. The memory carries all the thrill of battle without the danger and anxiety. To bring it back and enjoy it enhances the present moment with new meaning, different from what belongs to either the present or the past. Memory is like experiencing something secondhand, where all the emotional value of true experience is there, but without the stresses, changes, and troubles. The joy of victory in battle feels even more intense in a memorial war dance than it did at the moment of winning; the genuine human experience of the hunt happens when it's retold and acted out by the campfire. During the actual event, attention is focused on practical details and the tension of uncertainty. It's only later that those details come together into a story that forms a cohesive meaning. In moments of practical experience, a person lives from moment to moment, absorbed in what they are doing. As they reflect on all those moments, a drama unfolds with a beginning, middle, and a push toward the peak of success or failure.
Since man revives his past experience because of the interest added to what would otherwise be the emptiness of present leisure, the primitive life of memory is one of fancy and imagination, rather than of accurate recollection. After all, it is the story, the drama, which counts. Only those incidents are selected which have a present emotional value, to intensify the present tale as it is rehearsed in imagination or told to an admiring listener. What does not add to the thrill of combat or contribute to the goal of success or failure is dropped. Incidents are rearranged till they fit into the temper of the tale. Thus early man when left to himself, when not actually engaged in the struggle for existence, lived in a world of memories which was a world of suggestions. A suggestion differs from a recollection in that no attempt is made to test its correctness. Its correctness is a matter of relative indifference. The cloud suggests a camel or a man's face. It could not suggest these things unless some time there had been an actual, literal experience of camel and face. But the real likeness is of no account. The main thing is the emotional interest[Pg 4] in tracing the camel or following the fortunes of the face as it forms and dissolves.
Since people revisit their past experiences to add meaning to what would otherwise feel like the emptiness of leisure time, the early life of memory is more about fantasy and imagination than about accurate recollection. Ultimately, it's the story and the drama that matter. Only those events that have emotional significance in the present are chosen to enhance the current narrative, whether it's being played out in the imagination or shared with an interested listener. Anything that doesn’t heighten the intensity of the struggle or contribute to the outcome of success or failure is left out. Events are reordered to fit the mood of the story. In this way, early humans, when left alone and not directly engaged in the fight for survival, lived in a memory world filled with suggestions. A suggestion is different from a recollection in that there's no effort made to verify its accuracy. Its accuracy is relatively insignificant. The cloud might suggest a camel or a person's face. It could only suggest these things if there had once been a true, literal experience with both a camel and a face. But the actual resemblance doesn't really matter. What’s important is the emotional engagement in tracing the camel or following the changing features of the face as it comes together and then fades away.
Students of the primitive history of mankind tell of the enormous part played by animal tales, myths and cults. Sometimes a mystery is made out of this historical fact, as if it indicated that primitive man was moved by a different psychology from that which now animates humanity. But the explanation is, I think, simple. Until agriculture and the higher industrial arts were developed, long periods of empty leisure alternated with comparatively short periods of energy put forth to secure food or safety from attack. Because of our own habits, we tend to think of people as busy or occupied, if not with doing at least with thinking and planning. But then men were busy only when engaged in the hunt or fishing or fighting expedition. Yet the mind when awake must have some filling; it cannot remain literally vacant because the body is idle. And what thoughts should crowd into the human mind except experiences with animals, experiences transformed under the influence of dramatic interest to make more vivid and coherent the events typical of the chase? As men in fancy dramatically re-lived the interesting parts of their actual lives, animals inevitably became themselves dramatized.
Students of early human history discuss the significant role that animal stories, myths, and rituals played. Sometimes, this historical fact is framed as a mystery, suggesting that primitive people were influenced by a different mindset than we have today. But I believe the explanation is straightforward. Before the development of agriculture and advanced industrial techniques, long stretches of free time alternated with shorter bursts of energy dedicated to finding food or defending against attacks. Due to our contemporary habits, we tend to view people as busy or engaged, whether in action or just in thought and planning. However, back then, individuals were only busy during hunting, fishing, or combat. Yet, when the mind is active, it needs some stimulation; it can't just be empty because the body is idle. What thoughts would fill a person's mind other than their experiences with animals, experiences that were transformed by dramatic interest to make the typical events of the hunt more vivid and coherent? As people imaginatively re-lived the most captivating parts of their lives, animals naturally became dramatized as well.
They were true dramatis personæ and as such assumed the traits of persons. They too had desires,[Pg 5] hopes and fears, a life of affections, loves and hates, triumphs and defeats. Moreover, since they were essential to the support of the community, their activities and sufferings made them, in the imagination which dramatically revived the past, true sharers in the life of the community. Although they were hunted, yet they permitted themselves after all to be caught, and hence they were friends and allies. They devoted themselves, quite literally, to the sustenance and well-being of the community group to which they belonged. Thus were produced not merely the multitude of tales and legends dwelling affectionately upon the activities and features of animals, but also those elaborate rites and cults which made animals ancestors, heroes, tribal figure-heads and divinities.
They were real dramatis personæ and, as such, took on the characteristics of people. They had desires, [Pg 5] hopes and fears, a life filled with love, affection, hate, triumphs, and failures. Furthermore, because they were essential to the community's survival, their actions and struggles made them, in the imagination that dramatically brought the past to life, true participants in the community. Even though they were hunted, they ultimately allowed themselves to be caught, and so they became friends and allies. They devoted themselves, quite literally, to the support and well-being of the community group they were a part of. This resulted in not just a wealth of stories and legends that celebrated the actions and qualities of animals, but also in the intricate rites and traditions that honored animals as ancestors, heroes, tribal leaders, and deities.
I hope that I do not seem to you to have gone too far afield from my topic, the origin of philosophies. For it seems to me that the historic source of philosophies cannot be understood except as we dwell, at even greater length and in more detail, upon such considerations as these. We need to recognize that the ordinary consciousness of the ordinary man left to himself is a creature of desires rather than of intellectual study, inquiry or speculation. Man ceases to be primarily actuated by hopes and fears, loves and hates, only when he is subjected to a discipline which is foreign to human nature, which is, from the stand[Pg 6]point of natural man, artificial. Naturally our books, our scientific and philosophical books, are written by men who have subjected themselves in a superior degree to intellectual discipline and culture. Their thoughts are habitually reasonable. They have learned to check their fancies by facts, and to organize their ideas logically rather than emotionally and dramatically. When they do indulge in reverie and day-dreaming—which is probably more of the time than is conventionally acknowledged—they are aware of what they are doing. They label these excursions, and do not confuse their results with objective experiences. We tend to judge others by ourselves, and because scientific and philosophic books are composed by men in whom the reasonable, logical and objective habit of mind predominates, a similar rationality has been attributed by them to the average and ordinary man. It is then overlooked that both rationality and irrationality are largely irrelevant and episodical in undisciplined human nature; that men are governed by memory rather than by thought, and that memory is not a remembering of actual facts, but is association, suggestion, dramatic fancy. The standard used to measure the value of the suggestions that spring up in the mind is not congruity with fact but emotional congeniality. Do they stimulate and reinforce feeling, and fit into the dramatic tale? Are they consonant with the prevailing mood, and can[Pg 7] they be rendered into the traditional hopes and fears of the community? If we are willing to take the word dreams with a certain liberality, it is hardly too much to say that man, save in his occasional times of actual work and struggle, lives in a world of dreams, rather than of facts, and a world of dreams that is organized about desires whose success and frustration form its stuff.
I hope I don't seem to have strayed too far from my topic, the origin of philosophies. It seems to me that understanding the historical source of philosophies requires us to delve even deeper into considerations like these. We need to acknowledge that the average person's mind, when left to its own devices, is driven more by desires than by intellectual study, inquiry, or speculation. A person stops being primarily motivated by hopes and fears, loves and hates, only when subjected to a discipline that goes against human nature, which seems artificial from the standpoint of a naturally inclined person. Naturally, our books—our scientific and philosophical writings—are created by individuals who have committed themselves to a higher degree of intellectual discipline and culture. Their thoughts are typically logical. They know how to ground their ideas in facts and organize them logically rather than emotionally or dramatically. When they indulge in daydreaming, which is probably more often than is usually recognized, they are aware of what they're doing. They label these excursions and don't confuse the outcomes with actual experiences. We tend to evaluate others based on ourselves, and because scientific and philosophical works are written by people who predominantly embody rational, logical, and objective thinking, a similar rationality is often mistakenly attributed to the average person. It’s overlooked that both rationality and irrationality are mostly irrelevant and sporadic in the undisciplined human mind; people are driven by memory rather than thought, and memory doesn't just recall actual facts but is more about associations, suggestions, and dramatic imagination. The standard for judging the value of suggestions that arise in our minds is not their alignment with facts but how well they resonate emotionally. Do they provoke and reinforce feelings? Do they fit into the narrative? Are they in tune with the current mood and can they be expressed in the traditional hopes and fears of the community? If we can be a bit flexible with the term “dreams,” it’s not too much to say that except during moments of real work and struggle, humans live in a world of dreams rather than facts, a world organized around desires whose fulfilment and frustration form its essence.
To treat the early beliefs and traditions of mankind as if they were attempts at scientific explanation of the world, only erroneous and absurd attempts, is thus to be guilty of a great mistake. The material out of which philosophy finally emerges is irrelevant to science and to explanation. It is figurative, symbolic of fears and hopes, made of imaginations and suggestions, not significant of a world of objective fact intellectually confronted. It is poetry and drama, rather than science, and is apart from scientific truth and falsity, rationality or absurdity of fact in the same way in which poetry is independent of these things.
To treat the early beliefs and traditions of humanity as if they were just misguided scientific attempts to explain the world is a big mistake. The material that ultimately leads to philosophy doesn't have anything to do with science or explanation. It's figurative, symbolizing fears and hopes, made up of imagination and suggestions, not a reflection of a world of objective facts faced intellectually. It’s more like poetry and drama instead of science, and it's separate from scientific truth or falsehood, rationality, or absurdity in the same way that poetry is independent of those things.
This original material has, however, to pass through at least two stages before it becomes philosophy proper. One is the stage in which stories and legends and their accompanying dramatizations are consolidated. At first the emotionalized records of experiences are largely casual and transitory. Events that excite the emotions of an individual are seized upon and lived over in tale[Pg 8] and pantomime. But some experiences are so frequent and recurrent that they concern the group as a whole. They are socially generalized. The piecemeal adventure of the single individual is built out till it becomes representative and typical of the emotional life of the tribe. Certain incidents affect the weal and woe of the group in its entirety and thereby get an exceptional emphasis and elevation. A certain texture of tradition is built up; the story becomes a social heritage and possession; the pantomime develops into the stated rite. Tradition thus formed becomes a kind of norm to which individual fancy and suggestion conform. An abiding framework of imagination is constructed. A communal way of conceiving life grows up into which individuals are inducted by education. Both unconsciously and by definite social requirement individual memories are assimilated to group memory or tradition, and individual fancies are accommodated to the body of beliefs characteristic of a community. Poetry becomes fixated and systematized. The story becomes a social norm. The original drama which re-enacts an emotionally important experience is institutionalized into a cult. Suggestions previously free are hardened into doctrines.
This original material has to go through at least two stages before it turns into proper philosophy. The first stage involves consolidating stories, legends, and their accompanying dramatizations. Initially, the emotional accounts of experiences are mostly casual and fleeting. Events that stir strong emotions in a person are captured and relived through tales[Pg 8] and performance. However, some experiences happen so often that they relate to the group as a whole. They become socially generalized. The individual’s piecemeal adventures expand until they reflect the emotional life of the community. Certain events significantly impact the group’s well-being and hence receive special emphasis and prominence. A specific texture of tradition develops; the story transforms into a social heritage and collective possession; the performance evolves into a formal ritual. The tradition formed becomes a kind of standard that aligns individual creativity and ideas with it. A lasting framework of imagination is built. A shared way of understanding life emerges, into which individuals are guided through education. Both unconsciously and through explicit social norms, personal memories are integrated into the group’s memory or tradition, and individual creative thoughts align with the community's beliefs. Poetry becomes fixed and organized. The story establishes itself as a social norm. The original drama, which reenacts an emotionally significant experience, becomes formalized into a ritual. Previously free suggestions solidify into doctrines.
The systematic and obligatory nature of such doctrines is hastened and confirmed through conquests and political consolidation. As the area of a government is extended, there is a definite motive for systematizing[Pg 9] and unifying beliefs once free and floating. Aside from natural accommodation and assimilation springing from the fact of intercourse and the needs of common understanding, there is often political necessity which leads the ruler to centralize traditions and beliefs in order to extend and strengthen his prestige and authority. Judea, Greece, Rome, and I presume all other countries having a long history, present records of a continual working over of earlier local rites and doctrines in the interests of a wider social unity and a more extensive political power. I shall ask you to assume with me that in this way the larger cosmogonies and cosmologies of the race as well as the larger ethical traditions have arisen. Whether this is literally so or not, it is not necessary to inquire, much less to demonstrate. It is enough for our purposes that under social influences there took place a fixing and organizing of doctrines and cults which gave general traits to the imagination and general rules to conduct, and that such a consolidation was a necessary antecedent to the formation of any philosophy as we understand that term.
The systematic and mandatory nature of these doctrines is accelerated and reinforced through conquests and political consolidation. As a government expands its territory, there is a clear incentive to systematize and unify beliefs that were once fluid and independent. Beyond the natural accommodation and assimilation that come from interaction and the need for mutual understanding, there is often a political necessity that drives leaders to centralize traditions and beliefs to enhance their prestige and authority. Judea, Greece, Rome, and likely all other countries with long histories show evidence of continuously reshaping earlier local practices and doctrines to promote greater social unity and broader political power. I ask you to consider with me that this is how the larger cosmogonies, cosmologies, and ethical traditions of humanity have developed. Whether this is literally true or not is not essential to investigate or prove. It suffices for our discussion that social influences led to the solidification and organization of doctrines and cults, which provided common characteristics to imagination and universal guidelines for behavior, and that this consolidation was a necessary precursor to the development of any philosophy as we understand it today.
Although a necessary antecedent, this organization and generalization of ideas and principles of belief is not the sole and sufficient generator of philosophy. There is still lacking the motive for logical system and intellectual proof. This we may suppose to be furnished by the need of reconciling the moral rules and ideals em[Pg 10]bodied in the traditional code with the matter of fact positivistic knowledge which gradually grows up. For man can never be wholly the creature of suggestion and fancy. The requirements of continued existence make indispensable some attention to the actual facts of the world. Although it is surprising how little check the environment actually puts upon the formation of ideas, since no notions are too absurd not to have been accepted by some people, yet the environment does enforce a certain minimum of correctness under penalty of extinction. That certain things are foods, that they are to be found in certain places, that water drowns, fire burns, that sharp points penetrate and cut, that heavy things fall unless supported, that there is a certain regularity in the changes of day and night and the alternation of hot and cold, wet and dry:—such prosaic facts force themselves upon even primitive attention. Some of them are so obvious and so important that they have next to no fanciful context. Auguste Comte says somewhere that he knows of no savage people who had a God of weight although every other natural quality or force may have been deified. Gradually there grows up a body of homely generalizations preserving and transmitting the wisdom of the race about the observed facts and sequences of nature. This knowledge is especially connected with industries, arts and crafts where observation of materials and processes[Pg 11] is required for successful action, and where action is so continuous and regular that spasmodic magic will not suffice. Extravagantly fantastic notions are eliminated because they are brought into juxtaposition with what actually happens.
Although it's a necessary starting point, organizing and generalizing ideas and beliefs isn't the only thing that creates philosophy. We still need a motivation for logical systems and intellectual proof. This motivation likely comes from the need to reconcile the moral rules and ideals within traditional codes with the factual, positivistic knowledge that gradually develops. People can never be completely swayed by suggestion and imagination. The need for ongoing survival demands some focus on the real facts of the world. It's surprising how little the environment actually restricts the formation of ideas, since there are no notions too absurd to be accepted by some individuals. However, the environment does impose a minimum level of correctness under the threat of extinction. Certain things are recognized as food, found in specific locations; water can drown, fire can burn, sharp objects can pierce and cut, heavy items will fall unless supported, and there's a regularity to the cycles of day and night and shifts in hot and cold, wet and dry—these practical facts make an impression even on the most primitive observations. Some are so obvious and important that they hardly have any fanciful context. Auguste Comte mentions that he knows of no primitive society that worshipped a God of weight, even though they may have deified every other natural quality or force. Over time, a body of straightforward generalizations develops that preserves and passes on the wisdom of the race regarding observed facts and natural sequences. This knowledge is particularly tied to industries, arts, and crafts, where careful observation of materials and processes is necessary for successful action, and where actions are so consistent and regular that sporadic magic won't suffice. Outlandishly fantastical ideas get weeded out because they're compared with what actually occurs.
The sailor is more likely to be given to what we now term superstitions than say the weaver, because his activity is more at the mercy of sudden change and unforeseen occurrence. But even the sailor while he may regard the wind as the uncontrollable expression of the caprice of a great spirit, will still have to become acquainted with some purely mechanical principles of adjustment of boat, sails and oar to the wind. Fire may be conceived as a supernatural dragon because some time or other a swift, bright and devouring flame called before the mind's eye the quick-moving and dangerous serpent. But the housewife who tends the fire and the pots wherein food cooks will still be compelled to observe certain mechanical facts of draft and replenishment, and passage from wood to ash. Still more will the worker in metals accumulate verifiable details about the conditions and consequences of the operation of heat. He may retain for special and ceremonial occasions traditional beliefs, but everyday familiar use will expel these conceptions for the greater part of the time, when fire will be to him of uniform and prosaic behavior, controllable by practical relations of cause and effect.[Pg 12] As the arts and crafts develop and become more elaborate, the body of positive and tested knowledge enlarges, and the sequences observed become more complex and of greater scope. Technologies of this kind give that common-sense knowledge of nature out of which science takes its origin. They provide not merely a collection of positive facts, but they give expertness in dealing with materials and tools, and promote the development of the experimental habit of mind, as soon as an art can be taken away from the rule of sheer custom.
The sailor is more likely to believe in what we now call superstitions compared to, say, the weaver, because his work is more subject to unexpected changes and surprises. However, even the sailor, while he might see the wind as the unpredictable will of a great spirit, still needs to learn the basic mechanical principles for adjusting his boat, sails, and oars to the wind. Fire can be imagined as a supernatural dragon because at some point a quick, bright, and consuming flame evoked the image of a fast-moving and dangerous serpent. Yet the housewife who manages the fire and the pots cooking food must also pay attention to certain mechanical realities of airflow and replenishment, and the transformation from wood to ash. Even more so, the metalworker will gather concrete information about how heat operates and its effects. He may hold onto traditional beliefs for special ceremonies, but in everyday use, these ideas will mostly fade away, making fire seem consistent and ordinary to him, governed by practical cause-and-effect relationships.[Pg 12] As arts and crafts evolve and become more intricate, the amount of verified knowledge expands, and the observed sequences become more complex and broader in scope. These kinds of technologies provide a practical understanding of nature from which science originates. They not only compile positive facts but also develop expertise in handling materials and tools, and foster a mindset geared towards experimentation, as soon as an art can move beyond mere tradition.
For a long time the imaginative body of beliefs closely connected with the moral habits of a community group and with its emotional indulgences and consolations persists side by side with the growing body of matter of fact knowledge. Wherever possible they are interlaced. At other points, their inconsistencies forbid their interweaving, but the two things are kept apart as if in different compartments. Since one is merely super-imposed upon the other their incompatibility is not felt, and there is no need of reconciliation. In most cases, the two kinds of mental products are kept apart because they become the possession of separate social classes. The religious and poetic beliefs having acquired a definite social and political value and function are in the keeping of a higher class directly associated with the ruling elements in the society. The workers and craftsmen who possess the prosaic matter of fact knowledge[Pg 13] are likely to occupy a low social status, and their kind of knowledge is affected by the social disesteem entertained for the manual worker who engages in activities useful to the body. It doubtless was this fact in Greece which in spite of the keenness of observation, the extraordinary power of logical reasoning and the great freedom of speculation attained by the Athenian, postponed the general and systematic employment of the experimental method. Since the industrial craftsman was only just above the slave in social rank, his type of knowledge and the method upon which it depended lacked prestige and authority.
For a long time, the imaginative set of beliefs tied to the moral behaviors of a community and its emotional comforts and supports has existed alongside the increasing amount of factual knowledge. Whenever possible, they are intertwined. In other places, their inconsistencies prevent them from blending, but the two remain separate as if in different boxes. Since one simply layers over the other, their incompatibility is not felt, and there's no need for reconciliation. Usually, these two types of thought are kept apart because they belong to different social classes. The religious and poetic beliefs, having gained distinct social and political importance, are held by a higher class linked to the ruling elements of society. The workers and craftsmen who have the straightforward factual knowledge[Pg 13] are likely to be in a low social position, and their kind of knowledge is affected by the social disdain directed at manual workers who engage in activities beneficial to the body. This reality in Greece likely contributed to the delay in the widespread and systematic use of the experimental method, despite the Athenians' keen observation, exceptional logical reasoning, and great freedom of speculation. Since the industrial craftsman was only slightly above a slave in social ranking, his type of knowledge and the method it relied on lacked prestige and authority.
Nevertheless, the time came when matter of fact knowledge increased to such bulk and scope that it came into conflict with not merely the detail but with the spirit and temper of traditional and imaginative beliefs. Without going into the vexed question of how and why, there is no doubt that this is just what happened in what we term the sophistic movement in Greece, within which originated philosophy proper in the sense in which the western world understands that term. The fact that the sophists had a bad name given them by Plato and Aristotle, a name they have never been able to shake off, is evidence that with the sophists the strife between the two types of belief was the emphatic thing, and that the conflict had a disconcerting effect upon the traditional system of religious beliefs and the[Pg 14] moral code of conduct bound up with it. Although Socrates was doubtless sincerely interested in the reconciliation of the two sides, yet the fact that he approached the matter from the side of matter of fact method, giving its canons and criteria primacy, was enough to bring him to the condemnation of death as a contemner of the gods and a corrupter of youth.
Nevertheless, the time came when factual knowledge grew so vast and comprehensive that it clashed not only with the details but also with the spirit and attitude of traditional and imaginative beliefs. Without diving into the complicated question of how and why this happened, there's no denying that this is exactly what took place during what we call the sophistic movement in Greece, which gave rise to philosophy in the way the Western world understands it. The fact that the sophists earned a bad reputation from Plato and Aristotle—a reputation they have never been able to shake off—shows that the conflict between these two types of belief was a significant issue, and that it disrupted the traditional system of religious beliefs and the[Pg 14] moral code associated with it. While Socrates was genuinely interested in reconciling both sides, his approach from a factual method, prioritizing its principles and criteria, was enough to lead to his condemnation to death for being a contemptor of the gods and a corrupter of youth.
The fate of Socrates and the ill-fame of the sophists may be used to suggest some of the striking contrasts between traditional emotionalized belief on one hand and prosaic matter of fact knowledge on the other:—the purpose of the comparison being to bring out the point that while all the advantages of what we call science were on the side of the latter, the advantages of social esteem and authority, and of intimate contact with what gives life its deeper lying values were on the side of traditional belief. To all appearances, the specific and verified knowledge of the environment had only a limited and technical scope. It had to do with the arts, and the purpose and good of the artisan after all did not extend very far. They were subordinate and almost servile. Who would put the art of the shoemaker on the same plane as the art of ruling the state? Who would put even the higher art of the physician in healing the body, upon the level of the art of the priest in healing the soul? Thus Plato constantly[Pg 15] draws the contrast in his dialogues. The shoemaker is a judge of a good pair of shoes, but he is no judge at all of the more important question whether and when it is good to wear shoes; the physician is a good judge of health, but whether it is a good thing or not to be well or better to die, he knows not. While the artisan is expert as long as purely limited technical questions arise, he is helpless when it comes to the only really important questions, the moral questions as to values. Consequently, his type of knowledge is inherently inferior and needs to be controlled by a higher kind of knowledge which will reveal ultimate ends and purposes, and thus put and keep technical and mechanical knowledge in its proper place. Moreover, in Plato's pages we find, because of Plato's adequate dramatic sense, a lively depicting of the impact in particular men of the conflict between tradition and the new claims of purely intellectual knowledge. The conservative is shocked beyond measure at the idea of teaching the military art by abstract rules, by science. One does not just fight, one fights for one's country. Abstract science cannot convey love and loyalty, nor can it be a substitute, even upon the more technical side, for those ways and means of fighting in which devotion to the country has been traditionally embodied.
The fate of Socrates and the bad reputation of the sophists highlight the stark differences between traditional emotional beliefs and straightforward, factual knowledge. The purpose of this comparison is to emphasize that while science offers many advantages, social esteem, authority, and a deep connection to the values that give life meaning come from traditional beliefs. On the surface, specific and verified knowledge about the environment seems limited and technical. It relates to the trades, and the benefits of the artisan's work don’t extend very far; they seem subordinate and almost servile. Who would compare a shoemaker's craft to the art of governing a state? Who would place the physician's skill in healing the body on the same level as a priest's role in healing the soul? In his dialogues, Plato consistently illustrates this contrast. The shoemaker knows what makes a good pair of shoes, but he can’t judge when or if it's appropriate to wear them. The physician can assess health, but he has no understanding of whether being well is a good thing or if dying might be preferable. While artisans are knowledgeable about limited technical issues, they struggle with the essential moral questions about values. Therefore, their type of knowledge is inherently inferior and must be guided by a higher knowledge that reveals ultimate goals and purposes, keeping technical and mechanical understanding in its rightful place. Furthermore, Plato's strong sense of drama vividly depicts how individuals are affected by the struggle between tradition and the new demands of purely intellectual knowledge. Conservatives are horrified at the thought of teaching military skills through abstract rules or science. Fighting isn’t just about the act; it’s about fighting for one’s country. Abstract science can’t communicate love and loyalty, nor can it replace the customary methods of fighting that embody devotion to the nation.
The way to learn the fighting art is through association with those who have themselves learned to defend[Pg 16] the country, by becoming saturated with its ideals and customs; by becoming in short a practical adept in the Greek tradition as to fighting. To attempt to derive abstract rules from a comparison of native ways of fighting with the enemies' ways is to begin to go over to the enemies' traditions and gods: it is to begin to be false to one's own country.
The best way to learn the art of fighting is to connect with those who have mastered the skills to defend[Pg 16] the nation, by fully embracing its values and customs; in short, by becoming a practical expert in the Greek way of fighting. Trying to create abstract rules by comparing our fighting styles to those of our enemies is basically starting to adopt their traditions and beliefs: it means beginning to turn against your own country.
Such a point of view vividly realized enables us to appreciate the antagonism aroused by the positivistic point of view when it came into conflict with the traditional. The latter was deeply rooted in social habits and loyalties; it was surcharged with the moral aims for which men lived and the moral rules by which they lived. Hence it was as basic and as comprehensive as life itself, and palpitated with the warm glowing colors of the community life in which men realized their own being. In contrast, the positivistic knowledge was concerned with merely physical utilities, and lacked the ardent associations of belief hallowed by sacrifices of ancestors and worship of contemporaries. Because of its limited and concrete character it was dry, hard, cold.
Such a perspective clearly shows us the conflict sparked by the positivistic viewpoint when it clashed with traditional beliefs. The traditional view was deeply embedded in social customs and loyalties; it was filled with the moral purposes for which people lived and the moral guidelines they followed. Therefore, it was fundamental and all-encompassing, pulsating with the vibrant essence of community life where people found their identity. In comparison, positivistic knowledge focused only on practical uses and lacked the passionate connections of beliefs honored by the sacrifices of ancestors and the reverence of peers. Due to its narrow and concrete nature, it felt dry, rigid, and cold.
Yet the more acute and active minds, like that of Plato himself, could no longer be content to accept, along with the conservative citizen of the time, the old beliefs in the old way. The growth of positive knowledge and of the critical, inquiring spirit under[Pg 17]mined these in their old form. The advantages in definiteness, in accuracy, in verifiability were all on the side of the new knowledge. Tradition was noble in aim and scope, but uncertain in foundation. The unquestioned life, said Socrates, was not one fit to be lived by man, who is a questioning being because he is a rational being. Hence he must search out the reason of things, and not accept them from custom and political authority. What was to be done? Develop a method of rational investigation and proof which should place the essential elements of traditional belief upon an unshakable basis; develop a method of thought and knowledge which while purifying tradition should preserve its moral and social values unimpaired; nay, by purifying them, add to their power and authority. To put it in a word, that which had rested upon custom was to be restored, resting no longer upon the habits of the past, but upon the very metaphysics of Being and the Universe. Metaphysics is a substitute for custom as the source and guarantor of higher moral and social values—that is the leading theme of the classic philosophy of Europe, as evolved by Plato and Aristotle—a philosophy, let us always recall, renewed and restated by the Christian philosophy of Medieval Europe.
Yet the sharper and more active minds, like Plato's own, could no longer be satisfied with the old beliefs and traditional thinking that typical citizens accepted. The rise of concrete knowledge and a critical, questioning attitude under[Pg 17]undermined these old views in their former guise. The benefits of clarity, accuracy, and verifiability all favored the new knowledge. Tradition was admirable in purpose and reach, but shaky in foundation. Socrates stated that an unquestioned life was not one that a human, as a rational being, should live. Therefore, he must seek out the reasons behind things rather than simply accept them based on custom and political authority. What was to be done? Create a method of rational investigation and proof that would place the core elements of traditional belief on a solid foundation; develop a way of thinking and knowing that, while purifying tradition, would maintain its moral and social values intact; indeed, by purifying them, enhance their power and authority. In short, what had relied on custom would be restored, not through past habits, but through the very metaphysics of Being and the Universe. Metaphysics serves as a replacement for custom as the source and guarantor of higher moral and social values—that is the central theme of the classic philosophy of Europe, as developed by Plato and Aristotle—a philosophy, let us never forget, renewed and redefined by the Christian philosophy of Medieval Europe.
Out of this situation emerged, if I mistake not, the entire tradition regarding the function and office of[Pg 18] philosophy which till very recently has controlled the systematic and constructive philosophies of the western world. If I am right in my main thesis that the origin of philosophy lay in an attempt to reconcile the two different types of mental product, then the key is in our hands as to the main traits of subsequent philosophy so far as that was not of a negative and heterodox kind. In the first place, philosophy did not develop in an unbiased way from an open and unprejudiced origin. It had its task cut out for it from the start. It had a mission to perform, and it was sworn in advance to that mission. It had to extract the essential moral kernel out of the threatened traditional beliefs of the past. So far so good; the work was critical and in the interests of the only true conservatism—that which will conserve and not waste the values wrought out by humanity. But it was also precommitted to extracting this moral essence in a spirit congenial to the spirit of past beliefs. The association with imagination and with social authority was too intimate to be deeply disturbed. It was not possible to conceive of the content of social institutions in any form radically different from that in which they had existed in the past. It became the work of philosophy to justify on rational grounds the spirit, though not the form, of accepted beliefs and traditional customs.
Out of this situation came, if I'm not mistaken, the entire tradition regarding the role and purpose of[Pg 18] philosophy, which until very recently has shaped the systematic and constructive philosophies of the Western world. If I'm correct in my main argument that the origin of philosophy was an attempt to reconcile two different types of mental products, then we hold the key to understanding the main characteristics of later philosophy, as long as it wasn't negative or unconventional. First, philosophy did not develop in an unbiased manner from a neutral and open origin. It had a clear mission from the start. It was tasked with extracting the essential moral core from the threatened traditional beliefs of the past. That was fine; the work was critical and in favor of the only true conservatism—one that preserves and values what humanity has built. But it was also committed to extracting this moral essence in a way that aligned with the spirit of past beliefs. The connection with imagination and social authority was too close to be significantly disrupted. It was not possible to envision the content of social institutions in any form radically different from how they had existed in the past. Philosophy's role became to rationally justify the spirit, though not the form, of accepted beliefs and traditional customs.
The resulting philosophy seemed radical enough and[Pg 19] even dangerous to the average Athenian because of the difference of form and method. In the sense of pruning away excrescences and eliminating factors which to the average citizen were all one with the basic beliefs, it was radical. But looked at in the perspective of history and in contrast with different types of thought which developed later in different social environments, it is now easy to see how profoundly, after all, Plato and Aristotle reflected the meaning of Greek tradition and habit, so that their writings remain, with the writings of the great dramatists, the best introduction of a student into the innermost ideals and aspirations of distinctively Greek life. Without Greek religion, Greek art, Greek civic life, their philosophy would have been impossible; while the effect of that science upon which the philosophers most prided themselves turns out to have been superficial and negligible. This apologetic spirit of philosophy is even more apparent when Medieval Christianity about the twelfth century sought for a systematic rational presentation of itself and made use of classic philosophy, especially that of Aristotle, to justify itself to reason. A not unsimilar occurrence characterizes the chief philosophic systems of Germany in the early nineteenth century, when Hegel assumed the task of justifying in the name of rational idealism the doctrines and institutions which were menaced by the new spirit of science and popular government. The[Pg 20] result has been that the great systems have not been free from party spirit exercised in behalf of preconceived beliefs. Since they have at the same time professed complete intellectual independence and rationality, the result has been too often to impart to philosophy an element of insincerity, all the more insidious because wholly unconscious on the part of those who sustained philosophy.
The resulting philosophy seemed radical and[Pg 19] even dangerous to the average Athenian because of its different form and approach. It was radical in the way it trimmed away unnecessary parts and removed factors that seemed essential to the basic beliefs of the average citizen. However, from a historical perspective and when compared with other types of thought that emerged later in various social contexts, it's clear how deeply Plato and Aristotle reflected Greek tradition and customs, making their writings, along with those of the great dramatists, the best introduction for students to the core ideals and aspirations of distinctly Greek life. Without Greek religion, art, or civic life, their philosophy wouldn't have been possible; meanwhile, the science that the philosophers were most proud of turned out to be superficial and insignificant. This apologetic spirit of philosophy is even more evident when Medieval Christianity around the twelfth century sought a systematic and rational way to present itself, using classical philosophy, especially Aristotle's, to justify itself to reason. A similar situation characterized the main philosophical systems in Germany in the early nineteenth century when Hegel took on the task of justifying doctrines and institutions under threat from the new spirit of science and popular government in the name of rational idealism. The[Pg 20] result has been that these grand systems often showed signs of bias in support of predetermined beliefs. Since they also claimed complete intellectual independence and rationality, this led to an element of insincerity in philosophy, which was even more insidious because it was completely unconscious on the part of those who upheld philosophy.
And this brings us to a second trait of philosophy springing from its origin. Since it aimed at a rational justification of things that had been previously accepted because of their emotional congeniality and social prestige, it had to make much of the apparatus of reason and proof. Because of the lack of intrinsic rationality in the matters with which it dealt, it leaned over backward, so to speak, in parade of logical form. In dealing with matters of fact, simpler and rougher ways of demonstration may be resorted to. It is enough, so to say, to produce the fact in question and point to it—the fundamental form of all demonstration. But when it comes to convincing men of the truth of doctrines which are no longer to be accepted upon the say-so of custom and social authority, but which also are not capable of empirical verification, there is no recourse save to magnify the signs of rigorous thought and rigid demonstration. Thus arises that appearance of abstract definition and ultra-scientific argumentation[Pg 21] which repels so many from philosophy but which has been one of its chief attractions to its devotees.
And this brings us to a second characteristic of philosophy stemming from its origin. Since it aimed to provide a rational justification for things that had previously been accepted due to their emotional appeal and social status, it had to heavily emphasize the tools of reason and proof. Because of the lack of inherent logic in the subjects it addressed, it exaggerated the use of logical structure, so to speak. When discussing matters of fact, simpler and more straightforward methods of demonstration can be used. It's enough, so to speak, to present the fact in question and point to it—the basic form of all demonstration. But when it comes to convincing people of the truth of ideas that can no longer be accepted just based on tradition and social authority, and which also can't be verified through experience, the only option is to emphasize the markers of rigorous thought and strict demonstration. This creates that impression of abstract definitions and overly scientific arguments[Pg 21] that pushes many away from philosophy but has been one of its main appeals to its followers.
At the worst, this has reduced philosophy to a show of elaborate terminology, a hair-splitting logic, and a fictitious devotion to the mere external forms of comprehensive and minute demonstration. Even at the best, it has tended to produce an overdeveloped attachment to system for its own sake, and an over-pretentious claim to certainty. Bishop Butler declared that probability is the guide of life; but few philosophers have been courageous enough to avow that philosophy can be satisfied with anything that is merely probable. The customs dictated by tradition and desire had claimed finality and immutability. They had claimed to give certain and unvarying laws of conduct. Very early in its history philosophy made pretension to a similar conclusiveness, and something of this temper has clung to classic philosophies ever since. They have insisted that they were more scientific than the sciences—that, indeed, philosophy was necessary because after all the special sciences fail in attaining final and complete truth. There have been a few dissenters who have ventured to assert, as did William James, that "philosophy is vision" and that its chief function is to free men's minds from bias and prejudice and to enlarge their perceptions of the world about them. But in the main philosophy has set up much more ambitious pretensions.[Pg 22] To say frankly that philosophy can proffer nothing but hypotheses, and that these hypotheses are of value only as they render men's minds more sensitive to life about them, would seem like a negation of philosophy itself.
At its worst, this has turned philosophy into a display of complex terminology, overly detailed logic, and a fake commitment to just the surface aspects of thorough and detailed argumentation. Even at its best, it has led to an excessive focus on systems for their own sake, and an overly pretentious claim to certainty. Bishop Butler said that probability is life's guide; but few philosophers have been brave enough to admit that philosophy can be content with anything that's just probable. Customs shaped by tradition and desire have claimed to be final and unchanging. They insisted on providing definitive and fixed laws of conduct. Early on in its history, philosophy claimed a similar finality, and some of this mindset has lingered in classical philosophies ever since. They have insisted that they are more scientific than the sciences—that, in fact, philosophy is necessary because the special sciences ultimately fail to reach full and complete truth. There have been a few dissenters who dared to claim, like William James did, that "philosophy is vision" and that its main role is to free people's minds from bias and prejudice and to broaden their understanding of the world around them. But overall, philosophy has set much more ambitious claims.[Pg 22] To say outright that philosophy can offer nothing but hypotheses, and that these hypotheses are valuable only as they make people's minds more attuned to life around them, would seem like a denial of philosophy itself.
In the third place, the body of beliefs dictated by desire and imagination and developed under the influence of communal authority into an authoritative tradition, was pervasive and comprehensive. It was, so to speak, omnipresent in all the details of the group life. Its pressure was unremitting and its influence universal. It was then probably inevitable that the rival principle, reflective thought, should aim at a similar universality and comprehensiveness. It would be as inclusive and far-reaching metaphysically as tradition had been socially. Now there was just one way in which this pretension could be accomplished in conjunction with a claim of complete logical system and certainty.
In the third place, the set of beliefs shaped by desire and imagination, influenced by community authority into an established tradition, was widespread and all-encompassing. It was, in a sense, everywhere in every aspect of group life. Its impact was constant and its influence was total. Therefore, it was likely inevitable that the competing principle, reflective thought, would seek a similar level of universality and comprehensiveness. It aimed to be as inclusive and expansive metaphysically as tradition was socially. There was only one way this ambition could be achieved while also claiming a complete logical system and certainty.
All philosophies of the classic type have made a fixed and fundamental distinction between two realms of existence. One of these corresponds to the religious and supernatural world of popular tradition, which in its metaphysical rendering became the world of highest and ultimate reality. Since the final source and sanction of all important truths and rules of conduct in community life had been found in superior and[Pg 23] unquestioned religious beliefs, so the absolute and supreme reality of philosophy afforded the only sure guaranty of truth about empirical matters, and the sole rational guide to proper social institutions and individual behavior. Over against this absolute and noumenal reality which could be apprehended only by the systematic discipline of philosophy itself stood the ordinary empirical, relatively real, phenomenal world of everyday experience. It was with this world that the practical affairs and utilities of men were connected. It was to this imperfect and perishing world that matter of fact, positivistic science referred.
All classic philosophies have made a clear and fundamental distinction between two realms of existence. One of these corresponds to the religious and supernatural world of popular tradition, which in its metaphysical interpretation became the world of the highest ultimate reality. Since the ultimate source and authority of all significant truths and rules of conduct in community life had been found in superior and[Pg 23] unquestioned religious beliefs, the absolute and supreme reality of philosophy provided the only reliable guarantee of truth about empirical matters and the sole rational guide to proper social institutions and individual behavior. Against this absolute and noumenal reality, which could only be grasped through the systematic discipline of philosophy itself, stood the ordinary empirical, relatively real, phenomenal world of everyday experience. It was this world that was connected to the practical affairs and utilities of people. This imperfect and transient world was what matter-of-fact, positivistic science referred to.
This is the trait which, in my opinion, has affected most deeply the classic notion about the nature of philosophy. Philosophy has arrogated to itself the office of demonstrating the existence of a transcendent, absolute or inner reality and of revealing to man the nature and features of this ultimate and higher reality. It has therefore claimed that it was in possession of a higher organ of knowledge than is employed by positive science and ordinary practical experience, and that it is marked by a superior dignity and importance—a claim which is undeniable if philosophy leads man to proof and intuition of a Reality beyond that open to day-by-day life and the special sciences.
This is the trait that, in my view, has profoundly influenced the traditional idea of what philosophy is. Philosophy has taken on the role of proving the existence of a transcendent, absolute, or inner reality and of revealing to people the nature and characteristics of this ultimate, higher reality. It has thus asserted that it possesses a superior way of knowing compared to what is used by positive science and everyday practical experience and that it carries a greater dignity and importance—a claim that is undeniable if philosophy guides people to proof and insight into a Reality beyond what is accessible in daily life and the specific sciences.
This claim has, of course, been denied by various[Pg 24] philosophers from time to time. But for the most part these denials have been agnostic and sceptical. They have contented themselves with asserting that absolute and ultimate reality is beyond human ken. But they have not ventured to deny that such Reality would be the appropriate sphere for the exercise of philosophic knowledge provided only it were within the reach of human intelligence. Only comparatively recently has another conception of the proper office of philosophy arisen. This course of lectures will be devoted to setting forth this different conception of philosophy in some of its main contrasts to what this lecture has termed the classic conception. At this point, it can be referred to only by anticipation and in cursory fashion. It is implied in the account which has been given of the origin of philosophy out of the background of an authoritative tradition; a tradition originally dictated by man's imagination working under the influence of love and hate and in the interest of emotional excitement and satisfaction. Common frankness requires that it be stated that this account of the origin of philosophies claiming to deal with absolute Being in a systematic way has been given with malice prepense. It seems to me that this genetic method of approach is a more effective way of undermining this type of philosophic theorizing than any attempt at logical refutation could be.
This claim has, of course, been rejected by various[Pg 24] philosophers from time to time. However, for the most part, these rejections have been neutral and skeptical. They have simply claimed that absolute and ultimate reality is beyond human understanding. But they haven't gone so far as to deny that such Reality would be the right area for the exercise of philosophical knowledge if it were accessible to human intelligence. Only relatively recently has a different view of the role of philosophy emerged. This set of lectures will focus on presenting this alternative view of philosophy, highlighting its main contrasts with what this lecture has referred to as the classic view. At this moment, it can only be mentioned briefly and in passing. It is suggested in the discussion about the origins of philosophy stemming from an authoritative tradition; a tradition originally shaped by human imagination influenced by love and hate, and aimed at emotional excitement and satisfaction. It is necessary to state frankly that this account of the origins of philosophies claiming to address absolute Being in a systematic way has been presented with intentional bias. I believe this genetic approach to understanding is a more effective way of challenging this type of philosophical theorizing than any logical refutation could be.
If this lecture succeeds in leaving in your minds as a reasonable hypothesis the idea that philosophy originated not out of intellectual material, but out of social and emotional material, it will also succeed in leaving with you a changed attitude toward traditional philosophies. They will be viewed from a new angle and placed in a new light. New questions about them will be aroused and new standards for judging them will be suggested.
If this lecture manages to convince you that philosophy didn't come from just intellectual ideas, but from social and emotional experiences, it will also change how you view traditional philosophies. You’ll see them from a fresh perspective and in a new light. This will bring up new questions about them and suggest new ways to evaluate them.
If any one will commence without mental reservations to study the history of philosophy not as an isolated thing but as a chapter in the development of civilization and culture; if one will connect the story of philosophy with a study of anthropology, primitive life, the history of religion, literature and social institutions, it is confidently asserted that he will reach his own independent judgment as to the worth of the account which has been presented today. Considered in this way, the history of philosophy will take on a new significance. What is lost from the standpoint of would-be science is regained from the standpoint of humanity. Instead of the disputes of rivals about the nature of reality, we have the scene of human clash of social purpose and aspirations. Instead of impossible attempts to transcend experience, we have the significant record of the efforts of men to formulate the things of experience to which they are most deeply and passionately attached.[Pg 26] Instead of impersonal and purely speculative endeavors to contemplate as remote beholders the nature of absolute things-in-themselves, we have a living picture of the choice of thoughtful men about what they would have life to be, and to what ends they would have men shape their intelligent activities.
If anyone is willing to dive into the study of the history of philosophy without any mental reservations, viewing it not as something isolated but as a part of the overall development of civilization and culture; if one connects the story of philosophy with studies in anthropology, primitive life, the history of religion, literature, and social institutions, it's confidently stated that they will reach their own independent judgment regarding the value of the account presented today. Viewed this way, the history of philosophy gains new significance. What might be lost from a purely scientific perspective is regained from a human perspective. Instead of rival disputes over the nature of reality, we see a clash of social purposes and aspirations. Rather than fruitless attempts to go beyond experience, we have a significant record of people's efforts to articulate the experiences to which they feel most deeply and passionately connected. Instead of impersonal and purely speculative efforts to observe the nature of absolute things-in-themselves from a distance, we have a vivid picture of thoughtful people's choices about what they want life to be and the ends toward which they would guide their intelligent activities.[Pg 26]
Any one of you who arrives at such a view of past philosophy will of necessity be led to entertain a quite definite conception of the scope and aim of future philosophizing. He will inevitably be committed to the notion that what philosophy has been unconsciously, without knowing or intending it, and, so to speak, under cover, it must henceforth be openly and deliberately. When it is acknowledged that under disguise of dealing with ultimate reality, philosophy has been occupied with the precious values embedded in social traditions, that it has sprung from a clash of social ends and from a conflict of inherited institutions with incompatible contemporary tendencies, it will be seen that the task of future philosophy is to clarify men's ideas as to the social and moral strifes of their own day. Its aim is to become so far as is humanly possible an organ for dealing with these conflicts. That which may be pretentiously unreal when it is formulated in metaphysical distinctions becomes intensely significant when connected with the drama of the struggle of social beliefs and ideals. Philosophy which surrenders its somewhat[Pg 27] barren monopoly of dealings with Ultimate and Absolute Reality will find a compensation in enlightening the moral forces which move mankind and in contributing to the aspirations of men to attain to a more ordered and intelligent happiness.
Anyone who reaches this perspective on past philosophy will inevitably adopt a clearer understanding of the focus and purpose of future philosophical inquiry. They will be committed to the idea that philosophy, which has previously operated unconsciously and without clear intention, must now be practiced openly and purposefully. When we recognize that, beneath the façade of addressing ultimate reality, philosophy has been engaged with the valuable principles embedded in social traditions, arising from a clash of societal goals and conflicts between established institutions and incompatible contemporary views, it will become clear that the future task of philosophy is to clarify people's understanding of the social and moral conflicts of their time. Its goal is to serve, as much as humanly possible, as a means to address these conflicts. What may seem pretentiously insignificant when expressed in metaphysical terms becomes profoundly important when linked to the struggle of social beliefs and ideals. Philosophy that relinquishes its somewhat barren claim to be the sole authority on Ultimate and Absolute Reality will find rewards in shedding light on the moral forces that drive humanity and contributing to people's aspirations for a more organized and insightful happiness.
CHAPTER II
SOME HISTORICAL FACTORS IN PHILOSOPHICAL RECONSTRUCTION
Francis Bacon of the Elizabethan age is the great forerunner of the spirit of modern life. Though slight in accomplishment, as a prophet of new tendencies he is an outstanding figure of the world's intellectual life. Like many another prophet he suffers from confused intermingling of old and new. What is most significant in him has been rendered more or less familiar by the later course of events. But page after page is filled with matter which belongs to the past from which Bacon thought he had escaped. Caught between these two sources of easy disparagement, Bacon hardly receives his due as the real founder of modern thought, while he is praised for merits which scarcely belong to him, such as an alleged authorship of the specific methods of induction pursued by science. What makes Bacon memorable is that breezes blowing from a new world caught and filled his sails and stirred him to adventure in new seas. He never himself discovered the land of promise, but he proclaimed the new goal and by faith he descried its features from afar.
Francis Bacon from the Elizabethan era is a key precursor to the spirit of modern life. Although his achievements may seem limited, he stands out as a significant figure in the world's intellectual landscape for his foresight of new trends. Like many prophets, he struggles with the confusion of old and new ideas. Much of what is most important about him has become familiar through later developments. Yet, many pages are filled with ideas tied to the past that Bacon believed he had transcended. Torn between these two sources of easy criticism, Bacon often doesn’t get the recognition he deserves as the true founder of modern thought, while being credited with merits he didn’t really possess, like allegedly being the author of the specific methods of induction that science employs. What makes Bacon memorable is that he was inspired by fresh ideas from a new world, which motivated him to explore uncharted territories. He may not have discovered the promised land himself, but he announced this new objective and, through his vision, glimpsed its features from a distance.
The main traits of his thought put before our mind the larger features of a new spirit which was at work in causing intellectual reconstruction. They may suggest the social and historical forces out of which the new spirit was born. The best known aphorism of Bacon is that Knowledge is Power. Judged by this pragmatic criterion, he condemned the great body of learning then extant as not-knowledge, as pseudo- and pretentious-knowledge. For it did not give power. It was otiose, not operative. In his most extensive discussion he classified the learning of his day under three heads, delicate, fantastic and contentious. Under delicate learning, he included the literary learning which through the influence of the revival of ancient languages and literatures occupied so important a place in the intellectual life of the Renaissance. Bacon's condemnation is the more effective because he himself was a master of the classics and of all the graces and refinements which this literary study was intended to convey. In substance he anticipated most of the attacks which educational reformers since his time have made upon one-sided literary culture. It contributed not to power but to ornament and decoration. It was ostentatious and luxurious. By fantastic learning he meant the quasi-magical science that was so rife all over Europe in the sixteenth century—wild developments of alchemy, astrology, etc. Upon this he poured his greatest vials[Pg 30] of wrath because the corruption of the good is the worst of evils. Delicate learning was idle and vain, but fantastic learning aped the form of true knowledge. It laid hold of the true principle and aim of knowledge—control of natural forces. But it neglected the conditions and methods by which alone such knowledge could be obtained, and thus deliberately led men astray.
The main traits of his thought reveal the broader characteristics of a new mindset that was influencing intellectual transformation. They highlight the social and historical forces that shaped this new spirit. The most famous saying by Bacon is that Knowledge is Power. Based on this practical standard, he criticized the vast amount of existing knowledge as not-knowledge, labeling it as pseudo- and pretentious-knowledge. This type of knowledge did not provide power; it was useless, not functional. In his extensive discussions, he categorized the knowledge of his time into three types: delicate, fantastic, and contentious. Delicate learning referred to the literary knowledge that, fueled by the revival of ancient languages and literature, held a significant role in the intellectual life of the Renaissance. Bacon's critique is particularly striking because he himself was a master of the classics and of all the nuances and subtleties that this literary study aimed to impart. In essence, he anticipated many of the critiques that educational reformers have made against narrow literary culture since his era. It contributed not to empowerment, but to embellishment and show. It was flashy and extravagant. By fantastic learning, he referred to the quasi-magical sciences that were prevalent throughout Europe in the sixteenth century—wild trends in alchemy, astrology, etc. He poured his strongest critiques[Pg 30] on this because the corruption of what is good represents the worst kind of evil. While delicate learning was idle and superficial, fantastic learning imitated the form of genuine knowledge. It grasped the real principle and goal of knowledge—control over natural forces. However, it ignored the necessary conditions and methods that could actually lead to such knowledge, thereby intentionally misleading people.
For our purposes, however, what he says about contentious learning is the most important. For by this, he means the traditional science which had come down, in scanty and distorted measure to be sure, from antiquity through scholasticism. It is called contentious both because of the logical method used and the end to which it was put. In a certain sense it aimed at power, but power over other men in the interest of some class or sect or person, not power over natural forces in the common interest of all. Bacon's conviction of the quarrelsome, self-displaying character of the scholarship which had come down from antiquity was of course not so much due to Greek science itself as to the degenerate heritage of scholasticism in the fourteenth century, when philosophy had fallen into the hands of disputatious theologians, full of hair-splitting argumentativeness and quirks and tricks by which to win victory over somebody else.
For our purposes, what he says about contentious learning is the most important. By this, he refers to the traditional science that has been passed down, though in a limited and distorted way, from ancient times through scholasticism. It’s called contentious because of both the logical method used and the purpose it served. In a way, it aimed at power, but power over other people for the benefit of a specific class, group, or individual, rather than power over natural forces for the common good. Bacon's view of the argumentative and self-promoting nature of the scholarship from ancient times was mainly due to the degraded legacy of scholasticism in the fourteenth century, when philosophy fell into the hands of quarrelsome theologians, who were full of convoluted arguments and tricks to defeat others.
But Bacon also brought his charge against the Aristotelian method itself. In its rigorous forms it[Pg 31] aimed at demonstration, and in its milder forms at persuasion. But both demonstration and persuasion aim at conquest of mind rather than of nature. Moreover they both assume that some one is already in possession of a truth or a belief, and that the only problem is to convince some one else, or to teach. In contrast, his new method had an exceedingly slight opinion of the amount of truth already existent, and a lively sense of the extent and importance of truths still to be attained. It would be a logic of discovery, not a logic of argumentation, proof and persuasion. To Bacon, the old logic even at its best was a logic for teaching the already known, and teaching meant indoctrination, discipling. It was an axiom of Aristotle that only that which was already known could be learned, that growth in knowledge consisted simply in bringing together a universal truth of reason and a particular truth of sense which had previously been noted separately. In any case, learning meant growth of knowledge, and growth belongs in the region of becoming, change, and hence is inferior to possession of knowledge in the syllogistic self-revolving manipulation of what was already known—demonstration.
