This is a modern-English version of An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, originally written by Hume, David. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.


AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING
THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS


By David Hume


A 1912 Reprint Of The Edition Of 1777





Information About This E-Text Edition

Info About This E-Text Edition

The following is an e-text of a 1912 reprint of the 1777 edition of David Hume's An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Each page was cut out of the original book with an X-acto knife and fed into an Automatic Document Feeder Scanner to make this e-text, so the original book was disbinded in order to save it.

The following is an e-text of a 1912 reprint of the 1777 edition of David Hume's An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Each page was cut out of the original book with an X-acto knife and scanned using an Automatic Document Feeder Scanner to create this e-text, so the original book was taken apart to preserve it.

Some adaptations from the original text were made while formatting it for an e-text. Italics in the original book are capitalized in this e-text. The original spellings of words are preserved, such as "connexion" for "connection," "labour" for "labor," etc. Original footnotes are put in brackets at the points where they are cited in the text.

Some changes from the original text were made while preparing it for an e-text. Italics in the original book are capitalized in this e-text. The original spellings of words are kept, such as "connexion" for "connection," "labour" for "labor," etc. Original footnotes are included in brackets at the places where they are referenced in the text.







Contents






AUTHOR'S ADVERTISEMENT.

Most of the principles, and reasonings, contained in this volume,

Most of the principles and reasoning found in this book,

    [Footnote: Volume II. of the posthumous edition of Hume's works
published in 1777 and containing, besides the present ENQUIRY,
A DISSERTATION ON THE PASSIONS, and AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING HUMAN
UNDERSTANDING. A reprint of this latter treatise has already appeared in
The Religion of Science Library (NO. 45)]
    [Footnote: Volume II of the posthumous edition of Hume's works published in 1777, which includes, in addition to this ENQUIRY, A DISSERTATION ON THE PASSIONS, and AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING. A reprint of this latter treatise has already been released in The Religion of Science Library (NO. 45)]

were published in a work in three volumes, called A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE: A work which the Author had projected before he left College, and which he wrote and published not long after. But not finding it successful, he was sensible of his error in going to the press too early, and he cast the whole anew in the following pieces, where some negligences in his former reasoning and more in the expression, are, he hopes, corrected. Yet several writers who have honoured the Author's Philosophy with answers, have taken care to direct all their batteries against that juvenile work, which the author never acknowledged, and have affected to triumph in any advantages, which, they imagined, they had obtained over it: A practice very contrary to all rules of candour and fair-dealing, and a strong instance of those polemical artifices which a bigotted zeal thinks itself authorized to employ. Henceforth, the Author desires, that the following Pieces may alone be regarded as containing his philosophical sentiments and principles.

were published in a three-volume work called A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE: A project the Author had planned before leaving College, which he wrote and published shortly after. However, not finding it successful, he realized he had made a mistake by going to press too early, and he completely reworked it in the following pieces, where he hopes to have corrected some oversights in his earlier reasoning and even more in the expression. Nevertheless, several writers who have engaged with the Author's Philosophy have chosen to focus all their attacks on that early work, which the author never acknowledged, and have pretended to celebrate any advantages they think they have over it: a practice that goes against all rules of honesty and fairness, and is a clear example of the kind of tactics that a fanatical zeal feels justified in using. From now on, the Author asks that the following pieces be regarded as the only ones reflecting his philosophical thoughts and principles.





CONTENTS PAGE

      I.    Of the General Principles of Morals
      II.   Of Benevolence
      III.  Of Justice
      IV.   Of Political Society
      V.    Why Utility Pleases
      VI.   Of Qualities Useful to Ourselves
      VII.  Of Qualities Immediately Agreeable to Ourselves
      VIII. Of Qualities Immediately Agreeable to Others
      IX.   Conclusion
      I.    Of the General Principles of Morals  
      II.   Of Benevolence  
      III.  Of Justice  
      IV.   Of Political Society  
      V.    Why Utility is Enjoyable  
      VI.   Of Qualities Beneficial to Ourselves  
      VII.  Of Qualities that are Pleasing to Ourselves  
      VIII. Of Qualities that are Pleasing to Others  
      IX.   Conclusion  




APPENDIX.

      I.   Concerning Moral Sentiment
      II.  Of Self-love
      III. Some Farther Considerations with Regard to Justice
      IV.  Of Some Verbal Disputes
      I.   About Moral Feelings  
      II.  On Self-love  
      III. Additional Thoughts About Justice  
      IV.  About Some Word Disputes  




AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS





SECTION I. OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF MORALS.

DISPUTES with men, pertinaciously obstinate in their principles, are, of all others, the most irksome; except, perhaps, those with persons, entirely disingenuous, who really do not believe the opinions they defend, but engage in the controversy, from affectation, from a spirit of opposition, or from a desire of showing wit and ingenuity, superior to the rest of mankind. The same blind adherence to their own arguments is to be expected in both; the same contempt of their antagonists; and the same passionate vehemence, in inforcing sophistry and falsehood. And as reasoning is not the source, whence either disputant derives his tenets; it is in vain to expect, that any logic, which speaks not to the affections, will ever engage him to embrace sounder principles.

ARGUMENTS with people who stubbornly cling to their beliefs are, of all kinds, the most annoying; except, maybe, those with individuals who are completely insincere, who don’t actually believe the opinions they argue for, but get into the debate for show, out of a spirit of contradiction, or because they want to showcase their cleverness and creativity over others. You can expect the same blind loyalty to their own points in both types; the same disdain for their opponents; and the same intense fervor in pushing flawed reasoning and lies. And since neither debater derives their beliefs from reasoning, it’s pointless to hope that any logic that doesn’t appeal to emotions will persuade them to accept better principles.

Those who have denied the reality of moral distinctions, may be ranked among the disingenuous disputants; nor is it conceivable, that any human creature could ever seriously believe, that all characters and actions were alike entitled to the affection and regard of everyone. The difference, which nature has placed between one man and another, is so wide, and this difference is still so much farther widened, by education, example, and habit, that, where the opposite extremes come at once under our apprehension, there is no scepticism so scrupulous, and scarce any assurance so determined, as absolutely to deny all distinction between them. Let a man's insensibility be ever so great, he must often be touched with the images of Right and Wrong; and let his prejudices be ever so obstinate, he must observe, that others are susceptible of like impressions. The only way, therefore, of converting an antagonist of this kind, is to leave him to himself. For, finding that nobody keeps up the controversy with him, it is probable he will, at last, of himself, from mere weariness, come over to the side of common sense and reason.

Those who deny the existence of moral differences can be seen as insincere debaters; it's hard to imagine that anyone could genuinely believe that all behaviors and characters deserve the same love and respect from everyone. The gap that nature has created between individuals is vast, and this gap is made even wider by education, examples, and habits. When we directly compare two opposing extremes, there’s no skepticism too meticulous or certainty too strong to completely dismiss the distinction between them. No matter how indifferent someone might be, they will often feel the pull of what is Right and Wrong, and despite their stubborn biases, they will notice that others are affected by these concepts too. The only way to change the mind of someone like this is to let them be. When they see that no one is continuing the argument with them, it's likely they will, out of sheer fatigue, eventually align themselves with common sense and reason.

There has been a controversy started of late, much better worth examination, concerning the general foundation of Morals; whether they be derived from Reason, or from Sentiment; whether we attain the knowledge of them by a chain of argument and induction, or by an immediate feeling and finer internal sense; whether, like all sound judgement of truth and falsehood, they should be the same to every rational intelligent being; or whether, like the perception of beauty and deformity, they be founded entirely on the particular fabric and constitution of the human species.

A recent controversy has emerged that deserves closer examination regarding the foundation of morals. Are morals based on reason or sentiment? Do we understand them through logical reasoning and experience, or through immediate feelings and a deeper internal sense? Should they be universally recognized by all rational beings, like true and false judgments, or are they subjective, similar to our perceptions of beauty and ugliness, and influenced by the specific nature of humanity?

The ancient philosophers, though they often affirm, that virtue is nothing but conformity to reason, yet, in general, seem to consider morals as deriving their existence from taste and sentiment. On the other hand, our modern enquirers, though they also talk much of the beauty of virtue, and deformity of vice, yet have commonly endeavoured to account for these distinctions by metaphysical reasonings, and by deductions from the most abstract principles of the understanding. Such confusion reigned in these subjects, that an opposition of the greatest consequence could prevail between one system and another, and even in the parts of almost each individual system; and yet nobody, till very lately, was ever sensible of it. The elegant Lord Shaftesbury, who first gave occasion to remark this distinction, and who, in general, adhered to the principles of the ancients, is not, himself, entirely free from the same confusion.

The ancient philosophers often claimed that virtue is simply following reason, but generally, they viewed morals as coming from taste and feelings. In contrast, modern thinkers, while they also discuss the beauty of virtue and the ugliness of vice, usually try to explain these differences using complex reasoning and by deriving ideas from abstract principles of understanding. There was such confusion on these topics that a significant opposition could exist between different systems and even within parts of individual systems, and yet, until recently, no one seemed to notice. The sophisticated Lord Shaftesbury, who was the first to highlight this distinction and generally aligned with ancient principles, is not completely free from the same confusion himself.

It must be acknowledged, that both sides of the question are susceptible of specious arguments. Moral distinctions, it may be said, are discernible by pure reason: else, whence the many disputes that reign in common life, as well as in philosophy, with regard to this subject: the long chain of proofs often produced on both sides; the examples cited, the authorities appealed to, the analogies employed, the fallacies detected, the inferences drawn, and the several conclusions adjusted to their proper principles. Truth is disputable; not taste: what exists in the nature of things is the standard of our judgement; what each man feels within himself is the standard of sentiment. Propositions in geometry may be proved, systems in physics may be controverted; but the harmony of verse, the tenderness of passion, the brilliancy of wit, must give immediate pleasure. No man reasons concerning another's beauty; but frequently concerning the justice or injustice of his actions. In every criminal trial the first object of the prisoner is to disprove the facts alleged, and deny the actions imputed to him: the second to prove, that, even if these actions were real, they might be justified, as innocent and lawful. It is confessedly by deductions of the understanding, that the first point is ascertained: how can we suppose that a different faculty of the mind is employed in fixing the other? On the other hand, those who would resolve all moral determinations into sentiment, may endeavour to show, that it is impossible for reason ever to draw conclusions of this nature. To virtue, say they, it belongs to be amiable, and vice odious. This forms their very nature or essence. But can reason or argumentation distribute these different epithets to any subjects, and pronounce beforehand, that this must produce love, and that hatred? Or what other reason can we ever assign for these affections, but the original fabric and formation of the human mind, which is naturally adapted to receive them?

It should be recognized that both sides of the issue can make convincing arguments. It can be argued that moral distinctions are understandable through pure reason; otherwise, why do we see so many debates in everyday life and in philosophy regarding this topic? There's a long list of evidence often presented on both sides, with examples cited, authorities referenced, analogies used, fallacies identified, conclusions drawn, and several interpretations aligned with their principles. Truth can be debated; taste cannot. What exists in the nature of things serves as the basis of our judgment, while what each person feels within themselves serves as the gauge for sentiment. Propositions in geometry can be proven, and systems in physics can be challenged, but the beauty of poetry, the depth of emotion, and the spark of wit should give immediate enjoyment. No one debates someone else's beauty; however, they often discuss the fairness or unfairness of someone's actions. In every criminal trial, the first thing the accused tries to do is disprove the allegations and deny the actions attributed to them; the second is to show that, even if the actions were real, they could be justified as innocent and lawful. It’s acknowledged that it's through logic that we establish the first point; how can we think that a different mental faculty is used to determine the second? Conversely, those who claim that all moral judgments stem from sentiment may try to argue that it’s impossible for reason to make such conclusions. They say it’s in the nature of virtue to be lovable and of vice to be detestable. This is their inherent quality or essence. But can reason or argument assign these different labels to subjects and declare that this will lead to love and that to hatred? Or what other reason can we give for these feelings besides the original structure and design of the human mind, which is inherently shaped to accept them?

The end of all moral speculations is to teach us our duty; and, by proper representations of the deformity of vice and beauty of virtue, beget correspondent habits, and engage us to avoid the one, and embrace the other. But is this ever to be expected from inferences and conclusions of the understanding, which of themselves have no hold of the affections or set in motion the active powers of men? They discover truths: but where the truths which they discover are indifferent, and beget no desire or aversion, they can have no influence on conduct and behaviour. What is honourable, what is fair, what is becoming, what is noble, what is generous, takes possession of the heart, and animates us to embrace and maintain it. What is intelligible, what is evident, what is probable, what is true, procures only the cool assent of the understanding; and gratifying a speculative curiosity, puts an end to our researches.

The goal of all moral discussions is to teach us our responsibilities; and by properly showing the ugliness of vice and the beauty of virtue, we can develop corresponding habits and motivate ourselves to avoid one while embracing the other. But can we really expect this from conclusions and deductions of the mind, which by themselves don’t connect with our feelings or drive us to action? They can reveal truths, but if those truths are neutral and don’t inspire desire or dislike, they won’t affect our actions or behavior. What is honorable, fair, fitting, noble, and generous touches the heart and inspires us to adopt and uphold it. In contrast, what is clear, obvious, probable, and true only earns the detached agreement of the mind; satisfying a theoretical curiosity brings our exploration to a close.

Extinguish all the warm feelings and prepossessions in favour of virtue, and all disgust or aversion to vice: render men totally indifferent towards these distinctions; and morality is no longer a practical study, nor has any tendency to regulate our lives and actions.

Put out all the positive feelings and beliefs in favor of virtue, and any disgust or dislike for vice: make people completely indifferent to these differences; then morality is no longer a practical subject, nor does it have any influence on how we live and act.

These arguments on each side (and many more might be produced) are so plausible, that I am apt to suspect, they may, the one as well as the other, be solid and satisfactory, and that reason and sentiment concur in almost all moral determinations and conclusions. The final sentence, it is probable, which pronounces characters and actions amiable or odious, praise-worthy or blameable; that which stamps on them the mark of honour or infamy, approbation or censure; that which renders morality an active principle and constitutes virtue our happiness, and vice our misery; it is probable, I say, that this final sentence depends on some internal sense or feeling, which nature has made universal in the whole species. For what else can have an influence of this nature? But in order to pave the way for such a sentiment, and give a proper discernment of its object, it is often necessary, we find, that much reasoning should precede, that nice distinctions be made, just conclusions drawn, distant comparisons formed, complicated relations examined, and general facts fixed and ascertained. Some species of beauty, especially the natural kinds, on their first appearance, command our affection and approbation; and where they fail of this effect, it is impossible for any reasoning to redress their influence, or adapt them better to our taste and sentiment. But in many orders of beauty, particularly those of the finer arts, it is requisite to employ much reasoning, in order to feel the proper sentiment; and a false relish may frequently be corrected by argument and reflection. There are just grounds to conclude, that moral beauty partakes much of this latter species, and demands the assistance of our intellectual faculties, in order to give it a suitable influence on the human mind.

The arguments on both sides (and many more could be presented) are so convincing that I can’t help but think they might both be valid and satisfying, and that reason and emotion align in almost all moral judgments and conclusions. The final verdict, likely, that labels characters and actions as admirable or despicable, praiseworthy or blameworthy; that which assigns them the mark of honor or shame, approval or disapproval; that which makes morality an active principle and defines virtue as our happiness and vice as our misery; I believe this final verdict depends on some internal sense or feeling that nature has made universal across humanity. What else could have that kind of influence? But to prepare for such a feeling and to properly identify its object, it often requires a lot of reasoning ahead of time, making fine distinctions, drawing correct conclusions, forming distant comparisons, examining complex relationships, and establishing and confirming general facts. Some types of beauty, especially natural ones, immediately capture our affection and approval; when they do not, no amount of reasoning can change their impact or better align them with our taste and feelings. However, for many forms of beauty, especially in the fine arts, a lot of reasoning is necessary to evoke the proper sentiment; a mistaken appreciation can often be corrected through argument and reflection. There are valid reasons to conclude that moral beauty is largely of this latter kind and requires the support of our intellectual faculties to exert an appropriate influence on the human mind.

But though this question, concerning the general principles of morals, be curious and important, it is needless for us, at present, to employ farther care in our researches concerning it. For if we can be so happy, in the course of this enquiry, as to discover the true origin of morals, it will then easily appear how far either sentiment or reason enters into all determinations of this nature [Footnote: See Appendix I]. In order to attain this purpose, we shall endeavour to follow a very simple method: we shall analyse that complication of mental qualities, which form what, in common life, we call Personal Merit: we shall consider every attribute of the mind, which renders a man an object either of esteem and affection, or of hatred and contempt; every habit or sentiment or faculty, which, if ascribed to any person, implies either praise or blame, and may enter into any panegyric or satire of his character and manners. The quick sensibility, which, on this head, is so universal among mankind, gives a philosopher sufficient assurance, that he can never be considerably mistaken in framing the catalogue, or incur any danger of misplacing the objects of his contemplation: he needs only enter into his own breast for a moment, and consider whether or not he should desire to have this or that quality ascribed to him, and whether such or such an imputation would proceed from a friend or an enemy. The very nature of language guides us almost infallibly in forming a judgement of this nature; and as every tongue possesses one set of words which are taken in a good sense, and another in the opposite, the least acquaintance with the idiom suffices, without any reasoning, to direct us in collecting and arranging the estimable or blameable qualities of men. The only object of reasoning is to discover the circumstances on both sides, which are common to these qualities; to observe that particular in which the estimable qualities agree on the one hand, and the blameable on the other; and thence to reach the foundation of ethics, and find those universal principles, from which all censure or approbation is ultimately derived. As this is a question of fact, not of abstract science, we can only expect success, by following the experimental method, and deducing general maxims from a comparison of particular instances. The other scientific method, where a general abstract principle is first established, and is afterwards branched out into a variety of inferences and conclusions, may be more perfect in itself, but suits less the imperfection of human nature, and is a common source of illusion and mistake in this as well as in other subjects. Men are now cured of their passion for hypotheses and systems in natural philosophy, and will hearken to no arguments but those which are derived from experience. It is full time they should attempt a like reformation in all moral disquisitions; and reject every system of ethics, however subtle or ingenious, which is not founded on fact and observation.

But even though the question about the general principles of morals is interesting and important, we don't need to spend any more time investigating it right now. If we can be fortunate enough to find the true origin of morals during this inquiry, it will quickly become clear how much sentiment or reason plays a role in all related decisions [Footnote: See Appendix I]. To achieve this goal, we will use a very straightforward approach: we will analyze the mix of mental attributes that make up what we commonly refer to as Personal Merit. We will look at every quality of the mind that makes someone a subject of admiration and affection, or of hatred and contempt; every habit, sentiment, or ability that, when associated with a person, implies either praise or blame, and can be part of any praise or criticism of their character and behavior. The keen sensitivity that people have regarding this issue gives a philosopher enough confidence that they won't make significant mistakes in compiling the list or risk misclassifying the subjects of their analysis. They only need to reflect for a moment on their own feelings about whether they would want to have this or that quality attributed to them, and whether such an attribution would come from a friend or an enemy. The very nature of language almost always helps us make judgments of this kind; since every language has a set of words that have positive meanings and another with negative ones, even a basic understanding of the language is enough, without much reasoning, to help us gather and organize the admirable or blameworthy qualities of individuals. The purpose of reasoning is merely to uncover the circumstances common to these qualities; to observe that specific aspect where the admirable qualities align on one side, and the blameworthy ones on the other, and from there to reach the foundation of ethics and find those universal principles that all praise or criticism ultimately stems from. Since this is a matter of fact, not abstract science, we can only expect to succeed by using the experimental method and deriving general principles from a comparison of specific examples. The alternative scientific approach, where a general principle is established first and then branched into various conclusions, may be better in itself but is less suited to the imperfections of human nature and can often lead to illusions and mistakes in this and other areas. People have moved away from their fascination with hypotheses and systems in natural philosophy and will listen only to arguments based on experience. It is high time they make a similar shift in all moral discussions and reject any ethical system, no matter how clever or innovative, that is not based on factual evidence and observation.

We shall begin our enquiry on this head by the consideration of the social virtues, Benevolence and Justice. The explication of them will probably give us an opening by which the others may be accounted for.

We will start our investigation on this topic by looking at the social virtues, Benevolence and Justice. Explaining these will likely provide us with a way to understand the others.





SECTION II. OF BENEVOLENCE.





PART I.

It may be esteemed, perhaps, a superfluous task to prove, that the benevolent or softer affections are estimable; and wherever they appear, engage the approbation and good-will of mankind. The epithets SOCIABLE, GOOD-NATURED, HUMANE, MERCIFUL, GRATEFUL, FRIENDLY, GENEROUS, BENEFICENT, or their equivalents, are known in all languages, and universally express the highest merit, which HUMAN NATURE is capable of attaining. Where these amiable qualities are attended with birth and power and eminent abilities, and display themselves in the good government or useful instruction of mankind, they seem even to raise the possessors of them above the rank of HUMAN NATURE, and make them approach in some measure to the divine. Exalted capacity, undaunted courage, prosperous success; these may only expose a hero or politician to the envy and ill-will of the public: but as soon as the praises are added of humane and beneficent; when instances are displayed of lenity, tenderness or friendship; envy itself is silent, or joins the general voice of approbation and applause.

It might seem unnecessary to demonstrate that kind and gentle emotions are valuable; whenever they appear, they earn the approval and goodwill of people. Words like SOCIABLE, GOOD-NATURED, HUMANITARIAN, MERCIFUL, GRATEFUL, FRIENDLY, GENEROUS, and BENEVOLENT, or their equivalents, are recognized in every language and universally convey the highest virtues that HUMAN NATURE can achieve. When these admirable qualities come with privilege, power, and significant abilities, and are shown through good leadership or helpful education of others, they elevate the individuals who possess them beyond ordinary HUMAN NATURE and bring them closer to the divine. Exceptional skill, fearless courage, and successful outcomes may only expose a hero or politician to public envy and resentment. However, once they are praised for their kindness and generosity, and when examples of compassion, tenderness, or friendship are shared, even envy falls silent or joins in the overall approval and applause.

When Pericles, the great Athenian statesman and general, was on his death-bed, his surrounding friends, deeming him now insensible, began to indulge their sorrow for their expiring patron, by enumerating his great qualities and successes, his conquests and victories, the unusual length of his administration, and his nine trophies erected over the enemies of the republic. YOU FORGET, cries the dying hero, who had heard all, YOU FORGET THE MOST EMINENT OF MY PRAISES, WHILE YOU DWELL SO MUCH ON THOSE VULGAR ADVANTAGES, IN WHICH FORTUNE HAD A PRINCIPAL SHARE. YOU HAVE NOT OBSERVED THAT NO CITIZEN HAS EVER YET WORNE MOURNING ON MY ACCOUNT. [Plut. in Pericle]

When Pericles, the great Athenian statesman and general, was on his deathbed, his friends, thinking he was no longer aware, started to express their sadness over their dying leader by listing his great qualities and achievements, his conquests and victories, the remarkable length of his leadership, and his nine trophies set up against the enemies of the republic. "You’re forgetting," the dying hero exclaimed, who had heard everything, "YOU’RE FORGETTING THE MOST SIGNIFICANT OF MY ACCOMPLISHMENTS, WHILE YOU FOCUS ON THOSE COMMON ADVANTAGES, IN WHICH FATE PLAYED A BIG PART. YOU HAVEN'T NOTICED THAT NO CITIZEN HAS EVER WORN MOURNING BECAUSE OF ME." [Plut. in Pericle]

In men of more ordinary talents and capacity, the social virtues become, if possible, still more essentially requisite; there being nothing eminent, in that case, to compensate for the want of them, or preserve the person from our severest hatred, as well as contempt. A high ambition, an elevated courage, is apt, says Cicero, in less perfect characters, to degenerate into a turbulent ferocity. The more social and softer virtues are there chiefly to be regarded. These are always good and amiable [Cic. de Officiis, lib. I].

In men with more average talents and abilities, social virtues become even more essential; without them, there's nothing remarkable to make up for their absence or to prevent people from holding deep hatred, as well as contempt, for them. High ambition and elevated courage can, as Cicero puts it, turn into a chaotic ferocity in less perfected individuals. The more social and gentle virtues should be the focus in these cases. These are always good and likable.

The principal advantage, which Juvenal discovers in the extensive capacity of the human species, is that it renders our benevolence also more extensive, and gives us larger opportunities of spreading our kindly influence than what are indulged to the inferior creation [Sat. XV. 139 and seq.]. It must, indeed, be confessed, that by doing good only, can a man truly enjoy the advantages of being eminent. His exalted station, of itself but the more exposes him to danger and tempest. His sole prerogative is to afford shelter to inferiors, who repose themselves under his cover and protection.

The main benefit that Juvenal points out about the vast potential of humanity is that it allows our kindness to be broader and gives us more chances to share our positive influence than what’s available to lesser beings [Sat. XV. 139 and seq.]. It must be acknowledged that only by doing good can a person truly appreciate the perks of being prominent. His high status, in itself, makes him more vulnerable to challenges and turmoil. His only special privilege is to provide refuge to those beneath him, who find comfort and protection under his care.

But I forget, that it is not my present business to recommend generosity and benevolence, or to paint, in their true colours, all the genuine charms of the social virtues. These, indeed, sufficiently engage every heart, on the first apprehension of them; and it is difficult to abstain from some sally of panegyric, as often as they occur in discourse or reasoning. But our object here being more the speculative, than the practical part of morals, it will suffice to remark, (what will readily, I believe, be allowed) that no qualities are more intitled to the general good-will and approbation of mankind than beneficence and humanity, friendship and gratitude, natural affection and public spirit, or whatever proceeds from a tender sympathy with others, and a generous concern for our kind and species. These wherever they appear seem to transfuse themselves, in a manner, into each beholder, and to call forth, in their own behalf, the same favourable and affectionate sentiments, which they exert on all around.

But I forget that I’m not really here to promote generosity and kindness, or to fully capture all the genuine appeal of social virtues. These qualities naturally draw everyone in as soon as they’re recognized, and it’s hard not to praise them whenever they come up in conversation or debate. However, since our focus here is more on the theoretical than the practical aspects of morality, it’s enough to point out (and I believe most will agree) that no traits deserve more recognition and approval from people than kindness and compassion, friendship and gratitude, natural affection and civic spirit, or anything that comes from a deep empathy for others and a genuine concern for our fellow humans. Wherever these qualities show up, they seem to resonate with everyone, evoking the same positive and loving feelings in others that they inspire in those who exhibit them.





PART II.

We may observe that, in displaying the praises of any humane, beneficent man, there is one circumstance which never fails to be amply insisted on, namely, the happiness and satisfaction, derived to society from his intercourse and good offices. To his parents, we are apt to say, he endears himself by his pious attachment and duteous care still more than by the connexions of nature. His children never feel his authority, but when employed for their advantage. With him, the ties of love are consolidated by beneficence and friendship. The ties of friendship approach, in a fond observance of each obliging office, to those of love and inclination. His domestics and dependants have in him a sure resource; and no longer dread the power of fortune, but so far as she exercises it over him. From him the hungry receive food, the naked clothing, the ignorant and slothful skill and industry. Like the sun, an inferior minister of providence he cheers, invigorates, and sustains the surrounding world.

We can see that when talking about the praises of any kind, kind-hearted person, there’s one thing that’s always highlighted: the happiness and satisfaction that society gains from their interaction and good deeds. We often say that to their parents, they are more cherished for their loving care and devotion than just by their biological connection. Their children only feel their authority when it’s for their benefit. For them, the bonds of love are strengthened by kindness and friendship. The bonds of friendship, in their attentive care and helpful actions, come close to those of love and affection. Their staff and dependents find in them a reliable source of support and no longer fear the whims of fate, except to the extent that it affects them. From them, the hungry get food, the naked get clothing, and the uneducated and lazy get skills and motivation. Like the sun, as a humble servant of providence, they uplift, energize, and support the world around them.

If confined to private life, the sphere of his activity is narrower; but his influence is all benign and gentle. If exalted into a higher station, mankind and posterity reap the fruit of his labours.

If limited to private life, his range of activity is smaller; but his impact is all positive and gentle. If elevated to a higher position, humanity and future generations benefit from his work.

As these topics of praise never fail to be employed, and with success, where we would inspire esteem for any one; may it not thence be concluded, that the utility, resulting from the social virtues, forms, at least, a PART of their merit, and is one source of that approbation and regard so universally paid to them?

As these topics of praise are always used successfully to inspire respect for someone, can we not conclude that the benefits that come from social virtues are at least part of their value and a source of the approval and admiration they receive so widely?

When we recommend even an animal or a plant as USEFUL and BENEFICIAL, we give it an applause and recommendation suited to its nature. As, on the other hand, reflection on the baneful influence of any of these inferior beings always inspires us with the sentiment of aversion. The eye is pleased with the prospect of corn-fields and loaded vine-yards; horses grazing, and flocks pasturing: but flies the view of briars and brambles, affording shelter to wolves and serpents.

When we highlight an animal or a plant as USEFUL and BENEFICIAL, we praise it in a way that matches its nature. In contrast, thinking about the harmful effects of any of these lesser beings always fills us with a sense of dislike. The sight of cornfields and fruitful vineyards is pleasing; horses grazing and flocks feeding are enjoyable to see: but the sight of thorns and brambles, which provide shelter for wolves and snakes, is repelling.

A machine, a piece of furniture, a vestment, a house well contrived for use and conveniency, is so far beautiful, and is contemplated with pleasure and approbation. An experienced eye is here sensible to many excellencies, which escape persons ignorant and uninstructed.

A machine, a piece of furniture, an outfit, a house designed for comfort and practicality, is beautiful to the extent that it can be used efficiently, and people appreciate and enjoy it. A trained eye can recognize many qualities that those who are unaware and untrained might overlook.

Can anything stronger be said in praise of a profession, such as merchandize or manufacture, than to observe the advantages which it procures to society; and is not a monk and inquisitor enraged when we treat his order as useless or pernicious to mankind?

Can anything stronger be said in praise of a profession like trade or manufacturing than to highlight the benefits it brings to society? Isn't a monk or an inquisitor furious when we consider their order as pointless or harmful to humanity?

The historian exults in displaying the benefit arising from his labours. The writer of romance alleviates or denies the bad consequences ascribed to his manner of composition.

The historian takes pride in showcasing the advantages that come from his work. The romance author either softens or refutes the negative effects associated with his style of writing.

In general, what praise is implied in the simple epithet USEFUL! What reproach in the contrary!

In general, what praise is suggested by the simple term USEFUL! What criticism is implied by its opposite!

Your Gods, says Cicero [De Nat. Deor. lib. i.], in opposition to the Epicureans, cannot justly claim any worship or adoration, with whatever imaginary perfections you may suppose them endowed. They are totally useless and inactive. Even the Egyptians, whom you so much ridicule, never consecrated any animal but on account of its utility.

Your gods, Cicero says [De Nat. Deor. lib. i.], in contrast to the Epicureans, can't rightly demand any worship or adoration, no matter what imaginary traits you think they have. They are completely useless and inactive. Even the Egyptians, whom you mock so much, only honored animals because of their usefulness.

The sceptics assert [Sext. Emp. adrersus Math. lib. viii.], though absurdly, that the origin of all religious worship was derived from the utility of inanimate objects, as the sun and moon, to the support and well-being of mankind. This is also the common reason assigned by historians, for the deification of eminent heroes and legislators [Diod. Sic. passim.].

The skeptics claim [Sext. Emp. adrersus Math. lib. viii.], though rather absurdly, that the origin of all religious worship comes from the usefulness of inanimate objects, like the sun and moon, for the support and well-being of humanity. This is also the typical reasoning provided by historians for the deification of notable heroes and lawmakers [Diod. Sic. passim.].

To plant a tree, to cultivate a field, to beget children; meritorious acts, according to the religion of Zoroaster.

To plant a tree, to cultivate a field, to have children; these are commendable actions, according to Zoroastrianism.

In all determinations of morality, this circumstance of public utility is ever principally in view; and wherever disputes arise, either in philosophy or common life, concerning the bounds of duty, the question cannot, by any means, be decided with greater certainty, than by ascertaining, on any side, the true interests of mankind. If any false opinion, embraced from appearances, has been found to prevail; as soon as farther experience and sounder reasoning have given us juster notions of human affairs, we retract our first sentiment, and adjust anew the boundaries of moral good and evil.

In all discussions about morality, the aspect of public benefit is always a key consideration. Whenever disagreements come up, whether in philosophy or everyday life, regarding the limits of duty, the issue can't be resolved with any more certainty than by determining the genuine interests of humanity. If a misleading belief, accepted based on superficial evidence, has gained traction, once we gain more experience and clearer reasoning that provide us with better understandings of human matters, we withdraw our initial opinion and redefine the boundaries of what is morally right and wrong.

Giving alms to common beggars is naturally praised; because it seems to carry relief to the distressed and indigent: but when we observe the encouragement thence arising to idleness and debauchery, we regard that species of charity rather as a weakness than a virtue.

Giving money to common beggars is generally seen as a good thing because it helps those in need. However, when we notice that this can lead to laziness and bad behavior, we start to see this kind of charity more as a weakness than a virtue.

Tyrannicide, or the assassination of usurpers and oppressive princes, was highly extolled in ancient times; because it both freed mankind from many of these monsters, and seemed to keep the others in awe, whom the sword or poniard could not reach. But history and experience having since convinced us, that this practice increases the jealousy and cruelty of princes, a Timoleon and a Brutus, though treated with indulgence on account of the prejudices of their times, are now considered as very improper models for imitation.

Killing tyrants, or assassinating usurpers and oppressive rulers, was greatly praised in ancient times because it both liberated people from many of these monsters and seemed to keep others in check, whom the sword or dagger could not reach. However, history and experience have shown us that this practice increases the jealousy and cruelty of rulers. Figures like Timoleon and Brutus, who were once viewed favorably due to the views of their time, are now seen as very poor examples to follow.

Liberality in princes is regarded as a mark of beneficence, but when it occurs, that the homely bread of the honest and industrious is often thereby converted into delicious cates for the idle and the prodigal, we soon retract our heedless praises. The regrets of a prince, for having lost a day, were noble and generous: but had he intended to have spent it in acts of generosity to his greedy courtiers, it was better lost than misemployed after that manner.

Generosity in rulers is seen as a sign of kindness, but when it turns out that the hard-earned bread of the honest and hardworking is often transformed into lavish treats for the lazy and wasteful, we quickly take back our thoughtless praise. A prince’s regrets over losing a day are noble and generous; however, if he intended to spend it on acts of kindness toward his greedy advisors, then it was better wasted than misused in that way.

Luxury, or a refinement on the pleasures and conveniences of life, had not long been supposed the source of every corruption in government, and the immediate cause of faction, sedition, civil wars, and the total loss of liberty. It was, therefore, universally regarded as a vice, and was an object of declamation to all satirists, and severe moralists. Those, who prove, or attempt to prove, that such refinements rather tend to the increase of industry, civility, and arts regulate anew our MORAL as well as POLITICAL sentiments, and represent, as laudable or innocent, what had formerly been regarded as pernicious and blameable.

Luxury, or the enhancement of life’s pleasures and conveniences, had recently been seen as the root of all corruption in government and the primary cause of factions, rebellions, civil wars, and the complete loss of freedom. Because of this, it was widely considered a vice and criticized by satirists and strict moralists alike. Those who demonstrate, or try to demonstrate, that such luxuries actually promote greater industry, civility, and the arts challenge our moral as well as political views, portraying what was once seen as harmful and blameworthy as commendable or innocent.

Upon the whole, then, it seems undeniable, THAT nothing can bestow more merit on any human creature than the sentiment of benevolence in an eminent degree; and THAT a PART, at least, of its merit arises from its tendency to promote the interests of our species, and bestow happiness on human society. We carry our view into the salutary consequences of such a character and disposition; and whatever has so benign an influence, and forwards so desirable an end, is beheld with complacency and pleasure. The social virtues are never regarded without their beneficial tendencies, nor viewed as barren and unfruitful. The happiness of mankind, the order of society, the harmony of families, the mutual support of friends, are always considered as the result of their gentle dominion over the breasts of men.

All in all, it seems clear that nothing can give more value to any person than a strong sense of kindness; and that part of its value comes from its ability to benefit humanity and create happiness in society. We look at the positive effects of such a character and attitude; anything that has such a positive impact and promotes such a worthy goal is appreciated and welcomed. The social virtues are never seen without recognizing their beneficial effects, nor are they considered unproductive or fruitless. The happiness of people, the organization of society, the harmony within families, and the mutual support among friends are always seen as the results of their gentle influence on people's hearts.

How considerable a PART of their merit we ought to ascribe to their utility, will better appear from future disquisitions; [Footnote: Sect. III. and IV.] as well as the reason, why this circumstance has such a command over our esteem and approbation. [Footnote: Sect. V.]

How much of their value we should attribute to their usefulness will become clearer in later discussions; [Footnote: Sect. III. and IV.] as well as the reason why this factor has such an influence on our respect and approval. [Footnote: Sect. V.]





SECTION III. OF JUSTICE.





PART I.

THAT Justice is useful to society, and consequently that PART of its merit, at least, must arise from that consideration, it would be a superfluous undertaking to prove. That public utility is the SOLE origin of justice, and that reflections on the beneficial consequences of this virtue are the SOLE foundation of its merit; this proposition, being more curious and important, will better deserve our examination and enquiry.

THAT justice serves a purpose for society, and therefore that part of its value, at least, must come from that idea, is not something that needs to be proven. That public benefit is the ONLY source of justice, and that thinking about the positive outcomes of this quality is the ONLY basis for its value; this idea, being more intriguing and significant, deserves our closer look and investigation.

Let us suppose that nature has bestowed on the human race such profuse ABUNDANCE of all EXTERNAL conveniencies, that, without any uncertainty in the event, without any care or industry on our part, every individual finds himself fully provided with whatever his most voracious appetites can want, or luxurious imagination wish or desire. His natural beauty, we shall suppose, surpasses all acquired ornaments: the perpetual clemency of the seasons renders useless all clothes or covering: the raw herbage affords him the most delicious fare; the clear fountain, the richest beverage. No laborious occupation required: no tillage: no navigation. Music, poetry, and contemplation form his sole business: conversation, mirth, and friendship his sole amusement. It seems evident that, in such a happy state, every other social virtue would flourish, and receive tenfold increase; but the cautious, jealous virtue of justice would never once have been dreamed of. For what purpose make a partition of goods, where every one has already more than enough? Why give rise to property, where there cannot possibly be any injury? Why call this object MINE, when upon the seizing of it by another, I need but stretch out my hand to possess myself to what is equally valuable? Justice, in that case, being totally useless, would be an idle ceremonial, and could never possibly have place in the catalogue of virtues.

Let’s imagine that nature has gifted humanity such an incredible abundance of all external conveniences that, without any doubt about the outcome, and without any effort or hard work on our part, everyone finds themselves completely equipped with whatever their highest desires or fantasies could want. We’ll assume that their natural beauty exceeds any man-made adornments: the constant mildness of the seasons makes clothing or shelter unnecessary: the fresh greenery offers them the most delicious food; the clear spring provides the finest drink. No exhausting work is required: no farming, no sailing. Music, poetry, and reflection are their only pursuits: conversation, laughter, and companionship are their only pastimes. It seems clear that, in such a blissful state, every other social virtue would thrive and grow exponentially; however, the careful, protective virtue of justice would never have even been imagined. What would be the point of dividing goods if everyone already has more than enough? Why create property when there can’t be any harm? Why label something as MINE when I can just reach out and take something equally valuable if someone else has it? In that situation, justice would be completely unnecessary, simply a meaningless ritual, and it could never truly fit into the list of virtues.

We see, even in the present necessitous condition of mankind, that, wherever any benefit is bestowed by nature in an unlimited abundance, we leave it always in common among the whole human race, and make no subdivisions of right and property. Water and air, though the most necessary of all objects, are not challenged as the property of individuals; nor can any man commit injustice by the most lavish use and enjoyment of these blessings. In fertile extensive countries, with few inhabitants, land is regarded on the same footing. And no topic is so much insisted on by those, who defend the liberty of the seas, as the unexhausted use of them in navigation. Were the advantages, procured by navigation, as inexhaustible, these reasoners had never had any adversaries to refute; nor had any claims ever been advanced of a separate, exclusive dominion over the ocean.

We see, even in today's urgent situation for humanity, that wherever nature provides an abundance of benefits, we always keep it in common for everyone and don't divide it into individual rights or ownership. Water and air, which are essential for life, are not claimed as personal property; no one can do wrong by using and enjoying these resources freely. In large, fertile areas with few people, land is viewed in the same way. Those who promote the freedom of the seas emphasize that they can be used endlessly for navigation. If the benefits of navigation were truly endless, those who argue for this wouldn't face any opposition, and no one would have ever claimed exclusive ownership of the ocean.

It may happen, in some countries, at some periods, that there be established a property in water, none in land [Footnote: Genesis, chaps. xiii. and xxi.]; if the latter be in greater abundance than can be used by the inhabitants, and the former be found, with difficulty, and in very small quantities.

It might occur, in certain countries and at specific times, that there is ownership of water but not of land [Footnote: Genesis, chaps. xiii. and xxi.]; if the land is more abundant than the residents can use, while the water is scarce and hard to find.

Again; suppose, that, though the necessities of human race continue the same as at present, yet the mind is so enlarged, and so replete with friendship and generosity, that every man has the utmost tenderness for every man, and feels no more concern for his own interest than for that of his fellows; it seems evident, that the use of justice would, in this case, be suspended by such an extensive benevolence, nor would the divisions and barriers of property and obligation have ever been thought of. Why should I bind another, by a deed or promise, to do me any good office, when I know that he is already prompted, by the strongest inclination, to seek my happiness, and would, of himself, perform the desired service; except the hurt, he thereby receives, be greater than the benefit accruing to me? in which case, he knows, that, from my innate humanity and friendship, I should be the first to oppose myself to his imprudent generosity. Why raise landmarks between my neighbour's field and mine, when my heart has made no division between our interests; but shares all his joys and sorrows with the same force and vivacity as if originally my own? Every man, upon this supposition, being a second self to another, would trust all his interests to the discretion of every man; without jealousy, without partition, without distinction. And the whole human race would form only one family; where all would lie in common, and be used freely, without regard to property; but cautiously too, with as entire regard to the necessities of each individual, as if our own interests were most intimately concerned.

Again, let’s imagine that even though the needs of humanity remain the same as they are now, the human mind is so expanded and filled with friendship and generosity that everyone has the deepest care for each other. In this situation, people wouldn't care more for their own interests than for the well-being of others. It seems clear that the concept of justice would be set aside by such widespread kindness, and the ideas of property and obligation wouldn't even come to mind. Why would I need to bind someone else with a contract or promise to do something for me when I know they’re already inclined to seek my happiness and would willingly do the task unless the cost to them is greater than the benefit to me? In that case, they’d understand that my innate kindness and friendship would make me the first to stop their foolish generosity. Why create boundaries between my neighbor's land and mine when my heart sees no division between our interests, sharing all of their joys and sorrows as if they were my own? Everyone in this hypothetical scenario would be like a second self to another person, trusting each other completely with their interests—without jealousy, without separation, without distinction. The entire human race would form one family, where everything would be shared freely without concern for ownership, but also with careful consideration for everyone's needs as if our own interests were at stake.

In the present disposition of the human heart, it would, perhaps, be difficult to find complete instances of such enlarged affections; but still we may observe, that the case of families approaches towards it; and the stronger the mutual benevolence is among the individuals, the nearer it approaches; till all distinction of property be, in a great measure, lost and confounded among them. Between married persons, the cement of friendship is by the laws supposed so strong as to abolish all division of possessions; and has often, in reality, the force ascribed to it. And it is observable, that, during the ardour of new enthusiasms, when every principle is inflamed into extravagance, the community of goods has frequently been attempted; and nothing but experience of its inconveniencies, from the returning or disguised selfishness of men, could make the imprudent fanatics adopt anew the ideas of justice and of separate property. So true is it, that this virtue derives its existence entirely from its necessary USE to the intercourse and social state of mankind.

In today's world, it might be hard to find pure examples of such deep affection, but we can still see that families come close to it. The stronger the bond of goodwill among family members, the more it resembles that ideal, until distinctions of ownership become mostly blurred. In marriages, friendship is believed to be so strong that it should eliminate all divisions in possessions, and often it truly has that effect. Interestingly, during passionate new movements, when every belief is heightened to extremes, the idea of sharing everything has often been tried. Only the realization of its drawbacks, stemming from the return of selfish tendencies in people, has led these overly zealous individuals to revert to the concepts of fairness and personal property. This shows how true it is that this virtue exists solely because it is essential for the relationships and social conditions of humanity.

To make this truth more evident, let us reverse the foregoing suppositions; and carrying everything to the opposite extreme, consider what would be the effect of these new situations. Suppose a society to fall into such want of all common necessaries, that the utmost frugality and industry cannot preserve the greater number from perishing, and the whole from extreme misery; it will readily, I believe, be admitted, that the strict laws of justice are suspended, in such a pressing emergence, and give place to the stronger motives of necessity and self-preservation. Is it any crime, after a shipwreck, to seize whatever means or instrument of safety one can lay hold of, without regard to former limitations of property? Or if a city besieged were perishing with hunger; can we imagine, that men will see any means of preservation before them, and lose their lives, from a scrupulous regard to what, in other situations, would be the rules of equity and justice? The use and tendency of that virtue is to procure happiness and security, by preserving order in society: but where the society is ready to perish from extreme necessity, no greater evil can be dreaded from violence and injustice; and every man may now provide for himself by all the means, which prudence can dictate, or humanity permit. The public, even in less urgent necessities, opens granaries, without the consent of proprietors; as justly supposing, that the authority of magistracy may, consistent with equity, extend so far: but were any number of men to assemble, without the tie of laws or civil jurisdiction; would an equal partition of bread in a famine, though effected by power and even violence, be regarded as criminal or injurious?