But Bacon also criticized the Aristotelian method itself. In its strict forms, it[Pg 31] aimed for demonstration, and in its softer forms, it aimed for persuasion. However, both demonstration and persuasion focus on winning over the mind rather than understanding nature. Moreover, they both assume that someone already possesses a truth or belief, and the only challenge is to convince someone else or to teach. In contrast, his new method held a low opinion of the amount of truth already available and a strong awareness of the vastness and significance of truths still to be discovered. It would be a logic of discovery, not a logic of argument, proof, and persuasion. To Bacon, the old logic, even at its best, was about teaching what was already known, and teaching meant indoctrination and training. Aristotle’s axiom was that only what was already known could be learned, and that growth in knowledge was simply about connecting a universal truth of reason with a particular truth of experience that had been noted separately. In any case, learning meant growth of knowledge, and growth is linked to becoming, change, making it inferior to possession of knowledge in the self-reinforcing manipulation of what was already known—demonstration.
In contrast with this point of view, Bacon eloquently proclaimed the superiority of discovery of new facts and truths to demonstration of the old. Now there is only one road to discovery, and that is penetrating in[Pg 32]quiry into the secrets of nature. Scientific principles and laws do not lie on the surface of nature. They are hidden, and must be wrested from nature by an active and elaborate technique of inquiry. Neither logical reasoning nor the passive accumulation of any number of observations—which the ancients called experience—suffices to lay hold of them. Active experimentation must force the apparent facts of nature into forms different to those in which they familiarly present themselves; and thus make them tell the truth about themselves, as torture may compel an unwilling witness to reveal what he has been concealing. Pure reasoning as a means of arriving at truth is like the spider who spins a web out of himself. The web is orderly and elaborate, but it is only a trap. The passive accumulation of experiences—the traditional empirical method—is like the ant who busily runs about and collects and piles up heaps of raw materials. True method, that which Bacon would usher in, is comparable to the operations of the bee who, like the ant, collects material from the external world, but unlike that industrious creature attacks and modifies the collected stuff in order to make it yield its hidden treasure.
In contrast to this perspective, Bacon passionately argued that discovering new facts and truths is much more important than demonstrating the old ones. There is only one path to discovery, and that is through deep inquiry into the secrets of nature. Scientific principles and laws aren't obvious; they're hidden and must be extracted from nature using a careful and active method of inquiry. Just relying on logical reasoning or passively gathering observations—which the ancients referred to as experience—won't be enough to uncover them. Active experimentation must transform the apparent facts of nature into different forms than those in which they're normally seen, revealing their true nature, much like how torture can force a reluctant witness to disclose what they've been hiding. Pure reasoning as a way to find truth is like a spider that spins a web from itself. The web is organized and complex, but it's just a trap. The passive collection of experiences—the traditional empirical method—is like an ant that scurries around, collecting and stacking raw materials. The true method Bacon envisioned is like the work of a bee, which, similar to the ant, gathers materials from the outside world but actively processes and alters what it collects to uncover its hidden treasures.
Along with this contrast between subjugation of nature and subjection of other minds and the elevation of a method of discovery above a method of demonstration, went Bacon's sense of progress as the aim and[Pg 33] test of genuine knowledge. According to his criticisms, the classic logic, even in its Aristotelian form, inevitably played into the hands of inert conservatism. For in accustoming the mind to think of truth as already known, it habituated men to fall back on the intellectual attainments of the past, and to accept them without critical scrutiny. Not merely the medieval but the renaissance mind tended to look back to antiquity as a Golden Age of Knowledge, the former relying upon sacred scriptures, the latter upon secular literatures. And while this attitude could not fairly be charged up against the classic logic, yet Bacon felt, and with justice, that any logic which identified the technique of knowing with demonstration of truths already possessed by the mind, blunts the spirit of investigation and confines the mind within the circle of traditional learning.
Along with this contrast between controlling nature and controlling other minds, and prioritizing a method of discovery over a method of demonstration, Bacon saw progress as the goal and[Pg 33] test of true knowledge. He criticized classic logic, even in its Aristotelian version, for supporting stagnant conservatism. By getting people used to thinking of truth as something already known, it conditioned them to rely on the intellectual achievements of the past and accept them without questioning. Both the medieval and Renaissance mind tended to view antiquity as a Golden Age of Knowledge, with the former depending on sacred scriptures and the latter on secular literature. While this mindset couldn't be solely blamed on classic logic, Bacon rightly felt that any logic that equated knowing with demonstrating truths already known dulls the spirit of inquiry and keeps the mind trapped within traditional learning.
Such a logic could not avoid having for its salient features definition of what is already known (or thought to be known), and its systematization according to recognized canons of orthodoxy. A logic of discovery on the other hand looks to the future. Received truth it regards critically as something to be tested by new experiences rather than as something to be dogmatically taught and obediently received. Its chief interest in even the most carefully tested ready-made knowledge is the use which may be made of it in further inquiries[Pg 34] and discoveries. Old truth has its chief value in assisting the detection of new truth. Bacon's own appreciation of the nature of induction was highly defective. But his acute sense that science means invasion of the unknown, rather than repetition in logical form of the already known, makes him nevertheless the father of induction. Endless and persistent uncovering of facts and principles not known—such is the true spirit of induction. Continued progress in knowledge is the only sure way of protecting old knowledge from degeneration into dogmatic doctrines received on authority, or from imperceptible decay into superstition and old wives' tales.
Such a logic must include defining what is already known (or thought to be known) and organizing it according to accepted standards of orthodoxy. A logic of discovery, on the other hand, focuses on the future. It critically views accepted truths as something to be tested through new experiences rather than as rigid doctrines to be passively accepted. Its main interest in even the most thoroughly tested established knowledge lies in how it can be used for further inquiries and discoveries[Pg 34]. Old truths are primarily valuable for helping to uncover new truths. Bacon's understanding of induction was quite flawed. However, his sharp realization that science is about exploring the unknown, rather than merely restating known facts in logical form, still establishes him as the father of induction. The continuous and relentless discovery of facts and principles that are not yet known embodies the true spirit of induction. Ongoing progress in knowledge is the only reliable method for keeping established knowledge from deteriorating into dogmatic beliefs accepted solely on authority, or from slowly degrading into superstition and old wives' tales.
Ever-renewed progress is to Bacon the test as well as the aim of genuine logic. Where, Bacon constantly demands, where are the works, the fruits, of the older logic? What has it done to ameliorate the evils of life, to rectify defects, to improve conditions? Where are the inventions that justify its claim to be in possession of truth? Beyond the victory of man over man in law courts, diplomacy and political administration, they are nil. One had to turn from admired "sciences" to despised arts to find works, fruits, consequences of value to human kind through power over natural forces. And progress in the arts was as yet intermittent, fitful, accidental. A true logic or technique of inquiry would make advance in the industrial, agricultural and medi[Pg 35]cal arts continuous, cumulative and deliberately systematic.
Ever-renewed progress is for Bacon both the test and the goal of true logic. He constantly asks, where are the results and benefits from the old logic? What has it done to improve life’s challenges, correct flaws, and enhance conditions? Where are the inventions that support its claim to possess truth? Aside from the triumphs of man over man in courts, diplomacy, and politics, there’s nothing to show. One had to look away from esteemed "sciences" to the undervalued arts to find useful works and outcomes that benefit humanity through control over natural forces. Moreover, progress in the arts was still sporadic, inconsistent, and random. A true logic or method of inquiry would make advancements in industrial, agricultural, and medical arts continuous, cumulative, and systematically intentional.
If we take into account the supposed body of ready-made knowledge upon which learned men rested in supine acquiescence and which they recited in parrot-like chorus, we find it consists of two parts. One of these parts is made up of the errors of our ancestors, musty with antiquity and organized into pseudo-science through the use of the classic logic. Such "truths" are in fact only the systematized mistakes and prejudices of our ancestors. Many of them originated in accident; many in class interest and bias, perpetuated by authority for this very reason—a consideration which later actuated Locke's attack upon the doctrine of innate ideas. The other portion of accepted beliefs comes from instinctive tendencies of the human mind that give it a dangerous bias until counteracted by a conscious and critical logic.
If we consider the supposed body of established knowledge that scholars have accepted without question and repeat like parrots, we see it’s made up of two parts. One part consists of the mistakes of our ancestors, outdated and organized into pseudo-science through classic logic. These so-called "truths" are really just the systematic errors and biases of those who came before us. Many originated from chance; others from class interests and biases, maintained by those in power for that very reason — a point that later drove Locke to challenge the idea of innate knowledge. The other part of our accepted beliefs comes from instinctual tendencies of the human mind that create a dangerous bias unless corrected by conscious and critical thinking.
The mind of man spontaneously assumes greater simplicity, uniformity and unity among phenomena than actually exists. It follows superficial analogies and jumps to conclusions; it overlooks the variety of details and the existence of exceptions. Thus it weaves a web of purely internal origin which it imposes upon nature. What had been termed science in the past consisted of this humanly constructed and imposed web. Men looked at the work of their own minds and thought[Pg 36] they were seeing realities in nature. They were worshipping, under the name of science, the idols of their own making. So-called science and philosophy consisted of these "anticipations" of nature. And the worst thing that could be said about traditional logic was that instead of saving man from this natural source of error, it had, though attributing to nature a false rationality of unity, simplicity and generality, sanctioned these sources of delusion. The office of the new logic would be to protect the mind against itself: to teach it to undergo a patient and prolonged apprenticeship to fact in its infinite variety and particularity: to obey nature intellectually in order to command it practically. Such was the significance of the new logic—the new tool or organon of learning, so named in express opposition to the organon of Aristotle.
The human mind naturally tends to simplify, unify, and create consistency among phenomena more than what actually exists. It follows surface-level similarities and makes quick conclusions; it misses out on the variety of details and ignores exceptions. As a result, it constructs a framework entirely from its own perspective, which it imposes on nature. What was once called science was largely this human-created and imposed framework. People would look at their own mental creations and think[Pg 36] they were observing realities in nature. They were essentially idolizing, under the name of science, the ideas they had invented. So-called science and philosophy were made up of these "anticipations" of nature. The biggest flaw of traditional logic was that instead of protecting humanity from this natural source of error, it had, by attributing a false sense of unity, simplicity, and generality to nature, legitimized these illusions. The purpose of the new logic would be to safeguard the mind from itself: to train it to engage in a careful and extended apprenticeship with facts in all their diversity and specifics: to intellectually follow nature in order to practically control it. This is what the new logic represented—an innovative tool or methodology for learning, explicitly contrasting with Aristotle's methodology.
Certain other important oppositions are implied. Aristotle thought of reason as capable of solitary communion with rational truth. The counterpart of his celebrated saying that man is a political animal, is that Intelligence, Nous, is neither animal, human nor political. It is divinely unique and self-enclosed. To Bacon, error had been produced and perpetuated by social influences, and truth must be discovered by social agencies organized for that purpose. Left to himself, the individual can do little or nothing; he is likely to become involved in his own self-spun web of misconceptions.[Pg 37] The great need is the organization of co-operative research, whereby men attack nature collectively and the work of inquiry is carried on continuously from generation to generation. Bacon even aspired to the rather absurd notion of a method so perfected that differences in natural human ability might be discounted, and all be put on the same level in production of new facts and new truths. Yet this absurdity was only the negative side of his great positive prophecy of a combined and co-operative pursuit of science such as characterizes our own day. In view of the picture he draws in his New Atlantis of a State organized for collective inquiry, we readily forgive him his exaggerations.
Certain other important oppositions are implied. Aristotle viewed reason as capable of solitary communion with rational truth. The counterpart of his well-known statement that man is a political animal is that Intelligence, Nous, is neither animal, human, nor political. It is uniquely divine and self-contained. To Bacon, error was created and sustained by social influences, and truth must be found through social organizations designed for that purpose. Left to themselves, individuals can do little or nothing; they are likely to get tangled in their own web of misconceptions.[Pg 37] The major need is the organization of cooperative research, where people tackle nature together and the work of inquiry continues from generation to generation. Bacon even dreamed of the somewhat unrealistic idea of a method so perfected that differences in natural human ability could be overlooked, allowing everyone to contribute equally to the creation of new facts and truths. Yet this unrealistic notion was simply the negative side of his great positive vision of a combined and collaborative pursuit of science like we see in our own time. Considering the picture he paints in his New Atlantis of a state structured for collective inquiry, we easily forgive his exaggerations.
Power over nature was not to be individual but collective; the Empire, as he says, of Man over Nature, substituted for the Empire of Man over Man. Let us employ Bacon's own words with their variety of picturesque metaphor: "Men have entered into the desire of learning and knowledge,... seldom sincerely to give a true account of their gift of reason, to the benefit and use of men, but as if they sought in knowledge a couch whereon to rest a searching and wandering spirit; or a terrace for a wandering and variable mind to walk up and down with a fair prospect; or a tower for a proud mind to raise itself upon; or a fort or commanding ground for strife and contention; or a shop for profit and sale; and not a rich storehouse for the glory[Pg 38] of the creator and the relief of man's estate." When William James called Pragmatism a New Name for an Old Way of Thinking, I do not know that he was thinking expressly of Francis Bacon, but so far as concerns the spirit and atmosphere of the pursuit of knowledge, Bacon may be taken as the prophet of a pragmatic conception of knowledge. Many misconceptions of its spirit would be avoided if his emphasis upon the social factor in both the pursuit and the end of knowledge were carefully observed.
Power over nature should be collective rather than individual; the Empire, as he puts it, of Man over Nature replaces the Empire of Man over Man. Let’s use Bacon's own words with their vivid imagery: "People have embraced the desire for learning and knowledge,... rarely with the genuine intent to provide a truthful account of their reasoning for the benefit and use of humanity, but rather as if they were searching in knowledge for a bed to rest a restless and wandering spirit; or a balcony for a wayward and fickle mind to stroll back and forth with a beautiful view; or a tower for an arrogant mind to elevate itself; or a fortress or high ground for conflict and strife; or a marketplace for profit and trade; and not a rich repository for the glory[Pg 38] of the creator and the betterment of human existence." When William James referred to Pragmatism as a New Name for an Old Way of Thinking, I’m not sure he was specifically thinking of Francis Bacon, but in terms of the spirit and atmosphere surrounding the pursuit of knowledge, Bacon can be seen as the prophet of a pragmatic view of knowledge. Many misunderstandings of its essence could be avoided if we paid close attention to his emphasis on the social aspect in both the pursuit and the purpose of knowledge.
This somewhat over-long résumé of Bacon's ideas has not been gone into as a matter of historic retrospect. The summary is rather meant to put before our minds an authentic document of the new philosophy which may bring into relief the social causes of intellectual revolution. Only a sketchy account can be here attempted, but it may be of some assistance even barely to remind you of the direction of that industrial, political and religious change upon which Europe was entering.
This lengthy summary of Bacon's ideas isn't intended as a historical review. Instead, it aims to present a genuine document of the new philosophy that highlights the social factors behind the intellectual revolution. While only a brief overview can be attempted here, it might help to remind you of the industrial, political, and religious shifts Europe was experiencing.
Upon the industrial side, it is impossible, I think, to exaggerate the influence of travel, exploration and new commerce which fostered a romantic sense of adventure into novelty; loosened the hold of traditional beliefs; created a lively sense of new worlds to be investigated and subdued; produced new methods of manufacture, commerce, banking and finance; and then reacted everywhere to stimulate invention, and to intro[Pg 39]duce positive observation and active experimentation into science. The Crusades, the revival of the profane learning of antiquity and even more perhaps, the contact with the advanced learning of the Mohammedans, the increase of commerce with Asia and Africa, the introduction of the lens, compass and gunpowder, the finding and opening up of North and South America—most significantly called The New World—these are some of the obvious external facts. Contrast between peoples and races previously isolated is always, I think, most fruitful and influential for change when psychological and industrial changes coincide with and reinforce each other. Sometimes people undergo emotional change, what might almost be called a metaphysical change, through intercourse. The inner set of the mind, especially in religious matters, is altered. At other times, there is a lively exchange of goods, an adoption of foreign tools and devices, an imitation of alien habits of clothing, habitation and production of commodities. One of these changes is, so to speak, too internal and the other too external to bring about a profound intellectual development. But when the creation of a new mental attitude falls together with extensive material and economic changes, something significant happens.
On the industrial side, I believe it's impossible to overstate the impact of travel, exploration, and new trade, which encouraged a sense of adventure and novelty; loosened traditional beliefs; created an eagerness to discover and conquer new worlds; led to new methods of manufacturing, commerce, banking, and finance; and stimulated invention everywhere by introducing positive observation and active experimentation into science. The Crusades, the revival of secular learning from antiquity, and perhaps even more, the interaction with advanced knowledge from the Muslims, the growth of trade with Asia and Africa, the introduction of the lens, compass, and gunpowder, and the discovery and opening of North and South America—most notably called The New World—highlight some of these clear external factors. The contrast between peoples and races that were previously isolated is, in my view, most productive and influential for change when psychological and industrial shifts align and strengthen each other. Sometimes, people experience emotional shifts, something that could almost be described as a metaphysical change, through interactions. The core mindset, especially regarding religious matters, is transformed. Other times, there is an active exchange of goods, the adoption of foreign tools and techniques, and the imitation of different styles of clothing, living arrangements, and commodity production. One of these shifts is, so to speak, too internal, while the other is too external to lead to significant intellectual development. But when a new mental attitude aligns with substantial material and economic changes, something important occurs.
This coincidence of two kinds of change was, I take it, characteristic of the new contacts of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Clash of customs and traditional[Pg 40] beliefs dispelled mental inertia and sluggishness; it aroused a lively curiosity as to different and new ideas. The actual adventure of travel and exploration purged the mind of fear of the strange and unknown: as new territories geographically and commercially speaking were opened up, the mind was opened up. New contacts promoted the desire for still more contacts; the appetite for novelty and discovery grew by what it fed upon. Conservative adherence to old beliefs and methods underwent a steady attrition with every new voyage into new parts and every new report of foreign ways. The mind became used to exploration and discovery. It found a delight and interest in the revelations of the novel and the unusual which it no longer took in what was old and customary. Moreover, the very act of exploration, of expedition, the process of enterprising adventure into the remote, yielded a peculiar joy and thrill.
This combination of two types of change was, I think, typical of the new interactions that occurred in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The clash of customs and traditional[Pg 40] beliefs broke through mental inertia and sluggishness; it sparked a lively curiosity about different and new ideas. The actual experience of travel and exploration removed the fear of the strange and unknown: as new territories were opened up both geographically and commercially, people’s minds opened up too. New connections fueled the desire for even more connections; the longing for novelty and discovery grew as it explored more. Sticking to old beliefs and methods lost ground with every new voyage into unfamiliar places and each new account of foreign customs. People became accustomed to exploration and discovery. They found joy and interest in the revelations of the new and unusual, losing their fascination with what was old and customary. Moreover, the very act of exploration, of embarking on expeditions and adventurous journeys into the unknown, brought a unique joy and thrill.
This psychological change was essential to the birth of the new point of view in science and philosophy. Yet alone it could hardly have produced the new method of knowing. But positive changes in the habits and purposes of life gave objective conformation and support to the mental change. They also determined the channels in which the new spirit found exercise. Newfound wealth, the gold from the Americas and new articles of consumption and enjoyment, tended to wean men[Pg 41] from preoccupation with the metaphysical and theological, and to turn their minds with newly awakened interest to the joys of nature and this life. New material resources and new markets in America and India undermined the old dependence upon household and manual production for a local and limited market, and generated quantitative, large scale production by means of steam for foreign and expanding markets. Capitalism, rapid transit, and production for exchange against money and for profit, instead of against goods and for consumption, followed.
This psychological shift was crucial for the emergence of a new perspective in science and philosophy. However, on its own, it couldn't have created the new way of understanding. Positive changes in people's habits and life goals provided objective validation and support for this mental shift. They also shaped the avenues through which this new spirit expressed itself. The influx of wealth from the Americas, along with new goods for consumption and enjoyment, distracted people from their preoccupation with metaphysical and theological concerns, directing their attention to the pleasures of nature and life itself. New material resources and markets in America and India diminished the reliance on local household and manual production, paving the way for large-scale production powered by steam for foreign and expanding markets. Capitalism, rapid transport, and production aimed at exchange for money and profit—rather than for goods and consumption—took hold.
This cursory and superficial reminder of vast and complicated events may suggest the mutual interdependence of the scientific revolution and the industrial revolution. Upon the one hand, modern industry is so much applied science. No amount of desire to make money, or to enjoy new commodities, no amount of mere practical energy and enterprise, would have effected the economic transformation of the last few centuries and generations. Improvements in mathematical, physical, chemical and biological science were prerequisites. Business men through engineers of different sorts, have laid hold of the new insights gained by scientific men into the hidden energies of nature, and have turned them to account. The modern mine, factory, railway, steamship, telegraph, all of the appliances and equipment of production, and transportation, express scienti[Pg 42]fic knowledge. They would continue unimpaired even if the ordinary pecuniary accompaniments of economic activity were radically altered. In short, through the intermediary of invention, Bacon's watchword that knowledge is power and his dream of continuous empire over natural forces by means of natural science have been actualized. The industrial revolution by steam and electricity is the reply to Bacon's prophecy.
This brief and superficial overview of complex events highlights the interconnectedness of the scientific revolution and the industrial revolution. On one hand, modern industry is essentially applied science. No amount of desire for profit or enjoyment of new products, nor sheer practical energy and initiative, could have brought about the economic changes of the past few centuries. Advances in mathematical, physical, chemical, and biological sciences were essential. Businesspeople, through various engineers, have utilized the new knowledge gained from scientists about the hidden forces of nature and applied it practically. The modern mine, factory, railway, steamship, and telegraph—all the tools and equipment for production and transportation—embody scientific knowledge. They would remain effective even if the usual financial aspects of economic activity were drastically changed. In summary, through the process of invention, Bacon's maxim that knowledge is power and his vision of ongoing control over natural forces through natural science have been realized. The industrial revolution driven by steam and electricity is the fulfillment of Bacon's prediction.
On the other hand, it is equally true that the needs of modern industry have been tremendous stimuli to scientific investigation. The demands of progressive production and transportation have set new problems to inquiry; the processes used in industry have suggested new experimental appliances and operations in science; the wealth rolled up in business has to some extent been diverted to endowment of research. The uninterrupted and pervasive interaction of scientific discovery and industrial application has fructified both science and industry, and has brought home to the contemporary mind the fact that the gist of scientific knowledge is control of natural energies. These four facts, natural science, experimentation, control and progress have been inextricably bound up together. That up to the present the application of the newer methods and results has influenced the means of life rather than its ends; or, better put, that human aims have so far been affected in an accidental rather than[Pg 43] in an intelligently directed way, signifies that so far the change has been technical rather than human and moral, that it has been economic rather than adequately social. Put in the language of Bacon, this means that while we have been reasonably successful in obtaining command of nature by means of science, our science is not yet such that this command is systematically and pre-eminently applied to the relief of human estate. Such applications occur and in great numbers, but they are incidental, sporadic and external. And this limitation defines the specific problem of philosophical reconstruction at the present time. For it emphasizes the larger social deficiencies that require intelligent diagnosis, and projection of aims and methods.
On the other hand, it's also true that the needs of modern industry have been major drivers of scientific research. The demands of advanced production and transportation have raised new questions for inquiry; industrial processes have inspired new experimental tools and methods in science; and the wealth generated by business has, to some extent, been redirected to fund research. The ongoing and widespread interaction between scientific discovery and industrial application has benefited both fields, highlighting for today's thinkers that the essence of scientific knowledge is the control of natural energies. These four elements—natural science, experimentation, control, and progress—are deeply interconnected. So far, the use of new methods and findings has impacted the means of life more than its ultimate goals; or, better said, human aspirations have been influenced more by chance than in a thoughtfully directed way, indicating that the change we've experienced has been more technical than human and moral, more economic than truly social. In Bacon's terms, while we've had reasonable success in mastering nature through science, our science isn't yet focused on systematically applying that mastery to improve human life. Such applications do happen and in large numbers, but they are incidental, sporadic, and external. This limitation highlights the specific challenge of philosophical reconstruction today, as it underscores the broader social issues that need thoughtful analysis and the formulation of aims and methods.
It is hardly necessary to remind you however that marked political changes have already followed upon the new science and its industrial applications, and that in so far some directions of social development have at least been marked out. The growth of the new technique of industry has everywhere been followed by the fall of feudal institutions, in which the social pattern was formed in agricultural occupations and military pursuits. Wherever business in the modern sense has gone, the tendency has been to transfer power from land to financial capital, from the country to the city, from the farm to factory, from social titles based on personal allegiance, service and protection, to those based on[Pg 44] control of labor and exchange of goods. The change in the political centre of gravity has resulted in emancipating the individual from bonds of class and custom and in producing a political organization which depends less upon superior authority and more upon voluntary choice. Modern states, in other words, are regarded less as divine, and more as human works than they used to be; less as necessary manifestations of some supreme and over-ruling principles, and more as contrivances of men and women to realize their own desires.
It’s hardly necessary to remind you that significant political changes have already occurred as a result of the new science and its industrial applications, and in some ways, certain paths of social development have been outlined. The rise of the new industrial techniques has everywhere led to the decline of feudal institutions, which were built on agricultural jobs and military service. Wherever modern business has taken root, there has been a shift of power from land to financial capital, from rural areas to urban centers, from farms to factories, and from social titles based on personal loyalty, service, and protection to those based on[Pg 44] control of labor and trade. The shift in political focus has freed individuals from the constraints of class and tradition and created a political structure that relies less on authority and more on personal choice. In other words, modern states are seen less as divine entities and more as human creations than they once were; less as necessary outcomes of some supreme principles, and more as constructs by people to fulfill their own aspirations.
The contract theory of the origin of the state is a theory whose falsity may easily be demonstrated both philosophically and historically. Nevertheless this theory has had great currency and influence. In form, it stated that some time in the past men voluntarily got together and made a compact with one another to observe certain laws and to submit to certain authority and in that way brought the state and the relation of ruler and subject into existence. Like many things in philosophy, the theory, though worthless as a record of fact, is of great worth as a symptom of the direction of human desire. It testified to a growing belief that the state existed to satisfy human needs and could be shaped by human intention and volition. Aristotle's theory that the state exists by nature failed to satisfy the thought of the seventeenth century because it seemed by making the state a product of nature to re[Pg 45]move its constitution beyond human choice. Equally significant was the assumption of the contract theory that individuals by their personal decisions expressing their personal wishes bring the state into existence. The rapidity with which the theory gained a hold all over western Europe showed the extent to which the bonds of customary institutions had relaxed their grip. It proved that men had been so liberated from absorption in larger groups that they were conscious of themselves as individuals having rights and claims on their own account, not simply as members of a class, guild or social grade.
The contract theory of the origin of the state is a theory whose falsehood can easily be shown both philosophically and historically. Still, this theory has been widely accepted and influential. Essentially, it suggested that at some point in the past, people voluntarily came together to agree to follow certain laws and submit to certain authority, thereby creating the state and the relationship between rulers and subjects. Like many ideas in philosophy, this theory, while not a factual account, is valuable as a reflection of human desire. It indicated a growing belief that the state exists to meet human needs and can be shaped by human intention and choice. Aristotle's idea that the state exists by nature did not satisfy thinkers of the seventeenth century because it seemed to make the state's structure beyond human choice. Equally important was the contract theory's assumption that individuals, through their personal decisions and desires, create the state. The speed at which this theory spread across western Europe demonstrated how much the influence of traditional institutions had weakened. It showed that people had become so liberated from being absorbed into larger groups that they recognized themselves as individuals with their own rights and claims, not just as members of a class, guild, or social group.
Side by side with this political individualism went a religious and moral individualism. The metaphysical doctrine of the superiority of the species to the individual, of the permanent universal to the changing particular, was the philosophic support of political and ecclesiastical institutionalism. The universal church was the ground, end and limit of the individual's beliefs and acts in spiritual matters, just as the feudal hierarchical organization was the basis, law and fixed limit of his behavior in secular affairs. The northern barbarians had never completely come under the sway of classic ideas and customs. That which was indigenous where life was primarily derived from Latin sources was borrowed and more or less externally imposed in Germanic Europe. Protestantism marked the formal[Pg 46] breaking away from the domination of Roman ideas. It effected liberation of individual conscience and worship from control by an organized institution claiming to be permanent and universal. It cannot truly be said that at the outset the new religious movement went far in promoting freedom of thought and criticism, or in denying the notion of some supreme authority to which individual intelligence was absolutely in bonds. Nor at first did it go far in furthering tolerance or respect for divergency of moral and religious convictions. But practically it did tend to disintegration of established institutions. By multiplying sects and churches it encouraged at least a negative toleration of the right of individuals to judge ultimate matters for themselves. In time, there developed a formulated belief in the sacredness of individual conscience and in the right to freedom of opinion, belief and worship.
Alongside this political individualism was a religious and moral individualism. The metaphysical belief in the superiority of the species over the individual, and the permanent universal over the changing particular, provided the philosophical basis for political and religious institutionalism. The universal church served as the foundation, purpose, and limit of an individual's beliefs and actions in spiritual matters, just as the feudal hierarchical system was the basis, law, and strict boundary of behavior in secular matters. The northern barbarians had never fully adopted classic ideas and customs. What was native in regions where life was mainly shaped by Latin influences was borrowed and somewhat externally imposed in Germanic Europe. Protestantism signified the formal[Pg 46] break from the influence of Roman ideas. It liberated individual conscience and worship from the control of an organized institution claiming to be permanent and universal. It can't be accurately said that the new religious movement initially did much to promote freedom of thought and criticism, or to reject the idea of some supreme authority to which individual intelligence was entirely bound. Nor did it significantly advance tolerance or respect for differing moral and religious beliefs at first. However, it did contribute, in practice, to the disintegration of established institutions. By creating numerous sects and churches, it fostered at least a negative tolerance for individuals' rights to decide ultimate matters for themselves. Over time, a formulated belief in the sacredness of individual conscience and the right to freedom of opinion, belief, and worship emerged.
It is unnecessary to point out how the spread of this conviction increased political individualism, or how it accelerated the willingness of men to question received ideas in science and philosophy—to think and observe and experiment for themselves. Religious individualism served to supply a much needed sanction to initiative and independence of thought in all spheres, even when religious movements officially were opposed to such freedom when carried beyond a limited point. The greatest influence of Protestantism was, however, in developing[Pg 47] the idea of the personality of every human being as an end in himself. When human beings were regarded as capable of direct relationship with God, without the intermediary of any organization like the Church, and the drama of sin, redemption and salvation was something enacted within the innermost soul of individuals rather than in the species of which the individual was a subordinate part, a fatal blow was struck at all doctrines which taught the subordination of personality—a blow which had many political reverberations in promoting democracy. For when in religion the idea of the intrinsic worth of every soul as such was proclaimed, it was difficult to keep the idea from spilling over, so to say, into secular relationships.
It’s unnecessary to point out how the spread of this belief increased political individualism, or how it made people more willing to question established ideas in science and philosophy—to think, observe, and experiment for themselves. Religious individualism provided the much-needed support for initiative and independence of thought in all areas, even when religious movements officially opposed such freedom when it exceeded certain limits. However, the greatest impact of Protestantism was in developing[Pg 47] the idea of every individual being valuable in their own right. When people were seen as capable of having a direct relationship with God, without needing any organization like the Church as an intermediary, and when the experience of sin, redemption, and salvation was understood as something that happened within each person’s innermost soul rather than as a collective experience, a significant challenge was posed to all doctrines that promoted the subordination of individuality—a challenge that had many political repercussions in advancing democracy. Because when the idea of the inherent worth of every soul was embraced in religion, it was hard to prevent that idea from spilling over into everyday relationships.
The absurdity is obvious of trying in a few paragraphs to summarize movements in industry, politics and religion whose influence is still far from exhausted and about which hundreds and thousands of volumes have been written. But I shall count upon your forbearance to recall that these matters are alluded to only in order to suggest some of the forces that operated to mark out the channels in which new ideas ran. First, there is the transfer of interest from the eternal and universal to what is changing and specific, concrete—a movement that showed itself practically in carrying over of attention and thought from another world to this, from the supernaturalism characteristic of the Middle Ages[Pg 48] to delight in natural science, natural activity and natural intercourse. Secondly, there is the gradual decay of the authority of fixed institutions and class distinctions and relations, and a growing belief in the power of individual minds, guided by methods of observation, experiment and reflection, to attain the truths needed for the guidance of life. The operations and results of natural inquiry gained in prestige and power at the expense of principles dictated from high authority.
The absurdity of trying to sum up in just a few paragraphs the changes in industry, politics, and religion—forces that still have significant impact and about which countless volumes have been written—is clear. However, I hope you’ll be patient as I mention these topics to highlight some of the forces that shaped the paths for new ideas. First, there was a shift in focus from the eternal and universal to what is changing and specific, practical—this was seen in the transfer of attention and thought from another world to this one, moving away from the supernaturalism of the Middle Ages[Pg 48] to an appreciation for natural science, natural activity, and human connection. Secondly, there was a gradual decline in the authority of established institutions and class distinctions, accompanied by an increasing belief in the ability of individual minds, using observation, experimentation, and reflection, to discover the truths necessary for guiding life. The influence and outcomes of scientific inquiry gained more respect and power at the expense of principles handed down from authority.
Consequently principles and alleged truths are judged more and more by criteria of their origin in experience and their consequences of weal and woe in experience, and less by criteria of sublime origin from beyond everyday experience and independent of fruits in experience. It is no longer enough for a principle to be elevated, noble, universal and hallowed by time. It must present its birth certificate, it must show under just what conditions of human experience it was generated, and it must justify itself by its works, present and potential. Such is the inner meaning of the modern appeal to experience as an ultimate criterion of value and validity. In the third place, great store is set upon the idea of progress. The future rather than the past dominates the imagination. The Golden Age lies ahead of us not behind us. Everywhere new possibilities beckon and arouse courage and effort. The great[Pg 49] French thinkers of the later eighteenth century borrowed this idea from Bacon and developed it into the doctrine of the indefinite perfectibility of mankind on earth. Man is capable, if he will but exercise the required courage, intelligence and effort, of shaping his own fate. Physical conditions offer no insurmountable barriers. In the fourth place, the patient and experimental study of nature, bearing fruit in inventions which control nature and subdue her forces to social uses, is the method by which progress is made. Knowledge is power and knowledge is achieved by sending the mind to school to nature to learn her processes of change.
As a result, ideas and supposed truths are increasingly assessed based on their roots in experience and the outcomes of well-being and suffering in that experience, rather than being evaluated based on lofty origins from beyond everyday life that are independent of their results in experience. It’s not enough for a principle to be lofty, noble, universal, and honored by time anymore. It must provide proof of its origins, demonstrating the conditions under which it was formed, and it must justify itself by its actual and potential results. This encapsulates the modern reliance on experience as the ultimate standard of value and validity. Additionally, there is a strong belief in progress. The future, not the past, captures our imagination. The Golden Age is ahead of us, not behind us. New possibilities are everywhere, inspiring courage and effort. The great French thinkers of the late eighteenth century took this idea from Bacon and expanded it into the concept of the endless perfectibility of humanity on earth. Humans have the ability, if they show the necessary courage, intelligence, and effort, to shape their own destiny. Physical conditions do not pose insurmountable obstacles. Finally, the careful and experimental study of nature, leading to inventions that control nature and harness her forces for social benefit, is the method through which progress is achieved. Knowledge is power, and knowledge is gained by learning from nature about her processes of change.
In this lecture as in the previous one, I can hardly close better than by reference to the new responsibilities imposed upon philosophy and the new opportunities opened to it. Upon the whole, the greatest effect of these changes up to date has been to substitute an Idealism based on epistemology, or the theory of knowledge, for the Idealism based on the metaphysics of classic antiquity.
In this lecture, just like in the last one, I can hardly conclude better than by pointing out the new responsibilities and opportunities that have emerged for philosophy. Overall, the biggest impact of these changes so far has been to replace an Idealism grounded in epistemology, or the theory of knowledge, with an Idealism based on the metaphysics of ancient times.
Earlier modern philosophy (even though unconsciously to itself) had the problem of reconciling the traditional theory of the rational and ideal basis, stuff and end of the universe with the new interest in individual mind and the new confidence in its capacities. It was in a dilemma. On the one hand, it had no intention[Pg 50] of losing itself in a materialism which subordinated man to physical existence and mind to matter—especially just at the moment when in actual affairs man and mind were beginning to achieve genuine rule over nature. On the other hand, the conception that the world as it stood was an embodiment of a fixed and comprehensive Mind or Reason was uncongenial to those whose main concern was with the deficiencies of the world and with an attempt to remedy them. The effect of the objective theological idealism that had developed out of classic metaphysical idealism was to make the mind submissive and acquiescent. The new individualism chafed under the restrictions imposed upon it by the notion of a universal reason which had once and for all shaped nature and destiny.
Earlier modern philosophy (even if it didn't realize it) was trying to reconcile the traditional idea of a rational and ideal basis for the universe with a new focus on individual thought and a growing confidence in its abilities. It was caught in a dilemma. On one hand, it didn’t want to get lost in a materialism that placed human existence and mind under the control of physical matter—especially at a time when people and their minds were beginning to genuinely take charge of nature. On the other hand, the idea that the world, as it is, represents a fixed and all-encompassing Mind or Reason didn’t sit well with those who were mainly focused on the flaws in the world and trying to fix them. The impact of the objective theological idealism that emerged from classic metaphysical idealism was to make the mind submissive and compliant. The new individualism felt restricted by the concept of a universal reason that had predetermined nature and destiny.
In breaking away from antique and medieval thought, accordingly, early modern thought continued the older tradition of a Reason that creates and constitutes the world, but combined it with the notion that this Reason operates through the human mind, individual or collective. This is the common note of idealism sounded by all the philosophies of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, whether belonging to the British school of Locke, Berkeley and Hume or the Continental school of Descartes. In Kant as everybody knows the two strains came together; and the theme of the formation of the knowable world by means of a thought that[Pg 51] operated exclusively through the human knower became explicit. Idealism ceased to be metaphysical and cosmic in order to become epistemological and personal.
In moving away from old-fashioned and medieval ideas, early modern thinking carried on the older tradition of a Reason that creates and shapes the world, but paired it with the idea that this Reason functions through the human mind, whether individually or collectively. This is the shared theme of idealism that many philosophies of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries expressed, whether from the British school of Locke, Berkeley, and Hume, or the Continental school of Descartes. As everyone knows, in Kant, these two strands merged; and the idea of forming the knowable world through a thought that[Pg 51] functions solely through the human knower became clear. Idealism shifted from being metaphysical and cosmic to being epistemological and personal.
It is evident that this development represents merely a transitional stage. It tried, after all, to put the new wine in the old bottles. It did not achieve a free and unbiased formulation of the meaning of the power to direct nature's forces through knowledge—that is, purposeful, experimental action acting to reshape beliefs and institutions. The ancient tradition was still strong enough to project itself unconsciously into men's ways of thinking, and to hamper and compromise the expression of the really modern forces and aims. Essential philosophic reconstruction represents an attempt to state these causes and results in a way freed from incompatible inherited factors. It will regard intelligence not as the original shaper and final cause of things, but as the purposeful energetic re-shaper of those phases of nature and life that obstruct social well-being. It esteems the individual not as an exaggeratedly self-sufficient Ego which by some magic creates the world, but as the agent who is responsible through initiative, inventiveness and intelligently directed labor for re-creating the world, transforming it into an instrument and possession of intelligence.
It's clear that this development is just a temporary stage. It attempted, after all, to fit new ideas into old frameworks. It didn't succeed in creating a clear and unbiased understanding of the ability to harness nature's forces through knowledge—meaning purposeful, experimental actions aimed at reshaping beliefs and institutions. The old traditions were still strong enough to influence people's thinking unconsciously, hindering and diluting the expression of truly modern forces and goals. A fundamental philosophical overhaul represents an effort to articulate these causes and effects in a way that's free from conflicting inherited factors. It will view intelligence not as the original creator and ultimate cause of things, but as the active, purposeful force reshaping those aspects of nature and life that hinder social well-being. It sees the individual not as an overly self-sufficient Ego that magically creates the world, but as the agent responsible for re-creating the world through initiative, creativity, and intelligently directed work, transforming it into a tool and possession of intelligence.
The train of ideas represented by the Baconian Knowledge is Power thus failed in getting an emanci[Pg 52]pated and independent expression. These become hopelessly entangled in standpoints and prepossessions that embodied a social, political and scientific tradition with which they were completely incompatible. The obscurity, the confusion of modern philosophy is the product of this attempt to combine two things which cannot possibly be combined either logically or morally. Philosophic reconstruction for the present is thus the endeavor to undo the entanglement and to permit the Baconian aspirations to come to a free and unhindered expression. In succeeding lectures we shall consider the needed reconstruction as it affects certain classic philosophic antitheses, like those of experience and reason, the real and the ideal. But first we shall have to consider the modifying effect exercised upon philosophy by that changed conception of nature, animate and inanimate, which we owe to the progress of science.
The ideas represented by Bacon's Knowledge is Power failed to gain a clear and independent expression. They got hopelessly tangled in perspectives and biases rooted in a social, political, and scientific tradition that they were completely incompatible with. The confusion and obscurity of modern philosophy stem from this attempt to merge two things that can’t logically or morally fit together. Philosophic reconstruction today aims to unravel this entanglement and allow Bacon's aspirations to be expressed freely and openly. In upcoming lectures, we will look at the necessary reconstruction as it relates to classic philosophical oppositions, such as experience versus reason and the real versus the ideal. But first, we need to examine how the changing understanding of both living and non-living nature, thanks to advancements in science, has influenced philosophy.
CHAPTER III
THE SCIENTIFIC FACTOR IN RECONSTRUCTION OF PHILOSOPHY
Philosophy starts from some deep and wide way of responding to the difficulties life presents, but it grows only when material is at hand for making this practical response conscious, articulate and communicable. Accompanying the economic, political and ecclesiastical changes which were alluded to in an earlier lecture, was a scientific revolution enormous in scope and leaving unchanged almost no detail of belief about nature, physical and human. In part this scientific transformation was produced by just the change in practical attitude and temper. But as it progressed, it furnished that change an appropriate vocabulary, congenial to its needs, and made it articulate. The advance of science in its larger generalizations and in its specific detail of fact supplied precisely that intellectual equipment of ideas and concrete fact that was needed in order to formulate, precipitate, communicate and propagate the new disposition. Today, accordingly, we shall deal with those contrasting conceptions of the structure and constitution of Nature, which when they are accepted on the[Pg 54] authority of science (alleged or real), form the intellectual framework of philosophy.
Philosophy begins with a deep and broad approach to the challenges that life presents, but it only develops when there are materials available to make this practical response clear, expressible, and shareable. Alongside the economic, political, and church changes mentioned in an earlier lecture, there was a massive scientific revolution that left almost no aspect of belief about nature—both physical and human—unchanged. Part of this scientific shift was driven by changes in practical attitudes and mindset. As it evolved, it provided the right vocabulary that matched these needs and made it possible to express them. The progress of science, with its overarching ideas and specific details, supplied the intellectual tools and facts necessary to shape, clarify, share, and promote this new perspective. Today, we will explore those contrasting ideas regarding the structure and makeup of Nature, which, when accepted on the[Pg 54] authority of science (whether claimed or genuine), create the intellectual foundation of philosophy.
Contrasting conceptions of ancient and modern science have been selected. For I see no way in which the truly philosophic import of the picture of the world painted by modern science can be appreciated except to exhibit it in contrast with that earlier picture which gave classic metaphysics its intellectual foundation and confirmation. The world in which philosophers once put their trust was a closed world, a world consisting internally of a limited number of fixed forms, and having definite boundaries externally. The world of modern science is an open world, a world varying indefinitely without the possibility of assignable limit in its internal make-up, a world stretching beyond any assignable bounds externally. Again, the world in which even the most intelligent men of olden times thought they lived was a fixed world, a realm where changes went on only within immutable limits of rest and permanence, and a world where the fixed and unmoving was, as we have already noted, higher in quality and authority than the moving and altering. And in the third place, the world which men once saw with their eyes, portrayed in their imaginations and repeated in their plans of conduct, was a world of a limited number of classes, kinds, forms, distinct in quality (as kinds and species must be distinct) and[Pg 55] arranged in a graded order of superiority and inferiority.
Contrasting views of ancient and modern science have been chosen. I believe there's no way to truly appreciate the philosophical significance of the picture of the world created by modern science without showing it alongside the older picture that provided the intellectual basis and support for classic metaphysics. The world that philosophers once relied on was a closed world, consisting internally of a limited number of fixed forms and having clear external boundaries. The world of modern science is an open world, one that varies endlessly without any assignable limits in its internal structure and stretches beyond any assignable boundaries externally. Furthermore, the world that even the most intelligent people of ancient times believed they inhabited was a fixed world, where changes occurred only within unchanging limits of rest and permanence, and a world where the fixed and unmovable was, as we have already noted, seen as higher in quality and authority than the moving and changing. Lastly, the world that people once perceived with their senses, imagined, and incorporated into their plans was one of a limited number of distinct classes, kinds, and forms (as kinds and species must be distinct) arranged in a hierarchy of superiority and inferiority.[Pg 55]
It is not easy to recall the image of the universe which was taken for granted in the world tradition. In spite of its dramatic rendering (as in Dante), of the dialectical elaborations of Aristotle and St. Thomas, in spite of the fact that it held men's minds captive until the last three hundred years, and that its overthrow involved a religious upheaval, it is already dim, faded and remote. Even as a separate and abstract thing of theory it is not easy to recover.
It’s not easy to bring to mind the view of the universe that was simply accepted in traditional thought. Despite its vivid portrayals (like those in Dante), the complex explanations from Aristotle and St. Thomas, and the fact that it captivated people's minds until about three hundred years ago—leading to a major religious upheaval when it was challenged—it now feels distant, blurred, and lost. Even as a distinct and theoretical concept, it’s hard to grasp again.
As something pervasive, interwoven with all the details of reflection and observation, with the plans and rules of behavior, it is impossible to call it back again. Yet, as best we can, we need to put before our minds a definitely enclosed universe, something which can be called a universe in a literal and visible sense, having the earth at its fixed and unchanging centre and at a fixed circumference the heavenly arch of fixed stars moving in an eternal round of divine ether, hemming in all things and keeping them forever at one and in order. The earth, though at the centre, is the coarsest, grossest, most material, least significant and good (or perfect) of the parts of this closed world. It is the scene of maximum fluctuation and vicissitude. It is the least rational, and therefore the least notable, or knowable; it offers the least to reward contemplation, provoke[Pg 56] admiration and govern conduct. Between this grossly material centre and the immaterial, spiritual and eternal heavens lie a definite series of regions of moon, planets, sun, etc., each of which gains in rank, value, rationality and true being as it is farther from earth and nearer the heavens. Each of these regions is composed of its own appropriate stuff of earth, water, air, fire in its own dominant degree, until we reach the heavenly firmament which transcends all these principles, being constituted, as was just said, of that immaterial, inalterable energy called ether.
As something all-encompassing, woven into every detail of thought and observation, along with our plans and rules for behavior, it's impossible to bring it back. However, we need to envision a clearly defined universe, something we can literally and visibly call a universe, with the earth at its fixed and unchanging center and the heavenly arch of fixed stars moving endlessly in a divine ether at its boundary, enclosing everything and keeping it all in order. The earth, despite being at the center, is the most coarse, material, and insignificant part of this closed world. It's a place of maximum change and uncertainty. It's the least rational and therefore the least remarkable, or knowable; it offers the least reward for contemplation, admiration, and guiding behavior. Between this coarse material center and the immaterial, spiritual, and eternal heavens lies a specific series of regions: the moon, planets, sun, and so on, each gaining rank, value, rationality, and true existence as it moves further from the earth and closer to the heavens. Each of these regions is made up of its own mix of earth, water, air, and fire in different proportions, until we reach the heavenly realm that transcends all these elements, being made up of that immaterial, unchanging energy called ether.
Within this tight and pent in universe, changes take place of course. But they are only of a small number of fixed kinds; and they operate only within fixed limits. Each kind of stuff has its own appropriate motion. It is the nature of earthly things to be heavy, since they are gross, and hence to move downward. Fire and superior things are light and hence move upward to their proper place; air rises only to the plane of the planets, where it then takes its back and forth motion which naturally belongs to it, as is evident in the winds and in respiration. Ether being the highest of all physical things has a purely circular movement. The daily return of the fixed stars is the closest possible approximation to eternity, and to the self-involved revolution of mind upon its own ideal axis of reason. Upon the earth in virtue of its earthly nature—or rather its[Pg 57] lack of virtue—is a scene of mere change. Mere flux, aimless and meaningless, starts at no definite point and arrives at nothing, amounts to nothing. Mere changes of quantity, all purely mechanical changes, are of this kind. They are like the shiftings of the sands by the sea. They may be sensed, but they cannot be "noted" or understood; they lack fixed limits which govern them. They are contemptible. They are casual, the sport of accident.
Within this confined and limited universe, changes obviously occur. But they are only a few specific types and only happen within predetermined boundaries. Each type of matter has its own natural motion. It's in the nature of earthly things to be heavy, so they move downward. Fire and higher elements are lighter, so they rise to their rightful place; air only ascends to the level of the planets, where it then moves back and forth in a way that is natural to it, evident in the winds and in how we breathe. Ether, being the highest of all physical elements, has a purely circular motion. The daily return of the fixed stars is the closest we get to eternity and the self-contained revolution of the mind reflecting on its own ideal axis of reason. On Earth, because of its earthly nature—or rather its[Pg 57] lack of virtue—is a mere scene of change. Just flux, aimless and meaningless, starts with no specific beginning and leads to nothing, amounts to nothing. Simple changes in quantity, all purely mechanical changes, fall into this category. They resemble the shifting sands by the sea. They can be sensed, but they can't be fully "noted" or understood; they lack the fixed limits that control them. They are insignificant, random, mere playthings of chance.
Only changes which lead to some defined or fixed outcome of form are of any account and can have any account—any logos or reason—made of them. The growth of plants and animals illustrates the highest kind of change which is possible in the sublunary or mundane sphere. They go from one definite fixed form to another. Oaks generate only oaks, oysters only oysters, man only man. The material factor of mechanical production enters in, but enters in as accident to prevent the full consummation of the type of the species, and to bring about the meaningless variations which diversify various oaks or oysters from one another; or in extreme cases to produce freaks, sports, monsters, three-handed or four-toed men. Aside from accidental and undesirable variations, each individual has a fixed career to pursue, a fixed path in which to travel. Terms which sound modern, words like potentiality and development abound in Aristotelian thought,[Pg 58] and have misled some into reading into his thought modern meanings. But the significance of these words in classic and medieval thought is rigidly determined by their context. Development holds merely of the course of changes which takes place within a particular member of the species. It is only a name for the predetermined movement from the acorn to the oak tree. It takes place not in things generally but only in some one of the numerically insignificant members of the oak species. Development, evolution, never means, as in modern science, origin of new forms, a mutation from an old species, but only the monotonous traversing of a previously plotted cycle of change. So potentiality never means, as in modern life, the possibility of novelty, of invention, of radical deviation, but only that principle in virtue of which the acorn becomes the oak. Technically, it is the capacity for movement between opposites. Only the cold can become hot; only the dry can become wet; only the babe can become a man; the seed the full-grown wheat and so on. Potentiality instead of implying the emergence of anything novel means merely the facility with which a particular thing repeats the recurrent processes of its kind, and thus becomes a specific case of the eternal forms in and through which all things are constituted.
Only changes that lead to some defined or fixed outcome are worth noting and can have any reason made of them. The growth of plants and animals shows the highest form of change possible in the mundane world. They move from one definite fixed form to another. Oaks produce only oaks, oysters only oysters, humans only humans. The material factor of mechanical production plays a role, but it enters as an accident that prevents the full realization of the species type, leading to random variations that differentiate various oaks or oysters from one another; or in extreme cases, to produce oddities, abnormalities, or unusual individuals. Apart from these accidental and undesirable variations, each individual has a specific path to follow. Modern-sounding terms like potentiality and development are common in Aristotelian thought,[Pg 58] and have misled some readers into interpreting these concepts with modern meanings. However, the significance of these words in classical and medieval thought is strictly defined by their context. Development refers only to the changes that occur within a particular member of a species. It is just a term for the predetermined journey from acorn to oak tree. It happens not in things generally but only in some insignificant individual of the oak species. Development or evolution never implies, as in modern science, the origin of new forms or a mutation from an old species, but only the consistent progression through a previously established cycle of change. Thus, potentiality does not mean, as in modern life, the possibility of novelty, invention, or radical deviation, but merely the principle that allows the acorn to become the oak. Technically, it represents the capacity for movement between opposites. Only the cold can become hot; only the dry can become wet; only the infant can grow into a man; the seed can grow into mature wheat, and so forth. Instead of indicating the emergence of anything new, potentiality signifies just the ease with which a particular thing repeats the recurring processes of its kind, thus becoming a specific example of the eternal forms that constitute everything.
In spite of the almost infinite numerical diversity of individuals, there are only a limited number of species,[Pg 59] kinds or sorts. And the world is essentially a world which falls into sorts; it is pre-arranged into distinct classes. Moreover, just as we naturally arrange plants and animals into series, ranks and grades, from the lower to the highest, so with all things in the universe. The distinct classes to which things belong by their very nature form a hierarchical order. There are castes in nature. The universe is constituted on an aristocratic, one can truly say a feudal, plan. Species, classes do not mix or overlap—except in cases of accident, and to the result of chaos. Otherwise, everything belongs in advance to a certain class, and the class has its own fixed place in the hierarchy of Being. The universe is indeed a tidy spot whose purity is interfered with only by those irregular changes in individuals which are due to the presence of an obdurate matter that refuses to yield itself wholly to rule and form. Otherwise it is a universe with a fixed place for everything and where everything knows its place, its station and class, and keeps it. Hence what are known technically as final and formal causes are supreme, and efficient causes are relegated to an inferior place. The so-called final cause is just a name for the fact that there is some fixed form characteristic of a class or sort of things which governs the changes going on, so that they tend toward it as their end and goal, the fulfilment of their true nature. The supralunar region is the end[Pg 60] or final cause of the proper movements of air and fire; the earth of the motions of crass, heavy things; the oak of the acorn; the mature form in general of the germinal.