To make this truth clearer, let’s flip the earlier assumptions and take everything to the extreme opposite. Consider what would happen in these new situations. Imagine a society that runs so short of all basic needs that even the greatest frugality and hard work can’t stop most people from dying or prevent everyone from being in terrible misery. It’s quite likely that the strict laws of justice would be put aside in such a dire situation, giving way to the more urgent needs of survival and self-preservation. Is it wrong, after a shipwreck, to grab any means of safety you can find, ignoring previous property laws? Or if a city under siege is starving, can we really think that people would see a chance to survive and choose to die instead because they are worried about what would normally be fair and just? The purpose of that virtue is to ensure happiness and safety by keeping order in society. But when a society is on the brink of collapse due to extreme necessity, we can’t fear greater harm from violence and injustice; everyone may now provide for themselves using whatever means prudence allows or humanity permits. Even in less urgent situations, the public opens granaries without the owners’ permission, believing that the authority of officials can, in fairness, extend that far. But if a group of people were to come together without laws or civil authority, would an equal distribution of bread during a famine, even carried out through force, be seen as wrong or harmful?

Suppose likewise, that it should be a virtuous man's fate to fall into the society of ruffians, remote from the protection of laws and government; what conduct must he embrace in that melancholy situation? He sees such a desperate rapaciousness prevail; such a disregard to equity, such contempt of order, such stupid blindness to future consequences, as must immediately have the most tragical conclusion, and must terminate in destruction to the greater number, and in a total dissolution of society to the rest. He, meanwhile, can have no other expedient than to arm himself, to whomever the sword he seizes, or the buckler, may belong: To make provision of all means of defence and security: And his particular regard to justice being no longer of use to his own safety or that of others, he must consult the dictates of self-preservation alone, without concern for those who no longer merit his care and attention.

Imagine that a virtuous person ends up surrounded by criminals, far from the protection of laws and government; what should they do in such a sad situation? They see rampant greed, complete disregard for fairness, total disrespect for order, and a foolish ignorance of future consequences, all of which will surely lead to a tragic end, bringing destruction to most and total chaos to society. In this scenario, the only option left for them is to arm themselves, regardless of whose weapon they pick up: to gather all means of defense and security. Since their commitment to justice no longer protects them or others, they must prioritize their own survival, without worrying about those who no longer deserve their care and attention.

When any man, even in political society, renders himself by his crimes, obnoxious to the public, he is punished by the laws in his goods and person; that is, the ordinary rules of justice are, with regard to him, suspended for a moment, and it becomes equitable to inflict on him, for the BENEFIT of society, what otherwise he could not suffer without wrong or injury.

When anyone, even within a political society, makes himself a target for public disapproval through his crimes, he is punished by the law concerning his property and his person. This means that the usual rules of justice are temporarily set aside for him, and it becomes fair to impose on him, for the benefit of society, what he normally wouldn't endure without it being unjust or harmful.

The rage and violence of public war; what is it but a suspension of justice among the warring parties, who perceive, that this virtue is now no longer of any USE or advantage to them? The laws of war, which then succeed to those of equity and justice, are rules calculated for the ADVANTAGE and UTILITY of that particular state, in which men are now placed. And were a civilized nation engaged with barbarians, who observed no rules even of war, the former must also suspend their observance of them, where they no longer serve to any purpose; and must render every action or recounter as bloody and pernicious as possible to the first aggressors.

The anger and violence of open warfare; what is it if not a breakdown of justice between the fighting parties, who realize that this value no longer brings them any benefits? The laws of war that then take the place of fairness and justice are rules designed for the advantage and usefulness of that specific state in which people find themselves. If a civilized nation were to engage with barbarians, who follow no rules of war at all, the civilized nation must also stop following their own rules when they no longer serve any purpose; they must make every action or confrontation as brutal and harmful as possible to the initial aggressors.

Thus, the rules of equity or justice depend entirely on the particular state and condition in which men are placed, and owe their origin and existence to that utility, which results to the public from their strict and regular observance. Reverse, in any considerable circumstance, the condition of men: Produce extreme abundance or extreme necessity: Implant in the human breast perfect moderation and humanity, or perfect rapaciousness and malice: By rendering justice totally USELESS, you thereby totally destroy its essence, and suspend its obligation upon mankind. The common situation of society is a medium amidst all these extremes. We are naturally partial to ourselves, and to our friends; but are capable of learning the advantage resulting from a more equitable conduct. Few enjoyments are given us from the open and liberal hand of nature; but by art, labour, and industry, we can extract them in great abundance. Hence the ideas of property become necessary in all civil society: Hence justice derives its usefulness to the public: And hence alone arises its merit and moral obligation.

The principles of equity or justice completely rely on the specific circumstances and conditions people find themselves in, and they originate from the benefits that come to society when these principles are followed consistently. Change the circumstances of people significantly: Create extreme wealth or extreme need: Instill in people either perfect moderation and kindness or complete greed and malice: By making justice completely USELESS, you completely eliminate its essence and its responsibility towards humanity. The typical state of society is a balance between these extremes. We naturally favor ourselves and our friends, but we can also recognize the benefits that come from behaving more fairly. Nature doesn’t offer us many rewards freely; instead, through creativity, hard work, and effort, we can obtain them in great quantities. This is why the concept of property is essential in any civil society: This is how justice becomes beneficial to the public: And this is where its value and moral responsibility come from.

These conclusions are so natural and obvious, that they have not escaped even the poets, in their descriptions of the felicity attending the golden age or the reign of Saturn. The seasons, in that first period of nature, were so temperate, if we credit these agreeable fictions, that there was no necessity for men to provide themselves with clothes and houses, as a security against the violence of heat and cold: The rivers flowed with wine and milk: The oaks yielded honey; and nature spontaneously produced her greatest delicacies. Nor were these the chief advantages of that happy age. Tempests were not alone removed from nature; but those more furious tempests were unknown to human breasts, which now cause such uproar, and engender such confusion. Avarice, ambition, cruelty, selfishness, were never heard of: Cordial affection, compassion, sympathy, were the only movements with which the mind was yet acquainted. Even the punctilious distinction of MINE and THINE was banished from among the happy race of mortals, and carried with it the very notion of property and obligation, justice and injustice.

These conclusions are so natural and obvious that even poets have acknowledged them in their descriptions of the happiness of the golden age or the reign of Saturn. In that initial stage of nature, the seasons were so mild, if we believe these pleasant tales, that people didn’t need to make clothes or houses to protect themselves from extreme heat and cold: rivers flowed with wine and milk, oaks produced honey, and nature effortlessly provided its finest treats. But those weren’t the only benefits of that blissful time. Storms weren’t the only things absent from nature; those more intense storms of emotion were also unknown to humanity, which now cause such turmoil and confusion. Greed, ambition, cruelty, and selfishness didn’t exist: Only warm affection, compassion, and empathy were the feelings people knew. Even the strict distinction of MINE and YOURS was absent from that happy group of humans, taking with it the very concept of property, obligation, justice, and injustice.

This POETICAL fiction of the GOLDEN AGE, is in some respects, of a piece with the PHILOSOPHICAL fiction of the STATE OF NATURE; only that the former is represented as the most charming and most peaceable condition, which can possibly be imagined; whereas the latter is painted out as a state of mutual war and violence, attended with the most extreme necessity. On the first origin of mankind, we are told, their ignorance and savage nature were so prevalent, that they could give no mutual trust, but must each depend upon himself and his own force or cunning for protection and security. No law was heard of: No rule of justice known: No distinction of property regarded: Power was the only measure of right; and a perpetual war of all against all was the result of men's untamed selfishness and barbarity.

This poetic story of the Golden Age is, in some ways, similar to the philosophical concept of the State of Nature; however, the former is depicted as the most delightful and peaceful condition imaginable, while the latter is portrayed as a state of constant conflict and violence, marked by extreme necessity. At the dawn of humanity, we are told, people's ignorance and savage instincts were so dominant that they could not trust one another and had to rely solely on their own strength or cleverness for safety and security. There were no laws: no sense of justice: no regard for property rights: Power was the only measure of what was right, and the unrestrained selfishness and brutality of humans led to a situation where everyone was at war with one another.

     [Footnote: This fiction of a state of nature, as a state of war,
was not first started by Mr. Hobbes, as is commonly imagined. Plato
endeavours to refute an hypothesis very like it in the second, third,
and fourth books de republica. Cicero, on the contrary, supposes it
certain and universally acknowledged in the following passage. 'Quis
enim vestrum, judices, ignorat, ita naturam rerum tulisse, ut quodam
tempore homines, nondum neque naturali neque civili jure descripto,
fusi per agros ac dispersi vagarentur tantumque haberent quantum manu ac
viribus, per caedem ac vulnera, aut eripere aut retinere potuissent?
Qui igitur primi virtute & consilio praestanti extiterunt, ii perspecto
genere humanae docilitatis atque ingenii, dissipatos unum in locum
congregarunt, eosque ex feritate illa ad justitiam ac mansuetudinem
transduxerunt. Tum res ad communem utilitatem, quas publicas appellamus,
tum conventicula hominum, quae postea civitates nominatae sunt, tum
domicilia conjuncta, quas urbes dicamus, invento & divino & humano jure
moenibus sepserunt. Atque inter hanc vitam, perpolitam humanitate, &
llam immanem, nihil tam interest quam JUS atque VIS. Horum utro uti
nolimus, altero est utendum. Vim volumus extingui. Jus valeat necesse
est, idi est, judicia, quibus omne jus continetur. Judicia displicent,
ant nulla sunt. Vis dominetur necesse est. Haec vident omnes.' Pro Sext.
sec. 42.]
[Footnote: The idea of a state of nature as a state of war wasn't originally proposed by Mr. Hobbes, as is often thought. Plato tries to argue against a similar hypothesis in the second, third, and fourth books of *The Republic*. Cicero, on the other hand, assumes it to be true and universally accepted in the following passage: 'For who among you, judges, is unaware that the nature of things has led to a time when humans, without any natural or civil law defined, roamed freely across the fields and scattered about, possessing only what they could take with their hands and strength, whether through killing or wounding, or could either seize or retain? Therefore, those who first stood out due to their virtue and wisdom, recognizing the inherent teachability and talent of humanity, gathered the scattered people into one place, and led them from that wild state to justice and civility. Then, concerning the common good, which we call public matters, and the gatherings of people, which later came to be called cities, and the connected homes that we refer to as cities, they fortified them with both divine and human law. And between this civilized life and that savage existence, nothing is as crucial as LAW and FORCE. We wish to avoid using either; rather, we must use the latter. We want to eliminate force. Law must prevail, that is, the judiciary, which contains all law. If judgments are unsatisfactory, or do not exist, force must dominate. This is clear to everyone.' Pro Sext. sec. 42.]

Whether such a condition of human nature could ever exist, or if it did, could continue so long as to merit the appellation of a STATE, may justly be doubted. Men are necessarily born in a family-society, at least; and are trained up by their parents to some rule of conduct and behaviour. But this must be admitted, that, if such a state of mutual war and violence was ever real, the suspension of all laws of justice, from their absolute inutility, is a necessary and infallible consequence.

Whether such a condition of human nature could ever exist, or if it did, could last long enough to be called a STATE, can rightly be questioned. People are inevitably born into a family or society and are raised by their parents to follow some rules of conduct and behavior. However, it must be acknowledged that if such a state of mutual conflict and violence ever truly existed, the suspension of all laws of justice, due to their complete uselessness, is a necessary and certain outcome.

The more we vary our views of human life, and the newer and more unusual the lights are in which we survey it, the more shall we be convinced, that the origin here assigned for the virtue of justice is real and satisfactory.

The more we change our perspectives on human life, and the fresher and more unique the ways we look at it, the more we'll be convinced that the reason given for the virtue of justice is genuine and fulfilling.

Were there a species of creatures intermingled with men, which, though rational, were possessed of such inferior strength, both of body and mind, that they were incapable of all resistance, and could never, upon the highest provocation, make us feel the effects of their resentment; the necessary consequence, I think, is that we should be bound by the laws of humanity to give gentle usage to these creatures, but should not, properly speaking, lie under any restraint of justice with regard to them, nor could they possess any right or property, exclusive of such arbitrary lords. Our intercourse with them could not be called society, which supposes a degree of equality; but absolute command on the one side, and servile obedience on the other. Whatever we covet, they must instantly resign: Our permission is the only tenure, by which they hold their possessions: Our compassion and kindness the only check, by which they curb our lawless will: And as no inconvenience ever results from the exercise of a power, so firmly established in nature, the restraints of justice and property, being totally USELESS, would never have place in so unequal a confederacy.

If there were a species of creatures mixed among humans, which, although intelligent, had such inferior strength, both physically and mentally, that they couldn’t resist us at all and would never, even when provoked, make us feel their anger; I believe the consequence would be that we would be obliged by humanity to treat these creatures gently, but we wouldn’t really be bound by any rules of justice toward them, nor would they have any rights or property not given by their powerful masters. Our relationship with them couldn’t really be called society, which implies some level of equality; instead, it would be total control on one side and complete obedience on the other. Whatever we desire, they would have to give up immediately: Our permission is the only way they can keep their possessions: Our compassion and kindness are the only things that limit our unchecked desire: And since no problems arise from exercising a power so deeply rooted in nature, the constraints of justice and property would be completely USELESS and would have no place in such an unequal arrangement.

This is plainly the situation of men, with regard to animals; and how far these may be said to possess reason, I leave it to others to determine. The great superiority of civilized Europeans above barbarous Indians, tempted us to imagine ourselves on the same footing with regard to them, and made us throw off all restraints of justice, and even of humanity, in our treatment of them. In many nations, the female sex are reduced to like slavery, and are rendered incapable of all property, in opposition to their lordly masters. But though the males, when united, have in all countries bodily force sufficient to maintain this severe tyranny, yet such are the insinuation, address, and charms of their fair companions, that women are commonly able to break the confederacy, and share with the other sex in all the rights and privileges of society.

This is clearly the situation of men in relation to animals; how much reason they might actually have is for others to decide. The significant superiority of civilized Europeans over barbaric Indians led us to think we were on the same level as them, which caused us to disregard all principles of justice and even humanity in how we treated them. In many cultures, women are similarly subjected to slavery and denied any rights to property, positioned against their dominant masters. However, even though men, when united, have enough physical strength in every country to uphold this harsh oppression, the charm, influence, and appeal of their female counterparts often enable women to break that alliance and enjoy the same rights and privileges as men in society.

Were the human species so framed by nature as that each individual possessed within himself every faculty, requisite both for his own preservation and for the propagation of his kind: Were all society and intercourse cut off between man and man, by the primary intention of the supreme Creator: It seems evident, that so solitary a being would be as much incapable of justice, as of social discourse and conversation. Where mutual regards and forbearance serve to no manner of purpose, they would never direct the conduct of any reasonable man. The headlong course of the passions would be checked by no reflection on future consequences. And as each man is here supposed to love himself alone, and to depend only on himself and his own activity for safety and happiness, he would, on every occasion, to the utmost of his power, challenge the preference above every other being, to none of which he is bound by any ties, either of nature or of interest. But suppose the conjunction of the sexes to be established in nature, a family immediately arises; and particular rules being found requisite for its subsistence, these are immediately embraced; though without comprehending the rest of mankind within their prescriptions. Suppose that several families unite together into one society, which is totally disjoined from all others, the rules, which preserve peace and order, enlarge themselves to the utmost extent of that society; but becoming then entirely useless, lose their force when carried one step farther. But again suppose, that several distinct societies maintain a kind of intercourse for mutual convenience and advantage, the boundaries of justice still grow larger, in proportion to the largeness of men's views, and the force of their mutual connexions. History, experience, reason sufficiently instruct us in this natural progress of human sentiments, and in the gradual enlargement of our regards to justice, in proportion as we become acquainted with the extensive utility of that virtue.

If human beings were designed by nature in such a way that each person had all the abilities needed for their own survival and for continuing the species: If all social interactions between individuals were completely cut off by the primary intention of a supreme Creator: It seems clear that such a solitary being would be as incapable of justice as of engaging in conversation and social discourse. When mutual respect and patience serve no purpose, they wouldn’t guide the actions of any reasonable person. The impulsive nature of emotions would not be tempered by thoughts of future consequences. And since it's assumed that each person only loves themselves and relies solely on their own efforts for safety and happiness, they would, in every situation, claim priority over every other being, to which they have no obligations, either by nature or personal interest. But if we assume that the pairing of the sexes is established by nature, a family immediately forms; and specific rules are needed for its survival, which are quickly accepted, though without considering the rest of humanity in their regulations. If several families come together to form a society that is completely separate from all others, the rules that maintain peace and order expand to the fullest extent of that society; however, they become entirely useless and lose their effectiveness if applied even slightly beyond that. But again, if several distinct societies interact for mutual benefit and advantage, the boundaries of justice broaden according to the expansiveness of people’s perspectives and the strength of their connections. History, experience, and reason clearly show us this natural progression of human feelings and the gradual expansion of our understanding of justice as we become aware of the broad benefits of that virtue.





PART II.

If we examine the PARTICULAR laws, by which justice is directed, and property determined; we shall still be presented with the same conclusion. The good of mankind is the only object of all these laws and regulations. Not only is it requisite, for the peace and interest of society, that men's possessions should be separated; but the rules, which we follow, in making the separation, are such as can best be contrived to serve farther the interests of society.

If we look at the specific laws that guide justice and define property, we reach the same conclusion. The welfare of humanity is the sole purpose of all these laws and regulations. It's essential, for the peace and well-being of society, that people's belongings are separated; and the rules we use to make these separations are designed to best serve the interests of society.

We shall suppose that a creature, possessed of reason, but unacquainted with human nature, deliberates with himself what rules of justice or property would best promote public interest, and establish peace and security among mankind: His most obvious thought would be, to assign the largest possessions to the most extensive virtue, and give every one the power of doing good, proportioned to his inclination. In a perfect theocracy, where a being, infinitely intelligent, governs by particular volitions, this rule would certainly have place, and might serve to the wisest purposes: But were mankind to execute such a law; so great is the uncertainty of merit, both from its natural obscurity, and from the self-conceit of each individual, that no determinate rule of conduct would ever result from it; and the total dissolution of society must be the immediate consequence. Fanatics may suppose, THAT DOMINION IS FOUNDED ON GRACE, and THAT SAINTS ALONE INHERIT THE EARTH; but the civil magistrate very justly puts these sublime theorists on the same footing with common robbers, and teaches them by the severest discipline, that a rule, which, in speculation, may seem the most advantageous to society, may yet be found, in practice, totally pernicious and destructive.

Let’s assume there's a rational being who doesn't know anything about human nature and is thinking about what rules of justice or property would best serve the public good and create peace and security among people. This being's obvious idea would be to allocate the greatest resources to the most virtuous individuals and give everyone the ability to do good, based on how much they want to. In a perfect system governed by an infinitely intelligent being, this principle would definitely be applicable and could be used for the best outcomes. However, if humanity tried to enforce such a law, the uncertainty of merit—due to its natural complexity and everyone’s self-importance—would mean that no clear rules of behavior would come from it, leading to the total breakdown of society as a result. Some fanatics might believe that power comes from divine grace and that only saints own the earth, but civil authorities rightly put these lofty theorists on the same level as common criminals, teaching them through strict measures that a principle which seems beneficial in theory can actually be completely harmful and destructive in practice.

That there were RELIGIOUS fanatics of this kind in England, during the civil wars, we learn from history; though it is probable, that the obvious TENDENCY of these principles excited such horror in mankind, as soon obliged the dangerous enthusiasts to renounce, or at least conceal their tenets. Perhaps the LEVELLERS, who claimed an equal distribution of property, were a kind of POLITICAL fanatics, which arose from the religious species, and more openly avowed their pretensions; as carrying a more plausible appearance, of being practicable in themselves, as well as useful to human society. It must, indeed, be confessed, that nature is so liberal to mankind, that, were all her presents equally divided among the species, and improved by art and industry, every individual would enjoy all the necessaries, and even most of the comforts of life; nor would ever be liable to any ills but such as might accidentally arise from the sickly frame and constitution of his body. It must also be confessed, that, wherever we depart from this equality, we rob the poor of more satisfaction than we add to the rich, and that the slight gratification of a frivolous vanity, in one individual, frequently costs more than bread to many families, and even provinces. It may appear withal, that the rule of equality, as it would be highly USEFUL, is not altogether IMPRACTICABLE; but has taken place, at least in an imperfect degree, in some republics; particularly that of Sparta; where it was attended, it is said, with the most beneficial consequences. Not to mention that the Agrarian laws, so frequently claimed in Rome, and carried into execution in many Greek cities, proceeded, all of them, from a general idea of the utility of this principle.

That there were religious fanatics like this in England during the civil wars is something we know from history; however, it's likely that the clear implications of these beliefs created such horror in people that the dangerous enthusiasts were soon forced to give them up or at least hide their views. Perhaps the Levelers, who wanted an equal distribution of property, were a type of political fanatic stemming from religious roots and openly supported their claims, as they seemed more realistic and beneficial to society. We must admit that nature is so generous to humanity that if all her gifts were shared equally and enhanced through skill and effort, everyone would have all the essentials and most of life's comforts; they would only face issues arising from the frailness of their bodies. We must also acknowledge that whenever we stray from this equality, we take away more satisfaction from the poor than we provide to the rich, and the small boost to one person's superficial pride often costs far more than bread for many families and even entire regions. It may also seem that the principle of equality, while very beneficial, isn't entirely unachievable; it has, at least to some extent, been realized in certain republics, particularly in Sparta, where it reportedly had very positive outcomes. Not to mention that the Agrarian laws, frequently demanded in Rome and executed in many Greek cities, all originated from a general belief in the value of this principle.

But historians, and even common sense, may inform us, that, however specious these ideas of PERFECT equality may seem, they are really, at bottom, IMPRACTICABLE; and were they not so, would be extremely PERNICIOUS to human society. Render possessions ever so equal, men's different degrees of art, care, and industry will immediately break that equality. Or if you check these virtues, you reduce society to the most extreme indigence; and instead of preventing want and beggary in a few, render it unavoidable to the whole community. The most rigorous inquisition too is requisite to watch every inequality on its first appearance; and the most severe jurisdiction, to punish and redress it. But besides, that so much authority must soon degenerate into tyranny, and be exerted with great partialities; who can possibly be possessed of it, in such a situation as is here supposed? Perfect equality of possessions, destroying all subordination, weakens extremely the authority of magistracy, and must reduce all power nearly to a level, as well as property.

But historians, and even common sense, remind us that, no matter how appealing these ideas of PERFECT equality may seem, they are fundamentally IMPRACTICAL; and if they weren't, they would be extremely HARMFUL to human society. No matter how equal possessions are made, people's varying levels of skill, effort, and hard work will quickly disrupt that equality. Or if you suppress these qualities, you reduce society to the most extreme poverty; instead of preventing need and homelessness in a few, you make it unavoidable for the entire community. A strict investigation is also necessary to monitor any inequality as soon as it appears, and a harsh system is needed to punish and correct it. However, such power will inevitably turn into tyranny and be exercised with significant bias; who would even have that authority in such a situation? Perfect equality of possessions, which eliminates all hierarchy, greatly weakens the power of the government and inevitably levels all authority along with property.

We may conclude, therefore, that, in order to establish laws for the regulation of property, we must be acquainted with the nature and situation of man; must reject appearances, which may be false, though specious; and must search for those rules, which are, on the whole, most USEFUL and BENEFICIAL. Vulgar sense and slight experience are sufficient for this purpose; where men give not way to too selfish avidity, or too extensive enthusiasm.

We can conclude that to create laws for managing property, we need to understand human nature and circumstances; we should disregard misleading appearances, no matter how convincing they seem; and we should seek out rules that are, overall, the most USEFUL and BENEFICIAL. Common sense and a bit of experience are enough for this; as long as people don't give in to excessive greed or overly broad enthusiasm.

Who sees not, for instance, that whatever is produced or improved by a man's art or industry ought, for ever, to be secured to him, in order to give encouragement to such USEFUL habits and accomplishments? That the property ought also to descend to children and relations, for the same USEFUL purpose? That it may be alienated by consent, in order to beget that commerce and intercourse, which is so BENEFICIAL to human society? And that all contracts and promises ought carefully to be fulfilled, in order to secure mutual trust and confidence, by which the general INTEREST of mankind is so much promoted?

Who doesn’t see, for example, that anything created or improved by someone's skill or hard work should, forever, belong to that person to encourage these USEFUL habits and skills? That this property should also be passed down to children and family for the same USEFUL reason? That it can be transferred with consent to foster the commerce and interaction that is so BENEFICIAL to society? And that all contracts and promises should be honored to ensure mutual trust and confidence, which greatly benefits the general INTEREST of humanity?

Examine the writers on the laws of nature; and you will always find, that, whatever principles they set out with, they are sure to terminate here at last, and to assign, as the ultimate reason for every rule which they establish, the convenience and necessities of mankind. A concession thus extorted, in opposition to systems, has more authority than if it had been made in prosecution of them.

Look at the writers discussing the laws of nature, and you'll see that no matter what principles they start with, they always end up here, attributing every rule they create to the convenience and needs of people. A concession that is forced out in opposition to systems carries more weight than if it had been made in support of them.

What other reason, indeed, could writers ever give, why this must be MINE and that YOURS; since uninstructed nature surely never made any such distinction? The objects which receive those appellations are, of themselves, foreign to us; they are totally disjoined and separated from us; and nothing but the general interests of society can form the connexion.

What other reason could writers possibly provide for why this must be MINE and that YOURS, when nature itself never created such a distinction? The things we refer to with those labels are, in essence, unrelated to us; they are completely disconnected and separate from us; and only the broader interests of society can create that connection.

Sometimes the interests of society may require a rule of justice in a particular case; but may not determine any particular rule, among several, which are all equally beneficial. In that case, the slightest analogies are laid hold of, in order to prevent that indifference and ambiguity, which would be the source of perpetual dissension. Thus possession alone, and first possession, is supposed to convey property, where no body else has any preceding claim and pretension. Many of the reasonings of lawyers are of this analogical nature, and depend on very slight connexions of the imagination.

Sometimes the needs of society may call for a fair rule in a specific situation; however, they might not establish any particular rule among several that are all equally beneficial. In such cases, even the smallest similarities are emphasized to avoid the indifference and uncertainty that would lead to constant conflict. Therefore, possession alone, and the idea of being the first to possess something, is assumed to grant ownership when no one else has a prior claim. Many arguments made by lawyers are based on this kind of analogy and rely on very subtle connections of thought.

Does any one scruple, in extraordinary cases, to violate all regard to the private property of individuals, and sacrifice to public interest a distinction which had been established for the sake of that interest? The safety of the people is the supreme law: All other particular laws are subordinate to it, and dependent on it: And if, in the COMMON course of things, they be followed and regarded; it is only because the public safety and interest COMMONLY demand so equal and impartial an administration.

Does anyone hesitate, in exceptional situations, to ignore individual property rights and prioritize the public good over rules that were set up to protect that good? The safety of the people is the highest law: all other specific laws are subordinate to it and rely on it. And if, in the usual course of events, they are followed and respected, it's only because public safety and interest typically require such fair and unbiased enforcement.

Sometimes both UTILITY and ANALOGY fail, and leave the laws of justice in total uncertainty. Thus, it is highly requisite, that prescription or long possession should convey property; but what number of days or months or years should be sufficient for that purpose, it is impossible for reason alone to determine. CIVIL LAWS here supply the place of the natural CODE, and assign different terms for prescription, according to the different UTILITIES, proposed by the legislator. Bills of exchange and promissory notes, by the laws of most countries, prescribe sooner than bonds, and mortgages, and contracts of a more formal nature.

Sometimes both UTILITY and ANALOGY fall short, leaving the laws of justice in complete uncertainty. Therefore, it's really necessary that prescription or long possession should transfer property; however, determining how many days, months, or years are needed for that purpose is impossible for reason alone. CIVIL LAWS step in here to take the place of the natural CODE and set different timeframes for prescription, based on the different UTILITIES defined by the legislator. Bills of exchange and promissory notes have a shorter prescription period under the laws of most countries compared to bonds, mortgages, and more formal contracts.

In general we may observe that all questions of property are subordinate to the authority of civil laws, which extend, restrain, modify, and alter the rules of natural justice, according to the particular CONVENIENCE of each community. The laws have, or ought to have, a constant reference to the constitution of government, the manners, the climate, the religion, the commerce, the situation of each society. A late author of genius, as well as learning, has prosecuted this subject at large, and has established, from these principles, a system of political knowledge, which abounds in ingenious and brilliant thoughts, and is not wanting in solidity.

In general, we can observe that all property issues are subject to the authority of civil laws, which shape, limit, modify, and change the rules of natural justice based on the specific needs of each community. The laws should consistently take into account the government structure, the culture, the climate, the religion, the economy, and the context of each society. A recent talented and knowledgeable author has explored this topic in depth and has built a system of political understanding based on these principles, which is full of clever and insightful ideas and is also solidly grounded.

     [Footnote: The author of L'ESPRIT DES LOIX, This illustrious
     writer, however, sets out with a different theory, and
     supposes all right to be founded on certain RAPPORTS or
     relations; which is a system, that, in my opinion, never
     will be reconciled with true philosophy. Father Malebranche,
     as far as I can learn, was the first that started this
     abstract theory of morals, which was afterwards adopted by
     Cudworth, Clarke, and others; and as it excludes all
     sentiment, and pretends to found everything on reason, it
     has not wanted followers in this philosophic age. See
     Section I, Appendix I. With regard to justice, the virtue
     here treated of, the inference against this theory seems
     short and conclusive. Property is allowed to be dependent on
     civil laws; civil laws are allowed to have no other object,
     but the interest of society: This therefore must be allowed
     to be the sole foundation of property and justice. Not to
     mention, that our obligation itself to obey the magistrate
     and his laws is founded on nothing but the interests of
     society. If the ideas of justice, sometimes, do not follow
     the dispositions of civil law; we shall find, that these
     cases, instead of objections, are confirmations of the
     theory delivered above. Where a civil law is so perverse as
     to cross all the interests of society, it loses all its
     authority, and men judge by the ideas of natural justice,
     which are conformable to those interests. Sometimes also
     civil laws, for useful purposes, require a ceremony or form
     to any deed; and where that is wanting, their decrees run
     contrary to the usual tenour of justice; but one who takes
     advantage of such chicanes, is not commonly regarded as an
     honest man. Thus, the interests of society require, that
     contracts be fulfilled; and there is not a more material
     article either of natural or civil justice: But the omission
     of a trifling circumstance will often, by law, invalidate a
     contract, in foro humano, but not in foro conscientiae, as
     divines express themselves. In these cases, the magistrate
     is supposed only to withdraw his power of enforcing the
     right, not to have altered the right. Where his intention
     extends to the right, and is conformable to the interests of
     society; it never fails to alter the right; a clear proof of
     the origin of justice and of property, as assigned above.]
[Footnote: The author of L'ESPRIT DES LOIX, This well-known writer starts with a different theory, suggesting that all rights are based on certain relationships; I believe this system will never align with true philosophy. Father Malebranche was, as far as I know, the first to propose this abstract moral theory, later adopted by Cudworth, Clarke, and others. It dismisses all sentiment and claims to base everything on reason, and it has certainly found followers in this philosophical age. See Section I, Appendix I. When it comes to justice, the virtue we are discussing here, the argument against this theory seems brief and conclusive. Property is acknowledged to depend on civil laws; civil laws exist solely for the benefit of society. Therefore, society’s interests must be seen as the only foundation for property and justice. Furthermore, our obligation to obey the magistrate and his laws is based solely on society's interests. If concepts of justice occasionally don’t align with civil law, those instances confirm the theory presented above rather than contradict it. When a civil law is so unjust that it conflicts with society’s interests, it loses its authority, and people judge based on the principles of natural justice that align with those interests. Sometimes, civil laws require certain procedures or formalities for any agreement, and if those are missing, their rulings contradict the usual understanding of justice; however, someone who exploits these technicalities is generally not considered an honorable person. Thus, society's interests demand that contracts be honored, which is a crucial element of both natural and civil justice. Yet, overlooking a minor detail can often invalidate a contract in legal terms (in foro humano), but not in moral terms (as divines put it). In these cases, the magistrate is assumed to simply withdraw his power to enforce the right, not to change the right itself. If his intention impacts the right and aligns with society's interests, it inevitably changes the right; this is clear evidence of the origins of justice and property, as outlined above.]

WHAT IS A MAN'S PROPERTY? Anything which it is lawful for him, and for him alone, to use. BUT WHAT RULE HAVE WE, BY WHICH WE CAN DISTINGUISH THESE OBJECTS? Here we must have recourse to statutes, customs, precedents, analogies, and a hundred other circumstances; some of which are constant and inflexible, some variable and arbitrary. But the ultimate point, in which they all professedly terminate, is the interest and happiness of human society. Where this enters not into consideration, nothing can appear more whimsical, unnatural, and even superstitious, than all or most of the laws of justice and of property.

WHAT IS A MAN'S PROPERTY? Anything that it is legal for him, and only him, to use. BUT WHAT RULE DO WE HAVE TO TELL THESE OBJECTS APART? Here we need to refer to laws, traditions, past decisions, comparisons, and countless other factors; some of which are fixed and unyielding, while others are changeable and subjective. However, the main point they all ultimately focus on is the well-being and happiness of human society. Where this consideration is absent, most laws regarding justice and property can seem quite bizarre, unnatural, and even superstitious.

Those who ridicule vulgar superstitions, and expose the folly of particular regards to meats, days, places, postures, apparel, have an easy task; while they consider all the qualities and relations of the objects, and discover no adequate cause for that affection or antipathy, veneration or horror, which have so mighty an influence over a considerable part of mankind. A Syrian would have starved rather than taste pigeon; an Egyptian would not have approached bacon: But if these species of food be examined by the senses of sight, smell, or taste, or scrutinized by the sciences of chemistry, medicine, or physics, no difference is ever found between them and any other species, nor can that precise circumstance be pitched on, which may afford a just foundation for the religious passion. A fowl on Thursday is lawful food; on Friday abominable: Eggs in this house and in this diocese, are permitted during Lent; a hundred paces farther, to eat them is a damnable sin. This earth or building, yesterday was profane; to-day, by the muttering of certain words, it has become holy and sacred. Such reflections as these, in the mouth of a philosopher, one may safely say, are too obvious to have any influence; because they must always, to every man, occur at first sight; and where they prevail not, of themselves, they are surely obstructed by education, prejudice, and passion, not by ignorance or mistake.

Those who mock silly superstitions and highlight the absurdity of specific attitudes toward food, days, places, postures, and clothing have an easy job. They look at all the qualities and relationships of these things and find no real reason for the affection or aversion, respect or fear that greatly influence a large part of humanity. A Syrian would rather starve than eat pigeon; an Egyptian wouldn’t go near bacon. Yet, if these types of food are analyzed through sight, smell, or taste, or examined through chemistry, medicine, or physics, no difference is found between them and any other food. There’s no specific reason that can justify the religious fervor. Chicken is acceptable to eat on Thursday but is considered disgusting on Friday. Eggs in this house and diocese are allowed during Lent, but just a hundred steps away, eating them is seen as a damnable sin. This ground or building was secular yesterday; today, through the utterance of certain words, it’s been turned holy and sacred. Such reflections from a philosopher are too obvious to make an impact because they are something everyone notices right away. When they don’t have an effect, it’s clearly due to education, bias, and passion, not ignorance or error.

It may appear to a careless view, or rather a too abstracted reflection, that there enters a like superstition into all the sentiments of justice; and that, if a man expose its object, or what we call property, to the same scrutiny of sense and science, he will not, by the most accurate enquiry, find any foundation for the difference made by moral sentiment. I may lawfully nourish myself from this tree; but the fruit of another of the same species, ten paces off, it is criminal for me to touch. Had I worn this apparel an hour ago, I had merited the severest punishment; but a man, by pronouncing a few magical syllables, has now rendered it fit for my use and service. Were this house placed in the neighbouring territory, it had been immoral for me to dwell in it; but being built on this side the river, it is subject to a different municipal law, and by its becoming mine I incur no blame or censure. The same species of reasoning it may be thought, which so successfully exposes superstition, is also applicable to justice; nor is it possible, in the one case more than in the other, to point out, in the object, that precise quality or circumstance, which is the foundation of the sentiment.

It might seem to a casual observer, or perhaps to someone lost in thought, that a similar superstition influences all notions of justice. If a person examines its focus, or what we refer to as property, with the same level of scrutiny from the senses and science, they might not, through the most thorough investigation, discover any basis for the distinctions made by moral feelings. I can lawfully take fruit from this tree, but touching the fruit of another tree of the same kind, just ten steps away, is considered wrong. If I had worn these clothes an hour ago, I would have faced the harshest punishment; now, thanks to someone saying a few magical words, they are deemed suitable for my use. If this house were located in the nearby area, it would be wrong for me to live in it; however, because it’s on this side of the river, it's governed by a different set of laws, and owning it brings me no blame or criticism. One might argue that the same kind of reasoning that effectively challenges superstition can also apply to justice; and just as in the first case, it’s impossible to identify any specific quality or circumstance in the object that serves as the basis for the sentiment.

But there is this material difference between SUPERSTITION and JUSTICE, that the former is frivolous, useless, and burdensome; the latter is absolutely requisite to the well-being of mankind and existence of society. When we abstract from this circumstance (for it is too apparent ever to be overlooked) it must be confessed, that all regards to right and property, seem entirely without foundation, as much as the grossest and most vulgar superstition. Were the interests of society nowise concerned, it is as unintelligible why another's articulating certain sounds implying consent, should change the nature of my actions with regard to a particular object, as why the reciting of a liturgy by a priest, in a certain habit and posture, should dedicate a heap of brick and timber, and render it, thenceforth and for ever, sacred.

But there’s a significant difference between SUPERSTITION and JUSTICE: the former is trivial, pointless, and burdensome, while the latter is essential for the well-being of humanity and the existence of society. If we set this fact aside (since it’s too obvious to miss), we have to admit that all notions of rights and property seem completely unfounded, just like the most ridiculous and common superstitions. If society's interests weren’t at stake, it’s just as unclear why someone saying certain words that imply consent should change how I act regarding a specific object, as it is why a priest reciting a ritual in a particular outfit and position should make a pile of bricks and wood holy forever.

     [Footnote: It is evident, that the will or consent alone never
transfers property, nor causes the obligation of a promise (for the same
reasoning extends to both), but the will must be expressed by words or
signs, in order to impose a tie upon any man. The expression being once
brought in as subservient to the will, soon becomes the principal part
of the promise; nor will a man be less bound by his word, though he
secretly give a different direction to his intention, and withhold the
assent of his mind. But though the expression makes, on most occasions,
the whole of the promise, yet it does not always so; and one who should
make use of any expression, of which he knows not the meaning, and which
he uses without any sense of the consequences, would not certainly be
bound by it. Nay, though he know its meaning, yet if he use it in jest
only, and with such signs as evidently show, that he has no serious
intention of binding himself, he would not lie under any obligation of
performance; but it is necessary, that the words be a perfect expression
of the will, without any contrary signs. Nay, even this we must
not carry so far as to imagine, that one, whom, by our quickness of
understanding, we conjecture, from certain signs, to have an intention
of deceiving us, is not bound by his expression or verbal promise, if
we accept of it; but must limit this conclusion to those cases where
the signs are of a different nature from those of deceit. All these
contradictions are easily accounted for, if justice arise entirely from
its usefulness to society; but will never be explained on any other
hypothesis.

   It is remarkable that the moral decisions of the JESUITS and other
relaxed casuists, were commonly formed in prosecution of some such
subtilties of reasoning as are here pointed out, and proceed as much
from the habit of scholastic refinement as from any corruption of
the heart, if we may follow the authority of Mons. Bayle. See his
Dictionary, article Loyola. And why has the indignation of mankind risen
so high against these casuists; but because every one perceived, that
human society could not subsist were such practices authorized, and that
morals must always be handled with a view to public interest, more than
philosophical regularity? If the secret direction of the intention, said
every man of sense, could invalidate a contract; where is our security?
And yet a metaphysical schoolman might think, that, where an intention
was supposed to be requisite, if that intention really had not place,
no consequence ought to follow, and no obligation be imposed. The
casuistical subtilties may not be greater than the snbtilties of
lawyers, hinted at above; but as the former are PERNICIOUS, and the
latter INNOCENT and even NECESSARY, this is the reason of the very
different reception they meet with from the world.

   It is a doctrine of the Church of Rome, that the priest, by a secret
direction of his intention, can invalidate any sacrament. This position
is derived from a strict and regular prosecution of the obvious truth,
that empty words alone, without any meaning or intention in the speaker,
can never be attended with any effect. If the same conclusion be not
admitted in reasonings concerning civil contracts, where the affair is
allowed to be of so much less consequence than the eternal salvation
of thousands, it proceeds entirely from men's sense of the danger and
inconvenience of the doctrine in the former case: And we may
thence observe, that however positive, arrogant, and dogmatical any
superstition may appear, it never can convey any thorough persuasion
of the reality of its objects, or put them, in any degree, on a balance
with the common incidents of life, which we learn from daily observation
and experimental reasoning.]
[Footnote: It's clear that just having the will or consent doesn't transfer property or create an obligation for a promise (the same reasoning applies to both), but the will must be communicated through words or signs to bind anyone. Once the expression is used to express the will, it quickly becomes the main part of the promise; a person won’t be less bound by their word, even if they subtly direct their intention elsewhere and don’t agree in their mind. However, while expression usually forms the entirety of a promise, it's not always the case; someone using an expression they don’t understand and without any awareness of the consequences wouldn’t be bound by it. Furthermore, even if they know what it means, if they use it in jest and with signs that clearly show they have no serious intention to bind themselves, they wouldn’t be obliged to perform. It’s essential that the words perfectly express the will, without any conflicting signs. Moreover, we shouldn’t extend this too far to presume that someone whom we interpret, due to quick thinking, as having a deceptive intention isn’t bound by what they express or promise verbally if we accept it; this conclusion should only apply in cases where the signs suggest something other than deceit. All these contradictions are easily explained if we consider that justice arises solely from its usefulness to society, but they can’t be clarified on any other premise. 

   It’s noteworthy that the moral decisions of the JESUITS and other lax casuists were often based on the same complicated reasoning as mentioned here, stemming more from a habit of scholastic refinement than from any moral corruption, if we accept the authority of Mons. Bayle. See his Dictionary, article Loyola. And why has public outrage against these casuists been so intense? Because everyone recognizes that human society couldn’t survive if such practices were permitted, and that morals must always consider public interest more than philosophical consistency. If the hidden direction of intention could invalidate a contract, as every sensible person would argue, then where is our security? Yet, a metaphysical scholar might believe that if intentionally necessary assumptions aren’t genuinely present, then no consequences should follow, and no obligation should be enforced. The complexities of casuistry may not be greater than those faced by lawyers noted above; however, the former is considered HARMFUL, while the latter is seen as HARMLESS and even REQUIRED, which explains the starkly different reactions they receive from society. 

   The Church of Rome holds that a priest can nullify any sacrament through a hidden direction of his intention. This idea arises from a straightforward and proper examination of the obvious truth that mere empty words, without any meaning or intention from the speaker, can never have any effect. If this same conclusion is not accepted regarding civil contracts, where the stakes are obviously less important than the eternal salvation of many, it’s simply because people recognize the dangers and inconveniences of the doctrine in the first case. We can thus conclude that however definitive, arrogant, and dogmatic a superstition may seem, it can never genuinely convince anyone of the reality of its objects or compare them in any significant way to the everyday events in life that we learn from observation and practical reasoning.]

These reflections are far from weakening the obligations of justice, or diminishing anything from the most sacred attention to property. On the contrary, such sentiments must acquire new force from the present reasoning. For what stronger foundation can be desired or conceived for any duty, than to observe, that human society, or even human nature, could not subsist without the establishment of it; and will still arrive at greater degrees of happiness and perfection, the more inviolable the regard is, which is paid to that duty?

These thoughts don’t weaken the demands of justice or lessen the importance of property rights. In fact, these feelings should gain more strength from the current reasoning. What more solid basis could there be for any duty than to recognize that human society, or even human nature, couldn’t survive without it? And we will achieve even greater happiness and fulfillment the more respect we give to that duty.

The dilemma seems obvious: As justice evidently tends to promote public utility and to support civil society, the sentiment of justice is either derived from our reflecting on that tendency, or like hunger, thirst, and other appetites, resentment, love of life, attachment to offspring, and other passions, arises from a simple original instinct in the human breast, which nature has implanted for like salutary purposes. If the latter be the case, it follows, that property, which is the object of justice, is also distinguished by a simple original instinct, and is not ascertained by any argument or reflection. But who is there that ever heard of such an instinct? Or is this a subject in which new discoveries can be made? We may as well expect to discover, in the body, new senses, which had before escaped the observation of all mankind.

The dilemma seems clear: since justice clearly promotes public good and supports civil society, the feeling of justice comes either from our reflection on that tendency, or, like hunger, thirst, and other desires—such as resentment, the love of life, attachment to our children, and other passions—it arises from a basic instinct embedded in human nature for beneficial purposes. If it’s the latter, then property, which is what justice is concerned with, is also marked by a basic instinct and isn't defined by any reasoning or thought. But who has ever heard of such an instinct? Or is this a topic where new discoveries can be made? We might as well expect to find new senses in the body that have gone unnoticed by all of humanity.