Despite the almost infinite number of individuals, there are only a limited number of species, [Pg 59] kinds, or types. The world is fundamentally categorized; it is organized into distinct classes. Just like we naturally classify plants and animals into series, ranks, and grades from the lower to the highest, the same applies to everything in the universe. The distinct classes to which things naturally belong form a hierarchical order. There are castes in nature. The universe is structured on an aristocratic, one might even say a feudal, system. Species and classes do not mix or overlap—except in rare cases of accident, which leads to chaos. Otherwise, everything belongs to a certain class from the start, and each class has its own designated place in the hierarchy of Being. The universe is indeed an orderly place, its purity only disrupted by those irregular changes in individuals caused by a stubborn matter that refuses to completely conform to rules and shapes. Otherwise, it is a universe with a designated spot for everything, where everything knows its place, station, and class, and maintains it. Therefore, what are technically referred to as final and formal causes are paramount, while efficient causes take a lesser role. The so-called final cause simply refers to the idea that there is a fixed form characteristic of a class or type of things that directs the changes occurring, steering them toward it as their end and ultimate goal, fulfilling their true nature. The supralunar region is the end [Pg 60] or final cause of the rightful movements of air and fire; the earth governs the motions of heavy, dense things; the oak is the end result of the acorn; and the mature form in general is the outcome of the germinal.
The "efficient cause," that which produces and instigates a movement is only some external change as it accidentally gives a kind of push to an immature, imperfect being and starts it moving toward its perfected or fulfilled form. The final cause is the perfected form regarded as the explanation or reason of prior changes. When it is not taken in reference to the changes completed and brought to rest in it, but in itself it is the "formal cause": The inherent nature or character which "makes" or constitutes a thing what it is so far as it truly is, namely, what it is so far as it does not change. Logically and practically all of the traits which have been enumerated cohere. Attack one and you attack all. When any one is undermined, all go. This is the reason why the intellectual modification of the last few centuries may truly be called a revolution. It has substituted a conception of the world differing at every point. It makes little matter at what point you commence to trace the difference, you find yourself carried into all other points.
The "efficient cause," which initiates and drives a movement, is simply an external change that accidentally gives a push to an immature, imperfect being, setting it on a path toward its perfected or completed form. The final cause is that perfected form, seen as the explanation or reason for earlier changes. When it's considered independently of the changes that have been completed and settled within it, it becomes the "formal cause": the inherent nature or character that "makes" or defines a thing what it is in terms of its true essence, meaning what it is in the sense that it does not change. Logically and practically, all the traits mentioned are interconnected. If you challenge one, you challenge them all. When any one is undermined, they all fall. This is why the intellectual changes of the past few centuries can genuinely be called a revolution. It has replaced a worldview that differs at every level. No matter where you start tracing the differences, you end up discovering connections to all other aspects.
Instead of a closed universe, science now presents us with one infinite in space and time, having no limits here or there, at this end, so to speak, or at that, and as[Pg 61] infinitely complex in internal structure as it is infinite in extent. Hence it is also an open world, an infinitely variegated one, a world which in the old sense can hardly be called a universe at all; so multiplex and far-reaching that it cannot be summed up and grasped in any one formula. And change rather than fixity is now a measure of "reality" or energy of being; change is omnipresent. The laws in which the modern man of science is interested are laws of motion, of generation and consequence. He speaks of law where the ancients spoke of kind and essence, because what he wants is a correlation of changes, an ability to detect one change occurring in correspondence with another. He does not try to define and delimit something remaining constant in change. He tries to describe a constant order of change. And while the word "constant" appears in both statements, the meaning of the word is not the same. In one case, we are dealing with something constant in existence, physical or metaphysical; in the other case, with something constant in function and operation. One is a form of independent being; the other is a formula of description and calculation of interdependent changes.
Instead of a closed universe, science now shows us one that is infinite in both space and time, without limits anywhere, at one end or the other, and as[Pg 61] infinitely complex in its internal structure as it is vast in size. Therefore, it’s also an open world, an endlessly diverse one, a world that, in the traditional sense, can hardly be called a universe at all; so intricate and expansive that it can't be summed up or understood through any single formula. Change, rather than stability, is now seen as the measure of "reality" or the essence of existence; change is everywhere. The laws that modern scientists are interested in are laws of motion, of creation and consequence. He refers to law where ancient thinkers spoke of kind and essence because what he seeks is a correlation of changes, a way to recognize one change happening in relation to another. He doesn’t aim to define and restrict something that remains constant in change. He works to describe a constant order of change. And while the term "constant" may appear in both situations, its meaning is different. In one context, we’re talking about something constant in existence, whether physical or metaphysical; in the other, something constant in function and operation. One represents a form of independent existence; the other provides a framework for describing and calculating interdependent changes.
In short, classic thought accepted a feudally arranged order of classes or kinds, each "holding" from a superior and in turn giving the rule of conduct and service to an inferior. This trait reflects and[Pg 62] parallels most closely the social situation we were considering at the last hour. We have a fairly definite notion of society as organized upon the feudal basis. The family principle, the principle of kinship is strong, and especially is this true as we ascend in the social scale. At the lower end, individuals may be lost more or less in the mass. Since all are parts of the common herd, there is nothing especial to distinguish their birth. But among the privileged and ruling class the case is quite different. The tie of kinship at once marks a group off externally and gives it distinction, and internally holds all its members together. Kinship, kind, class, genus are synonymous terms, starting from social and concrete facts and going to the technical and abstract. For kinship is a sign of a common nature, of something universal and permanent running through all particular individuals, and giving them a real and objective unity. Because such and such persons are kin they are really, and not merely conventionally, marked off into a class having something unique about it. All contemporary members are bound into an objective unity which includes ancestors and descendants and excludes all who belong to another kin or kind. Assuredly this parcelling out of the world into separate kinds, each having its qualitatively distinct nature in contrast with other species, binding numerically distinct individuals together, and preventing their diversities from exceeding[Pg 63] fixed bounds, may without exaggeration be called a projection of the family principle into the world at large.
In short, classic thought accepted a feudal structure of classes, where each group was "held" by a superior, and in turn, provided rules of conduct and service to an inferior. This characteristic aligns most closely with the social situation we discussed last hour. We have a clear idea of society organized on a feudal basis. The family principle and kinship are strong, especially as we move up the social ladder. At the lower levels, individuals may blend into the crowd. Since everyone is part of the common group, nothing particularly distinguishes their background. But among the privileged and ruling class, it's a different story. The bond of kinship immediately sets a group apart externally and gives it distinction, while also bringing its members together internally. Kinship, kind, class, genus are all synonymous, starting from social and concrete facts and moving to the technical and abstract. Kinship indicates a shared nature, something universal and enduring that connects all specific individuals and provides them with real and objective unity. Because certain individuals are related, they are genuinely, not just conventionally, categorized into a class with unique qualities. All contemporary members are linked in an objective unity that includes ancestors and descendants, while excluding anyone from a different kin or group. Clearly, this categorization of the world into separate kinds, each possessing its distinct nature compared to other species, binding numerically distinct individuals together and preventing their differences from exceeding fixed limits, can accurately be described as a projection of the family principle into the broader world.
In a feudally organized society, moreover, each kinship group or species occupies a definite place. It is marked by the possession of a specific rank higher or lower with respect to other grades. This position confers upon it certain privileges, enabling it to enforce certain claims upon those lower in the scale and entailing upon it certain services and homage to be rendered to superiors. The relationship of causation, so to speak, is up and down. Influence, power, proceeds from above to below; the activities of the inferior are performed with respect, quite literally, to what is above. Action and reaction are far from being equal and in opposite directions. All action is of one sort, of the nature of lordship, and proceeds from the higher to the lower. Reaction is of the nature of subjection and deference and proceeds from lower to higher. The classic theory of the constitution of the world corresponds point by point to this ordering of classes in a scale of dignity and power.
In a feudal society, each family or group has a specific place. This is determined by their particular rank, which can be higher or lower compared to others. This rank comes with certain privileges, allowing the group to make claims on those of lower status and requiring them to provide certain services and respect to those above them. The relationship is hierarchical, with influence and power flowing from the top down; the actions of those below are carried out in relation to those above. The dynamics are not equal and opposite. All actions come from a position of authority and move from the higher to the lower. Reactions are characterized by submission and respect and move from the lower to the higher. This traditional view of the world's structure aligns perfectly with this hierarchy of classes based on dignity and power.
A third trait assigned by historians to feudalism is that the ordering of ranks centres about armed service and the relationship of armed defense and protection. I am afraid that what has already been said about the parallelism of ancient cosmology with social organization may seem a fanciful analogy; and if a comparison is also[Pg 64] drawn in this last regard, there will be no doubt in your minds that a metaphor is being forced. Such is truly the case if we take the comparison too literally. But not so, if we confine our attention to the notion of rule and command implied in both. Attention has already been called to the meaning that is now given the term law—a constant relationship among changes. Nevertheless, we often hear about laws which "govern" events, and it often seems to be thought that phenomena would be utterly disorderly were there not laws to keep them in order. This way of thinking is a survival of reading social relationships into nature—not necessarily a feudal relationship, but the relation of ruler and ruled, sovereign and subject. Law is assimilated to a command or order. If the factor of personal will is eliminated (as it was in the best Greek thought) still the idea of law or universal is impregnated with the sense of a guiding and ruling influence exerted from above on what is naturally inferior to it. The universal governs as the end and model which the artisan has in mind "governs" his movements. The Middle Ages added to this Greek idea of control the idea of a command proceeding from a superior will; and hence thought of the operations of nature as if they were a fulfilment of a task set by one who had authority to direct action.
A third trait that historians attribute to feudalism is that the structure of ranks is based on military service and the relationship between defense and protection. I worry that what has already been mentioned about the similarity between ancient cosmology and social organization might seem like a stretch; and if a comparison is also drawn in this final regard, there will be no doubt in your minds that a metaphor is being forced. This is indeed the case if we take the comparison too literally. However, it is not the case if we focus on the concept of rule and authority present in both. Attention has already been brought to the way the term law is currently understood—a consistent relationship among changes. Yet, we often hear about laws that "govern" events, and it often seems that people believe phenomena would be completely chaotic without laws to maintain order. This way of thinking is a remnant of interpreting social relationships in nature—not necessarily a feudal relationship, but the dynamic between rulers and the ruled, sovereigns and subjects. Law is equated with a command or order. Even if the aspect of personal will is removed (as it was in the best Greek thought), the idea of law or the universal is still infused with the notion of a guiding and ruling influence from above over what is naturally below it. The universal governs much like the end goal or model that an artisan has in mind "governs" their actions. The Middle Ages expanded on this Greek idea of control by incorporating the notion of a command coming from a superior will; thus, they viewed the workings of nature as if they were fulfilling a task assigned by someone with the authority to direct action.
The traits of the picture of nature drawn by modern[Pg 65] science fairly spring by contrast into high relief. Modern science took its first step when daring astronomers abolished the distinction of high, sublime and ideal forces operating in the heavens from lower and material forces actuating terrestrial events. The supposed heterogeneity of substances and forces between heaven and earth was denied. It was asserted that the same laws hold everywhere, that there is homogeneity of material and process everywhere throughout nature. The remote and esthetically sublime is to be scientifically described and explained in terms of homely familiar events and forces. The material of direct handling and observation is that of which we are surest; it is the better known. Until we can convert the grosser and more superficial observations of far-away things in the heavens into elements identical with those of things directly at hand, they remain blind and not understood. Instead of presenting superior worth, they present only problems. They are not means of enlightenment but challenges. The earth is not superior in rank to sun, moon and stars, but it is equal in dignity, and its occurrences give the key to the understanding of celestial existences. Being at hand, they are also capable of being brought under our hand; they can be manipulated, broken up, resolved into elements which can be managed, combined at will in old and new forms. The net result may be termed, I think, without any great[Pg 66] forcing, the substitution of a democracy of individual facts equal in rank for the feudal system of an ordered gradation of general classes of unequal rank.
The characteristics of the natural world depicted by modern[Pg 65] science stand out sharply in contrast. Modern science began when bold astronomers eliminated the division between the lofty, sublime, and ideal forces operating in the sky and the lower, material forces influencing earthly events. The idea that substances and forces differ between heaven and earth was rejected. It was claimed that the same laws apply universally, and that there is uniformity of material and processes throughout nature. The distant and aesthetically sublime should be scientifically described and explained in terms of everyday events and forces we recognize. The materials we can directly handle and observe are the ones we understand best. Until we can transform the coarser and more superficial observations of distant celestial bodies into elements that are identical to those around us, they remain obscure and misunderstood. Instead of offering greater value, they present only challenges. They do not enlighten us but pose questions. The earth is not hierarchically superior to the sun, moon, and stars; rather, it holds equal dignity, and its events unlock the understanding of celestial existence. Being at hand, they can also be brought under our control; they can be manipulated, broken apart, and resolved into elements that we can manage and combine in both old and new forms. The overall outcome could be described, I think, without much[Pg 66] exaggeration, as the replacement of a democracy of individual facts of equal significance for the feudal structure of a hierarchical ordering of general classes of unequal rank.
One important incident of the new science was the destruction of the idea that the earth is the centre of the universe. When the idea of a fixed centre went, there went with it the idea of a closed universe and a circumscribing heavenly boundary. To the Greek sense, just because its theory of knowing was dominated by esthetic considerations, the finite was the perfect. Literally, the finite was the finished, the ended, the completed, that with no ragged edges and unaccountable operations. The infinite or limitless was lacking in character just because it was in-finite. Being everything, it was nothing. It was unformed and chaotic, uncontrolled and unruly, the source of incalculable deviations and accidents. Our present feeling that associates infinity with boundless power, with capacity for expansion that knows no end, with the delight in a progress that has no external limit, would be incomprehensible were it not that interest has shifted from the esthetic to the practical; from interest in beholding a harmonious and complete scene to interest in transforming an inharmonious one. One has only to read the authors of the transition period, say Giordano Bruno, to realize what a pent-in, suffocating sensation they associated with a closed, finite world, and what a[Pg 67] feeling of exhilaration, expansion and boundless possibility was aroused in them by the thought of a world infinite in stretch of space and time, and composed internally of infinitesimal infinitely numerous elements. That which the Greeks withdrew from with repulsion they welcomed with an intoxicated sense of adventure. The infinite meant, it was true, something forever untraversed even by thought, and hence something forever unknown—no matter how great attainment in learning. But this "forever unknown" instead of being chilling and repelling was now an inspiring challenge to ever-renewed inquiry, and an assurance of inexhaustible possibilities of progress.
One significant development in the new science was the breakdown of the belief that the Earth is the center of the universe. Once the idea of a fixed center was abandoned, the concept of a closed universe and a surrounding heavenly boundary disappeared as well. To the Greeks, because their understanding was largely shaped by aesthetic considerations, the finite was seen as perfect. Essentially, the finite was the complete, the finished, without any rough edges or inexplicable processes. The infinite, on the other hand, was perceived as lacking in character simply because it was infinite. Since it encompassed everything, it was also viewed as nothing. It was unformed and chaotic, uncontrollable and unruly, a source of countless deviations and accidents. Our current perception of infinity, associated with unlimited power, an endless capacity for growth, and the joy of progress without external limits, would seem incomprehensible if interest hadn't shifted from aesthetics to practicality; from admiring a harmonious and complete scene to the desire to transform a disharmonious one. One only needs to read the authors from the transition period, like Giordano Bruno, to grasp the suffocating sensation they felt in a closed, finite world, and the exhilarating feeling of expansion and limitless possibility that the idea of an infinite universe—vast in space and time, filled with countless infinitesimal elements—evoked in them. What the Greeks recoiled from, they embraced with an intoxicating sense of adventure. The infinite indeed represented something perpetually uncharted by thought, and thus something eternally unknown—regardless of how much knowledge one gained. But this "forever unknown," rather than being cold and off-putting, became an inspiring challenge for continuous exploration and a promise of endless possibilities for progress.
The student of history knows well that the Greeks made great progress in the science of mechanics as well as of geometry. At first sight, it appears strange that with this advance in mechanics so little advance was made in the direction of modern science. The seeming paradox impels us to ask why it was that mechanics remained a separate science, why it was not used in description and explanation of natural phenomena after the manner of Galileo and Newton. The answer is found in the social parallelism already mentioned. Socially speaking, machines, tools, were devices employed by artisans. The science of mechanics had to do with the kind of things employed by human mechanics, and mechanics were base fellows. They were at the[Pg 68] lower end of the social scale, and how could light on the heavens, the highest, be derived from them? The application of considerations of mechanics to natural phenomena would moreover have implied an interest in the practical control and utilization of phenomena which was totally incompatible with the importance attached to final causes as fixed determiners of nature. All the scientific reformers of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries strikingly agree in regarding the doctrine of final causes as the cause of the failure of science. Why? Because this doctrine taught that the processes of nature are held in bondage to certain fixed ends which they must tend to realize. Nature was kept in leading strings; it was cramped down to production of a limited number of stereotyped results. Only a comparatively small number of things could be brought into being, and these few must be similar to the ends which similar cycles of change had effected in the past. The scope of inquiry and understanding was limited to the narrow round of processes eventuating in the fixed ends which the observed world offered to view. At best, invention and production of new results by use of machines and tools must be restricted to articles of transient dignity and bodily, not intellectual, use.
The history student knows that the Greeks made significant advances in the fields of mechanics and geometry. At first glance, it seems odd that despite this progress in mechanics, there was so little advancement towards modern science. This apparent contradiction leads us to question why mechanics remained a separate discipline and why it wasn't used to describe and explain natural phenomena like Galileo and Newton did. The answer lies in the previously mentioned social parallelism. Socially, machines and tools were seen as devices used by craftsmen. The science of mechanics was concerned with the types of things used by human mechanics, who were considered lowly workers. They occupied the lower end of the social hierarchy, so how could insights from them shed light on the heavens, which were regarded as the highest realm? Additionally, applying mechanics to natural phenomena would have suggested an interest in practically controlling and utilizing those phenomena, which clashed with the significance placed on final causes as fixed determinants of nature. All the scientific reformers of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries unanimously agreed that the doctrine of final causes was the root cause of the stagnation in science. Why? Because this doctrine held that natural processes were bound to specific fixed ends that they had to achieve. Nature was held back; it was restricted to producing a limited number of predictable results. Only a small variety of things could come into existence, and these had to resemble the outcomes that similar cycles of change had generated in the past. The range of inquiry and understanding was confined to the narrow set of processes leading to the fixed ends that the observable world presented. At best, the invention and production of new results through the use of machines and tools had to be limited to items of fleeting usefulness, physical rather than intellectual value.
When the rigid clamp of fixed ends was taken off from nature, observation and imagination were emancipated, and experimental control for scientific and prac[Pg 69]tical purposes enormously stimulated. Because natural processes were no longer restricted to a fixed number of immovable ends or results, anything might conceivably happen. It was only a question of what elements could be brought into juxtaposition so that they would work upon one another. Immediately, mechanics ceased to be a separate science and became an organ for attacking nature. The mechanics of the lever, wheel, pulley and inclined plane told accurately what happens when things in space are used to move one another during definite periods of time. The whole of nature became a scene of pushes and pulls, of cogs and levers, of motions of parts or elements to which the formulae of movements produced by well-known machines were directly applicable.
When the strict limits of fixed ends were removed from nature, observation and imagination were freed, and control through experimentation for both scientific and practical purposes greatly increased. Since natural processes were no longer bound to a fixed set of unchangeable ends or results, anything could potentially occur. It simply became a matter of which elements could be placed next to each other to interact. Immediately, mechanics stopped being a separate science and transformed into a tool for understanding nature. The mechanics of levers, wheels, pulleys, and inclined planes accurately explained what happens when objects in space move each other over specific periods of time. Nature turned into a landscape of pushes and pulls, gears and levers, with motions of parts or elements where the formulas for movements derived from familiar machines were directly applicable.
The banishing of ends and forms from the universe has seemed to many an ideal and spiritual impoverishment. When nature was regarded as a set of mechanical interactions, it apparently lost all meaning and purpose. Its glory departed. Elimination of differences of quality deprived it of beauty. Denial to nature of all inherent longings and aspiring tendencies toward ideal ends removed nature and natural science from contact with poetry, religion and divine things. There seemed to be left only a harsh, brutal despiritualized exhibition of mechanical forces. As a consequence, it has seemed to many philosophers that one of their[Pg 70] chief problems was to reconcile the existence of this purely mechanical world with belief in objective rationality and purpose—to save life from a degrading materialism. Hence many sought to re-attain by way of an analysis of the process of knowing, or epistemology, that belief in the superiority of Ideal Being which had anciently been maintained on the basis of cosmology. But when it is recognized that the mechanical view is determined by the requirements of an experimental control of natural energies, this problem of reconciliation no longer vexes us. Fixed forms and ends, let us recall, mark fixed limits to change. Hence they make futile all human efforts to produce and regulate change except within narrow and unimportant limits. They paralyze constructive human inventions by a theory which condemns them in advance to failure. Human activity can conform only to ends already set by nature. It was not till ends were banished from nature that purposes became important as factors in human minds capable of reshaping existence. A natural world that does not subsist for the sake of realizing a fixed set of ends is relatively malleable and plastic; it may be used for this end or that. That nature can be known through the application of mechanical formulae is the prime condition of turning it to human account. Tools, machines are means to be utilized. Only when nature is regarded as mechanical, is systematic invention and[Pg 71] construction of machines relevant to nature's activities. Nature is subdued to human purpose because it is no longer the slave of metaphysical and theological purpose.
The removal of goals and forms from the universe has seemed, to many, like a loss of ideals and spiritual richness. When nature was viewed as just a series of mechanical interactions, it seemed to lose all meaning and purpose, stripping away its glory. The removal of quality differences robbed it of beauty. Denying nature any inherent desires or aspirations toward ideal outcomes distanced nature and natural science from poetry, religion, and the divine. What remained appeared to be a harsh, brutal, soulless display of mechanical forces. As a result, many philosophers felt their main challenge was to reconcile the existence of this purely mechanical world with a belief in objective rationality and purpose—to save life from falling into degrading materialism. Thus, many attempted to reclaim, through the study of knowledge (epistemology), the belief in the supremacy of Ideal Being that had once been supported by cosmology. However, once we acknowledge that the mechanical view is shaped by the need for experimental control over natural energies, this reconciliation issue no longer troubles us. Fixed forms and goals, let's remember, impose strict limits on change. Therefore, they render all human efforts to create and manage change futile, except within narrow and insignificant boundaries. They hinder innovative human creations by a theory that predestines them for failure. Human activity can conform only to goals already set by nature. It wasn't until purposes were removed from nature that they became significant factors in human minds capable of reshaping reality. A natural world that doesn’t exist solely to achieve a fixed set of goals is relatively flexible and adaptable; it can be used for this purpose or that. The ability to understand nature through mechanical formulas is crucial for leveraging it for human benefit. Tools and machines are resources to be employed. Only when nature is seen as mechanical does systematic invention and the construction of machines become relevant to nature’s functions. Nature is made subordinate to human purposes because it is no longer bound to metaphysical and theological aims.
Bergson has pointed out that man might well be called Homo Faber. He is distinguished as the tool-making animal. This has held good since man was man; but till nature was construed in mechanical terms, the making of tools with which to attack and transform nature was sporadic and accidental. Under such circumstances it would not have occurred even to a Bergson that man's tool-making capacity was so important and fundamental that it could be used to define him. The very things that make the nature of the mechanical-physical scientist esthetically blank and dull are the things which render nature amenable to human control. When qualities were subordinated to quantitative and mathematical relationships, color, music and form disappeared from the object of the scientist's inquiry as such. But the remaining properties of weight, extension, numerable velocity of movement and so on were just the qualities which lent themselves to the substitution of one thing for another, to the conversion of one form of energy into another; to the effecting of transformations. When chemical fertilizers can be used in place of animal manures, when improved grain and cattle can be purposefully bred from inferior animals[Pg 72] and grasses, when mechanical energy can be converted into heat and electricity into mechanical energy, man gains power to manipulate nature. Most of all he gains power to frame new ends and aims and to proceed in regular system to their actualization. Only indefinite substitution and convertibility regardless of quality render nature manageable. The mechanization of nature is the condition of a practical and progressive idealism in action.
Bergson noted that humans could be called Homo Faber, which means "tool maker." We are identified as the animal that makes tools. This has always been true since humans existed; however, before nature was understood in mechanical terms, tool-making to interact with and change nature was random and occasional. In that context, even Bergson might not have seen tool-making as such a crucial part of human identity. The same characteristics that make mechanical and physical science seem aesthetically dull are the ones that allow us to control nature. When qualities were prioritized over quantitative and mathematical relationships, aspects like color, music, and form were absent from a scientist's focus. But the qualities that remained—weight, space, measurable speed of movement, and so forth—were exactly those that allowed for substituting one thing for another and transforming forms of energy. When chemical fertilizers replace animal manure, when we selectively breed better crops and livestock from lesser ones, and when we can convert mechanical energy to heat or electricity to mechanical power, humans gain the ability to manipulate nature. Most importantly, we acquire the power to set new goals and systematically work towards achieving them. Only through indefinite substitution and convertibility, regardless of quality, can we manage nature. The mechanization of nature is essential for action based on practical and progressive ideals.
It thus turns out that the old, old dread and dislike of matter as something opposed to mind and threatening it, to be kept within the narrowest bounds of recognition; something to be denied so far as possible lest it encroach upon ideal purposes and finally exclude them from the real world, is as absurd practically as it was impotent intellectually. Judged from the only scientific standpoint, what it does and how it functions, matter means conditions. To respect matter means to respect the conditions of achievement; conditions which hinder and obstruct and which have to be changed, conditions which help and further and which can be used to modify obstructions and attain ends. Only as men have learned to pay sincere and persistent regard to matter, to the conditions upon which depends negatively and positively the success of all endeavor, have they shown sincere and fruitful respect for ends and purposes. To profess to have an aim and then neglect[Pg 73] the means of its execution is self-delusion of the most dangerous sort. Education and morals will begin to find themselves on the same road of advance that say chemical industry and medicine have found for themselves when they too learn fully the lesson of wholehearted and unremitting attention to means and conditions—that is, to what mankind so long despised as material and mechanical. When we take means for ends we indeed fall into moral materialism. But when we take ends without regard to means we degenerate into sentimentalism. In the name of the ideal we fall back upon mere luck and chance and magic or exhortation and preaching; or else upon a fanaticism that will force the realization of preconceived ends at any cost.
It turns out that the long-standing fear and dislike of matter, seen as something that opposes and threatens the mind, which should be kept to a minimum, is as practically absurd as it was intellectually powerless. From a scientific standpoint, matter represents conditions. To respect matter is to respect the conditions necessary for achievement—conditions that can hinder and obstruct, which need to be changed, and conditions that can help and advance, which can be utilized to overcome obstacles and reach goals. Only as people have learned to genuinely and consistently pay attention to matter and the conditions that impact the success of all endeavors, both negatively and positively, have they shown true and fruitful respect for goals and purposes. Claiming to have a goal while ignoring the means to achieve it is a dangerous form of self-deception. Education and morals will begin to progress in the same way that chemical industry and medicine have, once they fully grasp the importance of wholehearted and persistent attention to means and conditions—that is, to what humanity has long looked down upon as material and mechanical. When we prioritize means over ends, we indeed slip into moral materialism. But when we focus on ends without considering means, we fall into sentimentalism. In the name of the ideal, we resort to mere luck, chance, and magic, or rely on exhortation and preaching; or we become fanatical, forcing the realization of predetermined ends at any cost.
I have touched in this lecture upon many things in a cursory way. Yet there has been but one point in mind. The revolution in our conceptions of nature and in our methods of knowing it has bred a new temper of imagination and aspiration. It has confirmed the new attitude generated by economic and political changes. It has supplied this attitude with definite intellectual material with which to formulate and justify itself.
I’ve quickly covered a lot of topics in this lecture. However, there’s really just one main idea. The shift in how we understand nature and how we learn about it has sparked a new sense of imagination and ambition. This change has reinforced the new mindset created by economic and political shifts. It has provided this mindset with clear intellectual resources to shape and support itself.
In the first lecture it was noted that in Greek life prosaic matter of fact or empirical knowledge was at a great disadvantage as compared with the imaginative beliefs that were bound up with special institutions[Pg 74] and moral habitudes. Now this empirical knowledge has grown till it has broken its low and limited sphere of application and esteem. It has itself become an organ of inspiring imagination through introducing ideas of boundless possibility, indefinite progress, free movement, equal opportunity irrespective of fixed limits. It has reshaped social institutions, and in so far developed a new morale. It has achieved ideal values. It is convertible into creative and constructive philosophy.
In the first lecture, it was pointed out that in Greek life, straightforward facts and empirical knowledge were at a significant disadvantage compared to the imaginative beliefs tied to specific institutions and moral habits.[Pg 74] Now, this empirical knowledge has grown to the point where it has broken free from its narrow and limited scope and recognition. It has become a source of inspiring imagination by introducing ideas of limitless possibilities, ongoing progress, unrestricted movement, and equal opportunities regardless of fixed boundaries. It has transformed social institutions and, in doing so, developed a new sense of morality. It has achieved ideal values and can be transformed into creative and constructive philosophy.
Convertible, however, rather than already converted. When we consider how deeply embedded in customs of thought and action the classic philosophy came to be and how congenial it is to man's more spontaneous beliefs, the throes that attended its birth are not to be wondered at. We should rather wonder that a view so upsetting, so undermining, made its way without more persecutions, martyrdoms and disturbances. It certainly is not surprising that its complete and consistent formulation in philosophy has been long delayed. The main efforts of thinkers were inevitably directed to minimizing the shock of change, easing the strains of transition, mediating and reconciling. When we look back upon almost all of the thinkers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, upon all excepting those who were avowedly sceptical and revolutionary, what strikes us is the amount of traditional subject-matter and[Pg 75] method that is to be found even among those who were regarded as most advanced. Men cannot easily throw off their old habits of thinking, and never can throw off all of them at once. In developing, teaching and receiving new ideas we are compelled to use some of the old ones as tools of understanding and communication. Only piecemeal, step-by-step, could the full import of the new science be grasped. Roughly speaking, the seventeenth century witnessed its application in astronomy and general cosmology; the eighteenth century in physics and chemistry; the nineteenth century undertook an application in geology and the biological sciences.
Convertible, but not yet fully converted. When we think about how deeply the classic philosophy became ingrained in our customs and how well it matched people's more instinctive beliefs, it's not surprising that its emergence was tumultuous. We should be more amazed that a perspective so disruptive and destabilizing gained traction without facing more persecution, martyrdom, and chaos. It's certainly not shocking that its complete and coherent expression in philosophy took so long to develop. Thinkers naturally focused their efforts on softening the impact of change, alleviating the tensions of transition, mediating, and reconciling. When we reflect on most of the thinkers from the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, except those who were openly skeptical and revolutionary, we notice how much traditional content and method are present even among those deemed most progressive. People can't easily abandon their old ways of thinking, and they can never entirely let go of all of them at once. In developing, teaching, and learning new ideas, we must use some of the old ones as tools for understanding and communication. Only gradually, step by step, could the full significance of the new science be comprehended. In broad terms, the seventeenth century saw its application in astronomy and general cosmology; the eighteenth century in physics and chemistry; and the nineteenth century focused on its application in geology and the biological sciences.
It was said that it has now become extremely difficult to recover the view of the world which universally obtained in Europe till the seventeenth century. Yet after all we need only recur to the science of plants and animals as it was before Darwin and to the ideas which even now are dominant in moral and political matters to find the older order of conceptions in full possession of the popular mind. Until the dogma of fixed unchangeable types and species, of arrangement in classes of higher and lower, of subordination of the transitory individual to the universal or kind had been shaken in its hold upon the science of life, it was impossible that the new ideas and method should be made at home in social and moral life. Does it not seem to be[Pg 76] the intellectual task of the twentieth century to take this last step? When this step is taken the circle of scientific development will be rounded out and the reconstruction of philosophy be made an accomplished fact.
It’s been said that it's now really tough to regain the worldview that was common in Europe until the seventeenth century. However, if we look back at the science of plants and animals as it was before Darwin, and also consider the ideas that still dominate moral and political issues today, we can see that the older ways of thinking are still very much in the public consciousness. Until the belief in fixed, unchangeable types and species, the classification of higher and lower forms, and the subordination of the temporary individual to the universal or kind lost its grip on biological science, it was impossible for new ideas and methods to take root in social and moral life. Doesn’t it seem like[Pg 76] the intellectual challenge of the twentieth century is to take this final step? Once this step is taken, the circle of scientific progress will be complete, and the reconstruction of philosophy will become a reality.
CHAPTER IV
CHANGED CONCEPTIONS OF EXPERIENCE AND REASON
What is experience and what is Reason, Mind? What is the scope of experience and what are its limits? How far is it a sure ground of belief and a safe guide of conduct? Can we trust it in science and in behavior? Or is it a quagmire as soon as we pass beyond a few low material interests? Is it so shaky, shifting, and shallow that instead of affording sure footing, safe paths to fertile fields, it misleads, betrays, and engulfs? Is a Reason outside experience and above it needed to supply assured principles to science and conduct? In one sense, these questions suggest technical problems of abstruse philosophy; in another sense, they contain the deepest possible questionings regarding the career of man. They concern the criteria he is to employ in forming his beliefs; the principles by which he is to direct his life and the ends to which he is to direct it. Must man transcend experience by some organ of unique character that carries him into the super-empirical? Failing this, must he wander sceptical and disillusioned? Or is human experience itself worth[Pg 78] while in its purposes and its methods of guidance? Can it organize itself into stable courses or must it be sustained from without?
What is experience, and what is reason or the mind? What is the extent of experience, and what are its limits? How reliable is it as a foundation for belief and a guide for our actions? Can we depend on it in science and in our behavior? Or does it become uncertain as soon as we move beyond simple material interests? Is it so unstable, inconsistent, and superficial that instead of giving us solid ground and clear paths to success, it misleads, deceives, and overwhelms? Do we need a reason that exists outside of experience to provide us with solid principles for science and our actions? On one level, these questions point to complex issues in deep philosophy; on another, they raise the most fundamental inquiries about humanity's journey. They relate to the standards we should use to form our beliefs, the principles we should follow to shape our lives, and the goals we should pursue. Must humans rise above experience through some unique capability that takes them beyond the empirical? If not, will they end up lost, skeptical, and disenchanted? Or is human experience itself valuable in its purposes and methods of guidance? Can it establish stable paths on its own, or does it need support from outside?
We know the answers of traditional philosophy. They do not thoroughly agree among themselves, but they agree that experience never rises above the level of the particular, the contingent, and the probable. Only a power transcending in origin and content any and all conceivable experience can attain to universal, necessary and certain authority and direction. The empiricists themselves admitted the correctness of these assertions. They only said that since there is no faculty of Pure Reason in the possession of mankind, we must put up with what we have, experience, and make the most possible out of it. They contented themselves with sceptical attacks upon the transcendentalist, with indications of the ways in which we might best seize the meaning and good of the passing moment; or like Locke, asserted that in spite of the limitation of experience, it affords the light needed to guide men's footsteps modestly in conduct. They affirmed that the alleged authoritative guidance by a higher faculty had practically hampered men.
We know the answers from traditional philosophy. They don’t completely agree with each other, but they all agree that experience is limited to what is specific, random, and likely. Only a power that goes beyond any conceivable experience can achieve universal, necessary, and certain authority and guidance. The empiricists themselves recognized that these statements are correct. They simply argued that since humanity doesn’t possess a faculty of Pure Reason, we have to deal with what we do have—experience—and make the best of it. They were satisfied with skeptical critiques of the transcendentalists, suggesting how we could best understand the meaning and value of the present moment; or like Locke, claimed that despite the limits of experience, it provides the insight needed to guide people's actions in a modest way. They believed that the supposed authoritative guidance of a higher faculty had actually hindered people.
It is the function of this lecture to show how and why it is now possible to make claims for experience as a guide in science and moral life which the older empiricists did not and could not make for it.
It is the purpose of this lecture to demonstrate how and why it is now possible to make claims for experience as a guide in science and moral life that the earlier empiricists did not and could not make for it.
Curiously enough, the key to the matter may be found in the fact that the old notion of experience was itself a product of experience—the only kind of experience which was then open to men. If another conception of experience is now possible, it is precisely because the quality of experience as it may now be lived has undergone a profound social and intellectual change from that of earlier times. The account of experience which we find in Plato and Aristotle is an account of what Greek experience actually was. It agrees very closely with what the modern psychologist knows as the method of learning by trial and error as distinct from the method of learning by ideas. Men tried certain acts, they underwent certain sufferings and affections. Each of these in the time of its occurrence is isolated, particular—its counterpart is transient appetite and transient sensation. But memory preserves and accumulates these separate incidents. As they pile up, irregular variations get cancelled, common features are selected, reinforced and combined. Gradually a habit of action is built up, and corresponding to this habit there forms a certain generalized picture of an object or situation. We come to know or note not merely this particular which as a particular cannot strictly be known at all (for not being classed it cannot be characterized and identified) but to recognize it as man, tree, stone, leather—an individual of a certain kind, marked by a certain[Pg 80] universal form characteristic of a whole species of thing. Along with the development of this common-sense knowledge, there grows up a certain regularity of conduct. The particular incidents fuse, and a way of acting which is general, as far as it goes, builds up. The skill develops which is shown by the artisan, the shoemaker, the carpenter, the gymnast, the physician, who have regular ways of handling cases. This regularity signifies, of course, that the particular case is not treated as an isolated particular, but as one of a kind, which therefore demands a kind of action. From the multitude of particular illnesses encountered, the physician in learning to class some of them as indigestion learns also to treat the cases of the class in a common or general way. He forms the rule of recommending a certain diet, and prescribing a certain remedy. All this forms what we call experience. It results, as the illustration shows, in a certain general insight and a certain organized ability in action.
Interestingly, the essence of the issue may lie in the fact that the old understanding of experience was itself shaped by experience—the only type of experience that was available to people at the time. If a different idea of experience is now achievable, it’s precisely because the nature of experience as we can live it has changed dramatically in terms of social and intellectual aspects compared to earlier times. The depiction of experience we find in Plato and Aristotle reflects what Greek experience actually was. It aligns closely with what modern psychologists refer to as learning through trial and error, as opposed to learning through ideas. People attempted certain actions, endured specific sufferings and emotions. Each of these events is isolated and unique at the moment it happens—its equivalent is fleeting desires and fleeting sensations. However, memory captures and gathers these distinct experiences. As they accumulate, irregular variations are minimized, while common features are identified, strengthened, and combined. Over time, a habitual way of acting is developed, and in line with this habit, a generalized view of an object or situation emerges. We come to understand not just this specific instance, which as an individual cannot truly be known (since it cannot be categorized, it cannot be defined and identified), but to recognize it as a person, tree, stone, leather—an individual of a specific type, identified by certain [Pg 80] universal traits typical of an entire category of objects. As this common-sense knowledge grows, a certain consistency in behavior also emerges. The specific incidents blend together, forming a general way of acting, as far as it applies. The skills develop that artisans, cobblers, carpenters, gymnasts, and doctors display, as they adopt regular methods for handling cases. This consistency indicates that a specific case is not treated as an isolated incident, but as one of its kind, which therefore requires a kind of response. From the range of specific illnesses faced, a doctor learns to categorize some as indigestion and consequently learns to treat those cases similarly. He establishes guidelines for recommending a particular diet and prescribing a specified remedy. All of this constitutes what we refer to as experience. It leads, as the example illustrates, to a certain general insight and a certain structured capacity for action.
But needless to insist, the generality and the organization are restricted and fallible. They hold, as Aristotle was fond of pointing out, usually, in most cases, as a rule, but not universally, of necessity, or as a principle. The physician is bound to make mistakes, because individual cases are bound to vary unaccountably: such is their very nature. The difficulty does not arise in a defective experience which is capable of[Pg 81] remedy in some better experience. Experience itself, as such, is defective, and hence default is inevitable and irremediable. The only universality and certainty is in a region above experience, that of the rational and conceptual. As the particular was a stepping-stone to image and habit, so the latter may become a stepping-stone to conceptions and principles. But the latter leave experience behind, untouched; they do not react to rectify it. Such is the notion which still lingers in the contrast of "empirical" and "rational" as when we say that a certain architect or physician is empirical, not scientific in his procedures. But the difference between the classic and the modern notion of experience is revealed in the fact that such a statement is now a charge, a disparaging accusation, brought against a particular architect or physician. With Plato, Aristotle and the Scholastic, it was a charge against the callings, since they were modes of experience. It was an indictment of all practical action in contrast with conceptual contemplation.
But it’s unnecessary to insist, the general principles and organization are limited and flawed. They usually hold true, as Aristotle liked to point out, in most cases, as a rule, but not always, by necessity, or as a principle. The doctor is bound to make errors because individual cases can vary unpredictably: that’s just their nature. The issue doesn’t stem from a lack of experience that can be improved with better experience. Experience itself, by its very nature, is flawed, so mistakes are unavoidable and unfixable. The only true universality and certainty exist in a realm beyond experience, in the rational and conceptual. Just as the specific can lead to images and habits, those later aspects may pave the way for concepts and principles. However, these concepts leave experience behind, untouched; they don’t correct it. This idea is still reflected in the distinction between "empirical" and "rational," when we say that a certain architect or doctor is empirical, not scientific in their methods. But today, the difference between the classic and modern understanding of experience is evident in the fact that such a statement is now seen as an accusation, a negative criticism aimed at a specific architect or doctor. In the time of Plato, Aristotle, and the Scholastics, it was a critique of the professions themselves since they represented modes of experience. It was a condemnation of all practical action in contrast to conceptual contemplation.
The modern philosopher who has professed himself an empiricist has usually had a critical purpose in mind. Like Bacon, Locke, Condillac and Helvetius, he stood face to face with a body of beliefs and a set of institutions in which he profoundly disbelieved. His problem was the problem of attack upon so much dead weight carried uselessly by humanity, crushing and distorting[Pg 82] it. His readiest way of undermining and disintegrating was by appealing to experience as a final test and criterion. In every case, active reformers were "empiricists" in the philosophical sense. They made it their business to show that some current belief or institution that claimed the sanction of innate ideas or necessary conceptions, or an origin in an authoritative revelation of reason, had in fact proceeded from a lowly origin in experience, and had been confirmed by accident, by class interest or by biased authority.
The modern philosopher who identifies as an empiricist usually has a critical goal in mind. Like Bacon, Locke, Condillac, and Helvetius, he directly confronts a set of beliefs and institutions that he strongly doubts. His challenge is to tackle the excessive baggage that humanity carries, which is suffocating and distorting it. The easiest way he undermines and breaks down these ideas is by using experience as the ultimate test and standard. In every situation, the active reformers were "empiricists" in the philosophical sense. They aimed to demonstrate that some prevailing belief or institution, which claimed to have the backing of innate ideas or necessary concepts, or an origin in an authoritative revelation of reason, actually emerged from a humble background in experience, and was reinforced by chance, class interest, or biased authority.
The philosophic empiricism initiated by Locke was thus disintegrative in intent. It optimistically took it for granted that when the burden of blind custom, imposed authority, and accidental associations was removed, progress in science and social organization would spontaneously take place. Its part was to help in removing the burden. The best way to liberate men from the burden was through a natural history of the origin and growth in the mind of the ideas connected with objectionable beliefs and customs. Santayana justly calls the psychology of this school a malicious psychology. It tended to identify the history of the formation of certain ideas with an account of the things to which the ideas refer—an identification which naturally had an unfavorable effect on the things. But Mr. Santayana neglects to notice the social zeal and aim latent in the malice. He fails to point out that this[Pg 83] "malice" was aimed at institutions and traditions which had lost their usefulness; he fails to point out that to a large extent it was true of them that an account of their psychological origin was equivalent to a destructive account of the things themselves. But after Hume with debonair clarity pointed out that the analysis of beliefs into sensations and associations left "natural" ideas and institutions in the same position in which the reformers had placed "artificial" ones, the situation changed. The rationalists employed the logic of sensationalistic-empiricism to show that experience, giving only a heap of chaotic and isolated particulars, is as fatal to science and to moral laws and obligations as to obnoxious institutions; and concluded that "Reason" must be resorted to if experience was to be furnished with any binding and connecting principles. The new rationalistic idealism of Kant and his successors seemed to be necessitated by the totally destructive results of the new empirical philosophy.
The philosophical empiricism that Locke started was intended to break things down. It optimistically assumed that removing the weight of blind customs, imposed authority, and random associations would naturally lead to progress in science and social organization. Its role was to help lift that weight. The best way to free people from this burden was by exploring the origins and development of the ideas linked to problematic beliefs and customs. Santayana rightly refers to the psychology of this approach as a malicious psychology. It tended to connect the history of certain ideas to the reality of what those ideas referred to—this connection naturally had a negative impact on those realities. However, Mr. Santayana overlooks the social passion and purpose behind this "malice." He fails to mention that this "malice" targeted institutions and traditions that had outlived their usefulness; he also doesn't point out that, to a large extent, understanding their psychological origins was equivalent to a damaging critique of the institutions themselves. But after Hume clearly pointed out that analyzing beliefs into sensations and associations left "natural" ideas and institutions in the same position as the "artificial" ones placed by reformers, the dynamics shifted. The rationalists used the logic of sensationalistic empiricism to argue that experience, which only provides a jumble of chaotic and unrelated specifics, is just as detrimental to science and moral laws and obligations as it is to undesirable institutions. They concluded that "Reason" needs to be used if experience is to have any binding and connecting principles. The new rationalistic idealism of Kant and his followers seemed necessary due to the completely destructive outcomes of the new empirical philosophy.
Two things have rendered possible a new conception of experience and a new conception of the relation of reason to experience, or, more accurately, of the place of reason in experience. The primary factor is the change that has taken place in the actual nature of experience, its contents and methods, as it is actually lived. The other is the development of a psychology[Pg 84] based upon biology which makes possible a new scientific formulation of the nature of experience.
Two things have made it possible to have a new understanding of experience and a new understanding of how reason relates to experience, or, more precisely, the role of reason in experience. The first factor is the change in the actual nature of experience, including its contents and methods, as it is lived out. The other is the development of a psychology[Pg 84] grounded in biology, which allows for a new scientific formulation of what experience is.
Let us begin with the technical side—the change in psychology. We are only just now commencing to appreciate how completely exploded is the psychology that dominated philosophy throughout the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. According to this theory, mental life originated in sensations which are separately and passively received, and which are formed, through laws of retention and association, into a mosaic of images, perceptions, and conceptions. The senses were regarded as gateways or avenues of knowledge. Except in combining atomic sensations, the mind was wholly passive and acquiescent in knowing. Volition, action, emotion, and desire follow in the wake of sensations and images. The intellectual or cognitive factor comes first and emotional and volitional life is only a consequent conjunction of ideas with sensations of pleasure and pain.
Let’s start with the technical aspect—the shift in psychology. We're just beginning to understand how completely outdated the psychology that dominated philosophy in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries really is. According to this theory, mental life comes from sensations that are received separately and passively, and are then formed, through retention and association, into a patchwork of images, perceptions, and concepts. The senses were seen as pathways to knowledge. Aside from combining basic sensations, the mind was entirely passive and submissive in the process of knowing. Will, action, emotion, and desire follow after sensations and images. The intellectual or cognitive aspect comes first, while emotional and volitional experiences are just results of connecting ideas with sensations of pleasure and pain.
The effect of the development of biology has been to reverse the picture. Wherever there is life, there is behavior, activity. In order that life may persist, this activity has to be both continuous and adapted to the environment. This adaptive adjustment, moreover, is not wholly passive; is not a mere matter of the moulding of the organism by the environment. Even a clam acts upon the environment and modifies it to some extent. It selects materials for food and for the shell that[Pg 85] protects it. It does something to the environment as well as has something done to itself. There is no such thing in a living creature as mere conformity to conditions, though parasitic forms may approach this limit. In the interests of the maintenance of life there is transformation of some elements in the surrounding medium. The higher the form of life, the more important is the active reconstruction of the medium. This increased control may be illustrated by the contrast of savage with civilized man. Suppose the two are living in a wilderness. With the savage there is the maximum of accommodation to given conditions; the minimum of what we may call hitting back. The savage takes things "as they are," and by using caves and roots and occasional pools leads a meagre and precarious existence. The civilized man goes to distant mountains and dams streams. He builds reservoirs, digs channels, and conducts the waters to what had been a desert. He searches the world to find plants and animals that will thrive. He takes native plants and by selection and cross-fertilization improves them. He introduces machinery to till the soil and care for the harvest. By such means he may succeed in making the wilderness blossom like the rose.
The impact of advances in biology has shifted our understanding. Wherever there is life, there is behavior and activity. For life to continue, this activity must be ongoing and suited to the environment. This adaptability is not entirely passive; it’s not just about the environment shaping the organism. Even a clam influences its environment and changes it in some ways. It chooses materials for food and for the shell that[Pg 85]protects it. It interacts with the environment as much as it is influenced by it. There is no living creature that just conforms to its conditions, although parasitic forms might come close. To maintain life, some elements in the surrounding medium are transformed. The higher the form of life, the more significant the active restoration of the environment becomes. This increased control can be seen in the contrast between primitive and civilized humans. Imagine both living in a wilderness. The primitive human adapts maximally to the conditions; there is minimal response to challenges. They accept things “as they are,” relying on caves, roots, and sparse pools to survive. In contrast, the civilized person travels to distant mountains and builds dams. They create reservoirs, dig channels, and direct water to areas that were once barren. They explore the world to find plants and animals that can flourish. They take native plants and, through selection and cross-breeding, enhance them. They introduce machinery to farm the land and manage the harvest. Through these methods, they can transform the wilderness into a flourishing landscape.
Such transformation scenes are so familiar that we overlook their meaning. We forget that the inherent power of life is illustrated in them. Note what a change[Pg 86] this point of view entails in the traditional notions of experience. Experience becomes an affair primarily of doing. The organism does not stand about, Micawber-like, waiting for something to turn up. It does not wait passive and inert for something to impress itself upon it from without. The organism acts in accordance with its own structure, simple or complex, upon its surroundings. As a consequence the changes produced in the environment react upon the organism and its activities. The living creature undergoes, suffers, the consequences of its own behavior. This close connection between doing and suffering or undergoing forms what we call experience. Disconnected doing and disconnected suffering are neither of them experiences. Suppose fire encroaches upon a man when he is asleep. Part of his body is burned away. The burn does not perceptibly result from what he has done. There is nothing which in any instructive way can be named experience. Or again there is a series of mere activities, like twitchings of muscles in a spasm. The movements amount to nothing; they have no consequences for life. Or, if they have, these consequences are not connected with prior doing. There is no experience, no learning, no cumulative process. But suppose a busy infant puts his finger in the fire; the doing is random, aimless, without intention or reflection. But something happens in consequence. The child undergoes heat, he suffers pain.[Pg 87] The doing and undergoing, the reaching and the burn, are connected. One comes to suggest and mean the other. Then there is experience in a vital and significant sense.
Such transformation scenes are so common that we overlook their meaning. We forget that the inherent power of life is illustrated in them. Note what a change[Pg 86] this perspective brings to traditional ideas of experience. Experience becomes primarily about action. The organism doesn’t just stand around, like Micawber, waiting for something to happen. It doesn’t passively wait for something to act upon it from the outside. The organism acts based on its own structure, whether simple or complex, in relation to its surroundings. As a result, the changes in the environment influence the organism and its activities. The living creature undergoes and feels the consequences of its own behavior. This close connection between action and the experience of suffering shapes what we call experience. Disconnected actions and disconnected suffering do not constitute experiences. Suppose a fire encroaches on a man while he is asleep. Part of his body gets burned. The burn does not visibly result from any action he took. There’s nothing that could be meaningfully described as experience. Or consider a series of mere actions, like the twitching of muscles during a spasm. These movements add up to nothing; they don’t affect life. And if they do, those effects aren’t linked to any prior action. There’s no experience, no learning, no cumulative process. But if a curious infant puts its finger in the fire, the action is random, aimless, without intention or thought. But something happens as a result. The child experiences heat and feels pain.[Pg 87] The action and the suffering, the reaching and the burn, are connected. One suggests and gives meaning to the other. Then there is experience in a vital and significant way.
Certain important implications for philosophy follow. In the first place, the interaction of organism and environment, resulting in some adaptation which secures utilization of the latter, is the primary fact, the basic category. Knowledge is relegated to a derived position, secondary in origin, even if its importance, when once it is established, is overshadowing. Knowledge is not something separate and self-sufficing, but is involved in the process by which life is sustained and evolved. The senses lose their place as gateways of knowing to take their rightful place as stimuli to action. To an animal an affection of the eye or ear is not an idle piece of information about something indifferently going on in the world. It is an invitation and inducement to act in a needed way. It is a clue in behavior, a directive factor in adaptation of life in its surroundings. It is urgent not cognitive in quality. The whole controversy between empiricism and rationalism as to the intellectual worth of sensations is rendered strangely obsolete. The discussion of sensations belongs under the head of immediate stimulus and response, not under the head of knowledge.
Certain important implications for philosophy follow. First, the interaction between organisms and their environment, which leads to adaptations that help take advantage of the latter, is the primary fact and the fundamental category. Knowledge takes a secondary role, being derived in origin, even though once established, its importance can overshadow everything else. Knowledge isn’t something separate and self-sufficient; instead, it’s part of the process that sustains and evolves life. The senses lose their status as mere gateways to knowledge and instead become essential stimuli for action. For an animal, any sensation in the eye or ear isn’t just random information about what’s happening in the world. It’s an invitation and motivation to act in a necessary way. It serves as a behavioral clue, a guiding element for adapting to its environment. It’s urgent rather than just cognitive. The entire debate between empiricism and rationalism regarding the intellectual value of sensations seems oddly outdated. Discussing sensations fits under immediate stimulus and response, not under the concept of knowledge.
As a conscious element, a sensation marks an inter[Pg 88]ruption in a course of action previously entered upon. Many psychologists since the time of Hobbes have dwelt upon what they call the relativity of sensations. We feel or sense cold in transition from warmth rather than absolutely; hardness is sensed upon a background of less resistance; a color in contrast with pure light or pure dark or in contrast with some other hue. A continuously unchanged tone or color cannot be attended to or sensed. What we take to be such monotonously prolonged sensations are in truth constantly interrupted by incursions of other elements, and represent a series of excursions back and forth. This fact was, however, misconstrued into a doctrine about the nature of knowledge. Rationalists used it to discredit sense as a valid or high mode of knowing things, since according to it we never get hold of anything in itself or intrinsically. Sensationalists used it to disparage all pretence at absolute knowledge.