But farther, though it seems a very simple proposition to say, that nature, by an instinctive sentiment, distinguishes property, yet in reality we shall find, that there are required for that purpose ten thousand different instincts, and these employed about objects of the greatest intricacy and nicest discernment. For when a definition of PROPERTY is required, that relation is found to resolve itself into any possession acquired by occupation, by industry, by prescription, by inheritance, by contract, &c. Can we think that nature, by an original instinct, instructs us in all these methods of acquisition?

But further, while it seems like a straightforward idea to say that nature instinctively recognizes property, in reality, we’ll discover that this requires countless different instincts, each dealing with highly complex objects and subtle distinctions. When we need a definition of PROPERTY, that relationship turns out to be related to any possession gained through occupation, labor, legal prescription, inheritance, contract, etc. Can we really believe that nature, through some original instinct, teaches us all these ways of acquiring?

These words too, inheritance and contract, stand for ideas infinitely complicated; and to define them exactly, a hundred volumes of laws, and a thousand volumes of commentators, have not been found sufficient. Does nature, whose instincts in men are all simple, embrace such complicated and artificial objects, and create a rational creature, without trusting anything to the operation of his reason?

These words, inheritance and contract, represent incredibly complex ideas; and to define them exactly, even a hundred volumes of laws and a thousand volumes of commentary haven't been enough. Does nature, whose instincts in humans are all simple, really incorporate such complicated and artificial concepts, creating a rational being without relying on the function of their reason?

But even though all this were admitted, it would not be satisfactory. Positive laws can certainly transfer property. It is by another original instinct, that we recognize the authority of kings and senates, and mark all the boundaries of their jurisdiction? Judges too, even though their sentence be erroneous and illegal, must be allowed, for the sake of peace and order, to have decisive authority, and ultimately to determine property. Have we original innate ideas of praetors and chancellors and juries? Who sees not, that all these institutions arise merely from the necessities of human society?

But even if we accept all of this, it still wouldn’t be enough. Laws can definitely transfer property. It’s from a different instinct that we acknowledge the authority of kings and parliaments, and define the limits of their power. Judges, even when their decisions are wrong or unlawful, must be granted, for the sake of peace and order, ultimate authority to settle matters of property. Do we really have inherent ideas of judges and chancellors and juries? Who can’t see that all these institutions come solely from the needs of human society?

All birds of the same species in every age and country, built their nests alike: In this we see the force of instinct. Men, in different times and places, frame their houses differently: Here we perceive the influence of reason and custom. A like inference may be drawn from comparing the instinct of generation and the institution of property.

All birds of the same species, no matter their age or where they are, build their nests in the same way: This shows the power of instinct. People, in different times and places, design their homes in various ways: Here we notice the impact of reason and tradition. A similar conclusion can be drawn by comparing the instinct for reproduction and the concept of property.

How great soever the variety of municipal laws, it must be confessed, that their chief outlines pretty regularly concur; because the purposes, to which they tend, are everywhere exactly similar. In like manner, all houses have a roof and walls, windows and chimneys; though diversified in their shape, figure, and materials. The purposes of the latter, directed to the conveniencies of human life, discover not more plainly their origin from reason and reflection, than do those of the former, which point all to a like end.

No matter how varied municipal laws may be, it must be acknowledged that their main outlines often align, because the goals they aim for are pretty much the same everywhere. Similarly, all houses have a roof and walls, windows and chimneys, even though they differ in shape, style, and materials. The purposes of these houses, designed to serve the needs of human life, show just as clearly their origin in reason and thought as do those of the laws, all of which lead to a similar outcome.

I need not mention the variations, which all the rules of property receive from the finer turns and connexions of the imagination, and from the subtilties and abstractions of law-topics and reasonings. There is no possibility of reconciling this observation to the notion of original instincts.

I don’t need to point out the differences that all property rules experience due to the more delicate twists and connections of the imagination, as well as the nuances and abstractions found in legal discussions and reasoning. It's impossible to align this observation with the idea of original instincts.

What alone will beget a doubt concerning the theory, on which I insist, is the influence of education and acquired habits, by which we are so accustomed to blame injustice, that we are not, in every instance, conscious of any immediate reflection on the pernicious consequences of it. The views the most familiar to us are apt, for that very reason, to escape us; and what we have very frequently performed from certain motives, we are apt likewise to continue mechanically, without recalling, on every occasion, the reflections, which first determined us. The convenience, or rather necessity, which leads to justice is so universal, and everywhere points so much to the same rules, that the habit takes place in all societies; and it is not without some scrutiny, that we are able to ascertain its true origin. The matter, however, is not so obscure, but that even in common life we have every moment recourse to the principle of public utility, and ask, WHAT MUST BECOME OF THE WORLD, IF SUCH PRACTICES PREVAIL? HOW COULD SOCIETY SUBSIST UNDER SUCH DISORDERS? Were the distinction or separation of possessions entirely useless, can any one conceive, that it ever should have obtained in society?

What will raise doubts about the theory I’m arguing for is the impact of education and learned habits. We’ve become so used to blaming injustice that we often don’t consciously think about its harmful effects. The ideas we’re most familiar with tend to escape our notice for that reason. When we frequently act on certain motivations, we’re likely to continue doing so automatically, without always bringing to mind the reasons that originally influenced us. The need for justice is so widespread and consistently points to the same principles that this habit exists in all societies. It takes some careful consideration to truly understand its origins. However, it’s not so unclear that in everyday life we don’t constantly refer to the principle of public good, asking ourselves, WHAT WILL HAPPEN TO THE WORLD IF SUCH PRACTICES CONTINUE? HOW CAN SOCIETY SURVIVE WITH SUCH CHAOS? If the division or ownership of property were completely pointless, can anyone really believe it would have ever been established in society?

Thus we seem, upon the whole, to have attained a knowledge of the force of that principle here insisted on, and can determine what degree of esteem or moral approbation may result from reflections on public interest and utility. The necessity of justice to the support of society is the sole foundation of that virtue; and since no moral excellence is more highly esteemed, we may conclude that this circumstance of usefulness has, in general, the strongest energy, and most entire command over our sentiments. It must, therefore, be the source of a considerable part of the merit ascribed to humanity, benevolence, friendship, public spirit, and other social virtues of that stamp; as it is the sole source of the moral approbation paid to fidelity, justice, veracity, integrity, and those other estimable and useful qualities and principles. It is entirely agreeable to the rules of philosophy, and even of common reason; where any principle has been found to have a great force and energy in one instance, to ascribe to it a like energy in all similar instances. This indeed is Newton's chief rule of philosophizing [Footnote: Principia. Lib. iii.].

Overall, it seems we've gained an understanding of the importance of the principle we've discussed, and we can figure out what level of respect or moral approval might come from thinking about the public good and utility. The need for justice to maintain society is the fundamental basis of that virtue; and since no moral quality is held in higher regard, we can conclude that this aspect of usefulness generally has the strongest influence and complete control over our feelings. Therefore, it must be a significant part of the value we assign to qualities like humanity, kindness, friendship, community spirit, and other similar social virtues. It is also the primary source of the moral approval given to qualities like loyalty, justice, honesty, integrity, and other admirable and useful traits. This aligns perfectly with the principles of philosophy and even common sense, as when a principle shows strong influence in one case, it's reasonable to expect it to have similar influence in all comparable situations. This indeed is Newton's main rule of reasoning [Footnote: Principia. Lib. iii.].





SECTION IV.

OF POLITICAL SOCIETY.

Had every man sufficient SAGACITY to perceive, at all times, the strong interest which binds him to the observance of justice and equity, and STRENGTH OF MIND sufficient to persevere in a steady adherence to a general and a distant interest, in opposition to the allurements of present pleasure and advantage; there had never, in that case, been any such thing as government or political society, but each man, following his natural liberty, had lived in entire peace and harmony with all others. What need of positive law where natural justice is, of itself, a sufficient restraint? Why create magistrates, where there never arises any disorder or iniquity? Why abridge our native freedom, when, in every instance, the utmost exertion of it is found innocent and beneficial? It is evident, that, if government were totally useless, it never could have place, and that the sole foundation of the duty of allegiance is the ADVANTAGE, which it procures to society, by preserving peace and order among mankind.

If every person had enough WISDOM to always recognize the strong interest that ties them to the practice of fairness and justice, and the WILLPOWER to stick to a common and long-term interest instead of giving in to the temptations of immediate pleasure and gain, then there wouldn’t be any need for government or political society. Each person would, instead, enjoy their natural freedom and live in complete peace and harmony with everyone else. What need is there for laws if natural justice is enough to hold us back? Why create authorities if there’s never any disorder or wrongdoing? Why limit our inherent freedom when, in every case, using it results in good and beneficial outcomes? It’s clear that if government were completely unnecessary, it couldn’t exist at all, and the only reason we have a duty to obey is because it brings benefits to society by maintaining peace and order among people.

When a number of political societies are erected, and maintain a great intercourse together, a new set of rules are immediately discovered to be USEFUL in that particular situation; and accordingly take place under the title of Laws of Nations. Of this kind are, the sacredness of the person of ambassadors, abstaining from poisoned arms, quarter in war, with others of that kind, which are plainly calculated for the ADVANTAGE of states and kingdoms in their intercourse with each other.

When several political societies are established and engage in significant interaction, a new set of rules is quickly recognized as USEFUL in that context, and these rules are adopted as the Laws of Nations. This includes things like the inviolability of ambassadors, the prohibition of poisoned weapons, and regulations regarding treatment in wartime, among others, all of which are clearly designed for the BENEFIT of states and countries in their dealings with one another.

The rules of justice, such as prevail among individuals, are not entirely suspended among political societies. All princes pretend a regard to the rights of other princes; and some, no doubt, without hypocrisy. Alliances and treaties are every day made between independent states, which would only be so much waste of parchment, if they were not found by experience to have SOME influence and authority. But here is the difference between kingdoms and individuals. Human nature cannot by any means subsist, without the association of individuals; and that association never could have place, were no regard paid to the laws of equity and justice. Disorder, confusion, the war of all against all, are the necessary consequences of such a licentious conduct. But nations can subsist without intercourse. They may even subsist, in some degree, under a general war. The observance of justice, though useful among them, is not guarded by so strong a necessity as among individuals; and the moral obligation holds proportion with the USEFULNESS. All politicians will allow, and most philosophers, that reasons of state may, in particular emergencies, dispense with the rules of justice, and invalidate any treaty or alliance, where the strict observance of it would be prejudicial, in a considerable degree, to either of the contracting parties. But nothing less than the most extreme necessity, it is confessed, can justify individuals in a breach of promise, or an invasion of the properties of others.

The rules of justice that apply among individuals aren't completely ignored in political societies. All rulers claim to respect the rights of other rulers, and some genuinely do. Alliances and treaties are routinely formed between independent states, which would just be pointless paperwork if they weren’t proven to have some real impact and authority. But here’s the difference between countries and individuals. Human nature can't survive without people coming together, and that cooperation wouldn't happen if the laws of fairness and justice didn't matter. Disorder, chaos, and a war of all against all are the inevitable results of such reckless behavior. However, nations can exist without interacting with each other. They might even continue to exist, to some extent, during a general war. While following justice is beneficial between nations, it’s not as urgently necessary as it is among individuals; the moral obligation is proportional to its usefulness. Many politicians, along with most philosophers, agree that in certain emergencies, state interests can override the rules of justice, allowing for the invalidation of any treaty or alliance if sticking to it would significantly harm one of the parties involved. Yet, it’s accepted that only the most extreme necessity can justify individuals in breaking a promise or taking the property of others.

In a confederated commonwealth, such as the Achaean republic of old, or the Swiss Cantons and United Provinces in modern times; as the league has here a peculiar UTILITY, the conditions of union have a peculiar sacredness and authority, and a violation of them would be regarded as no less, or even as more criminal, than any private injury or injustice.

In a united community, like the Achaean republic of the past, or the Swiss Cantons and the United Provinces today; since the alliance carries a unique SIGNIFICANCE, the terms of the union hold a special level of respect and authority, and breaking them would be seen as just as, if not more, wrong than any individual harm or injustice.

The long and helpless infancy of man requires the combination of parents for the subsistence of their young; and that combination requires the virtue of chastity or fidelity to the marriage bed. Without such a UTILITY, it will readily be owned, that such a virtue would never have been thought of.

The long and helpless infancy of humans requires parents to come together for the survival of their young, and that partnership depends on the virtue of chastity or loyalty to the marriage bed. Without this usefulness, it would be acknowledged that such a virtue would never have been considered.

     [Footnote: The only solution, which Plato gives to all the
objections that might be raised against the community of women,
established in his imaginary commonwealth, is, [Greek quotation here].
Scite enim istud et dicitur et dicetur, Id quod utile sit honestum esse,
quod autem inutile sit turpe esse. [De Rep lib v p 457 ex edit Ser]. And
this maxim will admit of no doubt, where public utility is concerned,
which is Plato's meaning. And indeed to what other purpose do all the
ideas of chastity and modesty serve? "Nisi utile est quod facimus,
frustra est gloria," says Phaedrus. [Greek quotation here], says
Plutarch, de vitioso pudore. "Nihil eorum quae damnosa sunt, pulchrum
est." The same was the opinion of the Stoics [Greek quotation here; from
Sept. Emp lib III cap 20].
[Footnote: The only solution that Plato offers to all the objections that could be raised against the community of women, established in his imaginary commonwealth, is, [Greek quotation here]. For it is rightly said and will continue to be said, that what is useful is also honorable, while what is useless is shameful. [De Rep lib v p 457 ex edit Ser]. This principle leaves no room for doubt regarding public utility, which is what Plato means. In fact, what else do all the concepts of chastity and modesty serve? "If what we do is not useful, glory is pointless," says Phaedrus. [Greek quotation here], says Plutarch, on wrongful shame. "Nothing that is harmful is beautiful." The Stoics held the same view [Greek quotation here; from Sept. Emp lib III cap 20].

An infidelity of this nature is much more PERNICIOUS in WOMEN than in MEN. Hence the laws of chastity are much stricter over the one sex than over the other.

An infidelity like this is much more harmful to women than to men. As a result, the rules around chastity are much stricter for one gender than the other.

These rules have all a reference to generation; and yet women past child-bearing are no more supposed to be exempted from them than those in the flower of their youth and beauty. GENERAL RULES are often extended beyond the principle whence they first arise; and this in all matters of taste and sentiment. It is a vulgar story at Paris, that, during the rage of the Mississippi, a hump-backed fellow went every day into the Rue de Quincempoix, where the stock-jobbers met in great crowds, and was well paid for allowing them to make use of his hump as a desk, in order to sign their contracts upon it. Would the fortune, which he raised by this expedient, make him a handsome fellow; though it be confessed, that personal beauty arises very much from ideas of utility? The imagination is influenced by associations of ideas; which, though they arise at first from the judgement, are not easily altered by every particular exception that occurs to us. To which we may add, in the present case of chastity, that the example of the old would be pernicious to the young; and that women, continually foreseeing that a certain time would bring them the liberty of indulgence, would naturally advance that period, and think more lightly of this whole duty, so requisite to society.

These rules all relate to generation; yet women past child-bearing age are not considered exempt from them any more than those in the prime of their youth and beauty. GENERAL RULES are often applied beyond the original principle from which they came; this is true in all matters of taste and sentiment. There’s a popular story in Paris that, during the Mississippi speculation craze, a hunchbacked man would go every day to Rue de Quincempoix, where stock traders gathered in large crowds, and he was well paid for allowing them to use his hump as a desk to sign their contracts. Would the fortune he made from this make him handsome? Although it can be agreed that personal beauty is often linked to ideas of utility. Our imagination is shaped by associations of ideas that, although they initially stem from judgment, are not easily changed by every specific exception we encounter. In the current discussion of chastity, we can add that the example set by older women could be harmful to the younger ones; and that women, constantly anticipating a certain time that would give them the freedom to indulge, would naturally rush that period and view the entire responsibility, which is essential for society, with less seriousness.

Those who live in the same family have such frequent opportunities of licence of this kind, that nothing could prevent purity of manners, were marriage allowed, among the nearest relations, or any intercourse of love between them ratified by law and custom. Incest, therefore, being PERNICIOUS in a superior degree, has also a superior turpitude and moral deformity annexed to it.

Those who live in the same family have plenty of chances for this kind of behavior, so nothing would stop good manners if marriage were allowed between close relatives or if any romantic relationships between them were accepted by law and society. Incest, therefore, is especially harmful, and it also carries an even greater moral ugliness and deformity.

What is the reason, why, by the Athenian laws, one might marry a half-sister by the father, but not by the mother? Plainly this: The manners of the Athenians were so reserved, that a man was never permitted to approach the women's apartment, even in the same family, unless where he visited his own mother. His step-mother and her children were as much shut up from him as the woman of any other family, and there was as little danger of any criminal correspondence between them. Uncles and nieces, for a like reason, might marry at Athens; but neither these, nor half-brothers and sisters, could contract that alliance at Rome, where the intercourse was more open between the sexes. Public utility is the cause of all these variations.

What’s the reason that, according to Athenian laws, a man could marry a half-sister from his father's side but not from his mother’s? It’s clear: the customs of the Athenians were so reserved that a man wasn’t allowed to enter the women’s quarters, even within his own family, unless he was visiting his own mother. His step-mother and her children were just as off-limits to him as women from any other family, meaning there was little chance of any inappropriate relationships occurring between them. Uncles and nieces could marry for similar reasons in Athens, but neither they nor half-siblings could form such unions in Rome, where social interactions between men and women were more relaxed. Public benefit explains all these differences.

To repeat, to a man's prejudice, anything that escaped him in private conversation, or to make any such use of his private letters, is highly blamed. The free and social intercourse of minds must be extremely checked, where no such rules of fidelity are established.

To repeat, to a man's disadvantage, anything that he revealed in a private conversation, or to misuse any of his private letters, is greatly criticized. The open and social exchange of ideas must be severely restricted where no such rules of loyalty are in place.

Even in repeating stories, whence we can foresee no ill consequences to result, the giving of one's author is regarded as a piece of indiscretion, if not of immorality. These stories, in passing from hand to hand, and receiving all the usual variations, frequently come about to the persons concerned, and produce animosities and quarrels among people, whose intentions are the most innocent and inoffensive.

Even in repeated stories, where we can't anticipate any negative outcomes, revealing the author's identity is seen as a lapse in judgment, if not outright wrong. As these stories are shared and change hands, picking up all sorts of usual variations, they often reach the people involved, leading to tensions and disputes among those who meant no harm.

To pry into secrets, to open or even read the letters of others, to play the spy upon their words and looks and actions; what habits more inconvenient in society? What habits, of consequence, more blameable?

To invade people's privacy, to open or even read their letters, to spy on their words, expressions, and actions; what behaviors are more disruptive in society? What behaviors, therefore, are more deserving of criticism?

This principle is also the foundation of most of the laws of good manners; a kind of lesser morality, calculated for the ease of company and conversation. Too much or too little ceremony are both blamed, and everything, which promotes ease, without an indecent familiarity, is useful and laudable.

This principle is also the basis of most rules of etiquette; a sort of lower-level morality designed for the comfort of social interactions and conversations. Both excessive and insufficient formality are criticized, and anything that encourages comfort without crossing into inappropriate familiarity is considered beneficial and commendable.

Constancy in friendships, attachments, and familiarities, is commendable, and is requisite to support trust and good correspondence in society. But in places of general, though casual concourse, where the pursuit of health and pleasure brings people promiscuously together, public conveniency has dispensed with this maxim; and custom there promotes an unreserved conversation for the time, by indulging the privilege of dropping afterwards every indifferent acquaintance, without breach of civility or good manners.

Staying loyal in friendships, attachments, and familiar connections is admirable and necessary for building trust and good relationships in society. However, in places where people gather casually, seeking health and enjoyment, public convenience has set aside this rule. In those settings, customs encourage open conversation for the moment, allowing individuals to later disengage from any casual acquaintances without any breach of politeness or good manners.

Even in societies, which are established on principles the most immoral, and the most destructive to the interests of the general society, there are required certain rules, which a species of false honour, as well as private interest, engages the members to observe. Robbers and pirates, it has often been remarked, could not maintain their pernicious confederacy, did they not establish a pew distributive justice among themselves, and recall those laws of equity, which they have violated with the rest of mankind.

Even in societies built on the most immoral and harmful principles to the interests of the general public, there are still certain rules that a kind of false honor, as well as personal gain, compel members to follow. It has often been noted that robbers and pirates couldn’t keep their harmful alliances if they didn’t create their own system of fairness among themselves and remember the principles of justice that they’ve broken with the rest of humanity.

I hate a drinking companion, says the Greek proverb, who never forgets. The follies of the last debauch should be buried in eternal oblivion, in order to give full scope to the follies of the next.

I hate a drinking buddy, says the Greek proverb, who never forgets. The mistakes from the last binge should be buried in permanent forgetfulness, so there’s plenty of room for the mistakes of the next one.

Among nations, where an immoral gallantry, if covered with a thin veil of mystery, is, in some degree, authorized by custom, there immediately arise a set of rules, calculated for the conveniency of that attachment. The famous court or parliament of love in Provence formerly decided all difficult cases of this nature.

Among nations, where selfish flirtation, if disguised with a slight mystery, is somewhat accepted by tradition, a series of guidelines quickly emerges to accommodate that kind of relationship. The renowned court or assembly of love in Provence once ruled on all complex matters of this kind.

In societies for play, there are laws required for the conduct of the game; and these laws are different in each game. The foundation, I own, of such societies is frivolous; and the laws are, in a great measure, though not altogether, capricious and arbitrary. So far is there a material difference between them and the rules of justice, fidelity, and loyalty. The general societies of men are absolutely requisite for the subsistence of the species; and the public conveniency, which regulates morals, is inviolably established in the nature of man, and of the world, in which he lives. The comparison, therefore, in these respects, is very imperfect. We may only learn from it the necessity of rules, wherever men have any intercourse with each other.

In societies created for play, specific rules are needed to guide the game, and these rules vary for each game. I admit that the basis of these societies is somewhat trivial, and the rules are mostly, though not entirely, random and arbitrary. There is a significant difference between these and the principles of justice, truthfulness, and loyalty. General human societies are essential for the survival of the species, and the social norms that govern morality are firmly rooted in human nature and the world we inhabit. Therefore, the comparison in these aspects is quite limited. All we can take from it is the understanding that rules are necessary whenever people interact with one another.

They cannot even pass each other on the road without rules. Waggoners, coachmen, and postilions have principles, by which they give the way; and these are chiefly founded on mutual ease and convenience. Sometimes also they are arbitrary, at least dependent on a kind of capricious analogy like many of the reasonings of lawyers.

They can’t even get past each other on the road without guidelines. Wagon drivers, coach drivers, and post drivers have rules that determine who goes first; these rules mainly focus on everyone’s comfort and convenience. Sometimes, they can also be random, relying on a sort of whimsical logic similar to the reasoning of lawyers.

     [Footnote: That the lighter machine yield to the heavier, and, in
machines of the same kind, that the empty yield to the loaded; this rule
is founded on convenience. That those who are going to the capital take
place of those who are coming from it; this seems to be founded on some
idea of dignity of the great city, and of the preference of the future
to the past. From like reasons, among foot-walkers, the right-hand
entitles a man to the wall, and prevents jostling, which peaceable
people find very disagreeable and inconvenient.]
     [Footnote: The lighter vehicle should give way to the heavier one, and among vehicles of the same type, the empty should give way to the loaded; this rule is based on practicality. People heading to the capital take precedence over those coming from it; this appears to stem from a sense of the importance of the great city and a preference for what is to come over what has gone. For similar reasons, among pedestrians, the right side allows a person to stay close to the wall, helping to avoid bumping into each other, which calm individuals find very annoying and inconvenient.]

To carry the matter farther, we may observe, that it is impossible for men so much as to murder each other without statutes, and maxims, and an idea of justice and honour. War has its laws as well as peace; and even that sportive kind of war, carried on among wrestlers, boxers, cudgel-players, gladiators, is regulated by fixed principles. Common interest and utility beget infallibly a standard of right and wrong among the parties concerned.

To take this further, we can note that it is impossible for people to even commit murder without laws, principles, and a sense of justice and honor. War has its own rules just like peace does; even the playful kinds of conflict, like wrestling, boxing, stick fighting, and gladiatorial contests, are governed by set principles. Shared interests and practical needs inevitably create a standard of right and wrong among those involved.





SECTION V. WHY UTILITY PLEASES.





PART I.

It seems so natural a thought to ascribe to their utility the praise, which we bestow on the social virtues, that one would expect to meet with this principle everywhere in moral writers, as the chief foundation of their reasoning and enquiry. In common life, we may observe, that the circumstance of utility is always appealed to; nor is it supposed, that a greater eulogy can be given to any man, than to display his usefulness to the public, and enumerate the services, which he has performed to mankind and society. What praise, even of an inanimate form, if the regularity and elegance of its parts destroy not its fitness for any useful purpose! And how satisfactory an apology for any disproportion or seeming deformity, if we can show the necessity of that particular construction for the use intended! A ship appears more beautiful to an artist, or one moderately skilled in navigation, where its prow is wide and swelling beyond its poop, than if it were framed with a precise geometrical regularity, in contradiction to all the laws of mechanics. A building, whose doors and windows were exact squares, would hurt the eye by that very proportion; as ill adapted to the figure of a human creature, for whose service the fabric was intended.

It seems so obvious to credit their usefulness for the praise we give to social virtues that one would expect to find this idea everywhere among moral thinkers as the main basis of their arguments and inquiries. In everyday life, we often see that usefulness is always referenced; it is assumed that there is no greater compliment for anyone than to highlight their contributions to the public and list the services they've provided to humanity and society. What kind of admiration can we offer even to an inanimate object if the neatness and beauty of its design compromise its utility? And how satisfying is the justification for any lack of proportion or apparent flaw if we can demonstrate that this specific structure is necessary for its intended use? A ship looks more appealing to an artist or someone with basic navigation skills when its bow is wide and rounded compared to its stern, rather than if it were designed with strict geometric precision, which would defy mechanics. A building with perfectly square doors and windows would be visually off-putting exactly because of that uniformity; it would be poorly suited to the shape of a human being, for whom the structure was meant.

What wonder then, that a man, whose habits and conduct are hurtful to society, and dangerous or pernicious to every one who has an intercourse with him, should, on that account, be an object of disapprobation, and communicate to every spectator the strongest sentiment of disgust and hatred.

What a surprise, then, that a man whose behavior and actions harm society and are dangerous or harmful to everyone who interacts with him would be viewed with disapproval and evoke strong feelings of disgust and hatred from all who see him.

     [Footnote: We ought not to imagine, because an inanimate object
may be useful as well as a man, that therefore it ought also, according
to this system, to merit he appellation of VIRTUOUS. The sentiments,
excited by utility, are, in the two cases, very different; and the one
is mixed with affection, esteem, approbation, &c., and not the other. In
like manner, an inanimate object may have good colour and proportions
as well as a human figure. But can we ever be in love with the former?
There are a numerous set of passions and sentiments, of which thinking
rational beings are, by the original constitution of nature, the only
proper objects: and though the very same qualities be transferred to an
insensible, inanimate being, they will not excite the same sentiments.
The beneficial qualities of herbs and minerals are, indeed, sometimes
called their VIRTUES; but this is an effect of the caprice of language,
which out not to be regarded in reasoning. For though there be a species
of approbation attending even inanimate objects, when beneficial, yet
this sentiment is so weak, and so different from that which is directed
to beneficent magistrates or statesman; that they ought not to be ranked
under the same class or appellation.

   A very small variation of the object, even where the same qualities are
preserved, will destroy a sentiment. Thus, the same beauty, transferred
to a different sex, excites no amorous passion, where nature is not
extremely perverted.]
[Footnote: We shouldn't assume that just because an inanimate object can be useful like a person, it should also be considered VIRTUOUS by this system. The feelings triggered by utility are very different in the two cases; one is mixed with affection, respect, approval, etc., while the other is not. Similarly, an inanimate object can have good color and proportions just like a human figure. But can we ever love the former? There is a wide range of emotions and feelings that rational beings are, by nature, the only appropriate objects for: even if the same qualities are attributed to an insensible, lifeless thing, they won't provoke the same emotions. The useful qualities of herbs and minerals are sometimes called their VIRTUES, but this is just a quirk of language that shouldn't be taken seriously in reasoning. While there is a kind of approval attached to beneficial inanimate objects, this feeling is weak and very different from that directed towards helpful leaders or politicians; thus, they shouldn't be categorized or labeled the same way.

A tiny change in the object, even if the same qualities are preserved, can completely alter the sentiment. For example, the same beauty applied to a different gender does not spark any romantic feelings unless nature is extremely distorted.]

But perhaps the difficulty of accounting for these effects of usefulness, or its contrary, has kept philosophers from admitting them into their systems of ethics, and has induced them rather to employ any other principle, in explaining the origin of moral good and evil. But it is no just reason for rejecting any principle, confirmed by experience, that we cannot give a satisfactory account of its origin, nor are able to resolve it into other more general principles. And if we would employ a little thought on the present subject, we need be at no loss to account for the influence of utility, and to deduce it from principles, the most known and avowed in human nature.

But maybe the challenge of explaining these effects of usefulness, or its opposite, has stopped philosophers from including them in their ethical systems, leading them to use other principles instead to explain the origins of moral good and evil. However, it's not a valid reason to dismiss any principle backed by experience just because we can't provide a clear explanation of its origin or break it down into more general principles. If we take a moment to think about it, we shouldn't struggle to understand the impact of utility and trace it back to the principles that are most acknowledged and recognized in human nature.

From the apparent usefulness of the social virtues, it has readily been inferred by sceptics, both ancient and modern, that all moral distinctions arise from education, and were, at first, invented, and afterwards encouraged, by the art of politicians, in order to render men tractable, and subdue their natural ferocity and selfishness, which incapacitated them for society. This principle, indeed, of precept and education, must so far be owned to have a powerful influence, that it may frequently increase or diminish, beyond their natural standard, the sentiments of approbation or dislike; and may even, in particular instances, create, without any natural principle, a new sentiment of this kind; as is evident in all superstitious practices and observances: But that ALL moral affection or dislike arises from this origin, will never surely be allowed by any judicious enquirer. Had nature made no such distinction, founded on the original constitution of the mind, the words, HONOURABLE and SHAMEFUL, LOVELY and ODIOUS, NOBLE and DESPICABLE, had never had place in any language; nor could politicians, had they invented these terms, ever have been able to render them intelligible, or make them convey any idea to the audience. So that nothing can be more superficial than this paradox of the sceptics; and it were well, if, in the abstruser studies of logic and metaphysics, we could as easily obviate the cavils of that sect, as in the practical and more intelligible sciences of politics and morals.

From the obvious usefulness of social virtues, skeptics, both ancient and modern, have quickly concluded that all moral distinctions come from education. They argue that these distinctions were originally created and later promoted by politicians to make people more manageable and to tame their natural aggression and selfishness, which made it difficult for them to live in society. This idea of teaching and education undeniably has a significant influence; it can often amplify or lessen feelings of approval or disapproval beyond their natural levels, and in some cases, it can even create a new feeling altogether without any natural basis, as seen in various superstitious beliefs and practices. However, the notion that ALL moral feelings of approval or disapproval stem solely from this source will never be accepted by any thoughtful investigator. If nature hadn’t established some kind of distinction based on the original workings of the mind, the words HONORABLE and SHAMEFUL, LOVELY and ODIOUS, NOBLE and DESPICABLE would never exist in any language; and even if politicians had invented these terms, they wouldn't have been able to make them clear or convey any idea to the audience. Therefore, the skepticism surrounding this viewpoint is quite shallow; it would be great if, in the more complex studies of logic and metaphysics, we could dismantle the arguments of that group as easily as we can in the more practical and understandable fields of politics and morals.

The social virtues must, therefore, be allowed to have a natural beauty and amiableness, which, at first, antecedent to all precept or education, recommends them to the esteem of uninstructed mankind, and engages their affections. And as the public utility of these virtues is the chief circumstance, whence they derive their merit, it follows, that the end, which they have a tendency to promote, must be some way agreeable to us, and take hold of some natural affection. It must please, either from considerations of self-interest, or from more generous motives and regards.

The social virtues should be recognized for their natural beauty and charm, which, before any teaching or education, make them appealing to uneducated people and win their affection. Since the main reason these virtues are valuable is their public benefit, it follows that the goal they aim to achieve must be somewhat agreeable to us and resonate with some natural feelings. It should be pleasing, either from a sense of self-interest or from more altruistic motives and concerns.

It has often been asserted, that, as every man has a strong connexion with society, and perceives the impossibility of his solitary subsistence, he becomes, on that account, favourable to all those habits or principles, which promote order in society, and insure to him the quiet possession of so inestimable a blessing, As much as we value our own happiness and welfare, as much must we applaud the practice of justice and humanity, by which alone the social confederacy can be maintained, and every man reap the fruits of mutual protection and assistance.

It’s often said that since everyone is strongly connected to society and realizes they can’t survive on their own, they naturally support habits and principles that promote order and ensure they can enjoy the invaluable blessing of peace. Just as much as we value our own happiness and well-being, we should also celebrate the practice of justice and compassion, which are essential for maintaining social unity and allowing everyone to benefit from mutual protection and support.

This deduction of morals from self-love, or a regard to private interest, is an obvious thought, and has not arisen wholly from the wanton sallies and sportive assaults of the sceptics. To mention no others, Polybius, one of the gravest and most judicious, as well as most moral writers of antiquity, has assigned this selfish origin to all our sentiments of virtue. [Footnote: Undutifulness to parents is disapproved of by mankind, [Greek quotation inserted here]. Ingratitude for a like reason (though he seems there to mix a more generous regard) [Greek quotation inserted here] Lib. vi cap. 4. (Ed. Gronorius.) Perhaps the historian only meant, that our sympathy and humanity was more enlivened, by our considering the similarity of our case with that of the person suffering; which is a just sentiment.] But though the solid practical sense of that author, and his aversion to all vain subtilties, render his authority on the present subject very considerable; yet is not this an affair to be decided by authority, and the voice of nature and experience seems plainly to oppose the selfish theory.

This idea that morals come from self-love or personal interest is pretty obvious and hasn't just come from the playful attacks of skeptics. For example, Polybius, one of the most serious, wise, and moral writers from ancient times, attributed this selfish basis to all our ideas of virtue. [Footnote: People disapprove of being disrespectful to parents, [Greek quotation inserted here]. People also frown upon ingratitude for a similar reason (though he seems to include a more generous consideration) [Greek quotation inserted here] Lib. vi cap. 4. (Ed. Gronorius.) Perhaps the historian only meant that our sympathy and humanity are heightened when we see how similar we are to the person who is suffering, which is a valid point.] However, while the practical wisdom of that author and his dislike of pointless subtleties give his views weight, this isn't something that should be determined by authority alone; the natural instincts and experiences seem to clearly contradict the selfish theory.

We frequently bestow praise on virtuous actions, performed in very distant ages and remote countries; where the utmost subtilty of imagination would not discover any appearance of self-interest, or find any connexion of our present happiness and security with events so widely separated from us.

We often give credit to good deeds done in far-off times and distant places, where even the most imaginative minds wouldn't see any sign of self-interest or connect our current happiness and security with events so removed from us.

A generous, a brave, a noble deed, performed by an adversary, commands our approbation; while in its consequences it may be acknowledged prejudicial to our particular interest.

A generous, brave, noble act done by an opponent earns our approval, even if it might negatively affect our personal interests.

Where private advantage concurs with general affection for virtue, we readily perceive and avow the mixture of these distinct sentiments, which have a very different feeling and influence on the mind. We praise, perhaps, with more alacrity, where the generous humane action contributes to our particular interest: But the topics of praise, which we insist on, are very wide of this circumstance. And we may attempt to bring over others to our sentiments, without endeavouring to convince them, that they reap any advantage from the actions which we recommend to their approbation and applause.

When personal benefit aligns with a general appreciation for virtue, we easily recognize and acknowledge the combination of these different feelings, which impact the mind in distinct ways. We might praise more eagerly when a generous, kind action serves our personal interests. However, the reasons for our praise often extend far beyond this connection. We can try to persuade others to share our views without trying to convince them that they gain any benefit from the actions we encourage them to support and applaud.

Frame the model of a praiseworthy character, consisting of all the most amiable moral virtues: Give instances, in which these display themselves after an eminent and extraordinary manner: You readily engage the esteem and approbation of all your audience, who never so much as enquire in what age and country the person lived, who possessed these noble qualities: A circumstance, however, of all others, the most material to self-love, or a concern for our own individual happiness. Once on a time, a statesman, in the shock and contest of parties, prevailed so far as to procure, by his eloquence, the banishment of an able adversary; whom he secretly followed, offering him money for his support during his exile, and soothing him with topics of consolation in his misfortunes. ALAS! cries the banished statesman, WITH WHAT REGRET MUST I LEAVE MY FRIENDS IN THIS CITY, WHERE EVEN ENEMIES ARE SO GENEROUS! Virtue, though in an enemy, here pleased him: And we also give it the just tribute of praise and approbation; nor do we retract these sentiments, when we hear, that the action passed at Athens, about two thousand years ago, and that the persons' names were Eschines and Demosthenes.

Frame the model of a commendable character, made up of all the most admirable moral virtues. Provide examples where these virtues are shown in a remarkable and extraordinary way. You easily gain the respect and approval of your audience, who don’t even ask what time period or place the person lived in who had these noble qualities. This is particularly relevant to self-love and concern for our own happiness. Once, a statesman, amidst the turmoil and conflict of political parties, managed to use his persuasive skills to achieve the banishment of a skilled opponent; whom he secretly followed, offering him money to support him during his exile, and comforting him with words of consolation in his misfortunes. “Alas!” cries the banished statesman, “With what regret must I leave my friends in this city, where even enemies are so generous!” Virtue, even when found in an enemy, pleased him here. We also give it the deserved recognition and praise; we don’t take back these feelings when we learn that this event took place in Athens around two thousand years ago and that the individuals involved were Eschines and Demosthenes.

WHAT IS THAT TO ME? There are few occasions, when this question is not pertinent: And had it that universal, infallible influence supposed, it would turn into ridicule every composition, and almost every conversation, which contain any praise or censure of men and manners.

WHAT DOES THAT MEAN TO ME? There are only a few instances when this question isn't relevant: And if it had that universal, undeniable power that’s assumed, it would make a joke of every piece of writing, and almost every conversation, that includes any praise or criticism of people and behaviors.

It is but a weak subterfuge, when pressed by these facts and arguments, to say, that we transport ourselves, by the force of imagination, into distant ages and countries, and consider the advantage, which we should have reaped from these characters, had we been contemporaries, and had any commerce with the persons. It is not conceivable, how a REAL sentiment or passion can ever arise from a known IMAGINARY interest; especially when our REAL interest is still kept in view, and is often acknowledged to be entirely distinct from the imaginary, and even sometimes opposite to it.

It's a weak excuse, when faced with these facts and arguments, to say that we use our imagination to transport ourselves to distant times and places, considering the benefits we would have gained from these characters if we had lived at the same time and interacted with them. It's hard to understand how a genuine feeling or passion can develop from a recognized imaginary interest, especially when our real interest is clearly in focus and is often recognized as completely different from the imaginary, and sometimes even in conflict with it.

A man, brought to the brink of a precipice, cannot look down without trembling; and the sentiment of IMAGINARY danger actuates him, in opposition to the opinion and belief of REAL safety. But the imagination is here assisted by the presence of a striking object; and yet prevails not, except it be also aided by novelty, and the unusual appearance of the object. Custom soon reconciles us to heights and precipices, and wears off these false and delusive terrors. The reverse is observable in the estimates which we form of characters and manners; and the more we habituate ourselves to an accurate scrutiny of morals, the more delicate feeling do we acquire of the most minute distinctions between vice and virtue. Such frequent occasion, indeed, have we, in common life, to pronounce all kinds of moral determinations, that no object of this kind can be new or unusual to us; nor could any FALSE views or prepossessions maintain their ground against an experience, so common and familiar. Experience being chiefly what forms the associations of ideas, it is impossible that any association could establish and support itself, in direct opposition to that principle.

A man standing on the edge of a cliff can't look down without shaking, and the feeling of IMAGINARY danger moves him, despite the belief in REAL safety. But here, the imagination is triggered by the sight of a striking object, and it only takes hold if it's backed by novelty and the unusual look of the object. We quickly get used to heights and cliffs, which helps diminish these false and misleading fears. The opposite happens with how we judge characters and behaviors; the more we train ourselves to accurately examine morals, the more sensitive we become to the subtle differences between vice and virtue. In everyday life, we often have to make moral judgments, so no moral object can truly be new or surprising to us; no FALSE views or biases can hold up against such familiar experience. Since experience is mainly what shapes our associations of ideas, it's impossible for any association to establish and maintain itself in direct conflict with that principle.

Usefulness is agreeable, and engages our approbation. This is a matter of fact, confirmed by daily observation. But, USEFUL? For what? For somebody's interest, surely. Whose interest then? Not our own only: For our approbation frequently extends farther. It must, therefore, be the interest of those, who are served by the character or action approved of; and these we may conclude, however remote, are not totally indifferent to us. By opening up this principle, we shall discover one great source of moral distinctions.

Usefulness is appealing and earns our approval. This is a fact confirmed by daily observations. But, USEFUL? For what? Surely for someone’s benefit. Whose benefit, then? Not just our own; our approval often goes beyond that. Therefore, it must serve the interests of those who benefit from the character or action we approve of; and even if they're distant, we can conclude they are not completely indifferent to us. By exploring this principle, we will uncover a significant source of moral distinctions.





PART II.

Self-love is a principle in human nature of such extensive energy, and the interest of each individual is, in general, so closely connected with that of the community, that those philosophers were excusable, who fancied that all our concern for the public might be resolved into a concern for our own happiness and preservation. They saw every moment, instances of approbation or blame, satisfaction or displeasure towards characters and actions; they denominated the objects of these sentiments, VIRTUES, or VICES; they observed, that the former had a tendency to increase the happiness, and the latter the misery of mankind; they asked, whether it were possible that we could have any general concern for society, or any disinterested resentment of the welfare or injury of others; they found it simpler to consider all these sentiments as modifications of self-love; and they discovered a pretence, at least, for this unity of principle, in that close union of interest, which is so observable between the public and each individual.

Self-love is a fundamental aspect of human nature that has a vast influence, and the interests of each person are generally so intertwined with those of the community that the philosophers who believed our concern for the public could be boiled down to a concern for our own happiness and survival were not entirely off base. They noted how, every moment, we express approval or disapproval, satisfaction or dissatisfaction towards people's behaviors and actions; they called these feelings VIRTUES or VICES. They saw that virtues tend to enhance human happiness, while vices tend to bring about misery; they questioned whether it was possible for us to genuinely care about society or feel unselfish concern for the wellbeing or harm of others. They found it easier to view all these feelings as expressions of self-love, and they identified a justification, at least, for this unity of principle in the strong connection of interests that exists between the community and each individual.

But notwithstanding this frequent confusion of interests, it is easy to attain what natural philosophers, after Lord Bacon, have affected to call the experimentum crucis, or that experiment which points out the right way in any doubt or ambiguity. We have found instances, in which private interest was separate from public; in which it was even contrary: And yet we observed the moral sentiment to continue, notwithstanding this disjunction of interests. And wherever these distinct interests sensibly concurred, we always found a sensible increase of the sentiment, and a more warm affection to virtue, and detestation of vice, or what we properly call, GRATITUDE and REVENGE. Compelled by these instances, we must renounce the theory, which accounts for every moral sentiment by the principle of self-love. We must adopt a more public affection, and allow, that the interests of society are not, even on their own account, entirely indifferent to us. Usefulness is only a tendency to a certain end; and it is a contradiction in terms, that anything pleases as means to an end, where the end itself no wise affects us. If usefulness, therefore, be a source of moral sentiment, and if this usefulness be not always considered with a reference to self; it follows, that everything, which contributes to the happiness of society, recommends itself directly to our approbation and good-will. Here is a principle, which accounts, in great part, for the origin of morality: And what need we seek for abstruse and remote systems, when there occurs one so obvious and natural?

But despite this frequent mix-up of interests, it’s easy to reach what natural philosophers, following Lord Bacon, have called the crucial experiment, or that experiment which shows the correct path in times of doubt or uncertainty. We’ve observed cases where private interests were separate from public ones; in some cases, they were even contradictory. Yet we noticed that moral feelings persisted, even with this separation of interests. Whenever these distinct interests clearly aligned, we consistently saw a strong increase in moral sentiment, along with a warmer appreciation for virtue and a strong aversion to vice, which we refer to as GRATITUDE and REVENGE. Given these examples, we must reject the theory that explains every moral sentiment solely through self-interest. We need to embrace a more communal concern and recognize that societal interests are not entirely indifferent to us, even for their own sake. Usefulness is merely a way to achieve a certain goal, and it’s contradictory to think that something pleases us as a means to an end when that end does not affect us at all. Therefore, if usefulness is a source of moral sentiment and if this usefulness isn’t always viewed in relation to ourselves, it follows that anything contributing to society’s happiness earns our approval and goodwill. This principle largely explains the origin of morality, so why search for complex and distant theories when there’s one so clear and natural?

[FOOTNOTE: It is needless to push our researches so far as to ask, why we have humanity or a fellow-feeling with others. It is sufficient, that this is experienced to be a principle in human nature. We must stop somewhere in our examination of causes; and there are, in every science, some general principles, beyond which we cannot hope to find any principle more general. No man is absolutely indifferent to the happiness and misery of others. The first has a natural tendency to give pleasure; the second, pain. This every one may find in himself. It is not probable, that these principles can be resolved into principles more simple and universal, whatever attempts may have been made to that purpose. But if it were possible, it belongs not to the present subject; and we may here safely consider these principles as original; happy, if we can render all the consequences sufficiently plain and perspicuous!]

[FOOTNOTE: There's no need to push our research so far as to ask why we have humanity or empathy for others. It's enough that this is felt as a principle in human nature. We have to stop somewhere in our exploration of causes; every science has some general principles beyond which we can’t hope to find any more universal principle. No one is completely indifferent to the happiness and suffering of others. Happiness tends to bring pleasure, while suffering brings pain. Everyone can find this in themselves. It's unlikely that these principles can be reduced to simpler or more universal principles, no matter how hard anyone tries. But even if it were possible, that’s not the focus here, and we can safely consider these principles as original; it's great if we can make all the consequences clear and understandable!]

Have we any difficulty to comprehend the force of humanity and benevolence? Or to conceive, that the very aspect of happiness, joy, prosperity, gives pleasure; that of pain, suffering, sorrow, communicates uneasiness? The human countenance, says Horace ['Uti ridentibus arrident, ita flentibus adflent Humani vultus,'—Hor.], borrows smiles or tears from the human countenance. Reduce a person to solitude, and he loses all enjoyment, except either of the sensual or speculative kind; and that because the movements of his heart are not forwarded by correspondent movements in his fellow-creatures. The signs of sorrow and mourning, though arbitrary, affect us with melancholy; but the natural symptoms, tears and cries and groans, never fail to infuse compassion and uneasiness. And if the effects of misery touch us in so lively a manner; can we be supposed altogether insensible or indifferent towards its causes; when a malicious or treacherous character and behaviour are presented to us?

Do we struggle to understand the power of humanity and kindness? Or to realize that happiness, joy, and prosperity bring pleasure, while pain, suffering, and sorrow create discomfort? The human face, as Horace said, is influenced by smiles or tears. Isolate someone, and they lose all enjoyment except for physical or abstract pleasures, because their feelings aren't mirrored by others around them. The signs of sorrow and mourning, even if they are just conventions, still make us feel sad; but natural expressions like tears, cries, and groans never fail to evoke compassion and unease. If the effects of misery affect us so deeply, can we really be completely insensitive or indifferent to its causes when confronted with a malicious or deceitful person?

We enter, I shall suppose, into a convenient, warm, well-contrived apartment: We necessarily receive a pleasure from its very survey; because it presents us with the pleasing ideas of ease, satisfaction, and enjoyment. The hospitable, good-humoured, humane landlord appears. This circumstance surely must embellish the whole; nor can we easily forbear reflecting, with pleasure, on the satisfaction which results to every one from his intercourse and good-offices.

We enter, I suppose, into a cozy, warm, well-designed apartment: We naturally feel a sense of pleasure just from looking at it; because it gives us thoughts of comfort, contentment, and enjoyment. The friendly, cheerful, kind landlord shows up. This must definitely enhance the whole experience; it's hard not to think about the happiness everyone gets from his interactions and helpfulness.

His whole family, by the freedom, ease, confidence, and calm enjoyment, diffused over their countenances, sufficiently express their happiness. I have a pleasing sympathy in the prospect of so much joy, and can never consider the source of it, without the most agreeable emotions.

His whole family, with their freedom, ease, confidence, and calm enjoyment evident in their faces, clearly show their happiness. I feel a warm connection to the idea of such joy and can never think about the source of it without feeling really good emotions.

He tells me, that an oppressive and powerful neighbour had attempted to dispossess him of his inheritance, and had long disturbed all his innocent and social pleasures. I feel an immediate indignation arise in me against such violence and injury.

He tells me that a powerful and oppressive neighbor tried to take away his inheritance and had long disrupted all his innocent and social joys. I feel a surge of anger against such violence and harm.

But it is no wonder, he adds, that a private wrong should proceed from a man, who had enslaved provinces, depopulated cities, and made the field and scaffold stream with human blood. I am struck with horror at the prospect of so much misery, and am actuated by the strongest antipathy against its author.

But it's no surprise, he adds, that a personal injustice would come from a man who had enslaved territories, emptied cities, and made the land and the gallows flow with human blood. I'm horrified at the thought of so much suffering and feel a deep hatred towards its perpetrator.

In general, it is certain, that, wherever we go, whatever we reflect on or converse about, everything still presents us with the view of human happiness or misery, and excites in our breast a sympathetic movement of pleasure or uneasiness. In our serious occupations, in our careless amusements, this principle still exerts its active energy.

In general, it's clear that wherever we go, whatever we think about or talk about, everything still shows us the reality of human happiness or misery, and stirs feelings of pleasure or discomfort within us. In our serious work and our carefree entertainment, this principle remains active.

A man who enters the theatre, is immediately struck with the view of so great a multitude, participating of one common amusement; and experiences, from their very aspect, a superior sensibility or disposition of being affected with every sentiment, which he shares with his fellow-creatures.

A man who walks into the theater is immediately impacted by the sight of such a large crowd enjoying the same entertainment together; and he feels, just from looking at them, a heightened sensitivity or inclination to be affected by every emotion that he shares with his fellow humans.

He observes the actors to be animated by the appearance of a full audience, and raised to a degree of enthusiasm, which they cannot command in any solitary or calm moment.

He sees the actors energized by the sight of a full audience, filled with a level of enthusiasm they can’t muster in any quiet or solitary moment.

Every movement of the theatre, by a skilful poet, is communicated, as it were by magic, to the spectators; who weep, tremble, resent, rejoice, and are inflamed with all the variety of passions, which actuate the several personages of the drama.

Every movement in the theater, crafted by a skilled poet, is communicated, almost like magic, to the audience; who cry, feel scared, get angry, rejoice, and are stirred by all the different emotions that drive the various characters in the play.

Where any event crosses our wishes, and interrupts the happiness of the favourite characters, we feel a sensible anxiety and concern. But where their sufferings proceed from the treachery, cruelty, or tyranny of an enemy, our breasts are affected with the liveliest resentment against the author of these calamities. It is here esteemed contrary to the rules of art to represent anything cool and indifferent. A distant friend, or a confident, who has no immediate interest in the catastrophe, ought, if possible, to be avoided by the poet; as communicating a like indifference to the audience, and checking the progress of the passions.

Whenever an event disrupts our hopes and interrupts the happiness of the beloved characters, we feel a strong sense of anxiety and concern. But when their suffering results from the betrayal, cruelty, or oppression of an enemy, it stirs our deepest anger towards the source of these misfortunes. It's generally considered poor craft to depict anything in a cool or indifferent manner. A distant friend or a confidant who isn't directly impacted by the tragedy should, if possible, be avoided by the writer, as they would convey a similar indifference to the audience and hinder the buildup of emotions.

Few species of poetry are more entertaining than PASTORAL; and every one is sensible, that the chief source of its pleasure arises from those images of a gentle and tender tranquillity, which it represents in its personages, and of which it communicates a like sentiment to the reader. Sannazarius, who transferred the scene to the sea-shore, though he presented the most magnificent object in nature, is confessed to have erred in his choice. The idea of toil, labour, and danger, suffered by the fishermen, is painful; by an unavoidable sympathy, which attends every conception of human happiness or misery.

Few types of poetry are more enjoyable than PASTORAL, and everyone can agree that the main source of its pleasure comes from the images of gentle and soothing tranquility it portrays through its characters, which also evokes similar feelings in the reader. Sannazarius, who moved the setting to the beach, even though he showcased the most magnificent sights in nature, is generally seen as having made a mistake in his choice. The thought of the toil, hard work, and dangers faced by the fishermen is distressing, due to an unavoidable empathy that comes with any idea of human happiness or suffering.

When I was twenty, says a French poet, Ovid was my favourite: Now I am forty, I declare for Horace. We enter, to be sure, more readily into sentiments, which resemble those we feel every day: But no passion, when well represented, can be entirely indifferent to us; because there is none, of which every man has not, within him, at least the seeds and first principles. It is the business of poetry to bring every affection near to us by lively imagery and representation, and make it look like truth and reality: A certain proof, that, wherever that reality is found, our minds are disposed to be strongly affected by it.

When I was twenty, a French poet said Ovid was my favorite; now that I’m forty, I support Horace. We definitely connect more easily with feelings that resemble those we experience daily. But no passion, when portrayed well, can be completely unimportant to us; because everyone has, within them, at least the seeds and beginnings of every emotion. It’s the job of poetry to bring every feeling closer to us through vivid imagery and representation, making it seem like truth and reality. This proves that wherever that reality exists, our minds are ready to be deeply moved by it.

Any recent event or piece of news, by which the fate of states, provinces, or many individuals is affected, is extremely interesting even to those whose welfare is not immediately engaged. Such intelligence is propagated with celerity, heard with avidity, and enquired into with attention and concern. The interest of society appears, on this occasion, to be in some degree the interest of each individual. The imagination is sure to be affected; though the passions excited may not always be so strong and steady as to have great influence on the conduct and behaviour.

Any recent event or piece of news that impacts the fate of countries, regions, or many individuals is very interesting, even to those whose own well-being isn't directly involved. News spreads quickly, is eagerly listened to, and is investigated with care and concern. In this case, the interest of society seems to reflect the interest of each person. While people's imaginations are definitely engaged, the emotions stirred up may not always be intense or stable enough to significantly influence their actions and behavior.

The perusal of a history seems a calm entertainment; but would be no entertainment at all, did not our hearts beat with correspondent movements to those which are described by the historian.

Reading history may seem like a calm pastime, but it wouldn’t be enjoyable at all if our hearts didn’t resonate with the feelings that the historian describes.

Thucydides and Guicciardin support with difficulty our attention; while the former describes the trivial encounters of the small cities of Greece, and the latter the harmless wars of Pisa. The few persons interested and the small interest fill not the imagination, and engage not the affections. The deep distress of the numerous Athenian army before Syracuse; the danger which so nearly threatens Venice; these excite compassion; these move terror and anxiety.

Thucydides and Guicciardin struggle to hold our attention; while the former talks about the petty conflicts of the small city-states in Greece, and the latter covers the minor wars in Pisa. The lack of significant interest and the few people involved fail to capture our imagination or evoke our feelings. However, the intense suffering of the large Athenian army before Syracuse and the imminent threat facing Venice inspire compassion, fear, and anxiety.

The indifferent, uninteresting style of Suetonius, equally with the masterly pencil of Tacitus, may convince us of the cruel depravity of Nero or Tiberius: But what a difference of sentiment! While the former coldly relates the facts; and the latter sets before our eyes the venerable figures of a Soranus and a Thrasea, intrepid in their fate, and only moved by the melting sorrows of their friends and kindred. What sympathy then touches every human heart! What indignation against the tyrant, whose causeless fear or unprovoked malice gave rise to such detestable barbarity!

The indifferent, unengaging style of Suetonius, along with the skilled writing of Tacitus, can show us the cruel depravity of Nero or Tiberius. But what a difference in feeling! While the former coldly recounts the facts, the latter presents the noble figures of Soranus and Thrasea, brave in their fate and only affected by the deep sorrow of their friends and family. What sympathy touches every human heart! What outrage against the tyrant, whose unfounded fear or wanton malice led to such horrific brutality!

If we bring these subjects nearer: If we remove all suspicion of fiction and deceit: What powerful concern is excited, and how much superior, in many instances, to the narrow attachments of self-love and private interest! Popular sedition, party zeal, a devoted obedience to factious leaders; these are some of the most visible, though less laudable effects of this social sympathy in human nature.

If we bring these topics closer together: If we eliminate any doubt of falsehood and trickery: What strong emotions are stirred up, and how much greater they are, in many cases, than the limited attachments of self-interest and personal gain! Public unrest, political enthusiasm, and blind loyalty to divisive leaders; these are some of the most apparent, though less admirable, outcomes of this social connection in human nature.

The frivolousness of the subject too, we may observe, is not able to detach us entirely from what carries an image of human sentiment and affection.

The lightness of the topic, we can see, doesn't completely disconnect us from anything that reflects human feelings and emotions.

When a person stutters, and pronounces with difficulty, we even sympathize with this trivial uneasiness, and suffer for him. And it is a rule in criticism, that every combination of syllables or letters, which gives pain to the organs of speech in the recital, appears also from a species of sympathy harsh and disagreeable to the ear. Nay, when we run over a book with our eye, we are sensible of such unharmonious composition; because we still imagine, that a person recites it to us, and suffers from the pronunciation of these jarring sounds. So delicate is our sympathy!

When someone stutters and struggles to speak, we often feel for them and share in their discomfort. There's a rule in criticism that says any combination of syllables or letters that causes difficulty in speaking is also harsh and unpleasant to listen to. Even when we skim through a book, we notice awkward phrasing because we can envision someone reading it aloud and struggling with those clashing sounds. Our sense of empathy is truly sensitive!

Easy and unconstrained postures and motions are always beautiful: An air of health and vigour is agreeable: Clothes which warm, without burthening the body; which cover, without imprisoning the limbs, are well-fashioned. In every judgement of beauty, the feelings of the person affected enter into consideration, and communicate to the spectator similar touches of pain or pleasure.

Comfortable and natural postures and movements are always attractive. A sense of health and energy is appealing. Clothes that keep you warm without weighing you down, that cover without restricting your movements, are well-designed. In every assessment of beauty, the emotions of the person experiencing it play a role, creating similar feelings of discomfort or joy in the observer.

     [Footnote: 'Decentior equus cujus astricta suntilia; sed idem
velocior. Pulcher aspectu sit athleta, cujus lacertos execitatio
expressit; idem certamini paratior nunquam enim SPECIES ab UTILITATE
dividitur. Sed hoc quidem discernere modici judicii est.'—Quintilian,
Inst. lib. viii. cap. 3.]
     [Footnote: 'A decent horse has restrained movements; but it is also faster. A good-looking athlete whose muscles are well-defined is also always ready for a competition, for appearance is never separate from usefulness. But this is indeed something only a person of modest judgment can discern.'—Quintilian, Inst. lib. viii. cap. 3.]

What wonder, then, if we can pronounce no judgement concerning the character and conduct of men, without considering the tendencies of their actions, and the happiness or misery which thence arises to society? What association of ideas would ever operate, were that principle here totally unactive.

What a surprise, then, if we can't make any judgments about people's character and behavior without looking at the impact of their actions and the happiness or suffering that results for society. What connections of ideas would even take place if that principle were completely absent?

     [Footnote: In proportion to the station which a man possesses,
according to the relations in which he is placed; we always expect from
him a greater or less degree of good, and when disappointed, blame his
inutility; and much more do we blame him, if any ill or prejudice
arise from his conduct and behaviour. When the interests of one country
interfere with those of another, we estimate the merits of a statesman
by the good or ill, which results to his own country from his measures
and councils, without regard to the prejudice which he brings on its
enemies and rivals. His fellow-citizens are the objects, which lie
nearest the eye, while we determine his character. And as nature has
implanted in every one a superior affection to his own country, we never
expect any regard to distant nations, where a competition arises. Not to
mention, that, while every man consults the good of his own community,
we are sensible, that the general interest of mankind is better
promoted, than any loose indeterminate views to the good of a species,
whence no beneficial action could ever result, for want of a duly
limited object, on which they could exert themselves.]
[Footnote: Depending on a person's position and the relationships they are in, we expect them to show varying degrees of goodness. When we are let down, we criticize their uselessness; and we blame them even more if any harm or bias results from their actions and behavior. When the interests of one country clash with those of another, we assess a politician's worth based on the benefits or harms their decisions bring to their own country, ignoring the negative impact on their enemies and rivals. Their fellow citizens are our main focus when judging their character. Since nature has instilled in everyone a greater loyalty to their own country, we rarely expect concern for far-off nations when competition arises. Additionally, while each person aims for the welfare of their own community, we recognize that the overall good of humanity is better served than any vague and undefined ambitions for the betterment of the human race, which could never lead to meaningful actions due to a lack of a specific target to direct those efforts toward.]

If any man from a cold insensibility, or narrow selfishness of temper, is unaffected with the images of human happiness or misery, he must be equally indifferent to the images of vice and virtue: As, on the other hand, it is always found, that a warm concern for the interests of our species is attended with a delicate feeling of all moral distinctions; a strong resentment of injury done to men; a lively approbation of their welfare. In this particular, though great superiority is observable of one man above another; yet none are so entirely indifferent to the interest of their fellow-creatures, as to perceive no distinctions of moral good and evil, in consequence of the different tendencies of actions and principles. How, indeed, can we suppose it possible in any one, who wears a human heart, that if there be subjected to his censure, one character or system of conduct, which is beneficial, and another which is pernicious to his species or community, he will not so much as give a cool preference to the former, or ascribe to it the smallest merit or regard? Let us suppose such a person ever so selfish; let private interest have ingrossed ever so much his attention; yet in instances, where that is not concerned, he must unavoidably feel SOME propensity to the good of mankind, and make it an object of choice, if everything else be equal. Would any man, who is walking along, tread as willingly on another's gouty toes, whom he has no quarrel with, as on the hard flint and pavement? There is here surely a difference in the case. We surely take into consideration the happiness and misery of others, in weighing the several motives of action, and incline to the former, where no private regards draw us to seek our own promotion or advantage by the injury of our fellow-creatures. And if the principles of humanity are capable, in many instances, of influencing our actions, they must, at all times, have some authority over our sentiments, and give us a general approbation of what is useful to society, and blame of what is dangerous or pernicious. The degrees of these sentiments may be the subject of controversy; but the reality of their existence, one should think, must be admitted in every theory or system.

If a person, due to a cold indifference or selfish nature, is unaffected by the sights of human happiness or suffering, they will also be indifferent to the images of good and bad behavior. Conversely, a genuine concern for the well-being of others typically comes with a keen awareness of moral distinctions; it brings a strong reaction against harm done to others and a genuine appreciation for their welfare. In this regard, while there are noticeable differences between individuals, none are completely indifferent to the interests of their fellow human beings to the extent that they fail to recognize the moral differences stemming from the impacts of actions and principles. How could anyone with a human heart possibly overlook a situation where one behavior benefits the community and another harms it? Would they not at least prefer the former and acknowledge it has some merit? Even if someone is selfish and preoccupied with their self-interest, in situations where personal gain is not at stake, they will inevitably feel some inclination toward the good of humanity and may choose it if nothing else matters. Would anyone casually step on another person's painful toes, whom they have no issue with, rather than walk on hard stones and pavement? Clearly, there’s a difference here. We definitely consider the happiness and suffering of others when thinking about our motivations, and we lean toward the former when we’re not driven by personal interests to hurt someone else for our own benefit. If our principles of humanity can often affect our actions, they must also consistently influence our feelings, leading us to generally support what benefits society and criticize what is harmful or dangerous. While the extent of these feelings may be debated, their existence should be acknowledged in any theory or system.

A creature, absolutely malicious and spiteful, were there any such in nature, must be worse than indifferent to the images of vice and virtue. All his sentiments must be inverted, and directly opposite to those, which prevail in the human species. Whatever contributes to the good of mankind, as it crosses the constant bent of his wishes and desires, must produce uneasiness and disapprobation; and on the contrary, whatever is the source of disorder and misery in society, must, for the same reason, be regarded with pleasure and complacency. Timon, who probably from his affected spleen more than an inveterate malice, was denominated the manhater, embraced Alcibiades with great fondness. GO ON, MY BOY! cried he, ACQUIRE THE CONFIDENCE OF THE PEOPLE: YOU WILL ONE DAY, I FORESEE, BE THE CAUSE OF GREAT CALAMITIES TO THEM [Footnote: Plutarch fit vita Ale.]. Could we admit the two principles of the Manicheans, it is an infallible consequence, that their sentiments of human actions, as well as of everything else, must be totally opposite, and that every instance of justice and humanity, from its necessary tendency, must please the one deity and displease the other. All mankind so far resemble the good principle, that, where interest or revenge or envy perverts not our disposition, we are always inclined, from our natural philanthropy, to give the preference to the happiness of society, and consequently to virtue above its opposite. Absolute, unprovoked, disinterested malice has never perhaps place in any human breast; or if it had, must there pervert all the sentiments of morals, as well as the feelings of humanity. If the cruelty of Nero be allowed entirely voluntary, and not rather the effect of constant fear and resentment; it is evident that Tigellinus, preferably to Seneca or Burrhus, must have possessed his steady and uniform approbation.

A creature, truly malicious and spiteful—if such a thing existed—would have to be worse than indifferent to notions of good and evil. All their feelings would be completely reversed and stand in direct opposition to those of humanity. Anything that benefits mankind would cause them discomfort and disapproval, while anything that brings chaos and suffering to society would be viewed with enjoyment and satisfaction. Timon, who was likely more affected by his own bitterness than actual hatred, was called the man-hater but embraced Alcibiades warmly. "Go on, my boy!" he exclaimed. "Win the people's trust; I foresee that one day you will bring them great misfortunes." If we accept the two principles of the Manicheans, then it logically follows that their views on human actions, along with everything else, would be completely opposite, and every act of justice and kindness would please one deity and displease the other. Humanity resembles the good principle to the extent that, unless interest, revenge, or envy distort our nature, we tend to lean towards promoting the happiness of society, thus valuing virtue over its contrary. Truly malicious, unprovoked spite may never have truly existed in any human heart; if it did, it would corrupt all moral sentiments and human feelings. If Nero's cruelty was entirely voluntary and not just a result of constant fear and resentment, it’s clear that Tigellinus, rather than Seneca or Burrhus, would have had his unwavering approval.

A statesman or patriot, who serves our own country in our own time, has always a more passionate regard paid to him, than one whose beneficial influence operated on distant ages or remote nations; where the good, resulting from his generous humanity, being less connected with us, seems more obscure, and affects us with a less lively sympathy. We may own the merit to be equally great, though our sentiments are not raised to an equal height, in both cases. The judgement here corrects the inequalities of our internal emotions and perceptions; in like manner, as it preserves us from error, in the several variations of images, presented to our external senses. The same object, at a double distance, really throws on the eye a picture of but half the bulk; yet we imagine that it appears of the same size in both situations; because we know that on our approach to it, its image would expand on the eye, and that the difference consists not in the object itself, but in our position with regard to it. And, indeed, without such a correction of appearances, both in internal and external sentiment, men could never think or talk steadily on any subject; while their fluctuating situations produce a continual variation on objects, and throw them into such different and contrary lights and positions.

A statesman or patriot who serves our country in our time always gets more passionate recognition than someone whose positive influence was felt in distant times or far-off nations. The good that comes from their generous actions feels less connected to us, seems more obscure, and stirs up less emotional response. We can acknowledge that the merit is equally significant, even if our feelings aren't as intense in both cases. Our judgment balances out the different levels of our feelings and perceptions, much like it protects us from making mistakes with the various images presented to our senses. The same object, from a greater distance, actually appears to be half its size; yet we think it looks the same in both situations because we know that as we get closer, its image would seem to grow larger, and the difference lies not in the object itself but in our position relative to it. Indeed, without correcting these perceptions, both internally and externally, people could never think or speak consistently about any topic, as their shifting circumstances create constant changes in how they see things, putting them in such different and opposing perspectives.

     [Footnote: For a little reason, the tendencies of actions and
characters, not their real accidental consequences, are alone regarded
in our more determinations or general judgements; though in our real
feeling or sentiment, we cannot help paying greater regard to one whose
station, joined to virtue, renders him really useful to society, then
to one, who exerts the social virtues only in good intentions and
benevolent affections. Separating the character from the furtone, by an
easy and necessary effort of thought, we pronounce these persons alike,
and give them the appearance: But is not able entirely to prevail our
sentiment.

   Why is this peach-tree said to be better than that other; but because
it produces more or better fruit? And would not the same praise be given
it, though snails or vermin had destroyed the peaches, before they came
to full maturity? In morals too, is not THE TREE KNOWN BY THE FRUIT?
And cannot we easily distinguish between nature and accident, in the one
case as well as in the other?]
     [Footnote: For a simple reason, we only consider the tendencies of actions and character, not their actual random outcomes, in our decisions or general judgments; however, in our genuine feelings or sentiments, we naturally give more importance to someone with a position and virtue that makes them truly beneficial to society than to someone who only expresses social virtues through good intentions and kind feelings. By easily and necessarily separating character from circumstance, we treat these individuals as equals, but our sentiments cannot be completely swayed.

   Why is this peach tree considered better than that one? It’s because it produces more or better fruit, right? And wouldn’t it still get the same praise even if snails or pests destroyed the peaches before they ripened? In moral terms as well, isn’t THE TREE KNOWN BY THE FRUIT? And can’t we clearly tell the difference between nature and accident in both cases?]

The more we converse with mankind, and the greater social intercourse we maintain, the more shall we be familiarized to these general preferences and distinctions, without which our conversation and discourse could scarcely be rendered intelligible to each other. Every man's interest is peculiar to himself, and the aversions and desires, which result from it, cannot be supposed to affect others in a like degree. General language, therefore, being formed for general use, must be moulded on some more general views, and must affix the epithets of praise or blame, in conformity to sentiments, which arise from the general interests of the community. And if these sentiments, in most men, be not so strong as those, which have a reference to private good; yet still they must make some distinction, even in persons the most depraved and selfish; and must attach the notion of good to a beneficent conduct, and of evil to the contrary. Sympathy, we shall allow, is much fainter than our concern for ourselves, and sympathy with persons remote from us much fainter than that with persons near and contiguous; but for this very reason it is necessary for us, in our calm judgements and discourse concerning the characters of men, to neglect all these differences, and render our sentiments more public and social. Besides, that we ourselves often change our situation in this particular, we every day meet with persons who are in a situation different from us, and who could never converse with us were we to remain constantly in that position and point of view, which is peculiar to ourselves. The intercourse of sentiments, therefore, in society and conversation, makes us form some general unalterable standard, by which we may approve or disapprove of characters and manners. And though the heart takes not part entirely with those general notions, nor regulates all its love and hatred by the universal abstract differences of vice and virtue, without regard to self, or the persons with whom we are more intimately connected; yet have these moral differences a considerable influence, and being sufficient, at least for discourse, serve all our purposes in company, in the pulpit, on the theatre, and in the schools.

The more we talk with others and maintain social interactions, the more we become familiar with these general preferences and distinctions, which are essential for making our conversations and discussions understandable. Each person's interests are unique to them, and the dislikes and desires that come from those interests don't affect others in the same way. Therefore, general language, created for everyone to use, must be based on broader views and must assign labels of praise or blame according to sentiments that come from the common interests of the community. Even if these sentiments are not as strong for most people compared to those related to personal gain, they still create some distinctions, even among those who are most corrupt and selfish, and associate good behavior with kindness and bad behavior with the opposite. We can agree that our empathy is much weaker than our concern for ourselves, and our sympathy for those far away is even less than for those nearby; yet for this reason, it is necessary for us to overlook these differences in our calm judgments and discussions about people's characters, making our opinions more public and social. Moreover, since our own situations often change, we encounter people daily who are in different positions than us, and who could never truly connect with us if we always stayed in the narrow perspective that is unique to ourselves. Therefore, the exchange of sentiments in society and conversation helps us establish a general, unchanging standard by which we can approve or disapprove of people's characters and behaviors. Although our hearts don't always align completely with these general ideas and don't govern all our feelings of love and hate based solely on universal differences of good and bad without considering ourselves or those we’re closer to; these moral distinctions still have a significant impact, and are at least adequate for discussions in social situations, in sermons, on stage, and in classrooms.

     [Footnote: It is wisely ordained by nature, that private
connexions should commonly prevail over univeral views and
considerations; otherwise our affections and actions would be dissopated
and lost, for want of a proper limited object. Thus a small benefit done
to ourselves, or our near friends, excites more lively sentiments
of love and approbation than a great benefit done to a distant
commonwealth: But still we know here, as in all the senses, to correct
these inequalities by reflection, and retain a general standard of vice
and virtue, founded chiefly on a general usefulness.]
     [Footnote: It's wisely set by nature that personal connections usually take priority over broader perspectives and considerations; otherwise, our feelings and actions would be scattered and wasted due to a lack of a suitable focus. A small favor we do for ourselves or our close friends inspires stronger feelings of love and approval than a significant benefit given to a distant society. Still, we understand, just like in all senses, how to balance these disparities through reflection and maintain a general standard of good and bad, primarily based on overall usefulness.]

Thus, in whatever light we take this subject, the merit, ascribed to the social virtues, appears still uniform, and arises chiefly from that regard, which the natural sentiment of benevolence engages us to pay to the interests of mankind and society. If we consider the principles of the human make, such as they appear to daily experience and observation, we must, A PRIORI, conclude it impossible for such a creature as man to be totally indifferent to the well or ill-being of his fellow-creatures, and not readily, of himself, to pronounce, where nothing gives him any particular bias, that what promotes their happiness is good, what tends to their misery is evil, without any farther regard or consideration. Here then are the faint rudiments, at least, or outlines, of a GENERAL distinction between actions; and in proportion as the humanity of the person is supposed to increase, his connexion with those who are injured or benefited, and his lively conception of their misery or happiness; his consequent censure or approbation acquires proportionable vigour. There is no necessity, that a generous action, barely mentioned in an old history or remote gazette, should communicate any strong feelings of applause and admiration. Virtue, placed at such a distance, is like a fixed star, which, though to the eye of reason it may appear as luminous as the sun in his meridian, is so infinitely removed as to affect the senses, neither with light nor heat. Bring this virtue nearer, by our acquaintance or connexion with the persons, or even by an eloquent recital of the case; our hearts are immediately caught, our sympathy enlivened, and our cool approbation converted into the warmest sentiments of friendship and regard. These seem necessary and infallible consequences of the general principles of human nature, as discovered in common life and practice.

So, no matter how we look at this subject, the value attributed to social virtues seems pretty consistent and mainly comes from the natural inclination of kindness that leads us to care for the well-being of people and society. If we think about the way humans are, based on daily experiences and observations, we have to conclude from the start that it’s impossible for someone like a human to be completely indifferent to the happiness or suffering of others. People are likely to instinctively say that things which promote others' happiness are good and things that cause misery are bad, without needing further justification. Here, then, are the basic elements, at least, of a general distinction between actions; and as a person's humanity is believed to grow, so does their connection with those who suffer or benefit, and their strong awareness of others’ happiness or misery; as a result, their judgment of actions becomes stronger. There’s no need for a generous act, mentioned only in an old history or distant news, to evoke strong feelings of praise and admiration. Virtue placed so far away is like a fixed star, which may seem as bright as the sun when viewed rationally, but is too far away to affect our senses with light or warmth. If we bring that virtue closer through our relationships with people or even through an eloquent recounting of their situation, our hearts are instantly engaged, our empathy awakened, and our mild approval turned into the warmest feelings of friendship and affection. These reactions seem to be necessary and reliable outcomes of the basic principles of human nature as seen in everyday life and practice.

Again; reverse these views and reasonings: Consider the matter a posteriori; and weighing the consequences, enquire if the merit of social virtue be not, in a great measure, derived from the feelings of humanity, with which it affects the spectators. It appears to be matter of fact, that the circumstance of UTILITY, in all subjects, is a source of praise and approbation: That it is constantly appealed to in all moral decisions concerning the merit and demerit of actions: That it is the SOLE source of that high regard paid to justice, fidelity, honour, allegiance, and chastity: That it is inseparable from all the other social virtues, humanity, generosity, charity, affability, lenity, mercy, and moderation: And, in a word, that it is a foundation of the chief part of morals, which has a reference to mankind and our fellow-creatures.

Once again, let’s flip these perspectives and arguments: Consider the matter from a practical standpoint; and weighing the outcomes, ask if the value of social virtue doesn't largely come from the feelings of humanity it evokes in those who observe it. It's clear that utility, in all matters, is a source of admiration and approval: It is consistently referenced in all moral decisions about the worth and unworthiness of actions: It is the ONLY source of the high respect given to justice, loyalty, honor, allegiance, and purity: It is tied to all other social virtues—humanity, generosity, charity, friendliness, kindness, mercy, and moderation: In short, it forms the foundation of the main part of morals that relates to humanity and our fellow beings.

It appears also, that, in our general approbation of characters and manners, the useful tendency of the social virtues moves us not by any regards to self-interest, but has an influence much more universal and extensive. It appears that a tendency to public good, and to the promoting of peace, harmony, and order in society, does always, by affecting the benevolent principles of our frame, engage us on the side of the social virtues. And it appears, as an additional confirmation, that these principles of humanity and sympathy enter so deeply into all our sentiments, and have so powerful an influence, as may enable them to excite the strongest censure and applause. The present theory is the simple result of all these inferences, each of which seems founded on uniform experience and observation.

It also seems that our overall approval of characters and behaviors isn't driven by self-interest, but rather has a much broader and widespread impact. A focus on the public good and the promotion of peace, harmony, and order in society consistently aligns us with social virtues by appealing to our benevolent instincts. Additionally, these principles of kindness and empathy are so deeply rooted in all our feelings that they can trigger strong criticism or praise. The current theory is simply the result of all these conclusions, each supported by consistent experience and observation.

Were it doubtful, whether there were any such principle in our nature as humanity or a concern for others, yet when we see, in numberless instances, that whatever has a tendency to promote the interests of society, is so highly approved of, we ought thence to learn the force of the benevolent principle; since it is impossible for anything to please as means to an end, where the end is totally indifferent. On the other hand, were it doubtful, whether there were, implanted in our nature, any general principle of moral blame and approbation, yet when we see, in numberless instances, the influence of humanity, we ought thence to conclude, that it is impossible, but that everything which promotes the interest of society must communicate pleasure, and what is pernicious give uneasiness. But when these different reflections and observations concur in establishing the same conclusion, must they not bestow an undisputed evidence upon it?

If there were any doubt about whether we have a principle in our nature like humanity or concern for others, we can see from countless examples that things which promote the interests of society are highly valued. We should learn from this the strength of our benevolent nature, as nothing can genuinely please us as a means to an end if we are indifferent to that end. Similarly, even if we questioned whether there is a general principle of moral blame and approval within us, the influence of humanity in various cases suggests that anything promoting societal interests must bring pleasure, while harmful actions cause distress. When these different thoughts and observations all point to the same conclusion, shouldn't they provide clear evidence for it?

It is however hoped, that the progress of this argument will bring a farther confirmation of the present theory, by showing the rise of other sentiments of esteem and regard from the same or like principles.

It is hoped that the development of this argument will provide further support for the current theory by demonstrating the emergence of other feelings of respect and admiration based on similar principles.





SECTION VI. OF QUALITIES USEFUL TO OURSELVES.





PART I.

IT seems evident, that where a quality or habit is subjected to our examination, if it appear in any respect prejudicial to the person possessed of it, or such as incapacitates him for business and action, it is instantly blamed, and ranked among his faults and imperfections. Indolence, negligence, want of order and method, obstinacy, fickleness, rashness, credulity; these qualities were never esteemed by any one indifferent to a character; much less, extolled as accomplishments or virtues. The prejudice, resulting from them, immediately strikes our eye, and gives us the sentiment of pain and disapprobation.

It seems obvious that when we examine a quality or habit, if it appears harmful to the person who has it or prevents them from being effective in their work and actions, it is quickly criticized and seen as a fault or imperfection. Laziness, carelessness, lack of organization, stubbornness, unpredictability, impulsiveness, and gullibility are qualities that no one who cares about character would value, let alone praise as traits or virtues. The negative impact of these traits is immediately noticeable and evokes feelings of discomfort and disapproval.

No quality, it is allowed, is absolutely either blameable or praiseworthy. It is all according to its degree. A due medium, says the Peripatetics, is the characteristic of virtue. But this medium is chiefly determined by utility. A proper celerity, for instance, and dispatch in business, is commendable. When defective, no progress is ever made in the execution of any purpose: When excessive, it engages us in precipitate and ill-concerted measures and enterprises: By such reasonings, we fix the proper and commendable mediocrity in all moral and prudential disquisitions; and never lose view of the advantages, which result from any character or habit. Now as these advantages are enjoyed by the person possessed of the character, it can never be SELF-LOVE which renders the prospect of them agreeable to us, the spectators, and prompts our esteem and approbation. No force of imagination can convert us into another person, and make us fancy, that we, being that person, reap benefit from those valuable qualities, which belong to him. Or if it did, no celerity of imagination could immediately transport us back, into ourselves, and make us love and esteem the person, as different from us. Views and sentiments, so opposite to known truth and to each other, could never have place, at the same time, in the same person. All suspicion, therefore, of selfish regards, is here totally excluded. It is a quite different principle, which actuates our bosom, and interests us in the felicity of the person whom we contemplate. Where his natural talents and acquired abilities give us the prospect of elevation, advancement, a figure in life, prosperous success, a steady command over fortune, and the execution of great or advantageous undertakings; we are struck with such agreeable images, and feel a complacency and regard immediately arise towards him. The ideas of happiness, joy, triumph, prosperity, are connected with every circumstance of his character, and diffuse over our minds a pleasing sentiment of sympathy and humanity.

No quality is completely blameworthy or praiseworthy; it all depends on its degree. The Peripatetics say that virtue is characterized by a proper medium, which is mainly determined by usefulness. For example, having the right speed and efficiency in business is commendable. When this is lacking, progress is stalled, and when it’s excessive, it leads to hasty and poorly planned actions. Through such reasoning, we can identify the proper and commendable middle ground in all moral and practical discussions, while always keeping in mind the benefits that come from any character or habit. Since these benefits are enjoyed by the person with the character, it can’t be self-love that makes the prospect of these benefits appealing to us as observers and prompts our admiration and approval. No amount of imagination can transform us into another person and make us believe that by being that person, we are gaining from their valuable qualities. Even if we could, no speed of imagination could instantly bring us back to ourselves and allow us to love and esteem that individual as separate from us. Such conflicting views and feelings cannot coexist in the same person at the same time. Therefore, any suspicion of selfish motives is completely excluded here. It’s a different principle that moves us and makes us care about the happiness of the person we’re observing. When their natural talents and learned abilities promise us elevation, progress, a good position in life, successful outcomes, control over fortune, and the ability to undertake great or beneficial projects, we are captivated by these pleasant visions and immediately feel a sense of affection and regard for them. The ideas of happiness, joy, triumph, and prosperity are tied to every aspect of their character, filling our minds with a warm sentiment of empathy and humanity.

     [Footnote: One may venture to affirm, that there is no human
nature, to whom the appearance of happiness (where envy or revenge has
no place) does not give pleasure, that of misery, uneasiness. This
seems inseparable from our make and constitution. But they are only more
generous minds, that are thence prompted to seek zealously the good of
others, and to have a real passion for their welfare. With men of narrow
and ungenerous spirits, this sympathy goes not beyond a slight
feeling of the imagination, which serves only to excite sentiments
of complacency or ensure, and makes them apply to the object either
honorable or dishonorable appellations. A griping miser, for instance,
praises extremely INDUSTRY and FRUGALITY even in others, and sets them,
in his estimation, above all the other virtues. He knows the good that
results from them, and feels that species of happiness with a more
lively sympathy, than any other you could represent to him; though
perhaps he would not part with a shilling to make the fortune of the
industrious man, whom he praises so highly.]
     [Footnote: One might argue that there's no human nature that doesn't find joy in the sight of happiness (where envy or revenge have no role) and discomfort in the sight of misery. This seems to be an inherent part of who we are. However, it’s only the more generous individuals who are inspired to actively seek the well-being of others and have a true passion for their welfare. For those with narrow and unkind spirits, this sympathy barely goes beyond a fleeting feeling that only serves to evoke feelings of self-satisfaction or approval, and leads them to label the object with either honorable or dishonorable terms. Take a stingy miser, for instance, who highly praises INDUSTRY and FRUGALITY in others and considers these traits superior to all other virtues. He understands the benefits that come from them and feels a stronger connection to that kind of happiness than to any other you might describe; although he likely wouldn't part with a single penny to help the industrious person he praises so much.]

Let us suppose a person originally framed so as to have no manner of concern for his fellow-creatures, but to regard the happiness and misery of all sensible beings with greater indifference than even two contiguous shades of the same colour. Let us suppose, if the prosperity of nations were laid on the one hand, and their ruin on the other, and he were desired to choose; that he would stand like the schoolman's ass, irresolute and undetermined, between equal motives; or rather, like the same ass between two pieces of wood or marble, without any inclination or propensity to either side. The consequence, I believe, must be allowed just, that such a person, being absolutely unconcerned, either for the public good of a community or the private utility of others, would look on every quality, however pernicious, or however beneficial, to society, or to its possessor, with the same indifference as on the most common and uninteresting object.

Let’s imagine a person who is completely indifferent to his fellow humans, treating the happiness and suffering of all sentient beings with less concern than two shades of the same color. Suppose he had to choose between the prosperity of nations on one side and their destruction on the other; he would be like the philosopher's donkey, unsure and undecided between equal options, or rather, like the same donkey standing between two pieces of wood or marble, with no preference for either side. The conclusion must be accepted as valid: such a person, showing no concern for the public good of a community or the well-being of others, would view every trait, whether harmful or beneficial to society or its owner, with the same indifference as the most mundane and uninteresting object.

But if, instead of this fancied monster, we suppose a MAN to form a judgement or determination in the case, there is to him a plain foundation of preference, where everything else is equal; and however cool his choice may be, if his heart be selfish, or if the persons interested be remote from him; there must still be a choice or distinction between what is useful, and what is pernicious. Now this distinction is the same in all its parts, with the MORAL DISTINCTION, whose foundation has been so often, and so much in vain, enquired after. The same endowments of the mind, in every circumstance, are agreeable to the sentiment of morals and to that of humanity; the same temper is susceptible of high degrees of the one sentiment and of the other; and the same alteration in the objects, by their nearer approach or by connexions, enlivens the one and the other. By all the rules of philosophy, therefore, we must conclude, that these sentiments are originally the same; since, in each particular, even the most minute, they are governed by the same laws, and are moved by the same objects.

But if, instead of this imagined monster, we consider a PERSON making a judgment or decision in the situation, there is a clear basis for preference as long as everything else is equal; and no matter how detached his choice may seem, if his heart is selfish, or if the people involved are distant from him, there must still be a choice or distinction between what is beneficial and what is harmful. This distinction is completely aligned with the MORAL DISTINCTION, whose basis has been often and unsuccessfully searched for. The same qualities of the mind, in every circumstance, resonate with the sentiment of morals and that of humanity; the same disposition can strongly feel both sentiments; and any change in the objects, whether by their closer presence or by connections, enhances both. Therefore, according to all the principles of philosophy, we must conclude that these sentiments are fundamentally the same; since, in every instance, even the smallest ones, they are governed by the same rules and influenced by the same objects.

Why do philosophers infer, with the greatest certainty, that the moon is kept in its orbit by the same force of gravity, that makes bodies fall near the surface of the earth, but because these effects are, upon computation, found similar and equal? And must not this argument bring as strong conviction, in moral as in natural disquisitions?

Why do philosophers confidently conclude that the moon stays in its orbit due to the same force of gravity that causes objects to fall near the surface of the Earth? Isn't it because these effects, when calculated, are found to be similar and equal? And shouldn't this reasoning provide just as strong a conviction in moral discussions as it does in natural inquiries?

To prove, by any long detail, that all the qualities, useful to the possessor, are approved of, and the contrary censured, would be superfluous. The least reflection on what is every day experienced in life, will be sufficient. We shall only mention a few instances, in order to remove, if possible, all doubt and hesitation.

To prove, in great detail, that all the qualities beneficial to the owner are praised while the opposite is criticized would be unnecessary. Just a little thought about our everyday experiences will be enough. We’ll only point out a few examples to try to clear up any doubt or uncertainty.

The quality, the most necessary for the execution of any useful enterprise, is discretion; by which we carry on a safe intercourse with others, give due attention to our own and to their character, weigh each circumstance of the business which we undertake, and employ the surest and safest means for the attainment of any end or purpose. To a Cromwell, perhaps, or a De Retz, discretion may appear an alderman-like virtue, as Dr. Swift calls it; and being incompatible with those vast designs, to which their courage and ambition prompted them, it might really, in them, be a fault or imperfection. But in the conduct of ordinary life, no virtue is more requisite, not only to obtain success, but to avoid the most fatal miscarriages and disappointments. The greatest parts without it, as observed by an elegant writer, may be fatal to their owner; as Polyphemus, deprived of his eye, was only the more exposed, on account of his enormous strength and stature.

The most essential quality for successfully carrying out any useful venture is discretion. It allows us to interact safely with others, pay proper attention to both our own character and theirs, consider every aspect of the task at hand, and use the safest and most reliable methods to achieve any goal. For someone like Cromwell or De Retz, discretion might seem like a quality suited for a city official, as Dr. Swift puts it; since it doesn't align with their ambitious and daring plans, it could actually be viewed as a flaw in them. However, in everyday life, no virtue is more important, not just for achieving success but also for avoiding serious mistakes and disappointments. Without discretion, even the greatest abilities can become a liability for their possessor; as the poet notes, Polyphemus, stripped of his eye, became even more vulnerable due to his immense strength and size.

The best character, indeed, were it not rather too perfect for human nature, is that which is not swayed by temper of any kind; but alternately employs enterprise and caution, as each is useful to the particular purpose intended. Such is the excellence which St. Evremond ascribes to Mareschal Turenne, who displayed every campaign, as he grew older, more temerity in his military enterprises; and being now, from long experience, perfectly acquainted with every incident in war, he advanced with greater firmness and security, in a road so well known to him. Fabius, says Machiavel, was cautious; Scipio enterprising: And both succeeded, because the situation of the Roman affairs, during the command of each, was peculiarly adapted to his genius; but both would have failed, had these situations been reversed. He is happy, whose circumstances suit his temper; but he is more excellent, who can suit his temper to any circumstances.