As a conscious element, a sensation represents a disruption in a previously established course of action. Many psychologists since Hobbes have discussed what they refer to as the relativity of sensations. We feel or sense cold during a transition from warmth rather than in absolute terms; we sense hardness against a backdrop of less resistance; a color is perceived in contrast to pure light, pure darkness, or another hue. A tone or color that remains unchanged cannot truly be perceived or focused on. What we consider to be monotonously prolonged sensations are actually constantly interrupted by other elements, representing a series of shifts back and forth. However, this fact was misinterpreted into a doctrine about the nature of knowledge. Rationalists used it to undermine sensation as a valid or reliable way of understanding things, arguing that we can never grasp anything in itself or intrinsically. Sensationalists used it to dismiss any claim to absolute knowledge.
Properly speaking, however, this fact of the relativity of sensation does not in the least belong in the sphere of knowing. Sensations of this sort are emotional and practical rather than cognitive and intellectual. They are shocks of change, due to interruption of a prior adjustment. They are signals to redirections of action. Let me take a trivial illustration. The person who is taking notes has no sensation of the pressure of his pencil on the paper or on his hand as long[Pg 89] as it functions properly. It operates merely as stimulus to ready and effective adjustment. The sensory activity incites automatically and unconsciously its proper motor response. There is a preformed physiological connection, acquired from habit but ultimately going back to an original connection in the nervous system. If the pencil-point gets broken or too blunt and the habit of writing does not operate smoothly, there is a conscious shock:—the feeling of something the matter, something gone wrong. This emotional change operates as a stimulus to a needed change in operation. One looks at his pencil, sharpens it or takes another pencil from one's pocket. The sensation operates as a pivot of readjusting behavior. It marks a break in the prior routine of writing and the beginning of some other mode of action. Sensations are "relative" in the sense of marking transitions in habits of behavior from one course to another way of behaving.
However, this fact about the relativity of sensation doesn't belong in the realm of knowledge. These types of sensations are more emotional and practical than cognitive and intellectual. They are jolts of change caused by a disruption in a prior adjustment. They signal a need for changes in action. Let me give a simple example. A person taking notes isn't aware of the pressure of their pencil on the paper or their hand as long as it works correctly. It just serves as a stimulus for smooth and efficient adjustment. The sensory activity automatically and unconsciously triggers the appropriate motor response. There’s a preexisting physiological link, formed by habit, that ultimately traces back to an original connection in the nervous system. When the pencil tip breaks or becomes too dull and writing doesn’t go smoothly, there’s a conscious shock: the feeling that something is off, something has gone wrong. This emotional shift acts as a prompt for a necessary change in what they're doing. One checks the pencil, sharpens it, or grabs another pencil from their pocket. The sensation acts as a turning point for adjusting behavior. It signifies a break in the previous writing routine and the start of a different action. Sensations are "relative" in the sense that they indicate shifts in behavior habits from one way of acting to another.
The rationalist was thus right in denying that sensations as such are true elements of knowledge. But the reasons he gave for this conclusion and the consequences he drew from it were all wrong. Sensations are not parts of any knowledge, good or bad, superior or inferior, imperfect or complete. They are rather provocations, incitements, challenges to an act of inquiry which is to terminate in knowledge. They are not ways of knowing things inferior in value to reflective ways, to[Pg 90] the ways that require thought and inference, because they are not ways of knowing at all. They are stimuli to reflection and inference. As interruptions, they raise the questions: What does this shock mean? What is happening? What is the matter? How is my relation to the environment disturbed? What should be done about it? How shall I alter my course of action to meet the change that has taken place in the surroundings? How shall I readjust my behavior in response? Sensation is thus, as the sensationalist claimed, the beginning of knowledge, but only in the sense that the experienced shock of change is the necessary stimulus to the investigating and comparing which eventually produce knowledge.
The rationalist was right to reject the idea that sensations are true elements of knowledge. However, the reasons he provided for this conclusion and the implications he drew from it were completely incorrect. Sensations aren’t parts of any knowledge, whether it’s good or bad, superior or inferior, imperfect or complete. Instead, they serve as provocations, triggers, and challenges for an inquiry that leads to knowledge. They aren’t inferior ways of knowing compared to reflective methods—those that involve thought and inference—because they don't function as ways of knowing at all. They are simply stimuli for reflection and inference. As interruptions, they prompt questions like: What does this shock mean? What’s happening? What’s the problem? How is my relationship with my environment affected? What should I do about it? How should I change my actions to address the shift in my surroundings? How can I adjust my behavior in response? So, sensation is, as the sensationalist argued, the start of knowledge, but only in the sense that the jolt of change is the essential catalyst for the investigation and comparison that eventually leads to knowledge.
When experience is aligned with the life-process and sensations are seen to be points of readjustment, the alleged atomism of sensations totally disappears. With this disappearance is abolished the need for a synthetic faculty of super-empirical reason to connect them. Philosophy is not any longer confronted with the hopeless problem of finding a way in which separate grains of sand may be woven into a strong and coherent rope—or into the illusion and pretence of one. When the isolated and simple existences of Locke and Hume are seen not to be truly empirical at all but to answer to certain demands of their theory of mind, the necessity ceases for the elaborate Kantian and Post-Kantian ma[Pg 91]chinery of a priori concepts and categories to synthesize the alleged stuff of experience. The true "stuff" of experience is recognized to be adaptive courses of action, habits, active functions, connections of doing and undergoing; sensori-motor co-ordinations. Experience carries principles of connection and organization within itself. These principles are none the worse because they are vital and practical rather than epistemological. Some degree of organization is indispensable to even the lowest grade of life. Even an amoeba must have some continuity in time in its activity and some adaptation to its environment in space. Its life and experience cannot possibly consist in momentary, atomic, and self-enclosed sensations. Its activity has reference to its surroundings and to what goes before and what comes after. This organization intrinsic to life renders unnecessary a super-natural and super-empirical synthesis. It affords the basis and material for a positive evolution of intelligence as an organizing factor within experience.
When experience aligns with the life process and sensations are viewed as points of adjustment, the supposed individuality of sensations completely disappears. With this disappearance, there's no longer a need for a higher reasoning ability to connect them. Philosophy no longer faces the frustrating problem of figuring out how separate grains of sand can be woven into a strong and coherent rope—or into the illusion of one. When the isolated and simple existences described by Locke and Hume are recognized as not truly empirical but instead responding to specific demands of their theory of mind, the need for the complex Kantian and Post-Kantian machinery of a priori concepts and categories to synthesize the supposed essence of experience vanishes. The real "essence" of experience is understood to be adaptive courses of action, habits, active functions, and interactions of doing and experiencing; sensory-motor coordination. Experience inherently includes principles of connection and organization. These principles are no less valid simply because they are vital and practical rather than purely epistemological. Some level of organization is necessary even for the simplest forms of life. Even an amoeba must maintain some continuity over time in its activity and adapt to its environment in space. Its life and experience cannot consist of momentary, isolated, and self-contained sensations. Its actions relate to its surroundings and to what happens before and after. This intrinsic organization within life makes any supernatural and beyond-empirical synthesis unnecessary. It provides the foundation and material for a positive evolution of intelligence as an organizing force within experience.
Nor is it entirely aside from the subject to point out the extent in which social as well as biological organization enters into the formation of human experience. Probably one thing that strengthened the idea that the mind is passive and receptive in knowing was the observation of the helplessness of the human infant. But the observation points in quite another direction.[Pg 92] Because of his physical dependence and impotency, the contacts of the little child with nature are mediated by other persons. Mother and nurse, father and older children, determine what experiences the child shall have; they constantly instruct him as to the meaning of what he does and undergoes. The conceptions that are socially current and important become the child's principles of interpretation and estimation long before he attains to personal and deliberate control of conduct. Things come to him clothed in language, not in physical nakedness, and this garb of communication makes him a sharer in the beliefs of those about him. These beliefs coming to him as so many facts form his mind; they furnish the centres about which his own personal expeditions and perceptions are ordered. Here we have "categories" of connection and unification as important as those of Kant, but empirical not mythological.
It's also relevant to highlight how both social and biological structures impact the development of human experience. One reason people might think the mind is only passive and receptive in knowing is due to the observation of how helpless a human infant is. However, this observation points in a different direction.[Pg 92] Because of their physical dependence and inability to act independently, a young child's interactions with the world are mediated by others. Parents, caregivers, and siblings decide what experiences the child will have; they continuously teach the child the meanings of their actions and experiences. The concepts that are socially significant and prevalent become the child's guiding principles for interpretation and evaluation long before they develop personal and intentional control over their actions. Information comes to them wrapped in language, rather than in raw form, and this method of communication allows them to share in the beliefs of those around them. These beliefs, which they absorb as facts, shape their minds; they provide the focal points around which their personal explorations and perceptions are organized. Here, we encounter "categories" of connection and unification that are just as crucial as those proposed by Kant, but they are grounded in experience rather than mythology.
From these elementary, if somewhat technical considerations, we turn to the change which experience itself has undergone in the passage from ancient and medieval to modern life. To Plato, experience meant enslavement to the past, to custom. Experience was almost equivalent to established customs formed not by reason or under intelligent control but by repetition and blind rule of thumb. Only reason can lift us above subjection to the accidents of the past. When we come to Bacon and his successors, we discover a curious re[Pg 93]versal. Reason and its bodyguard of general notions is now the conservative, mind-enslaving factor. Experience is the liberating power. Experience means the new, that which calls us away from adherence to the past, that which reveals novel facts and truths. Faith in experience produces not devotion to custom but endeavor for progress. This difference in temper is the more significant because it was so unconsciously taken for granted. Some concrete and vital change must have occurred in actual experience as that is lived. For, after all, the thought of experience follows after and is modelled upon the experience actually undergone.
From these basic, though somewhat technical points, we shift to the change that experience itself has gone through as we moved from ancient and medieval times to modern life. For Plato, experience meant being trapped by the past and by tradition. Experience was nearly the same as established customs shaped not by reason or thoughtful control, but by repetition and blind habits. Only reason can help us rise above the constraints of past occurrences. When we look at Bacon and his followers, we see a strange reversal. Now, reason and its collection of general concepts become the conservative force that enslaves the mind. Experience becomes the freeing force. Experience represents the new, pulling us away from sticking to the past, revealing fresh facts and truths. Trusting in experience doesn't lead to devotion to tradition but to efforts for progress. This difference in attitude is particularly significant because it was largely taken for granted. A real and vital change must have occurred in the way we experience life. After all, our thoughts about experience follow and are shaped by the experiences we actually have.
When mathematics and other rational sciences developed among the Greeks, scientific truths did not react back into daily experience. They remained isolated, apart and super-imposed. Medicine was the art in which perhaps the greatest amount of positive knowledge was obtained, but it did not reach the dignity of science. It remained an art. In practical arts, moreover, there was no conscious invention or purposeful improvement. Workers followed patterns that were handed down to them, while departure from established standards and models usually resulted in degenerate productions. Improvements came either from a slow, gradual, and unacknowledged accumulation of changes or else from some sudden inspiration, which at once set a new stand[Pg 94]ard. Being the result of no conscious method, it was fittingly attributed to the gods. In the social arts, such a radical reformer as Plato felt that existing evils were due to the absence of such fixed patterns as controlled the productions of artisans. The ethical purport of philosophy was to furnish them, and when once they were instituted, they were to be consecrated by religion, adorned by art, inculcated by education and enforced by magistrates so that alteration of them would be impossible.
When mathematics and other logical sciences were developing among the Greeks, scientific truths didn’t connect back to everyday life. They remained separate, isolated, and layered on top of each other. Medicine was the field where perhaps the most positive knowledge was gained, but it never achieved the status of science. It remained just an art. In practical skills, there was no intentional invention or deliberate improvement. Workers followed the methods passed down to them, and straying from established standards typically led to inferior results. Improvements came either from a slow, gradual, and unnoticed accumulation of changes or from some sudden inspiration that immediately set a new standard. As these changes weren’t the result of any conscious method, they were fittingly attributed to the gods. In the social sciences, a radical reformer like Plato believed that existing problems were due to the lack of fixed patterns that governed the work of craftsmen. The ethical purpose of philosophy was to provide these patterns, and once they were established, they were to be sanctioned by religion, enhanced by art, taught through education, and enforced by authorities so that changes to them would be impossible.
It is unnecessary to repeat what has been so often dwelt upon as to the effect of experimental science in enabling man to effect a deliberate control of his environment. But since the impact of this control upon the traditional notion of experience is often overlooked, we must point out that when experience ceased to be empirical and became experimental, something of radical importance occurred. Aforetime man employed the results of his prior experience only to form customs that henceforth had to be blindly followed or blindly broken. Now, old experience is used to suggest aims and methods for developing a new and improved experience. Consequently experience becomes in so far constructively self-regulative. What Shakespeare so pregnantly said of nature, it is "made better by no mean, but nature makes that mean," becomes true of experience. We do not merely have to repeat the past,[Pg 95] or wait for accidents to force change upon us. We use our past experiences to construct new and better ones in the future. The very fact of experience thus includes the process by which it directs itself in its own betterment.
It’s unnecessary to repeat what has been said many times about how experimental science allows us to deliberately control our environment. However, the effect of this control on the traditional idea of experience is often overlooked, so we need to highlight that when experience shifted from being empirical to experimental, something fundamentally important happened. In the past, people used the results of their previous experiences only to create customs that had to be either followed blindly or broken without thought. Now, we use past experiences to suggest goals and methods for developing new and improved experiences. As a result, experience becomes constructively self-regulating. What Shakespeare insightfully expressed about nature—“made better by no mean, but nature makes that mean”—applies to experience as well. We don’t just have to repeat the past,[Pg 95] or wait for random events to force change upon us. We actively use our past experiences to create new and better ones in the future. The very concept of experience includes the process by which it guides itself toward improvement.
Science, "reason" is not therefore something laid from above upon experience. Suggested and tested in experience, it is also employed through inventions in a thousand ways to expand and enrich experience. Although, as has been so often repeated, this self-creation and self-regulation of experience is still largely technological rather than truly artistic or human, yet what has been achieved contains the guaranty of the possibility of an intelligent administering of experience. The limits are moral and intellectual, due to defects in our good will and knowledge. They are not inherent metaphysically in the very nature of experience. "Reason" as a faculty separate from experience, introducing us to a superior region of universal truths begins now to strike us as remote, uninteresting and unimportant. Reason, as a Kantian faculty that introduces generality and regularity into experience, strikes us more and more as superfluous—the unnecessary creation of men addicted to traditional formalism and to elaborate terminology. Concrete suggestions arising from past experiences, developed and matured in the light of the needs and deficiencies of the present, employed as aims[Pg 96] and methods of specific reconstruction, and tested by success or failure in accomplishing this task of readjustment, suffice. To such empirical suggestions used in constructive fashion for new ends the name intelligence is given.
Science, "reason" isn't just something imposed on experience. It's suggested and tested through experience, and it’s also used in countless inventions to enhance and enrich that experience. Even though it’s often said that this self-creation and self-regulation of experience is mostly technological rather than genuinely artistic or human, what has been accomplished shows the potential for intelligently managing experience. The limits come from moral and intellectual shortcomings in our goodwill and knowledge. They are not inherently metaphysical to the essence of experience. "Reason" as a separate faculty from experience, one that leads us to a higher realm of universal truths, now feels distant, uninteresting, and irrelevant. Reason, viewed through a Kantian lens that brings generality and regularity into experience, increasingly seems unnecessary—the pointless creation of people fixated on traditional formalism and complicated terminology. Concrete ideas derived from past experiences, shaped and refined by the needs and gaps of the present, used as goals[Pg 96] and methods for specific reconstruction, and tested by success or failure in achieving this adjustment, are enough. We call these practical suggestions, when used constructively for new purposes, intelligence.
This recognition of the place of active and planning thought within the very processes of experience radically alters the traditional status of the technical problems of particular and universal, sense and reason, perceptual and conceptual. But the alteration is of much more than technical significance. For reason is experimental intelligence, conceived after the pattern of science, and used in the creation of social arts; it has something to do. It liberates man from the bondage of the past, due to ignorance and accident hardened into custom. It projects a better future and assists man in its realization. And its operation is always subject to test in experience. The plans which are formed, the principles which man projects as guides of reconstructive action, are not dogmas. They are hypotheses to be worked out in practice, and to be rejected, corrected and expanded as they fail or succeed in giving our present experience the guidance it requires. We may call them programmes of action, but since they are to be used in making our future acts less blind, more directed, they are flexible. Intelligence is not something possessed once for all. It is in constant process of form[Pg 97]ing, and its retention requires constant alertness in observing consequences, an open-minded will to learn and courage in re-adjustment.
This understanding of the role of active and planning thought in the very processes of experience completely changes the traditional perspective on the technical issues of the specific and universal, perception and reasoning, and the relationship between perception and concepts. But this change is more than just technical. Reason is experimental intelligence, shaped like science, and applied in the creation of social practices; it has a purpose. It frees people from being trapped by the past, which is often shaped by ignorance and habits developed by chance. It envisions a better future and helps people achieve it. Its effectiveness can always be tested through experience. The plans that are created, the principles that people establish as guides for constructive action, are not rigid rules. They are hypotheses to be developed in practice and revised, corrected, or expanded based on whether they successfully guide our current experiences. We can refer to them as action plans, but because they are meant to help make our future decisions more informed and intentional, they remain adaptable. Intelligence isn’t something you have once and for all. It’s continuously evolving, and maintaining it requires constant vigilance in observing outcomes, a willingness to learn, and the courage to adjust as needed.
In contrast with this experimental and re-adjusting intelligence, it must be said that Reason as employed by historic rationalism has tended to carelessness, conceit, irresponsibility, and rigidity—in short absolutism. A certain school of contemporary psychology uses the term "rationalization" to denote those mental mechanisms by which we unconsciously put a better face on our conduct or experience than facts justify. We excuse ourselves to ourselves by introducing a purpose and order into that of which we are secretly ashamed. In like fashion, historic rationalism has often tended to use Reason as an agency of justification and apologetics. It has taught that the defects and evils of actual experience disappear in the "rational whole" of things; that things appear evil merely because of the partial, incomplete nature of experience. Or, as was noted by Bacon, "reason" assumes a false simplicity, uniformity and universality, and opens for science a path of fictitious ease. This course results in intellectual irresponsibility and neglect:—irresponsibility because rationalism assumes that the concepts of reason are so self-sufficient and so far above experience that they need and can secure no confirmation in experience. Neglect, because this same assumption makes men care[Pg 98]less about concrete observations and experiments. Contempt for experience has had a tragic revenge in experience; it has cultivated disregard for fact and this disregard has been paid for in failure, sorrow and war.
In contrast to this experimental and adaptable intelligence, it's important to note that Reason, as used by historical rationalism, has often led to carelessness, arrogance, irresponsibility, and rigidity—in short, absolutism. A certain branch of modern psychology refers to "rationalization" to describe the mental processes through which we subconsciously present a better version of our actions or experiences than the facts allow. We justify our behavior to ourselves by imposing a sense of purpose and order on what we’re secretly ashamed of. Similarly, historical rationalism often used Reason as a means of justification and defense. It has claimed that the flaws and wrongs of actual experience vanish in the "rational whole" of things; that things seem wrong simply because our experience is partial and incomplete. Or, as Bacon noted, "reason" presents a false simplicity, uniformity, and universality, creating a deceptive ease for science. This approach results in intellectual irresponsibility and neglect: irresponsibility because rationalism assumes that the concepts of reason are so self-sufficient and so far removed from experience that they require no confirmation from it. Neglect arises because this belief leads people to disregard concrete observations and experiments. This contempt for experience has had a tragic backlash in experience; it has fostered a disregard for facts, and that disregard has resulted in failure, sorrow, and war.
The dogmatic rigidity of Rationalism is best seen in the consequences of Kant's attempt to buttress an otherwise chaotic experience with pure concepts. He set out with a laudable attempt at restricting the extravagant pretensions of Reason apart from experience. He called his philosophy critical. But because he taught that the understanding employs fixed, a priori, concepts, in order to introduce connection into experience and thereby make known objects possible (stable, regular relationships of qualities), he developed in German thought a curious contempt for the living variety of experience and a curious overestimate of the value of system, order, regularity for their own sakes. More practical causes were at work in producing the peculiarly German regard for drill, discipline, "order" and docility.
The rigid dogmatism of Rationalism is most evident in the results of Kant's efforts to support an otherwise chaotic experience with pure concepts. He aimed to limit the excessive claims of Reason separate from experience, referring to his philosophy as critical. However, he argued that understanding uses fixed, a priori concepts to create connections in experience and make objects known possible (stable, regular relationships of qualities). This led to a strange contempt for the rich variety of experience in German thought and an inflated appreciation for system, order, and regularity purely for their own sake. More practical factors also contributed to the distinctly German emphasis on discipline, "order," and compliance.
But Kant's philosophy served to provide an intellectual justification or "rationalization" of subordination of individuals to fixed and ready-made universal, "principles," laws. Reason and law were held to be synonyms. And as reason came into experience from without and above, so law had to come into life from some external and superior authority. The[Pg 99] practical correlate to absolutism is rigidity, stiffness, inflexibility of disposition. When Kant taught that some conceptions, and these the important ones, are a priori, that they do not arise in experience and cannot be verified or tested in experience, that without such ready-made injections into experience the latter is anarchic and chaotic, he fostered the spirit of absolutism, even though technically he denied the possibility of absolutes. His successors were true to his spirit rather than his letter, and so they taught absolutism systematically. That the Germans with all their scientific competency and technological proficiency should have fallen into their tragically rigid and "superior" style of thought and action (tragic because involving them in inability to understand the world in which they lived) is a sufficient lesson of what may be involved in a systematical denial of the experimental character of intelligence and its conceptions.
But Kant's philosophy provided an intellectual justification or "rationalization" for the subordination of individuals to fixed and ready-made universal "principles" and laws. Reason and law were seen as the same thing. Just as reason came into experience from outside and above, law had to come into life from some external and superior authority. The[Pg 99] practical counterpart to absolutism is rigidity, stiffness, and inflexibility of character. When Kant taught that some concepts, especially the important ones, are a priori, meaning they don't come from experience and can't be verified or tested through it, he encouraged the spirit of absolutism, even though he technically denied the existence of absolutes. His followers remained true to his spirit rather than his letter, and thus they systematically taught absolutism. That the Germans, with all their scientific expertise and technological skills, ended up adopting such a tragically rigid and "superior" way of thinking and acting (tragic because it prevented them from understanding the world they lived in) serves as a clear lesson on what can result from a systematic rejection of the experimental nature of intelligence and its concepts.
By common consent, the effect of English empiricism was sceptical where that of German rationalism was apologetic; it undermined where the latter justified. It detected accidental associations formed into customs under the influence of self- or class-interest where German rational-idealism discovered profound meanings due to the necessary evolution of absolute reason. The modern world has suffered because in so many matters philosophy has offered it only an arbitrary choice be[Pg 100]tween hard and fast opposities: Disintegrating analysis or rigid synthesis; complete radicalism neglecting and attacking the historic past as trivial and harmful, or complete conservatism idealizing institutions as embodiments of eternal reason; a resolution of experience into atomic elements that afford no support to stable organization or a clamping down of all experience by fixed categories and necessary concepts—these are the alternatives that conflicting schools have presented.
By general agreement, English empiricism had a skeptical impact, while German rationalism took a justifying stance; it tore down what the latter upheld. It revealed random connections turned into customs influenced by self-interest or class interests, whereas German rational-idealism found deep meanings from the necessary evolution of absolute reason. The modern world has suffered because philosophy has often given it only an arbitrary choice between strict opposites: disintegrating analysis or rigid synthesis; extreme radicalism that dismisses and attacks the historical past as trivial and damaging, or extreme conservatism that idealizes institutions as expressions of eternal reason; breaking down experience into basic elements that offer no support for stable organization or restricting all experience with fixed categories and necessary concepts—these are the choices that competing schools have put forward.
They are the logical consequences of the traditional opposition of Sense and Thought, Experience and Reason. Common sense has refused to follow both theories to their ultimate logic, and has fallen back on faith, intuition or the exigencies of practical compromise. But common sense too often has been confused and hampered instead of enlightened and directed by the philosophies proffered it by professional intellectuals. Men who are thrown back upon "common sense" when they appeal to philosophy for some general guidance are likely to fall back on routine, the force of some personality, strong leadership or on the pressure of momentary circumstances. It would be difficult to estimate the harm that has resulted because the liberal and progressive movement of the eighteenth and earlier nineteenth centuries had no method of intellectual articulation commensurate with its practical aspirations. Its[Pg 101] heart was in the right place. It was humane and social in intention. But it had no theoretical instrumentalities of constructive power. Its head was sadly deficient. Too often the logical import of its professed doctrines was almost anti-social in their atomistic individualism, anti-human in devotion to brute sensation. This deficiency played into the hands of the reactionary and obscurantist. The strong point of the appeal to fixed principles transcending experience, to dogmas incapable of experimental verification, the strong point of reliance upon a priori canons of truth and standards of morals in opposition to dependence upon fruits and consequences in experience, has been the unimaginative conception of experience which professed philosophic empiricists have entertained and taught.
They are the logical outcomes of the traditional clash between Sense and Thought, Experience and Reason. Common sense has avoided following both theories to their logical extremes and has instead relied on faith, intuition, or the necessities of practical compromises. However, common sense has often been confused and obstructed rather than clarified and guided by the philosophies presented by professional intellectuals. People who turn to "common sense" when seeking general guidance from philosophy are likely to resort to routine, the influence of someone’s personality, strong leadership, or the pressure of immediate circumstances. It’s hard to assess the damage that resulted because the liberal and progressive movements of the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries lacked an intellectual framework that matched their practical goals. Its[Pg 101] heart was in the right place. It was humane and social in intent. But it had no theoretical tools for constructive action. Its intellectual foundation was sadly lacking. Too often, the logical implications of its stated doctrines were nearly anti-social in their individualism and anti-human in their focus on raw sensation. This shortcoming played into the hands of reactionaries and obscurantists. The strong appeal to fixed principles beyond experience, to dogmas that can’t be tested experimentally, and the reliance on a priori truths and moral standards instead of depending on the outcomes and implications of experience, has stemmed from the narrow-minded view of experience that self-proclaimed philosophic empiricists have embraced and taught.
A philosophic reconstruction which should relieve men of having to choose between an impoverished and truncated experience on one hand and an artificial and impotent reason on the other would relieve human effort from the heaviest intellectual burden it has to carry. It would destroy the division of men of good will into two hostile camps. It would permit the co-operation of those who respect the past and the institutionally established with those who are interested in establishing a freer and happier future. For it would determine the conditions under which the funded experience of the past and the contriving intelligence which looks to the[Pg 102] future can effectually interact with each other. It would enable men to glorify the claims of reason without at the same time falling into a paralyzing worship of super-empirical authority or into an offensive "rationalization" of things as they are.
A philosophical reworking that frees people from having to choose between a limited and incomplete experience on one side and a fake and ineffective reason on the other would lift the heaviest intellectual burden from human efforts. It would eliminate the divide between goodwill individuals into two opposing sides. It would allow collaboration between those who value the past and established institutions and those who want to create a freer and happier future. For it would define the conditions under which the accumulated experiences of the past and the inventive intelligence looking to the[Pg 102] future can effectively interact with one another. It would allow people to celebrate the power of reason without slipping into a paralyzing reverence for super-empirical authority or into an annoying "rationalization" of the current state of things.
CHAPTER V
CHANGED CONCEPTIONS OF THE IDEAL AND THE REAL
It has been noted that human experience is made human through the existence of associations and recollections, which are strained through the mesh of imagination so as to suit the demands of the emotions. A life that is humanly interesting is, short of the results of discipline, a life in which the tedium of vacant leisure is filled with images that excite and satisfy. It is in this sense that poetry preceded prose in human experience, religion antedated science, and ornamental and decorative art while it could not take the place of utility early reached a development out of proportion to the practical arts. In order to give contentment and delight, in order to feed present emotion and give the stream of conscious life intensity and color, the suggestions which spring from past experiences are worked over so as to smooth out their unpleasantnesses and enhance their enjoyableness. Some psychologists claim that there is what they call a natural tendency to obliviscence of the disagreeable—that men turn from the unpleasant in thought and recollection as they do[Pg 104] from the obnoxious in action. Every serious-minded person knows that a large part of the effort required in moral discipline consists in the courage needed to acknowledge the unpleasant consequences of one's past and present acts. We squirm, dodge, evade, disguise, cover up, find excuses and palliations—anything to render the mental scene less uncongenial. In short, the tendency of spontaneous suggestion is to idealize experience, to give it in consciousness qualities which it does not have in actuality. Time and memory are true artists; they remould reality nearer to the heart's desire.
It’s been observed that human experience becomes meaningful through our connections and memories, which are filtered through our imagination to meet our emotional needs. A life that is engaging, apart from the results of discipline, is one where the boredom of idle time is filled with images that inspire and fulfill us. In this way, poetry came before prose in human experience, religion came before science, and decorative art, while not replacing practical functions, developed early on in a way that surpassed functional arts. To provide satisfaction and joy, to nourish our present feelings, and to give depth and vibrancy to our stream of consciousness, the ideas stemming from past experiences are revised to soften their unpleasant aspects and enhance their enjoyment. Some psychologists argue there’s a natural tendency to forget unpleasantness—that people turn away from negative thoughts and memories just as they do from unpleasant actions. Every thoughtful person understands that a significant part of moral discipline involves the courage to face the unpleasant consequences of our past and present actions. We squirm, avoid, dodge, disguise, cover up, and make excuses—anything to make the mental picture less uncomfortable. In summary, the natural tendency of spontaneous thought is to romanticize experience, to present it in a way that attributes qualities it doesn’t actually possess. Time and memory are true artists; they reshape reality closer to what we desire.
As imagination becomes freer and less controlled by concrete actualities, the idealizing tendency takes further flights unrestrained by the rein of the prosaic world. The things most emphasized in imagination as it reshapes experience are things which are absent in reality. In the degree in which life is placid and easy, imagination is sluggish and bovine. In the degree in which life is uneasy and troubled, fancy is stirred to frame pictures of a contrary state of things. By reading the characteristic features of any man's castles in the air you can make a shrewd guess as to his underlying desires which are frustrated. What is difficulty and disappointment in real life becomes conspicuous achievement and triumph in revery; what is negative in fact will be positive in the image drawn by fancy; what[Pg 105] is vexation in conduct will be compensated for in high relief in idealizing imagination.
As imagination becomes more free and less held back by concrete realities, the idealizing tendency can soar without being limited by the mundane world. The aspects that stand out the most in imagination, as it reshapes experience, are the things that are missing in reality. When life is calm and easy, imagination tends to be dull and sluggish. However, when life is turbulent and challenging, creativity is prompted to picture a better situation. By examining the distinctive features of someone’s daydreams, you can make a smart guess about their underlying frustrated desires. What feels like difficulty and disappointment in real life turns into obvious success and victory in dreams; what is a negative in reality transforms into a positive in the images created by imagination; what[Pg 105] is frustration in action will be compensated for in vibrant relief in idealized imagination.
These considerations apply beyond mere personal psychology. They are decisive for one of the most marked traits of classic philosophy:—its conception of an ultimate supreme Reality which is essentially ideal in nature. Historians have more than once drawn an instructive parallel between the developed Olympian Pantheon of Greek religion and the Ideal Realm of Platonic philosophy. The gods, whatever their origin and original traits, became idealized projections of the selected and matured achievements which the Greeks admired among their mortal selves. The gods were like mortals, but mortals living only the lives which men would wish to live, with power intensified, beauty perfected, and wisdom ripened. When Aristotle criticized the theory of Ideas of his master, Plato, by saying that the Ideas were after all only things of sense eternalized, he pointed out in effect the parallelism of philosophy with religion and art to which allusion has just been made. And save for matters of merely technical import, is it not possible to say of Aristotle's Forms just what he said of Plato's Ideas? What are they, these Forms and Essences which so profoundly influenced for centuries the course of science and theology, save the objects of ordinary experience with their blemishes removed, their imperfections eliminated, their lacks[Pg 106] rounded out, their suggestions and hints fulfilled? What are they in short but the objects of familiar life divinized because reshaped by the idealizing imagination to meet the demands of desire in just those respects in which actual experience is disappointing?
These ideas go beyond just personal psychology. They're crucial for one of the most prominent features of classic philosophy: its view of an ultimate supreme Reality that is fundamentally ideal. Historians have often made an insightful comparison between the fully developed Olympian Pantheon of Greek religion and the Ideal Realm of Platonic philosophy. The gods, regardless of their origins and initial characteristics, became idealized representations of the qualities and accomplishments that the Greeks admired in themselves. The gods were like humans, but they lived the lives that people aspired to, with enhanced power, perfected beauty, and matured wisdom. When Aristotle criticized his teacher Plato's theory of Ideas by saying that the Ideas were just eternalized sensory things, he effectively highlighted the similarities between philosophy, religion, and art that I just mentioned. And aside from technical details, isn't it fair to say about Aristotle’s Forms what he said about Plato’s Ideas? What are these Forms and Essences that have so deeply influenced science and theology for centuries, except for ordinary experiences with their flaws removed, their imperfections fixed, their deficiencies addressed, their hints and suggestions completed? In essence, what are they but the familiar aspects of life transformed into a divine form by the idealizing imagination to satisfy our desires in those areas where real life falls short?
That Plato, and Aristotle in somewhat different fashion, and Plotinus and Marcus Aurelius and Saint Thomas Aquinas, and Spinoza and Hegel all taught that Ultimate Reality is either perfectly Ideal and Rational in nature, or else has absolute ideality and rationality as its necessary attribute, are facts well known to the student of philosophy. They need no exposition here. But it is worth pointing out that these great systematic philosophies defined perfect Ideality in conceptions that express the opposite of those things which make life unsatisfactory and troublesome. What is the chief source of the complaint of poet and moralist with the goods, the values and satisfactions of experience? Rarely is the complaint that such things do not exist; it is that although existing they are momentary, transient, fleeting. They do not stay; at worst they come only to annoy and tease with their hurried and disappearing taste of what might be; at best they come only to inspire and instruct with a passing hint of truer reality. This commonplace of the poet and moralist as to the impermanence not only of sensuous enjoyment, but of fame and civic achievements was profoundly[Pg 107] reflected upon by philosophers, especially by Plato and Aristotle. The results of their thinking have been wrought into the very fabric of western ideas. Time, change, movement are signs that what the Greeks called Non-Being somehow infect true Being. The phraseology is now strange, but many a modern who ridicules the conception of Non-Being repeats the same thought under the name of the Finite or Imperfect.
That Plato, and Aristotle in a slightly different way, along with Plotinus, Marcus Aurelius, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Spinoza, and Hegel all taught that Ultimate Reality is either completely Ideal and Rational in nature, or possesses absolute ideality and rationality as a necessary trait, are facts well known to philosophy students. They don't need further explanation here. However, it’s important to note that these significant philosophical systems defined perfect Ideality in ways that contradict the aspects that make life unsatisfactory and challenging. What is the main source of complaints from poets and moralists regarding the goods, values, and satisfactions of experience? Rarely is the complaint that such things don’t exist; it’s that, although they do exist, they are momentary, transient, and fleeting. They don’t last; at worst, they only come to annoy and tease with a quick and vanishing taste of what could be; at best, they only inspire and instruct with a brief glimpse of a deeper reality. This common idea among poets and moralists regarding the impermanence not only of sensory enjoyment but also of fame and civic accomplishments was deeply contemplated by philosophers, especially by Plato and Aristotle. The outcomes of their thinking have been woven into the very fabric of Western thought. Time, change, and movement are signs that what the Greeks called Non-Being somehow taints true Being. The terminology may seem strange now, but many modern individuals who mock the idea of Non-Being echo the same thought under the terms of the Finite or Imperfect.
Wherever there is change, there is instability, and instability is proof of something the matter, of absence, deficiency, incompleteness. These are the ideas common to the connection between change, becoming and perishing, and Non-Being, finitude and imperfection. Hence complete and true Reality must be changeless, unalterable, so full of Being that it always and forever maintains itself in fixed rest and repose. As Bradley, the most dialectially ingenious Absolutist of our own day, expresses the doctrine "Nothing that is perfectly real moves." And while Plato took, comparatively speaking, a pessimistic view of change as mere lapse and Aristotle a complacent view of it as tendency to realization, yet Aristotle doubted no more than Plato that the fully realized reality, the divine and ultimate, is changeless. Though it is called Activity or Energy, the Activity knew no change, the energy did nothing. It was the activity of an army forever marking time and never going anywhere.
Wherever there is change, there’s instability, and instability indicates that something is wrong, that there’s a lack, a deficiency, or incompleteness. These ideas are central to the connection between change, becoming and perishing, and Non-Being, finitude, and imperfection. Therefore, complete and true Reality must be unchanging and unalterable, so full of Being that it always and forever maintains itself in a state of fixed rest and peace. As Bradley, the most dialectically clever Absolutist of our time, puts it, "Nothing that is perfectly real moves." While Plato had a rather pessimistic view of change as mere decline and Aristotle took a more relaxed view of it as a tendency towards realization, both philosophers agreed that the fully realized reality, the divine and ultimate, is changeless. Although it’s referred to as Activity or Energy, this Activity undergoes no change, and the energy doesn’t do anything. It was like an army that’s always marking time but never actually going anywhere.
From this contrast of the permanent with the transient arise other features which mark off the Ultimate Reality from the imperfect realities of practical life. Where there is change, there is of necessity numerical plurality, multiplicity, and from variety comes opposition, strife. Change is alteration, or "othering" and this means diversity. Diversity means division, and division means two sides and their conflict. The world which is transient must be a world of discord, for in lacking stability it lacks the government of unity. Did unity completely rule, these would remain an unchanging totality. What alters has parts and partialities which, not recognizing the rule of unity, assert themselves independently and make life a scene of contention and discord. Ultimate and true Being on the other hand, since it is changeless is Total, All-Comprehensive and One. Since it is One, it knows only harmony, and therefore enjoys complete and eternal Good. It is Perfection.
From the contrast between what is permanent and what is temporary, other characteristics emerge that distinguish Ultimate Reality from the flawed realities of everyday life. Where there is change, there must be numerical plurality, multiplicity, and from variety comes conflict and struggle. Change is about alteration or "othering," which leads to diversity. Diversity leads to division, and division brings about two sides that are in conflict. The transient world **must** be a world of discord, for lacking stability means lacking the governance of unity. If unity were to completely dominate, there would be an unchanging totality. What changes has parts and partial viewpoints that, lacking awareness of unity's governance, assert themselves independently and turn life into a scene of conflict and discord. Ultimate and true Being, on the other hand, is changeless, Total, All-Comprehensive, and One. Because it is One, it knows only harmony, and thus experiences complete and eternal Good. It **is** Perfection.
Degrees of knowledge and truth correspond with degrees of reality point by point. The higher and more complete the Reality the truer and more important the knowledge that refers to it. Since the world of becoming, of origins and perishings, is deficient in true Being, it cannot be known in the best sense. To know it means to neglect its flux and alteration and discover some permanent form which limits the processes that[Pg 109] alter in time. The acorn undergoes a series of changes; these are knowable only in reference to the fixed form of the oak which is the same in the entire oak species in spite of the numerical diversity of trees. Moreover, this form limits the flux of growth at both ends, the acorn coming from the oak as well as passing into it. Where such unifying and limiting eternal forms cannot be detected, there is mere aimless variation and fluctuation, and knowledge is out of the question. On the other hand, as objects are approached in which there is no movement at all, knowledge becomes really demonstrative, certain, perfect—truth pure and unalloyed. The heavens can be more truly known than the earth, God the unmoved mover than the heavens.
Degrees of knowledge and truth align with degrees of reality point by point. The higher and more complete the reality, the truer and more significant the knowledge related to it. Since the world of change, origins, and endings lacks true being, it can't be fully understood in the best sense. To know it means ignoring its constant flow and change, trying to find some permanent form that restricts the processes that alter over time. The acorn goes through a series of changes; these can only be understood in relation to the fixed form of the oak, which remains consistent across the entire oak species despite the individual diversity of trees. Additionally, this form limits the growth process at both ends, with the acorn coming from the oak and eventually becoming part of it. Where such unifying and limiting eternal forms cannot be found, there is only aimless variation and fluctuation, making knowledge impossible. Conversely, when dealing with objects that have no movement at all, knowledge becomes genuinely demonstrative, certain, and perfect—pure and untainted truth. The heavens can be known more accurately than the earth, and God, the unmoved mover, more than the heavens.
From this fact follows the superiority of contemplative to practical knowledge, of pure theoretical speculation to experimentation, and to any kind of knowing that depends upon changes in things or that induces change in them. Pure knowing is pure beholding, viewing, noting. It is complete in itself. It looks for nothing beyond itself; it lacks nothing and hence has no aim or purpose. It is most emphatically its own excuse for being. Indeed, pure contemplative knowing is so much the most truly self-enclosed and self-sufficient thing in the universe that it is the highest and indeed the only attribute that can be ascribed to God, the Highest Being in the scale of Being. Man himself is[Pg 110] divine in the rare moments when he attains to purely self-sufficient theoretical insight.
From this fact comes the superiority of contemplative knowledge over practical knowledge, of pure theoretical speculation over experimentation, and any kind of understanding that relies on changes in things or causes changes in them. Pure knowledge is simply pure seeing, observing, and noting. It is complete in itself. It seeks nothing beyond itself; it lacks nothing and therefore has no aim or purpose. It is absolutely its own justification for existence. In fact, pure contemplative knowledge is the most truly self-contained and self-sufficient thing in the universe, making it the highest and indeed the only attribute that can be attributed to God, the Highest Being in the hierarchy of existence. Humanity is[Pg 110] divine in those rare moments when they achieve purely self-sufficient theoretical insight.
In contrast with such knowing, the so-called knowing of the artisan is base. He has to bring about changes in things, in wood and stone, and this fact is of itself evidence that his material is deficient in Being. What condemns his knowledge even more is the fact that it is not disinterestedly for its own sake. It has reference to results to be attained, food, clothing, shelter, etc. It is concerned with things that perish, the body and its needs. It thus has an ulterior aim, and one which itself testifies to imperfection. For want, desire, affection of every sort, indicate lack. Where there is need and desire—as in the case of all practical knowledge and activity—there is incompleteness and insufficiency. While civic or political and moral knowledge rank higher than do the conceptions of the artisan, yet intrinsically considered they are a low and untrue type. Moral and political action is practical; that is, it implies needs and effort to satisfy them. It has an end beyond itself. Moreover, the very fact of association shows lack of self-sufficiency; it shows dependence upon others. Pure knowing is alone solitary, and capable of being carried on in complete, self-sufficing independence.
In contrast to that kind of understanding, the so-called understanding of the craftsman is basic. He has to create changes in materials like wood and stone, and this alone shows that his materials lack true essence. What's even more limiting about his knowledge is that it isn't purely for its own sake. It focuses on achieving results—like food, clothing, and shelter. It deals with things that are temporary, the body and its needs. Therefore, it has an ulterior goal, which itself indicates imperfection. Want, desire, and various sorts of affection all point to a deficiency. Where there is need and desire—as found in all practical knowledge and activities—there is incompleteness and inadequacy. While civic, political, and moral knowledge are considered higher than the craftsperson's concepts, they are still fundamentally a lower and less true type of understanding. Moral and political actions are practical; that is, they imply certain needs and the effort to meet them. They have an end that goes beyond themselves. Additionally, the very act of coming together reveals a lack of self-sufficiency; it indicates dependence on others. Pure knowledge, on the other hand, exists alone and is capable of being pursued in complete, self-sufficient independence.
In short, the measure of the worth of knowledge according to Aristotle, whose views are here summarized, is the degree in which it is purely contemplative. The[Pg 111] highest degree is attained in knowing ultimate Ideal Being, pure Mind. This is Ideal, the Form of Forms, because it has no lacks, no needs, and experiences no change or variety. It has no desires because in it all desires are consummated. Since it is perfect Being, it is perfect Mind and perfect Bliss;—the acme of rationality and ideality. One point more and the argument is completed. The kind of knowing that concerns itself with this ultimate reality (which is also ultimate ideality) is philosophy. Philosophy is therefore the last and highest term in pure contemplation. Whatever may be said for any other kind of knowledge, philosophy is self-enclosed. It has nothing to do beyond itself; it has no aim or purpose or function—except to be philosophy—that is, pure, self-sufficing beholding of ultimate reality. There is of course such a thing as philosophic study which falls short of this perfection. Where there is learning, there is change and becoming. But the function of study and learning of philosophy is, as Plato put it, to convert the eye of the soul from dwelling contentedly upon the images of things, upon the inferior realities that are born and that decay, and to lead it to the intuition of supernal and eternal Being. Thus the mind of the knower is transformed. It becomes assimilated to what it knows.
In short, according to Aristotle, whose ideas are summarized here, the value of knowledge is measured by how purely contemplative it is. The highest form of knowledge is understanding the ultimate Ideal Being, pure Mind. This is Ideal, the Form of Forms, because it lacks nothing, has no needs, and undergoes no change or variety. It has no desires because all desires are fulfilled within it. Since it is perfect Being, it is also perfect Mind and perfect Bliss—the peak of rationality and ideality. One last point completes the argument. The type of knowing that deals with this ultimate reality (which is also the ultimate ideal) is philosophy. Therefore, philosophy is the ultimate expression of pure contemplation. No matter what can be said about any other type of knowledge, philosophy stands alone. It exists for its own sake; it has no aim, purpose, or function—other than to be philosophy itself—a pure, self-sufficient contemplation of ultimate reality. Of course, there is philosophic study that doesn't reach this level of perfection. Where there is learning, there is change and transformation. But the role of studying and learning philosophy is, as Plato stated, to redirect the eye of the soul from being content with the images of things, the lower realities that come and go, and to guide it towards the perception of higher and eternal Being. In this way, the mind of the knower is transformed. It becomes aligned with what it understands.
Through a variety of channels, especially Neo-Platonism and St. Augustine, these ideas found their[Pg 112] way into Christian theology; and great scholastic thinkers taught that the end of man is to know True Being, that knowledge is contemplative, that True Being is pure Immaterial Mind, and to know it is Bliss and Salvation. While this knowledge cannot be achieved in this stage of life nor without supernatural aid, yet so far as it is accomplished it assimilates the human mind to the divine essence and so constitutes salvation. Through this taking over of the conception of knowledge as Contemplative into the dominant religion of Europe, multitudes were affected who were totally innocent of theoretical philosophy. There was bequeathed to generations of thinkers as an unquestioned axiom the idea that knowledge is intrinsically a mere beholding or viewing of reality—the spectator conception of knowledge. So deeply engrained was this idea that it prevailed for centuries after the actual progress of science had demonstrated that knowledge is power to transform the world, and centuries after the practice of effective knowledge had adopted the method of experimentation.
Through various channels, particularly Neo-Platonism and St. Augustine, these ideas found their[Pg 112] way into Christian theology; and great scholastic thinkers taught that the purpose of humanity is to know True Being, that knowledge is contemplative, that True Being is pure Immaterial Mind, and that knowing it brings Bliss and Salvation. Although this knowledge can't be achieved in this life or without supernatural help, to the extent that it is realized, it aligns the human mind with the divine essence, thus constituting salvation. By incorporating the idea of knowledge as Contemplative into the dominant religion of Europe, many people who were completely unaware of theoretical philosophy were influenced. The notion that knowledge is fundamentally just a seeing or observing of reality—the spectator conception of knowledge—was passed down to generations of thinkers as an unquestioned principle. This idea was so deeply rooted that it continued for centuries, even after the actual advancement of science had shown that knowledge is a power to change the world, and long after the practice of effective knowledge had embraced experimentation as its method.
Let us turn abruptly from this conception of the measure of true knowledge and the nature of true philosophy to the existing practice of knowledge. Nowadays if a man, say a physicist or chemist, wants to know something, the last thing he does is merely to contemplate. He does not look in however earnest and[Pg 113] prolonged way upon the object expecting that thereby he will detect its fixed and characteristic form. He does not expect any amount of such aloof scrutiny to reveal to him any secrets. He proceeds to do something, to bring some energy to bear upon the substance to see how it reacts; he places it under unusual conditions in order to induce some change. While the astronomer cannot change the remote stars, even he no longer merely gazes. If he cannot change the stars themselves, he can at least by lens and prism change their light as it reaches the earth; he can lay traps for discovering changes which would otherwise escape notice. Instead of taking an antagonistic attitude toward change and denying it to the stars because of their divinity and perfection, he is on constant and alert watch to find some change through which he can form an inference as to the formation of stars and systems of stars.
Let’s abruptly shift from this idea of true knowledge and the essence of real philosophy to how knowledge is actually practiced today. Nowadays, if a person, like a physicist or chemist, wants to learn something, the last thing they do is just think about it. They don’t stare at the object seriously and for a long time, hoping to uncover its fixed and defining shape. They don’t expect that just observing will reveal any secrets. Instead, they take action, applying some energy to the substance to see how it reacts; they create unusual conditions to induce change. While an astronomer can’t alter distant stars, they don’t simply watch anymore. If they can’t change the stars themselves, they can at least use lenses and prisms to change the light as it reaches Earth; they can set up ways to spot changes that might otherwise go unnoticed. Rather than resisting change and denying it to the stars because of their supposed perfection and divinity, they are always on the lookout for changes that might help them infer how stars and star systems form.
Change in short is no longer looked upon as a fall from grace, as a lapse from reality or a sign of imperfection of Being. Modern science no longer tries to find some fixed form or essence behind each process of change. Rather, the experimental method tries to break down apparent fixities and to induce changes. The form that remains unchanged to sense, the form of seed or tree, is regarded not as the key to knowledge of the thing, but as a wall, an obstruction to be broken down. Consequently the scientific man experiments with[Pg 114] this and that agency applied to this and that condition until something begins to happen; until there is, as we say, something doing. He assumes that there is change going on all the time, that there is movement within each thing in seeming repose; and that since the process is veiled from perception the way to know it is to bring the thing into novel circumstances until change becomes evident. In short, the thing which is to be accepted and paid heed to is not what is originally given but that which emerges after the thing has been set under a great variety of circumstances in order to see how it behaves.
Change, in short, is no longer seen as a fall from grace, a detachment from reality, or a sign of imperfection in existence. Modern science doesn’t try to find a fixed form or essence behind each process of change anymore. Instead, the experimental method seeks to dismantle apparent certainties and induce changes. The form that seems unchanged to our senses, like that of a seed or tree, is viewed not as the key to understanding the thing, but as a barrier to overcome. As a result, scientists experiment with[Pg 114] various agents applied under different conditions until something starts to happen; until, as we say, action is taking place. They assume that change is happening all the time, that there is movement within each thing that appears still; and since this process is hidden from our perception, the way to understand it is to place the thing in new circumstances until change becomes clear. In short, what should be acknowledged and focused on is not what is originally present but what emerges after the thing has been subjected to a wide range of conditions to see how it reacts.
Now this marks a much more general change in the human attitude than perhaps appears at first sight. It signifies nothing less than that the world or any part of it as it presents itself at a given time is accepted or acquiesced in only as material for change. It is accepted precisely as the carpenter, say, accepts things as he finds them. If he took them as things to be observed and noted for their own sake, he never would be a carpenter. He would observe, describe, record the structures, forms and changes which things exhibit to him, and leave the matter there. If perchance some of the changes going on should present him with a shelter, so much the better. But what makes the carpenter a builder is the fact that he notes things not just as objects in themselves, but with reference to what he[Pg 115] wants to do to them and with them; to the end he has in mind. Fitness to effect certain special changes that he wishes to see accomplished is what concerns him in the wood and stones and iron which he observes. His attention is directed to the changes they undergo and the changes they make other things undergo so that he may select that combination of changes which will yield him his desired result. It is only by these processes of active manipulation of things in order to realize his purpose that he discovers what the properties of things are. If he foregoes his own purpose and in the name of a meek and humble subscription to things as they "really are" refuses to bend things as they "are" to his own purpose, he not only never achieves his purpose but he never learns what the things themselves are. They are what they can do and what can be done with them,—things that can be found by deliberate trying.
Now, this represents a much broader shift in human mindset than it might seem at first. It indicates that the world, or any part of it, is accepted only as material for change at any given time. It's accepted much like how a carpenter approaches the materials he encounters. If he viewed them merely as objects to observe and note for no particular reason, he would never be a carpenter. He would simply observe, describe, and record the structures, forms, and changes that he sees, and leave it at that. If, by chance, some of those changes provided him with a shelter, that would be a bonus. What makes the carpenter a builder is that he observes things not just as they are but in relation to what he[Pg 115] wants to create with them; he has a goal in mind. His concern lies in the suitability of the wood, stone, and iron for achieving specific changes he wants to make. His focus is on the changes those materials undergo and the changes they can cause in other things so that he can pick the combination of changes that will give him the results he desires. It’s only by actively manipulating things to achieve his goals that he discovers their properties. If he abandons his purpose and, in an attempt to humbly accept things as they "really are," refuses to shape them to fulfill his own aims, he not only fails to reach his goals but also misses out on understanding what those things actually are. They are defined by what they can do and what can be done with them—insights that can only be gained through deliberate experimentation.
The outcome of this idea of the right way to know is a profound modification in man's attitude toward the natural world. Under differing social conditions, the older or classic conception sometimes bred resignation and submission; sometimes contempt and desire to escape; sometimes, notably in the case of the Greeks, a keen esthetic curiosity which showed itself in acute noting of all the traits of given objects. In fact, the whole conception of knowledge as beholding and noting is fundamentally an idea connected with esthetic enjoy[Pg 116]ment and appreciation where the environment is beautiful and life is serene, and with esthetic repulsion and depreciation where life is troubled, nature morose and hard. But in the degree in which the active conception of knowledge prevails, and the environment is regarded as something that has to be changed in order to be truly known, men are imbued with courage, with what may almost be termed an aggressive attitude toward nature. The latter becomes plastic, something to be subjected to human uses. The moral disposition toward change is deeply modified. This loses its pathos, it ceases to be haunted with melancholy through suggesting only decay and loss. Change becomes significant of new possibilities and ends to be attained; it becomes prophetic of a better future. Change is associated with progress rather than with lapse and fall. Since changes are going on anyway, the great thing is to learn enough about them so that we be able to lay hold of them and turn them in the direction of our desires. Conditions and events are neither to be fled from nor passively acquiesced in; they are to be utilized and directed. They are either obstacles to our ends or else means for their accomplishment. In a profound sense knowing ceases to be contemplative and becomes practical.
The result of this idea of the right way to know leads to a significant change in how people view the natural world. Depending on social circumstances, the older or traditional view sometimes created resignation and submission; other times, it fostered contempt and a desire to escape; and sometimes, particularly with the Greeks, it sparked a deep aesthetic curiosity that displayed itself in keen observation of the characteristics of various objects. Essentially, the whole concept of knowledge as observing and noting is fundamentally related to aesthetic enjoyment and appreciation when the environment is beautiful and life is peaceful, and it links to aesthetic aversion and devaluation when life is troubled, nature is gloomy, and harsh. However, as the active concept of knowledge takes hold, and the environment is seen as something that needs to be changed to be truly understood, people gain courage, adopting what might be called an aggressive stance toward nature. Nature turns into something malleable, something that can be shaped for human purposes. The attitude towards change is deeply transformed. It loses its emotional weight and stops being filled with sadness by suggesting only decay and loss. Change starts to signify new possibilities and goals to be achieved; it becomes a promise of a better future. Change is linked to progress rather than decline and downfall. Since changes are happening regardless, the important thing is to learn enough about them so we can grasp them and steer them toward our desires. Conditions and events shouldn't be avoided or passively accepted; they should be harnessed and directed. They can be either obstacles to our goals or tools to achieve them. In a significant way, knowing moves away from being contemplative and becomes practical.
Unfortunately men, educated men, cultivated men in particular, are still so dominated by the older conception of an aloof and self-sufficing reason and knowledge[Pg 117] that they refuse to perceive the import of this doctrine. They think they are sustaining the cause of impartial, thorough-going and disinterested reflection when they maintain the traditional philosophy of intellectualism—that is, of knowing as something self-sufficing and self-enclosed. But in truth, historic intellectualism, the spectator view of knowledge, is a purely compensatory doctrine which men of an intellectual turn have built up to console themselves for the actual and social impotency of the calling of thought to which they are devoted. Forbidden by conditions and held back by lack of courage from making their knowledge a factor in the determination of the course of events, they have sought a refuge of complacency in the notion that knowing is something too sublime to be contaminated by contact with things of change and practice. They have transformed knowing into a morally irresponsible estheticism. The true import of the doctrine of the operative or practical character of knowing, of intelligence, is objective. It means that the structures and objects which science and philosophy set up in contrast to the things and events of concrete daily experience do not constitute a realm apart in which rational contemplation may rest satisfied; it means that they represent the selected obstacles, material means and ideal methods of giving direction to that change which is bound to occur anyway.
Unfortunately, men—especially educated and cultured ones—are still heavily influenced by the outdated idea of a detached and self-sufficient reason and knowledge[Pg 117]. They believe they are supporting the cause of impartial, thorough, and disinterested reflection when they cling to the traditional philosophy of intellectualism, which views knowledge as something self-sufficient and self-contained. However, the reality is that historic intellectualism, or the spectator view of knowledge, is a purely compensatory doctrine that intellectuals have created to soothe themselves for the real and social powerlessness of their calling. Restricted by circumstances and lacking the courage to make their knowledge a driving force in shaping events, they have sought comfort in the belief that knowledge is too elevated to be tainted by practical matters and change. They've turned knowledge into a morally irresponsible form of aestheticism. The real meaning of the doctrine that emphasizes the operative or practical nature of knowing and intelligence is objective. It signifies that the frameworks and concepts established by science and philosophy, when contrasted with the tangible experiences of daily life, do not exist as a separate realm where rational contemplation can find peace; instead, they represent the chosen challenges, material tools, and ideal approaches to guide the inevitable changes that are bound to happen.
This change of human disposition toward the world does not mean that man ceases to have ideals, or ceases to be primarily a creature of the imagination. But it does signify a radical change in the character and function of the ideal realm which man shapes for himself. In the classic philosophy, the ideal world is essentially a haven in which man finds rest from the storms of life; it is an asylum in which he takes refuge from the troubles of existence with the calm assurance that it alone is supremely real. When the belief that knowledge is active and operative takes hold of men, the ideal realm is no longer something aloof and separate; it is rather that collection of imagined possibilities that stimulates men to new efforts and realizations. It still remains true that the troubles which men undergo are the forces that lead them to project pictures of a better state of things. But the picture of the better is shaped so that it may become an instrumentality of action, while in the classic view the Idea belongs ready-made in a noumenal world. Hence, it is only an object of personal aspiration or consolation, while to the modern, an idea is a suggestion of something to be done or of a way of doing.
This shift in how people perceive the world doesn’t mean that individuals stop having ideals or stop being creatures of imagination. However, it does indicate a fundamental change in the nature and purpose of the ideal world that people create for themselves. In traditional philosophy, the ideal world is essentially a refuge where individuals find relief from life's challenges; it is a safe space where they escape the difficulties of existence, fully confident that it is the only true reality. When the belief that knowledge is dynamic and actionable takes root, the ideal world becomes something that is no longer distant and separate; instead, it becomes a collection of imagined possibilities that inspire people to take new actions and achieve realizations. It remains true that the struggles people face motivate them to envision a better state of affairs. However, the vision of improvement is formed in a way that it can be a tool for action, whereas in the classic view, the Ideal exists already and is part of a transcendent world. Thus, it serves merely as a personal aspiration or comfort, while for the modern perspective, an idea is seen as a prompt for something to be accomplished or a method of acting.
An illustration will, perhaps, make the difference clear. Distance is an obstacle, a source of trouble. It separates friends and prevents intercourse. It isolates, and makes contact and mutual understanding difficult.[Pg 119] This state of affairs provokes discontent and restlessness; it excites the imagination to construct pictures of a state of things where human intercourse is not injuriously affected by space. Now there are two ways out. One way is to pass from a mere dream of some heavenly realm in which distance is abolished and by some magic all friends are in perpetual transparent communication, to pass, I say, from some idle castle-building to philosophic reflection. Space, distance, it will then be argued, is merely phenomenal; or, in a more modern version, subjective. It is not, metaphysically speaking, real. Hence the obstruction and trouble it gives is not after all "real" in the metaphysical sense of reality. Pure minds, pure spirits, do not live in a space world; for them distance is not. Their relationships in the true world are not in any way affected by special considerations. Their intercommunication is direct, fluent, unobstructed.
An example might clarify the difference. Distance is an obstacle, causing problems. It separates friends and hinders interaction. It isolates people, making contact and mutual understanding difficult.[Pg 119] This situation creates discontent and restlessness; it sparks the imagination to envision a scenario where human interaction isn’t negatively impacted by space. There are two solutions. One is to move from just dreaming about some ideal place where distance doesn’t exist and friends can communicate effortlessly, to a deeper philosophical reflection. It could be argued that space and distance are just appearances; in more modern terms, they are subjective. They aren’t, in a metaphysical sense, real. So, the challenges they present aren’t "real" in the true sense of reality. Pure minds and spirits don’t exist in a world defined by space; for them, distance doesn’t matter. Their true relationships aren’t affected by specific conditions. Their communication is direct, smooth, and unrestricted.
Does the illustration involve a caricature of ways of philosophizing with which we are all familiar? But if it is not an absurd caricature, does it not suggest that much of what philosophies have taught about the ideal and noumenal or superiorly real world, is after all, only casting a dream into an elaborate dialectic form through the use of a speciously scientific terminology? Practically, the difficulty, the trouble, remains. Practically, however it may be "metaphysically," space is[Pg 120] still real:—it acts in a definite objectionable way. Again, man dreams of some better state of things. From troublesome fact he takes refuge in fantasy. But this time, the refuge does not remain a permanent and remote asylum.
Does the illustration involve a caricature of the ways of thinking that we all recognize? But if it’s not just a ridiculous caricature, does it imply that much of what philosophies have taught about the ideal and the noumenal or superior reality is really just a way of turning a dream into a complicated argument using misleadingly scientific language? Practically, the difficulty, the trouble, remains. Practically, no matter how it may be "metaphysically," space is[Pg 120] still real: it behaves in a distinctly annoying way. Again, people dream of a better situation. From troublesome reality, they escape into fantasy. But this time, the escape does not stay a permanent and distant refuge.
The idea becomes a standpoint from which to examine existing occurrences and to see if there is not among them something which gives a hint of how communication at a distance can be effected, something to be utilized as a medium of speech at long range. The suggestion or fancy though still ideal is treated as a possibility capable of realization in the concrete natural world, not as a superior reality apart from that world. As such, it becomes a platform from which to scrutinize natural events. Observed from the point of view of this possibility, things disclose properties hitherto undetected. In the light of these ascertainments, the idea of some agency for speech at a distance becomes less vague and floating: it takes on positive form. This action and reaction goes on. The possibility or idea is employed as a method for observing actual existence; and in the light of what is discovered the possibility takes on concrete existence. It becomes less of a mere idea, a fancy, a wished-for possibility, and more of an actual fact. Invention proceeds, and at last we have the telegraph, the telephone, first through wires, and then with no artificial medium. The concrete environ[Pg 121]ment is transformed in the desired direction; it is idealized in fact and not merely in fancy. The ideal is realized through its own use as a tool or method of inspection, experimentation, selection and combination of concrete natural operations.
The idea becomes a perspective from which to look at current events and to see if there is something among them that hints at how long-distance communication can happen, something that can serve as a medium for communication over long distances. The suggestion or concept, while still ideal, is treated as a possibility that can be realized in the real world, not as a higher reality separate from it. As such, it becomes a foundation for examining natural events. Viewed through this possibility, things reveal properties that haven’t been noticed before. With these findings, the idea of some way to communicate at a distance becomes clearer and more tangible. This process of action and reaction continues. The possibility or idea is used as a method for observing actual reality; and based on what is learned, that possibility becomes a concrete reality. It shifts from being just an idea, a whim, a hoped-for possibility, to an actual fact. Invention moves forward, and eventually we have the telegraph, the telephone, first through wires and then wirelessly. The concrete environment is transformed in the desired way; it is idealized in reality and not just in imagination. The ideal is realized through its application as a tool or method for inspection, experimentation, selection, and combination of real natural processes.
Let us pause to take stock of results. The division of the world into two kinds of Being, one superior, accessible only to reason and ideal in nature, the other inferior, material, changeable, empirical, accessible to sense-observation, turns inevitably into the idea that knowledge is contemplative in nature. It assumes a contrast between theory and practice which was all to the disadvantage of the latter. But in the actual course of the development of science, a tremendous change has come about. When the practice of knowledge ceased to be dialectical and became experimental, knowing became preoccupied with changes and the test of knowledge became the ability to bring about certain changes. Knowing, for the experimental sciences, means a certain kind of intelligently conducted doing; it ceases to be contemplative and becomes in a true sense practical. Now this implies that philosophy, unless it is to undergo a complete break with the authorized spirit of science, must also alter its nature. It must assume a practical nature; it must become operative and experimental. And we have pointed out what an enormous change this transformation of philosophy entails in the two con[Pg 122]ceptions which have played the greatest rôle in historic philosophizing—the conceptions of the "real" and "ideal" respectively. The former ceases to be something ready-made and final; it becomes that which has to be accepted as the material of change, as the obstructions and the means of certain specific desired changes. The ideal and rational also ceased to be a separate ready-made world incapable of being used as a lever to transform the actual empirical world, a mere asylum from empirical deficiencies. They represent intelligently thought-out possibilities of the existent world which may be used as methods for making over and improving it.
Let’s take a moment to assess the outcomes. The world is divided into two types of Being: one that is superior, accessible only through reason and ideal in nature, and the other that is inferior, material, changeable, and observable through the senses. This leads to the idea that knowledge is inherently contemplative. It sets up a contrast between theory and practice, which unfairly disadvantages the latter. However, a significant change has occurred in the actual development of science. When knowledge moved from being dialectical to experimental, it began to focus on changes, and the test of knowledge became the ability to produce specific changes. For the experimental sciences, knowing means engaging in a particular kind of intelligently carried out action; it shifts from being contemplative to genuinely practical. This suggests that philosophy, unless it wants to completely disconnect from the accepted spirit of science, must also change its nature. It needs to take on a practical approach; it must become operational and experimental. We've highlighted how this transformation in philosophy brings about a massive shift in the two notions that have played the biggest role in historical philosophy—the concepts of "real" and "ideal." The former is no longer seen as something fixed and final; it becomes what needs to be accepted as the material for change, comprising the obstacles and means for achieving specific desired changes. Similarly, the ideal and rational are no longer viewed as a separate finished world that cannot be leveraged to transform the actual empirical world—a mere refuge from empirical shortcomings. Instead, they represent thoughtfully considered possibilities of the existing world that can be used as methods for changing and improving it.
Philosophically speaking, this is the great difference involved in the change from knowledge and philosophy as contemplative to operative. The change does not mean the lowering in dignity of philosophy from a lofty plane to one of gross utilitarianism. It signifies that the prime function of philosophy is that of rationalizing the possibilities of experience, especially collective human experience. The scope of this change may be realized by considering how far we are from accomplishing it. In spite of inventions which enable men to use the energies of nature for their purposes, we are still far from habitually treating knowledge as the method of active control of nature and of experience. We tend to think of it after the model of a spectator viewing a finished picture rather than after that of the artist[Pg 123] producing the painting. Thus there arise all the questions of epistemology with which the technical student of philosophy is so familiar, and which have made modern philosophy in especial so remote from the understanding of the everyday person and from the results and processes of science. For these questions all spring from the assumption of a merely beholding mind on one side and a foreign and remote object to be viewed and noted on the other. They ask how a mind and world, subject and object, so separate and independent can by any possibility come into such relationship to each other as to make true knowledge possible. If knowing were habitually conceived of as active and operative, after the analogy of experiment guided by hypothesis, or of invention guided by the imagination of some possibility, it is not too much to say that the first effect would be to emancipate philosophy from all the epistemological puzzles which now perplex it. For these all arise from a conception of the relation of mind and world, subject and object, in knowing, which assumes that to know is to seize upon what is already in existence.
Philosophically speaking, this is the major difference involved in shifting from knowledge and philosophy as contemplative to operative. This shift doesn't mean that philosophy is being downgraded from a high level to a low form of utilitarianism. Instead, it indicates that the main purpose of philosophy is to rationalize the possibilities of experience, particularly collective human experience. We can grasp the extent of this shift by realizing how far we are from achieving it. Despite inventions that allow us to harness nature's energies for our needs, we still don’t consistently treat knowledge as a way to actively control nature and experience. We often think of knowledge like a spectator admiring a completed painting rather than like the artist[Pg 123] who creates it. This leads to all the epistemological questions that technical philosophy students know so well, making modern philosophy, in particular, feel distant from everyday understanding and the practical results of science. These questions stem from the assumption of a passive observer on one side and a distant object to be observed on the other. They inquire how a mind and world, subject and object, that are so separate and independent can come into a relationship that makes genuine knowledge possible. If knowing were routinely viewed as active and operative, akin to experiments guided by hypotheses or inventions fueled by imaginative possibilities, it’s fair to say that the first result would be freeing philosophy from all the epistemological dilemmas that currently confuse it. These dilemmas arise from a view of the relationship between mind and world, subject and object, in knowing, which assumes that to know is to grasp what already exists.
Modern philosophic thought has been so preoccupied with these puzzles of epistemology and the disputes between realist and idealist, between phenomenalist and absolutist, that many students are at a loss to know what would be left for philosophy if there were removed[Pg 124] both the metaphysical task of distinguishing between the noumenal and phenomenal worlds and the epistemological task of telling how a separate subject can know an independent object. But would not the elimination of these traditional problems permit philosophy to devote itself to a more fruitful and more needed task? Would it not encourage philosophy to face the great social and moral defects and troubles from which humanity suffers, to concentrate its attention upon clearing up the causes and exact nature of these evils and upon developing a clear idea of better social possibilities; in short upon projecting an idea or ideal which, instead of expressing the notion of another world or some far-away unrealizable goal, would be used as a method of understanding and rectifying specific social ills?
Modern philosophical thought has become so focused on the puzzles of knowledge and the arguments between realists and idealists, and between phenomenalists and absolutists, that many students are unsure what philosophy would even focus on if we removed[Pg 124] both the metaphysical challenge of distinguishing between the noumenal and phenomenal worlds and the epistemological challenge of explaining how a separate subject can know an independent object. But wouldn't getting rid of these traditional problems allow philosophy to shift its attention to a more productive and necessary task? Wouldn't it encourage philosophy to tackle the significant social and moral flaws and issues that humanity faces, focusing on understanding the causes and true nature of these problems and developing a clear vision of better social possibilities? In short, it could work on creating an idea or ideal that, rather than representing another world or some distant, unattainable goal, would serve as a way to understand and address specific social issues?
This is a vague statement. But note in the first place that such a conception of the proper province of philosophy where it is released from vain metaphysics and idle epistemology is in line with the origin of philosophy sketched in the first hour. And in the second place, note how contemporary society, the world over, is in need of more general and fundamental enlightenment and guidance than it now possesses. I have tried to show that a radical change of the conception of knowledge from contemplative to active is the inevitable result of the way in which inquiry and invention are now conducted. But in claiming this, it must also be[Pg 125] conceded, or rather asserted, that so far the change has influenced for the most part only the more technical side of human life. The sciences have created new industrial arts. Man's physical command of natural energies has been indefinitely multiplied. There is control of the sources of material wealth and prosperity. What would once have been miracles are now daily performed with steam and coal and electricity and air, and with the human body. But there are few persons optimistic enough to declare that any similar command of the forces which control man's social and moral welfare has been achieved.
This is a vague statement. But first, note that this idea of the proper scope of philosophy, freed from pointless metaphysics and idle epistemology, aligns with the origin of philosophy discussed in the first hour. Second, it’s important to recognize that contemporary society, globally, needs more general and fundamental understanding and guidance than it currently has. I’ve tried to demonstrate that a significant shift in the concept of knowledge, from passive contemplation to active engagement, is the inevitable outcome of how inquiry and invention are now conducted. However, in making this claim, it must also be[Pg 125] acknowledged, or rather emphasized, that so far this change has mostly impacted the more technical aspects of human life. The sciences have led to new industrial skills. Humanity's physical control over natural energies has increased significantly. There is management of the sources of material wealth and prosperity. What once would have been considered miracles are now performed daily using steam, coal, electricity, air, and the human body. Yet, very few are optimistic enough to claim that a similar control over the forces that influence human social and moral well-being has been achieved.
Where is the moral progress that corresponds to our economic accomplishments? The latter is the direct fruit of the revolution that has been wrought in physical science. But where is there a corresponding human science and art? Not only has the improvement in the method of knowing remained so far mainly limited to technical and economic matters, but this progress has brought with it serious new moral disturbances. I need only cite the late war, the problem of capital and labor, the relation of economic classes, the fact that while the new science has achieved wonders in medicine and surgery, it has also produced and spread occasions for diseases and weaknesses. These considerations indicate to us how undeveloped are our politics, how crude and primitive our education, how passive and[Pg 126] inert our morals. The causes remain which brought philosophy into existence as an attempt to find an intelligent substitute for blind custom and blind impulse as guides to life and conduct. The attempt has not been successfully accomplished. Is there not reason for believing that the release of philosophy from its burden of sterile metaphysics and sterile epistemology instead of depriving philosophy of problems and subject-matter would open a way to questions of the most perplexing and the most significant sort?
Where is the moral progress that matches our economic achievements? The latter is a direct result of the revolution in physical science. But where is the corresponding human science and art? The improvement in our ways of knowing has mostly been focused on technical and economic issues, and this progress has led to serious new moral challenges. Just look at the recent war, the issues between capital and labor, the relationship among economic classes, and the fact that while modern science has made incredible advances in medicine and surgery, it has also created and spread opportunities for diseases and weaknesses. These factors show us just how underdeveloped our politics are, how basic and outdated our education is, and how passive and [Pg 126] stagnant our morals have become. The reasons behind the emergence of philosophy still exist as a way to find a smart alternative to blindly following customs and impulses as guides for life and behavior. This attempt has not yet been successful. Isn’t there a good reason to believe that freeing philosophy from its burdensome metaphysics and unproductive epistemology would not deprive it of problems and subjects but instead open up pathways to the most complex and significant questions?
Let me specify one problem quite directly suggested by certain points in this lecture. It has been pointed out that the really fruitful application of the contemplative idea was not in science but in the esthetic field. It is difficult to imagine any high development of the fine arts except where there is curious and loving interest in forms and motions of the world quite irrespective of any use to which they may be put. And it is not too much to say that every people that has attained a high esthetic development has been a people in which the contemplative attitude has flourished—as the Greek, the Hindoo, the medieval Christian. On the other hand, the scientific attitude that has actually proved itself in scientific progress is, as has been pointed out, a practical attitude. It takes forms as disguises for hidden processes. Its interest in change is in what it leads to, what can be done with it, to what use it can be put.[Pg 127] While it has brought nature under control, there is something hard and aggressive in its attitude toward nature unfavorable to the esthetic enjoyment of the world. Surely there is no more significant question before the world than this question of the possibility and method of reconciliation of the attitudes of practical science and contemplative esthetic appreciation. Without the former, man will be the sport and victim of natural forces which he cannot use or control. Without the latter, mankind might become a race of economic monsters, restlessly driving hard bargains with nature and with one another, bored with leisure or capable of putting it to use only in ostentatious display and extravagant dissipation.
Let me address a problem that this lecture clearly highlights. It's been noted that the most valuable use of the contemplative idea was found not in science, but in art. It's hard to picture any significant growth in the fine arts without a genuine and passionate interest in the forms and movements of the world, regardless of their practical applications. It's fair to say that every culture that has reached a high level of artistic development has also been one where a contemplative mindset thrived—like the Greeks, the Hindus, and medieval Christians. Conversely, the scientific mindset that has led to real scientific advancements is, as mentioned, a practical one. It regards forms as mere covers for underlying processes. Its curiosity about change focuses on its outcomes, what can be achieved with it, and how it can be utilized. While it has managed to dominate nature, there’s a certain harshness and aggression in this practical attitude towards nature that hinders the aesthetic appreciation of the world. There’s no more pressing question facing us than how to reconcile the practical approaches of science and the contemplative enjoyment of aesthetics. Without the former, humanity risks becoming powerless against natural forces we can't harness or control. Without the latter, we could turn into a race of economic creatures, relentlessly striking hard deals with nature and each other, either bored with leisure or able to use it only for flashy displays and wasteful extravagance.[Pg 127]
Like other moral questions, this matter is social and even political. The western peoples advanced earlier on the path of experimental science and its applications in control of nature than the oriental. It is not, I suppose wholly fanciful, to believe that the latter have embodied in their habits of life more of the contemplative, esthetic and speculatively religious temper, and the former more of the scientific, industrial and practical. This difference and others which have grown up around it is one barrier to easy mutual understanding, and one source of misunderstanding. The philosophy which, then, makes a serious effort to comprehend these respective attitudes in their relation and due balance,[Pg 128] could hardly fail to promote the capacity of peoples to profit by one another's experience and to co-operate more effectually with one another in the tasks of fruitful culture.
Like other moral issues, this topic is both social and even political. Western societies progressed faster on the path of experimental science and its applications in controlling nature than Eastern societies. It’s not entirely unrealistic to think that the latter have incorporated more of a contemplative, aesthetic, and religious approach into their way of life, while the former have embraced a more scientific, industrial, and practical mindset. This difference, along with others that have developed around it, creates a barrier to easy mutual understanding and is a source of misunderstandings. A philosophy that seriously tries to understand these different attitudes in their relationship and balance could greatly enhance the ability of societies to learn from each other’s experiences and work together more effectively in the pursuit of fruitful culture.[Pg 128]
Indeed, it is incredible that the question of the relation of the "real" and the "ideal" should ever have been thought to be a problem belonging distinctively to philosophy. The very fact that this most serious of all human issues has been taken possession of by philosophy is only another proof of the disasters that follow in the wake of regarding knowledge and intellect as something self-sufficient. Never have the "real" and the "ideal" been so clamorous, so self-assertive, as at the present time. And never in the history of the world have they been so far apart. The world war was carried on for purely ideal ends:—for humanity, justice and equal liberty for strong and weak alike. And it was carried on by realistic means of applied science, by high explosives, and bombing airplanes and blockading marvels of mechanism that reduced the world well nigh to ruin, so that the serious-minded are concerned for the perpetuity of those choice values we call civilization. The peace settlement is loudly proclaimed in the name of the ideals that stir man's deepest emotions, but with the most realistic attention to details of economic advantage distributed in proportion to physical power to create future disturbances.
Indeed, it's amazing that the question of the relationship between the "real" and the "ideal" was ever seen as a problem unique to philosophy. The fact that this critical human issue has been claimed by philosophy only demonstrates the trouble that comes from viewing knowledge and intellect as wholly self-sufficient. Never have the "real" and the "ideal" been as vocal and assertive as they are today. And never in history have they been so far apart. The world war was fought for purely ideal reasons: for humanity, justice, and equal freedom for both the strong and the weak. Yet, it was conducted using realistic means of applied science, such as powerful explosives, bombers, and an array of mechanical marvels that nearly brought the world to ruin, prompting the serious-minded to worry about the survival of the valued aspects we call civilization. The peace settlement is loudly declared in the name of the ideals that resonate with the deepest human emotions, but it is carried out with a sharp focus on the details of economic gain distributed according to the physical power to provoke future conflicts.
It is not surprising that some men are brought to regard all idealism as a mere smoke-screen behind which the search for material profit may be more effectually carried on, and are converted to the materialistic interpretation of history. "Reality" is then conceived as physical force and as sensations of power, profit and enjoyment; any politics that takes account of other factors, save as elements of clever propaganda and for control of those human beings who have not become realistically enlightened, is based on illusions. But others are equally sure that the real lesson of the war is that humanity took its first great wrong step when it entered upon a cultivation of physical science and an application of the fruits of science to the improvement of the instruments of life—industry and commerce. They will sigh for the return of the day when, while the great mass died as they were born in animal fashion, the few elect devoted themselves not to science and the material decencies and comforts of existence but to "ideal" things, the things of the spirit.
It's not surprising that some men come to see all idealism as just a facade that allows the pursuit of material gain to continue more effectively, leading them to embrace a materialistic view of history. "Reality" becomes defined by physical power, profit, and enjoyment; any politics that considers other factors, unless they serve as clever propaganda or means to control those who haven't achieved true enlightenment, is seen as based on illusions. However, others firmly believe that the real lesson of the war is that humanity made its first major mistake when it focused on the advancement of physical science and applied its benefits to improve the tools of life—like industry and commerce. They long for the days when, while the majority lived and died in primitive ways, the few chosen ones dedicated themselves not to science and material comforts, but to "ideal" pursuits, the things of the spirit.
Yet the most obvious conclusion would seem to be the impotency and the harmfulness of any and every ideal that is proclaimed wholesale and in the abstract, that is, as something in itself apart from the detailed concrete existences whose moving possibilities it embodies. The true moral would seem to lie in enforcing the tragedy of that idealism which believes[Pg 130] in a spiritual world which exists in and by itself, and the tragic need for the most realistic study of forces and consequences, a study conducted in a more scientifically accurate and complete manner than that of the professed Real-politik. For it is not truly realistic or scientific to take short views, to sacrifice the future to immediate pressure, to ignore facts and forces that are disagreeable and to magnify the enduring quality of whatever falls in with immediate desire. It is false that the evils of the situation arise from absence of ideals; they spring from wrong ideals. And these wrong ideals have in turn their foundation in the absence in social matters of that methodic, systematic, impartial, critical, searching inquiry into "real" and operative conditions which we call science and which has brought man in the technical realm to the command of physical energies.
Yet the most obvious conclusion seems to be the ineffectiveness and harmfulness of any ideal that is declared broadly and abstractly—essentially, as something separate from the specific, concrete situations it aims to address. The real lesson appears to be in recognizing the tragedy of idealism that believes in a spiritual world that exists independently and the pressing need for a realistic examination of forces and outcomes, one that is carried out in a scientifically accurate and comprehensive way, more so than the so-called Real-politik. It isn't genuinely realistic or scientific to take a short-term view, to sacrifice the future for immediate pressure, to ignore unpleasant facts and forces, and to inflate the lasting nature of whatever aligns with immediate desires. It's incorrect to claim that the problems of the situation stem from a lack of ideals; they arise from misguided ideals. These misguided ideals, in turn, are rooted in the absence of that methodical, systematic, impartial, and critical inquiry into "real" and active conditions that we refer to as science, which has enabled humanity to harness physical energies in the technical domain.
Philosophy, let it be repeated, cannot "solve" the problem of the relation of the ideal and the real. That is the standing problem of life. But it can at least lighten the burden of humanity in dealing with the problem by emancipating mankind from the errors which philosophy has itself fostered—the existence of conditions which are real apart from their movement into something new and different, and the existence of ideals, spirit and reason independent of the possibilities of the material and physical. For as long[Pg 131] as humanity is committed to this radically false bias, it will walk forward with blinded eyes and bound limbs. And philosophy can effect, if it will, something more than this negative task. It can make it easier for mankind to take the right steps in action by making it clear that a sympathetic and integral intelligence brought to bear upon the observation and understanding of concrete social events and forces, can form ideals, that is aims, which shall not be either illusions or mere emotional compensations.
Philosophy, it should be noted, cannot "solve" the issue of the connection between the ideal and the real. That is a persistent challenge in life. However, it can at least ease the burden of humanity in confronting this issue by freeing people from the misconceptions that philosophy has contributed to—such as believing in conditions that exist independently of their transformation into something new and different, and in ideals, spirit, and reason that exist separately from the possibilities of the material and physical world. As long as humanity remains attached to this fundamentally misguided belief, it will move forward with blind eyes and restricted capabilities. Moreover, philosophy can do more than just this negative work. It can help humanity take the right actions by demonstrating that a compassionate and comprehensive understanding applied to the observation and analysis of real social events and forces can create ideals, or goals, that are not merely illusions or emotional distractions.
CHAPTER VI
THE SIGNIFICANCE OF LOGICAL RECONSTRUCTION
Logic—like philosophy itself—suffers from a curious oscillation. It is elevated into the supreme and legislative science only to fall into the trivial estate of keeper of such statements as A is A and the scholastic verses for the syllogistic rules. It claims power to state the laws of the ultimate structure of the universe, on the ground that it deals with the laws of thought which are the laws according to which Reason has formed the world. Then it limits its pretensions to laws of correct reasoning which is correct even though it leads to no matter of fact, or even to material falsity. It is regarded by the modern objective idealist as the adequate substitute for ancient ontological metaphysics; but others treat it as that branch of rhetoric which teaches proficiency in argumentation. For a time a superficial compromise equilibrium was maintained wherein the logic of formal demonstration which the Middle Ages extracted from Aristotle was supplemented by an inductive logic of discovery of truth that Mill extracted from the practice of scientific men. But[Pg 133] students of German philosophy, of mathematics, and of psychology, no matter how much they attacked one another, have made common cause in attack upon the orthodox logics both of deductive proof and inductive discovery.
Logic—like philosophy itself—goes through a strange back-and-forth. It gets raised to the highest level as the ultimate science only to get dragged down to trivial stuff like stating that A is A and the formal rules of syllogisms. It claims the authority to express the laws governing the very structure of the universe because it deals with the laws of thought, which are how Reason has shaped the world. Then, it scales back its claims to just the laws of correct reasoning, which can be accurate even if they don’t lead to any actual facts or even to outright falsehoods. The modern objective idealist sees it as a replacement for the ancient ontological metaphysics; yet others view it as a part of rhetoric that teaches effective argumentation. For a while, a superficial balance was kept where the logic of formal proof extracted from Aristotle during the Middle Ages was combined with an inductive logic for discovering truth that Mill derived from the practices of scientists. But[Pg 133] students of German philosophy, mathematics, and psychology, no matter how much they critiqued each other, joined forces in their criticism of traditional logics, both deductive proof and inductive discovery.
Logical theory presents a scene of chaos. There is little agreement as to its subject-matter, scope or purpose. This disagreement is not formal or nominal but affects the treatment of every topic. Take such a rudimentary matter as the nature of judgment. Reputable authority can be quoted in behalf of every possible permutation of doctrine. Judgment is the central thing in logic; and judgment is not logical at all, but personal and psychological. If logical, it is the primary function to which both conception and inference are subordinate; and it is an after-product from them. The distinction of subject and predicate is necessary, and it is totally irrelevant; or again, though it is found in some cases, it is not of great importance. Among those who hold that the subject-predicate relationship is essential, some hold that judgment is an analysis of something prior into them, and others assert that it is a synthesis of them into something else. Some hold that reality is always the subject of judgment, and others that "reality" is logically irrelevant. Among those who deny that judgment is the attribution of predicate to subject, who regard it as a relation of elements,[Pg 134] some hold that the relation is "internal," some that it is "external," and others that it is sometimes one and sometimes the other.
Logical theory looks pretty chaotic. There's hardly any consensus on what it really covers, its extent, or its purpose. This disagreement isn't just superficial; it influences how every topic is approached. Take something as basic as the nature of judgment. You can find respected authorities backing pretty much any viewpoint. Judgment is the core of logic, yet it isn't logical at all—it's personal and psychological. If it were logical, it would be the main function, with both conception and inference being secondary to it, and it would come after those processes. The distinction between subject and predicate is necessary, but it’s largely irrelevant; or, when it does apply, it doesn’t really matter. Among those who believe the subject-predicate relationship is crucial, some argue that judgment breaks down something prior into these components, while others argue it combines them into something new. Some believe that reality is always the subject of judgment, while others claim that "reality" is actually irrelevant to logic. Among those who reject the idea that judgment is about attributing a predicate to a subject, and view it as a relationship between elements,[Pg 134] some think the relationship is "internal," some say it's "external," and others believe it can be either, depending on the situation.
Unless logic is a matter of some practical account, these contrarieties are so numerous, so extensive, and so irreconcilable that they are ludicrous. If logic is an affair of practical moment, then these inconsistencies are serious. They testify to some deep-lying cause of intellectual disagreement and incoherency. In fact, contemporary logical theory is the ground upon which all philosophical differences and disputes are gathered together and focussed. How does the modification in the traditional conception of the relation of experience and reason, the real and ideal affect logic?
Unless logic is practically relevant, these contradictions are so many, so widespread, and so incompatible that they become ridiculous. If logic matters in real life, then these inconsistencies are significant. They point to some underlying cause of intellectual disagreement and confusion. In fact, today’s logical theory is the foundation on which all philosophical differences and debates come together and are concentrated. How does the change in the traditional view of the relationship between experience and reason, the real and the ideal, influence logic?
It affects, in the first place, the nature of logic itself. If thought or intelligence is the means of intentional reconstruction of experience, then logic, as an account of the procedure of thought, is not purely formal. It is not confined to laws of formally correct reasoning apart from truth of subject-matter. Neither, on the contrary, is it concerned with the inherent thought structures of the universe, as Hegel's logic would have it; nor with the successive approaches of human thought to this objective thought structure as the logic of Lotze, Bosanquet, and other epistemological logicians would have it. If thinking is the way in which deliberate reorganization of experience is secured, then logic is such[Pg 135] a clarified and systematized formulation of the procedures of thinking as will enable the desired reconstruction to go on more economically and efficiently. In language familiar to students, logic is both a science and an art; a science so far as it gives an organized and tested descriptive account of the way in which thought actually goes on; an art, so far as on the basis of this description it projects methods by which future thinking shall take advantage of the operations that lead to success and avoid those which result in failure.
It primarily impacts the nature of logic itself. If thinking or intelligence is the tool for intentionally reworking experience, then logic, as an explanation of how thought works, isn’t just a formal exercise. It’s not limited to rules of correct reasoning without regard to the truth of the content. Nor is it, on the flip side, focused on the inherent structures of thought in the universe, as Hegel suggested; or on the gradual approaches of human thought towards this objective structure, as Lotze, Bosanquet, and other epistemological logicians proposed. If thinking is how we purposefully reorganize experience, then logic is a clarified and systematized way of formulating the processes of thinking that allows for more efficient and effective reconstruction. In terms familiar to students, logic is both a science and an art; a science because it provides an organized and tested descriptive account of how thought actually works; an art because, based on this description, it suggests methods for future thinking to harness the operations that lead to success and avoid those that lead to failure.
Thus is answered the dispute whether logic is empirical or normative, psychological or regulative. It is both. Logic is based on a definite and executive supply of empirical material. Men have been thinking for ages. They have observed, inferred, and reasoned in all sorts of ways and to all kinds of results. Anthropology, the study of the origin of myth, legend and cult; linguistics and grammar; rhetoric and former logical compositions all tell us how men have thought and what have been the purposes and consequences of different kinds of thinking. Psychology, experimental and pathological, makes important contributions to our knowledge of how thinking goes on and to what effect. Especially does the record of the growth of the various sciences afford instruction in those concrete ways of inquiry and testing which have led men astray and which have proved efficacious. Each science from mathematics to history[Pg 136] exhibits typical fallacious methods and typical efficacious methods in special subject-matters. Logical theory has thus a large, almost inexhaustible field of empirical study.
Thus the debate is settled on whether logic is empirical or normative, psychological or regulative. It is both. Logic relies on a clear and practical set of empirical data. People have been thinking for ages. They have observed, inferred, and reasoned in various ways and towards numerous results. Anthropology, the study of the origins of myth, legend, and belief; linguistics and grammar; rhetoric and earlier logical compositions all reveal how people have thought and what the aims and outcomes of different types of thinking have been. Psychology, both experimental and pathological, significantly contributes to our understanding of how thinking occurs and its effects. Particularly, the history of the development of various sciences offers insights into the specific methods of inquiry and testing that have misled people and those that have proven effective. Each science, from mathematics to history[Pg 136], demonstrates typical flawed methods and effective methods within their specific subjects. Therefore, logical theory has a vast, nearly limitless field of empirical study.
The conventional statement that experience only tells us how men have thought or do think, while logic is concerned with norms, with how men should think, is ludicrously inept. Some sorts of thinking are shown by experience to have got nowhere, or worse than nowhere—into systematized delusion and mistake. Others have proved in manifest experience that they lead to fruitful and enduring discoveries. It is precisely in experience that the different consequences of different methods of investigation and ratiocination are convincingly shown. The parrot-like repetition of the distinction between an empirical description of what is and a normative account of what should be merely neglects the most striking fact about thinking as it empirically is—namely, its flagrant exhibition of cases of failure and success—that is, of good thinking and bad thinking. Any one who considers this empirical manifestation will not complain of lack of material from which to construct a regulative art. The more study that is given to empirical records of actual thought, the more apparent becomes the connection between the specific features of thinking which have produced failure and success. Out of this relationship of cause and effect[Pg 137] as it is empirically ascertained grow the norms and regulations of an art of thinking.
The usual claim that experience only shows us how people have thought or do think, while logic deals with standards for how people should think, is completely misguided. Some types of thinking have been proven by experience to lead nowhere or worse—into systematic delusion and error. Others have clearly shown through experience that they lead to valuable and lasting discoveries. It is precisely through experience that we can see the different results of various methods of investigation and reasoning. Simply repeating the distinction between an empirical description of what is and a normative account of what should be ignores the most striking aspect of thinking as it actually exists—its blatant display of both failures and successes—that is, good thinking and bad thinking. Anyone who considers this empirical evidence will find plenty of material to build a regulative art. The more we study real records of actual thought, the clearer the connection becomes between the specific characteristics of thinking that have resulted in failure and success. From this cause-and-effect relationship[Pg 137] as it is confirmed empirically, the norms and regulations of a thinking art emerge.
Mathematics is often cited as an example of purely normative thinking dependent upon a priori canons and supra-empirical material. But it is hard to see how the student who approaches the matter historically can avoid the conclusion that the status of mathematics is as empirical as that of metallurgy. Men began with counting and measuring things just as they began with pounding and burning them. One thing, as common speech profoundly has it, led to another. Certain ways were successful—not merely in the immediately practical sense, but in the sense of being interesting, of arousing attention, of exciting attempts at improvement. The present-day mathematical logician may present the structure of mathematics as if it had sprung all at once from the brain of a Zeus whose anatomy is that of pure logic. But, nevertheless, this very structure is a product of long historic growth, in which all kinds of experiments have been tried, in which some men have struck out in this direction and some in that, and in which some exercises and operations have resulted in confusion and others in triumphant clarifications and fruitful growths; a history in which matter and methods have been constantly selected and worked over on the basis of empirical success and failure.
Mathematics is often mentioned as an example of purely normative thinking based on a priori standards and beyond-empirical material. However, it's difficult to see how a student who looks at the topic historically can avoid concluding that the status of mathematics is just as empirical as that of metallurgy. People started with counting and measuring things just like they began with pounding and burning them. As common speech wisely says, one thing led to another. Certain approaches worked well—not just in an immediately practical sense, but also in being interesting, grabbing attention, and inspiring attempts at improvement. Today’s mathematical logician might present the structure of mathematics as if it emerged suddenly from the mind of a Zeus whose makeup is pure logic. However, this very structure is the result of a long historical process, where all sorts of experiments were conducted, some people ventured in one direction while others went another way, leading to some methods causing confusion and others resulting in clear successes and fruitful developments; a history in which materials and methods have continually been chosen and refined based on real-world success and failure.
The structure of alleged normative a priori mathe[Pg 138]matics is in truth the crowned result of ages of toilsome experience. The metallurgist who should write on the most highly developed method of dealing with ores would not, in truth, proceed any differently. He too selects, refines, and organizes the methods which in the past have been found to yield the maximum of achievement. Logic is a matter of profound human importance precisely because it is empirically founded and experimentally applied. So considered, the problem of logical theory is none other than the problem of the possibility of the development and employment of intelligent method in inquiries concerned with deliberate reconstruction of experience. And it is only saying again in more specific form what has been said in general form to add that while such a logic has been developed in respect to mathematics and physical science, intelligent method, logic, is still far to seek in moral and political affairs.
The structure of supposed normative a priori mathe[Pg 138]matics is actually the result of years of hard-earned experience. The metallurgist who writes about the most advanced methods for handling ores wouldn't approach it any differently. They also choose, refine, and organize the techniques that have previously proven to achieve the best results. Logic is incredibly important for humanity precisely because it’s grounded in experience and applied through experimentation. From this perspective, the challenge of logical theory boils down to whether we can develop and use intelligent methods in inquiries aimed at thoughtfully reconstructing experience. To put it simply, while we’ve developed such logic for mathematics and physical sciences, intelligent methods and logic are still lacking in moral and political issues.
Assuming, accordingly, this idea of logic without argument, let us proceed to discuss some of its chief features. First, light is thrown by the origin of thinking upon a logic which shall be a method of intelligent guidance of experience. In line with what has already been said about experience being a matter primarily of behavior, a sensori-motor matter, is the fact that thinking takes its departure from specific conflicts in experience that occasion perplexity and trouble. Men do not,[Pg 139] in their natural estate, think when they have no troubles to cope with, no difficulties to overcome. A life of ease, of success without effort, would be a thoughtless life, and so also would a life of ready omnipotence. Beings who think are beings whose life is so hemmed in and constricted that they cannot directly carry through a course of action to victorious consummation. Men also do not tend to think when their action, when they are amid difficulties, is dictated to them by authority. Soldiers have difficulties and restrictions in plenty, but qua soldiers (as Aristotle would say) they are not notorious for being thinkers. Thinking is done for them, higher up. The same is too true of most workingmen under present economic conditions. Difficulties occasion thinking only when thinking is the imperative or urgent way out, only when it is the indicated road to a solution. Wherever external authority reigns, thinking is suspected and obnoxious.
Assuming this idea of logic without argument, let's discuss some of its main features. First, the origin of thinking sheds light on a logic that serves as a method for intelligently guiding our experiences. As mentioned earlier, experience is mostly about behavior, a sensory-motor issue, and thinking arises from specific conflicts in our experiences that cause confusion and trouble. People generally do not,[Pg 139] in their natural state, think when they have no problems to deal with, no challenges to face. A life of ease, success without effort, would be a life devoid of thought, as would a life of effortless power. Those who think are individuals whose lives are so constrained that they cannot easily achieve their goals. People also tend not to think when their actions amid difficulties are dictated by authority. Soldiers face many challenges and restrictions, but qua soldiers (as Aristotle would put it), they aren't known for their thinking. Higher-ups think for them. The same is true for most workers under current economic conditions. Difficulties only lead to thinking when thinking is the necessary or urgent way out, when it’s the clear path to a solution. Wherever external authority dominates, thinking is seen as questionable and undesirable.
Thinking, however, is not the only way in which a personal solution of difficulties is sought. As we have seen, dreams, reveries, emotional idealizations are roads which are taken to escape the strain of perplexity and conflict. According to modern psychology, many systematized delusions and mental disorders, probably hysteria itself, originate as devices for getting freedom from troublesome conflicting factors. Such considerations throw into relief some of the traits essential to[Pg 140] thinking as a way of responding to difficulty. The short-cut "solutions" alluded to do not get rid of the conflict and problems; they only get rid of the feeling of it. They cover up consciousness of it. Because the conflict remains in fact and is evaded in thought, disorders arise.
Thinking, however, isn’t the only way people try to find personal solutions to their struggles. As we've seen, dreams, daydreams, and emotional idealizations are paths people take to escape the pressure of confusion and conflict. According to modern psychology, many organized delusions and mental disorders, possibly even hysteria, start as methods for gaining freedom from annoying conflicting issues. These points highlight some key traits of[Pg 140] thinking as a response to challenges. The quick "solutions" mentioned don’t actually eliminate the conflicts and problems; they just remove the feeling of them. They hide awareness of those issues. Since the conflict still exists in reality but is avoided in thought, disorders can develop.
The first distinguishing characteristic of thinking then is facing the facts—inquiry, minute and extensive scrutinizing, observation. Nothing has done greater harm to the successful conduct of the enterprise of thinking (and to the logics which reflect and formulate the undertaking) than the habit of treating observation as something outside of and prior to thinking, and thinking as something which can go on in the head without including observation of new facts as part of itself. Every approximation to such "thinking" is really an approach to the method of escape and self-delusion just referred to. It substitutes an emotionally agreeable and rationally self-consistent train of meanings for inquiry into the features of the situation which cause the trouble. It leads to that type of Idealism which has well been termed intellectual somnambulism. It creates a class of "thinkers" who are remote from practice and hence from testing their thought by application—a socially superior and irresponsible class. This is the condition causing the tragic division of theory and practice, and leading to an unreasonable exaltation of theory on one[Pg 141] side and an unreasonable contempt for it on the other. It confirms current practice in its hard brutalities and dead routines just because it has transferred thinking and theory to a separate and nobler region. Thus has the idealist conspired with the materialist to keep actual life impoverished and inequitable.
The first distinguishing characteristic of thinking is facing the facts—investigating, thoroughly examining, and observing. Nothing has harmed the successful practice of thinking (and the logic that reflects and shapes this practice) more than the tendency to treat observation as something separate from and prior to thinking, and to view thinking as something that can happen in one’s head without incorporating the observation of new facts. Any attempt at such "thinking" is really just a way to escape and delude oneself. It replaces an emotionally convenient and logically consistent flow of ideas with an inquiry into the aspects of the situation that are problematic. This leads to a kind of Idealism that has been accurately described as intellectual sleepwalking. It creates a group of "thinkers" who are disconnected from real-world practice and, therefore, fail to test their ideas through application—forming a socially superior and irresponsible elite. This situation causes a tragic split between theory and practice, resulting in an unreasonable glorification of theory on one side and unwarranted disdain for it on the other. It reinforces existing practices in their harsh realities and stagnant routines precisely because it has isolated thinking and theory in a separate and supposedly nobler realm. In this way, idealists and materialists work together to keep real life impoverished and unfair.
The isolation of thinking from confrontation with facts encourages that kind of observation which merely accumulates brute facts, which occupies itself laboriously with mere details, but never inquires into their meaning and consequences—a safe occupation, for it never contemplates any use to be made of the observed facts in determining a plan for changing the situation. Thinking which is a method of reconstructing experience treats observation of facts, on the other hand, as the indispensable step of defining the problem, of locating the trouble, of forcing home a definite, instead of a merely vague emotional, sense of what the difficulty is and where it lies. It is not aimless, random, miscellaneous, but purposeful, specific and limited by the character of the trouble undergone. The purpose is so to clarify the disturbed and confused situation that reasonable ways of dealing with it may be suggested. When the scientific man appears to observe aimlessly, it is merely that he is so in love with problems as sources and guides of inquiry, that he is striving to turn up a problem where none appears on the surface: he[Pg 142] is, as we say, hunting for trouble because of the satisfaction to be had in coping with it.
The separation of thinking from engaging with facts leads to a type of observation that just collects raw information, spending a lot of time on trivial details without questioning their significance or implications. This approach is safe because it doesn’t consider how these facts might be used to create a plan for changing the situation. In contrast, thinking that aims to reconstruct experience views observing facts as a crucial step in identifying the problem, pinpointing the issue, and developing a clear, rather than vague, emotional understanding of what the difficulty is and where it lies. This process isn't random or scattered; it's focused, specific, and shaped by the nature of the challenge at hand. The goal is to clarify the chaotic and unclear situation so that sensible ways to address it can emerge. When a scientist seems to be observing without purpose, it’s simply because they are so passionate about problems as sources and guides for inquiry that they are trying to uncover an issue where none seems apparent; they are, as we say, seeking out challenges because of the satisfaction that comes from tackling them.
Specific and wide observation of concrete fact always, then, corresponds not only with a sense of a problem or difficulty, but with some vague sense of the meaning of the difficulty, that is, of what it imports or signifies in subsequent experience. It is a kind of anticipation or prediction of what is coming. We speak, very truly, of impending trouble, and in observing the signs of what the trouble is, we are at the same time expecting, forecasting—in short, framing an idea, becoming aware of meaning. When the trouble is not only impending but completely actual and present, we are overwhelmed. We do not think, but give way to depression. The kind of trouble that occasions thinking is that which is incomplete and developing, and where what is found, already in existence can be employed as a sign from which to infer what is likely to come. When we intelligently observe, we are, as we say apprehensive, as well as apprehending. We are on the alert for something still to come. Curiosity, inquiry, investigation, are directed quite as truly into what is going to happen next as into what has happened. An intelligent interest in the latter is an interest in getting evidence, indications, symptoms for inferring the former. Observation is diagnosis and diagnosis implies an interest in anticipation and preparation. It makes ready in advance an[Pg 143] attitude of response so that we shall not be caught unawares.
Specific and broad observation of concrete facts always corresponds not only with a sense of a problem or challenge but also with some vague sense of the meaning behind the difficulty, that is, what it implies or signifies in future experiences. It's a kind of anticipation or prediction of what’s coming. We often refer to impending trouble, and by observing the signs of that trouble, we simultaneously expect and forecast—in short, we're forming an idea and becoming aware of its meaning. When the trouble is not only looming but fully present, we feel overwhelmed. We stop thinking and succumb to depression. The type of trouble that prompts thought is that which is still unfolding, where the existing evidence can serve as a clue to what is likely to happen next. When we observe intelligently, we are, as we say, apprehensive, as well as comprehending. We stay alert for what’s still to come. Curiosity, inquiry, and investigation aimed at understanding what will happen next are just as important as looking into what has already happened. An intelligent interest in the past is essentially an interest in gathering evidence, signs, and symptoms to infer what may occur next. Observation is diagnosis, and diagnosis involves an interest in anticipation and preparation. It readies an[Pg 143] attitude of response so that we won’t be caught off guard.
That which is not already in existence, that which is only anticipated and inferred, cannot be observed. It does not have the status of fact, of something given, a datum, but of a meaning, an idea. So far as ideas are not fancies, framed by emotionalized memory for escape and refuge, they are precisely anticipations of something still to come aroused by looking into the facts of a developing situation. The blacksmith watches his iron, its color and texture, to get evidence of what it is getting ready to pass into; the physician observes his patient to detect symptoms of change in some definite direction; the scientific man keeps his attention upon his laboratory material to get a clue as to what will happen under certain conditions. The very fact that observation is not an end in itself but a search for evidence and signs shows that along with observation goes inference, anticipatory forecast—in short an idea, thought or conception.
What doesn't already exist, what’s only expected and implied, can’t be seen. It doesn’t hold the status of fact, something given, a datum, but rather of meaning, an idea. As long as ideas aren’t just fantasies created by emotional memories for escape and comfort, they are actually anticipations of something that’s yet to come, sparked by examining the facts of a developing situation. The blacksmith watches his iron, its color and texture, to gather clues about what it’s getting ready to become; the doctor looks at his patient to find signs of changes in a specific direction; the scientist focuses on his lab materials to get hints about what will happen under certain conditions. The very fact that observation isn’t an end in itself but a quest for evidence and signs shows that along with observation comes inference, predictive forecasting—in short, an idea, thought, or concept.
In a more technical context, it would be worth while to see what light this logical correspondence of observed fact and projected idea or meaning throws upon certain traditional philosophical problems and puzzles, including that of subject and predicate in judgment, object and subject in knowledge, "real" and "ideal" generally. But at this time, we must confine ourselves to[Pg 144] pointing out that this view of the correlative origin and function of observed fact and projected idea in experience, commits us to some very important consequences concerning the nature of ideas, meanings, conceptions, or whatever word may be employed to denote the specifically mental function. Because they are suggestions of something that may happen or eventuate, they are (as we saw in the case of ideals generally) platforms of response to what is going on. The man who detects that the cause of his difficulty is an automobile bearing down upon him is not guaranteed safety; he may have made his observation-forecast too late. But if his anticipation-perception comes in season, he has the basis for doing something which will avert threatening disaster. Because he foresees an impending result, he may do something that will lead to the situation eventuating in some other way. All intelligent thinking means an increment of freedom in action—an emancipation from chance and fatality. "Thought" represents the suggestion of a way of response that is different from that which would have been followed if intelligent observation had not effected an inference as to the future.
In a more technical sense, it’s helpful to consider how this logical link between observed facts and projected ideas or meanings sheds light on some traditional philosophical issues and puzzles, including the concepts of subject and predicate in judgment, and object and subject in knowledge, as well as the general distinction between "real" and "ideal." However, for now, we need to focus on[Pg 144] pointing out that this perspective on the interconnected origin and role of observed facts and projected ideas in our experiences leads us to some significant implications about the nature of ideas, meanings, and concepts, or whatever term we use to refer to the specifically mental functions. Since they are suggestions of what might happen or occur, they act as platforms for responding to what is happening. A person who realizes that the cause of their problem is a car speeding towards them isn’t assured safety; they might have made that observation too late. But if their anticipation comes in time, they have the basis for taking action that could prevent a disaster. By foreseeing an imminent outcome, they might take steps that will change the situation’s outcome. All intelligent thinking results in an increase in freedom of action—liberation from randomness and inevitability. "Thought" represents the suggestion of a different way to respond than one would take if intelligent observation hadn’t prompted an inference about the future.