The best character, truly, if not a bit too perfect for human nature, is one that isn't swayed by any kind of temperament. Instead, it uses a mix of boldness and caution, depending on what's needed for the particular goal. This is the quality that St. Evremond attributes to Mareschal Turenne, who, with each campaign and as he got older, showed more boldness in his military actions. With years of experience, he became fully familiar with every aspect of war and moved forward with greater confidence and security on paths he knew well. Machiavelli says that Fabius was cautious while Scipio was bold. Both succeeded because the situation of Roman affairs during their leadership matched their strengths perfectly; however, both would have failed if the situations had been switched. He is fortunate whose circumstances match his temperament; but he is even greater who can adapt his temperament to any situation.

What need is there to display the praises of industry, and to extol its advantages, in the acquisition of power and riches, or in raising what we call a FORTUNE in the world? The tortoise, according to the fable, by his perseverance, gained the race of the hare, though possessed of much superior swiftness. A man's time, when well husbanded, is like a cultivated field, of which a few acres produce more of what is useful to life, than extensive provinces, even of the richest soil, when over-run with weeds and brambles.

What's the point of singing the praises of hard work and highlighting its benefits in gaining power and wealth, or in building what we call a FORTUNE in life? According to the fable, the tortoise, through perseverance, won the race against the hare, which was much faster. A person's time, when managed well, is like a well-tended field, where just a few acres can yield more of what is essential for life than vast provinces of even the richest soil that are overrun with weeds and thorns.

But all prospect of success in life, or even of tolerable subsistence, must fail, where a reasonable frugality is wanting. The heap, instead of increasing, diminishes daily, and leaves its possessor so much more unhappy, as, not having been able to confine his expences to a large revenue, he will still less be able to live contentedly on a small one. The souls of men, according to Plato [Footnote: Phaedo.], inflamed with impure appetites, and losing the body, which alone afforded means of satisfaction, hover about the earth, and haunt the places, where their bodies are deposited; possessed with a longing desire to recover the lost organs of sensation. So may we see worthless prodigals, having consumed their fortune in wild debauches, thrusting themselves into every plentiful table, and every party of pleasure, hated even by the vicious, and despised even by fools.

But any chance of success in life, or even just getting by, will fail if there’s no reasonable frugality. Instead of growing, the wealth shrinks daily, leaving its owner even unhappier, since they couldn’t stick to their spending with a large income and will have an even harder time being content with a smaller one. The souls of men, according to Plato [Footnote: Phaedo.], consumed by unhealthy desires, lose the body, which was their only source of satisfaction, and linger around the earth, haunting the places where their bodies are buried; they are filled with a longing to regain their lost senses. Similarly, we see worthless spendthrifts, who have wasted their fortune on reckless partying, pushing themselves into every lavish feast and every social gathering, hated even by the immoral and looked down upon even by fools.

The one extreme of frugality is avarice, which, as it both deprives a man of all use of his riches, and checks hospitality and every social enjoyment, is justly censured on a double account. PRODIGALITY, the other extreme, is commonly more hurtful to a man himself; and each of these extremes is blamed above the other, according to the temper of the person who censures, and according to his greater or less sensibility to pleasure, either social or sensual.

The extreme of frugality is greed, which cuts a person off from enjoying their wealth and hinders hospitality and social enjoyment, making it rightly criticized for two reasons. On the other hand, extravagance is usually more damaging to a person themselves. Each of these extremes is criticized more than the other, depending on the attitude of the critic and their sensitivity to either social or physical pleasure.

Qualities often derive their merit from complicated sources. Honesty, fidelity, truth, are praised for their immediate tendency to promote the interests of society; but after those virtues are once established upon this foundation, they are also considered as advantageous to the person himself, and as the source of that trust and confidence, which can alone give a man any consideration in life. One becomes contemptible, no less than odious, when he forgets the duty, which, in this particular, he owes to himself as well as to society.

Qualities often gain their value from complex origins. Honesty, loyalty, and truth are celebrated for their direct ability to benefit society; however, once those virtues are established on this basis, they are also seen as beneficial for the individual and as the foundation of the trust and confidence that can truly give a person any respect in life. A person becomes not only contemptible but also detestable when they neglect the duty they owe to themselves as well as to society.

Perhaps, this consideration is one CHIEF source of the high blame, which is thrown on any instance of failure among women in point of CHASTITY. The greatest regard, which can be acquired by that sex, is derived from their fidelity; and a woman becomes cheap and vulgar, loses her rank, and is exposed to every insult, who is deficient in this particular. The smallest failure is here sufficient to blast her character. A female has so many opportunities of secretly indulging these appetites, that nothing can give us security but her absolute modesty and reserve; and where a breach is once made, it can scarcely ever be fully repaired. If a man behave with cowardice on one occasion, a contrary conduct reinstates him in his character. But by what action can a woman, whose behaviour has once been dissolute, be able to assure us, that she has formed better resolutions, and has self-command enough to carry them into execution?

Perhaps, this consideration is a major reason for the heavy criticism directed at any instance of failure among women regarding chastity. The highest regard that women can earn comes from their fidelity; when a woman lacks this, she becomes cheap and common, loses her status, and is vulnerable to insults. Even the slightest failure can ruin her reputation. A woman has numerous opportunities to indulge these desires secretly, so the only way to feel secure is through her absolute modesty and reserve; and once a breach occurs, it is nearly impossible to fully repair it. If a man acts cowardly on one occasion, he can regain his reputation through a different behavior. But how can a woman, whose behavior has once been immoral, convince us that she has made better choices and has the self-control to follow through?

All men, it is allowed, are equally desirous of happiness; but few are successful in the pursuit: One considerable cause is the want of strength of mind, which might enable them to resist the temptation of present ease or pleasure, and carry them forward in the search of more distant profit and enjoyment. Our affections, on a general prospect of their objects, form certain rules of conduct, and certain measures of preference of one above another: and these decisions, though really the result of our calm passions and propensities, (for what else can pronounce any object eligible or the contrary?) are yet said, by a natural abuse of terms, to be the determinations of pure REASON and reflection. But when some of these objects approach nearer to us, or acquire the advantages of favourable lights and positions, which catch the heart or imagination; our general resolutions are frequently confounded, a small enjoyment preferred, and lasting shame and sorrow entailed upon us. And however poets may employ their wit and eloquence, in celebrating present pleasure, and rejecting all distant views to fame, health, or fortune; it is obvious, that this practice is the source of all dissoluteness and disorder, repentance and misery. A man of a strong and determined temper adheres tenaciously to his general resolutions, and is neither seduced by the allurements of pleasure, nor terrified by the menaces of pain; but keeps still in view those distant pursuits, by which he, at once, ensures his happiness and his honour.

All people, it’s true, want to be happy; but few actually succeed in achieving that happiness. One major reason is the lack of mental strength, which would allow them to resist the temptation of immediate comfort or pleasure and push them forward in the pursuit of greater long-term benefits and joy. Our feelings, when we look at the bigger picture of what we desire, create certain rules for how we act and how we prioritize what we want: these decisions, though they come from our calm emotions and inclinations (because what else can determine if something is desirable or not?), are often inaccurately described as conclusions of pure REASON and reflection. However, when some of these desires get closer to us or are presented in a more appealing way that captivates our hearts or imaginations, our general plans often get thrown off track, and we choose a fleeting pleasure instead, which can lead to lasting shame and regret. And while poets may use their cleverness and charm to celebrate immediate enjoyment and dismiss any thoughts of future fame, health, or fortune, it’s clear that this way of thinking leads to a life of chaos, regret, and unhappiness. A person with strong willpower sticks to their overall plans and isn’t swayed by the temptations of pleasure or frightened by the threat of pain; they remain focused on those long-term goals that ultimately secure their happiness and honor.

Self-satisfaction, at least in some degree, is an advantage, which equally attends the fool and the wise man: But it is the only one; nor is there any other circumstance in the conduct of life, where they are upon an equal footing. Business, books, conversation; for all of these, a fool is totally incapacitated, and except condemned by his station to the coarsest drudgery, remains a useless burthen upon the earth. Accordingly, it is found, that men are extremely jealous of their character in this particular; and many instances are seen of profligacy and treachery, the most avowed and unreserved; none of bearing patiently the imputation of ignorance and stupidity. Dicaearchus, the Macedonian general, who, as Polybius tells us [Footnote: Lib. xvi. Cap. 35.], openly erected one altar to impiety, another to injustice, in order to bid defiance to mankind; even he, I am well assured, would have started at the epithet of FOOL, and have meditated revenge for so injurious an appellation. Except the affection of parents, the strongest and most indissoluble bond in nature, no connexion has strength sufficient to support the disgust arising from this character. Love itself, which can subsist under treachery, ingratitude, malice, and infidelity, is immediately extinguished by it, when perceived and acknowledged; nor are deformity and old age more fatal to the dominion of that passion. So dreadful are the ideas of an utter incapacity for any purpose or undertaking, and of continued error and misconduct in life!

Self-satisfaction, to some extent, is an advantage that both fools and wise people share. But it’s the only one; there’s no other aspect of life where they’re on the same level. When it comes to work, reading, and conversation, a fool is completely unfit, and unless stuck in the most menial job, they remain a useless burden on society. As a result, people are very protective of their reputation in this regard, and there are plenty of cases of shamelessness and betrayal, where no one can tolerate being labeled as ignorant or stupid. Dicaearchus, the Macedonian general, who, as Polybius tells us, openly built one altar to impiety and another to injustice to challenge mankind; even he would have recoiled at being called a FOOL and would have thought about revenge for such a hurtful label. Besides the love of parents, which is the strongest and most unbreakable bond in nature, no connection is strong enough to overcome the disgust that comes from being labeled a fool. Love itself, which can survive betrayal, ingratitude, malice, and infidelity, is immediately extinguished when foolishness is recognized and acknowledged; nor is ugliness or old age any more damaging to the power of that emotion. The idea of being completely incapable of achieving anything and constantly making mistakes in life is terrifying!

When it is asked, whether a quick or a slow apprehension be most valuable? Whether one, that, at first view, penetrates far into a subject, but can perform nothing upon study; or a contrary character, which must work out everything by dint of application? Whether a clear head or a copious invention? Whether a profound genius or a sure judgement? In short, what character, or peculiar turn of understanding, is more excellent than another? It is evident, that we can answer none of these questions, without considering which of those qualities capacitates a man best for the world, and carries him farthest in any undertaking.

When asked whether quick thinking or slow thinking is more valuable, or if someone who can grasp a subject quickly but struggles with deeper study is better than someone who works hard to understand everything, or whether clarity of thought is better than creativity, or if deep insight is superior to sound judgment—essentially, which type of understanding is more superior—is not straightforward. It's clear that we can't answer any of these questions without considering which of these traits equips a person best for success in the world and helps them achieve their goals.

If refined sense and exalted sense be not so USEFUL as common sense, their rarity, their novelty, and the nobleness of their objects make some compensation, and render them the admiration of mankind: As gold, though less serviceable than iron, acquires from its scarcity a value which is much superior.

If refined sense and elevated sense aren't as USEFUL as common sense, their rarity, novelty, and the greatness of their subjects make up for that, earning them the admiration of people: Just as gold, though less useful than iron, gains a value from its scarcity that is much greater.

The defects of judgement can be supplied by no art or invention; but those of memory frequently may, both in business and in study, by method and industry, and by diligence in committing everything to writing; and we scarcely ever hear a short memory given as a reason for a man's failure in any undertaking. But in ancient times, when no man could make a figure without the talent of speaking, and when the audience were too delicate to bear such crude, undigested harangues as our extemporary orators offer to public assemblies; the faculty of memory was then of the utmost consequence, and was accordingly much more valued than at present. Scarce any great genius is mentioned in antiquity, who is not celebrated for this talent; and Cicero enumerates it among the other sublime qualities of Caesar himself. [Footnote: Fruit in Illo Ingenium, ratio, memoria, literae, cura, cogitatio, diligentia &c. Phillip. 2.].

The shortcomings in judgment can't be fixed by any skill or invention, but issues with memory often can, both in work and learning, through organization, hard work, and careful note-taking. We hardly ever hear someone’s poor memory cited as a reason for their failure in a task. However, in ancient times, when no one could stand out without being a good speaker, and when audiences couldn’t tolerate the rough, unrefined speeches our impromptu speakers give today; memory was extremely important and was therefore much more appreciated than it is now. Almost every great thinker from antiquity is praised for this ability, and Cicero lists it among the other remarkable qualities of Caesar himself. [Footnote: Fruit in Illo Ingenium, ratio, memoria, literae, cura, cogitatio, diligentia &c. Phillip. 2.].

Particular customs and manners alter the usefulness of qualities: they also alter their merit. Particular situations and accidents have, in some degree, the same influence. He will always be more esteemed, who possesses those talents and accomplishments, which suit his station and profession, than he whom fortune has misplaced in the part which she has assigned him. The private or selfish virtues are, in this respect, more arbitrary than the public and social. In other respects they are, perhaps, less liable to doubt and controversy.

Specific customs and behaviors change the value of qualities; they also change their worth. Specific situations and events have a similar effect. Someone who has the skills and abilities that fit their role and career will always be more valued than someone who has been put in the wrong position by luck. In this sense, personal or selfish virtues are more subjective than public and social ones. In other ways, they might be less open to debate and disagreement.

In this kingdom, such continued ostentation, of late years, has prevailed among men in ACTIVE life with regard to PUBLIC SPIRIT, and among those in SPECULATIVE with regard to BENEVOLENCE; and so many false pretensions to each have been, no doubt, detected, that men of the world are apt, without any bad intention, to discover a sullen incredulity on the head of those moral endowments, and even sometimes absolutely to deny their existence and reality. In like manner I find, that, of old, the perpetual cant of the STOICS and CYNICS concerning VIRTUE, their magnificent professions and slender performances, bred a disgust in mankind; and Lucian, who, though licentious with regard to pleasure, is yet in other respects a very moral writer, cannot sometimes talk of virtue, so much boasted without betraying symptoms of spleen and irony. But surely this peevish delicacy, whence-ever it arises can never be carried so far as to make us deny the existence of every species of merit, and all distinction of manners and behaviour. Besides DISCRETION, CAUTION, ENTERPRISE, INDUSTRY, ASSIDUITY, FRUGALITY, ECONOMY, GOOD-SENSE, PRUDENCE, DISCERNMENT; besides these endowments, I say, whose very names force an avowal of their merit, there are many others, to which the most determined scepticism cannot for a moment refuse the tribute of praise and approbation. TEMPERANCE, SOBRIETY, PATIENCE, CONSTANCY, PERSEVERANCE, FORETHOUGHT, CONSIDERATENESS, SECRECY, ORDER, INSINUATION, ADDRESS, PRESENCE OF MIND, QUICKNESS OF CONCEPTION, FACILITY OF EXPRESSION, these, and a thousand more of the same kind, no man will ever deny to be excellencies and perfections. As their merit consists in their tendency to serve the person, possessed of them, without any magnificent claim to public and social desert, we are the less jealous of their pretensions, and readily admit them into the catalogue of laudable qualities. We are not sensible that, by this concession, we have paved the way for all the other moral excellencies, and cannot consistently hesitate any longer, with regard to disinterested benevolence, patriotism, and humanity.

In this kingdom, lately, there's been a lot of show-off behavior among people in active roles regarding public spirit, and among those in more theoretical roles regarding benevolence; and so many fake claims to both have been uncovered that people tend to show a gloomy disbelief in these moral qualities, and sometimes outright deny their existence altogether. Similarly, I notice that in the past, the constant talk from the Stoics and Cynics about virtue, their grand claims but minimal actions, created a sense of disgust among people; and Lucian, who, while indulging in pleasures, is still a fairly moral writer, sometimes struggles to speak of virtue, so frequently praised, without showing signs of annoyance and irony. However, this irritating sensitivity, no matter where it comes from, cannot be pushed so far as to make us deny the existence of any kind of merit or the distinctions in manners and behavior. Besides discretion, caution, enterprise, industry, diligence, frugality, economy, good sense, prudence, and discernment—besides these traits, whose names alone demand acknowledgment of their merit—there are many others that even the most skeptical cannot deny deserving praise and approval. Temperance, sobriety, patience, perseverance, forethought, thoughtfulness, secrecy, order, insight, quick wit, clarity of expression, and countless others like them will always be recognized as qualities of excellence. Since their merit lies in how they benefit the individual possessing them, without any grand claims to public or social recognition, we feel less defensive about their merits and easily include them in the list of commendable qualities. We don’t realize that by making this concession, we have opened the door for all other moral excellencies, and we can no longer reasonably hesitate when it comes to selfless benevolence, patriotism, and humanity.

It seems, indeed, certain, that first appearances are here, as usual, extremely deceitful, and that it is more difficult, in a speculative way, to resolve into self-love the merit which we ascribe to the selfish virtues above mentioned, than that even of the social virtues, justice and beneficence. For this latter purpose, we need but say, that whatever conduct promotes the good of the community is loved, praised, and esteemed by the community, on account of that utility and interest, of which every one partakes; and though this affection and regard be, in reality, gratitude, not self-love, yet a distinction, even of this obvious nature, may not readily be made by superficial reasoners; and there is room, at least, to support the cavil and dispute for a moment. But as qualities, which tend only to the utility of their possessor, without any reference to us, or to the community, are yet esteemed and valued; by what theory or system can we account for this sentiment from self-love, or deduce it from that favourite origin? There seems here a necessity for confessing that the happiness and misery of others are not spectacles entirely indifferent to us; but that the view of the former, whether in its causes or effects, like sunshine or the prospect of well-cultivated plains (to carry our pretensions no higher), communicates a secret joy and satisfaction; the appearance of the latter, like a lowering cloud or barren landscape, throws a melancholy damp over the imagination. And this concession being once made, the difficulty is over; and a natural unforced interpretation of the phenomena of human life will afterwards, we may hope, prevail among all speculative enquirers.

It seems clear that first impressions are, as usual, very misleading, and that it's more challenging to see self-love as the motivation behind the selfish virtues mentioned earlier than it is for the social virtues like justice and kindness. For the latter, we can simply say that any behavior that benefits the community is loved, praised, and valued by its members because of the utility and interest shared by everyone; and although this affection is really gratitude, not self-love, superficial thinkers might not easily recognize this distinction, and there’s at least some space for debate. However, when we consider qualities that only benefit their owner, without any regard for us or the community, how can we explain this sentiment through self-love or trace it back to that favored origin? It seems necessary to admit that the happiness and suffering of others are not entirely indifferent to us; seeing happiness, whether in its causes or effects, like sunshine or the view of well-tended fields, brings us a hidden joy and satisfaction; while the appearance of suffering, like a dark cloud or a barren landscape, casts a gloomy shadow over our imagination. Once we accept this point, the difficulty is resolved, and we can hope for a natural, unforced understanding of human life’s phenomena among all thoughtful inquirers.





PART II.

It may not be improper, in this place, to examine the influence of bodily endowments, and of the goods of fortune, over our sentiments of regard and esteem, and to consider whether these phenomena fortify or weaken the present theory. It will naturally be expected, that the beauty of the body, as is supposed by all ancient moralists, will be similar, in some respects, to that of the mind; and that every kind of esteem, which is paid to a man, will have something similar in its origin, whether it arise from his mental endowments, or from the situation of his exterior circumstances.

It might be worth looking into how physical attributes and wealth influence our feelings of respect and admiration, and whether these factors support or challenge the current theory. It's reasonable to think that the beauty of the body, as all ancient philosophers believed, shares some similarities with the beauty of the mind. Additionally, any form of respect given to a person likely has a similar root, whether it comes from their mental abilities or their external circumstances.

It is evident, that one considerable source of BEAUTY in all animals is the advantage which they reap from the particular structure of their limbs and members, suitably to the particular manner of life, to which they are by nature destined. The just proportions of a horse, described by Xenophon and Virgil, are the same that are received at this day by our modern jockeys; because the foundation of them is the same, namely, experience of what is detrimental or useful in the animal.

It’s clear that a significant source of beauty in all animals comes from the specific way their limbs and bodies are structured to fit their natural way of life. The ideal proportions of a horse, as described by Xenophon and Virgil, are still accepted by today's jockeys because the basis for these proportions remains the same: the understanding of what is harmful or beneficial for the animal.

Broad shoulders, a lank belly, firm joints, taper legs; all these are beautiful in our species, because signs of force and vigour. Ideas of utility and its contrary, though they do not entirely determine what is handsome or deformed, are evidently the source of a considerable part of approbation or dislike.

Broad shoulders, a lean belly, strong joints, and tapered legs; all these traits are attractive in our species because they signal strength and vitality. While notions of usefulness and its opposite don’t fully define beauty or deformity, they clearly contribute significantly to what we approve of or dislike.

In ancient times, bodily strength and dexterity, being of greater USE and importance in war, was also much more esteemed and valued, than at present. Not to insist on Homer and the poets, we may observe, that historians scruple not to mention FORCE OF BODY among the other accomplishments even of Epaminondas, whom they acknowledge to be the greatest hero, statesman, and general of all the Greeks. [Footnote: CUM ALACRIBUS, SALTU; CUMM VELOCIBUS, CURSU; CUM VALIDIS RECTE CERTABATA. Sallust apud Veget.] A like praise is given to Pompey, one of the greatest of the Romans. [Footnote: Diodorus Siculus, lib. xv. It may be improper to give the character of Epaminondas, as drawn by the historian, in order to show the idea of perfect merit, which prevailed in those ages. In other illustrious men, say he, you will observe, that each possessed some one shining quality, which was the foundation of his fame: In Epaminondas all the VIRTUES are found united; force of body. eloquence of expression, vigour of mind, contempt of riches, gentleness of disposition, and what is chiefly to be regarded, courage and conduct of war.] This instance is similar to what we observed above with regard to memory.

In ancient times, physical strength and agility were much more valued and essential in warfare than they are today. Without diving into Homer and the poets, we can note that historians do not hesitate to include physical prowess alongside the other skills of Epaminondas, who is recognized as the greatest hero, statesman, and general among the Greeks. [Footnote: CUM ALACRIBUS, SALTU; CUMM VELOCIBUS, CURSU; CUM VALIDIS RECTE CERTABATA. Sallust apud Veget.] A similar recognition is given to Pompey, one of the greatest Romans. [Footnote: Diodorus Siculus, lib. xv. It may be inappropriate to portray Epaminondas's character as described by the historian to highlight the concept of perfect merit that was prevalent in those times. He states that in other notable individuals, one can see that each possessed one outstanding quality that formed the basis of their reputation: In Epaminondas, all the VIRTUES are found combined; physical strength, eloquence, mental sharpness, disregard for wealth, gentle nature, and, most importantly, bravery and military skill.] This example mirrors what we discussed earlier regarding memory.

What derision and contempt, with both sexes, attend IMPOTENCE; while the unhappy object is regarded as one deprived of so capital a pleasure in life, and at the same time, as disabled from communicating it to others. BARRENNESS in women, being also a species of INUTILITY, is a reproach, but not in the same degree: of which the reason is very obvious, according to the present theory.

What scorn and disdain, from both genders, accompany IMPOTENCE; while the unfortunate person is seen as being deprived of such a significant pleasure in life and simultaneously unable to share it with others. BARRENNESS in women, being another form of INUTILITY, is a shame, but not to the same extent: the reason for this is very clear, according to the current understanding.

There is no rule in painting or statuary more indispensible than that of balancing the figures, and placing them with the greatest exactness on their proper centre of gravity. A figure, which is not justly balanced, is ugly; because it conveys the disagreeable ideas of fall, harm, and pain.

There’s no rule in painting or sculpture more essential than balancing the figures and positioning them accurately at their proper center of gravity. A figure that isn’t properly balanced looks ugly because it sends off uncomfortable ideas of falling, injury, and pain.

[Footenote: All men are equally liable to pain and disease and sickness;
and may again recover health and ease. These circumstances, as they make
no distinction between one man and another, are no source of pride or
humility, regard or contempt. But comparing our own species to superior
ones, it is a very mortifying consideration, that we should all be so
liable to diseases and infirmities; and divines accordingly employ this
topic, in order to depress self-conceit and vanity. They would have more
success, if the common bent of our thoughts were not perpetually turned
to compare ourselves with others.

   The infirmities of old age are mortifying; because a comparison with
the young may take place. The king's evil is industriously concealed,
because it affects others, and is often transmitted to posterity. The
case is nearly the same with such diseases as convey any nauseous or
frightful images; the epilepsy, for instance, ulcers, sores, scabs, &c.]
[Footnote: Everyone is equally vulnerable to pain, illness, and sickness; yet they can also regain their health and comfort. Because these situations make no distinction between individuals, they don't bring pride or humility, admiration or scorn. However, when we compare ourselves to superior beings, it’s really disheartening that we are all so susceptible to diseases and weaknesses. Consequently, religious leaders often use this topic to lower self-importance and vanity. They would be more effective if we weren't constantly inclined to compare ourselves with others.

   The weaknesses of old age are disheartening because they invite comparison with the young. The king's evil is carefully hidden because it affects others and can often be passed down to future generations. The situation is similar with diseases that create unpleasant or terrifying images, such as epilepsy, ulcers, sores, scabs, etc.]

A disposition or turn of mind, which qualifies a man to rise in the world and advance his fortune, is entitled to esteem and regard, as has already been explained. It may, therefore, naturally be supposed, that the actual possession of riches and authority will have a considerable influence over these sentiments.

A mindset or attitude that helps someone succeed and improve their situation deserves respect and appreciation, as previously mentioned. It can be assumed that truly having wealth and power will significantly impact these feelings.

Let us examine any hypothesis by which we can account for the regard paid to the rich and powerful; we shall find none satisfactory, but that which derives it from the enjoyment communicated to the spectator by the images of prosperity, happiness, ease, plenty, authority, and the gratification of every appetite. Self-love, for instance, which some affect so much to consider as the source of every sentiment, is plainly insufficient for this purpose. Where no good-will or friendship appears, it is difficult to conceive on what we can found our hope of advantage from the riches of others; though we naturally respect the rich, even before they discover any such favourable disposition towards us.

Let’s take a look at any idea that explains why we hold the rich and powerful in high regard; we won’t find any explanation that makes sense except for the one that comes from the pleasure the images of wealth, happiness, comfort, abundance, authority, and the fulfillment of desires provide to onlookers. For example, self-love, which some people like to believe is the source of all feelings, clearly doesn’t suffice for this. When there’s no goodwill or friendship evident, it’s hard to see how we can expect to gain something from the wealth of others; yet we naturally respect the wealthy, even before they show any positive feelings towards us.

We are affected with the same sentiments, when we lie so much out of the sphere of their activity, that they cannot even be supposed to possess the power of serving us. A prisoner of war, in all civilized nations, is treated with a regard suited to his condition; and riches, it is evident, go far towards fixing the condition of any person. If birth and quality enter for a share, this still affords us an argument to our present purpose. For what is it we call a man of birth, but one who is descended from a long succession of rich and powerful ancestors, and who acquires our esteem by his connexion with persons whom we esteem? His ancestors, therefore, though dead, are respected, in some measure, on account of their riches; and consequently, without any kind of expectation.

We feel the same way when we move so far outside their realm of influence that it seems impossible for them to help us. A prisoner of war, in all civilized countries, is treated with respect appropriate to their situation; and clearly, wealth plays a significant role in determining a person's status. Even if birth and social standing contribute to this, it still supports our current argument. What do we mean by a man of noble birth, if not someone who comes from a long line of wealthy and powerful ancestors, earning our respect through their connections with people we admire? Therefore, even though their ancestors are no longer living, they are still respected, at least in part, because of their wealth; and thus, without any expectation.

But not to go so far as prisoners of war or the dead, to find instances of this disinterested regard for riches; we may only observe, with a little attention, those phenomena which occur in common life and conversation. A man, who is himself, we shall suppose, of a competent fortune, and of no profession, being introduced to a company of strangers, naturally treats them with different degrees of respect, as he is informed of their different fortunes and conditions; though it is impossible that he can so suddenly propose, and perhaps he would not accept of, any pecuniary advantage from them. A traveller is always admitted into company, and meets with civility, in proportion as his train and equipage speak him a man of great or moderate fortune. In short, the different ranks of men are, in a great measure, regulated by riches; and that with regard to superiors as well as inferiors, strangers as well as acquaintance.

But to avoid going as far as prisoners of war or the dead to find examples of this selfless attitude towards wealth, we can just look at the things that happen in everyday life and conversation. Let’s say a man has a decent amount of money and doesn’t have a job. When he meets a group of strangers, he naturally shows them different levels of respect based on what he learns about their wealth and status; although it’s unlikely he could quickly ask for, or even want, any financial benefit from them. A traveler is always welcomed into social settings and treated politely, depending on how his belongings and appearance suggest that he is a person of significant or moderate wealth. In short, the different social ranks are largely determined by wealth, affecting both superiors and inferiors, as well as strangers and acquaintances.

What remains, therefore, but to conclude, that, as riches are desired for ourselves only as the means of gratifying our appetites, either at present or in some imaginary future period, they beget esteem in others merely from their having that influence. This indeed is their very nature or offence: they have a direct reference to the commodities, conveniences, and pleasures of life. The bill of a banker, who is broke, or gold in a desert island, would otherwise be full as valuable. When we approach a man who is, as we say, at his ease, we are presented with the pleasing ideas of plenty, satisfaction, cleanliness, warmth; a cheerful house, elegant furniture, ready service, and whatever is desirable in meat, drink, or apparel. On the contrary, when a poor man appears, the disagreeable images of want, penury, hard labour, dirty furniture, coarse or ragged clothes, nauseous meat and distasteful liquor, immediately strike our fancy. What else do we mean by saying that one is rich, the other poor? And as regard or contempt is the natural consequence of those different situations in life, it is easily seen what additional light and evidence this throws on our preceding theory, with regard to all moral distinctions.

What else can we conclude but that people want riches mainly to satisfy their own desires, whether in the present or some imagined future? Wealth earns respect from others simply because it has that kind of power. That's essentially what it is: it relates directly to the goods, comforts, and pleasures in life. A banknote from a bankrupt bank or gold on a deserted island would be equally worthless. When we see someone who seems to be comfortable, we are greeted with the pleasant ideas of abundance, contentment, cleanliness, warmth; a cheerful home, nice furniture, attentive service, and everything desirable in food, drink, or clothing. In contrast, when a poor person appears, we immediately think of the unpleasant images of need, poverty, hard work, shabby furniture, worn-out clothes, unappetizing food, and unpleasant drinks. What else do we mean when we say one person is rich and another is poor? Since respect or disdain naturally follows from those different life situations, it’s clear how this sheds further light on our previous discussion about moral distinctions.

     [Footnote: There is something extraordinary, and seemingly
unaccountable in the operation of our passions, when we consider the
fortune and situation of others. Very often another's advancement and
prosperity produces envy, which has a strong mixture of hatred, and
arises chiefly from the comparison of ourselves with the person. At the
very same time, or at least in very short intervals, we may feel the
passion of respect, which is a species of affection or good-will, with
a mixture of humility. On the other hand, the misfortunes of our fellows
often cause pity, which has in it a strong mixture of good-will. This
sentiment of pity is nearly allied to contempt, which is a species of
dislike, with a mixture of pride. I only point out these phenomena, as
a subject of speculation to such as are curious with regard to moral
enquiries. It is sufficient for the present purpose to observe in
general, that power and riches commonly cause respect, poverty and
meanness contempt, though particular views and incidents may sometimes
raise the passions of envy and of pity.]
     [Footnote: There’s something remarkable and seemingly inexplicable about how we feel when we think about the successes and situations of others. Often, when someone else achieves success and happiness, it triggers envy, which is mixed with a strong dose of hatred and comes mainly from comparing ourselves to that person. At the same time, or at least very shortly after, we might experience respect, which is a type of affection or goodwill mixed with humility. Conversely, when others face hardships, we often feel pity, which contains a good amount of goodwill. This feeling of pity is closely related to contempt, which is a type of dislike mixed with pride. I mention these feelings simply as a topic for thought for those interested in moral questions. For now, it’s enough to note that power and wealth generally earn respect, while poverty and low status lead to contempt, although specific situations and perspectives might sometimes stir up envy or pity.]

A man who has cured himself of all ridiculous pre-possessions, and is fully, sincerely, and steadily convinced, from experience as well as philosophy, that the difference of fortune makes less difference in happiness than is vulgarly imagined; such a one does not measure out degrees of esteem according to the rent-rolls of his acquaintance. He may, indeed, externally pay a superior deference to the great lord above the vassal; because riches are the most convenient, being the most fixed and determinate, source of distinction. But his internal sentiments are more regulated by the personal characters of men, than by the accidental and capricious favours of fortune.

A man who has freed himself from all silly biases, and is completely, genuinely, and consistently convinced, based on both experience and philosophy, that differences in wealth impact happiness less than most people think; such a person doesn't judge the value of others based on their wealth. He might, of course, show more outward respect to a wealthy lord than to a humble servant, because money is the easiest and most clear-cut way to distinguish people. However, his true feelings are shaped more by the individual qualities of people than by the random and unreliable gifts of fortune.

In most countries of Europe, family, that is, hereditary riches, marked with titles and symbols from the sovereign, is the chief source of distinction. In England, more regard is paid to present opulence and plenty. Each practice has its advantages and disadvantages. Where birth is respected, unactive, spiritless minds remain in haughty indolence, and dream of nothing but pedigrees and genealogies: the generous and ambitious seek honour and authority, and reputation and favour. Where riches are the chief idol, corruption, venality, rapine prevail: arts, manufactures, commerce, agriculture flourish. The former prejudice, being favourable to military virtue, is more suited to monarchies. The latter, being the chief spur to industry, agrees better with a republican government. And we accordingly find that each of these forms of government, by varying the utility of those customs, has commonly a proportionable effect on the sentiments of mankind.

In most European countries, family wealth, which includes inherited riches, titles, and symbols from the monarchy, is the main source of distinction. In England, more emphasis is placed on current wealth and abundance. Each approach has its pros and cons. In societies that value birth, passive and uninspired individuals tend to live in arrogant laziness, only dreaming of lineages and family trees. Meanwhile, the ambitious and generous aim for honor, power, reputation, and favor. In contrast, when wealth is the top priority, corruption, greed, and theft flourish, while the arts, manufacturing, commerce, and agriculture thrive. The former attitude, which supports military virtue, aligns better with monarchies. The latter, being the main driver of productivity, fits better with republican governments. As a result, we often see that each type of government, by altering the value of these customs, has a corresponding effect on people's attitudes.





SECTION VII.

OF QUALITIES IMMEDIATELY AGREEABLE TO OURSELVES.

Whoever has passed an evening with serious melancholy people, and has observed how suddenly the conversation was animated, and what sprightliness diffused itself over the countenance, discourse, and behaviour of every one, on the accession of a good-humoured, lively companion; such a one will easily allow that cheerfulness carries great merit with it, and naturally conciliates the good-will of mankind. No quality, indeed, more readily communicates itself to all around; because no one has a greater propensity to display itself, in jovial talk and pleasant entertainment. The flame spreads through the whole circle; and the most sullen and morose are often caught by it. That the melancholy hate the merry, even though Horace says it, I have some difficulty to allow; because I have always observed that, where the jollity is moderate and decent, serious people are so much the more delighted, as it dissipates the gloom with which they are commonly oppressed, and gives them an unusual enjoyment.

Whoever has spent an evening with seriously gloomy people and noticed how suddenly the conversation brightened and how much liveliness spread across everyone’s face, speech, and behavior when a cheerful, lively person joined in; such a person will easily agree that cheerfulness has great value and naturally wins people over. No quality, in fact, spreads more easily to those around because no one is more inclined to express it in cheerful conversations and enjoyable gatherings. The joy spreads throughout the entire group, and even the most grumpy and moody individuals often catch on to it. While Horace says that the sad dislike the happy, I find it hard to accept; because I’ve always noticed that when the joy is moderate and appropriate, serious people are even more pleased, as it lifts the darkness they usually feel and brings them unexpected happiness.

From this influence of cheerfulness, both to communicate itself and to engage approbation, we may perceive that there is another set of mental qualities, which, without any utility or any tendency to farther good, either of the community or of the possessor, diffuse a satisfaction on the beholders, and procure friendship and regard. Their immediate sensation, to the person possessed of them, is agreeable. Others enter into the same humour, and catch the sentiment, by a contagion or natural sympathy; and as we cannot forbear loving whatever pleases, a kindly emotion arises towards the person who communicates so much satisfaction. He is a more animating spectacle; his presence diffuses over us more serene complacency and enjoyment; our imagination, entering into his feelings and disposition, is affected in a more agreeable manner than if a melancholy, dejected, sullen, anxious temper were presented to us. Hence the affection and probation which attend the former: the aversion and disgust with which we regard the latter.

From this influence of happiness, both to spread itself and to gain approval, we can see that there are other mental qualities that, without any real usefulness or any chance for greater good, either for the community or the person who possesses them, create a sense of satisfaction in those who observe them and foster friendship and affection. The immediate feeling for the person who has these qualities is pleasant. Others share in the same mood and catch the feeling through a kind of natural sympathy; and since we can't help but love whatever makes us happy, a warm emotion arises towards the person who brings such joy. They are a more uplifting presence; their existence spreads a sense of calm enjoyment over us; our imagination connects with their feelings and state of mind in a more pleasant way than if we were faced with a sad, downcast, or anxious disposition. This is why we feel affection and approval towards the former and aversion and disgust towards the latter.

     [Footnote: There is no man, who, on particular occasions, is not
affected with all the disagreeable passions, fear, anger, dejection,
grief, melancholy, anxiety, &c. But these, so far as they are natural,
and universal, make no difference between one man and another, and can
never be the object of blame. It is only when the disposition gives a
PROPENSITY to any of these disagreeable passions, that they disfigure
the character, and by giving uneasiness, convey the sentiment of
disapprobation to the spectator.]
     [Footnote: There’s no person who, on certain occasions, doesn’t experience all the unpleasant emotions—fear, anger, sadness, grief, depression, anxiety, etc. However, these feelings, to the extent that they are natural and universal, don’t differentiate one person from another and can never be blamed. It’s only when someone has a tendency toward any of these negative emotions that they distort their character, and by causing discomfort, they transmit a feeling of disapproval to those observing.]

Few men would envy the character which Caesar gives of Cassius:

Few men would envy the description Caesar gives of Cassius:

 He loves no play,
 As thou do'st, Anthony: he hears no music:
 Seldom he smiles; and smiles in such a sort,
 As if he mock'd himself, and scorn'd his spirit
 That could be mov'd to smile at any thing.
He doesn't enjoy playing,
Like you do, Anthony: he doesn't listen to music:
He rarely smiles; and when he does, it's in a way,
That seems to make fun of himself, and disdain his soul
That could be stirred to smile at anything.

Not only such men, as Caesar adds, are commonly DANGEROUS, but also, having little enjoyment within themselves, they can never become agreeable to others, or contribute to social entertainment. In all polite nations and ages, a relish for pleasure, if accompanied with temperance and decency, is esteemed a considerable merit, even in the greatest men; and becomes still more requisite in those of inferior rank and character. It is an agreeable representation, which a French writer gives of the situation of his own mind in this particular, VIRTUE I LOVE, says he, WITHOUT AUSTERITY: PLEASURE WITHOUT EFFEMINACY: AND LIFE, WITHOUT FEARING ITS END. [Footnote: 'J'aime la vertu, sans rudesse; J'aime le plaisir, sans molesse; J'aime la vie, et n'en crains point la fin.'-ST. EVREMONT.]

Not only are these kinds of people, as Caesar points out, often DANGEROUS, but also, since they find little joy within themselves, they can never be enjoyable to others or contribute to social interactions. In all cultured societies and throughout history, a taste for pleasure, when paired with moderation and respectability, is considered a significant virtue, even in the most prominent individuals; it becomes even more important for those of lesser status and character. A French writer offers a nice view of his own mindset on this matter: I LOVE VIRTUE, he says, WITHOUT AUSTERITY; PLEASURE WITHOUT WEAKNESS; AND LIFE, WITHOUT FEARING ITS END. [Footnote: 'J'aime la vertu, sans rudesse; J'aime le plaisir, sans molesse; J'aime la vie, et n'en crains point la fin.'-ST. EVREMONT.]

Who is not struck with any signal instance of greatness of mind or dignity of character; with elevation of sentiment, disdain of slavery, and with that noble pride and spirit, which arises from conscious virtue? The sublime, says Longinus, is often nothing but the echo or image of magnanimity; and where this quality appears in any one, even though a syllable be not uttered, it excites our applause and admiration; as may be observed of the famous silence of Ajax in the Odyssey, which expresses more noble disdain and resolute indignation than any language can convey [Footnote: Cap. 9.].

Who isn't impressed by a clear example of greatness of mind or dignity of character; by elevated feelings, a rejection of slavery, and that noble pride and spirit that come from knowing one's own virtue? According to Longinus, the sublime is often just the echo or reflection of greatness of character; and when this quality is present in someone, even if they don’t say a word, it inspires our praise and admiration. This can be seen in the famous silence of Ajax in the Odyssey, which conveys more noble disdain and determined anger than any words can express. [Footnote: Cap. 9.]

WERE I Alexander, said Parmenio, I WOULD ACCEPT OF THESE OFFERS MADE BY DARIUS. SO WOULD I TOO, replied Alexander, WERE I PARMENIO. This saying is admirable, says Longinus, from a like principle. [Footnote: Idem.]

WERE I Alexander, said Parmenio, I WOULD ACCEPT THESE OFFERS MADE BY DARIUS. SO WOULD I TOO, replied Alexander, WERE I PARMENIO. This saying is impressive, says Longinus, for a similar reason. [Footnote: Idem.]

GO! cries the same hero to his soldiers, when they refused to follow him to the Indies, GO TELL YOUR COUNTRYMEN, THAT YOU LEFT Alexander COMPLETING THE CONQUEST OF THE WORLD. 'Alexander,' said the Prince of Conde, who always admired this passage, 'abandoned by his soldiers, among barbarians, not yet fully subdued, felt in himself such a dignity and right of empire, that he could not believe it possible that any one would refuse to obey him. Whether in Europe or in Asia, among Greeks or Persians, all was indifferent to him: wherever he found men, he fancied he should find subjects.'

"Go!" the same hero shouts to his soldiers when they hesitate to join him on the journey to the Indies. "Go tell your countrymen that you left Alexander finishing the conquest of the world." The Prince of Conde, who always admired this moment, remarked, "Alexander, abandoned by his soldiers among barbarians who were not fully conquered, felt such a sense of dignity and right to rule that he couldn't believe anyone would refuse to follow him. Whether in Europe or Asia, among Greeks or Persians, it didn’t matter to him: wherever he found people, he believed he would find subjects."

The confident of Medea in the tragedy recommends caution and submission; and enumerating all the distresses of that unfortunate heroine, asks her, what she has to support her against her numerous and implacable enemies. MYSELF, replies she; MYSELF I SAY, AND IT IS ENOUGH. Boileau justly recommends this passage as an instance of true sublime [Footnote: Reflexion 10 sur Longin.].

The confidence of Medea in the tragedy suggests caution and submission; and as she lists all the hardships of that unfortunate heroine, she asks her what she has to stand against her many relentless enemies. MYSELF, she replies; MYSELF I SAY, AND IT IS ENOUGH. Boileau rightly highlights this passage as an example of true sublimity [Footnote: Reflexion 10 sur Longin.].

When Phocion, the modest, the gentle Phocion, was led to execution, he turned to one of his fellow-sufferers, who was lamenting his own hard fate, IS IT NOT GLORY ENOUGH FOR YOU, says he, THAT YOU DIE WITH PHOCION? [Footnote: Plutarch in Phoc.]

When Phocion, the humble and gentle Phocion, was taken to be executed, he turned to one of his fellow prisoners, who was mourning his unfortunate situation, and said, "Is it not glorious enough for you that you die with Phocion?" [Footnote: Plutarch in Phoc.]

Place in opposition the picture which Tacitus draws of Vitellius, fallen from empire, prolonging his ignominy from a wretched love of life, delivered over to the merciless rabble; tossed, buffeted, and kicked about; constrained, by their holding a poniard under his chin, to raise his head, and expose himself to every contumely. What abject infamy! What low humiliation! Yet even here, says the historian, he discovered some symptoms of a mind not wholly degenerate. To a tribune, who insulted him, he replied, I AM STILL YOUR EMPEROR.

Place in contrast the image that Tacitus paints of Vitellius, who, after losing his empire, drags out his disgrace due to a pathetic love of life, submitted to a ruthless mob; shoved around, beaten, and kicked; forced, with a dagger held under his chin, to lift his head and subject himself to every humiliation. What utter disgrace! What deep humiliation! Yet even in this situation, the historian notes, he showed some signs of a mind that wasn't completely lost. To a tribune who insulted him, he responded, I AM STILL YOUR EMPEROR.

     [Footnote: Tacit. hist. lib. iii. The author entering upon the
narration, says, LANIATA VESTE, FOEDUM SPECACULUM DUCEBATUR, MULTIS
INCREPANTIBUS, NULLO INLACRIMANTE: deformatitas exitus misericordiam
abstulerat. To enter thoroughly into this method of thinking, we must
make allowance for the ancient maxims, that no one ought to prolong his
life after it became dishonourable; but, as he had always a right to
dispose of it, it then became a duty to part with it.]
     [Footnote: Tacit. hist. lib. iii. The author begins the account by saying, "With torn clothing, a disgusting spectacle was being led, surrounded by many mocking him, and no one shedding a tear: the ugliness of the outcome had taken away all compassion." To fully understand this way of thinking, we need to consider the ancient saying that no one should extend their life after it has become shameful; however, since one always had the right to end their life, it then became a responsibility to do so.]