Now a method of action, a mode of response, intended to produce a certain result—that is, to enable the blacksmith to give a certain form to his hot iron, the physician to treat the patient so as to facilitate recovery, the[Pg 145] scientific experimenter to draw a conclusion which will apply to other cases,—is by the nature of the case tentative, uncertain till tested by its results. The significance of this fact for the theory of truth will be discussed below. Here it is enough to note that notions, theories, systems, no matter how elaborate and self-consistent they are, must be regarded as hypotheses. They are to be accepted as bases of actions which test them, not as finalities. To perceive this fact is to abolish rigid dogmas from the world. It is to recognize that conceptions, theories and systems of thought are always open to development through use. It is to enforce the lesson that we must be on the lookout quite as much for indications to alter them as for opportunities to assert them. They are tools. As in the case of all tools, their value resides not in themselves but in their capacity to work shown in the consequences of their use.
Now a way of acting, a method of responding, designed to achieve a specific outcome—that is, to allow the blacksmith to shape his hot iron, the doctor to treat the patient for better recovery, the[Pg 145] researcher to draw a conclusion that applies to other situations— is, by its very nature, tentative and uncertain until tested by its outcomes. The importance of this for the theory of truth will be discussed later. For now, it's enough to acknowledge that ideas, theories, and systems, no matter how detailed and coherent, should be seen as hypotheses. They should be accepted as foundations for actions that test them, not as absolutes. Recognizing this helps eliminate rigid dogmas from our understanding. It acknowledges that concepts, theories, and thought systems are always subject to evolution through their application. It emphasizes that we should be just as attentive to signs that suggest we need to change them as we are to chances to affirm them. They are tools. Like all tools, their worth lies not in themselves but in their ability to produce results demonstrated by their use.
Nevertheless, inquiry is free only when the interest in knowing is so developed that thinking carries with it something worth while for itself, something having its own esthetic and moral interest. Just because knowing is not self-enclosed and final but is instrumental to reconstruction of situations, there is always danger that it will be subordinated to maintaining some preconceived purpose or prejudice. Then reflection ceases to be complete; it falls short. Being precommitted to[Pg 146] arriving at some special result, it is not sincere. It is one thing to say that all knowing has an end beyond itself, and another thing, a thing of a contrary kind, to say that an act of knowing has a particular end which it is bound, in advance, to reach. Much less is it true that the instrumental nature of thinking means that it exists for the sake of attaining some private, one-sided advantage upon which one has set one's heart. Any limitation whatever of the end means limitation in the thinking process itself. It signifies that it does not attain its full growth and movement, but is cramped, impeded, interfered with. The only situation in which knowing is fully stimulated is one in which the end is developed in the process of inquiry and testing.
However, inquiry is truly free only when the desire to know is so strong that thinking produces valuable insights on its own, with inherent aesthetic and moral significance. Since knowledge isn’t self-contained or final but serves to reconstruct situations, there’s always a risk that it will be forced to align with some pre-existing goal or bias. In those cases, reflection becomes incomplete; it falls short. Being committed to achieving a specific outcome makes it insincere. It’s one thing to say that all knowledge has a purpose beyond itself, and quite another to claim that an act of knowing is destined to hit a particular target from the outset. It is even less accurate to suggest that the instrumental nature of thought means it exists only to gain some personal, narrow advantage that one is fixated on. Any restriction on the goal limits the thinking process itself. It shows that it doesn’t reach its full potential and development but is constrained, hindered, and obstructed. The only time when knowing is fully stimulated is when the goal unfolds during the process of inquiry and testing.
Disinterested and impartial inquiry is then far from meaning that knowing is self-enclosed and irresponsible. It means that there is no particular end set up in advance so as to shut in the activities of observation, forming of ideas, and application. Inquiry is emancipated. It is encouraged to attend to every fact that is relevant to defining the problem or need, and to follow up every suggestion that promises a clue. The barriers to free inquiry are so many and so solid that mankind is to be congratulated that the very act of investigation is capable of itself becoming a delightful and absorbing pursuit, capable of enlisting on its side man's sporting instincts.
Disinterested and impartial inquiry doesn't mean that knowledge is isolated and irresponsible. It means that there’s no specific goal set ahead of time that limits observation, idea formation, and application. Inquiry is free. It is encouraged to pay attention to every relevant fact that helps define the problem or need, and to explore every suggestion that could lead to a clue. The obstacles to free inquiry are numerous and substantial, so humanity deserves praise for the fact that the act of investigation can itself become a rewarding and engaging pursuit, capable of appealing to people's adventurous instincts.
Just in the degree in which thought ceases to be held down to ends fixed by social custom, a social division of labor grows up. Investigation has become a dominant life occupation for some persons. Only superficially, however, does this confirm the idea that theory and knowledge are ends in themselves. They are, relatively speaking, ends in themselves for some persons. But these persons represent a social division of labor; and their specialization can be trusted only when such persons are in unobstructed co-operation with other social occupations, sensitive to others' problems and transmitting results to them for wider application in action. When this social relationship of persons particularly engaged in carrying on the enterprise of knowing is forgotten and the class becomes isolated, inquiry loses stimulus and purpose. It degenerates into sterile specialization, a kind of intellectual busy work carried on by socially absent-minded men. Details are heaped up in the name of science, and abstruse dialectical developments of systems occur. Then the occupation is "rationalized" under the lofty name of devotion to truth for its own sake. But when the path of true science is retaken these things are brushed aside and forgotten. They turn out to have been the toyings of vain and irresponsible men. The only guarantee of impartial, disinterested inquiry is the social sensitiveness of the inquirer to the needs[Pg 148] and problems of those with whom he is associated.
As thought moves away from being constrained by societal norms, a social division of labor emerges. For some individuals, investigation has become a primary life pursuit. However, this only superficially supports the notion that theory and knowledge are self-sufficient goals. They can be seen as goals for certain individuals, but these individuals represent a social division of labor; their specialization can only be relied upon when they collaborate freely with other social roles, addressing others' issues and sharing results for broader application. If this social connection among those dedicated to the pursuit of knowledge is overlooked and the group becomes isolated, inquiry loses its motivation and purpose. It devolves into unproductive specialization, like intellectual busywork performed by socially detached individuals. Information accumulates in the name of science, and complicated theoretical developments occur. Then, the work is "rationalized" under the grand title of commitment to truth for its own sake. However, when the true path of science is resumed, these concerns are set aside and forgotten. They prove to be mere distractions of self-important and careless individuals. The only assurance of impartial, unbiased inquiry is the inquirer's social awareness of the needs and problems of those they are connected with.
As the instrumental theory is favorable to high esteem for impartial and disinterested inquiry, so, contrary to the impressions of some critics, it sets much store upon the apparatus of deduction. It is a strange notion that because one says that the cognitive value of conceptions, definitions, generalizations, classifications and the development of consecutive implications is not self-resident, that therefore one makes light of the deductive function, or denies its fruitfulness and necessity. The instrumental theory only attempts to state with some scrupulousness where the value is found and to prevent its being sought in the wrong place. It says that knowing begins with specific observations that define the problem and ends with specific observations that test a hypothesis for its solution. But that the idea, the meaning, which the original observations suggest and the final ones test, itself requires careful scrutiny and prolonged development, the theory would be the last to deny. To say that a locomotive is an agency, that it is intermediate between a need in experience and its satisfaction, is not to depreciate the worth of careful and elaborate construction of the locomotive, or the need of subsidiary tools and processes that are devoted to introducing improvements into its structure. One would rather say that because the locomotive is[Pg 149] intermediary in experience, not primary and not final, it is impossible to devote too much care to its constructive development.
As the instrumental theory encourages a high regard for unbiased and objective investigation, it actually places significant value on the deductive process, contrary to what some critics may believe. It's a strange idea that because one states that the cognitive value of concepts, definitions, generalizations, classifications, and the development of sequential implications is not inherent, it follows that one undervalues the deductive function or denies its usefulness and necessity. The instrumental theory aims to clarify exactly where the value lies and to prevent it from being pursued in the wrong direction. It asserts that knowledge starts with specific observations that define the problem and concludes with specific observations that test a hypothesis for its solution. However, the theory acknowledges that the idea and meaning that arise from the initial observations and are tested by the final ones require careful examination and extensive development. To say that a locomotive serves as a means to connect a need in experience with its fulfillment does not diminish the importance of the locomotive's careful and detailed design, nor the necessity of the additional tools and processes that help improve its structure. One would rather argue that because the locomotive acts as[Pg 149] an intermediary in experience, and is neither primary nor final, it is crucial to invest as much care as possible into its construction and development.
Such a deductive science as mathematics represents the perfecting of method. That a method to those concerned with it should present itself as an end on its own account is no more surprising than that there should be a distinct business for making any tool. Rarely are those who invent and perfect a tool those who employ it. There is, indeed, one marked difference between the physical and the intellectual instrumentality. The development of the latter runs far beyond any immediately visible use. The artistic interest in perfecting the method by itself is strong—as the utensils of civilization may themselves become works of finest art. But from the practical standpoint this difference shows that the advantage as an instrumentality is on the side of the intellectual tool. Just because it is not formed with a special application in mind, because it is a highly generalized tool, it is the more flexible in adaptation to unforeseen uses. It can be employed in dealing with problems that were not anticipated. The mind is prepared in advance for all sorts of intellectual emergencies, and when the new problem occurs it does not have to wait till it can get a special instrument ready.
Mathematics, as a deductive science, represents the refinement of method. It's not surprising that those involved would see a method as an end in itself, just like there's a specific industry for creating any tool. Usually, the people who invent and improve a tool aren’t the ones who use it. There is a clear difference between physical tools and intellectual ones. The development of intellectual tools goes far beyond their immediate practical use. The artistic drive to refine the method itself is significant, as the tools of civilization can become remarkable works of art. However, from a practical perspective, this difference indicates that the benefit lies with intellectual tools. Because they are not designed for a specific application and are broad in nature, they are more adaptable to unexpected uses. They can be used to tackle problems that weren't anticipated. The mind is equipped in advance for a variety of intellectual challenges, and when a new problem arises, it doesn't have to wait to prepare a specialized tool.
More definitely, abstraction is indispensable if one[Pg 150] experience is to be applicable in other experiences. Every concrete experience in its totality is unique; it is itself, non-reduplicable. Taken in its full concreteness, it yields no instruction, it throws no light. What is called abstraction means that some phase of it is selected for the sake of the aid it gives in grasping something else. Taken by itself, it is a mangled fragment, a poor substitute for the living whole from which it is extracted. But viewed teleologically or practically, it represents the only way in which one experience can be made of any value for another—the only way in which something enlightening can be secured. What is called false or vicious abstractionism signifies that the function of the detached fragment is forgotten and neglected, so that it is esteemed barely in itself as something of a higher order than the muddy and irregular concrete from which it was wrenched. Looked at functionally, not structurally and statically, abstraction means that something has been released from one experience for transfer to another. Abstraction is liberation. The more theoretical, the more abstract, an abstraction, or the farther away it is from anything experienced in its concreteness, the better fitted it is to deal with any one of the indefinite variety of things that may later present themselves. Ancient mathematics and physics were much nearer the gross concrete experience than are modern. For that very reason they were[Pg 151] more impotent in affording any insight into and control over such concretes as present themselves in new and unexpected forms.
More clearly, abstraction is essential if one[Pg 150] experience is to be relevant to other experiences. Every concrete experience in its entirety is unique; it’s one-of-a-kind and cannot be replicated. When looked at in its full detail, it provides no instruction and offers no clarity. What we call abstraction means that a specific aspect is chosen to help understand something else. On its own, it’s a disjointed piece, a poor replacement for the living whole from which it comes. But when seen from a practical perspective, it represents the only way one experience can be useful for another—the only way to gain something enlightening. What’s termed false or harmful abstractionism means that the function of the separated piece is overlooked, leading it to be valued merely as a higher entity than the messy and irregular concrete from which it was taken. Viewed functionally instead of structure-wise and stagnantly, abstraction signifies that something has been taken from one experience to apply to another. Abstraction is freedom. The more theoretical and abstract an abstraction is, or the further it is from any concrete experience, the better it is suited to address any of the many things that may later arise. Ancient mathematics and physics were much closer to the raw concrete experience than the modern ones. For that reason, they were[Pg 151] less effective in providing insight into and control over concretes that appear in new and unexpected forms.
Abstraction and generalization have always been recognized as close kin. It may be said that they are the negative and positive sides of the same function. Abstraction sets free some factor so that it may be used. Generalization is the use. It carries over and extends. It is always in some sense a leap in the dark. It is an adventure. There can be no assurance in advance that what is extracted from one concrete can be fruitfully extended to another individual case. Since these other cases are individual and concrete they must be dissimilar. The trait of flying is detached from the concrete bird. This abstraction is then carried over to the bat, and it is expected in view of the application of the quality to have some of the other traits of the bird. This trivial instance indicates the essence of generalization, and also illustrates the riskiness of the proceeding. It transfers, extends, applies, a result of some former experience to the reception and interpretation of a new one. Deductive processes define, delimit, purify and set in order the conceptions through which this enriching and directive operation is carried on, but they cannot, however perfect, guarantee the outcome.
Abstraction and generalization have always been seen as closely related. You could say they represent the negative and positive sides of the same process. Abstraction frees up a factor so that it can be used, while generalization is the act of using it. It transfers and expands on ideas. There's always an element of uncertainty involved. It's like going on an adventure without knowing what to expect. You can't be sure that what you've taken from one specific example will apply successfully to another unique case. Since these other cases are distinct and specific, they must be different. The trait of flying is taken from a specific bird. This abstraction is then applied to a bat, with the assumption that it will share some of the bird’s other traits. This simple example highlights the essence of generalization and also shows the risks involved. It takes, extends, and applies knowledge from past experiences to understand and interpret something new. Deductive reasoning helps to clarify, define, and organize the ideas involved in this enriching and guiding process, but even the most refined methods can’t guarantee the outcome.
The pragmatic value of organization is so conspicu[Pg 152]ously enforced in contemporary life that it hardly seems necessary to dwell upon the instrumental significance of classification and systematization. When the existence of qualitative and fixed species was denied to be the supreme object of knowledge, classification was often regarded, especially by the empirical school, as merely a linguistic device. It was convenient for memory and communication to have words that sum up a number of particulars. Classes were supposed to exist only in speech. Later, ideas were recognized as a kind of tertium quid between things and words. Classes were allowed to exist in the mind as purely mental things. The critical disposition of empiricism is well exemplified here. To assign any objectivity to classes was to encourage a belief in eternal species and occult essences and to strengthen the arms of a decadent and obnoxious science—a point of view well illustrated in Locke. General ideas are useful in economizing effort, enabling us to condense particular experiences into simpler and more easily carried bunches and making it easier to identify new observations.
The practical importance of organization is so clearly emphasized in modern life that it hardly seems necessary to talk about the essential role of classification and systematization. When the existence of distinct and fixed categories was seen as the ultimate goal of knowledge, classification was often viewed, especially by the empirical school, as just a tool for language. It was helpful for memory and communication to have terms that encapsulate several details. Categories were thought to exist only in speech. Eventually, ideas were acknowledged as a kind of tertium quid between things and words. Classes were accepted to exist in the mind as purely mental constructs. The critical nature of empiricism is well demonstrated here. Assigning any objectivity to classes was seen as promoting a belief in eternal categories and hidden essences, reinforcing the grip of a declining and troublesome science—a perspective clearly illustrated in Locke. General ideas are helpful in saving effort, allowing us to condense specific experiences into simpler, more manageable concepts and making it easier to recognize new observations.
So far nominalism and conceptualism—the theory that kinds exist only in words or in ideas—was on the right track. It emphasized the teleological character of systems and classifications, that they exist for the sake of economy and efficiency in reaching ends. But this truth was perverted into a false notion, because[Pg 153] the active and doing side of experience was denied or ignored. Concrete things have ways of acting, as many ways of acting as they have points of interaction with other things. One thing is callous, unresponsive, inert in the presence of some other things; it is alert, eager, and on the aggressive with respect to other things; in a third case, it is receptive, docile. Now different ways of behaving, in spite of their endless diversity, may be classed together in view of common relationship to an end. No sensible person tries to do everything. He has certain main interests and leading aims by which he makes his behavior coherent and effective. To have an aim is to limit, select, concentrate, group. Thus a basis is furnished for selecting and organizing things according as their ways of acting are related to carrying forward pursuit. Cherry trees will be differently grouped by woodworkers, orchardists, artists, scientists and merry-makers. To the execution of different purposes different ways of acting and reacting on the part of trees are important. Each classification may be equally sound when the difference of ends is borne in mind.
So far, nominalism and conceptualism—the idea that categories only exist in words or thoughts—were on the right path. They highlighted the purposeful nature of systems and classifications, showing that they exist for the sake of efficiency and effectiveness in achieving goals. However, this truth was twisted into a false concept because[Pg 153] the active and practical side of experience was either denied or overlooked. Concrete things have ways of acting, with as many behavioral ways as they have points of interaction with other things. One thing can be detached, unresponsive, and passive in the presence of some objects; it can be alert, eager, and aggressive towards others; or it can be open and compliant in another situation. Now, different behaviors, despite their endless variety, can be grouped together based on their common relation to an objective. No reasonable person tries to accomplish everything. They have specific main interests and key goals that help them make their actions coherent and effective. Having a goal means limiting, selecting, concentrating, and grouping. This provides a foundation for choosing and organizing things according to how their actions relate to achieving those goals. Cherry trees will be categorized differently by woodworkers, orchardists, artists, scientists, and party-goers. Different ends require different ways of acting and responding from the trees. Each classification can be equally valid if we keep in mind the difference in objectives.
Nevertheless there is a genuine objective standard for the goodness of special classifications. One will further the cabinetmaker in reaching his end while another will hamper him. One classification will assist the botanist in carrying on fruitfully his work of inquiry, and an[Pg 154]other will retard and confuse him. The teleological theory of classification does not therefore commit us to the notion that classes are purely verbal or purely mental. Organization is no more merely nominal or mental in any art, including the art of inquiry, than it is in a department store or railway system. The necessity of execution supplies objective criteria. Things have to be sorted out and arranged so that their grouping will promote successful action for ends. Convenience, economy and efficiency are the bases of classification, but these things are not restricted to verbal communication with others nor to inner consciousness; they concern objective action. They must take effect in the world.
Nevertheless, there is a real objective standard for the value of specific classifications. Some will help the cabinetmaker achieve his goals, while others will hinder him. One classification will support the botanist in effectively conducting his research, and another will slow him down and confuse him. The teleological theory of classification doesn’t mean that classes are just words or just in our heads. Organization isn’t just a matter of naming or mental concepts in any field, including the field of inquiry, any more than it is in a department store or a railway system. The need for execution provides objective criteria. Things need to be sorted and arranged so that their grouping encourages successful actions towards specific goals. Convenience, economy, and efficiency are the foundations of classification, but these aren’t limited to just communicating verbally with others or to our inner thoughts; they involve objective actions. They must have real effects in the world.
At the same time, a classification is not a bare transcript or duplicate of some finished and done-for arrangement pre-existing in nature. It is rather a repertory of weapons for attack upon the future and the unknown. For success, the details of past knowledge must be reduced from bare facts to meanings, the fewer, simpler and more extensive the better. They must be broad enough in scope to prepare inquiry to cope with any phenomenon however unexpected. They must be arranged so as not to overlap, for otherwise when they are applied to new events they interfere and produce confusion. In order that there may be ease and economy of movement in dealing with the[Pg 155] enormous diversity of occurrences that present themselves, we must be able to move promptly and definitely from one tool of attack to another. In other words, our various classes and kinds must be themselves classified in graded series from the larger to the more specific. There must not only be streets, but the streets must be laid out with reference to facilitating passage from any one to any other. Classification transforms a wilderness of by-ways in experience into a well-ordered system of roads, promoting transportation and communication in inquiry. As soon as men begin to take foresight for the future and to prepare themselves in advance to meet it effectively and prosperously, the deductive operations and their results gain in importance. In every practical enterprise there are goods to be produced, and whatever eliminates wasted material and promotes economy and efficiency of production is precious.
At the same time, a classification isn't just a simple copy or replica of some existing arrangement in nature. It’s more like a toolkit for tackling the future and the unknown. To succeed, the details of past knowledge need to be simplified from mere facts to meaningful insights, with fewer, simpler, and broader concepts being preferable. They should be comprehensive enough to help us deal with any unexpected phenomenon. They need to be organized to avoid overlap, because if they do overlap when faced with new situations, they can create confusion. To ensure smooth and efficient navigation through the vast array of events that come our way, we must be able to switch easily and clearly from one tool to another. In other words, our different categories must be structured in a hierarchy from the general to the specific. There not only need to be pathways, but those pathways must be designed to make movement from one to another easy. Classification turns a chaotic collection of experiences into a well-organized system of routes, enhancing travel and communication in our inquiries. As soon as people start planning for the future and preparing in advance to address it effectively and successfully, the deductive processes and their outcomes become more important. In every practical endeavor, there are goods to produce, and anything that reduces waste and boosts the efficiency of production is invaluable.
Little time is left to speak of the account of the nature of truth given by the experimental and functional type of logic. This is less to be regretted because this account is completely a corollary from the nature of thinking and ideas. If the view held as to the latter is understood, the conception of truth follows as a matter of course. If it be not understood, any attempt to present the theory of truth is bound to be confusing, and the theory itself to seem arbi[Pg 156]trary and absurd. If ideas, meanings, conceptions, notions, theories, systems are instrumental to an active reorganization of the given environment, to a removal of some specific trouble and perplexity, then the test of their validity and value lies in accomplishing this work. If they succeed in their office, they are reliable, sound, valid, good, true. If they fail to clear up confusion, to eliminate defects, if they increase confusion, uncertainty and evil when they are acted upon, then are they false. Confirmation, corroboration, verification lie in works, consequences. Handsome is that handsome does. By their fruits shall ye know them. That which guides us truly is true—demonstrated capacity for such guidance is precisely what is meant by truth. The adverb "truly" is more fundamental than either the adjective, true, or the noun, truth. An adverb expresses a way, a mode of acting. Now an idea or conception is a claim or injunction or plan to act in a certain way as the way to arrive at the clearing up of a specific situation. When the claim or pretension or plan is acted upon it guides us truly or falsely; it leads us to our end or away from it. Its active, dynamic function is the all-important thing about it, and in the quality of activity induced by it lies all its truth and falsity. The hypothesis that works is the true one; and truth is an abstract noun applied to the collection of cases, actual, foreseen and desired, that[Pg 157] receive confirmation in their works and consequences.
There's little time left to discuss the way experimental and functional logic defines truth. This isn't too regrettable since this definition is simply a result of understanding thinking and ideas. If we grasp the latter, the concept of truth logically follows. If we don't understand it, trying to explain the theory of truth will likely be confusing, making the theory itself appear arbitrary and nonsensical. If ideas, meanings, concepts, theories, and systems help actively reorganize our environment to resolve specific problems and confusion, their validity and value depend on their effectiveness in doing this. If they succeed, they are reliable, sound, valid, and true. If they fail to clarify confusion, eliminate issues, or if they lead to more uncertainty and harm, then they are false. Confirmation, support, and verification come from their outcomes and consequences. Actions speak louder than words. You will know them by their results. What truly guides us is true—showing the ability to provide such guidance is exactly what we mean by truth. The adverb "truly" is more fundamental than the adjective "true" or the noun "truth." An adverb indicates a manner or way of acting. An idea or concept is essentially a proposal or plan to act in a certain way to resolve a specific situation. When this proposal is acted upon, it can guide us correctly or incorrectly; it can lead us towards our goal or away from it. Its active, dynamic role is what matters most, and its truth or falsehood lies in the quality of the actions it inspires. The hypothesis that works is the true one; truth is an abstract term applied to the collection of cases—actual, expected, and desired—that receive validation through their outcomes and consequences.
So wholly does the worth of this conception of truth depend upon the correctness of the prior account of thinking that it is more profitable to consider why the conception gives offence than to expound it on its own account. Part of the reason why it has been found so obnoxious is doubtless its novelty and defects in its statement. Too often, for example, when truth has been thought of as satisfaction, it has been thought of as merely emotional satisfaction, a private comfort, a meeting of purely personal need. But the satisfaction in question means a satisfaction of the needs and conditions of the problem out of which the idea, the purpose and method of action, arises. It includes public and objective conditions. It is not to be manipulated by whim or personal idiosyncrasy. Again when truth is defined as utility, it is often thought to mean utility for some purely personal end, some profit upon which a particular individual has set his heart. So repulsive is a conception of truth which makes it a mere tool of private ambition and aggrandizement, that the wonder is that critics have attributed such a notion to sane men. As matter of fact, truth as utility means service in making just that contribution to reorganization in experience that the idea or theory claims to be able to make. The usefulness[Pg 158] of a road is not measured by the degree in which it lends itself to the purposes of a highwayman. It is measured by whether it actually functions as a road, as a means of easy and effective public transportation and communication. And so with the serviceableness of an idea or hypothesis as a measure of its truth.
The value of this idea of truth relies heavily on the accuracy of the earlier explanation of thinking, making it more useful to explore why the idea offends rather than to explain it on its own merits. Part of the reason it’s been seen as so problematic is likely due to its novelty and shortcomings in its presentation. For instance, when truth is viewed as satisfaction, it’s often considered just emotional satisfaction, a personal comfort, or fulfilling individual needs. However, the satisfaction in question refers to meeting the needs and conditions of the problem that gave rise to the idea, purpose, and method of action. It incorporates public and objective conditions. It shouldn’t be swayed by personal whims or quirks. Similarly, when truth is defined as utility, it’s frequently misunderstood as being beneficial only for individual gain, something that serves a particular person’s interests. The idea that truth could be just a tool for private ambition is so unappealing that it’s surprising critics have ascribed such a notion to rational people. In reality, truth as utility signifies its role in contributing to restructuring experiences, just as the idea or theory claims. The effectiveness[Pg 158] of a road isn’t gauged by how well it serves a highwayman’s goals; rather, it’s based on whether it actually works as a road, enabling easy and efficient public transportation and communication. The same principle applies to the usefulness of an idea or hypothesis as a standard for its truth.
Turning from such rather superficial misunderstandings, we find, I think, the chief obstacle to the reception of this notion of truth in an inheritance from the classic tradition that has become so deeply engrained in men's minds. In just the degree in which existence is divided into two realms, a higher one of perfect being and a lower one of seeming, phenomenal, deficient reality, truth and falsity are thought of as fixed, ready-made static properties of things themselves. Supreme Reality is true Being, inferior and imperfect Reality is false Being. It makes claims to Reality which it cannot substantiate. It is deceitful, fraudulent, inherently unworthy of trust and belief. Beliefs are false not because they mislead us; they are not mistaken ways of thinking. They are false because they admit and adhere to false existences or subsistences. Other notions are true because they do have to do with true Being—with full and ultimate Reality. Such a notion lies at the back of the head of every one who has, in however an indirect way, been a recipient of the ancient and medieval tradition. This view is radically challenged by[Pg 159] the pragmatic conception of truth, and the impossibility of reconciliation or compromise is, I think, the cause of the shock occasioned by the newer theory.
Turning away from these rather superficial misunderstandings, we find, I believe, the main obstacle to accepting this idea of truth lies in an inheritance from the classic tradition that has become deeply ingrained in people's minds. To the extent that existence is divided into two realms—a higher one of perfect being and a lower one of seeming, phenomenal, imperfect reality—truth and falsity are seen as fixed, ready-made, static qualities of things themselves. Supreme Reality is true Being, while inferior and imperfect Reality is false Being. It makes claims to Reality that it cannot back up. It is deceitful, fraudulent, and inherently unworthy of trust and belief. Beliefs are false not because they mislead us; they are not mistaken ways of thinking. They are false because they accept and cling to false existences or existences that don't hold true. Other beliefs are true because they pertain to true Being—full and ultimate Reality. This notion exists in the minds of everyone who has, in any indirect way, absorbed the ancient and medieval tradition. This perspective is fundamentally challenged by[Pg 159] the pragmatic view of truth, and the inability to reconcile or compromise is, I believe, what causes the shock brought about by the newer theory.
This contrast, however, constitutes the importance of the new theory as well as the unconscious obstruction to its acceptance. The older conception worked out practically to identify truth with authoritative dogma. A society that chiefly esteems order, that finds growth painful and change disturbing, inevitably seeks for a fixed body of superior truths upon which it may depend. It looks backward, to something already in existence, for the source and sanction of truth. It falls back upon what is antecedent, prior, original, a priori, for assurance. The thought of looking ahead, toward the eventual, toward consequences, creates uneasiness and fear. It disturbs the sense of rest that is attached to the ideas of fixed Truth already in existence. It puts a heavy burden of responsibility upon us for search, unremitting observation, scrupulous development of hypotheses and thoroughgoing testing. In physical matters men have slowly grown accustomed in all specific beliefs to identifying the true with the verified. But they still hesitate to recognize the implication of this identification and to derive the definition of truth from it. For while it is nominally agreed upon as a commonplace that definitions ought to spring from concrete and specific cases rather than be invented in the[Pg 160] empty air and imposed upon particulars, there is a strange unwillingness to act upon the maxim in defining truth. To generalize the recognition that the true means the verified and means nothing else places upon men the responsibility for surrendering political and moral dogmas, and subjecting to the test of consequences their most cherished prejudices. Such a change involves a great change in the seat of authority and the methods of decision in society. Some of them, as first fruits of the newer logic, will be considered in the following lectures.
This contrast highlights both the significance of the new theory and the unconscious resistance to its acceptance. The older viewpoint practically equated truth with established authority. A society that mainly values order, finds growth uncomfortable, and sees change as unsettling, naturally looks for a solid set of superior truths to rely on. It turns to what already exists for the source and validation of truth. It depends on what is prior, original, a priori, for reassurance. The idea of looking forward, towards the eventual and the consequences, brings about anxiety and fear. It disrupts the sense of stability tied to the concepts of fixed Truth that are already in place. It places a significant burden of responsibility on us to search, observe continuously, develop hypotheses meticulously, and conduct thorough testing. In physical matters, people have gradually gotten used to associating truth with what has been verified in all specific beliefs. However, they still hesitate to acknowledge the implications of this association and derive a definition of truth from it. Although it's generally accepted that definitions should come from concrete and specific cases rather than being created out of thin air and imposed on particular instances, there is a strange reluctance to apply this principle when defining truth. Recognizing that the true means the verified and nothing else places the responsibility on individuals to abandon political and moral doctrines and to subject their most cherished biases to the test of consequences. Such a shift represents a major transformation in the sources of authority and the methods of decision-making in society. Some of these, as initial outcomes of the new logic, will be discussed in the following lectures.
CHAPTER VII
RECONSTRUCTION IN MORAL CONCEPTIONS
The impact of the alteration in methods of scientific thinking upon moral ideas is, in general, obvious. Goods, ends are multiplied. Rules are softened into principles, and principles are modified into methods of understanding. Ethical theory began among the Greeks as an attempt to find a regulation for the conduct of life which should have a rational basis and purpose instead of being derived from custom. But reason as a substitute for custom was under the obligation of supplying objects and laws as fixed as those of custom had been. Ethical theory ever since has been singularly hypnotized by the notion that its business is to discover some final end or good or some ultimate and supreme law. This is the common element among the diversity of theories. Some have held that the end is loyalty or obedience to a higher power or authority; and they have variously found this higher principle in Divine Will, the will of the secular ruler, the maintenance of institutions in which the purpose of superiors is embodied, and the rational consciousness of duty. But they have differed from one another because there was[Pg 162] one point in which they were agreed: a single and final source of law. Others have asserted that it is impossible to locate morality in conformity to law-giving power, and that it must be sought in ends that are goods. And some have sought the good in self-realization, some in holiness, some in happiness, some in the greatest possible aggregate of pleasures. And yet these schools have agreed in the assumption that there is a single, fixed and final good. They have been able to dispute with one another only because of their common premise.
The effect of changes in scientific thinking on moral ideas is, for the most part, clear. Values and goals have multiplied. Rules have shifted into principles, and principles have adapted into methods of understanding. Ethical theory originated with the Greeks as an effort to establish a guideline for living that would be based on reason and purpose instead of tradition. However, using reason as a substitute for tradition had to provide objects and laws that were as solid as those established by custom. Since then, ethical theory has been notably fixated on the idea of discovering a final goal or good or some ultimate law. This is the common thread among the range of theories. Some have argued that the goal is loyalty or obedience to a higher power or authority; they have found this higher principle in divine will, the will of the secular leader, the preservation of institutions that reflect the aims of those in charge, and the rational awareness of duty. Yet they have disagreed because there was[Pg 162] one point they shared: a single and ultimate source of law. Others have claimed that it is impossible to base morality on the authority of law, arguing instead that it must be found in goals that are good. Some have searched for the good in self-fulfillment, others in holiness, some in happiness, and some in maximizing overall pleasure. Still, these groups have aligned in the assumption that there exists a single, fixed, and ultimate good. Their debates have been possible only because of this shared premise.
The question arises whether the way out of the confusion and conflict is not to go to the root of the matter by questioning this common element. Is not the belief in the single, final and ultimate (whether conceived as good or as authoritative law) an intellectual product of that feudal organization which is disappearing historically and of that belief in a bounded, ordered cosmos, wherein rest is higher than motion, which has disappeared from natural science? It has been repeatedly suggested that the present limit of intellectual reconstruction lies in the fact that it has not as yet been seriously applied in the moral and social disciplines. Would not this further application demand precisely that we advance to a belief in a plurality of changing, moving, individualized goods and ends, and to a belief that principles, criteria, laws are intellectual[Pg 163] instruments for analyzing individual or unique situations?
The question comes up whether the way to resolve the confusion and conflict is to get to the root of the issue by questioning this common factor. Isn’t the belief in a single, ultimate truth (whether seen as good or as an authoritative law) an idea stemming from a feudal system that is historically fading, and from the belief in a limited, ordered universe, where rest is valued more than motion, which has vanished from modern science? It has been suggested multiple times that the current limits of intellectual progress come from the fact that it hasn't been seriously applied in moral and social fields yet. Wouldn't applying this further require us to embrace the idea of multiple, changing, individual goods and goals, as well as to see principles, criteria, and laws as intellectual[Pg 163] tools for analyzing specific or unique situations?
The blunt assertion that every moral situation is a unique situation having its own irreplaceable good may seem not merely blunt but preposterous. For the established tradition teaches that it is precisely the irregularity of special cases which makes necessary the guidance of conduct by universals, and that the essence of the virtuous disposition is willingness to subordinate every particular case to adjudication by a fixed principle. It would then follow that submission of a generic end and law to determination by the concrete situation entails complete confusion and unrestrained licentiousness. Let us, however, follow the pragmatic rule, and in order to discover the meaning of the idea ask for its consequences. Then it surprisingly turns out that the primary significance of the unique and morally ultimate character of the concrete situation is to transfer the weight and burden of morality to intelligence. It does not destroy responsibility; it only locates it. A moral situation is one in which judgment and choice are required antecedently to overt action. The practical meaning of the situation—that is to say the action needed to satisfy it—is not self-evident. It has to be searched for. There are conflicting desires and alternative apparent goods. What is needed is to find the right course of action, the right[Pg 164] good. Hence, inquiry is exacted: observation of the detailed makeup of the situation; analysis into its diverse factors; clarification of what is obscure; discounting of the more insistent and vivid traits; tracing the consequences of the various modes of action that suggest themselves; regarding the decision reached as hypothetical and tentative until the anticipated or supposed consequences which led to its adoption have been squared with actual consequences. This inquiry is intelligence. Our moral failures go back to some weakness of disposition, some absence of sympathy, some one-sided bias that makes us perform the judgment of the concrete case carelessly or perversely. Wide sympathy, keen sensitiveness, persistence in the face of the disagreeable, balance of interests enabling us to undertake the work of analysis and decision intelligently are the distinctively moral traits—the virtues or moral excellencies.
The straightforward claim that every moral situation is unique and has its own irreplaceable good might seem not just direct but also ridiculous. The established tradition argues that it's exactly the uniqueness of specific cases that makes it necessary to guide behavior by universal principles, and that a virtuous attitude is about being willing to submit each specific case to judgment by a fixed principle. Thus, it would seem that submitting a general goal and law to evaluation by a specific circumstance leads to total chaos and uncontrolled behavior. However, if we apply the pragmatic approach and seek the implications of this idea, we surprisingly find that the main significance of the unique and morally ultimate nature of the concrete situation shifts the weight and responsibility of morality to intelligence. It doesn’t eliminate responsibility; it just places it where it belongs. A moral situation requires judgment and choice before any action is taken. The practical meaning of that situation—what action is needed to address it—is not obvious. It has to be uncovered. There are conflicting desires and seemingly different goods. What’s necessary is to determine the right course of action, the right[Pg 164] good. Therefore, a thorough inquiry is essential: observing the details of the situation, analyzing its various components, clarifying any ambiguities, setting aside the more compelling and vivid aspects, tracing the potential outcomes of the various suggested actions, and treating the conclusion reached as hypothetical and tentative until the expected or assumed results that prompted it are aligned with the actual outcomes. This inquiry represents intelligence. Our moral failures stem from some weakness in our character, a lack of empathy, or a one-sided bias that leads us to judge the concrete case carelessly or wrongly. Broad empathy, strong sensitivity, persistence when faced with discomfort, and a balance of interests that allow us to analyze and decide intelligently are the core moral qualities—the virtues or moral excellencies.
It is worth noting once more that the underlying issue is, after all, only the same as that which has been already threshed out in physical inquiry. There too it long seemed as if rational assurance and demonstration could be attained only if we began with universal conceptions and subsumed particular cases under them. The men who initiated the methods of inquiry that are now everywhere adopted were denounced in their day (and sincerely) as subverters of truth and foes of[Pg 165] science. If they have won in the end, it is because, as has already been pointed out, the method of universals confirmed prejudices and sanctioned ideas that had gained currency irrespective of evidence for them; while placing the initial and final weight upon the individual case, stimulated painstaking inquiry into facts and examination of principles. In the end, loss of eternal truths was more than compensated for in the accession of quotidian facts. The loss of the system of superior and fixed definitions and kinds was more than made up for by the growing system of hypotheses and laws used in classifying facts. After all, then, we are only pleading for the adoption in moral reflection of the logic that has been proved to make for security, stringency and fertility in passing judgments upon physical phenomena. And the reason is the same. The old method in spite of its nominal and esthetic worship of reason discouraged reason, because it hindered the operation of scrupulous and unremitting inquiry.
It’s important to point out again that the core issue is really the same as what has already been explored in physical research. It also seemed for a long time that we could only achieve rational certainty and proof by starting with universal concepts and then fitting specific cases into those. The individuals who pioneered the inquiry methods that are now widely accepted were condemned in their time (and genuinely) as destroyers of truth and enemies of[Pg 165] science. If they ultimately succeeded, it’s because, as previously mentioned, the method of universals affirmed biases and legitimized ideas that were accepted without evidence; while focusing on individual cases prompted thorough investigation into facts and analysis of principles. In the end, the loss of timeless truths was more than balanced by the addition of everyday facts. The disappearance of a system of superior and fixed definitions and categories was more than compensated for by the expanding system of hypotheses and laws used to classify facts. So, we are essentially advocating for the application of the logic that has been shown to ensure reliability, rigor, and growth in making judgments about physical phenomena in moral reflection. The reason is unchanged. The old method, despite its apparent reverence for reason, actually stifled it because it obstructed thorough and relentless inquiry.
More definitely, the transfer of the burden of the moral life from following rules or pursuing fixed ends over to the detection of the ills that need remedy in a special case and the formation of plans and methods for dealing with them, eliminates the causes which have kept moral theory controversial, and which have also kept it remote from helpful contact with the exigencies[Pg 166] of practice. The theory of fixed ends inevitably leads thought into the bog of disputes that cannot be settled. If there is one summum bonum, one supreme end, what is it? To consider this problem is to place ourselves in the midst of controversies that are as acute now as they were two thousand years ago. Suppose we take a seemingly more empirical view, and say that while there is not a single end, there also are not as many as there are specific situations that require amelioration; but there are a number of such natural goods as health, wealth, honor or good name, friendship, esthetic appreciation, learning and such moral goods as justice, temperance, benevolence, etc. What or who is to decide the right of way when these ends conflict with one another, as they are sure to do? Shall we resort to the method that once brought such disrepute upon the whole business of ethics: Casuistry? Or shall we have recourse to what Bentham well called the ipse dixit method: the arbitrary preference of this or that person for this or that end? Or shall we be forced to arrange them all in an order of degrees from the highest good down to the least precious? Again we find ourselves in the middle of unreconciled disputes with no indication of the way out.
More specifically, shifting the focus of moral life from following rules or pursuing fixed goals to identifying specific problems that need fixing and creating plans and methods to address them removes the issues that have made moral theory controversial and distant from practical application. The theory of fixed goals inevitably leads to complicated disputes that can’t be resolved. If there is one supreme good, what is it? Considering this question places us in the middle of arguments that are just as intense now as they were two thousand years ago. Let’s take a more practical approach and say that while there isn’t a single goal, there aren’t as many as there are specific situations needing a solution. Instead, we can recognize several natural goods like health, wealth, honor, friendship, aesthetic appreciation, learning, and moral goods like justice, temperance, and benevolence. Who or what decides what takes priority when these goals conflict, which they surely will? Should we go back to the method that once discredited the whole field of ethics: Casuistry? Or revert to what Bentham aptly labeled the ipse dixit method: the arbitrary preference of one person over another regarding a specific goal? Or do we have to rank them all from the highest good to the lowest? Once again, we find ourselves in the midst of unresolved disputes with no clear way out.
Meantime, the special moral perplexities where the aid of intelligence is required go unenlightened. We cannot seek or attain health, wealth, learning, justice[Pg 167] or kindness in general. Action is always specific, concrete, individualized, unique. And consequently judgments as to acts to be performed must be similarly specific. To say that a man seeks health or justice is only to say that he seeks to live healthily or justly. These things, like truth, are adverbial. They are modifiers of action in special cases. How to live healthily or justly is a matter which differs with every person. It varies with his past experience, his opportunities, his temperamental and acquired weaknesses and abilities. Not man in general but a particular man suffering from some particular disability aims to live healthily, and consequently health cannot mean for him exactly what it means for any other mortal. Healthy living is not something to be attained by itself apart from other ways of living. A man needs to be healthy in his life, not apart from it, and what does life mean except the aggregate of his pursuits and activities? A man who aims at health as a distinct end becomes a valetudinarian, or a fanatic, or a mechanical performer of exercises, or an athlete so one-sided that his pursuit of bodily development injures his heart. When the endeavor to realize a so-called end does not temper and color all other activities, life is portioned out into strips and fractions. Certain acts and times are devoted to getting health, others to cultivating religion, others to seeking learning, to being a good citizen, a devotee of fine art[Pg 168] and so on. This is the only logical alternative to subordinating all aims to the accomplishment of one alone—fanaticism. This is out of fashion at present, but who can say how much of distraction and dissipation in life, and how much of its hard and narrow rigidity is the outcome of men's failure to realize that each situation has its own unique end and that the whole personality should be concerned with it? Surely, once more, what a man needs is to live healthily, and this result so affects all the activities of his life that it cannot be set up as a separate and independent good.
Meanwhile, the particular moral dilemmas that require intelligence remain unaddressed. We can’t pursue or achieve health, wealth, knowledge, justice[Pg 167], or kindness in general. Actions are always specific, concrete, individualized, and unique. Therefore, judgments about the actions to be taken must also be specific. Saying that someone seeks health or justice simply means they want to live healthily or justly. These concepts, like truth, are adverbial. They modify actions in specific situations. How to live healthily or justly varies for each person, depending on their past experiences, opportunities, and personal strengths and weaknesses. It’s not mankind in general that aims for health, but an individual man dealing with a particular challenge, and thus health can’t mean the same for him as it does for someone else. Healthy living isn’t something that can be achieved in isolation from other ways of living. A person needs to be healthy within his life, not separate from it, and what does life mean if not the totality of his pursuits and activities? A man who targets health as a distinct goal risks becoming overly concerned with it, turning into a health fanatic, a robotic exercise performer, or an athlete so focused on physical fitness that he neglects other important areas. When the effort to achieve a so-called goal doesn’t blend with all other activities, life gets divided into segments. Some times and efforts go into achieving health, others into nurturing spirituality, pursuing education, being a good citizen, or appreciating fine art[Pg 168], and so on. This is the only logical alternative to prioritizing one aim above all others—fanaticism. While that’s out of style now, who can say how much distraction and rigidity in life results from people not realizing that each situation has its own unique goal and that the entire personality should be engaged with it? Ultimately, what a person really needs is to live healthily, and this goal impacts all of his life's activities so profoundly that it can't be considered a separate and independent good.
Nevertheless the general notions of health, disease, justice, artistic culture are of great importance: Not, however, because this or that case may be brought exhaustively under a single head and its specific traits shut out, but because generalized science provides a man as physician and artist and citizen, with questions to ask, investigations to make, and enables him to understand the meaning of what he sees. Just in the degree in which a physician is an artist in his work he uses his science, no matter how extensive and accurate, to furnish him with tools of inquiry into the individual case, and with methods of forecasting a method of dealing with it. Just in the degree in which, no matter how great his learning, he subordinates the individual case to some classification of diseases and some generic rule of treatment, he sinks to the level of the routine[Pg 169] mechanic. His intelligence and his action become rigid, dogmatic, instead of free and flexible.
Nevertheless, the general ideas about health, illness, justice, and artistic culture are really important. Not because every situation can be completely categorized under one heading and its specific features ignored, but because broader knowledge gives a person—whether a doctor, artist, or citizen—questions to ask, research to conduct, and helps them understand what they observe. The more a doctor approaches their work as an artist, the more they use their knowledge, no matter how extensive and precise, as tools to investigate individual cases and to develop methods for addressing them. Conversely, if they rely too much on classifying diseases and applying generic treatment rules, no matter how learned they are, they become like a routine mechanic. Their thinking and actions become rigid and dogmatic instead of being free and adaptable.[Pg 169]
Moral goods and ends exist only when something has to be done. The fact that something has to be done proves that there are deficiencies, evils in the existent situation. This ill is just the specific ill that it is. It never is an exact duplicate of anything else. Consequently the good of the situation has to be discovered, projected and attained on the basis of the exact defect and trouble to be rectified. It cannot intelligently be injected into the situation from without. Yet it is the part of wisdom to compare different cases, to gather together the ills from which humanity suffers, and to generalize the corresponding goods into classes. Health, wealth, industry, temperance, amiability, courtesy, learning, esthetic capacity, initiative, courage, patience, enterprise, thoroughness and a multitude of other generalized ends are acknowledged as goods. But the value of this systematization is intellectual or analytic. Classifications suggest possible traits to be on the lookout for in studying a particular case; they suggest methods of action to be tried in removing the inferred causes of ill. They are tools of insight; their value is in promoting an individualized response in the individual situation.
Moral goods and goals only exist when there’s something that needs to be done. The necessity for action shows that there are shortcomings or evils in the current situation. This problem is unique and specific to itself; it’s never exactly like anything else. Therefore, the good that can be achieved must be identified, envisioned, and pursued based on the exact issue that needs fixing. It can’t just be imposed from the outside. However, it is wise to compare different situations, to compile the various problems that humanity faces, and to categorize the corresponding goods into groups. Health, wealth, hard work, moderation, kindness, politeness, knowledge, artistic ability, initiative, bravery, patience, entrepreneurship, thoroughness, and many other generalized goals are recognized as goods. But the value of this classification is intellectual or analytical. Classifications suggest potential traits to monitor when examining a specific case; they propose action methods to try in addressing the identified causes of problems. They serve as tools for understanding; their value lies in encouraging a tailored response to each individual situation.
Morals is not a catalogue of acts nor a set of rules to be applied like drugstore prescriptions or cook-book[Pg 170] recipes. The need in morals is for specific methods of inquiry and of contrivance: Methods of inquiry to locate difficulties and evils; methods of contrivance to form plans to be used as working hypotheses in dealing with them. And the pragmatic import of the logic of individualized situations, each having its own irreplaceable good and principle, is to transfer the attention of theory from preoccupation with general conceptions to the problem of developing effective methods of inquiry.
Morals aren’t just a list of actions or a set of rules to follow like pharmacy prescriptions or cookbooks[Pg 170]. What we need in morals are specific ways to explore and come up with solutions: ways to investigate problems and wrongs, and ways to create plans that can be used as working hypotheses to address them. The practical significance of the logic behind individual situations, each with its own unique good and principle, is to shift the focus of theory from being overly concerned with general ideas to figuring out how to develop effective methods of investigation.
Two ethical consequences of great moment should be remarked. The belief in fixed values has bred a division of ends into intrinsic and instrumental, of those that are really worth while in themselves and those that are of importance only as means to intrinsic goods. Indeed, it is often thought to be the very beginning of wisdom, of moral discrimination, to make this distinction. Dialectically, the distinction is interesting and seems harmless. But carried into practice it has an import that is tragic. Historically, it has been the source and justification of a hard and fast difference between ideal goods on one side and material goods on the other. At present those who would be liberal conceive intrinsic goods as esthetic in nature rather than as exclusively religious or as intellectually contemplative. But the effect is the same. So-called intrinsic goods, whether religious or esthetic, are divorced from those interests[Pg 171] of daily life which because of their constancy and urgency form the preoccupation of the great mass. Aristotle used this distinction to declare that slaves and the working class though they are necessary for the state—the commonweal—are not constituents of it. That which is regarded as merely instrumental must approach drudgery; it cannot command either intellectual, artistic or moral attention and respect. Anything becomes unworthy whenever it is thought of as intrinsically lacking worth. So men of "ideal" interests have chosen for the most part the way of neglect and escape. The urgency and pressure of "lower" ends have been covered up by polite conventions. Or, they have been relegated to a baser class of mortals in order that the few might be free to attend to the goods that are really or intrinsically worth while. This withdrawal, in the name of higher ends, has left, for mankind at large and especially for energetic "practical" people the lower activities in complete command.
Two important ethical consequences should be noted. The belief in fixed values has led to a split between intrinsic and instrumental ends—those that are truly valuable in themselves and those that matter only as a means to inherent goods. It’s often seen as a sign of true wisdom and moral discernment to make this distinction. While it might seem harmless when discussed theoretically, applying it in real life can have tragic implications. Historically, it has justified a strict divide between ideal goods on one side and material goods on the other. Nowadays, those who consider themselves progressive view intrinsic goods as primarily aesthetic, rather than only religious or intellectual. However, the impact remains the same. These so-called intrinsic goods, whether religious or aesthetic, are disconnected from the interests of everyday life, which, due to their constant and urgent nature, occupy the attention of the vast majority. Aristotle used this distinction to argue that while slaves and the working class are necessary for the state—the common good—they are not seen as integral to it. What is viewed as merely instrumental tends to be seen as a boring chore; it cannot earn intellectual, artistic, or moral attention and respect. Anything is considered unworthy when it is viewed as lacking intrinsic value. Consequently, individuals focused on "ideal" interests have mostly opted for neglect and avoidance. The urgency and demands of "lower" ends have been hidden under polite conventions or pushed onto a lower class of people so that a select few can focus on what is genuinely or intrinsically valuable. This retreat, in the name of higher purposes, has left the lower activities under complete control, especially for those energetic "practical" individuals.
No one can possibly estimate how much of the obnoxious materialism and brutality of our economic life is due to the fact that economic ends have been regarded as merely instrumental. When they are recognized to be as intrinsic and final in their place as any others, then it will be seen that they are capable of idealization, and that if life is to be worth while, they must acquire ideal and intrinsic value. Esthetic, re[Pg 172]ligious and other "ideal" ends are now thin and meagre or else idle and luxurious because of the separation from "instrumental" or economic ends. Only in connection with the latter can they be woven into the texture of daily life and made substantial and pervasive. The vanity and irresponsibility of values that are merely final and not also in turn means to the enrichment of other occupations of life ought to be obvious. But now the doctrine of "higher" ends gives aid, comfort and support to every socially isolated and socially irresponsible scholar, specialist, esthete and religionist. It protects the vanity and irresponsibility of his calling from observation by others and by himself. The moral deficiency of the calling is transformed into a cause of admiration and gratulation.
No one can really estimate how much of the annoying materialism and brutality in our economy comes from viewing economic goals as just tools. When we start to see them as having their own intrinsic value, just like any other goals, it will become clear that they can be idealized. For life to have meaning, these economic goals need to gain ideal and intrinsic value. Aesthetic, religious, and other "ideal" goals are currently thin and weak, or simply idle and luxurious, because they’re separated from economic goals. Only when connected to these economic ends can they be integrated into daily life and become significant and widespread. The emptiness and irresponsibility of values that are only seen as final, without also serving to enhance other aspects of life, should be obvious. But right now, the belief in "higher" goals supports and comforts every socially isolated and irresponsible scholar, specialist, artist, and religious person. It shields the emptiness and irresponsibility of their professions from scrutiny, both by others and themselves. The moral shortcomings of their work turn into a source of admiration and praise.
The other generic change lies in doing away once for all with the traditional distinction between moral goods, like the virtues, and natural goods like health, economic security, art, science and the like. The point of view under discussion is not the only one which has deplored this rigid distinction and endeavored to abolish it. Some schools have even gone so far as to regard moral excellencies, qualities of character as of value only because they promote natural goods. But the experimental logic when carried into morals makes every quality that is judged to be good according as it contributes to amelioration of existing ills. And in so doing, it[Pg 173] enforces the moral meaning of natural science. When all is said and done in criticism of present social deficiencies, one may well wonder whether the root difficulty does not lie in the separation of natural and moral science. When physics, chemistry, biology, medicine, contribute to the detection of concrete human woes and to the development of plans for remedying them and relieving the human estate, they become moral; they become part of the apparatus of moral inquiry or science. The latter then loses its peculiar flavor of the didactic and pedantic; its ultra-moralistic and hortatory tone. It loses its thinness and shrillness as well as its vagueness. It gains agencies that are efficacious. But the gain is not confined to the side of moral science. Natural science loses its divorce from humanity; it becomes itself humanistic in quality. It is something to be pursued not in a technical and specialized way for what is called truth for its own sake, but with the sense of its social bearing, its intellectual indispensableness. It is technical only in the sense that it provides the technique of social and moral engineering.