We never excuse the absolute want of spirit and dignity of character, or a proper sense of what is due to one's self, in society and the common intercourse of life. This vice constitutes what we properly call MEANNESS; when a man can submit to the basest slavery, in order to gain his ends; fawn upon those who abuse him; and degrade himself by intimacies and familiarities with undeserving inferiors. A certain degree of generous pride or self-value is so requisite, that the absence of it in the mind displeases, after the same manner as the want of a nose, eye, or any of the most material feature of the face or member of the body.

We never excuse a complete lack of spirit and dignity of character, or a proper sense of self-respect, in society and everyday interactions. This flaw is what we rightly call MEANNESS; when someone can submit to the lowest form of servitude to achieve their goals, flatter those who mistreat them, and lower themselves by getting too close with unworthy people. A certain level of healthy pride or self-worth is so essential that the absence of it is just as displeasing as lacking a nose, an eye, or any other crucial feature of the face or body.

     [Footnote: The absence of virtue may often be a vice; and that of
the highest kind; as in the instance of ingratitude, as well as
meanness. Where we expect a beauty, the disappointment gives an uneasy
sensation, and produces a real deformity. An abjectness of character,
likewise, is disgustful and contemptible in another view. Where a man
has no sense of value in himself, we are not likely to have any higher
esteem of him. And if the same person, who crouches to his superiors,
is insolent to his inferiors (as often happens), this contrariety
of behaviour, instead of correcting the former vice, aggravates it
extremely by the addition of a vice still more odious. See Sect. VIII.]
[Footnote: The lack of virtue can often be a major flaw, particularly in cases like ingratitude and meanness. When we anticipate beauty, the resulting disappointment creates an uncomfortable feeling and leads to a true ugliness. Similarly, having a low character is both distasteful and contemptible in another way. When someone has no self-worth, we are unlikely to hold him in any higher regard. If that same person who bows down to his superiors is rude to his subordinates (which often happens), this contradiction in behavior doesn't correct the initial flaw but instead makes it worse by adding an even more distasteful flaw. See Sect. VIII.]

The utility of courage, both to the public and to the person possessed of it, is an obvious foundation of merit. But to any one who duly considers of the matter, it will appear that this quality has a peculiar lustre, which it derives wholly from itself, and from that noble elevation inseparable from it. Its figure, drawn by painters and by poets, displays, in each feature, a sublimity and daring confidence; which catches the eye, engages the affections, and diffuses, by sympathy, a like sublimity of sentiment over every spectator.

The usefulness of courage, both to society and to the person who has it, is an obvious basis for its value. However, for anyone who really thinks about it, they’ll see that this quality has a unique brilliance that comes entirely from itself and the noble spirit that goes along with it. Its depiction by artists and poets shows a boldness and confidence in every aspect; it grabs attention, stirs emotions, and spreads a similar sense of greatness among everyone who observes it.

Under what shining colours does Demosthenes [Footnote: De Corona.] represent Philip; where the orator apologizes for his own administration, and justifies that pertinacious love of liberty, with which he had inspired the Athenians. 'I beheld Philip,' says he, 'he with whom was your contest, resolutely, while in pursuit of empire and dominion, exposing himself to every wound; his eye gored, his neck wrested, his arm, his thigh pierced, what ever part of his body fortune should seize on, that cheerfully relinquishing; provided that, with what remained, he might live in honour and renown. And shall it be said that he, born in Pella, a place heretofore mean and ignoble, should be inspired with so high an ambition and thirst of fame: while you, Athenians, &c.' These praises excite the most lively admiration; but the views presented by the orator, carry us not, we see, beyond the hero himself, nor ever regard the future advantageous consequences of his valour.

Under what bright colors does Demosthenes [Footnote: De Corona.] portray Philip, where the orator defends his administration and justifies the relentless love of freedom that he instilled in the Athenians. 'I saw Philip,' he says, 'the one you competed against, boldly exposing himself to every injury in his quest for empire and power; his eye injured, his neck twisted, his arm and thigh pierced—whatever part of his body fate seized upon, he willingly let go, as long as he could live with honor and fame. And shall it be said that he, born in Pella, a place once small and insignificant, was inspired with such high ambition and desire for glory: while you, Athenians, etc.' These praises evoke the deepest admiration; however, the orator's perspective only focuses on the hero himself and doesn't consider the future benefits of his bravery.

The material temper of the Romans, inflamed by continual wars, had raised their esteem of courage so high, that, in their language, it was called VIRTUE, by way of excellence and of distinction from all other moral qualities. THE Suevi, in the opinion of Tacitus, tus, [Footnote: De moribus Germ.] DRESSED THEIR HAIR WITH A LAUDIBLE INTENT: NOT FOR THE PURPOSE OF LOVING OR BEING LOVES; THEY DORNED THEMSELVES ONLY FOR THEIR ENEMIES, AND IN ORDER TO APPEAR MORE TERRIBLE. A sentiment of the historian, which would sound a little oddly in other nations and other ages.

The mindset of the Romans, stirred by constant wars, had elevated their view of courage to such a level that they referred to it as VIRTUE, distinguishing it from all other moral qualities. The Suevi, according to Tacitus, styled their hair with a respectable purpose: not to attract love or be loved; they adorned themselves only for their enemies, aiming to appear more fearsome. This perspective from the historian might seem a bit strange in other cultures and times.

The Scythians, according to Herodotus, [Footnote: Lib. iv.] after scalping their enemies, dressed the skin like leather, and used it as a towel; and whoever had the most of those towels was most esteemed among them. So much had martial bravery, in that nation, as well as in many others, destroyed the sentiments of humanity; a virtue surely much more useful and engaging.

The Scythians, according to Herodotus, [Footnote: Lib. iv.] after scalping their enemies, treated the skin like leather and used it as a towel; and whoever had the most of those towels was highly regarded among them. So much had martial bravery, in that nation, as well as in many others, destroyed the feelings of humanity; a quality that is surely much more useful and appealing.

It is indeed observable, that, among all uncultivated nations, who have not as yet had full experience of the advantages attending beneficence, justice, and the social virtues, courage is the predominant excellence; what is most celebrated by poets, recommended by parents and instructors, and admired by the public in general. The ethics of Homer are, in this particular, very different from those of Fenelon, his elegant imitator; and such as were well suited to an age, when one hero, as remarked by Thucydides [Lib.i.], could ask another, without offence, whether he were a robber or not. Such also very lately was the system of ethics which prevailed in many barbarous parts of Ireland; if we may credit Spencer, in his judicious account of the state of that kingdom.

It’s clear that, among all uncivilized nations that haven't fully experienced the benefits of kindness, justice, and social virtues, bravery is seen as the highest quality; it's what poets celebrate, parents and teachers promote, and what the public generally admires. The ethics of Homer are, in this respect, very different from those of Fenelon, his polished imitator; they were suited to a time when one hero, as Thucydides pointed out [Lib.i.], could question another about whether he was a robber without causing offense. Similarly, this was the moral code that existed recently in many parts of barbaric Ireland, if we can trust Spencer’s insightful account of that kingdom.

     [Footnote from Spencer: It is a common use, says he, amongst
their gentlemen's sons, that, as soon as they are able to use their
weapons, they strait gather to themselves three or four stragglers or
kern, with whom wandering a while up and down idly the country, taking
only meat, he at last falleth into some bad occasion, that shall be
offered; which being once made known, he is thenceforth counted a man of
worth, in whom there is courage.]
     [Footnote from Spencer: He says it's a common practice among the sons of gentlemen that, as soon as they can handle their weapons, they quickly gather a few stragglers or kern. They wander around the countryside aimlessly, only taking meat, and eventually, he gets involved in some trouble that comes his way. Once this is known, he is thereafter regarded as a man of value, one who has courage.]

Of the same class of virtues with courage is that undisturbed philosophical tranquillity, superior to pain, sorrow, anxiety, and each assault of adverse fortune. Conscious of his own virtue, say the philosophers, the sage elevates himself above every accident of life; and securely placed in the temple of wisdom, looks down on inferior mortals engaged in pursuit of honours, riches, reputation, and every frivolous enjoyment. These pretentious, no doubt, when stretched to the utmost, are by far too magnificent for human nature. They carry, however, a grandeur with them, which seizes the spectator, and strikes him with admiration. And the nearer we can approach in practice to this sublime tranquillity and indifference (for we must distinguish it from a stupid insensibility), the more secure enjoyment shall we attain within ourselves, and the more greatness of mind shall we discover to the world. The philosophical tranquillity may, indeed, be considered only as a branch of magnanimity.

Alongside courage is a calm philosophical mindset that’s unaffected by pain, sadness, worry, or any challenges life throws our way. Philosophers say that a wise person, aware of their own virtue, rises above all life’s ups and downs. Firmly rooted in the temple of wisdom, they look down on those chasing after honors, wealth, fame, and all kinds of trivial pleasures. These pursuits, while perhaps grand, are ultimately too extravagant for human nature. However, they do carry a certain splendor that captivates observers and fills them with awe. The closer we get to this elevated calmness and indifference (which we need to differentiate from a mindless numbness), the more profound enjoyment we will find within ourselves, and the greater we’ll appear to the world. This philosophical tranquility can indeed be seen as a part of being magnanimous.

Who admires not Socrates; his perpetual serenity and contentment, amidst the greatest poverty and domestic vexations; his resolute contempt of riches, and his magnanimous care of preserving liberty, while he refused all assistance from his friends and disciples, and avoided even the dependence of an obligation? Epictetus had not so much as a door to his little house or hovel; and therefore, soon lost his iron lamp, the only furniture which he had worth taking. But resolving to disappoint all robbers for the future, he supplied its place with an earthen lamp, of which he very peacefully kept possession ever after.

Who doesn’t admire Socrates? His constant calm and happiness, even in the face of great poverty and personal troubles; his steadfast disregard for wealth; and his noble commitment to preserving freedom, all while he turned down help from his friends and students, avoiding any sense of obligation. Epictetus didn’t even have a door to his small house or shack, so he quickly lost his iron lamp, the only piece of furniture worth taking. But determined not to be fooled by thieves again, he replaced it with an earthen lamp, which he peacefully kept for the rest of his days.

Among the ancients, the heroes in philosophy, as well as those in war and patriotism, have a grandeur and force of sentiment, which astonishes our narrow souls, and is rashly rejected as extravagant and supernatural. They, in their turn, I allow, would have had equal reason to consider as romantic and incredible, the degree of humanity, clemency, order, tranquillity, and other social virtues, to which, in the administration of government, we have attained in modern times, had any one been then able to have made a fair representation of them. Such is the compensation, which nature, or rather education, has made in the distribution of excellencies and virtues, in those different ages.

Among the ancients, the heroes of philosophy, as well as those in war and patriotism, have a grandeur and emotional strength that amazes our limited minds and is often dismissed as unrealistic and supernatural. In their time, I admit, they would have had every right to view the level of humanity, kindness, order, peace, and other social virtues we've achieved in modern governance as romantic and unbelievable, if anyone back then could have accurately represented them. This reflects the balance that nature, or rather education, has provided in the distribution of strengths and virtues across different eras.

The merit of benevolence, arising from its utility, and its tendency to promote the good of mankind has been already explained, and is, no doubt, the source of a CONSIDERABLE part of that esteem, which is so universally paid to it. But it will also be allowed, that the very softness and tenderness of the sentiment, its engaging endearments, its fond expressions, its delicate attentions, and all that flow of mutual confidence and regard, which enters into a warm attachment of love and friendship: it will be allowed, I say, that these feelings, being delightful in themselves, are necessarily communicated to the spectators, and melt them into the same fondness and delicacy. The tear naturally starts in our eye on the apprehension of a warm sentiment of this nature: our breast heaves, our heart is agitated, and every humane tender principle of our frame is set in motion, and gives us the purest and most satisfactory enjoyment.

The value of kindness, stemming from its usefulness and its ability to enhance the wellbeing of humanity, has already been discussed and is certainly a big part of the respect it receives everywhere. However, it should also be acknowledged that the gentle and caring nature of this sentiment, its charming affection, loving words, thoughtful gestures, and the flow of mutual trust and regard that come with a close bond of love and friendship, evoke feelings that are enjoyable in themselves. These feelings naturally affect anyone witnessing them, drawing them into the same warmth and sensitivity. A tear can easily fall from our eyes at the thought of such a heartfelt sentiment: our chest tightens, our heart races, and every compassionate and tender instinct within us is stirred, providing us with the purest and most fulfilling joy.

When poets form descriptions of Elysian fields, where the blessed inhabitants stand in no need of each other's assistance, they yet represent them as maintaining a constant intercourse of love and friendship, and sooth our fancy with the pleasing image of these soft and gentle passions. The idea of tender tranquillity in a pastoral Arcadia is agreeable from a like principle, as has been observed above. [Footnote: Sect. v. Part 2.]

When poets describe the Elysian fields, where the blessed residents don’t need each other’s help, they still show them as having a constant exchange of love and friendship, soothing our imagination with the lovely image of these soft and gentle feelings. The idea of calm serenity in a pastoral Arcadia is appealing for the same reason, as mentioned above. [Footnote: Sect. v. Part 2.]

Who would live amidst perpetual wrangling, and scolding, and mutual reproaches? The roughness and harshness of these emotions disturb and displease us: we suffer by contagion and sympathy; nor can we remain indifferent spectators, even though certain that no pernicious consequences would ever follow from such angry passions.

Who would want to live in constant fighting, scolding, and blaming each other? The roughness and harshness of these feelings unsettle and irritate us: we get affected by them through empathy and shared feelings; we can't stay indifferent onlookers, even if we're sure that no harmful outcomes would ever result from such angry emotions.

As a certain proof that the whole merit of benevolence is not derived from its usefulness, we may observe, that in a kind way of blame, we say, a person is TOO GOOD; when he exceeds his part in society, and carries his attention for others beyond the proper bounds. In like manner, we say, a man is too HIGH-SPIRITED, TOO INTREPID, TOO INDIFFERENT ABOUT FORTUNE: reproaches, which really, at bottom, imply more esteem than many panegyrics. Being accustomed to rate the merit and demerit of characters chiefly by their useful or pernicious tendencies, we cannot forbear applying the epithet of blame, when we discover a sentiment, which rises to a degree, that is hurtful; but it may happen, at the same time, that its noble elevation, or its engaging tenderness so seizes the heart, as rather to increase our friendship and concern for the person.

As clear proof that the value of kindness doesn't come solely from its usefulness, we can see that when we criticize someone gently, we often say they're TOO GOOD; this happens when they go overboard in looking out for others beyond what's appropriate. Similarly, we say someone is too HIGH-SPIRITED, TOO BRAVE, or TOO UNCONCERNED ABOUT FORTUNE: these criticisms often show more respect than many praises do. Since we usually judge people's worth based on how helpful or harmful they are, we can't help but assign blame when we notice feelings that become excessive and detrimental; however, it can also be true that this admirable quality or heartfelt compassion can touch us deeply, ultimately strengthening our bond and concern for that person.

     [Footnote: Cheerfulness could scarce admit of blame from its
excess, were it not that dissolute mirth, without a proper cause or
subject, is a sure symptom and characteristic of folly, and on that
account disgustful.]
[Footnote: Cheerfulness can hardly be blamed for being excessive, but mindless joy, lacking a valid reason or purpose, is definitely a sign of foolishness, and for that reason, it's off-putting.]

The amours and attachments of Harry the IVth of France, during the civil wars of the league, frequently hurt his interest and his cause; but all the young, at least, and amorous, who can sympathize with the tender passions, will allow that this very weakness, for they will readily call it such, chiefly endears that hero, and interests them in his fortunes.

The romances and relationships of Henry IV of France during the civil wars of the League often harmed his interests and his cause; however, all the young and romantic individuals who can relate to tender feelings will agree that this very weakness, which they will easily label as such, primarily makes that hero endearing and engages them in his fate.

The excessive bravery and resolute inflexibility of Charles the XIIth ruined his own country, and infested all his neighbours; but have such splendour and greatness in their appearance, as strikes us with admiration; and they might, in some degree, be even approved of, if they betrayed not sometimes too evident symptoms of madness and disorder.

The extreme bravery and stubbornness of Charles the XIIth destroyed his own country and troubled all his neighbors. However, they have a certain splendor and greatness that impresses us, and they might even be somewhat admired if they didn’t occasionally show clear signs of madness and chaos.

The Athenians pretended to the first invention of agriculture and of laws: and always valued themselves extremely on the benefit thereby procured to the whole race of mankind. They also boasted, and with reason, of their war like enterprises; particularly against those innumerable fleets and armies of Persians, which invaded Greece during the reigns of Darius and Xerxes. But though there be no comparison in point of utility, between these peaceful and military honours; yet we find, that the orators, who have writ such elaborate panegyrics on that famous city, have chiefly triumphed in displaying the warlike achievements. Lysias, Thucydides, Plato, and Isocrates discover, all of them, the same partiality; which, though condemned by calm reason and reflection, appears so natural in the mind of man.

The Athenians claimed to be the first to invent agriculture and laws, and they took great pride in the benefits this brought to all of humanity. They also boasted, and rightly so, about their military exploits, especially against the countless Persian fleets and armies that invaded Greece during the reigns of Darius and Xerxes. While there’s no comparison in terms of value between these peaceful and military honors, we see that the orators who have written such detailed praises of that famous city mostly focused on its military accomplishments. Lysias, Thucydides, Plato, and Isocrates all show this same bias, which, although criticized by reason and reflection, seems very natural to human nature.

It is observable, that the great charm of poetry consists in lively pictures of the sublime passions, magnanimity, courage, disdain of fortune; or those of the tender affections, love and friendship; which warm the heart, and diffuse over it similar sentiments and emotions. And though all kinds of passion, even the most disagreeable, such as grief and anger, are observed, when excited by poetry, to convey a satisfaction, from a mechanism of nature, not easy to be explained: Yet those more elevated or softer affections have a peculiar influence, and please from more than one cause or principle. Not to mention that they alone interest us in the fortune of the persons represented, or communicate any esteem and affection for their character.

It's clear that the real appeal of poetry lies in its vibrant depictions of grand emotions like nobility, bravery, and disregard for fate, as well as gentle feelings like love and friendship. These evoke warmth in our hearts and spread similar feelings and emotions. While all types of passion, even the most unpleasant ones like grief and anger, can bring a certain satisfaction through a natural mechanism that's hard to explain, the more elevated or tender feelings have a unique impact and please us for multiple reasons. Not to mention, they engage us with the characters' destinies and foster admiration and affection for their traits.

And can it possibly be doubted, that this talent itself of poets, to move the passions, this pathetic and sublime of sentiment, is a very considerable merit; and being enhanced by its extreme rarity, may exalt the person possessed of it, above every character of the age in which he lives? The prudence, address, steadiness, and benign government of Augustus, adorned with all the splendour of his noble birth and imperial crown, render him but an unequal competitor for fame with Virgil, who lays nothing into the opposite scale but the divine beauties of his poetical genius.

And can anyone really doubt that the ability of poets to evoke emotions, their poignant and elevated feelings, is a significant talent? Given how rare it is, it can elevate someone who possesses it above everyone else in their time. The wisdom, skill, steadiness, and kind leadership of Augustus, celebrated by his noble lineage and imperial crown, make him an unequal rival for fame compared to Virgil, who brings nothing to the table but the extraordinary beauty of his poetic genius.

The very sensibility to these beauties, or a delicacy of taste, is itself a beauty in any character; as conveying the purest, the most durable, and most innocent of all enjoyments.

The ability to appreciate these beauties, or a refined taste, is itself a beauty in anyone; as it brings the purest, most lasting, and most innocent of all pleasures.

These are some instances of the several species of merit, that are valued for the immediate pleasure which they communicate to the person possessed of them. No views of utility or of future beneficial consequences enter into this sentiment of approbation; yet is it of a kind similar to that other sentiment, which arises from views of a public or private utility. The same social sympathy, we may observe, or fellow-feeling with human happiness or misery, gives rise to both; and this analogy, in all the parts of the present theory, may justly be regarded as a confirmation of it.

These are a few examples of the different types of merit that people appreciate for the immediate pleasure they bring to those who have them. No thoughts about usefulness or future benefits influence this feeling of approval; however, it's similar to the other sentiment that comes from considerations of public or private good. The same social empathy or shared concern for human happiness or suffering fuels both emotions, and this parallel throughout the current theory can rightly be seen as supporting it.





SECTION VIII.

OF QUALITIES IMMEDIATELY AGREEABLE TO OTHERS.

     [Footnote: It is the nature and, indeed, the definition of
virtue, that it is A QUALITY OF THE MIND AGREEABLE TO OR APPROVED OF BY
EVERY ONE WHO CONSIDERS OR CONTEMPLATES IT. But some qualities produce
pleasure, because they are useful to society, or useful or agreeable
to the person himself; others produce it more immediately, which is the
case with the class of virtues here considered.]
     [Footnote: Virtue is defined as a quality of the mind that is pleasing to or valued by everyone who thinks about it. Some qualities bring pleasure because they are beneficial to society, or are helpful or enjoyable to the individual; others provide pleasure more directly, which applies to the group of virtues being discussed here.]

AS the mutual shocks, in SOCIETY, and the oppositions of interest and self-love have constrained mankind to establish the laws of JUSTICE, in order to preserve the advantages of mutual assistance and protection: in like manner, the eternal contrarieties, in COMPANY, of men's pride and self-conceit, have introduced the rules of Good Manners or Politeness, in order to facilitate the intercourse of minds, and an undisturbed commerce and conversation. Among well-bred people, a mutual deference is affected; contempt of others disguised; authority concealed; attention given to each in his turn; and an easy stream of conversation maintained, without vehemence, without interruption, without eagerness for victory, and without any airs of superiority. These attentions and regards are immediately AGREEABLE to others, abstracted from any consideration of utility or beneficial tendencies: they conciliate affection, promote esteem, and extremely enhance the merit of the person who regulates his behaviour by them.

As the mutual conflicts in society and the clash of interests and self-interest have driven people to create the laws of justice to protect the benefits of cooperation and safety, similarly, the constant oppositions in social settings between people's pride and self-importance have led to the establishment of rules of good manners or politeness to make interactions smoother and maintain easy communication and conversation. Among well-mannered individuals, there is a display of mutual respect; disdain for others is hidden; authority is kept low-key; attention is given to everyone in their turn; and a smooth flow of conversation is maintained without intensity, interruptions, eagerness to win, or any sense of superiority. These gestures and considerations are inherently pleasing to others, aside from any thoughts of usefulness or benefits: they foster affection, boost esteem, and significantly increase the value of the person who follows them.

Many of the forms of breeding are arbitrary and casual; but the thing expressed by them is still the same. A Spaniard goes out of his own house before his guest, to signify that he leaves him master of all. In other countries, the landlord walks out last, as a common mark of deference and regard.

Many ways of breeding are random and laid-back; however, what they convey remains the same. A Spaniard steps out of his house before his guest to show that he is leaving him in charge. In other countries, the host leaves last as a common sign of respect and consideration.

But, in order to render a man perfect GOOD COMPANY, he must have Wit and Ingenuity as well as good manners. What wit is, it may not be easy to define; but it is easy surely to determine that it is a quality immediately AGREEABLE to others, and communicating, on its first appearance, a lively joy and satisfaction to every one who has any comprehension of it. The most profound metaphysics, indeed, might be employed in explaining the various kinds and species of wit; and many classes of it, which are now received on the sole testimony of taste and sentiment, might, perhaps, be resolved into more general principles. But this is sufficient for our present purpose, that it does affect taste and sentiment, and bestowing an immediate enjoyment, is a sure source of approbation and affection.

But to make someone truly great company, they need to have wit and creativity as well as good manners. Wit might be hard to define, but it’s clear that it’s a quality that people find immediately enjoyable, bringing a sense of joy and satisfaction to anyone who understands it. One could certainly dive deep into the complexities of wit, explaining the different types and forms it takes; many of these are accepted based solely on individual taste and feeling, and could possibly be explained by broader principles. However, for our current discussion, it’s enough to say that wit influences taste and sentiment, and by providing immediate enjoyment, it is a reliable source of approval and fondness.

In countries where men pass most of their time in conversation, and visits, and assemblies, these COMPANIONABLE qualities, so to speak, are of high estimation, and form a chief part of personal merit. In countries where men live a more domestic life, and either are employed in business, or amuse themselves in a narrower circle of acquaintance, the more solid qualities are chiefly regarded. Thus, I have often observed, that, among the French, the first questions with regard to a stranger are, IS HE POLITE? HAS HE WIT? In our own country, the chief praise bestowed is always that of a GOOD-NATURED, SENSIBLE FELLOW.

In countries where men spend most of their time talking, visiting, and socializing, these FRIENDLY traits are highly valued and are a major part of someone's personal worth. In places where men live a more home-centered life and either work or socialize in a smaller circle, the more substantial qualities are what really matter. I've often noticed that, among the French, the first questions about a stranger are, IS HE POLITE? DOES HE HAVE WIT? In our own country, the highest compliment is usually that of a GOOD-NATURED, SENSIBLE GUY.

In conversation, the lively spirit of dialogue is AGREEABLE, even to those who desire not to have any share in the discourse: hence the teller of long stories, or the pompous declaimer, is very little approved of. But most men desire likewise their turn in the conversation, and regard, with a very evil eye, that LOQUACITY which deprives them of a right they are naturally so jealous of.

In conversation, the dynamic energy of dialogue is PLEASANT, even for those who don’t want to participate in the discussion: that's why someone who tells long stories or speaks in a grandiose manner is not very well-liked. However, most people also want their chance to speak and look down on that CHATTINESS which takes away a right they are naturally protective of.

There is a sort of harmless LIARS, frequently to be met with in company, who deal much in the marvellous. Their usual intention is to please and entertain; but as men are most delighted with what they conceive to be truth, these people mistake extremely the means of pleasing, and incur universal blame. Some indulgence, however, to lying or fiction is given in HUMOROUS stories; because it is there really agreeable and entertaining, and truth is not of any importance.

There are some harmless LIARS you often encounter in social settings who love to share amazing tales. Their main goal is to entertain and amuse, but since people are usually more delighted by what they believe to be true, these individuals seriously misjudge how to please and end up facing widespread criticism. However, a bit of tolerance for lying or fiction is allowed in HUMOROUS stories, because in that context, it's genuinely enjoyable and entertaining, and the truth doesn’t really matter.

Eloquence, genius of all kinds, even good sense, and sound reasoning, when it rises to an eminent degree, and is employed upon subjects of any considerable dignity and nice discernment; all these endowments seem immediately agreeable, and have a merit distinct from their usefulness. Rarity, likewise, which so much enhances the price of every thing, must set an additional value on these noble talents of the human mind.

Eloquence, all forms of genius, even common sense and logical reasoning, when they reach a high level and are applied to subjects of significance and subtle distinction, all these qualities seem instantly appealing and have a value separate from their practicality. Rarity, which increases the value of everything, must also add extra worth to these exceptional talents of the human mind.

Modesty may be understood in different senses, even abstracted from chastity, which has been already treated of. It sometimes means that tenderness and nicety of honour, that apprehension of blame, that dread of intrusion or injury towards others, that Pudor, which is the proper guardian of every kind of virtue, and a sure preservative against vice and corruption. But its most usual meaning is when it is opposed to IMPUDENCE and ARROGANCE, and expresses a diffidence of our own judgement, and a due attention and regard for others. In young men chiefly, this quality is a sure sign of good sense; and is also the certain means of augmenting that endowment, by preserving their ears open to instruction, and making them still grasp after new attainments. But it has a further charm to every spectator; by flattering every man's vanity, and presenting the appearance of a docile pupil, who receives, with proper attention and respect, every word they utter.

Modesty can be understood in various ways, even apart from chastity, which has already been discussed. Sometimes, it refers to a sensitivity and care for honor, a fear of blame, a concern about intruding on or harming others, and that sense of decency, which is a true protector of all virtues and a reliable guard against vice and corruption. However, it most commonly means the opposite of IMPUDENCE and ARROGANCE, reflecting humility in our own judgments and a genuine consideration and respect for others. Especially in young men, this trait is a clear indicator of good sense and a great way to enhance their abilities, keeping them open to learning and eager for new achievements. Additionally, it has an added appeal to everyone watching; it flatters people's egos and shows them a model student who listens attentively and respectfully to everything they say.

Men have, in general, a much greater propensity to overvalue than undervalue themselves; notwithstanding the opinion of Aristotle [Footnote: Ethic. ad Nicomachum.]. This makes us more jealous of the excess on the former side, and causes us to regard, with a peculiar indulgence, all tendency to modesty and self-diffidence; as esteeming the danger less of falling into any vicious extreme of that nature. It is thus in countries where men's bodies are apt to exceed in corpulency, personal beauty is placed in a much greater degree of slenderness, than in countries where that is the most usual defect. Being so often struck with instances of one species of deformity, men think they can never keep at too great a distance from it, and wish always to have a leaning to the opposite side. In like manner, were the door opened to self-praise, and were Montaigne's maxim observed, that one should say as frankly, I HAVE SENSE, I HAVE LEARNING, I HAVE COURAGE, BEAUTY, OR WIT, as it is sure we often think so; were this the case, I say, every one is sensible that such a flood of impertinence would break in upon us, as would render society wholly intolerable. For this reason custom has established it as a rule, in common societies, that men should not indulge themselves in self-praise, or even speak much of themselves; and it is only among intimate friends or people of very manly behaviour, that one is allowed to do himself justice. Nobody finds fault with Maurice, Prince of Orange, for his reply to one who asked him, whom he esteemed the first general of the age, THE MARQUIS OF SPINOLA, said he, IS THE SECOND. Though it is observable, that the self-praise implied is here better implied, than if it had been directly expressed, without any cover or disguise.

In general, men tend to value themselves more than undervalue themselves, despite Aristotle's viewpoint. This makes us more jealous of those who overdo it, and we view modesty and self-doubt more favorably, seeing the risk of falling into excessive arrogance as less concerning. In places where people tend to be heavier, personal beauty is often defined by being leaner, unlike areas where being overweight is more common. Because they frequently encounter a specific type of imperfection, men believe they can never distance themselves enough from it and prefer to lean towards the opposite extreme. Similarly, if self-praise were common, and if Montaigne's idea that we should freely say we possess intelligence, knowledge, courage, beauty, or wit were embraced, we would quickly be overwhelmed by a flood of arrogance that would make society unbearable. For this reason, it's become a rule in social settings that men shouldn't indulge in self-praise or talk too much about themselves; self-justification is only permitted among close friends or very confident individuals. No one criticizes Maurice, Prince of Orange, for his response to someone who asked him who he thought was the greatest general of his time. He said, "The Marquis of Spinola is the second." It's interesting that the self-praise here is more subtly implied than if it had been directly stated without any nuance.

He must be a very superficial thinker, who imagines that all instances of mutual deference are to be understood in earnest, and that a man would be more esteemable for being ignorant of his own merits and accomplishments. A small bias towards modesty, even in the internal sentiment, is favourably regarded, especially in young people; and a strong bias is required in the outward behaviour; but this excludes not a noble pride and spirit, which may openly display itself in its full extent, when one lies under calumny or oppression of any kind. The generous contumacy of Socrates, as Cicero calls it, has been highly celebrated in all ages; and when joined to the usual modesty of his behaviour, forms a shining character. Iphicrates, the Athenian, being accused of betraying the interests of his country, asked his accuser, WOULD YOU, says he, HAVE, ON A LIKE OCCASION, BEEN GUILTY OF THAT CRIME? BY NO MEANS, replied the other. AND CAN YOU THEN IMAGINE, cried the hero, that Iphicrates WOULD BE GUILTY? [Footnote: Quinctil. lib. v. cap. 12.]—In short, a generous spirit and self-value, well founded, decently disguised, and courageously supported under distress and calumny, is a great excellency, and seems to derive its merit from the noble elevation of its sentiment, or its immediate agreeableness to its possessor. In ordinary characters, we approve of a bias towards modesty, which is a quality immediately agreeable to others: the vicious excess of the former virtue, namely, insolence or haughtiness, is immediately disagreeable to others; the excess of the latter is so to the possessor. Thus are the boundaries of these duties adjusted.

He must be a very shallow thinker who believes that all instances of mutual respect are meant to be taken seriously and that a person would be more admirable for being unaware of their own strengths and achievements. A slight tendency toward modesty, even in private feelings, is viewed positively, especially in young people; and a strong tendency is expected in public behavior. However, this doesn't exclude a noble pride and spirit, which can openly show itself in full force when facing slander or oppression of any kind. The noble defiance of Socrates, as Cicero calls it, has been celebrated throughout history; and when combined with his usual modesty, it creates a remarkable character. Iphicrates, the Athenian, when accused of betraying his country, asked his accuser, "Would you, in a similar situation, have committed that crime?" "Of course not," the accuser replied. "Then can you imagine," exclaimed the hero, "that Iphicrates would be guilty?" [Footnote: Quinctil. lib. v. cap. 12.]—In short, a generous spirit and well-founded self-respect, modestly presented and courageously upheld in the face of hardship and slander, is a great virtue, and seems to gain its value from the noble elevation of its mindset or its immediate appeal to its possessor. In ordinary individuals, we appreciate a tendency toward modesty, a quality that is immediately agreeable to others: the extreme negative side of the former virtue, namely, arrogance or pride, is immediately off-putting to others; while the extreme of the latter is unpleasant for the person themselves. This is how the boundaries of these virtues are defined.

A desire of fame, reputation, or a character with others, is so far from being blameable, that it seems inseparable from virtue, genius, capacity, and a generous or noble disposition. An attention even to trivial matters, in order to please, is also expected and demanded by society; and no one is surprised, if he find a man in company to observe a greater elegance of dress and more pleasant flow of conversation, than when he passes his time at home, and with his own family. Wherein, then, consists Vanity, which is so justly regarded as a fault or imperfection. It seems to consist chiefly in such an intemperate display of our advantages, honours, and accomplishments; in such an importunate and open demand of praise and admiration, as is offensive to others, and encroaches too far on their secret vanity and ambition. It is besides a sure symptom of the want of true dignity and elevation of mind, which is so great an ornament in any character. For why that impatient desire of applause; as if you were not justly entitled to it, and might not reasonably expect that it would for ever at tend you? Why so anxious to inform us of the great company which you have kept; the obliging things which were said to you; the honours, the distinctions which you met with; as if these were not things of course, and what we could readily, of ourselves, have imagined, without being told of them?

A desire for fame, reputation, or recognition from others is far from blameworthy; it seems to be inseparable from virtue, talent, capability, and a generous or noble character. Society expects and demands attention to even trivial matters to please others, and no one is surprised to find someone in a social setting presenting themselves with greater elegance in dress and more engaging conversation than when they are at home with their own family. So, what then is Vanity, which is rightly seen as a fault or imperfection? It seems to stem primarily from an excessive display of our advantages, honors, and skills; from an insistent and blatant demand for praise and admiration that offends others and intrudes too much on their own hidden vanity and ambition. Moreover, it indicates a clear lack of true dignity and a lofty mindset, which are such valuable traits in any character. Why the restless craving for applause, as if you weren’t rightfully deserving of it, and couldn’t reasonably expect it to always follow you? Why such eagerness to tell us about the distinguished company you’ve kept, the flattering remarks made to you, and the honors and distinctions you’ve received, as if these weren’t expected things that we could easily have guessed for ourselves without being told?

Decency, or a proper regard to age, sex, character, and station in the world, may be ranked among the qualities which are immediately agreeable to others, and which, by that means, acquire praise and approbation. An effeminate behaviour in a man, a rough manner in a woman; these are ugly because unsuitable to each character, and different from the qualities which we expect in the sexes. It is as if a tragedy abounded in comic beauties, or a comedy in tragic. The disproportions hurt the eye, and convey a disagreeable sentiment to the spectators, the source of blame and disapprobation. This is that INDECORUM, which is explained so much at large by Cicero in his Offices.

Decency, or a proper consideration of age, gender, character, and social status, is one of those qualities that people generally find appealing. As a result, it earns praise and approval. When a man acts too feminine or a woman behaves too roughly, it looks unattractive because it's inappropriate for their respective roles and different from the traits we expect in each gender. It's like a tragedy filled with comedic elements or a comedy full of tragic ones. These mismatches are uncomfortable to see and create an unpleasant feeling for the audience, leading to criticism and disapproval. This is what we call INDECORUM, which Cicero discusses extensively in his Offices.

Among the other virtues, we may also give Cleanliness a place; since it naturally renders us agreeable to others, and is no inconsiderable source of love and affection. No one will deny, that a negligence in this particular is a fault; and as faults are nothing but smaller vices, and this fault can have no other origin than the uneasy sensation which it excites in others; we may, in this instance, seemingly so trivial, clearly discover the origin of moral distinctions, about which the learned have involved themselves in such mazes of perplexity and error.

Among other virtues, we should also recognize Cleanliness; it naturally makes us more pleasant to others and is a significant source of love and affection. No one can deny that being careless about this is a flaw, and since flaws are simply lesser vices, this flaw stems from the uncomfortable feelings it causes in others. In this seemingly trivial case, we can clearly see the origin of moral distinctions that experts have gotten so tangled up in with confusion and mistakes.

But besides all the AGREEABLE qualities, the origin of whose beauty we can, in some degree, explain and account for, there still remains something mysterious and inexplicable, which conveys an immediate satisfaction to the spectator, but how, or why, or for what reason, he cannot pretend to determine. There is a manner, a grace, an ease, a genteelness, an I-know-not-what, which some men possess above others, which is very different from external beauty and comeliness, and which, however, catches our affection almost as suddenly and powerfully. And though this MANNER be chiefly talked of in the passion between the sexes, where the concealed magic is easily explained, yet surely much of it prevails in all our estimation of characters, and forms no inconsiderable part of personal merit. This class of accomplishments, therefore, must be trusted entirely to the blind, but sure testimony of taste and sentiment; and must be considered as a part of ethics, left by nature to baffle all the pride of philosophy, and make her sensible of her narrow boundaries and slender acquisitions.

But in addition to all the pleasant qualities, the source of whose beauty we can somewhat explain, there's still something mysterious and inexplicable that gives an immediate satisfaction to the viewer, but how, or why, or for what reason, they can't really figure out. There’s a certain style, grace, ease, gentility, and some indescribable quality that some people have more than others, which is very different from physical beauty and attractiveness, and yet, it captures our affection almost as suddenly and intensely. And while this style is mostly talked about in romantic relationships, where the hidden charm is easily explained, it definitely plays a significant role in how we judge character overall, and it forms an important part of personal merit. Therefore, this type of achievement must be left entirely to the blind but reliable judgment of taste and emotion; it should be seen as part of ethics, left by nature to challenge all the pride of philosophy, highlighting its limited scope and modest achievements.

We approve of another, because of his wit, politeness, modesty, decency, or any agreeable quality which he possesses; although he be not of our acquaintance, nor has ever given us any entertainment, by means of these accomplishments. The idea, which we form of their effect on his acquaintance, has an agreeable influence on our imagination, and gives us the sentiment of approbation. This principle enters into all the judgements which we form concerning manners and characters.

We like someone because of their humor, kindness, humility, decency, or any other appealing quality they have, even if we don’t know them personally or haven’t been entertained by them because of these traits. The impression we have of how these qualities affect their relationships has a positive impact on our imagination and makes us feel approval. This principle is involved in all the judgments we make about people’s behavior and character.





SECTION IX. CONCLUSION.





PART I.

IT may justly appear surprising that any man in so late an age, should find it requisite to prove, by elaborate reasoning, that Personal Merit consists altogether in the possession of mental qualities, USEFUL or AGREEABLE to the PERSON HIMSELF or to OTHERS. It might be expected that this principle would have occurred even to the first rude, unpractised enquirers concerning morals, and been received from its own evidence, without any argument or disputation. Whatever is valuable in any kind, so naturally classes itself under the division of USEFUL or AGREEABLE, the UTILE or the DULCE, that it is not easy to imagine why we should ever seek further, or consider the question as a matter of nice research or inquiry. And as every thing useful or agreeable must possess these qualities with regard either to the PERSON HIMSELF or to OTHERS, the complete delineation or description of merit seems to be performed as naturally as a shadow is cast by the sun, or an image is reflected upon water. If the ground, on which the shadow is cast, be not broken and uneven; nor the surface from which the image is reflected, disturbed and confused; a just figure is immediately presented, without any art or attention. And it seems a reasonable presumption, that systems and hypotheses have perverted our natural understanding, when a theory, so simple and obvious, could so long have escaped the most elaborate examination.

It may be quite surprising that in this day and age, someone feels the need to demonstrate, through detailed reasoning, that personal merit is entirely based on having mental qualities that are either USEFUL or AGREEABLE to the person himself or to others. One might expect that this principle would have been recognized even by the earliest, inexperienced inquirers into morals, and accepted based on its own clarity, without any need for argument or debate. Anything valuable naturally falls into the categories of USEFUL or AGREEABLE, the UTILE or the DULCE, making it hard to understand why we would need to explore further or treat the question as a complex matter of research or inquiry. Since everything that is useful or agreeable must have these qualities in relation to either the person himself or to others, outlining or defining merit seems to happen as naturally as a shadow being cast by the sun or an image being reflected on water. If the ground where the shadow is cast is smooth and even, and the surface from which the image is reflected is clear and undisturbed, a true image is presented immediately, without any special effort or focus. It seems reasonable to assume that theories and systems have distorted our natural understanding when a concept so simple and obvious could remain overlooked for so long despite extensive examination.

But however the case may have fared with philosophy, in common life these principles are still implicitly maintained; nor is any other topic of praise or blame ever recurred to, when we employ any panegyric or satire, any applause or censure of human action and behaviour. If we observe men, in every intercourse of business or pleasure, in every discourse and conversation, we shall find them nowhere, except the schools, at any loss upon this subject. What so natural, for instance, as the following dialogue? You are very happy, we shall suppose one to say, addressing himself to another, that you have given your daughter to Cleanthes. He is a man of honour and humanity. Every one, who has any intercourse with him, is sure of FAIR and KIND treatment. [Footnote: Qualities useful to others.] I congratulate you too, says another, on the promising expectations of this son-in-law; whose assiduous application to the study of the laws, whose quick penetration and early knowledge both of men and business, prognosticate the greatest honours and advancement. [Footnote: Qualities useful to the person himself.] You surprise me, replies a third, when you talk of Cleanthes as a man of business and application. I met him lately in a circle of the gayest company, and he was the very life and soul of our conversation: so much wit with good manners; so much gallantry without affectation; so much ingenious knowledge so genteelly delivered, I have never before observed in any one. [Footnote: Qualities immediately agreeable to others,] You would admire him still more, says a fourth, if you knew him more familiarly. That cheerfulness, which you might remark in him, is not a sudden flash struck out by company: it runs through the whole tenor of his life, and preserves a perpetual serenity on his countenance, and tranquillity in his soul. He has met with severe trials, misfortunes as well as dangers; and by his greatness of mind, was still superior to all of them [Footnote: Qualities immediately agreeable to the person himself]. The image, gentlemen, which you have here delineated of Cleanthes, cried I, is that of accomplished merit. Each of you has given a stroke of the pencil to his figure; and you have unawares exceeded all the pictures drawn by Gratian or Castiglione. A philosopher might select this character as a model of perfect virtue.

But no matter how philosophy has fared, these principles are still implicitly held in everyday life; we don't really talk about anything else when we offer praise or criticism of human actions and behaviors. If we observe people in every interaction—whether in business or in leisure, in discussions and conversations—we'll find that they’re never confused about this topic, except in academic settings. For instance, consider this natural dialogue: One person might say to another, "You must be very happy that you’ve married your daughter to Cleanthes. He is a man of honor and kindness. Everyone who interacts with him knows they will be treated fairly and kindly." I congratulate you too, says another, "on the promising expectations for this son-in-law, whose diligent study of the law and sharp insight into people and matters predict great honors and advancements." You surprise me, replies a third, "when you call Cleanthes a man of business and diligence. I recently saw him among the most lively company, and he was the very life of our conversation: so much wit combined with good manners; so much charm without pretension; so much clever knowledge delivered so graciously, I have never seen anything like it before." You would admire him even more, says a fourth, "if you knew him better. That cheerfulness you see in him isn’t just a momentary spark ignited by company; it flows through every aspect of his life and keeps a constant serenity on his face and tranquility in his soul. He has faced significant challenges and adversities, yet his strong character has kept him above them all." The image you’ve painted of Cleanthes, I said, is one of true merit. Each of you has contributed to his portrait, and you have unwittingly surpassed the depictions made by Gratian or Castiglione. A philosopher could use this character as a model of perfect virtue.

And as every quality which is useful or agreeable to ourselves or others is, in common life, allowed to be a part of personal merit; so no other will ever be received, where men judge of things by their natural, unprejudiced reason, without the delusive glosses of superstition and false religion. Celibacy, fasting, penance, mortification, self-denial, humility, silence, solitude, and the whole train of monkish virtues; for what reason are they everywhere rejected by men of sense, but because they serve to no manner of purpose; neither advance a man's fortune in the world, nor render him a more valuable member of society; neither qualify him for the entertainment of company, nor increase his power of self-enjoyment? We observe, on the contrary, that they cross all these desirable ends; stupify the understanding and harden the heart, obscure the fancy and sour the temper. We justly, therefore, transfer them to the opposite column, and place them in the catalogue of vices; nor has any superstition force sufficient among men of the world, to pervert entirely these natural sentiments. A gloomy, hair-brained enthusiast, after his death, may have a place in the calendar; but will scarcely ever be admitted, when alive, into intimacy and society, except by those who are as delirious and dismal as himself.