The other general change is to finally eliminate the traditional distinction between moral goods, like virtues, and natural goods such as health, economic security, art, science, and the like. The perspective being discussed isn’t the only one that has criticized this rigid distinction and tried to eliminate it. Some schools have even suggested that moral qualities are valuable only because they enhance natural goods. However, applying experimental logic to morals means that every quality deemed good is judged based on how it helps improve existing problems. In doing so, it[Pg 173] reinforces the moral significance of natural science. When considering the criticisms of current social issues, one might wonder if the main issue lies in the separation of natural and moral sciences. When physics, chemistry, biology, and medicine help identify real human problems and develop plans to address and alleviate them, they become moral; they become part of moral inquiry or science. This process removes the didactic and pedantic nature from moral science, along with its overly moralistic and preachy tone. It loses its thinness and harshness, along with its vagueness, and instead gains effective tools. But this benefit isn't limited to moral science. Natural science loses its separation from humanity; it becomes inherently humanistic. It should be pursued not in a purely technical and specialized manner for what is termed truth for its own sake, but with an awareness of its social implications and intellectual necessity. It is technical only in that it provides the means for social and moral engineering.
When the consciousness of science is fully impregnated with the consciousness of human value, the greatest dualism which now weighs humanity down, the split between the material, the mechanical, the scientific and the moral and ideal will be destroyed. Human forces that now waver because of this division will be[Pg 174] unified and reinforced. As long as ends are not thought of as individualized according to specific needs and opportunities, the mind will be content with abstractions, and the adequate stimulus to the moral or social use of natural science and historical data will be lacking. But when attention is concentrated upon the diversified concretes, recourse to all intellectual materials needed to clear up the special cases will be imperative. At the same time that morals are made to focus in intelligence, things intellectual are moralized. The vexatious and wasteful conflict between naturalism and humanism is terminated.
When the understanding of science is fully infused with the awareness of human value, the biggest divide that currently weighs down humanity—the gap between the material, mechanical, scientific, and the moral and ideal—will be eliminated. Human energies that now fluctuate because of this separation will be unified and strengthened. As long as goals aren't seen as individualized based on specific needs and opportunities, the mind will settle for abstract concepts, and there will be a lack of motivation for the moral or social application of natural science and historical data. However, when focus is directed towards the diverse specifics, accessing all the intellectual resources needed to clarify special cases will become essential. At the same time that morals are aligned with intelligence, intellectual pursuits will be moralized. The frustrating and wasteful conflict between naturalism and humanism will come to an end.
These general considerations may be amplified. First: Inquiry, discovery take the same place in morals that they have come to occupy in sciences of nature. Validation, demonstration become experimental, a matter of consequences. Reason, always an honorific term in ethics, becomes actualized in the methods by which the needs and conditions, the obstacles and resources, of situations are scrutinized in detail, and intelligent plans of improvement are worked out. Remote and abstract generalities promote jumping at conclusions, "anticipations of nature." Bad consequences are then deplored as due to natural perversity and untoward fate. But shifting the issue to analysis of a specific situation makes inquiry obligatory and alert observation of consequences imperative. No past decision nor[Pg 175] old principle can ever be wholly relied upon to justify a course of action. No amount of pains taken in forming a purpose in a definite case is final; the consequences of its adoption must be carefully noted, and a purpose held only as a working hypothesis until results confirm its rightness. Mistakes are no longer either mere unavoidable accidents to be mourned or moral sins to be expiated and forgiven. They are lessons in wrong methods of using intelligence and instructions as to a better course in the future. They are indications of the need of revision, development, readjustment. Ends grow, standards of judgment are improved. Man is under just as much obligation to develop his most advanced standards and ideals as to use conscientiously those which he already possesses. Moral life is protected from falling into formalism and rigid repetition. It is rendered flexible, vital, growing.
These general ideas can be expanded. First: Inquiry and discovery hold the same importance in ethics as they do in the natural sciences. Validation and demonstration become experimental, dependent on outcomes. Reason, always a respected term in ethics, is realized in the ways we analyze the needs and conditions, obstacles and resources of situations in detail, and develop smart improvement plans. Vague and abstract generalizations lead to hasty conclusions, “anticipations of nature.” Negative outcomes are then regretted, attributed to natural flaws and bad luck. However, shifting the focus to analyzing a specific situation makes inquiry necessary and careful observation of results crucial. No past decision or old principle can be entirely trusted to justify a course of action. No effort spent on forming a goal in a specific case is final; the outcomes of that choice must be closely observed, and a goal should be treated as a working hypothesis until results validate its correctness. Mistakes are no longer simply unavoidable accidents to grieve over or moral failings to atone for and forgive. They are lessons in ineffective ways to apply intelligence and guidance for a better approach in the future. They signal the need for review, development, and adjustment. Goals evolve, and standards of judgment improve. People have just as much responsibility to advance their highest standards and ideals as to use responsibly those they already have. Moral life is safeguarded from becoming formalistic and repetitive. It remains flexible, vital, and evolving.
In the second place, every case where moral action is required becomes of equal moral importance and urgency with every other. If the need and deficiencies of a specific situation indicate improvement of health as the end and good, then for that situation health is the ultimate and supreme good. It is no means to something else. It is a final and intrinsic value. The same thing is true of improvement of economic status, of making a living, of attending to business and family demands—all of the things which under the sanction of[Pg 176] fixed ends have been rendered of secondary and merely instrumental value, and so relatively base and unimportant. Anything that in a given situation is an end and good at all is of equal worth, rank and dignity with every other good of any other situation, and deserves the same intelligent attention.
In addition, every situation that requires a moral action holds equal moral significance and urgency as any other. If the needs and shortcomings of a particular situation point to health as the goal and good, then in that context, health is the ultimate and highest good. It isn't just a means to another end; it has final and inherent value. The same applies to improving economic status, earning a living, and addressing business and family obligations—all of which have been deemed secondary and merely instrumental due to fixed ends under the sanction of[Pg 176], making them seem relatively trivial and unimportant. Anything that serves as an end and good in a given situation is equally valuable, ranked, and dignified as any other good in any other situation and deserves the same thoughtful consideration.
We note thirdly the effect in destroying the roots of Phariseeism. We are so accustomed to thinking of this as deliberate hypocrisy that we overlook its intellectual premises. The conception which looks for the end of action within the circumstances of the actual situation will not have the same measure of judgment for all cases. When one factor of the situation is a person of trained mind and large resources, more will be expected than with a person of backward mind and uncultured experience. The absurdity of applying the same standard of moral judgment to savage peoples that is used with civilized will be apparent. No individual or group will be judged by whether they come up to or fall short of some fixed result, but by the direction in which they are moving. The bad man is the man who no matter how good he has been is beginning to deteriorate, to grow less good. The good man is the man who no matter how morally unworthy he has been is moving to become better. Such a conception makes one severe in judging himself and humane in judging others. It excludes that arrogance which always accompanies[Pg 177] judgment based on degree of approximation to fixed ends.
We see, thirdly, the impact on eradicating the roots of Phariseeism. We're so used to thinking of this as intentional hypocrisy that we miss its underlying beliefs. The idea that looks for the purpose of action within the specific circumstances of a given situation won't apply the same standards of judgment to all cases. When one part of the situation involves a well-educated person with considerable resources, we expect more than we would from someone who is less educated and has limited experience. The ridiculousness of using the same moral judgment standard for uncivilized people as we do for civilized ones will be obvious. No individual or group should be assessed by whether they meet or fail to meet a fixed outcome, but rather by the direction they're heading. The bad person is the one who, regardless of how good they have been, is starting to decline and become less good. The good person is the one who, no matter how morally lacking they have been, is striving to improve. This perspective encourages a strict self-assessment while promoting compassion in the evaluation of others. It eliminates the arrogance that often comes with judgment based on how closely someone approaches fixed goals.
In the fourth place, the process of growth, of improvement and progress, rather than the static outcome and result, becomes the significant thing. Not health as an end fixed once and for all, but the needed improvement in health—a continual process—is the end and good. The end is no longer a terminus or limit to be reached. It is the active process of transforming the existent situation. Not perfection as a final goal, but the ever-enduring process of perfecting, maturing, refining is the aim in living. Honesty, industry, temperance, justice, like health, wealth and learning, are not goods to be possessed as they would be if they expressed fixed ends to be attained. They are directions of change in the quality of experience. Growth itself is the only moral "end."
In the fourth place, the process of growth, improvement, and progress, rather than a set outcome or result, becomes what matters most. It’s not about health as a fixed destination, but rather the necessary improvements in health—a continuous journey—is what truly matters. The goal isn’t a final destination or limit to achieve. It’s the active process of transforming the current situation. Perfection isn’t the ultimate aim; instead, it’s about the ongoing process of perfecting, maturing, and refining as we live. Honesty, hard work, moderation, and justice, just like health, wealth, and knowledge, aren’t things to possess as if they were fixed goals to reach. They represent directions of change in the quality of our experiences. Growth itself is the only moral "end."
Although the bearing of this idea upon the problem of evil and the controversy between optimism and pessimism is too vast to be here discussed, it may be worth while to touch upon it superficially. The problem of evil ceases to be a theological and metaphysical one, and is perceived to be the practical problem of reducing, alleviating, as far as may be removing, the evils of life. Philosophy is no longer under obligation to find ingenious methods for proving that evils are only apparent, not real, or to elaborate schemes for explaining[Pg 178] them away or, worse yet, for justifying them. It assumes another obligation:—That of contributing in however humble a way to methods that will assist us in discovering the causes of humanity's ills. Pessimism is a paralyzing doctrine. In declaring that the world is evil wholesale, it makes futile all efforts to discover the remediable causes of specific evils and thereby destroys at the root every attempt to make the world better and happier. Wholesale optimism, which has been the consequence of the attempt to explain evil away, is, however, equally an incubus.
Although the impact of this idea on the problem of evil and the debate between optimism and pessimism is too broad to discuss in detail here, it's worthwhile to briefly touch on it. The problem of evil shifts from being a theological and metaphysical issue to a practical one focused on reducing, alleviating, and as much as possible, removing the difficulties of life. Philosophy is no longer required to come up with clever ways to prove that evils are just illusions or to create elaborate explanations to dismiss them, or worse, justify them. Instead, it takes on a new responsibility: to contribute, even in a modest way, to understanding the causes of humanity's suffering. Pessimism is a paralyzing belief. By claiming that the world is entirely evil, it renders all efforts to identify the specific causes of these evils pointless, undermining any attempt to improve the world and make it a happier place. On the other hand, extreme optimism, which results from the effort to explain away evil, is just as burdensome.
After all, the optimism that says that the world is already the best possible of all worlds might be regarded as the most cynical of pessimisms. If this is the best possible, what would a world which was fundamentally bad be like? Meliorism is the belief that the specific conditions which exist at one moment, be they comparatively bad or comparatively good, in any event may be bettered. It encourages intelligence to study the positive means of good and the obstructions to their realization, and to put forth endeavor for the improvement of conditions. It arouses confidence and a reasonable hopefulness as optimism does not. For the latter in declaring that good is already realized in ultimate reality tends to make us gloss over the evils that concretely exist. It becomes too readily the creed of those who live at ease, in comfort, of those who have been suc[Pg 179]cessful in obtaining this world's rewards. Too readily optimism makes the men who hold it callous and blind to the sufferings of the less fortunate, or ready to find the cause of troubles of others in their personal viciousness. It thus co-operates with pessimism, in spite of the extreme nominal differences between the two, in benumbing sympathetic insight and intelligent effort in reform. It beckons men away from the world of relativity and change into the calm of the absolute and eternal.
After all, the belief that the world is already the best it can be might actually be the most cynical form of pessimism. If this is the best we can get, what would a truly bad world look like? Meliorism is the idea that the conditions we have right now, whether they are relatively bad or good, can always be improved. It encourages us to think critically about the positive ways to create good and the obstacles that stand in the way, and to work actively towards bettering our circumstances. It fosters confidence and a sense of reasonable hopefulness, unlike optimism. Optimism, by insisting that good is already achieved in the ultimate reality, tends to make us overlook the real evils that exist. It often becomes the belief system of those who live comfortably and have successfully gained the rewards of this world. Too often, optimism can make its followers indifferent and blind to the struggles of the less fortunate, or quick to blame others' problems on their personal flaws. In this way, it collaborates with pessimism, despite their apparent differences, in dulling our capacity for empathy and effective reform efforts. It lures people away from the reality of change and into the quiet of the unchanging and eternal.
The import of many of these changes in moral attitude focusses in the idea of happiness. Happiness has often been made the object of the moralists' contempt. Yet the most ascetic moralist has usually restored the idea of happiness under some other name, such as bliss. Goodness without happiness, valor and virtue without satisfaction, ends without conscious enjoyment—these things are as intolerable practically as they are self-contradictory in conception. Happiness is not, however, a bare possession; it is not a fixed attainment. Such a happiness is either the unworthy selfishness which moralists have so bitterly condemned, or it is, even if labelled bliss, an insipid tedium, a millennium of ease in relief from all struggle and labor. It could satisfy only the most delicate of molly-coddles. Happiness is found only in success; but success means succeeding, getting forward, moving in advance. It is an active[Pg 180] process, not a passive outcome. Accordingly it includes the overcoming of obstacles, the elimination of sources of defect and ill. Esthetic sensitiveness and enjoyment are a large constituent in any worthy happiness. But the esthetic appreciation which is totally separated from renewal of spirit, from re-creation of mind and purification of emotion is a weak and sickly thing, destined to speedy death from starvation. That the renewal and re-creation come unconsciously not by set intention but makes them the more genuine.
The significance of many of these changes in moral perspective centers around the idea of happiness. Happiness has often been looked down upon by moralists. Still, even the most strict moralists usually bring back the idea of happiness under a different name, like bliss. Goodness without happiness, courage and virtue without fulfillment, goals without real enjoyment—these concepts are as practically intolerable as they are contradictory in theory. However, happiness isn't just a simple possession; it isn't a fixed achievement. Such a happiness is either the undesirable selfishness that moralists have harshly criticized, or it is, even if called bliss, a boring monotony, a time of ease devoid of all struggle and effort. It would only satisfy the most fragile individuals. Happiness is found only in success; but success means progressing, moving forward, advancing. It is an active process, not a passive result. Therefore, it involves overcoming obstacles and removing sources of flaws and negativity. Aesthetic sensitivity and enjoyment are a major part of any true happiness. However, aesthetic appreciation that is completely disconnected from spiritual renewal, mental rejuvenation, and emotional purification is weak and frail, destined to quickly perish from neglect. The fact that renewal and recreation happen unconsciously, rather than through deliberate intent, makes them feel more authentic.
Upon the whole, utilitarianism has marked the best in the transition from the classic theory of ends and goods to that which is now possible. It had definite merits. It insisted upon getting away from vague generalities, and down to the specific and concrete. It subordinated law to human achievement instead of subordinating humanity to external law. It taught that institutions are made for man and not man for institutions; it actively promoted all issues of reform. It made moral good natural, humane, in touch with the natural goods of life. It opposed unearthly and other worldly morality. Above all, it acclimatized in human imagination the idea of social welfare as a supreme test. But it was still profoundly affected in fundamental points by old ways of thinking. It never questioned the idea of a fixed, final and supreme end. It only questioned the current notions as to the nature of this[Pg 181] end; and then inserted pleasure and the greatest possible aggregate of pleasures in the position of the fixed end.
Overall, utilitarianism has represented the best in the shift from the classic theory of goals and goods to what is possible now. It had clear advantages. It pushed for moving away from vague generalities and focused on the specific and concrete. It placed human achievement above laws instead of putting humanity below external laws. It taught that institutions exist for people, not the other way around; it actively supported all reform issues. It made moral goodness feel natural and human, connected to the essential goods of life. It rejected otherworldly and mystical morality. Most importantly, it ingrained the idea of social welfare as a fundamental measure in people's minds. However, it was still heavily influenced by old ways of thinking on key points. It never questioned the notion of a fixed, final, and ultimate goal. It only challenged contemporary ideas about what that end should be and then proposed pleasure and the greatest total of pleasures as that fixed end.
Such a point of view treats concrete activities and specific interests not as worth while in themselves, or as constituents of happiness, but as mere external means to getting pleasures. The upholders of the old tradition could therefore easily accuse utilitarianism of making not only virtue but art, poetry, religion and the state into mere servile means of attaining sensuous enjoyments. Since pleasure was an outcome, a result valuable on its own account independently of the active processes that achieve it, happiness was a thing to be possessed and held onto. The acquisitive instincts of man were exaggerated at the expense of the creative. Production was of importance not because of the intrinsic worth of invention and reshaping the world, but because its external results feed pleasure. Like every theory that sets up fixed and final aims, in making the end passive and possessive, it made all active operations mere tools. Labor was an unavoidable evil to be minimized. Security in possession was the chief thing practically. Material comfort and ease were magnified in contrast with the pains and risk of experimental creation.
Such a perspective views concrete activities and specific interests not as valuable in themselves, or as parts of happiness, but merely as external means to gain pleasures. Supporters of the traditional view could easily accuse utilitarianism of reducing not just virtue but also art, poetry, religion, and the state to mere tools for achieving sensory enjoyment. Since pleasure was seen as an outcome, a result that had its own value apart from the active processes that lead to it, happiness was viewed as something to be owned and clung to. The human instinct to acquire was emphasized at the expense of creativity. Production mattered not because of the intrinsic value of invention and transforming the world, but because its external outcomes provided pleasure. Like every theory that establishes fixed and final goals, by making the end passive and possessive, it turned all active efforts into mere tools. Work was seen as an unavoidable evil to be minimized. The security of ownership was seen as the most important practical concern. Material comfort and ease were exaggerated in comparison to the pains and risks of innovative creation.
These deficiencies, under certain conceivable conditions, might have remained merely theoretical. But the disposition of the times and the interests of those who[Pg 182] propagated the utilitarian ideas, endowed them with power for social harm. In spite of the power of the new ideas in attacking old social abuses, there were elements in the teaching which operated or protected to sanction new social abuses. The reforming zeal was shown in criticism of the evils inherited from the class system of feudalism, evils economic, legal and political. But the new economic order of capitalism that was superseding feudalism brought its own social evils with it, and some of these ills utilitarianism tended to cover up or defend. The emphasis upon acquisition and possession of enjoyments took on an untoward color in connection with the contemporary enormous desire for wealth and the enjoyments it makes possible.
These shortcomings, under certain possible conditions, might have just remained theoretical. However, the attitudes of the time and the interests of those who[Pg 182] promoted utilitarian ideas gave them harmful social power. Despite the strength of the new ideas in challenging old social injustices, there were aspects of the theory that contributed to or justified new social wrongs. The drive for reform was evident in the criticism of the problems inherited from the class system of feudalism—economic, legal, and political issues. Yet, the new economic system of capitalism that replaced feudalism brought its own social problems, and some of these issues utilitarianism tended to hide or defend. The focus on acquiring and enjoying possessions took on a troubling tone, especially in relation to the overwhelming desire for wealth and the pleasures it can provide.
If utilitarianism did not actively promote the new economic materialism, it had no means of combating it. Its general spirit of subordinating productive activity to the bare product was indirectly favorable to the cause of an unadorned commercialism. In spite of its interest in a thoroughly social aim, utilitarianism fostered a new class interest, that of the capitalistic property-owning interests, provided only property was obtained through free competition and not by governmental favor. The stress that Bentham put on security tended to consecrate the legal institution of private property provided only certain legal abuses in connection with its acquisition and transfer were[Pg 183] abolished. Beati possidentes—provided possessions had been obtained in accord with the rules of the competitive game—without, that is, extraneous favors from government. Thus utilitarianism gave intellectual confirmation to all those tendencies which make "business" not a means of social service and an opportunity for personal growth in creative power but a way of accumulating the means of private enjoyments. Utilitarian ethics thus afford a remarkable example of the need of philosophic reconstruction which these lectures have been presenting. Up to a certain point, it reflected the meaning of modern thought and aspirations. But it was still tied down by fundamental ideas of that very order which it thought it had completely left behind: The idea of a fixed and single end lying beyond the diversity of human needs and acts rendered utilitarianism incapable of being an adequate representative of the modern spirit. It has to be reconstructed through emancipation from its inherited elements.
If utilitarianism didn't actively support the new economic materialism, it also had no way to challenge it. Its overall tendency to prioritize production over the final product indirectly favored plain commercialism. Despite its focus on a genuinely social goal, utilitarianism advanced a new class interest—the interests of capitalists—so long as property was acquired through free competition and not through government favoritism. Bentham's emphasis on security reinforced the legal institution of private property as long as certain legal abuses related to its acquisition and transfer were[Pg 183] eliminated. Beati possidentes—as long as possessions were obtained according to the rules of the competitive game—without external government favors. Thus, utilitarianism provided intellectual support for trends that view "business" not as a means of social service or a chance for personal growth and creativity but as a way to accumulate resources for personal enjoyment. Utilitarian ethics exemplify the need for philosophical reconstruction, which these lectures have been discussing. To some extent, it reflected the essence of modern thought and aspirations. However, it remained constrained by fundamental ideas from the very order it believed it had overcome: the notion of a fixed and singular goal beyond the variety of human needs and actions rendered utilitarianism incapable of adequately representing the modern spirit. It needs to be reconstructed by breaking free from its inherited elements.
If a few words are added upon the topic of education, it is only for the sake of suggesting that the educative process is all one with the moral process, since the latter is a continuous passage of experience from worse to better. Education has been traditionally thought of as preparation: as learning, acquiring certain things because they will later be useful. The end is remote, and education is getting ready, is a preliminary to some[Pg 184]thing more important to happen later on. Childhood is only a preparation for adult life, and adult life for another life. Always the future, not the present, has been the significant thing in education: Acquisition of knowledge and skill for future use and enjoyment; formation of habits required later in life in business, good citizenship and pursuit of science. Education is thought of also as something needed by some human beings merely because of their dependence upon others. We are born ignorant, unversed, unskilled, immature, and consequently in a state of social dependence. Instruction, training, moral discipline are processes by which the mature, the adult, gradually raise the helpless to the point where they can look out for themselves. The business of childhood is to grow into the independence of adulthood by means of the guidance of those who have already attained it. Thus the process of education as the main business of life ends when the young have arrived at emancipation from social dependence.
If we add a few words about education, it’s only to suggest that the learning process is closely linked to the moral process, as the latter involves a continuous journey from worse to better. Education has traditionally been seen as preparation: learning and acquiring certain knowledge because it will be useful later on. The end goal feels distant, and education is perceived as getting ready, a stepping stone to something more significant that will happen in the future. Childhood is simply a preparation for adult life, and adult life for another stage. The future, not the present, has always been emphasized in education: acquiring knowledge and skills for future use and enjoyment, forming habits necessary for later life in work, good citizenship, and the pursuit of knowledge. Education is also considered something that some people need simply because they depend on others. We are born ignorant, inexperienced, unskilled, and immature, and thus in a state of social dependence. Instruction, training, and moral guidance are processes by which adults gradually help those who are helpless to reach a point where they can take care of themselves. The role of childhood is to grow into adult independence through the guidance of those who have already achieved it. So, the process of education, which is the central aspect of life, concludes when young people achieve independence from social dependence.
These two ideas, generally assumed but rarely explicitly reasoned out, contravene the conception that growing, or the continuous reconstruction of experience, is the only end. If at whatever period we choose to take a person, he is still in process of growth, then education is not, save as a by-product, a preparation for something coming later. Getting from the present the degree[Pg 185] and kind of growth there is in it is education. This is a constant function, independent of age. The best thing that can be said about any special process of education, like that of the formal school period, is that it renders its subject capable of further education: more sensitive to conditions of growth and more able to take advantage of them. Acquisition of skill, possession of knowledge, attainment of culture are not ends: they are marks of growth and means to its continuing.
These two ideas, often taken for granted but seldom fully explained, contradict the belief that growth, or the ongoing reconstruction of experience, is the ultimate goal. If we consider a person at any point in their life, they are still growing; therefore, education is not just a preparation for something in the future, it occurs as a by-product. Gaining the degree[Pg 185] and type of growth available in the present moment is what education is about. This process is constant, regardless of age. The best thing we can say about a specific educational process, like formal schooling, is that it makes individuals more capable of further education: more aware of growth conditions and better equipped to take advantage of them. Acquiring skills, gaining knowledge, and achieving culture aren’t ends in themselves; they are indicators of growth and ways to encourage ongoing development.
The contrast usually assumed between the period of education as one of social dependence and of maturity as one of social independence does harm. We repeat over and over that man is a social animal, and then confine the significance of this statement to the sphere in which sociality usually seems least evident, politics. The heart of the sociality of man is in education. The idea of education as preparation and of adulthood as a fixed limit of growth are two sides of the same obnoxious untruth. If the moral business of the adult as well as the young is a growing and developing experience, then the instruction that comes from social dependencies and interdependencies are as important for the adult as for the child. Moral independence for the adult means arrest of growth, isolation means induration. We exaggerate the intellectual dependence of childhood so that children are too much kept in leading strings, and then we exaggerate the independence of adult life from inti[Pg 186]macy of contacts and communication with others. When the identity of the moral process with the processes of specific growth is realized, the more conscious and formal education of childhood will be seen to be the most economical and efficient means of social advance and reorganization, and it will also be evident that the test of all the institutions of adult life is their effect in furthering continued education. Government, business, art, religion, all social institutions have a meaning, a purpose. That purpose is to set free and to develop the capacities of human individuals without respect to race, sex, class or economic status. And this is all one with saying that the test of their value is the extent to which they educate every individual into the full stature of his possibility. Democracy has many meanings, but if it has a moral meaning, it is found in resolving that the supreme test of all political institutions and industrial arrangements shall be the contribution they make to the all-around growth of every member of society.
The contrast often seen between the educational phase as one of social dependence and the stage of maturity as one of social independence is harmful. We constantly remind ourselves that humans are social beings, yet we limit the importance of this idea to areas where social aspects seem least visible, like politics. The essence of human sociality lies in education. Thinking of education merely as preparation and adulthood as a final stage of development is a misleading belief. If both kids and adults are engaged in ongoing moral growth and development, then the lessons learned through social connections are just as vital for adults as they are for children. For adults, moral independence often leads to stunted growth, and isolation results in a hardened character. We tend to overstate the intellectual dependence of childhood, keeping kids too much under control, while at the same time, we exaggerate the independence of adulthood from the intimacy of relationships and interactions with others. When we understand that the moral development process aligns with specific growth processes, we will see that the more structured and deliberate education of children is the most efficient way to promote social progress and reform. It will also become clear that the value of all institutions in adult life is measured by how well they support ongoing education. Government, business, art, religion—every social institution has a meaning and purpose. That purpose is to free and develop the abilities of every individual, regardless of their race, gender, class, or economic situation. This means that their value is judged by how much they help each person reach their full potential. Democracy can mean many things, but if it has a moral significance, it lies in ensuring that the ultimate measure of all political and economic systems is their contribution to the overall growth of every individual in society.
CHAPTER VIII
RECONSTRUCTION AS AFFECTING SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY
How can philosophic change seriously affect social philosophy? As far as fundamentals are concerned, every view and combination appears to have been formulated already. Society is composed of individuals: this obvious and basic fact no philosophy, whatever its pretensions to novelty, can question or alter. Hence these three alternatives: Society must exist for the sake of individuals; or individuals must have their ends and ways of living set for them by society; or else society and individuals are correlative, organic, to one another, society requiring the service and subordination of individuals and at the same time existing to serve them. Beyond these three views, none seems to be logically conceivable. Moreover, while each of the three types includes many subspecies and variations within itself, yet the changes seem to have been so thoroughly rung that at most only minor variations are now possible.
How can philosophical change really impact social philosophy? When it comes to the basics, every idea and combination seems to have already been expressed. Society is made up of individuals: this clear and fundamental truth can’t be questioned or changed by any philosophy, no matter how new it claims to be. So we have these three options: Society must exist for individuals; or individuals must have their goals and ways of living determined by society; or society and individuals are interconnected, both needing each other—society depends on the service and support of individuals while also existing to benefit them. Beyond these three perspectives, nothing else really makes sense. Additionally, while each of the three types includes many subcategories and variations, it seems that we’ve explored these ideas so thoroughly that now only minor changes are possible.
Especially would it seem true that the "organic" conception meets all the objections to the extreme individualistic and extreme socialistic theories, avoiding the[Pg 188] errors alike of Plato and Bentham. Just because society is composed of individuals, it would seem that individuals and the associative relations that hold them together must be of coequal importance. Without strong and competent individuals, the bonds and ties that form society have nothing to lay hold on. Apart from associations with one another, individuals are isolated from one another and fade and wither; or are opposed to one another and their conflicts injure individual development. Law, state, church, family, friendship, industrial association, these and other institutions and arrangements are necessary in order that individuals may grow and find their specific capacities and functions. Without their aid and support human life is, as Hobbes said, brutish, solitary, nasty.
It seems especially true that the "organic" view addresses all the criticisms of both extreme individualistic and extreme socialistic theories, avoiding the[Pg 188] mistakes of both Plato and Bentham. Since society is made up of individuals, it appears that both individuals and the connections that bind them together are equally important. Without strong and capable individuals, the relationships and structures that make up society have nothing to support them. Without connections to one another, individuals become isolated, fade away, or end up in conflict, which hinders personal growth. Laws, government, religion, family, friendships, and business relationships—these and other institutions are essential for individuals to develop and discover their unique abilities and roles. Without their support, human life is, as Hobbes put it, brutish, solitary, and unpleasant.
We plunge into the heart of the matter, by asserting that these various theories suffer from a common defect. They are all committed to the logic of general notions under which specific situations are to be brought. What we want light upon is this or that group of individuals, this or that concrete human being, this or that special institution or social arrangement. For such a logic of inquiry, the traditionally accepted logic substitutes discussion of the meaning of concepts and their dialectical relationship to one another. The discussion goes on in terms of the state, the individual; the nature of institutions as such, society in general.
We dive into the main issue by stating that these different theories share a common flaw. They all rely on general ideas under which specific situations must fit. What we need to focus on is this particular group of people, this specific individual, this unique institution or social setup. Instead of this approach, traditional logic shifts the discussion to the meaning of concepts and how they relate to each other. The conversation revolves around the state, the individual, the essence of institutions as a whole, and society in general.
We need guidance in dealing with particular perplexities in domestic life, and are met by dissertations on the Family or by assertions of the sacredness of individual Personality. We want to know about the worth of the institution of private property as it operates under given conditions of definite time and place. We meet with the reply of Proudhon that property generally is theft, or with that of Hegel that the realization of will is the end of all institutions, and that private ownership as the expression of mastery of personality over physical nature is a necessary element in such realization. Both answers may have a certain suggestiveness in connection with specific situations. But the conceptions are not proffered for what they may be worth in connection with special historic phenomena. They are general answers supposed to have a universal meaning that covers and dominates all particulars. Hence they do not assist inquiry. They close it. They are not instrumentalities to be employed and tested in clarifying concrete social difficulties. They are ready-made principles to be imposed upon particulars in order to determine their nature. They tell us about the state when we want to know about some state. But the implication is that what is said about the state applies to any state that we happen to wish to know about.
We need guidance for the specific challenges in our daily lives, but we often encounter lengthy discussions about the family or claims about the sacredness of individual identity. We want to understand the value of private property as it functions in a particular time and place. Instead, we are met with Proudhon’s idea that property is essentially theft, or Hegel’s belief that the realization of will is the ultimate goal of all institutions, with private ownership being a necessary part of this realization. While both viewpoints may offer some insight for certain situations, they are not presented based on their relevance to specific historical events. They are general answers that are believed to have a universal meaning that oversimplifies and overshadows all details. As a result, they don’t help in inquiries; they shut them down. They aren’t tools to engage with and test in order to clarify real social issues. They are pre-packaged principles forced onto specifics to define their nature. They inform us about the state when we need to understand some state. Yet, the underlying assumption is that what is said about the state applies universally to any state we may want to learn about.
In transferring the issue from concrete situations to definitions and conceptual deductions, the effect, espe[Pg 190]cially of the organic theory, is to supply the apparatus for intellectual justification of the established order. Those most interested in practical social progress and the emancipation of groups from oppression have turned a cold shoulder to the organic theory. The effect, if not the intention, of German idealism as applied in social philosophy was to provide a bulwark for the maintenance of the political status quo against the tide of radical ideas coming from revolutionary France. Although Hegel asserted in explicit form that the end of states and institutions is to further the realization of the freedom of all, his effect was to consecrate the Prussian State and to enshrine bureaucratic absolutism. Was this apologetic tendency accidental, or did it spring from something in the logic of the notions that were employed?
In moving the discussion from specific situations to definitions and theoretical deductions, the impact—especially of the organic theory—provides the framework for intellectually justifying the established order. Those most focused on practical social progress and freeing groups from oppression have largely ignored the organic theory. The outcome, if not the goal, of German idealism in social philosophy was to create a safeguard for the political status quo against the wave of radical ideas from revolutionary France. Even though Hegel claimed that the purpose of states and institutions is to promote the freedom of everyone, his influence ended up legitimizing the Prussian State and supporting bureaucratic absolutism. Was this apologetic trend a coincidence, or did it stem from something within the logic of the concepts that were used?
Surely the latter. If we talk about the state and the individual, rather than about this or that political organization and this or that group of needy and suffering human beings, the tendency is to throw the glamor and prestige, the meaning and value attached to the general notion, over the concrete situation and thereby to cover up the defects of the latter and disguise the need of serious reforms. The meanings which are found in the general notions are injected into the particulars that come under them. Quite properly so if we once grant the logic of rigid universals under which the concrete cases[Pg 191] have to be subsumed in order to be understood and explained.
Surely the latter. If we talk about the state and the individual, rather than specific political organizations or particular groups of needy and suffering people, we tend to assign the glamor and prestige, the meaning and value associated with the general idea, to the specific situation. This can cover up the flaws of that situation and disguise the need for serious reforms. The meanings found in general concepts are applied to the specific cases that fall under them. This is appropriate if we accept the logic of rigid universals, under which concrete cases[Pg 191] must be categorized to be understood and explained.
Again, the tendency of the organic point of view is to minimize the significance of specific conflicts. Since the individual and the state or social institution are but two sides of the same reality, since they are already reconciled in principle and conception, the conflict in any particular case can be but apparent. Since in theory the individual and the state are reciprocally necessary and helpful to one another, why pay much attention to the fact that in this state a whole group of individuals are suffering from oppressive conditions? In "reality" their interests cannot be in conflict with those of the state to which they belong; the opposition is only superficial and casual. Capital and labor cannot "really" conflict because each is an organic necessity to the other, and both to the organized community as a whole. There cannot "really" be any sex-problem because men and women are indispensable both to one another and to the state. In his day, Aristotle could easily employ the logic of general concepts superior to individuals to show that the institution of slavery was in the interests both of the state and of the slave class. Even if the intention is not to justify the existing order the effect is to divert attention from special situations. Rationalistic logic formerly made men careless in observation of the concrete in physical philosophy. It now operates to[Pg 192] depress and retard observation in specific social phenomena. The social philosopher, dwelling in the region of his concepts, "solves" problems by showing the relationship of ideas, instead of helping men solve problems in the concrete by supplying them hypotheses to be used and tested in projects of reform.
Again, the organic perspective tends to downplay the importance of specific conflicts. Since the individual and the state or social institution are just two sides of the same coin, and they are already fundamentally aligned in principle and concept, any particular conflict can only be seen as superficial. In theory, the individual and the state are mutually necessary and beneficial to each other, so why focus too much on the fact that in this state, a whole group of individuals is suffering under oppressive conditions? In "reality," their interests can't truly clash with those of the state they belong to; the opposition is merely surface-level and casual. Capital and labor can't genuinely be in conflict because each is an essential need for the other, and both are necessary for the organized community as a whole. There can't "really" be a sex issue because men and women are vital to each other and to the state. In his time, Aristotle could easily use the logic of general concepts over individuals to argue that slavery benefited both the state and the enslaved people. Even if there’s no intent to justify the current order, the effect is to distract from specific situations. Rationalistic logic once made people careless in observing the concrete in physical philosophy. Now, it operates to[Pg 192] hinder and slow down observation of specific social phenomena. The social philosopher, lost in his ideas, "solves" problems by demonstrating the relationships of concepts, instead of helping people tackle real issues by providing them with hypotheses to test in reform efforts.
Meanwhile, of course, the concrete troubles and evils remain. They are not magically waived out of existence because in theory society is organic. The region of concrete difficulties, where the assistance of intelligent method for tentative plans for experimentation is urgently needed, is precisely where intelligence fails to operate. In this region of the specific and concrete, men are thrown back upon the crudest empiricism, upon short-sighted opportunism and the matching of brute forces. In theory, the particulars are all neatly disposed of; they come under their appropriate heading and category; they are labelled and go into an orderly pigeon-hole in a systematic filing cabinet, labelled political science or sociology. But in empirical fact they remain as perplexing, confused and unorganized as they were before. So they are dealt with not by even an endeavor at scientific method but by blind rule of thumb, citation of precedents, considerations of immediate advantage, smoothing things over, use of coercive force and the clash of personal ambitions. The world still survives; it has therefore got on somehow:—so[Pg 193] much cannot be denied. The method of trial and error and competition of selfishnesses has somehow wrought out many improvements. But social theory nevertheless exists as an idle luxury rather than as a guiding method of inquiry and planning. In the question of methods concerned with reconstruction of special situations rather than in any refinements in the general concepts of institution, individuality, state, freedom, law, order, progress, etc., lies the true impact of philosophical reconstruction.
Meanwhile, the real issues and problems still persist. They don’t just disappear because society is considered to be organic in theory. The area where we face concrete difficulties, where we desperately need smart approaches for trying out new ideas, is exactly where our intelligence tends to fall short. In this specific and tangible realm, people revert to the most basic trial-and-error methods, short-sighted opportunism, and clashing aggressive forces. In theory, all the details could be neatly organized; each would fall into its proper category, be labeled, and placed in an orderly filing system under political science or sociology. But in real life, they remain as confusing and disorganized as ever. As a result, they aren’t handled with any real scientific method, but rather through instinctive practices, references to past cases, immediate benefits, smoothing things over, using force, and the competition of personal ambitions. The world continues to exist; it has somehow managed to keep going:—that much is undeniable. The trial and error method, along with competition among self-interests, has led to some progress. However, social theory still functions more as a luxury than as a practical guide for inquiry and planning. The true significance of philosophical reconstruction lies in the methods for rebuilding specific situations rather than in refining general concepts like institutions, individuality, the state, freedom, law, order, and progress, etc.
Consider the conception of the individual self. The individualistic school of England and France in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries was empirical in intent. It based its individualism, philosophically speaking, upon the belief that individuals are alone real, that classes and organizations are secondary and derived. They are artificial, while individuals are natural. In what way then can individualism be said to come under the animadversions that have been passed? To say the defect was that this school overlooked those connections with other persons which are a part of the constitution of every individual is true as far as it goes; but unfortunately it rarely goes beyond the point of just that wholesale justification of institutions which has been criticized.
Consider the idea of the individual self. The individualistic movement in England and France during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries was focused on empirical understanding. It grounded its individualism, philosophically speaking, on the belief that individuals are the only true reality, while classes and organizations are secondary and derived. They are artificial, whereas individuals are natural. So, in what way can individualism be criticized as has been done? It is true that a main flaw of this school of thought is that it ignores the connections with other people that are part of every individual’s makeup; however, it unfortunately seldom goes beyond merely justifying institutions that have been criticized.
The real difficulty is that the individual is regarded as something given, something already there. Conse[Pg 194]quently, he can only be something to be catered to, something whose pleasures are to be magnified and possessions multiplied. When the individual is taken as something given already, anything that can be done to him or for him it can only be by way of external impressions and belongings: sensations of pleasure and pain, comforts, securities. Now it is true that social arrangements, laws, institutions are made for man, rather than that man is made for them; that they are means and agencies of human welfare and progress. But they are not means for obtaining something for individuals, not even happiness. They are means of creating individuals. Only in the physical sense of physical bodies that to the senses are separate is individuality an original datum. Individuality in a social and moral sense is something to be wrought out. It means initiative, inventiveness, varied resourcefulness, assumption of responsibility in choice of belief and conduct. These are not gifts, but achievements. As achievements, they are not absolute but relative to the use that is to be made of them. And this use varies with the environment.
The real challenge is that individuals are seen as something given, something that's already there. As a result, they can only be treated as something to be catered to, whose pleasures are to be highlighted and possessions increased. When a person is viewed as something that's already established, any actions taken towards them can only come through external impressions and belongings: feelings of pleasure and pain, comforts, securities. It is true that social structures, laws, and institutions are created for people, rather than people being created for them; that they are tools for human welfare and progress. However, they do not serve to provide something for individuals, not even happiness. They are tools for creating individuals. In the pure physical sense, individuality is an original fact defined by separate physical bodies perceived by the senses. But individuality in a social and moral context has to be developed. It requires initiative, creativity, diverse problem-solving, and taking responsibility for choices in beliefs and actions. These are not just gifts; they are accomplishments. As accomplishments, they are not absolute but relative to how they will be used. And this usage changes with the environment.
The import of this conception comes out in considering the fortunes of the idea of self-interest. All members of the empirical school emphasized this idea. It was the sole motive of mankind. Virtue was to be attained by making benevolent action profitable to the[Pg 195] individual; social arrangements were to be reformed so that egoism and altruistic consideration of others would be identified. Moralists of the opposite school were not backward in pointing out the evils of any theory that reduced both morals and political science to means of calculating self-interest. Consequently they threw the whole idea of interest overboard as obnoxious to morals. The effect of this reaction was to strengthen the cause of authority and political obscurantism. When the play of interest is eliminated, what remains? What concrete moving forces can be found? Those who identified the self with something ready-made and its interest with acquisition of pleasure and profit took the most effective means possible to reinstate the logic of abstract conceptions of law, justice, sovereignty, freedom, etc.—all of those vague general ideas that for all their seeming rigidity can be manipulated by any clever politician to cover up his designs and to make the worse seem the better cause. Interests are specific and dynamic; they are the natural terms of any concrete social thinking. But they are damned beyond recovery when they are identified with the things of a petty selfishness. They can be employed as vital terms only when the self is seen to be in process, and interest to be a name for whatever is concerned in furthering its movement.
The significance of this idea becomes clear when we look at the concept of self-interest. All members of the empirical school stressed this idea. It was the only motivation for humanity. Virtue was to be achieved by making kind actions beneficial for the[Pg 195] individual; social systems were to be changed so that self-interest and concern for others would align. Moralists from the opposing viewpoint didn't hesitate to point out the problems with any theory that reduced both ethics and political science to mere calculations of self-interest. As a result, they completely rejected the notion of interest as detrimental to morals. This backlash ended up reinforcing the case for authority and political obscurantism. When you take interest out of the equation, what’s left? What real driving forces can be identified? Those who connected the self with something predetermined and its interest with the pursuit of pleasure and profit found the most effective way to restore the logic of abstract ideas like law, justice, sovereignty, and freedom—all those vague concepts that, despite their apparent rigidity, can be manipulated by any clever politician to disguise their intentions and make the worse appear the better option. Interests are specific and dynamic; they are fundamental to any practical social thinking. However, they are ultimately lost when linked to mere petty selfishness. They can only be effectively used as meaningful terms when the self is viewed as a process, with interest understood as whatever helps promote that development.
The same logic applies to the old dispute of whether[Pg 196] reform should start with the individual or with institutions. When the self is regarded as something complete within itself, then it is readily argued that only internal moralistic changes are of importance in general reform. Institutional changes are said to be merely external. They may add conveniences and comforts to life, but they cannot effect moral improvements. The result is to throw the burden for social improvement upon free-will in its most impossible form. Moreover, social and economic passivity are encouraged. Individuals are led to concentrate in moral introspection upon their own vices and virtues, and to neglect the character of the environment. Morals withdraw from active concern with detailed economic and political conditions. Let us perfect ourselves within, and in due season changes in society will come of themselves is the teaching. And while saints are engaged in introspection, burly sinners run the world. But when self-hood is perceived to be an active process it is also seen that social modifications are the only means of the creation of changed personalities. Institutions are viewed in their educative effect:—with reference to the types of individuals they foster. The interest in individual moral improvement and the social interest in objective reform of economic and political conditions are identified. And inquiry into the meaning of social arrangements gets definite point and direction. We are led to ask what the specific stimulating, foster[Pg 197]ing and nurturing power of each specific social arrangement may be. The old-time separation between politics and morals is abolished at its root.
The same logic applies to the ongoing debate about whether[Pg 196] reform should start with individuals or institutions. When we see the self as something complete on its own, it becomes easy to argue that only internal moral changes are important for broader reform. Changes in institutions are considered merely external. While they might add conveniences and comforts to life, they can’t really improve morality. This places the responsibility for social improvement solely on free will in its most unrealistic form. Additionally, it encourages social and economic passivity. Individuals tend to focus on their own vices and virtues through moral introspection while ignoring the conditions of their environment. Morality pulls away from actively engaging with specific economic and political issues. The teaching suggests that if we perfect ourselves internally, societal changes will eventually occur on their own. Meanwhile, while the virtuous are caught up in introspection, those who misbehave run the world. However, when we see the self as an active process, it becomes clear that social changes are essential for developing new personalities. Institutions are viewed for their educational impact, particularly in terms of the kinds of individuals they nurture. The pursuit of individual moral improvement aligns with the social interest in reforming economic and political conditions. This leads to a focused inquiry into the meaning of social structures. We start to ask what the specific stimulating, fostering, and nurturing effects of each social arrangement might be. The outdated division between politics and morals is fundamentally dismantled.
Consequently we cannot be satisfied with the general statement that society and the state is organic to the individual. The question is one of specific causations. Just what response does this social arrangement, political or economic, evoke, and what effect does it have upon the disposition of those who engage in it? Does it release capacity? If so, how widely? Among a few, with a corresponding depression in others, or in an extensive and equitable way? Is the capacity which is set free also directed in some coherent way, so that it becomes a power, or its manifestation spasmodic and capricious? Since responses are of an indefinite diversity of kind, these inquiries have to be detailed and specific. Are men's senses rendered more delicately sensitive and appreciative, or are they blunted and dulled by this and that form of social organization? Are their minds trained so that the hands are more deft and cunning? Is curiosity awakened or blunted? What is its quality: is it merely esthetic, dwelling on the forms and surfaces of things or is it also an intellectual searching into their meaning? Such questions as these (as well as the more obvious ones about the qualities conventionally labelled moral), become the starting-points of inquiries about every institution of the community[Pg 198] when it is recognized that individuality is not originally given but is created under the influences of associated life. Like utilitarianism, the theory subjects every form of organization to continual scrutiny and criticism. But instead of leading us to ask what it does in the way of causing pains and pleasures to individuals already in existence, it inquires what is done to release specific capacities and co-ordinate them into working powers. What sort of individuals are created?
Consequently, we can't just be satisfied with the broad claim that society and the state are organic to the individual. The real question involves specific causes. What response does this social arrangement—political or economic—elicit, and what effect does it have on the people involved? Does it unlock potential? If so, how widespread is that potential? Is it limited to a few, resulting in a corresponding decline in others, or is it released in a broad and fair manner? Is the potential that's unleashed guided in a coherent way, turning into a power, or is its expression random and unpredictable? Given the endless variety of potential responses, these questions need to be detailed and precise. Are people's senses made more finely attuned and appreciative, or are they dulled and blunted by various forms of social organization? Are their minds trained so that their hands become more skillful and clever? Does it spark curiosity or dull it? What kind of curiosity is it: merely aesthetic, focused on forms and surfaces, or is it also an intellectual exploration of deeper meanings? Questions like these (as well as the more obvious ones about what we usually call moral qualities) become starting points for examining every community institution[Pg 198] when we recognize that individuality isn't something we're born with, but is shaped by our interactions with others. Like utilitarianism, this theory places all forms of organization under continuous examination and critique. However, instead of simply asking what causes pleasure or pain for existing individuals, it investigates what is done to unlock specific capacities and coordinate them into effective powers. What kinds of individuals are formed as a result?
The waste of mental energy due to conducting discussion of social affairs in terms of conceptual generalities is astonishing. How far would the biologist and the physician progress if when the subject of respiration is under consideration, discussion confined itself to bandying back and forth the concepts of organ and organism:—If for example one school thought respiration could be known and understood by insisting upon the fact that it occurs in an individual body and therefore is an "individual" phenomenon, while an opposite school insisted that it is simply one function in organic interaction with others and can be known or understood therefore only by reference to other functions taken in an equally general or wholesale way? Each proposition is equally true and equally futile. What is needed is specific inquiries into a multitude of specific structures and interactions. Not only does the solemn reiteration of categories of individual and organic or[Pg 199] social whole not further these definite and detailed inquiries, but it checks them. It detains thought within pompous and sonorous generalities wherein controversy is as inevitable as it is incapable of solution. It is true enough that if cells were not in vital interaction with one another, they could neither conflict nor co-operate. But the fact of the existence of an "organic" social group, instead of answering any questions merely marks the fact that questions exist: Just what conflicts and what co-operations occur, and what are their specific causes and consequences? But because of the persistence within social philosophy of the order of ideas that has been expelled from natural philosophy, even sociologists take conflict or co-operation as general categories upon which to base their science, and condescend to empirical facts only for illustrations. As a rule, their chief "problem" is a purely dialectical one, covered up by a thick quilt of empirical anthropological and historical citations: How do individuals unite to form society? How are individuals socially controlled? And the problem is justly called dialectical because it springs from antecedent conceptions of "individual" and "social."
The waste of mental energy spent discussing social issues using vague concepts is surprising. How far would biologists and doctors get if, when talking about respiration, they only exchanged ideas about organs and organisms? For example, one group might believe respiration is only understandable as an "individual" phenomenon since it happens in a single body, while another group insists it’s just one function that interacts with others and can only be understood in relation to those other functions. Both ideas are true but pointless. What’s really needed are specific investigations into a wide range of structures and interactions. The repetitive discussion of terms like "individual," "organic," or "social whole" doesn’t help these inquiries; instead, it hinders them. It traps thought in grand, formal generalizations, where debate is unavoidable but unsolvable. It’s true that if cells weren’t interacting with each other, they couldn’t conflict or cooperate. But the existence of an "organic" social group doesn’t clarify things; it simply shows that questions are there: What specific conflicts and cooperations occur, and what causes and consequences do they have? Yet, because social philosophy clings to outdated ideas from natural philosophy, even sociologists treat conflict and cooperation as general categories to base their studies on, only using real-world facts as examples. Usually, their main "problem" is a strictly theoretical one, concealed under a layer of empirical anthropological and historical references: How do individuals come together to form society? How are individuals controlled socially? This issue is rightly termed dialectical because it originates from earlier ideas of "individual" and "social."
Just as "individual" is not one thing, but is a blanket term for the immense variety of specific reactions, habits, dispositions and powers of human nature that are evoked, and confirmed under the influences of[Pg 200] associated life, so with the term "social." Society is one word, but infinitely many things. It covers all the ways in which by associating together men share their experiences, and build up common interests and aims; street gangs, schools for burglary, clans, social cliques, trades unions, joint stock corporations, villages and international alliances. The new method takes effect in substituting inquiry into these specific, changing and relative facts (relative to problems and purposes, not metaphysically relative) for solemn manipulation of general notions.
Just like "individual" isn’t just one thing, but a broad term that encompasses the huge variety of specific reactions, habits, traits, and abilities of human nature that are triggered and confirmed by the influences of[Pg 200] related life, the same goes for the term "social." Society is a single word, yet it represents countless things. It includes all the ways people come together to share their experiences and develop common interests and goals: street gangs, burglary schools, clans, social groups, labor unions, corporations, villages, and international alliances. The new method focuses on exploring these specific, changing, and relative facts (relative to problems and goals, not metaphysically relative) instead of the serious handling of broad concepts.
Strangely enough, the current conception of the state is a case in point. For one direct influence of the classic order of fixed species arranged in hierarchical order is the attempt of German political philosophy in the nineteenth century to enumerate a definite number of institutions, each having its own essential and immutable meaning; to arrange them in an order of "evolution" which corresponds with the dignity and rank of the respective meanings. The National State was placed at the top as the consummation and culmination, and also the basis of all other institutions.
Strangely enough, the current idea of the state is a perfect example. One direct impact of the traditional classification of fixed categories arranged in a hierarchy is the effort of German political philosophy in the nineteenth century to list a specific number of institutions, each with its own essential and unchanging meaning; to organize them in an "evolutionary" order that reflects the dignity and rank of their respective meanings. The National State was positioned at the top as the peak and the foundation of all other institutions.
Hegel is a striking example of this industry, but he is far from the only one. Many who have bitterly quarrelled with him, have only differed as to the details of the "evolution" or as to the particular meaning to be attributed as essential Begriff to some one of the[Pg 201] enumerated institutions. The quarrel has been bitter only because the underlying premises were the same. Particularly have many schools of thought, varying even more widely in respect to method and conclusion, agreed upon the final consummating position of the state. They may not go as far as Hegel in making the sole meaning of history to be the evolution of National Territorial States, each of which embodies more than the prior form of the essential meaning or conception of the State and consequently displaces it, until we arrive at that triumph of historical evolution, the Prussian State. But they do not question the unique and supreme position of the State in the social hierarchy. Indeed that conception has hardened into unquestionable dogma under the title of sovereignty.
Hegel is a notable example of this field, but he’s not the only one. Many who have fiercely disagreed with him have only differed in the details of the "evolution" or in the specific meaning that should be seen as essential Begriff for some of the[Pg 201] listed institutions. The conflicts have been intense mainly because the foundational ideas were the same. In particular, many schools of thought, which vary even more in terms of methods and conclusions, have agreed on the ultimate position of the state. They might not go as far as Hegel in asserting that the sole meaning of history is the evolution of National Territorial States—each of which represents a more advanced form of the essential meaning or concept of the State and thus replaces the previous one, culminating in the success of historical evolution, the Prussian State. However, they do not challenge the unique and highest position of the State in the social hierarchy. In fact, that idea has solidified into an unquestionable belief under the term sovereignty.
There can be no doubt of the tremendously important rôle played by the modern territorial national state. The formation of these states has been the centre of modern political history. France, Great Britain, Spain were the first peoples to attain nationalistic organization, but in the nineteenth century their example was followed by Japan, Germany and Italy, to say nothing of a large number of smaller states, Greece, Servia, Bulgaria, etc. As everybody knows, one of the most important phases of the recent world war was the struggle to complete the nationalistic movement, resulting in the erection of Bohemia, Poland, etc., into independent[Pg 202] states, and the accession of Armenia, Palestine, etc., to the rank of candidates.