And just as every quality that is helpful or pleasing to ourselves or others is generally recognized as a part of personal merit in everyday life, no other qualities will be accepted where people evaluate things based on their natural, unbiased reasoning, free from the misleading influences of superstition and false beliefs. Celibacy, fasting, penance, self-denial, humility, silence, solitude, and the whole range of monk-like virtues—why are they rejected by sensible people everywhere? It's because they serve no real purpose; they don’t improve someone’s situation in life, make them a more valuable member of society, help them enjoy company, or enhance their ability to find personal happiness. In fact, we see that they hinder all these desirable goals, dulling the mind and hardening the heart, clouding the imagination and souring the mood. Therefore, we rightly categorize them as vices and place them in the opposite column. No superstition is powerful enough among practical people to completely distort these natural feelings. A gloomy, fanatical enthusiast might gain a spot in the calendar after death, but is unlikely ever to be welcomed into friendships and social circles while alive, except by those who are just as delirious and morose as he is.

It seems a happiness in the present theory, that it enters not into that vulgar dispute concerning the DEGREES of benevolence or self-love, which prevail in human nature; a dispute which is never likely to have any issue, both because men, who have taken part, are not easily convinced, and because the phenomena, which can be produced on either side, are so dispersed, so uncertain, and subject to so many interpretations, that it is scarcely possible accurately to compare them, or draw from them any determinate inference or conclusion. It is sufficient for our present purpose, if it be allowed, what surely, without the greatest absurdity cannot be disputed, that there is some benevolence, however small, infused into our bosom; some spark of friendship for human kind; some particle of the dove kneaded into our frame, along with the elements of the wolf and serpent. Let these generous sentiments be supposed ever so weak; let them be insufficient to move even a hand or finger of our body, they must still direct the determinations of our mind, and where everything else is equal, produce a cool preference of what is useful and serviceable to mankind, above what is pernicious and dangerous. A MORAL DISTINCTION, therefore, immediately arises; a general sentiment of blame and approbation; a tendency, however faint, to the objects of the one, and a proportionable aversion to those of the other. Nor will those reasoners, who so earnestly maintain the predominant selfishness of human kind, be any wise scandalized at hearing of the weak sentiments of virtue implanted in our nature. On the contrary, they are found as ready to maintain the one tenet as the other; and their spirit of satire (for such it appears, rather than of corruption) naturally gives rise to both opinions; which have, indeed, a great and almost an indissoluble connexion together.

It seems that there's a certain happiness in the current theory, as it avoids the common debate about the DEGREES of benevolence or self-love that exists in human nature; a debate that is unlikely to be resolved. This is because the people involved are hard to persuade, and the evidence on both sides is so scattered, uncertain, and open to many interpretations that it's nearly impossible to compare them accurately or derive any clear conclusions. For our current purpose, it’s enough to accept—without utter absurdity—that there’s some level of benevolence, however small, within us; a bit of friendliness towards humanity; a touch of compassion mixed in with the instincts of the wolf and serpent. Even if these generous feelings are weak and unable to move even a hand or finger, they must still influence our thoughts, and where everything else is equal, lead us to prefer what is beneficial and helpful to humanity over what is harmful and dangerous. Thus, a MORAL DISTINCTION arises immediately; a general feeling of blame and approval; a subtle inclination towards the one and a corresponding aversion to the other. Those thinkers who strongly argue for the predominance of selfishness in humanity won't be shocked to hear about the weak sense of virtue that’s part of our nature. In fact, they seem just as eager to support both views; their sense of satire (which appears more like a critique than a moral failing) naturally gives rise to both positions, which are indeed closely and almost inseparably linked together.

Avarice, ambition, vanity, and all passions vulgarly, though improperly, comprised under the denomination of SELF-LOVE, are here excluded from our theory concerning the origin of morals, not because they are too weak, but because they have not a proper direction for that purpose. The notion of morals implies some sentiment common to all mankind, which recommends the same object to general approbation, and makes every man, or most men, agree in the same opinion or decision concerning it. It also implies some sentiment, so universal and comprehensive as to extend to all mankind, and render the actions and conduct, even of the persons the most remote, an object of applause or censure, according as they agree or disagree with that rule of right which is established. These two requisite circumstances belong alone to the sentiment of humanity here insisted on. The other passions produce in every breast, many strong sentiments of desire and aversion, affection and hatred; but these neither are felt so much in common, nor are so comprehensive, as to be the foundation of any general system and established theory of blame or approbation.

Greed, ambition, vanity, and all those passions commonly but inaccurately referred to as SELF-LOVE are excluded from our theory about the origin of morals, not because they are too weak, but because they don't have the right focus for that purpose. The idea of morals involves a sentiment that is shared by all humanity, which promotes the same goals for general approval, leading most people to agree on the same opinions or decisions regarding it. It also involves a sentiment that is so universal and inclusive that it applies to all people, making the actions and behaviors of even those most distant from us subject to praise or criticism based on whether they align with the established standard of right. These two essential elements belong solely to the sentiment of humanity that we are discussing. Other passions create strong feelings of desire and aversion, love and hate in each person; however, these feelings are neither commonly shared nor broad enough to form the basis of any general system or established theory of blame or approval.

When a man denominates another his ENEMY, his RIVAL, his ANTAGONIST, his ADVERSARY, he is understood to speak the language of self-love, and to express sentiments, peculiar to himself, and arising from his particular circumstances and situation. But when he bestows on any man the epithets of VICIOUS or ODIOUS or DEPRAVED, he then speaks another language, and expresses sentiments, in which he expects all his audience are to concur with him. He must here, therefore, depart from his private and particular situation, and must choose a point of view, common to him with others; he must move some universal principle of the human frame, and touch a string to which all mankind have an accord and symphony. If he mean, therefore, to express that this man possesses qualities, whose tendency is pernicious to society, he has chosen this common point of view, and has touched the principle of humanity, in which every man, in some degree, concurs. While the human heart is compounded of the same elements as at present, it will never be wholly indifferent to public good, nor entirely unaffected with the tendency of characters and manners. And though this affection of humanity may not generally be esteemed so strong as vanity or ambition, yet, being common to all men, it can alone be the foundation of morals, or of any-general system of blame or praise. One man's ambition is not another's ambition, nor will the same event or object satisfy both; but the humanity of one man is the humanity of every one, and the same object touches this passion in all human creatures.

When a man calls another his ENEMY, RIVAL, ANTAGONIST, or ADVERSARY, it's clear he's speaking from a place of self-interest, sharing feelings that are uniquely his, shaped by his own experiences and circumstances. However, when he labels someone as VICIOUS, ODIOUS, or DEPRAVED, he switches to a different tone and conveys feelings that he expects everyone to agree with. In this case, he has to step outside his individual point of view and find a perspective that he shares with others; he must appeal to some universal aspect of human nature and strike a chord that resonates with everyone. If he intends to convey that this person has qualities harmful to society, he has indeed found this common perspective and connected with a principle of humanity that everyone can relate to. As long as human nature remains the same as it is now, people will never be completely indifferent to the common good or unaffected by the influences of character and behavior. While this concern for humanity may not always be as powerful as vanity or ambition, it is something all humans share, and it serves as the basis for morality and any widespread system of judgment or appreciation. One person’s ambition isn’t the same as another’s, and the same situation won’t satisfy everyone; but the humanity of one person reflects the humanity of all, and the same issues resonate with this shared feeling in every human being.

But the sentiments, which arise from humanity, are not only the same in all human creatures, and produce the same approbation or censure; but they also comprehend all human creatures; nor is there any one whose conduct or character is not, by their means, an object to every one of censure or approbation. On the contrary, those other passions, commonly denominated selfish, both produce different sentiments in each individual, according to his particular situation; and also contemplate the greater part of mankind with the utmost indifference and unconcern. Whoever has a high regard and esteem for me flatters my vanity; whoever expresses contempt mortifies and displeases me; but as my name is known but to a small part of mankind, there are few who come within the sphere of this passion, or excite, on its account, either my affection or disgust. But if you represent a tyrannical, insolent, or barbarous behaviour, in any country or in any age of the world, I soon carry my eye to the pernicious tendency of such a conduct, and feel the sentiment of repugnance and displeasure towards it. No character can be so remote as to be, in this light, wholly indifferent to me. What is beneficial to society or to the person himself must still be preferred. And every quality or action, of every human being, must, by this means, be ranked under some class or denomination, expressive of general censure or applause.

But the feelings that come from being human are not only the same for all people, resulting in the same approval or disapproval; they also include all humanity. There's no one whose behavior or character doesn't become a subject of approval or disapproval through these feelings. In contrast, other emotions, often called selfish, create different feelings in each person based on their specific situation, and they mostly disregard most of mankind with indifference. If someone holds me in high regard, it flatters my ego; if someone shows contempt, it hurts and annoys me. However, since my name is known only to a small part of the population, few people trigger this emotion in me, whether positively or negatively. But if you depict tyrannical, arrogant, or cruel behavior in any country or throughout any era, I quickly recognize the harmful nature of such actions and feel disgust and displeasure towards them. No character can be so distant that it doesn't matter to me in this context. What benefits society or the individual must always be favored. Therefore, every quality or action of every person must be categorized in some way that reflects either general criticism or praise.

What more, therefore, can we ask to distinguish the sentiments, dependent on humanity, from those connected with any other passion, or to satisfy us, why the former are the origin of morals, not the latter? Whatever conduct gains my approbation, by touching my humanity, procures also the applause of all mankind, by affecting the same principle in them; but what serves my avarice or ambition pleases these passions in me alone, and affects not the avarice and ambition of the rest of mankind. There is no circumstance of conduct in any man, provided it have a beneficial tendency, that is not agreeable to my humanity, however remote the person; but every man, so far removed as neither to cross nor serve my avarice and ambition, is regarded as wholly indifferent by those passions. The distinction, therefore, between these species of sentiment being so great and evident, language must soon be moulded upon it, and must invent a peculiar set of terms, in order to express those universal sentiments of censure or approbation, which arise from humanity, or from views of general usefulness and its contrary. Virtue and Vice become then known; morals are recognized; certain general ideas are framed of human conduct and behaviour; such measures are expected from men in such situations. This action is determined to be conformable to our abstract rule; that other, contrary. And by such universal principles are the particular sentiments of self-love frequently controlled and limited.

What more can we ask to distinguish feelings that depend on our humanity from those linked to any other passion? Why are the former the source of morals and not the latter? Any behavior that earns my approval because it touches my humanity also gets the approval of everyone else by appealing to the same principle in them. However, actions that fulfill my greed or ambition only please those passions in me and don't resonate with the greed and ambition of others. There’s no behavior in anyone that has a positive effect, no matter how distant the person is, that doesn’t agree with my humanity. Yet, any person who is so far removed that they neither contribute to nor hinder my greed and ambition is seen as completely irrelevant by those passions. The distinction between these types of feelings is so significant and clear that language must naturally evolve to reflect it, creating a unique set of terms to express those universal feelings of approval or disapproval that come from humanity or from considerations of general usefulness and its opposite. Virtue and vice then become recognized; morals are acknowledged; certain general ideas about human behavior are developed; expectations are set for how people should act in specific situations. One action is deemed consistent with our abstract moral code, while another is seen as contrary. Through these universal principles, the specific feelings of self-interest are often checked and limited.

     [Footnote: It seems certain, both from reason and experience,
that a rude, untaught savage regulates chiefly his love and hatred by
the ideas of private utility and injury, and has but faint conceptions
of a general rule or system of behaviour. The man who stands opposite
to him in battle, he hates heartedly, not only for the present moment,
which is almost unavoidable, but for ever after; nor is he satisfied
without the most extreme punishment and vengeance. But we, accustomed
to society, and to more enlarged reflections, consider, that this man
is serving his own country and community; that any man, in the same
situation, would do the same; that we ourselves, in like circumstances,
observe a like conduct; that; in general, human society is best
supported on such maxims: and by these suppositions and views, we
correct, in some measure, our ruder and narrower positions. And though
much of our friendship and enemity be still regulated by private
considerations of benefit and harm, we pay, at least, this homage to
general rules, which we are accustomed to respect, that we commonly
perver our adversary's conduct, by imputing malice or injustice to him,
in order to give vent to those passions, which arise from self-love
and private interest. When the heart is full of rage, it never wants
pretences of this nature; though sometimes as frivolous, as those from
which Horace, being almost crushed by the fall of a tree, effects to
accuse of parricide the first planter of it.]
[Footnote: It seems clear, both from reason and experience, that a rough, untrained savage primarily bases his feelings of love and hate on personal gain or harm, and has only a vague understanding of any general rules or systems of behavior. The person he faces in battle is someone he hates deeply, not just for the moment, which is almost unavoidable, but for all time afterward; he won't be satisfied without the harshest punishment and revenge. In contrast, we, who are used to society and broader reflections, recognize that this person is serving his own country and community; that anyone in the same situation would act similarly; that we ourselves would behave the same way in similar circumstances; and that, in general, human society functions best on these principles. By considering these viewpoints, we somewhat adjust our more primitive and narrow perspectives. Although much of our friendship and enmity is still driven by personal considerations of benefit and harm, we do at least show some respect for the general rules we have come to recognize, often viewing our opponent's actions as malicious or unjust to justify the emotions that stem from self-interest. When anger fills the heart, it readily finds reasons like these, even if they are as trivial as those from which Horace, nearly crushed by a falling tree, pretended to blame its first planter for murder.]

From instances of popular tumults, seditions, factions, panics, and of all passions, which are shared with a multitude, we may learn the influence of society in exciting and supporting any emotion; while the most ungovernable disorders are raised, we find, by that means, from the slightest and most frivolous occasions. Solon was no very cruel, though, perhaps, an unjust legislator, who punished neuters in civil wars; and few, I believe, would, in such cases, incur the penalty, were their affection and discourse allowed sufficient to absolve them. No selfishness, and scarce any philosophy, have there force sufficient to support a total coolness and indifference; and he must be more or less than man, who kindles not in the common blaze. What wonder then, that moral sentiments are found of such influence in life; though springing from principles, which may appear, at first sight, somewhat small and delicate? But these principles, we must remark, are social and universal; they form, in a manner, the PARTY of humankind against vice or disorder, its common enemy. And as the benevolent concern for others is diffused, in a greater or less degree, over all men, and is the same in all, it occurs more frequently in discourse, is cherished by society and conversation, and the blame and approbation, consequent on it, are thereby roused from that lethargy into which they are probably lulled, in solitary and uncultivated nature. Other passions, though perhaps originally stronger, yet being selfish and private, are often overpowered by its force, and yield the dominion of our breast to those social and public principles.

From examples of popular unrest, rebellions, factions, panics, and shared emotions, we can see how society can stir up and support any feeling; often the most uncontrollable chaos arises from the smallest and most trivial events. Solon wasn't particularly cruel, though he might have been an unjust lawmaker, punishing those who remained neutral during civil wars. I believe few would face such punishment if their feelings and words were openly expressed enough for them to be excused. No amount of selfishness or even philosophy can fully maintain complete detachment and indifference; a person must be more than human if they don't ignite in the shared fervor. So, it’s no surprise that moral feelings hold such power in life, even if they stem from ideas that may initially seem small and fragile. However, we must note that these ideas are social and universal; they form, in a way, the collective stance of humanity against vice or disorder, its common enemy. As the instinct to care for others spreads more or less among all people, and is consistent in everyone, it emerges more often in conversation, is supported by society, and the praise and blame that come from it are stirred from the lethargy into which they might otherwise fall in solitude and untamed nature. Other emotions, although possibly stronger at first, being selfish and private, are often overcome by this force, yielding control of our hearts to these social and public principles.

Another spring of our constitution, that brings a great addition of force to moral sentiments, is the love of fame; which rules, with such uncontrolled authority, in all generous minds, and is often the grand object of all their designs and undertakings. By our continual and earnest pursuit of a character, a name, a reputation in the world, we bring our own deportment and conduct frequently in review, and consider how they appear in the eyes of those who approach and regard us. This constant habit of surveying ourselves, as it were, in reflection, keeps alive all the sentiments of right and wrong, and begets, in noble natures, a certain reverence for themselves as well as others, which is the surest guardian of every virtue. The animal conveniencies and pleasures sink gradually in their value; while every inward beauty and moral grace is studiously acquired, and the mind is accomplished in every perfection, which can adorn or embellish a rational creature.

Another important aspect of our nature that adds strength to our moral feelings is the desire for fame. This drive holds a powerful influence over all generous individuals and often becomes the main goal of their plans and efforts. As we continuously and earnestly seek a good character, a name, and a reputation in the world, we regularly assess our behavior and actions and think about how they come across to those around us. This ongoing practice of reflecting on ourselves keeps our sense of right and wrong alive and fosters a sense of respect for ourselves and others among noble individuals, which is the best safeguard for all virtues. The basic comforts and pleasures of life gradually lose their importance, while every inner quality and moral grace is carefully developed, and the mind strives for every perfection that can enhance or beautify a rational being.

Here is the most perfect morality with which we are acquainted: here is displayed the force of many sympathies. Our moral sentiment is itself a feeling chiefly of that nature, and our regard to a character with others seems to arise only from a care of preserving a character with ourselves; and in order to attain this end, we find it necessary to prop our tottering judgement on the correspondent approbation of mankind.

Here’s the most perfect morality we know: it shows the strength of many sympathies. Our moral sense is mainly a feeling of this kind, and our concern for a character in relation to others seems to come from a desire to maintain our own character. To achieve this, we often feel the need to lean on the approval of others to support our shaky judgment.

But, that we may accommodate matters, and remove if possible every difficulty, let us allow all these reasonings to be false. Let us allow that, when we resolve the pleasure, which arises from views of utility, into the sentiments of humanity and sympathy, we have embraced a wrong hypothesis. Let us confess it necessary to find some other explication of that applause, which is paid to objects, whether inanimate, animate, or rational, if they have a tendency to promote the welfare and advantage of mankind. However difficult it be to conceive that an object is approved of on account of its tendency to a certain end, while the end itself is totally indifferent: let us swallow this absurdity, and consider what are the consequences. The preceding delineation or definition of Personal Merit must still retain its evidence and authority: it must still be allowed that every quality of the mind, which is USEFUL or AGREEABLE to the PERSON HIMSELF or to OTHERS, communicates a pleasure to the spectator, engages his esteem, and is admitted under the honourable denomination of virtue or merit. Are not justice, fidelity, honour, veracity, allegiance, chastity, esteemed solely on account of their tendency to promote the good of society? Is not that tendency inseparable from humanity, benevolence, lenity, generosity, gratitude, moderation, tenderness, friendship, and all the other social virtues? Can it possibly be doubted that industry, discretion, frugality, secrecy, order, perseverance, forethought, judgement, and this whole class of virtues and accomplishments, of which many pages would not contain the catalogue; can it be doubted, I say, that the tendency of these qualities to promote the interest and happiness of their possessor, is the sole foundation of their merit? Who can dispute that a mind, which supports a perpetual serenity and cheerfulness, a noble dignity and undaunted spirit, a tender affection and good-will to all around; as it has more enjoyment within itself, is also a more animating and rejoicing spectacle, than if dejected with melancholy, tormented with anxiety, irritated with rage, or sunk into the most abject baseness and degeneracy? And as to the qualities, immediately AGREEABLE to OTHERS, they speak sufficiently for themselves; and he must be unhappy, indeed, either in his own temper, or in his situation and company, who has never perceived the charms of a facetious wit or flowing affability, of a delicate modesty or decent genteelness of address and manner.

But to make things easier and try to eliminate any difficulties, let’s assume all these arguments are incorrect. Let’s assume that when we break down the pleasure derived from utility into feelings of humanity and sympathy, we’ve adopted a flawed idea. Let’s admit that we need to find another explanation for the admiration given to objects—whether they are inanimate, living, or rational—if they tend to enhance the welfare and benefit of humanity. Even if it’s hard to understand how something can be valued purely for its ability to achieve an outcome while being indifferent to that outcome itself, let’s accept this oddity and examine its implications. The earlier definition of Personal Merit should still hold its validity and significance: it must still be recognized that any quality of the mind that is USEFUL or PLEASANT to the PERSON THEMSELF or to OTHERS brings joy to the observer, earns their respect, and is categorized as virtue or merit. Isn’t justice, loyalty, honor, truthfulness, fidelity, and chastity valued primarily for their ability to benefit society? Isn’t that benefit intrinsically linked to humanity, kindness, compassion, generosity, gratitude, moderation, tenderness, friendship, and all other social virtues? Can anyone really doubt that qualities like hard work, wisdom, thrift, discretion, organization, persistence, foresight, judgment, and a whole range of virtues and skills—too many to list comprehensively—are deemed valuable simply because they further the interests and happiness of their owner? Who can argue that a mind that maintains constant serenity and cheerfulness, with noble dignity and courageous spirit, along with warm affection and goodwill toward everyone, is far more pleasurable to be around than one that is burdened by sadness, filled with anxiety, stirred by anger, or dragged down into misery and degradation? Regarding qualities that are directly PLEASANT to OTHERS, they speak for themselves; one must be truly unfortunate—either in their character or in their circumstances—if they’ve never noticed the appeal of a witty personality or friendly charm, of gentle modesty, or polite and pleasing manners.

I am sensible, that nothing can be more unphilosophical than to be positive or dogmatical on any subject; and that, even if excessive scepticism could be maintained, it would not be more destructive to all just reasoning and inquiry. I am convinced that, where men are the most sure and arrogant, they are commonly the most mistaken, and have there given reins to passion, without that proper deliberation and suspense, which can alone secure them from the grossest absurdities. Yet, I must confess, that this enumeration puts the matter in so strong a light, that I cannot, at PRESENT, be more assured of any truth, which I learn from reasoning and argument, than that personal merit consists entirely in the usefulness or agreeableness of qualities to the person himself possessed of them, or to others, who have any intercourse with him. But when I reflect that, though the bulk and figure of the earth have been measured and delineated, though the motions of the tides have been accounted for, the order and economy of the heavenly bodies subjected to their proper laws, and Infinite itself reduced to calculation; yet men still dispute concerning the foundation of their moral duties. When I reflect on this, I say, I fall back into diffidence and scepticism, and suspect that an hypothesis, so obvious, had it been a true one, would, long ere now, have been received by the unanimous suffrage and consent of mankind.

I'm aware that nothing is less philosophical than being certain or dogmatic about any topic; and that even if extreme skepticism could be maintained, it wouldn't be more destructive to good reasoning and inquiry. I'm convinced that where people are the most confident and arrogant, they are usually the most wrong and have let their passions take over, without the proper thoughtfulness and hesitation needed to protect them from the greatest absurdities. However, I must admit that this discussion makes things so clear that I can't, at THIS MOMENT, be more certain about any truth gained from reasoning and argument than the fact that personal merit is entirely based on the usefulness or likability of qualities to the person who possesses them, or to others who interact with them. But when I think that, despite having measured and mapped the size and shape of the earth, accounted for the movements of the tides, established the order and laws governing the heavenly bodies, and even calculated the Infinite; men still argue about the foundations of their moral duties. When I reflect on this, I find myself returning to doubt and skepticism, and I suspect that a hypothesis so apparent, if it were true, would have been accepted long ago by the unanimous agreement of humanity.





PART II.

Having explained the moral APPROBATION attending merit or virtue, there remains nothing but briefly to consider our interested OBLIGATION to it, and to inquire whether every man, who has any regard to his own happiness and welfare, will not best find his account in the practice of every moral duty. If this can be clearly ascertained from the foregoing theory, we shall have the satisfaction to reflect, that we have advanced principles, which not only, it is hoped, will stand the test of reasoning and inquiry, but may contribute to the amendment of men's lives, and their improvement in morality and social virtue. And though the philosophical truth of any proposition by no means depends on its tendency to promote the interests of society; yet a man has but a bad grace, who delivers a theory, however true, which, he must confess, leads to a practice dangerous and pernicious. Why rake into those corners of nature which spread a nuisance all around? Why dig up the pestilence from the pit in which it is buried? The ingenuity of your researches may be admired, but your systems will be detested; and mankind will agree, if they cannot refute them, to sink them, at least, in eternal silence and oblivion. Truths which are pernicious to society, if any such there be, will yield to errors which are salutary and ADVANTAGEOUS.

Having explained the moral approval that comes with merit or virtue, we now need to briefly consider our personal obligation to it and explore whether anyone who cares about their own happiness and well-being will find it most beneficial to practice every moral duty. If we can clearly determine this from the previous theory, we can take satisfaction in knowing that we have proposed principles that, we hope, will withstand reasoning and scrutiny, and may even help improve people's lives and enhance their morality and social virtue. While the philosophical truth of any idea doesn't depend on its ability to benefit society, it's not a good look for someone to present a theory, no matter how true, that they admit leads to harmful and dangerous practices. Why delve into those dark corners of nature that spread harm all around? Why unearth the disease from the pit where it lies buried? Your clever research may be admired, but your ideas will be hated; and people will agree, if they can't disprove them, to bury them in eternal silence and forgetfulness. Truths that are harmful to society, if they exist, will yield to errors that are beneficial and advantageous.

But what philosophical truths can be more advantageous to society, than those here delivered, which represent virtue in all her genuine and most engaging charms, and makes us approach her with ease, familiarity, and affection? The dismal dress falls off, with which many divines, and some philosophers, have covered her; and nothing appears but gentleness, humanity, beneficence, affability; nay, even at proper intervals, play, frolic, and gaiety. She talks not of useless austerities and rigours, suffering and self-denial. She declares that her sole purpose is to make her votaries and all mankind, during every instant of their existence, if possible, cheerful and happy; nor does she ever willingly part with any pleasure but in hopes of ample compensation in some other period of their lives. The sole trouble which she demands, is that of just calculation, and a steady preference of the greater happiness. And if any austere pretenders approach her, enemies to joy and pleasure, she either rejects them as hypocrites and deceivers; or, if she admit them in her train, they are ranked, however, among the least favoured of her votaries.

But what philosophical truths could benefit society more than the ones presented here, which show virtue in all her true and most captivating forms and allow us to connect with her easily, comfortably, and warmly? The gloomy facade that many religious figures and some philosophers have draped over her falls away, revealing only kindness, humanity, generosity, and friendliness; indeed, at the right moments, playfulness, fun, and joy. She doesn’t talk about pointless strictness and hardships, suffering, or self-denial. She states that her only goal is to make her followers and all of humanity, at every moment of their lives, as cheerful and happy as possible; she never willingly gives up any joy without expecting to gain something better at another time in their lives. The only effort she asks for is careful consideration and a consistent focus on the greater happiness. And if any strict pretenders come near her, those who oppose joy and pleasure, she either dismisses them as hypocrites and frauds, or, if she does allow them to follow, they are considered among the least favored of her followers.

And, indeed, to drop all figurative expression, what hopes can we ever have of engaging mankind to a practice which we confess full of austerity and rigour? Or what theory of morals can ever serve any useful purpose, unless it can show, by a particular detail, that all the duties which it recommends, are also the true interest of each individual? The peculiar advantage of the foregoing system seems to be, that it furnishes proper mediums for that purpose.

And honestly, to put it plainly, what hopes do we have of getting people to adopt a practice that we admit is strict and severe? Or what moral theory can really be useful unless it can demonstrate, in detail, that all the duties it promotes are also in the best interest of each individual? The unique benefit of the system mentioned earlier seems to be that it provides the right tools for that purpose.

That the virtues which are immediately USEFUL or AGREEABLE to the person possessed of them, are desirable in a view to self-interest, it would surely be superfluous to prove. Moralists, indeed, may spare themselves all the pains which they often take in recommending these duties. To what purpose collect arguments to evince that temperance is advantageous, and the excesses of pleasure hurtful, when it appears that these excesses are only denominated such, because they are hurtful; and that, if the unlimited use of strong liquors, for instance, no more impaired health or the faculties of mind and body than the use of air or water, it would not be a whit more vicious or blameable?

It's obviously unnecessary to prove that the virtues that are directly useful or pleasing to someone are appealing in terms of self-interest. Moralists can save themselves the effort they often put into promoting these duties. Why gather arguments to show that moderation is beneficial and that overindulgence is harmful, when it's clear that these excesses are labeled as such simply because they're damaging? If, for example, the unrestricted consumption of strong drinks didn't impair health or mental and physical abilities any more than air or water, it wouldn't be considered any more immoral or blameworthy.

It seems equally superfluous to prove, that the COMPANIONABLE virtues of good manners and wit, decency and genteelness, are more desirable than the contrary qualities. Vanity alone, without any other consideration, is a sufficient motive to make us wish for the possession of these accomplishments. No man was ever willingly deficient in this particular. All our failures here proceed from bad education, want of capacity, or a perverse and unpliable disposition. Would you have your company coveted, admired, followed; rather than hated, despised, avoided? Can any one seriously deliberate in the case? As no enjoyment is sincere, without some reference to company and society; so no society can be agreeable, or even tolerable, where a man feels his presence unwelcome, and discovers all around him symptoms of disgust and aversion.

It seems pointless to prove that the friendly virtues of good manners and wit, decency and sophistication, are more desirable than their opposites. Vanity alone, without any other reason, is enough to make us want these qualities. No one willingly lacks them. Our shortcomings in this area come from poor upbringing, a lack of ability, or a stubborn and unyielding nature. Would you prefer your company to be desired, admired, and sought after, rather than hated, looked down upon, and avoided? Can anyone seriously think about this? Just as no enjoyment is genuine without some connection to friends and community, no social setting can be pleasant, or even bearable, if someone feels unwelcome and senses disgust and aversion from those around them.

But why, in the greater society or confederacy of mankind, should not the case be the same as in particular clubs and companies? Why is it more doubtful, that the enlarged virtues of humanity, generosity, beneficence, are desirable with a view of happiness and self-interest, than the limited endowments of ingenuity and politeness? Are we apprehensive lest those social affections interfere, in a greater and more immediate degree than any other pursuits, with private utility, and cannot be gratified, without some important sacrifice of honour and advantage? If so, we are but ill-instructed in the nature of the human passions, and are more influenced by verbal distinctions than by real differences.

But why, in the larger society or community of people, shouldn't it be the same as in specific clubs and organizations? Why is it more uncertain that the broader virtues of humanity, like generosity and kindness, are desirable for happiness and self-interest than the limited qualities of cleverness and politeness? Are we worried that these social feelings interfere, to a greater and more immediate extent than any other pursuits, with personal benefits, and that they can't be fulfilled without a significant sacrifice of honor and advantage? If that’s the case, we’re not well-informed about the nature of human emotions and are more swayed by words than by actual differences.

Whatever contradiction may vulgarly be supposed between the SELFISH and SOCIAL sentiments or dispositions, they are really no more opposite than selfish and ambitious, selfish and revengeful, selfish and vain. It is requisite that there be an original propensity of some kind, in order to be a basis to self-love, by giving a relish to the objects of its pursuit; and none more fit for this purpose than benevolence or humanity. The goods of fortune are spent in one gratification or another: the miser who accumulates his annual income, and lends it out at interest, has really spent it in the gratification of his avarice. And it would be difficult to show why a man is more a loser by a generous action, than by any other method of expense; since the utmost which he can attain by the most elaborate selfishness, is the indulgence of some affection.

Whatever contradiction people commonly think exists between selfish and social feelings or behaviors, they’re really not more opposed than being selfish and ambitious, selfish and vengeful, or selfish and vain. There has to be some kind of original tendency to serve as the foundation for self-love, which gives satisfaction to the objects of its pursuit; and nothing is more suitable for this than kindness or humanity. The benefits of wealth are spent on one pleasure or another: the miser who accumulates his yearly income and lends it out for interest is actually spending it on satisfying his greed. It would also be hard to explain why a person is more at a loss from a generous act than from any other way of spending; since the most he can gain from extreme selfishness is the gratification of some desire.

Now if life, without passion, must be altogether insipid and tiresome; let a man suppose that he has full power of modelling his own disposition, and let him deliberate what appetite or desire he would choose for the foundation of his happiness and enjoyment. Every affection, he would observe, when gratified by success, gives a satisfaction proportioned to its force and violence; but besides this advantage, common to all, the immediate feeling of benevolence and friendship, humanity and kindness, is sweet, smooth, tender, and agreeable, independent of all fortune and accidents. These virtues are besides attended with a pleasing consciousness or remembrance, and keep us in humour with ourselves as well as others; while we retain the agreeable reflection of having done our part towards mankind and society. And though all men show a jealousy of our success in the pursuits of avarice and ambition; yet are we almost sure of their good-will and good wishes, so long as we persevere in the paths of virtue, and employ ourselves in the execution of generous plans and purposes. What other passion is there where we shall find so many advantages united; an agreeable sentiment, a pleasing consciousness, a good reputation? But of these truths, we may observe, men are, of themselves, pretty much convinced; nor are they deficient in their duty to society, because they would not wish to be generous, friendly, and humane; but because they do not feel themselves such.

Now, if life without passion is completely dull and exhausting, let a person imagine they have the full ability to shape their own character and think about what desires or ambitions they would pick as the basis for their happiness and enjoyment. They would notice that every feeling, when fulfilled by success, brings satisfaction that matches its intensity and strength; but beyond that shared benefit, the immediate sensation of kindness, friendship, and compassion is sweet, smooth, gentle, and pleasant, unaffected by circumstances. These virtues also come with a nice sense of awareness or memory that keeps us in good spirits with ourselves and others. We enjoy the comforting thought of having contributed to humanity and society. While everyone tends to envy our success in the chase for wealth and power, we are almost guaranteed their kind feelings and good wishes as long as we continue on the path of virtue and dedicate ourselves to noble plans and goals. What other passion offers so many combined benefits—an enjoyable feeling, a satisfying awareness, a good reputation? Yet, we can see that people are generally convinced of these truths; they aren’t neglecting their duty to society because they don’t want to be generous, friendly, and compassionate, but because they don’t see themselves that way.

Treating vice with the greatest candour, and making it all possible concessions, we must acknowledge that there is not, in any instance, the smallest pretext for giving it the preference above virtue, with a view of self-interest; except, perhaps, in the case of justice, where a man, taking things in a certain light, may often seem to be a loser by his integrity. And though it is allowed that, without a regard to property, no society could subsist; yet according to the imperfect way in which human affairs are conducted, a sensible knave, in particular incidents, may think that an act of iniquity or infidelity will make a considerable addition to his fortune, without causing any considerable breach in the social union and confederacy. That HONESTY IS THE BEST POLICY, may be a good general rule, but is liable to many exceptions; and he, it may perhaps be thought, conducts himself with most wisdom, who observes the general rule, and takes advantage of all the exceptions. I must confess that, if a man think that this reasoning much requires an answer, it would be a little difficult to find any which will to him appear satisfactory and convincing. If his heart rebel not against such pernicious maxims, if he feel no reluctance to the thoughts of villainy or baseness, he has indeed lost a considerable motive to virtue; and we may expect that this practice will be answerable to his speculation. But in all ingenuous natures, the antipathy to treachery and roguery is too strong to be counter-balanced by any views of profit or pecuniary advantage. Inward peace of mind, consciousness of integrity, a satisfactory review of our own conduct; these are circumstances, very requisite to happiness, and will be cherished and cultivated by every honest man, who feels the importance of them.

Addressing vice honestly and making all possible concessions, we have to admit that there’s never a valid reason to favor it over virtue for the sake of self-interest—except maybe in the case of justice, where a person may feel like they are losing out by being honorable. While it's true that no society could survive without regard for property, a savvy cheat might believe that committing a wrong or betraying trust could significantly boost their wealth without seriously disrupting social ties. The saying that HONESTY IS THE BEST POLICY might be a good general rule, but it has many exceptions; someone might argue that the wisest approach is to follow the general rule while taking advantage of the exceptions. I must admit, if someone thinks this reasoning needs a rebuttal, it would be quite challenging to find one that seems satisfying or convincing to them. If their conscience doesn't rebel against these harmful ideas, and they feel no hesitation about thinking of dishonesty, they have lost a significant motivation for being virtuous, and we can expect their actions will reflect their mindset. But in all honorable people, the strong aversion to deceit and trickery outweighs any profit or financial gain they might foresee. Inner peace, a clear conscience, and a satisfying reflection on our own actions are essential for happiness and will be valued and nurtured by every honest person who understands their importance.

Such a one has, besides, the frequent satisfaction of seeing knaves, with all their pretended cunning and abilities, betrayed by their own maxims; and while they purpose to cheat with moderation and secrecy, a tempting incident occurs, nature is frail, and they give into the snare; whence they can never extricate themselves, without a total loss of reputation, and the forfeiture of all future trust and confidence with mankind.

Such a person often finds satisfaction in watching con artists, with all their fake cleverness and skills, get caught by their own principles. While they plan to cheat carefully and keep it under wraps, a tempting situation arises, and human nature is weak, leading them to fall into the trap. Once that happens, they can never escape without completely losing their reputation and forfeiting all future trust and confidence from others.

But were they ever so secret and successful, the honest man, if he has any tincture of philosophy, or even common observation and reflection, will discover that they themselves are, in the end, the greatest dupes, and have sacrificed the invaluable enjoyment of a character, with themselves at least, for the acquisition of worthless toys and gewgaws. How little is requisite to supply the necessities of nature? And in a view to pleasure, what comparison between the unbought satisfaction of conversation, society, study, even health and the common beauties of nature, but above all the peaceful reflection on one's own conduct; what comparison, I say, between these and the feverish, empty amusements of luxury and expense? These natural pleasures, indeed, are really without price; both because they are below all price in their attainment, and above it in their enjoyment.

But no matter how secretive and successful they may be, a genuinely honest person, if they have even a hint of philosophy or just some basic observation and reflection, will realize that they are, in the end, the biggest fools. They’ve sacrificed the priceless joy of a good character, at least to themselves, for the sake of worthless trinkets and flashy items. How little is needed to cover the essentials of life? And when it comes to pleasure, how can you compare the unbought joy of conversation, companionship, study, even health and the simple beauties of nature, especially the calm reflection on one's own actions; what comparison exists between these and the restless, hollow pleasures of luxury and extravagance? These natural pleasures are truly priceless; they are both easily attained and rich in enjoyment.





APPENDIX I. CONCERNING MORAL SENTIMENT

IF the foregoing hypothesis be received, it will now be easy for us to determine the question first started, [FOOTNOTE: Sect. 1.] concerning the general principles of morals; and though we postponed the decision of that question, lest it should then involve us in intricate speculations, which are unfit for moral discourses, we may resume it at present, and examine how far either REASON or SENTIMENT enters into all decisions of praise or censure.

IF the previous hypothesis is accepted, it will now be simple for us to address the question we initially raised, [FOOTNOTE: Sect. 1.] concerning the overall principles of morality; and although we delayed answering that question to avoid getting caught up in complex theories that aren't suitable for discussions about morality, we can take it up again now and explore to what extent either REASON or SENTIMENT influences all judgments of approval or disapproval.

One principal foundation of moral praise being supposed to lie in the usefulness of any quality or action, it is evident that REASON must enter for a considerable share in all decisions of this kind; since nothing but that faculty can instruct us in the tendency of qualities and actions, and point out their beneficial consequences to society and to their possessor. In many cases this is an affair liable to great controversy: doubts may arise; opposite interests may occur; and a preference must be given to one side, from very nice views, and a small overbalance of utility. This is particularly remarkable in questions with regard to justice; as is, indeed, natural to suppose, from that species of utility which attends this virtue [Footnote: See App. II.]. Were every single instance of justice, like that of benevolence, useful to society; this would be a more simple state of the case, and seldom liable to great controversy. But as single instances of justice are often pernicious in their first and immediate tendency, and as the advantage to society results only from the observance of the general rule, and from the concurrence and combination of several persons in the same equitable conduct; the case here becomes more intricate and involved. The various circumstances of society; the various consequences of any practice; the various interests which may be proposed; these, on many occasions, are doubtful, and subject to great discussion and inquiry. The object of municipal laws is to fix all the questions with regard to justice: the debates of civilians; the reflections of politicians; the precedents of history and public records, are all directed to the same purpose. And a very accurate REASON or JUDGEMENT is often requisite, to give the true determination, amidst such intricate doubts arising from obscure or opposite utilities.

One main foundation of moral praise is believed to be the usefulness of any quality or action. It's clear that REASON must play a significant role in all decisions of this nature since only that ability can guide us in understanding the effects of qualities and actions and highlight their benefits to society and the individual. In many situations, this can be quite controversial: doubts may arise, conflicting interests may appear, and a preference must be given to one side based on careful considerations and a slight edge in utility. This is especially evident in discussions about justice, which is natural considering the type of utility associated with this virtue [Footnote: See App. II.]. If every instance of justice were as useful to society as acts of kindness, the situation would be simpler and less prone to major disputes. However, because individual acts of justice can often have harmful immediate effects, and the benefits to society stem only from following general rules and the cooperation of multiple people in the same fair behavior, the situation becomes more complex. The different circumstances of society, the varying outcomes of any practice, and the various interests at stake can often lead to uncertainty and significant debate. The purpose of municipal laws is to clarify all questions related to justice: the discussions among legal experts, the considerations of politicians, and historical precedents all serve this aim. A very precise REASON or JUDGMENT is often necessary to arrive at the correct decision amidst the intricate doubts created by unclear or conflicting utilities.

But though reason, when fully assisted and improved, be sufficient to instruct us in the pernicious or useful tendency of qualities and actions; it is not alone sufficient to produce any moral blame or approbation. Utility is only a tendency to a certain end; and were the end totally indifferent to us, we should feel the same indifference towards the means. It is requisite a SENTIMENT should here display itself, in order to give a preference to the useful above the pernicious tendencies. This SENTIMENT can be no other than a feeling for the happiness of mankind, and a resentment of their misery; since these are the different ends which virtue and vice have a tendency to promote. Here therefore REASON instructs us in the several tendencies of actions, and HUMANITY makes a distinction in favour of those which are useful and beneficial.

But while reason, when fully developed and enhanced, is enough to teach us about the harmful or helpful nature of qualities and actions, it isn't enough on its own to create any moral judgment or approval. Utility is merely a pathway to a certain outcome; if that outcome didn't matter to us at all, we would feel the same way about the means. It’s necessary for a SENTIMENT to emerge here in order to value the useful over the harmful tendencies. This SENTIMENT must be a concern for the happiness of humanity and a dislike for their suffering, as these are the different outcomes that virtue and vice aim to promote. Therefore, REASON guides us in understanding the various outcomes of actions, while HUMANITY helps us differentiate in favor of those that are helpful and beneficial.

This partition between the faculties of understanding and sentiment, in all moral decisions, seems clear from the preceding hypothesis. But I shall suppose that hypothesis false: it will then be requisite to look out for some other theory that may be satisfactory; and I dare venture to affirm that none such will ever be found, so long as we suppose reason to be the sole source of morals. To prove this, it will be proper t o weigh the five following considerations.

This separation between the faculties of understanding and emotion in all moral decisions seems clear from the earlier hypothesis. However, I'll assume that hypothesis is incorrect: it'll then be necessary to search for some other theory that might be satisfactory; and I confidently assert that none will ever be found as long as we believe reason is the only source of morality. To demonstrate this, it will be appropriate to consider the following five points.

I. It is easy for a false hypothesis to maintain some appearance of truth, while it keeps wholly in generals, makes use of undefined terms, and employs comparisons, instead of instances. This is particularly remarkable in that philosophy, which ascribes the discernment of all moral distinctions to reason alone, without the concurrence of sentiment. It is impossible that, in any particular instance, this hypothesis can so much as be rendered intelligible, whatever specious figure it may make in general declamations and discourses. Examine the crime of INGRATITUDE, for instance; which has place, wherever we observe good-will, expressed and known, together with good-offices performed, on the one side, and a return of ill-will or indifference, with ill-offices or neglect on the other: anatomize all these circumstances, and examine, by your reason alone, in what consists the demerit or blame. You never will come to any issue or conclusion.

I. It’s easy for a false argument to seem true as long as it stays vague, uses unclear terms, and relies on comparisons instead of specific examples. This is especially evident in the philosophy that claims all moral distinctions come from reason alone, without any input from feelings. In any specific case, this argument can’t really be understood, no matter how convincing it may sound in general discussions. Take the crime of INGRATITUDE, for example; it occurs whenever we see goodwill expressed and recognized, along with helpful actions on one side, and a response of ill-will or indifference, with neglect or harmful actions on the other. Break down these circumstances and try to understand, using only your reason, where the blame or fault lies. You’ll never reach a clear conclusion.

Reason judges either of MATTER OF FACT or of RELATIONS. Enquire then, first, where is that matter of fact which we here call crime; point it out; determine the time of its existence; describe its essence or nature; explain the sense or faculty to which it discovers itself. It resides in the mind of the person who is ungrateful. He must, therefore, feel it, and be conscious of it. But nothing is there, except the passion of ill-will or absolute indifference. You cannot say that these, of themselves, always, and in all circumstances, are crimes. No, they are only crimes when directed towards persons who have before expressed and displayed good-will towards us. Consequently, we may infer, that the crime of ingratitude is not any particular individual FACT; but arises from a complication of circumstances, which, being presented to the spectator, excites the SENTIMENT of blame, by the particular structure and fabric of his mind.