There’s no doubt about the hugely important role played by the modern territorial nation-state. The creation of these states has been at the heart of modern political history. France, Great Britain, and Spain were the first countries to achieve nationalistic organization, but in the nineteenth century, their example was followed by Japan, Germany, and Italy, not to mention a number of smaller states like Greece, Serbia, and Bulgaria. As everyone knows, one of the key phases of the recent world war was the struggle to complete the nationalistic movement, leading to the establishment of Bohemia, Poland, and other independent[Pg 202] states, and the rise of Armenia, Palestine, and others as candidates for independence.
The struggle for the supremacy of the State over other forms of organization was directed against the power of minor districts, provinces, principalities, against the dispersion of power among feudal lords as well as, in some countries, against the pretensions of an ecclesiastic potentate. The "State" represents the conspicuous culmination of the great movement of social integration and consolidation taking place in the last few centuries, tremendously accelerated by the concentrating and combining forces of steam and electricity. Naturally, inevitably, the students of political science have been preoccupied with this great historic phenomenon, and their intellectual activities have been directed to its systematic formulation. Because the contemporary progressive movement was to establish the unified state against the inertia of minor social units and against the ambitions of rivals for power, political theory developed the dogma of the sovereignty of the national state, internally and externally.
The fight for the dominance of the State over other types of organization targeted the authority of smaller districts, provinces, and principalities, opposing the distribution of power among feudal lords and, in some places, challenging the claims of powerful religious leaders. The "State" symbolizes the significant peak of the large movement of social integration and consolidation that has occurred over the past few centuries, greatly accelerated by the unifying forces of steam and electricity. Naturally, the students of political science have focused on this important historical phenomenon, directing their intellectual efforts toward its systematic understanding. Since the contemporary progressive movement aimed to establish a unified state against the resistance of smaller social units and the ambitions of rival powers, political theory developed the concept of the sovereignty of the national state, both internally and externally.
As the work of integration and consolidation reaches its climax, the question arises, however, whether the national state, once it is firmly established and no longer struggling against strong foes, is not just an instrumentality for promoting and protecting other and more voluntary forms of association, rather than a supreme[Pg 203] end in itself. Two actual phenomena may be pointed to in support of an affirmative answer. Along with the development of the larger, more inclusive and more unified organization of the state has gone the emancipation of individuals from restrictions and servitudes previously imposed by custom and class status. But the individuals freed from external and coercive bonds have not remained isolated. Social molecules have at once recombined in new associations and organizations. Compulsory associations have been replaced by voluntary ones; rigid organizations by those more amenable to human choice and purposes—more directly changeable at will. What upon one side looks like a movement toward individualism, turns out to be really a movement toward multiplying all kinds and varieties of associations: Political parties, industrial corporations, scientific and artistic organizations, trade unions, churches, schools, clubs and societies without number, for the cultivation of every conceivable interest that men have in common. As they develop in number and importance, the state tends to become more and more a regulator and adjuster among them; defining the limits of their actions, preventing and settling conflicts.
As the process of integrating and consolidating reaches its peak, a question arises: once the nation-state is firmly established and no longer facing strong opponents, is it really just a tool for promoting and protecting other, more voluntary forms of association, rather than an ultimate goal in itself? Two real phenomena can support a positive answer. Along with the growth of a larger, more inclusive, and unified state organization, individuals have gained freedom from the restrictions and servitudes that custom and class status previously imposed. However, these individuals, freed from external and coercive bonds, have not become isolated. Social groups have quickly reformed into new associations and organizations. Mandatory associations have been replaced by voluntary ones; rigid structures have given way to those that respond better to human choice and purposes—more easily changeable as needed. What may seem like a shift towards individualism is actually a shift towards creating a greater variety of associations: political parties, industrial corporations, scientific and artistic organizations, trade unions, churches, schools, clubs, and countless societies for fostering every interest that people share. As these associations grow in number and significance, the state increasingly becomes a regulator and mediator among them, defining the boundaries of their actions and preventing and resolving conflicts.
Its "supremacy" approximates that of the conductor of an orchestra, who makes no music himself but who harmonizes the activities of those who in producing it are doing the thing intrinsically worth while. The[Pg 204] state remains highly important—but its importance consists more and more in its power to foster and co-ordinate the activities of voluntary groupings. Only nominally is it in any modern community the end for the sake of which all the other societies and organizations exist. Groupings for promoting the diversity of goods that men share have become the real social units. They occupy the place which traditional theory has claimed either for mere isolated individuals or for the supreme and single political organization. Pluralism is well ordained in present political practice and demands a modification of hierarchical and monistic theory. Every combination of human forces that adds its own contribution of value to life has for that reason its own unique and ultimate worth. It cannot be degraded into a means to glorify the State. One reason for the increased demoralization of war is that it forces the State into an abnormally supreme position.
Its "supremacy" is similar to that of an orchestra conductor, who doesn't create music himself but harmonizes the efforts of those who are making it, which is what truly matters. The [Pg 204] state is still very important—but its significance is increasingly found in its ability to support and coordinate the activities of voluntary groups. In a modern community, it is only nominally the ultimate goal for which all other societies and organizations exist. Groups that promote the variety of goods shared by people have become the real social units. They take the place that traditional theory has assigned either to isolated individuals or to a singular, dominant political organization. Pluralism is well-established in today's political landscape and calls for a revision of hierarchical and monistic theories. Every combination of human forces that contributes its own value to life has its own unique and ultimate significance. It cannot be reduced to a means for glorifying the State. One reason for the rising disillusionment with war is that it forces the State into an uncharacteristically dominant role.
The other concrete fact is the opposition between the claim of independent sovereignty in behalf of the territorial national state and the growth of international and what have well been called trans-national interests. The weal and woe of any modern state is bound up with that of others. Weakness, disorder, false principles on the part of any state are not confined within its boundaries. They spread and infect other states. The same is true of economic, artistic and scientific advances.[Pg 205] Moreover the voluntary associations just spoken of do not coincide with political boundaries. Associations of mathematicians, chemists, astronomers; business corporations, labor organizations, churches are trans-national because the interests they represent are worldwide. In such ways as these, internationalism is not an aspiration but a fact, not a sentimental ideal but a force. Yet these interests are cut across and thrown out of gear by the traditional doctrine of exclusive national sovereignty. It is the vogue of this doctrine, or dogma, that presents the strongest barrier to the effective formation of an international mind which alone agrees with the moving forces of present-day labor, commerce, science, art and religion.
The other undeniable fact is the conflict between the idea of independent sovereignty for the territorial nation-state and the rise of international and what have been called transnational interests. The well-being of any modern state is connected to that of others. Weakness, chaos, and misguided principles in any state don't stay within its borders; they spread and affect other states. The same goes for economic, artistic, and scientific progress.[Pg 205] Furthermore, the voluntary associations just mentioned don't align with political boundaries. Groups of mathematicians, chemists, astronomers; businesses, labor unions, and churches operate on a transnational level because the interests they represent are global. In this sense, internationalism is not just an aspiration but a reality, not merely a sentimental ideal but a driving force. Yet, these interests are undermined and disrupted by the traditional idea of exclusive national sovereignty. The prevalence of this doctrine, or dogma, presents the biggest obstacle to effectively creating an international mindset that aligns with the driving forces of contemporary labor, commerce, science, art, and religion.
Society, as was said, is many associations not a single organization. Society means association; coming together in joint intercourse and action for the better realization of any form of experience which is augmented and confirmed by being shared. Hence there are as many associations as there are goods which are enhanced by being mutually communicated and participated in. And these are literally indefinite in number. Indeed, capacity to endure publicity and communication is the test by which it is decided whether a pretended good is genuine or spurious. Moralists have always insisted upon the fact that good is universal, objective, not just private, particular. But too often, like Plato,[Pg 206] they have been content with a metaphysical universality or, like Kant, with a logical universality. Communication, sharing, joint participation are the only actual ways of universalizing the moral law and end. We insisted at the last hour upon the unique character of every intrinsic good. But the counterpart of this proposition is that the situation in which a good is consciously realized is not one of transient sensations or private appetites but one of sharing and communication—public, social. Even the hermit communes with gods or spirits; even misery loves company; and the most extreme selfishness includes a band of followers or some partner to share in the attained good. Universalization means socialization, the extension of the area and range of those who share in a good.
Society, as mentioned, consists of many associations rather than being a single organization. Society means coming together; it's about interacting and acting together for a better understanding of any experience that is deepened and confirmed by being shared. Thus, there are as many associations as there are goods that are enhanced through mutual communication and participation, and these are literally countless. In fact, the ability to handle publicity and communication is the criterion that determines whether a supposed good is real or fake. Moralists have always pointed out that good is universal and objective, not just private or specific. But too often, like Plato, they settled for a metaphysical universality or, like Kant, a logical universality. Communication, sharing, and joint participation are the only true ways to universalize the moral law and objective. We emphasized, right up to the end, the unique nature of every intrinsic good. However, the flip side of this idea is that the context in which a good is consciously realized is not about fleeting sensations or private desires but about sharing and communication—public and social. Even a hermit connects with gods or spirits; even misery seeks companionship; and even the most extreme selfishness involves a group of followers or a partner to share in the achieved good. Universalization means socialization, extending the circle and range of those who share in a good.
The increasing acknowledgment that goods exist and endure only through being communicated and that association is the means of conjoint sharing lies back of the modern sense of humanity and democracy. It is the saving salt in altruism and philanthropy, which without this factor degenerate into moral condescension and moral interference, taking the form of trying to regulate the affairs of others under the guise of doing them good or of conferring upon them some right as if it were a gift of charity. It follows that organization is never an end in itself. It is a means of promoting asso[Pg 207]ciation, of multiplying effective points of contact between persons, directing their intercourse into the modes of greatest fruitfulness.
The growing recognition that goods only exist and thrive through communication, and that connection is the way we share together, is the foundation of our modern understanding of humanity and democracy. It's the essential ingredient in altruism and philanthropy, which, without this element, can turn into moral patronization and moral meddling. This often manifests as attempts to control other people’s affairs under the pretense of helping them or giving them rights as if they were charitable gifts. Therefore, organization is never an end in itself. It is a way to promote asso[Pg 207]ciation, to create more effective connections between people, and to guide their interactions towards the most fruitful outcomes.
The tendency to treat organization as an end in itself is responsible for all the exaggerated theories in which individuals are subordinated to some institution to which is given the noble name of society. Society is the process of associating in such ways that experiences, ideas, emotions, values are transmitted and made common. To this active process, both the individual and the institutionally organized may truly be said to be subordinate. The individual is subordinate because except in and through communication of experience from and to others, he remains dumb, merely sentient, a brute animal. Only in association with fellows does he become a conscious centre of experience. Organization, which is what traditional theory has generally meant by the term Society or State, is also subordinate because it becomes static, rigid, institutionalized whenever it is not employed to facilitate and enrich the contacts of human beings with one another.
The tendency to see organization as an end in itself leads to all the exaggerated theories where individuals are placed below some institution that's given the lofty title of society. Society is the process of connecting in ways that share experiences, ideas, emotions, and values. In this active process, both individuals and organized institutions can be considered subordinate. The individual is subordinate because, unless they communicate experiences with others, they remain silent, merely sentient, like a brute animal. It's only through association with others that they become a conscious hub of experience. Organization—which is what traditional theory usually refers to as Society or State—is also subordinate because it becomes static, rigid, and institutionalized whenever it isn't used to foster and enhance connections between people.
The long-time controversy between rights and duties, law and freedom is another version of the strife between the Individual and Society as fixed concepts. Freedom for an individual means growth, ready change when modification is required.
The long-standing debate between rights and responsibilities, law and freedom is just another version of the conflict between the Individual and Society as established ideas. For an individual, freedom means personal growth and the ability to adapt when changes are necessary.
It signifies an active process, that of release of[Pg 208] capacity from whatever hems it in. But since society can develop only as new resources are put at its disposal, it is absurd to suppose that freedom has positive significance for individuality but negative meaning for social interests. Society is strong, forceful, stable against accident only when all its members can function to the limit of their capacity. Such functioning cannot be achieved without allowing a leeway of experimentation beyond the limits of established and sanctioned custom. A certain amount of overt confusion and irregularity is likely to accompany the granting of the margin of liberty without which capacity cannot find itself. But socially as well as scientifically the great thing is not to avoid mistakes but to have them take place under conditions such that they can be utilized to increase intelligence in the future.
It represents an active process, the release of[Pg 208] capability from whatever restricts it. However, since society can only grow as new resources become available, it's unrealistic to think that freedom has a positive impact on individuality but a negative effect on social interests. Society is strong, effective, and resilient only when all its members can operate to their full potential. This level of functioning can't be achieved without allowing some experimentation beyond the boundaries of established and accepted norms. A certain degree of overt confusion and irregularity is likely to come with granting the freedom needed for capability to be realized. But, both socially and scientifically, the key is not to avoid mistakes but to ensure they occur in ways that can be used to enhance intelligence in the future.
If British liberal social philosophy tended, true to the spirit of its atomistic empiricism, to make freedom and the exercise of rights ends in themselves, the remedy is not to be found in recourse to a philosophy of fixed obligations and authoritative law such as characterized German political thinking. The latter, as events have demonstrated, is dangerous because of its implicit menace to the free self-determination of other social groups. But it is also weak internally when put to the final test. In its hostility to the free experimentation and power of choice of the individual in determining[Pg 209] social affairs, it limits the capacity of many or most individuals to share effectively in social operations, and thereby deprives society of the full contribution of all its members. The best guarantee of collective efficiency and power is liberation and use of the diversity of individual capacities in initiative, planning, foresight, vigor and endurance. Personality must be educated, and personality cannot be educated by confining its operations to technical and specialized things, or to the less important relationships of life. Full education comes only when there is a responsible share on the part of each person, in proportion to capacity, in shaping the aims and policies of the social groups to which he belongs. This fact fixes the significance of democracy. It cannot be conceived as a sectarian or racial thing nor as a consecration of some form of government which has already attained constitutional sanction. It is but a name for the fact that human nature is developed only when its elements take part in directing things which are common, things for the sake of which men and women form groups—families, industrial companies, governments, churches, scientific associations and so on. The principle holds as much of one form of association, say in industry and commerce, as it does in government. The identification of democracy with political democracy which is responsible for most of its failures is, however, based upon the traditional ideas which make the[Pg 210] individual and the state ready-made entities in themselves.
If British liberal social philosophy tended, true to its atomistic empiricism, to view freedom and the exercise of rights as ends in themselves, the solution is not to revert to a philosophy of fixed obligations and authoritative law, which characterized German political thought. The latter has been proven dangerous due to its implicit threat to the free self-determination of other social groups. However, it is also weak internally when put to the ultimate test. By opposing the free experimentation and the individual's power of choice in determining[Pg 209] social affairs, it limits many or most individuals' ability to engage effectively in social operations, thereby depriving society of the full contributions of all its members. The best guarantee of collective efficiency and power is the liberation and utilization of individual diverse capabilities in initiative, planning, foresight, vigor, and endurance. Personality must be nurtured, and it cannot be developed by restricting its activities to technical and specialized tasks, or to the less significant relationships in life. True education only happens when everyone is responsibly involved, according to their capacity, in shaping the goals and policies of the social groups they are part of. This underscores the importance of democracy. It cannot be thought of as a sectarian or racial concept nor as an endorsement of some already accepted form of government. It simply represents the idea that human nature develops only when its components take part in directing common interests, the reasons for which people form groups—families, businesses, governments, churches, scientific associations, and so on. This principle is applicable to all forms of association, including industry and commerce, just as it is in government. However, the association of democracy solely with political democracy accounts for many of its failures, as it is based on traditional ideas that view the[Pg 210] individual and the state as predefined entities.
As the new ideas find adequate expression in social life, they will be absorbed into a moral background, and will the ideas and beliefs themselves be deepened and be unconsciously transmitted and sustained. They will color the imagination and temper the desires and affections. They will not form a set of ideas to be expounded, reasoned out and argumentatively supported, but will be a spontaneous way of envisaging life. Then they will take on religious value. The religious spirit will be revivified because it will be in harmony with men's unquestioned scientific beliefs and their ordinary day-by-day social activities. It will not be obliged to lead a timid, half-concealed and half-apologetic life because tied to scientific ideas and social creeds that are continuously eaten into and broken down. But especially will the ideas and beliefs themselves be deepened and intensified because spontaneously fed by emotion and translated into imaginative vision and fine art, while they are now maintained by more or less conscious effort, by deliberate reflection, by taking thought. They are technical and abstract just because they are not as yet carried as matter of course by imagination and feelings.
As new ideas find their place in society, they will blend into a moral framework, which will deepen these ideas and beliefs, transmitting and sustaining them unconsciously. They will shape our imagination and influence our desires and emotions. They won’t just be a collection of concepts to be explained, analyzed, and debated; rather, they will become a natural way of viewing life. At that point, they will gain religious significance. The religious spirit will be revitalized because it will align with people’s undisputed scientific beliefs and their everyday social interactions. It won’t have to lead a cautious, hidden, or apologetic existence, tethered to scientific ideas and social norms that are constantly challenged and broken down. Moreover, the ideas and beliefs will be deepened and intensified, fueled by emotions and transformed into imaginative expression and fine art, rather than being upheld through conscious effort, deliberate reflection, or careful thought. They are technical and abstract mainly because they are not yet instinctively carried by imagination and feelings.
We began by pointing out that European philosophy arose when intellectual methods and scientific results[Pg 211] moved away from social traditions which had consolidated and embodied the fruits of spontaneous desire and fancy. It was pointed out that philosophy had ever since had the problem of adjusting the dry, thin and meagre scientific standpoint with the obstinately persisting body of warm and abounding imaginative beliefs. Conceptions of possibility, progress, free movement and infinitely diversified opportunity have been suggested by modern science. But until they have displaced from imagination the heritage of the immutable and the once-for-all ordered and systematized, the ideas of mechanism and matter will lie like a dead weight upon the emotions, paralyzing religion and distorting art. When the liberation of capacity no longer seems a menace to organization and established institutions, something that cannot be avoided practically and yet something that is a threat to conservation of the most precious values of the past, when the liberating of human capacity operates as a socially creative force, art will not be a luxury, a stranger to the daily occupations of making a living. Making a living economically speaking, will be at one with making a life that is worth living. And when the emotional force, the mystic force one might say, of communication, of the miracle of shared life and shared experience is spontaneously felt, the hardness and crudeness of contemporary life will be bathed in the light that never was on land or sea.
We started by noting that European philosophy emerged when intellectual methods and scientific findings[Pg 211] drifted away from social traditions that had solidified and captured the outcomes of natural desire and imagination. It was highlighted that philosophy has since faced the challenge of reconciling the dry, narrow, and insufficient scientific perspective with the stubbornly enduring body of rich and vibrant imaginative beliefs. Modern science has introduced concepts of possibility, progress, free movement, and countless opportunities. However, until these concepts replace in imagination the legacy of the unchanging and the meticulously organized and structured, the notions of mechanism and matter will weigh heavily on emotions, stifling religion and warping art. When the freeing of human potential no longer appears as a threat to organization and established institutions—something unavoidable yet perceived as a danger to preserving the most valuable aspects of the past—when that liberation turns into a force for social creativity, art will no longer be a luxury, nor an outsider to the everyday struggle for survival. Earning a living, in economic terms, will align with creating a life that is genuinely worth living. And when the emotional and mystical power of connection, of the miracle of shared life and experiences, is genuinely felt, the harshness and brutality of contemporary life will be illuminated by a light that has never existed on land or sea.
Poetry, art, religion are precious things. They cannot be maintained by lingering in the past and futilely wishing to restore what the movement of events in science, industry and politics has destroyed. They are an out-flowering of thought and desires that unconsciously converge into a disposition of imagination as a result of thousands and thousands of daily episodes and contact. They cannot be willed into existence or coerced into being. The wind of the spirit bloweth where it listeth and the kingdom of God in such things does not come with observation. But while it is impossible to retain and recover by deliberate volition old sources of religion and art that have been discredited, it is possible to expedite the development of the vital sources of a religion and art that are yet to be. Not indeed by action directly aimed at their production, but by substituting faith in the active tendencies of the day for dread and dislike of them, and by the courage of intelligence to follow whither social and scientific changes direct us. We are weak today in ideal matters because intelligence is divorced from aspiration. The bare force of circumstance compels us onwards in the daily detail of our beliefs and acts, but our deeper thoughts and desires turn backwards. When philosophy shall have co-operated with the course of events and made clear and coherent the meaning of the daily detail, science and emotion will interpenetrate, practice and[Pg 213] imagination will embrace. Poetry and religious feeling will be the unforced flowers of life. To further this articulation and revelation of the meanings of the current course of events is the task and problem of philosophy in days of transition.
Poetry, art, and religion are valuable. They can't survive by clinging to the past and fruitlessly wishing to bring back what science, industry, and politics have already changed. They emerge from thoughts and desires that come together in our imagination through countless daily experiences and interactions. They can't be created through sheer will or force. The spirit moves where it wants, and the realm of God in these matters doesn’t come with visible signs. While it's impossible to hold onto and recover old sources of religion and art that have lost their credibility, we can help develop new sources of religion and art that are yet to emerge. Not by trying to directly create them, but by replacing fear and dislike of current trends with faith in their potential and having the courage to follow where social and scientific changes lead us. We're currently lacking in ideals because our intelligence is disconnected from our aspirations. Life’s circumstances push us forward in our daily beliefs and actions, but our deeper thoughts and desires pull us back. When philosophy collaborates with the flow of events and clarifies the meaning of our daily experiences, science and emotion will blend, and practice and imagination will unite. Poetry and spirituality will naturally thrive as expressions of life. Fostering this understanding and revelation of the meanings behind our current experiences is the challenge and focus of philosophy during times of change.
INDEX
Absolute reality, 23, 27
Absolutism, 97, 190;
Kant and, 99
Abstract definition, 20
Abstractions, 149-150, 174
Absurdities, 10
Achievements, 194
Action, kind of, 80
Adult life, 185, 186
America, 41
Amoeba, 91
Animals, dramatisation in primitive life of man, 4
Antiquity, 33
Apprehension, 142
Aquinas, 55, 106
Argumentation, 31, 132
Aristotle, 13, 17, 19, 55;
Bacon's charge against, 30-31, 36;
distinction in ends, 171;
experience, 79, 80;
forms, 105;
on change, 107;
on philosophy as contemplation, 109, 110;
on slavery, 191;
theory of the state, 44;
ultimate reality, 106
Art, 34, 103, 211, 212
Artisan, 15;
knowledge, 110
Associations, 205;
voluntary, 203
Astronomers, 65, 113
Astronomy, 75
Athenians, 13, 19
Augustine, St., 111
Authority, 48, 139, 195;
final, 161;
seat of, 160.
See also Final good
Bacon, Francis, 28, 81, 97;
criticism of the learning of his day, 29-30;
experience, 97-98;
"knowledge is power," 29;
summary of ideas, 29
Being, perfect, 111
Being and non-being, 107
Beliefs and facts, 12
Bentham, 166, 182, 188
Bergson, 71
Berkeley, 50
Biology, 75, 84
Bliss, 111, 112
Bosanquet, 134
Bradley, 107
Bruno, 66
Business, 41, 43, 183
Butler, Bishop, 21
Capital, 43
Capital and labour, 191
Capitalism, 41, 182
Castes, material, 59
Casuistry, 166
Causation, 63
Causes, 59, 60
Certainty, 21, 22
Change, ancient idea of, 57;
existing view, 113;
law of the universe, 61;
Plato and Aristotle on, 107;
progress and, 116
Chemistry, 75
Child life, 91-92, 184
Christian mediaeval philosophy, 17, 19
Christian theology, 111
Church, 47;
universal, 45
Classes, 75, 152, 155;
in the ancient conception of the world, 59
[Pg 218]
Classic conception of philosophy, 17, 22, 24, 74, 105
Classification, 152, 169
Common sense, 100
Communication at a distance, 118, 120
Comte, Auguste, 10
Conceptions, 81, 144, 145;
reconstruction in, moral, 161;
truth, 156
Concrete cases, in morals, 161;
in social philosophy, 188
Concreteness, 150
Condillac, 81
Conduct, 80;
right course, 163
Conflict, 108, 138, 140;
of ends, 166
Conscience, 46
Consequences, investigating, 163-164
Conservatism, 18, 33, 40, 100
Constant, 61
Contemplation, 109, 111
Contract theory of the state, 45
Control, 42, 64
Co-operation in research, 37
Cosmogonies and cosmologies, 9
Cosmology, 70, 75
Craftsmen, 12, 13
Criteria, 77
Crusades, 39
Cults, 8;
consolidation, 9
Custom, 17, 161
Dante, 55
Darwin, 75
Deduction, 148
Delusions, 139
Democracy, 47, 186, 206;
of facts, 66;
significance, 209
Demonstration, 20, 21, 31;
discovery vs., 32
Descartes, 50
Desires, 110, 111;
frustration, 104
Details, 141
Development, Aristotle's use of term, 57, 58
Diagnosis, 142
Direction, 176
Disagreeable, 103
Discipline, 103, 104, 184
Discord, 108
Discovery, contacts of 16th and 17th centuries, 39;
demonstration vs., 32;
logic of, 31, 33;
moral, 174
Distance, 118-119, 120
Doctrines, 8;
consolidation, 9
Dogma, 145, 159
Dreams, 119, 120, 139;
world of, 7
Dualism, 173
Duties and rights, 207
Earth, ancient conception, 55;
relation to universe, 66
Economic ends, 171-172
Education, 125, 183, 209
Efficient cause, 59, 60
Emotion, 103, 210
Empirical and rational, 81, 87
Empiricists, 78, 82
Ends, conflicting, 166;
fixed, 70;
intrinsic and instrumental, 170, 172-173;
means and, 72-73;
values, 175
English empiricism, 99
Environment, 10;
life and, 84
Epistemology, 49, 70, 123, 126
Errors, 35
Esthetic and practical, 66
Estheticism, 115-116, 117, 180;
science and, reconciling, 127
Ether, 55, 56
Ethical theory, 161
Europe, nationalistic movement, 201;
social cause of intellectual revolution in 16th and 17th centuries, 38-39
Evil, problem of, 177
Evolution, in Aristotle, 58;
of the state, 200-201
Existence, two realms, 22
[Pg 219]
Experience, 32;
as a guide in science and moral life, 78;
basis of old notion of, 79;
changed conceptions, 77;
classic notion and modern, 81;
combined doing and suffering, 86;
evil result of unimaginative conception of, 100-101;
Greek, 79;
modern appeal to, 48;
new conception, 83;
Plato, 92;
principles and, 48;
self-regulative, 94-95;
true "stuff" of, 91
Experimental method, 13
Experimentation, 42
Exploration, 39, 40
Facing facts, 140, 141, 143
Facts, 10, 98
Falsity, 158
Family principle, 189;
in the world at large, 61-62
Fanaticism, 168
Fancy. See Imagination
Fear, 40
Feudalism, 43, 45;
of the universe in ancient conception, 59, 61-62
Fighting, 15
Final cause, 59, 60, 68
Final good, 161-162, 183;
existence of a single good questioned, 162
Fine arts, 126
Finite, 107
Finite and infinite, 66
Fire, 11, 56, 86
Fixed ends, 165
Flux, 57, 108
Formal cause, 59, 60
Forms of Aristotle, 105
Free will, 196
Freedom, law and, 207;
religious, 46
Future, 48
Future aim of philosophy, 26
General notions, in morals, 161;
in social philosophy, 188
Generalities, 174;
social affairs and, 198
Generalisations, 10, 151
Geology, 75
German political philosophy, 200, 208-209
German rationalism, 99
Germans, system, order, docility, 98-99
Germany, 19
God, 10, 109
Golden Age, 48
Good. See Final good
Goodness, 179
Greeks, 9, 13, 19, 66, 67, 126;
ethical theory, 161;
religion, 105;
science and arts, 93
Growth, 184;
of knowledge, 31;
moral, 177
Happiness, 179
Healthy living, 166, 167, 177
Heavens, ancient conception, 56
Hegel, 19, 106, 189, 190;
conception of the state, 200, 201;
logic, 134
Helvetius, 81
Hierarchical order, 59
"Higher" ends, 172
Hindoos, 126
History, Hegel's conception, 201
History of philosophy, 25
Hobbes, 88, 188
Homo faber, 71
Human aims, 42, 43
Human life, "real" and "ideal," a live issue, 128
Humanism and naturalism, 174
Humanity, 206
Hume, 50, 83, 89
Hypotheses, 22, 145
Hysteria, 139
Ideal, changed conceptions, 103;
[Pg 220]problem of relation to the real, 130;
real and, a human issue, 128
Ideal realm, classic and modern conceptions contrasted, 118
Idealism, 129;
epistemological, 49, 51;
theological, 50;
tragic kind, 129-130
Ideality, one with reality, 111;
philosophic conception, 106
Ideas of Plato, 105
Idols, 36
Ills, 169;
philosophy and, 177-178
Imagination, 211;
empirical knowledge and, 73, 74;
reshaping power, 103, 106
Independence, 110;
social, 185
India, 41
Individual, 36, 45, 51;
concept as something given, 193;
in social and moral sense, 194;
social and, 199;
state and, 190, 191
Individualism, 50;
political, 45, 46;
religious, 46;
religious and moral, 46
Induction, 34
Industrial revolution and scientific revolution, 38, 41
Industry, movements, 47;
science and, 38, 41, 42
Infinite, 66, 67
Initiative 46, 209
Innate ideas, 35, 82
Inquiry, 174;
free, 146;
impartial, 147;
methods in moral ills, 170
Insincerity, 20
Instability, 107
Institutions, 196;
true starting-points of inquiry about, 197
Instrumental ends, 171
Intellect, 6
Intellectual somnambulism, 140
Intellectualism, 117
Intelligence, 36, 51;
as inquiry into consequences, 163-164;
definition, 96
Interest, 194-195
International interests, 204, 205
Intrinsic good, 170, 206
Introspection, 196
Invention, 39, 42, 49, 122
Investigation, 147
Ipse dixit method, 166
Irresponsibility, 97
James, William, 21;
Pragmatism, 38
Judea, 9
Judgment, 133;
moral, 176;
standards, 175
Kant, 50, 83, 98, 206;
his philosophy and German character, 98-99
Kinship, 62
Knowledge, conception as beholding, 115;
degrees, 108;
empirical as organ of imagination, 73, 74;
existing practice, 112;
modern view of right way to get it, 113;
positive, 12;
positive vs. tradition, 16;
practical and operative, 121, 122;
sensations and, 87, 88, 89;
spectator conception, 112, 117
"Knowledge is power," 29, 42, 51
Law, 61, 64;
freedom and, 207;
reason and, 98.
See also Final good
Learning, Bacon's three kinds, 29
Licentiousness, 163
Life, 167, 211;
environment and, 84-85
Literary culture, 39
Locke, 35, 50, 81, 89, 152;
philosophic empiricism, 82
Logic, a science and an art, 135;
apparatus, 20, 21;
character, 132, 134;
[Pg 221]importance, 138;
in morals and politics, 138;
inconsistencies, 134;
new, 36;
of discovery, 33;
of discovery vs. that of argumentation, 31;
theory, chaotic state, 133
Logical system, 9
Lotze, 134
Making a living, 211
Man, perfectibility, 49;
primitive, 4, 5;
savage and civilized, 85;
tool-maker, 71
Marcus Aurelius, 106
Materialism, 50, 70, 73, 171, 182
Mathematics, 137, 149
Matter, 72, 211
Means and ends, 72-73
Mechanics, 67, 69;
Greeks and, 67
Mechanism, 211
Mechanisation of nature, 71-72
Mediaeval Christianity, 17, 19, 126
Meliorism, 178
Memory, 1, 6, 103;
emotional character, 2;
individual and group, 8;
primitive, 3
Metaphysics, 17, 124, 126
Methods, 149;
social philosophy, 193;
true, 32
Middle Ages, 47, 64, 132
Military art, 15
Mill, J. S., 132
Mind, pure, 111
Miracles, 125
Mistakes, 175
Modern thought, 52;
Bacon as founder, 28;
early, 49, 50.
See also Thought
Mohammedans, 39
Moral ends, 169
Moral life, 165
Moral science. See under Science
Morality, pragmatic rule, 163;
standard of judgment, 176
Morals, 126, 169;
politics and, 197
National state, 200;
end or instrument, 202-203;
rôle of the modern, 201
Nationalistic movement, 201
Natural Science. See under Science
Naturalism and humanism, 174
Nature, contrast of ancient and modern conceptions, 53-54;
inquiry into, 32, 37, 48, 49;
loss of poetry when considered as mechanism, 69;
profound change in man's attitude to, 115;
value of mechanisation, 71-72;
web imposed on, 35-36
Neglect, 97
Neo-Platonism, 111
New World, 39
Non-being, 107
Noumenal reality, 23
Nous, 36
Obliviscence of the disagreeable, 103
Observation, 140
Optimism, 178
Opportunity, 211
Organic society, 187
Organisms, 86
Organisation, 206-207
Oriental nations, 127
Origin of philosophies, 5, 18, 24, 25
Pantheon, Greek, 105
Past, 212
Perfectibility of mankind, 49
Perfection, 177
Personality, 47, 189, 209
Persuasion, 31
Pessimism, 178
Phariseeism, 176
[Pg 222]
Phenomenal reality, 23
Philosophy, emancipation, 123;
function, 111, 122;
future aim and scope, 26;
hard and fast alternatives of English and German schools, 99-100;
history, 25;
opportunities, 49;
origin, 5, 18, 24, 25;
practical nature, 121;
proper province, 21, 124;
work, 18
Physician, 168
Physics, 75
Plato, 13, 14, 17, 19, 188, 205;
dramatic sense, 15;
experience, 79, 92;
ideas, ideal realm, 105;
on change, 107;
social arts, 94;
ultimate reality, 106
Pleasure, 181
Plotinus, 106
Pluralism, 204
Poetry, 7, 8, 103, 212
Political changes, 43
Political organisation, 44
Politics, 125;
morals and, 197;
movements, 47
Possession of knowledge, 31
Potentiality, Aristotle's use of term, 57, 58
Practical and esthetic, 66
Pragmatism, 38
Pretensions, 21
Primitive man, 4
Principles, 81, 163;
criteria of experience, 48
Probability, 21
Production, 181
Progress, 42, 48, 116, 211;
Bacon and, 32, 34;
economic and moral, contrast, 125
Proof, 20
Property, 182, 189
Protestantism, 46
Proudhon, 189
Prussian State, 190, 201
Psychology, 83, 135;
change in, 84;
malicious, 82
Pure reason, 78
Questioning, 17. See also Inquiry
Radicalism, 18, 19, 100
Rank, 63
Rationalism, 97;
rigidity, 98
Rationalists 87, 88, 89
Rationalisation, 97, 102
Real, changed conceptions, 103;
ideal and, a human issue, 128;
problem of relation to the ideal, 130
Reality, 23, 27;
classic conception, 105;
nomenal vs. phenomenal, 23;
ultimate, 106;
ultimate, one with ideality, 111
Reason, 83, 174;
as a faculty separate from experience, 95;
as re-adjusting intelligence, 96;
changed conceptions, 77
Reasoning, 32
Reconstruction of philosophy, 52;
essential, 51;
historical factors, 28;
in moral conceptions, 161;
scientific factor, 53;
social philosophy and, 187;
specific present problem, 43;
value of a solution of the dilemma of reason and experience, 101
Re-creation, 51, 180
Reform, 179, 180;
starting-point, 196
Relativity of sensations, 88
Religion, 103, 211, 212;
movements, 47
Religious freedom, 46
Religious spirit, 210
Renaissance, 29
Research, 42;
co-operative, 37
Responsibility, 163
Revolution of thought, 60
Rights and duties, 207
[Pg 223]
Rome, 9
Ruler and subject, 44;
in nature, 64
Rules of conduct, 165
Sailors, 11
Salvation, 112
Santayana, George, on Locke, 82
Satisfaction, 157
Savage, 85, 176
Scholasticism, 30
Science, 11, 23;
advance in, 53;
co-operative pursuit, 37;
estheticism and, reconciling, 127;
human value, 173;
industry and, 38, 41, 42;
natural, 42, 48;
open world of, 61;
origin, 12;
picture of universe, 64-65;
relation to experience, 95;
separation of natural and moral, 173;
so-called, 36;
traditional, 30
Scientific revolution, 53
Self-delusion, 140
Self-interest, 194-195
Sensations, 84;
as points of readjustment, 89;
relativity, 88
Senses, 84, 87
Sentimentalism, 73
Shakespeare, 94
Slavery, 191
Social belief, 26
Social development, 43
Social evils, 182.
See also Ills
Social philosophy, reconstruction, 187;
reconstructive impact, 193
Social unit, real, 204
Social welfare, 180
Sociality, 185
Society, 200, 205;
defect of usual theories about, 188;
individuals and, three views, 187-188;
philosophy and, 124
Socrates, 14, 17
Soldiers, 139
Sophists, 13, 14
Space, 118-119, 120
Spinoza, 106
Standards, 175
State, Aristotle's theory, 44;
contract theory, 45;
current conception, 200;
importance, 204;
individual and, 190, 191;
modern, 44;
origin, 44;
supremacy, 202, 203
Subject and ruler, 44;
in nature, 64
Success, 179
Suggestions, 3, 6, 7
Summum Bonum. See Final good
Supernaturalism, 47
System, 98, 99
Telegraph, 120
Telephone, 120
Terminology, 21
Theories, 144, 145;
validity, 156
Theory and practice, 140
Things as they are, 115
Thinking, habits, 74, 75.
See also Thought
Thomas, St. See Aquinas
Thought, 117;
good and bad thinking, 136;
instrumental nature, 145-146;
its origin in difficulties, 138-139;
kinds, 135;
logic and, 134;
place, 96;
systems, 145
Tolerance, 46
Tradition, 14;
positive knowledge vs., 16
Transitoriousness, 106
Travel, 39, 40
Trouble, 138, 140
Truth, as utility, 157;
defining, 159-160;
logical conception, 156-157;
old and new, 33, 34;
pragmatic conception, 156, 159;
test of, nature of, 155, 166;
why the modern conception is offensive, 157, 158
[Pg 224]
Unity, 108
Universal, 64
Universe, closed conception, 54
Utilitarianism, defects, 181;
merit, 180;
need of reconstruction, 183
Utility, 157
Valves, 15
Verification, 156
Virtues, 164
Vision, 21
War, 204
War, world, lesson, 129;
nationalistic phase, 201;
"real" and "ideal" in, 128
Wealth, 40, 42, 125
Wind, 11
Work, 181
Workingmen, 139
World, closed and open conceptions, 54, 60-61;
modern conception as material for change, 114;
nomenal and phenomenal, 23
Absolute reality, 23, 27
Absolutism, 97, 190;
Kant and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Abstract definition, 20
Abstractions, 149-150, 174
Absurdities, 10
Achievements, 194
Action, type of, 80
Adult life, 185, 186
America, 41
Amoeba, 91
Animals, dramatization in primitive life of man, 4
Antiquity, 33
Apprehension, 142
Aquinas, 55, 106
Argumentation, 31, 132
Aristotle, 13, 17, 19, 55;
Bacon's critique of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__;
distinction in purposes, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
experience, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
forms, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
on change, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
on philosophy as reflection, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
on slavery, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
theory of the state, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
ultimate reality, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Art, 34, 103, 211, 212
Artisan, 15;
knowledge, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Associations, 205;
voluntary, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Astronomers, 65, 113
Astronomy, 75
Athenians, 13, 19
Augustine, St., 111
Authority, 48, 139, 195;
final, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
seat of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.
Check this out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Bacon, Francis, 28, 81, 97;
critique of the knowledge of his time, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
experience, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
"Knowledge is power," __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
summary of ideas, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Being, perfect, 111
Being and non-being, 107
Beliefs and facts, 12
Bentham, 166, 182, 188
Bergson, 71
Berkeley, 50
Biology, 75, 84
Bliss, 111, 112
Bosanquet, 134
Bradley, 107
Bruno, 66
Business, 41, 43, 183
Butler, Bishop, 21
Capital, 43
Capital and labor, 191
Capitalism, 41, 182
Castes, material, 59
Casuistry, 166
Causation, 63
Causes, 59, 60
Certainty, 21, 22
Change, ancient idea of, 57;
current view, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
universal law, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
Plato and Aristotle, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
progress and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Chemistry, 75
Child life, 91-92, 184
Christian medieval philosophy, 17, 19
Christian theology, 111
Church, 47;
universal, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Classes, 75, 152, 155;
In the ancient perspective on the world, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
[Pg 218]
Classic view of philosophy, 17, 22, 24, 74, 105
Classification, 152, 169
Common sense, 100
Communication at a distance, 118, 120
Comte, Auguste, 10
Conceptions, 81, 144, 145;
reconstruction in, ethical, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
truth, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Concrete cases, in morals, 161;
in social philosophy, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Concreteness, 150
Condillac, 81
Conduct, 80;
right path, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Conflict, 108, 138, 140;
of purposes, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Conscience, 46
Consequences, investigating, 163-164
Conservatism, 18, 33, 40, 100
Constant, 61
Contemplation, 109, 111
Contract theory of the state, 45
Control, 42, 64
Cooperation in research, 37
Cosmogonies and cosmologies, 9
Cosmology, 70, 75
Craftsmen, 12, 13
Criteria, 77
Crusades, 39
Cults, 8;
consolidation, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Custom, 17, 161
Dante, 55
Darwin, 75
Deduction, 148
Delusions, 139
Democracy, 47, 186, 206;
of facts, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
importance, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Demonstration, 20, 21, 31;
discovery vs. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Descartes, 50
Desires, 110, 111;
frustration, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Details, 141
Development, Aristotle's use of the term, 57, 58
Diagnosis, 142
Direction, 176
Disagreeable, 103
Discipline, 103, 104, 184
Discord, 108
Discovery, contacts of 16th and 17th centuries, 39;
demonstration vs. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
logic of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
moral lesson, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Distance, 118-119, 120
Doctrines, 8;
consolidation, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Dogma, 145, 159
Dreams, 119, 120, 139;
world of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Dualism, 173
Duties and rights, 207
Earth, ancient conception, 55;
relation to the universe, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Economic ends, 171-172
Education, 125, 183, 209
Efficient cause, 59, 60
Emotion, 103, 210
Empirical and rational, 81, 87
Empiricists, 78, 82
Ends, conflicting, 166;
fixed, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
intrinsic and instrumental, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__;
means and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
values, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
English empiricism, 99
Environment, 10;
life and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Epistemology, 49, 70, 123, 126
Errors, 35
Aesthetic and practical, 66
Aestheticism, 115-116, 117, 180;
science and reconciling __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Ether, 55, 56
Ethical theory, 161
Europe, nationalistic movement, 201;
The social factors behind the intellectual revolution in the 16th and 17th centuries, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Evil, problem of, 177
Evolution, in Aristotle, 58;
of the state, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Existence, two realms, 22
[Pg 219]
Experience, 32;
as a guide in science and moral living, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
basis of the old idea of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
changed ideas, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
classic idea and modern, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
combined doing and suffering, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
the negative outcome of a lack of creative thinking about __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
Greek, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
modern appeal to, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
new idea, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
Plato, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
principles and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
self-regulating, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
real "stuff" of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Experimental method, 13
Experimentation, 42
Exploration, 39, 40
Facing facts, 140, 141, 143
Facts, 10, 98
Falsity, 158
Family principle, 189;
in the broader world, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Fanaticism, 168
Fancy. See Imagination
Fear, 40
Feudalism, 43, 45;
of the universe in ancient understanding, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__
Fighting, 15
Final cause, 59, 60, 68
Final good, 161-162, 183;
the existence of a single good is questioned, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Fine arts, 126
Finite, 107
Finite and infinite, 66
Fire, 11, 56, 86
Fixed ends, 165
Flux, 57, 108
Formal cause, 59, 60
Forms of Aristotle, 105
Free will, 196
Freedom, law and, 207;
religious, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Future, 48
Future aim of philosophy, 26
General notions, in morals, 161;
in social philosophy, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Generalities, 174;
social issues and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Generalisations, 10, 151
Geology, 75
German political philosophy, 200, 208-209
German rationalism, 99
Germans, system, order, docility, 98-99
Germany, 19
God, 10, 109
Golden Age, 48
Good. See Final good
Goodness, 179
Greeks, 9, 13, 19, 66, 67, 126;
ethical theory, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
religion, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
science and arts, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Growth, 184;
of knowledge, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
moral, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Happiness, 179
Healthy living, 166, 167, 177
Heavens, ancient conception, 56
Hegel, 19, 106, 189, 190;
conception of the state, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
logic, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Helvetius, 81
Hierarchical order, 59
"Higher" ends, 172
Hindoos, 126
History, Hegel's conception, 201
History of philosophy, 25
Hobbes, 88, 188
Homo faber, 71
Human aims, 42, 43
Human life, "real" and "ideal," a live issue, 128
Humanism and naturalism, 174
Humanity, 206
Hume, 50, 83, 89
Hypotheses, 22, 145
Hysteria, 139
Ideal, changed conceptions, 103;
[Pg 220]the issue of connecting to reality, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
real and a human issue, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Ideal realm, classic and modern conceptions contrasted, 118
Idealism, 129;
epistemological, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
theological, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
tragic type, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Ideality, one with reality, 111;
philosophical concept, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Ideas of Plato, 105
Idols, 36
Ills, 169;
philosophy and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Imagination, 211;
empirical knowledge and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
reshaping power, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Independence, 110;
social, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
India, 41
Individual, 36, 45, 51;
concept as something given, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
in social and moral terms, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
social and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
state and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Individualism, 50;
political, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
religious, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
spiritual and ethical, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Induction, 34
Industrial revolution and scientific revolution, 38, 41
Industry, movements, 47;
science and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__
Infinite, 66, 67
Initiative 46, 209
Innate ideas, 35, 82
Inquiry, 174;
free, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
fair, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
methods in ethical issues, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Insincerity, 20
Instability, 107
Institutions, 196;
true starting points for inquiry about, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Instrumental ends, 171
Intellect, 6
Intellectual somnambulism, 140
Intellectualism, 117
Intelligence, 36, 51;
as inquiry into consequences, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
definition, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Interest, 194-195
International interests, 204, 205
Intrinsic good, 170, 206
Introspection, 196
Invention, 39, 42, 49, 122
Investigation, 147
Ipse dixit method, 166
Irresponsibility, 97
James, William, 21;
Practicality, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Judea, 9
Judgment, 133;
moral, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
standards, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Kant, 50, 83, 98, 206;
his philosophy and German traits, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Kinship, 62
Knowledge, conception as perception, 115;
degrees, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
empirical as a tool of imagination, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
current practice, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
modern perspective on the proper way to obtain it, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
positive, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
positive vs. tradition, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
practical and operational, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
sensations and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__;
audience perception, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
"Knowledge is power," 29, 42, 51
Law, 61, 64;
freedom and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
reason and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__.
See also __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Learning, Bacon's three types, 29
Licentiousness, 163
Life, 167, 211;
environment and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Literary culture, 39
Locke, 35, 50, 81, 89, 152;
philosophical empiricism, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Logic, a science and an art, 135;
tools, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
character, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
[Pg 221]importance, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
in ethics and politics, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
inconsistencies, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
new, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
of discovery, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
of discovery versus that of argumentation, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
theory, chaotic state, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Logical system, 9
Lotze, 134
Making a living, 211
Man, perfectibility, 49;
primitive, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
savage and civilized, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
tool creator, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Marcus Aurelius, 106
Materialism, 50, 70, 73, 171, 182
Mathematics, 137, 149
Matter, 72, 211
Means and ends, 72-73
Mechanics, 67, 69;
Greeks and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Mechanism, 211
Mechanisation of nature, 71-72
Medieval Christianity, 17, 19, 126
Meliorism, 178
Memory, 1, 6, 103;
emotional character, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
individual and group, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
primitive, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Metaphysics, 17, 124, 126
Methods, 149;
social philosophy, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
true, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Middle Ages, 47, 64, 132
Military art, 15
Mill, J. S., 132
Mind, pure, 111
Miracles, 125
Mistakes, 175
Modern thought, 52;
Bacon as founder, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
early, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__.
Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Mohammedans, 39
Moral ends, 169
Moral life, 165
Moral science. See under Science
Morality, pragmatic rule, 163;
standard of judgment, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Morals, 126, 169;
politics and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
National state, 200;
end or tool, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
role of the modern, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Nationalistic movement, 201
Natural Science. See under Science
Naturalism and humanism, 174
Nature, contrast of ancient and modern conceptions, 53-54;
inquiry into, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_3__;
loss of poetry when seen as a mechanism, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
significant shift in humanity's perspective on __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
value of automation, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
web imposed on, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Neglect, 97
Neo-Platonism, 111
New World, 39
Non-being, 107
Noumenal reality, 23
Nous, 36
Obliviscence of the disagreeable, 103
Observation, 140
Optimism, 178
Opportunity, 211
Organic society, 187
Organisms, 86
Organisation, 206-207
Oriental nations, 127
Origin of philosophies, 5, 18, 24, 25
Pantheon, Greek, 105
Past, 212
Perfectibility of mankind, 49
Perfection, 177
Personality, 47, 189, 209
Persuasion, 31
Pessimism, 178
Phariseeism, 176
[Pg 222]
Phenomenal reality, 23
Philosophy, emancipation, 123;
function, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
future goals and scope, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
strict and definite alternatives of English and German schools, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
history, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
opportunities, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
origin, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_3__;
practical nature, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
proper province, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
work, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Physician, 168
Physics, 75
Plato, 13, 14, 17, 19, 188, 205;
dramatic effect, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
experience, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
ideas, perfect world, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
on change, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
social arts, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
ultimate reality, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Pleasure, 181
Plotinus, 106
Pluralism, 204
Poetry, 7, 8, 103, 212
Political changes, 43
Political organisation, 44
Politics, 125;
morals and __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
movements, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Possession of knowledge, 31
Potentiality, Aristotle's use of the term, 57, 58
Practical and aesthetic, 66
Pragmatism, 38
Pretensions, 21
Primitive man, 4
Principles, 81, 163;
experience criteria, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Probability, 21
Production, 181
Progress, 42, 48, 116, 211;
Bacon and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
economic and moral contrast, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Proof, 20
Property, 182, 189
Protestantism, 46
Proudhon, 189
Prussian State, 190, 201
Psychology, 83, 135;
change in, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
malicious, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Pure reason, 78
Questioning, 17. See also Inquiry
Radicalism, 18, 19, 100
Rank, 63
Rationalism, 97;
rigidity, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Rationalists 87, 88, 89
Rationalisation, 97, 102
Real, changed conceptions, 103;
ideal and, a human issue, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
the issue of being connected to the ideal, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Reality, 23, 27;
classic view, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
nomenal vs. phenomenal, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
ultimate, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
ultimate, one with perfection, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Reason, 83, 174;
as a faculty separate from experience, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
as realigning intelligence, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
changed ideas, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Reasoning, 32
Reconstruction of philosophy, 52;
essential, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
historical factors, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
in moral beliefs, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
scientific factor, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
social philosophy and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
current issue, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
value of a solution to the dilemma of reason and experience, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Re-creation, 51, 180
Reform, 179, 180;
starting point, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Relativity of sensations, 88
Religion, 103, 211, 212;
movements, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Religious freedom, 46
Religious spirit, 210
Renaissance, 29
Research, 42;
co-op, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Responsibility, 163
Revolution of thought, 60
Rights and duties, 207
[Pg 223]
Rome, 9
Ruler and subject, 44;
in nature, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Rules of conduct, 165
Sailors, 11
Salvation, 112
Santayana, George, on Locke, 82
Satisfaction, 157
Savage, 85, 176
Scholasticism, 30
Science, 11, 23;
advancements in __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
collaborative effort, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
aestheticism and reconciling __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
human value, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
industry and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__;
natural, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
open world of __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
origin, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
picture of the universe, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
relation to experience, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
division of natural and moral, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
so-called, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
traditional, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Scientific revolution, 53
Self-delusion, 140
Self-interest, 194-195
Sensations, 84;
as adjustment points, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
relativity, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Senses, 84, 87
Sentimentalism, 73
Shakespeare, 94
Slavery, 191
Social belief, 26
Social development, 43
Social evils, 182.
Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Social philosophy, reconstruction, 187;
reconstructive impact, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Social unit, real, 204
Social welfare, 180
Sociality, 185
Society, 200, 205;
flaw in common theories about __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
individuals and three views, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
philosophy and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Socrates, 14, 17
Soldiers, 139
Sophists, 13, 14
Space, 118-119, 120
Spinoza, 106
Standards, 175
State, Aristotle's theory, 44;
contract theory, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
current view, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
importance, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
individual and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
modern, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
origin, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
supremacy, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
Subject and ruler, 44;
in nature, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Success, 179
Suggestions, 3, 6, 7
Summum Bonum. See Final good
Supernaturalism, 47
System, 98, 99
Telegraph, 120
Telephone, 120
Terminology, 21
Theories, 144, 145;
validity, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Theory and practice, 140
Things as they are, 115
Thinking, habits, 74, 75.
Check out __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Thomas, St. See Aquinas
Thought, 117;
positive and negative thinking, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
instrumental nature, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
its origin in challenges, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
types, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
logic and, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
place, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__;
systems, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Tolerance, 46
Tradition, 14;
positive knowledge vs. __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__
Transitoriness, 106
Travel, 39, 40
Trouble, 138, 140
Truth, as utility, 157;
defining, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
logical view, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__-__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
old and new, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
practical perspective, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
test of, nature of, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__;
why the current perspective is offensive, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__, __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__
[Pg 224]
Transcriber's Notes:
Typos corrected:
(Chapter III) "Home Faber" to "Homo Faber"
(Index entry) "Summum Conum" to "Summum Bonum"
The text is in American-English but the Index seems to be done in British-English.
Below are some words in the Index which are different from the text:
Typos corrected:
(Chapter III) "Home Faber" to "Homo Faber"
(Index entry) "Summum Conum" to "Summum Bonum"
The text is in American English, but the Index appears to be in British English.
Below are some words in the Index that differ from the text:
INDEX | TEXT |
---|---|
dramatisation | dramatization |
labour | labor |
mediaeval | medieval |
Generalisations | Generalizations |
mechanisation | mechanization (2 instances) |
organisation | organization (2 instances) |
Rationalisation | Rationalization |
nomenal | noumenal (2 instances) |
Download ePUB
If you like this ebook, consider a donation!