Reason judges either based on FACTS or RELATIONS. So, let’s first ask, where is the fact we call crime? Identify it; determine when it happened; describe what it is; explain how it reveals itself. It exists in the mind of the ungrateful person. They must, therefore, feel it and be aware of it. But really, there’s nothing there except for feelings of resentment or complete indifference. You can’t say these feelings are crimes in themselves, always, and in every situation. No, they only become crimes when directed at people who have previously shown kindness towards us. Therefore, we can conclude that the crime of ingratitude isn’t a specific ACTION; it comes from a mix of circumstances that, when viewed by an observer, trigger feelings of blame due to the particular makeup of their mind.

This representation, you say, is false. Crime, indeed, consists not in a particular FACT, of whose reality we are assured by reason; but it consists in certain MORAL RELATIONS, discovered by reason, in the same manner as we discover by reason the truths of geometry or algebra. But what are the relations, I ask, of which you here talk? In the case stated above, I see first good-will and good-offices in one person; then ill-will and ill-offices in the other. Between these, there is a relation of CONTRARIETY. Does the crime consist in that relation? But suppose a person bore me ill-will or did me ill-offices; and I, in return, were indifferent towards him, or did him good offices. Here is the same relation of CONTRARIETY; and yet my conduct is often highly laudable. Twist and turn this matter as much as you will, you can never rest the morality on relation; but must have recourse to the decisions of sentiment.

You say this representation is false. Crime doesn't really consist of a specific FACT, which we know to be real through reason; rather, it involves certain MORAL RELATIONS that we discover with reason, just like we uncover the truths of geometry or algebra. But what are these relations you’re talking about? In the case mentioned earlier, I see one person showing good intentions and helpfulness, while the other shows bad intentions and unhelpfulness. There’s a relationship of CONTRARIETY between these two. Does the crime lie in that relationship? But what if someone had bad intentions toward me or acted unhelpfully, and I, in return, felt indifferent or acted kindly toward them? That’s still the same relationship of CONTRARIETY, yet my actions might often be considered commendable. No matter how you spin this, you can never base morality on just relationships; you have to rely on the judgments of sentiment.

When it is affirmed that two and three are equal to the half of ten, this relation of equality I understand perfectly. I conceive, that if ten be divided into two parts, of which one has as many units as the other; and if any of these parts be compared to two added to three, it will contain as many units as that compound number. But when you draw thence a comparison to moral relations, I own that I am altogether at a loss to understand you. A moral action, a crime, such as ingratitude, is a complicated object. Does the morality consist in the relation of its parts to each other? How? After what manner? Specify the relation: be more particular and explicit in your propositions, and you will easily see their falsehood.

When it’s said that two and three make up half of ten, I completely get that relationship. I understand that if you split ten into two equal parts, and if you compare one of those parts to two plus three, they will have the same number of units. But when you start comparing this to moral issues, I have to admit I'm completely confused. A moral action, like ingratitude, is complex. Does the morality come from the way its parts relate to one another? How? In what way? Be specific about the relationship: clarify your statements and you’ll quickly see where they’re mistaken.

No, say you, the morality consists in the relation of actions to the rule of right; and they are denominated good or ill, according as they agree or disagree with it. What then is this rule of right? In what does it consist? How is it determined? By reason, you say, which examines the moral relations of actions. So that moral relations are determined by the comparison of action to a rule. And that rule is determined by considering the moral relations of objects. Is not this fine reasoning?

No, you say, morality is about how actions relate to the rule of right; they are called good or bad based on whether they align with it. So what is this rule of right? What does it involve? How is it figured out? You say it’s by reason, which looks at the moral relationships of actions. So moral relationships are determined by comparing actions to a rule. And that rule is figured out by looking at the moral relationships of objects. Isn’t this great reasoning?

All this is metaphysics, you cry. That is enough; there needs nothing more to give a strong presumption of falsehood. Yes, reply I, here are metaphysics surely; but they are all on your side, who advance an abstruse hypothesis, which can never be made intelligible, nor quadrate with any particular instance or illustration. The hypothesis which we embrace is plain. It maintains that morality is determined by sentiment. It defines virtue to be WHATEVER MENTAL ACTION OR QUALITY GIVES TO A SPECTATOR THE PLEASING SENTIMENT OF APPROBATION; and vice the contrary. We then proceed to examine a plain matter of fact, to wit, what actions have this influence. We consider all the circumstances in which these actions agree, and thence endeavour to extract some general observations with regard to these sentiments. If you call this metaphysics, and find anything abstruse here, you need only conclude that your turn of mind is not suited to the moral sciences.

All this is just metaphysics, you say. That's enough; it strongly suggests falsehood. Yes, I reply, there are definitely metaphysics here; but they're all on your side, as you present a complex hypothesis that can never be made clear or fit any specific example or illustration. The hypothesis we accept is straightforward. It asserts that morality is determined by sentiment. It defines virtue as ANY MENTAL ACTION OR QUALITY THAT PROVIDES A SPECTATOR WITH THE PLEASANT FEELING OF APPROVAL; and vice, the opposite. We then go on to examine a straightforward fact, namely, which actions have this effect. We look at all the circumstances in which these actions align, and from there, we try to draw some general conclusions about these sentiments. If you consider this metaphysics and find anything complex here, you can only conclude that your way of thinking isn't suited for the moral sciences.

II. When a man, at any time, deliberates concerning his own conduct (as, whether he had better, in a particular emergence, assist a brother or a benefactor), he must consider these separate relations, with all the circumstances and situations of the persons, in order to determine the superior duty and obligation; and in order to determine the proportion of lines in any triangle, it is necessary to examine the nature of that figure, and the relation which its several parts bear to each other. But notwithstanding this appearing similarity in the two cases, there is, at bottom, an extreme difference between them. A speculative reasoner concerning triangles or circles considers the several known and given relations of the parts of these figures; and thence infers some unknown relation, which is dependent on the former. But in moral deliberations we must be acquainted beforehand with all the objects, and all their relations to each other; and from a comparison of the whole, fix our choice or approbation. No new fact to be ascertained; no new relation to be discovered. All the circumstances of the case are supposed to be laid before us, ere we can fix any sentence of blame or approbation. If any material circumstance be yet unknown or doubtful, we must first employ our inquiry or intellectual faculties to assure us of it; and must suspend for a time all moral decision or sentiment. While we are ignorant whether a man were aggressor or not, how can we determine whether the person who killed him be criminal or innocent? But after every circumstance, every relation is known, the understanding has no further room to operate, nor any object on which it could employ itself. The approbation or blame which then ensues, cannot be the work of the judgement, but of the heart; and is not a speculative proposition or affirmation, but an active feeling or sentiment. In the disquisitions of the understanding, from known circumstances and relations, we infer some new and unknown. In moral decisions, all the circumstances and relations must be previously known; and the mind, from the contemplation of the whole, feels some new impression of affection or disgust, esteem or contempt, approbation or blame.

II. When someone thinks about their own actions (like whether they should help a sibling or a benefactor in a certain situation), they need to consider all the different relationships and circumstances of the people involved to figure out their main duty and obligation. Just like to determine the proportions of lines in a triangle, it’s important to understand the nature of that shape and how its parts relate to each other. However, despite the apparent similarity between these two situations, there’s a significant difference at the core. A theoretical thinker about triangles or circles looks at the known relationships of the parts of these shapes and infers an unknown relationship based on those. But in moral decision-making, we must already know all the objects and their relationships to one another; only then can we make our choice or judgment. There can be no new facts to discover or new relationships to find. All circumstances of the case need to be presented to us before we can assign blame or approval. If any important detail is still unknown or unclear, we have to first use our inquiry or thinking skills to clarify it, postponing any moral judgment or feeling. While we don’t know whether someone was the aggressor, how can we decide if the person who killed them is guilty or innocent? But once every detail and every relationship is known, the understanding has nothing left to analyze or consider. The approval or blame that follows cannot be the result of judgment, but rather a feeling from the heart; it’s not a theoretical statement or affirmation but an active emotion or sentiment. In cognitive inquiries, we derive some new and unknown from known circumstances and relationships. In moral judgments, all circumstances and relationships must be already known, and the mind, reflecting on the whole, experiences a new sense of affection or distaste, respect or disdain, approval or disapproval.

Hence the great difference between a mistake of FACT and one of RIGHT; and hence the reason why the one is commonly criminal and not the other. When Oedipus killed Laius, he was ignorant of the relation, and from circumstances, innocent and involuntary, formed erroneous opinions concerning the action which he committed. But when Nero killed Agrippina, all the relations between himself and the person, and all the circumstances of the fact, were previously known to him; but the motive of revenge, or fear, or interest, prevailed in his savage heart over the sentiments of duty and humanity. And when we express that detestation against him to which he himself, in a little time, became insensible, it is not that we see any relations, of which he was ignorant; but that, for the rectitude of our disposition, we feel sentiments against which he was hardened from flattery and a long perseverance in the most enormous crimes.

Hence the significant difference between a mistake of FACT and one of RIGHT; and that’s why one is usually seen as criminal and the other is not. When Oedipus killed Laius, he didn’t know their relationship and, due to the circumstances, was innocent and acted unintentionally, forming incorrect beliefs about the action he took. But when Nero killed Agrippina, he was fully aware of his relationship with her and all the circumstances surrounding the act; however, his motives of revenge, fear, or self-interest overwhelmed his sense of duty and humanity. And when we express our intense disgust towards him—something he himself became numb to over time—it’s not because we see any unknown relationships, but rather because, in our moral integrity, we feel a revulsion against which he had become hardened through flattery and a long history of committing horrific crimes.

In these sentiments then, not in a discovery of relations of any kind, do all moral determinations consist. Before we can pretend to form any decision of this kind, everything must be known and ascertained on the side of the object or action. Nothing remains but to feel, on our part, some sentiment of blame or approbation; whence we pronounce the action criminal or virtuous.

In these feelings, not in discovering relationships of any kind, do all moral judgments exist. Before we can claim to make any decision like this, everything about the object or action must be known and verified. All that’s left is for us to have some feeling of disapproval or approval; from which we label the action as wrong or good.

III. This doctrine will become still more evident, if we compare moral beauty with natural, to which in many particulars it bears so near a resemblance. It is on the proportion, relation, and position of parts, that all natural beauty depends; but it would be absurd thence to infer, that the perception of beauty, like that of truth in geometrical problems, consists wholly in the perception of relations, and was performed entirely by the understanding or intellectual faculties. In all the sciences, our mind from the known relations investigates the unknown. But in all decisions of taste or external beauty, all the relations are beforehand obvious to the eye; and we thence proceed to feel a sentiment of complacency or disgust, according to the nature of the object, and disposition of our organs.

III. This idea will become even clearer when we compare moral beauty with natural beauty, which resembles it in many ways. Natural beauty is based on the proportions, relationships, and positioning of parts; however, it would be unreasonable to conclude that the perception of beauty, like the perception of truth in geometry, is solely based on understanding these relationships and is entirely a function of our intellect. In all sciences, our mind explores the unknown based on known relationships. But when it comes to taste or external beauty, all the relationships are already obvious to the eye; from there, we develop a feeling of pleasure or discomfort, depending on the nature of the object and the way our senses are tuned.

Euclid has fully explained all the qualities of the circle; but has not in any proposition said a word of its beauty. The reason is evident. The beauty is not a quality of the circle. It lies not in any part of the line, whose parts are equally distant from a common centre. It is only the effect which that figure produces upon the mind, whose peculiar fabric of structure renders it susceptible of such sentiments. In vain would you look for it in the circle, or seek it, either by your senses or by mathematical reasoning, in all the properties of that figure.

Euclid has thoroughly explained all the properties of the circle, but he hasn't mentioned its beauty in any of his propositions. The reason is clear. Beauty isn’t a property of the circle. It doesn’t exist in any part of the line, as all parts are equally distant from a common center. It’s simply the impact that this shape has on the mind, which is uniquely structured to appreciate such feelings. It’s pointless to search for beauty within the circle or to find it through your senses or mathematical reasoning in all the attributes of that figure.

Attend to Palladio and Perrault, while they explain all the parts and proportions of a pillar. They talk of the cornice, and frieze, and base, and entablature, and shaft, and architrave; and give the description and position of each of these members. But should you ask the description and position of its beauty, they would readily reply, that the beauty is not in any of the parts or members of a pillar, but results from the whole, when that complicated figure is presented to an intelligent mind, susceptible to those finer sensations. Till such a spectator appear, there is nothing but a figure of such particular dimensions and proportions: from his sentiments alone arise its elegance and beauty.

Pay attention to Palladio and Perrault as they explain all the parts and proportions of a pillar. They discuss the cornice, frieze, base, entablature, shaft, and architrave, describing the details and positions of each component. But if you were to ask about the description and position of its beauty, they would quickly say that beauty isn't found in any individual part of the pillar; it comes from the whole structure when that complex figure is presented to an understanding mind, open to those subtle feelings. Until such a viewer appears, it's just a shape with specific dimensions and proportions: its elegance and beauty arise solely from their sentiments.

Again; attend to Cicero, while he paints the crimes of a Verres or a Catiline. You must acknowledge that the moral turpitude results, in the same manner, from the contemplation of the whole, when presented to a being whose organs have such a particular structure and formation. The orator may paint rage, insolence, barbarity on the one side; meekness, suffering, sorrow, innocence on the other. But if you feel no indignation or compassion arise in you from this complication of circumstances, you would in vain ask him, in what consists the crime or villainy, which he so vehemently exclaims against? At what time, or on what subject it first began to exist? And what has a few months afterwards become of it, when every disposition and thought of all the actors is totally altered or annihilated? No satisfactory answer can be given to any of these questions, upon the abstract hypothesis of morals; and we must at last acknowledge, that the crime or immorality is no particular fact or relation, which can be the object of the understanding, but arises entirely from the sentiment of disapprobation, which, by the structure of human nature, we unavoidably feel on the apprehension of barbarity or treachery.

Once again, pay attention to Cicero as he describes the wrongdoings of Verres or Catiline. You have to admit that moral corruption stems from viewing the whole situation when it's presented to someone whose senses are specifically shaped. The speaker can show rage, arrogance, and brutality on one side; and gentleness, suffering, sadness, and innocence on the other. But if you don't feel any anger or sympathy from this mix of circumstances, it would be pointless to ask him what makes the crime or wickedness he passionately speaks against. When did it first start? What was it about? And what happened to it a few months later when everyone's feelings and thoughts have completely changed or vanished? No clear answers can be provided to these questions based on a purely moral viewpoint; ultimately, we must accept that crime or immorality is not a specific fact or relationship that we can analyze, but instead arises entirely from the disapproval we inherently feel when confronted with cruelty or betrayal.

IV. Inanimate objects may bear to each other all the same relations which we observe in moral agents; though the former can never be the object of love or hatred, nor are consequently susceptible of merit or iniquity. A young tree, which over-tops and destroys its parent, stands in all the same relations with Nero, when he murdered Agrippina; and if morality consisted merely in relations, would no doubt be equally criminal.

IV. Inanimate objects can have the same relationships with each other as we see in moral beings; however, they can never be the subject of love or hate, and therefore cannot possess merit or wrongdoing. A young tree that grows taller and destroys its parent has the same kind of relationship with Nero when he killed Agrippina; if morality were just about relationships, it would certainly be considered just as wrong.

V. It appears evident that—the ultimate ends of human actions can never, in any case, be accounted for by reason, but recommend themselves entirely to the sentiments and affections of mankind, without any dependance on the intellectual faculties. Ask a man WHY HE USES EXERCISE; he will answer, BECAUSE HE DESIRES TO KEEP HIS HEALTH. If you then enquire, WHY HE DESIRES HEALTH, he will readily reply, BECAUSE SICKNESS IS PAINFUL. If you push your enquiries farther, and desire a reason WHY HE HATES PAIN, it is impossible he can ever give any. This is an ultimate end, and is never referred to any other object.

V. It seems clear that the ultimate reasons for human actions can never be explained by logic; instead, they are driven entirely by people's feelings and emotions, without relying on intellectual reasoning. If you ask someone WHY THEY EXERCISE, they will answer, BECAUSE THEY WANT TO STAY HEALTHY. If you then ask, WHY THEY WANT TO BE HEALTHY, they will quickly say, BECAUSE SICKNESS IS PAINFUL. If you push further and ask WHY THEY HATE PAIN, they can't really provide an answer. This is an ultimate reason and is never tied to anything else.

Perhaps to your second question, WHY HE DESIRES HEALTH, he may also reply, that IT IS NECESSARY FOR THE EXERCISE OF HIS CALLING. If you ask, WHY HE IS ANXIOUS ON THAT HEAD, he will answer, BECAUSE HE DESIRES TO GET MONEY. If you demand WHY? IT IS THE INSTRUMENT OF PLEASURE, says he. And beyond this it is an absurdity to ask for a reason. It is impossible there can be a progress IN INFINITUM; and that one thing can always be a reason why another is desired. Something must be desirable on its own account, and because of its immediate accord or agreement with human sentiment and affection.

Perhaps in response to your second question, WHY HE DESIRES HEALTH, he might say that IT IS NECESSARY FOR HIS JOB. If you ask, WHY HE IS CONCERNED ABOUT THAT, he will reply, BECAUSE HE WANTS TO MAKE MONEY. If you press WHY? HE SAYS IT’S THE MEANS TO ENJOYMENT. Beyond this, it doesn’t make sense to ask for more reasons. There can’t be an endless chain of reasons, and one thing can't always explain why another is wanted. Something must be appealing on its own and because it aligns with human feelings and desires.

Now as virtue is an end, and is desirable on its own account, without fee and reward, merely for the immediate satisfaction which it conveys; it is requisite that there should be some sentiment which it touches, some internal taste or feeling, or whatever you may please to call it, which distinguishes moral good and evil, and which embraces the one and rejects the other.

Now, since virtue is a goal and is valuable in itself, not needing any payment or reward, just for the immediate satisfaction it brings; there must be some feeling or sentiment that it resonates with, some inner sense or emotion—whatever you want to call it—that differentiates between moral good and evil, accepting the former and rejecting the latter.

Thus the distinct boundaries and offices of REASON and of TASTE are easily ascertained. The former conveys the knowledge of truth and falsehood: the latter gives the sentiment of beauty and deformity, vice and virtue. The one discovers objects as they really stand in nature, without addition and diminution: the other has a productive faculty, and gilding or staining all natural objects with the colours, borrowed from internal sentiment, raises in a manner a new creation. Reason being cool and disengaged, is no motive to action, and directs only the impulse received from appetite or inclination, by showing us the means of attaining happiness or avoiding misery: Taste, as it gives pleasure or pain, and thereby constitutes happiness or misery, becomes a motive to action, and is the first spring or impulse to desire and volition. From circumstances and relations, known or supposed, the former leads us to the discovery of the concealed and unknown: after all circumstances and relations are laid before us, the latter makes us feel from the whole a new sentiment of blame or approbation. The standard of the one, being founded on the nature of things, is eternal and inflexible, even by the will of the Supreme Being: the standard of the other arising from the eternal frame and constitution of animals, is ultimately derived from that Supreme Will, which bestowed on each being its peculiar nature, and arranged the several classes and orders of existence.

The clear boundaries and roles of REASON and TASTE are easy to identify. Reason provides knowledge of truth and falsehood, while Taste offers feelings of beauty and ugliness, good and bad. Reason reveals objects as they truly are in nature, without adding or taking away. In contrast, Taste has a creative ability, coloring all natural objects with emotions, which effectively results in a new creation. Since Reason is rational and detached, it doesn’t motivate action; it only guides our appetites or inclinations by showing us how to achieve happiness or avoid suffering. Taste, by giving pleasure or pain, directly influences happiness or unhappiness and acts as the primary motivator for desire and action. Based on known or assumed circumstances and relationships, Reason helps us uncover what is hidden and unknown; once all circumstances and relationships are known, Taste evokes in us a new sense of approval or disapproval. The standard of Reason, grounded in the nature of things, is eternal and unchangeable, even by the will of the Supreme Being. In contrast, Taste, which stems from the inherent structure and constitution of beings, ultimately comes from that Supreme Will, which has given each being its unique nature and organized the different classes and orders of existence.





APPENDIX II. OF SELF-LOVE.

THERE is a principle, supposed to prevail among many, which is utterly incompatible with all virtue or moral sentiment; and as it can proceed from nothing but the most depraved disposition, so in its turn it tends still further to encourage that depravity. This principle is, that all BENEVOLENCE is mere hypocrisy, friendship a cheat, public spirit a farce, fidelity a snare to procure trust and confidence; and that while all of us, at bottom, pursue only our private interest, we wear these fair disguises, in order to put others off their guard, and expose them the more to our wiles and machinations. What heart one must be possessed of who possesses such principles, and who feels no internal sentiment that belies so pernicious a theory, it is easy to imagine: and also what degree of affection and benevolence he can bear to a species whom he represents under such odious colours, and supposes so little susceptible of gratitude or any return of affection. Or if we should not ascribe these principles wholly to a corrupted heart, we must at least account for them from the most careless and precipitate examination. Superficial reasoners, indeed, observing many false pretences among mankind, and feeling, perhaps, no very strong restraint in their own disposition, might draw a general and a hasty conclusion that all is equally corrupted, and that men, different from all other animals, and indeed from all other species of existence, admit of no degrees of good or bad, but are, in every instance, the same creatures under different disguises and appearances.

THERE is a principle, believed by many, that is completely incompatible with any sense of virtue or moral feeling; and since it can only come from the most corrupt mindset, it further encourages that corruption. This principle is that all BENEVOLENCE is just a cover-up, friendship is a deception, public spirit is a joke, and loyalty is just a trap to gain trust and confidence; and that while at our core we all pursue our own interests, we wear these nice disguises to catch others off guard and make it easier to manipulate them. One can easily imagine what kind of heart someone must have who holds such principles and who feels no internal conflict that contradicts such a harmful theory. It's also easy to see how much affection and goodwill they can feel for a species they depict in such a negative light, assuming they are not capable of gratitude or any form of love in return. If we don't attribute these principles entirely to a corrupted heart, we must still consider them as coming from a lazy and hasty analysis. Superficial thinkers, noticing many false pretenses among people, and perhaps lacking strong self-control, might jump to a quick and broad conclusion that everything is equally corrupt, believing that humans, unlike other animals and indeed all forms of existence, have no degrees of good or bad, but are simply the same beings in different disguises and appearances.

There is another principle, somewhat resembling the former; which has been much insisted on by philosophers, and has been the foundation of many a system; that, whatever affection one may feel, or imagine he feels for others, no passion is, or can be disinterested; that the most generous friendship, however sincere, is a modification of self-love; and that, even unknown to ourselves, we seek only our own gratification, while we appear the most deeply engaged in schemes for the liberty and happiness of mankind. By a turn of imagination, by a refinement of reflection, by an enthusiasm of passion, we seem to take part in the interests of others, and imagine ourselves divested of all selfish considerations: but, at bottom, the most generous patriot and most niggardly miser, the bravest hero and most abject coward, have, in every action, an equal regard to their own happiness and welfare.

There’s another principle that's similar to the first one, which philosophers have emphasized a lot and has been the basis for many theories: whatever feelings we think we have for others, no passion is or can be completely selfless. Even the kindest friendship, no matter how genuine, is just a form of self-love. Even if we’re not aware of it, we’re only looking for our own satisfaction, while appearing to be fully invested in the freedom and happiness of others. Through imaginative thinking, thoughtful reflection, or passionate enthusiasm, we seem to care about others' interests and believe we’ve set aside any selfish motivations. But deep down, the most generous patriot and the most greedy miser, the bravest hero and the most cowardly person, all have their actions rooted in a keen awareness of their own happiness and well-being.

Whoever concludes from the seeming tendency of this opinion, that those, who make profession of it, cannot possibly feel the true sentiments of benevolence, or have any regard for genuine virtue, will often find himself, in practice, very much mistaken. Probity and honour were no strangers to Epicurus and his sect. Atticus and Horace seem to have enjoyed from nature, and cultivated by reflection, as generous and friendly dispositions as any disciple of the austerer schools. And among the modern, Hobbes and Locke, who maintained the selfish system of morals, lived irreproachable lives; though the former lay not under any restraint of religion which might supply the defects of his philosophy.

Whoever thinks that those who subscribe to this view can't truly feel benevolence or care about real virtue is often mistaken in practice. Integrity and honor were not unfamiliar to Epicurus and his followers. Atticus and Horace appeared to have naturally generous and friendly dispositions, which they also developed through reflection, just like any student from the stricter schools. Even among modern thinkers, Hobbes and Locke, who supported the self-centered system of morality, lived lives that were above reproach, although Hobbes did not adhere to any religious constraints that might compensate for the shortcomings of his philosophy.

An epicurean or a Hobbist readily allows, that there is such a thing as a friendship in the world, without hypocrisy or disguise; though he may attempt, by a philosophical chymistry, to resolve the elements of this passion, if I may so speak, into those of another, and explain every affection to be self-love, twisted and moulded, by a particular turn of imagination, into a variety of appearances. But as the same turn of imagination prevails not in every man, nor gives the same direction to the original passion; this is sufficient even according to the selfish system to make the widest difference in human characters, and denominate one man virtuous and humane, another vicious and meanly interested. I esteem the man whose self-love, by whatever means, is so directed as to give him a concern for others, and render him serviceable to society: as I hate or despise him, who has no regard to any thing beyond his own gratifications and enjoyments. In vain would you suggest that these characters, though seemingly opposite, are at bottom the same, and that a very inconsiderable turn of thought forms the whole difference between them. Each character, notwithstanding these inconsiderable differences, appears to me, in practice, pretty durable and untransmutable. And I find not in this more than in other subjects, that the natural sentiments arising from the general appearances of things are easily destroyed by subtile reflections concerning the minute origin of these appearances. Does not the lively, cheerful colour of a countenance inspire me with complacency and pleasure; even though I learn from philosophy that all difference of complexion arises from the most minute differences of thickness, in the most minute parts of the skin; by means of which a superficies is qualified to reflect one of the original colours of light, and absorb the others?

An epicurean or a Hobbesian would readily agree that there is such a thing as genuine friendship in the world, free from hypocrisy or pretense; though they might try to deconstruct this feeling through a philosophical analysis, breaking down its elements into those of other emotions, and claim that every affection boils down to self-love, shaped and transformed by a person's unique way of thinking into various forms. But since this particular way of thinking doesn’t apply to everyone, nor does it direct the original emotion in the same way, this is enough, even within a selfish framework, to create significant differences in human personalities, labeling one person as virtuous and compassionate, while another is seen as cruel and self-serving. I respect the individual whose self-love, through whatever means, is directed towards caring for others and making a positive impact on society; while I dislike or look down on someone who only cares about their own pleasures and satisfactions. It would be pointless to argue that these two types of people, despite appearing oppositional, are fundamentally similar, and that only a slight shift in thought accounts for the entire difference between them. Each character, despite these minor variations, seems quite consistent and unchangeable in practice. And I don’t find, in this case any more than in others, that the natural feelings arising from the overall appearance of things can be easily undermined by subtle reflections on the tiny origins of those appearances. Don't you think that a lively, cheerful complexion inspires me with warmth and joy, even when I learn from philosophy that all differences in skin color stem from tiny variations in the thickness of the skin's outer layers, which allow the surface to reflect one of the original colors of light while absorbing the others?

But though the question concerning the universal or partial selfishness of man be not so material as is usually imagined to morality and practice, it is certainly of consequence in the speculative science of human nature, and is a proper object of curiosity and enquiry. It may not, therefore, be unsuitable, in this place, to bestow a few reflections upon it.

But even though the question about whether people are universally or partially selfish isn’t as important for morality and everyday life as many think, it definitely matters in the study of human nature and is worth exploring. So, it might be fitting to share some thoughts on it here.

     [Footnote: Benevolence naturally divides into two kinds, the
GENERAL and the PARTICULAR. The first is, where we have no friendship
or connexion or esteem for the person, but feel only a general sympathy
with him or a compassion for his pains, and a congratulation with his
pleasures. The other species of benevolence is founded on an opinion
of virtue, on services done us, or on some particular connexions. Both
these sentiments must be allowed real in human nature: but whether they
will resolve into some nice considerations of self-love, is a question
more curious than important. The former sentiment, to wit, that of
general benevolence, or humanity, or sympathy, we shall have occasion
frequently to treat of in the course of this inquiry; and I assume it as
real, from general experience, without any other proof.]
     [Footnote: Benevolence naturally divides into two types, GENERAL and PARTICULAR. The first type occurs when we don't have any friendship, connection, or regard for someone, but still feel a general sympathy for their suffering and share in their happiness. The second type of benevolence is based on our view of someone's character, the help they've given us, or specific connections we have with them. Both of these feelings are genuine parts of human nature; however, whether they stem from deeper self-interest is a question that's more intriguing than significant. The first feeling, namely general benevolence, humanity, or sympathy, will be discussed frequently throughout this inquiry, and I take it as real based on common experience, without needing further evidence.]

The most obvious objection to the selfish hypothesis is, that, as it is contrary to common feeling and our most unprejudiced notions, there is required the highest stretch of philosophy to establish so extraordinary a paradox. To the most careless observer there appear to be such dispositions as benevolence and generosity; such affections as love, friendship, compassion, gratitude. These sentiments have their causes, effects, objects, and operations, marked by common language and observation, and plainly distinguished from those of the selfish passions. And as this is the obvious appearance of things, it must be admitted, till some hypothesis be discovered, which by penetrating deeper into human nature, may prove the former affections to be nothing but modifications of the latter. All attempts of this kind have hitherto proved fruitless, and seem to have proceeded entirely from that love of SIMPLICITY which has been the source of much false reasoning in philosophy. I shall not here enter into any detail on the present subject. Many able philosophers have shown the insufficiency of these systems. And I shall take for granted what, I believe, the smallest reflection will make evident to every impartial enquirer.

The most obvious objection to the selfish hypothesis is that, since it goes against common intuition and our most unbiased views, it takes a high level of philosophy to prove such an extraordinary paradox. To even the most casual observer, there seem to be traits like kindness and generosity; feelings like love, friendship, compassion, and gratitude. These emotions have their causes, effects, subjects, and actions, clearly marked by everyday language and observation, and are distinctly different from selfish impulses. Since this is the clear appearance of things, we must accept it until a new hypothesis is found that can delve deeper into human nature and show that the former feelings are merely variations of the latter. So far, all efforts to do this have been unsuccessful and seem to stem entirely from a desire for SIMPLICITY, which has led to much flawed reasoning in philosophy. I won’t go into detail about this topic here. Many skilled philosophers have demonstrated the weaknesses of these theories. I will assume what I believe any fair-minded inquirer will find evident with just a little reflection.

But the nature of the subject furnishes the strongest presumption, that no better system will ever, for the future, be invented, in order to account for the origin of the benevolent from the selfish affections, and reduce all the various emotions of the human mind to a perfect simplicity. The case is not the same in this species of philosophy as in physics. Many an hypothesis in nature, contrary to first appearances, has been found, on more accurate scrutiny, solid and satisfactory. Instances of this kind are so frequent that a judicious, as well as witty philosopher, [Footnote: Mons. Fontenelle.] has ventured to affirm, if there be more than one way in which any phenomenon may be produced, that there is general presumption for its arising from the causes which are the least obvious and familiar. But the presumption always lies on the other side, in all enquiries concerning the origin of our passions, and of the internal operations of the human mind. The simplest and most obvious cause which can there be assigned for any phenomenon, is probably the true one. When a philosopher, in the explication of his system, is obliged to have recourse to some very intricate and refined reflections, and to suppose them essential to the production of any passion or emotion, we have reason to be extremely on our guard against so fallacious an hypothesis. The affections are not susceptible of any impression from the refinements of reason or imagination; and it is always found that a vigorous exertion of the latter faculties, necessarily, from the narrow capacity of the human mind, destroys all activity in the former. Our predominant motive or intention is, indeed, frequently concealed from ourselves when it is mingled and confounded with other motives which the mind, from vanity or self-conceit, is desirous of supposing more prevalent: but there is no instance that a concealment of this nature has ever arisen from the abstruseness and intricacy of the motive. A man that has lost a friend and patron may flatter himself that all his grief arises from generous sentiments, without any mixture of narrow or interested considerations: but a man that grieves for a valuable friend, who needed his patronage and protection; how can we suppose, that his passionate tenderness arises from some metaphysical regards to a self-interest, which has no foundation or reality? We may as well imagine that minute wheels and springs, like those of a watch, give motion to a loaded waggon, as account for the origin of passion from such abstruse reflections.

But the nature of the topic strongly suggests that no better system will ever be created in the future to explain how the kind feelings come from selfish emotions, and to simplify all the various feelings of the human mind into a straightforward concept. This isn't the same in this area of philosophy as it is in physics. Many hypotheses in nature, despite initial appearances, have turned out to be solid and satisfactory upon closer examination. Examples of this occur so often that a clever and witty philosopher, [Footnote: Mons. Fontenelle.] has boldly stated that if there’s more than one way to explain a phenomenon, there’s a general presumption that it arises from the least obvious and familiar causes. However, when it comes to examining the origins of our emotions and the workings of the human mind, the opposite presumption usually holds. The simplest and most obvious explanation for a phenomenon is likely the correct one. When a philosopher has to rely on very complicated and refined reasoning to explain their system and insists it’s essential for understanding any emotion, we should be cautious of such a misleading hypothesis. Emotions aren't affected by the complexities of reason or imagination; and it’s usually the case that an intense application of the latter abilities, given the limited capacity of the human mind, inhibits all action in the former. Our main motive or intention is often hidden from us when it's mixed with other motives that our minds, out of vanity or self-importance, want to believe are more significant: but there's no evidence that such concealment ever stems from the complexity and intricacy of the motive. A person who has lost a friend and supporter might convince themselves that all their sorrow comes from generous feelings, without any selfish or narrow considerations involved. But when someone mourns a dear friend who relied on their support and protection, how can we believe that their intense feelings come from some philosophical notions of self-interest that have no real foundation? We might as well think that tiny gears and springs, like those in a watch, could make a heavy wagon move, as to explain the origin of emotions through such complicated reflections.

Animals are found susceptible of kindness, both to their own species and to ours; nor is there, in this case, the least suspicion of disguise or artifice. Shall we account for all THEIR sentiments, too, from refined deductions of self-interest? Or if we admit a disinterested benevolence in the inferior species, by what rule of analogy can we refuse it in the superior?

Animals are capable of showing kindness, both to their own kind and to humans; and in this regard, there’s no hint of deceit or trickery. Should we explain all THEIR feelings solely based on self-serving reasons? Or if we accept that lower species can act out of genuine goodwill, what reason do we have to deny that possibility in higher species?

Love between the sexes begets a complacency and good-will, very distinct from the gratification of an appetite. Tenderness to their offspring, in all sensible beings, is commonly able alone to counter-balance the strongest motives of self-love, and has no manner of dependance on that affection. What interest can a fond mother have in view, who loses her health by assiduous attendance on her sick child, and afterwards languishes and dies of grief, when freed, by its death, from the slavery of that attendance?

Love between genders brings about a sense of comfort and kindness that’s quite different from simply satisfying a desire. Care for their children, in all sensible beings, is usually strong enough to outweigh the strongest instincts of self-interest and doesn’t rely on that affection at all. What could a loving mother possibly gain from sacrificing her health by constantly caring for her sick child, only to suffer and die from grief once she is finally free from that responsibility after the child’s death?

Is gratitude no affection of the human breast, or is that a word merely, without any meaning or reality? Have we no satisfaction in one man's company above another's, and no desire of the welfare of our friend, even though absence or death should prevent us from all participation in it? Or what is it commonly, that gives us any participation in it, even while alive and present, but our affection and regard to him?

Is gratitude not a feeling in the human heart, or is it just a word with no real meaning? Do we not find more joy in one person's company than another's, and do we not care about our friend's well-being, even when distance or death keeps us from being involved in it? What is it that allows us to share in someone's joy, even when they are alive and right there with us, if not our love and concern for them?

These and a thousand other instances are marks of a general benevolence in human nature, where no REAL interest binds us to the object. And how an IMAGINARY interest known and avowed for such, can be the origin of any passion or emotion, seems difficult to explain. No satisfactory hypothesis of this kind has yet been discovered; nor is there the smallest probability that the future industry of men will ever be attended with more favourable success.

These and countless other examples show a general kindness in human nature, even when there's no real interest connecting us to the situation. It's hard to explain how a made-up interest, recognized and admitted as such, can create any passion or emotion. No convincing theory of this kind has been found yet, and it's unlikely that future efforts will lead to greater success.

But farther, if we consider rightly of the matter, we shall find that the hypothesis which allows of a disinterested benevolence, distinct from self-love, has really more SIMPLICITY in it, and is more conformable to the analogy of nature than that which pretends to resolve all friendship and humanity into this latter principle. There are bodily wants or appetites acknowledged by every one, which necessarily precede all sensual enjoyment, and carry us directly to seek possession of the object. Thus, hunger and thirst have eating and drinking for their end; and from the gratification of these primary appetites arises a pleasure, which may become the object of another species of desire or inclination that is secondary and interested. In the same manner there are mental passions by which we are impelled immediately to seek particular objects, such as fame or power, or vengeance without any regard to interest; and when these objects are attained a pleasing enjoyment ensues, as the consequence of our indulged affections. Nature must, by the internal frame and constitution of the mind, give an original propensity to fame, ere we can reap any pleasure from that acquisition, or pursue it from motives of self-love, and desire of happiness. If I have no vanity, I take no delight in praise: if I be void of ambition, power gives me no enjoyment: if I be not angry, the punishment of an adversary is totally indifferent to me. In all these cases there is a passion which points immediately to the object, and constitutes it our good or happiness; as there are other secondary passions which afterwards arise, and pursue it as a part of our happiness, when once it is constituted such by our original affections. Were there no appetite of any kind antecedent to self-love, that propensity could scarcely ever exert itself; because we should, in that case, have felt few and slender pains or pleasures, and have little misery or happiness to avoid or to pursue.

But further, if we think about it correctly, we’ll find that the idea of selfless kindness, separate from self-interest, actually has more SIMPLICITY and aligns better with the natural world than the idea that everything about friendship and humanity can be explained by self-love. There are basic physical needs that everyone recognizes, which come before any physical enjoyment and drive us to seek what we want. For example, hunger and thirst lead us to eat and drink; and from satisfying these basic needs comes a pleasure that may turn into another type of desire that is interested and secondary. Similarly, there are mental passions that push us to pursue specific things like fame, power, or revenge, without any consideration for self-interest; and achieving these goals brings us satisfaction as a result of our indulged feelings. Nature must, through the makeup and structure of the mind, provide an innate drive for fame before we can enjoy that achievement or want it for self-loving reasons or happiness. If I'm not vain, I don’t find joy in praise; if I lack ambition, power doesn’t bring me pleasure; if I’m not angry, punishing an opponent is completely irrelevant to me. In all these situations, there’s a passion directing us straight toward the object, making it our good or happiness; while there are also other secondary passions that arise later and chase it as a part of our happiness once it has been deemed so by our original feelings. If there were no desires of any kind before self-love, that inclination would struggle to take effect since we would then experience few and minor pains or pleasures, and have little misery or happiness to avoid or pursue.

Now where is the difficulty in conceiving, that this may likewise be the case with benevolence and friendship, and that, from the original frame of our temper, we may feel a desire of another's happiness or good, which, by means of that affection, becomes our own good, and is afterwards pursued, from the combined motives of benevolence and self-enjoyments? Who sees not that vengeance, from the force alone of passion, may be so eagerly pursued, as to make us knowingly neglect every consideration of ease, interest, or safety; and, like some vindictive animals, infuse our very souls into the wounds we give an enemy; [Footnote: Animasque in vulnere ponunt. VIRG, Dum alteri noceat, sui negligens says Seneca of Anger. De Ira, I. i.] and what a malignant philosophy must it be, that will not allow to humanity and friendship the same privileges which are undisputably granted to the darker passions of enmity and resentment; such a philosophy is more like a satyr than a true delineation or description of human nature; and may be a good foundation for paradoxical wit and raillery, but is a very bad one for any serious argument or reasoning.

Now, what's so hard to understand about the idea that benevolence and friendship might work the same way? From our natural disposition, we might genuinely want another person's happiness, which, through that affection, becomes our own happiness and is then pursued because of both kindness and self-interest. Who doesn’t recognize that vengeance, driven purely by passion, can be so intensely sought after that we completely ignore our ease, interests, or safety? Like some vengeful creatures, we can pour our very souls into the harm we inflict on an enemy; [Footnote: Animasque in vulnere ponunt. VIRG, Dum alteri noceat, sui negligens says Seneca of Anger. De Ira, I. i.] and what a cruel philosophy it must be that denies humanity and friendship the same allowances granted to the darker feelings of hatred and resentment. Such a philosophy resembles more a satyr than a true representation of human nature; it might serve as a root for witty contradictions and sarcasm, but it’s a terrible basis for any serious argument or reasoning.





APPENDIX III. SOME FARTHER CONSIDERATIONS WITH REGARD TO JUSTICE.

The intention of this Appendix is to give some more particular explication of the origin and nature of Justice, and to mark some differences between it and the other virtues.

The purpose of this Appendix is to provide a more detailed explanation of the origin and nature of Justice, and to highlight some differences between it and the other virtues.

The social virtues of humanity and benevolence exert their influence immediately by a direct tendency or instinct, which chiefly keeps in view the simple object, moving the affections, and comprehends not any scheme or system, nor the consequences resulting from the concurrence, imitation, or example of others. A parent flies to the relief of his child; transported by that natural sympathy which actuates him, and which affords no leisure to reflect on the sentiments or conduct of the rest of mankind in like circumstances. A generous man cheerfully embraces an opportunity of serving his friend; because he then feels himself under the dominion of the beneficent affections, nor is he concerned whether any other person in the universe were ever before actuated by such noble motives, or will ever afterwards prove their influence. In all these cases the social passions have in view a single individual object, and pursue the safety or happiness alone of the person loved and esteemed. With this they are satisfied: in this they acquiesce. And as the good, resulting from their benign influence, is in itself complete and entire, it also excites the moral sentiment of approbation, without any reflection on farther consequences, and without any more enlarged views of the concurrence or imitation of the other members of society. On the contrary, were the generous friend or disinterested patriot to stand alone in the practice of beneficence, this would rather enhance his value in our eyes, and join the praise of rarity and novelty to his other more exalted merits.

The social virtues of humanity and kindness have an immediate impact through a direct instinct that focuses on a simple goal, stirring emotions without considering any plans, systems, or the outcomes that come from the actions or examples of others. A parent instinctively rushes to help their child, driven by a natural sympathy that leaves no room for thoughts about how others might act in similar situations. A generous person happily seizes the chance to help a friend, feeling compelled by their kind instincts, without worrying whether anyone else in the world has ever been motivated by such noble reasons or will be again in the future. In all these instances, social emotions focus on one individual, aiming solely for the safety or happiness of the person they care about. This is enough for them; this is where they find contentment. And since the good that comes from their kind actions is complete in itself, it also brings about a sense of moral approval, without any consideration of further consequences or a broader view of the actions of others in society. Conversely, if the generous friend or selfless patriot were to act alone in doing good, it would actually increase their worth in our eyes, adding the praise of rarity and uniqueness to their already admirable qualities.

The case is not the same with the social virtues of justice and fidelity. They are highly useful, or indeed absolutely necessary to the well-being of mankind: but the benefit resulting from them is not the consequence of every individual single act; but arises from the whole scheme or system concurred in by the whole, or the greater part of the society. General peace and order are the attendants of justice or a general abstinence from the possessions of others; but a particular regard to the particular right of one individual citizen may frequently, considered in itself, be productive of pernicious consequences. The result of the individual acts is here, in many instances, directly opposite to that of the whole system of actions; and the former may be extremely hurtful, while the latter is, to the highest degree, advantageous. Riches, inherited from a parent, are, in a bad man's hand, the instrument of mischief. The right of succession may, in one instance, be hurtful. Its benefit arises only from the observance of the general rule; and it is sufficient, if compensation be thereby made for all the ills and inconveniences which flow from particular characters and situations.

The situation is different when it comes to the social virtues of justice and loyalty. They are very important, or even absolutely necessary, for the well-being of humanity; however, the benefits they provide don’t come from each individual action but rather from the overall system agreed upon by the majority of society. General peace and order accompany justice or a widespread avoidance of taking what's not yours; however, a specific focus on one individual citizen's rights can often lead to negative outcomes when considered on its own. In many cases, the results of individual actions can be the exact opposite of the overall system's outcomes; individual actions may be very harmful while the overall system is extremely beneficial. Wealth inherited from a parent can become a tool for harm in the hands of a bad person. The right to inherit can sometimes be detrimental. Its benefits only come from following the general principle, and it's enough if compensation is provided for all the problems and inconveniences caused by specific individuals and situations.

Cyrus, young and unexperienced, considered only the individual case before him, and reflected on a limited fitness and convenience, when he assigned the long coat to the tall boy, and the short coat to the other of smaller size. His governor instructed him better, while he pointed out more enlarged views and consequences, and informed his pupil of the general, inflexible rules, necessary to support general peace and order in society.

Cyrus, young and inexperienced, thought only about the specific situation in front of him and considered a limited sense of suitability when he gave the long coat to the tall boy and the short coat to the smaller one. His teacher guided him on this matter, highlighting broader perspectives and outcomes, and taught his student about the general, strict rules essential for maintaining peace and order in society.

The happiness and prosperity of mankind, arising from the social virtue of benevolence and its subdivisions, may be compared to a wall, built by many hands, which still rises by each stone that is heaped upon it, and receives increase proportional to the diligence and care of each workman. The same happiness, raised by the social virtue of justice and its subdivisions, may be compared to the building of a vault, where each individual stone would, of itself, fall to the ground; nor is the whole fabric supported but by the mutual assistance and combination of its corresponding parts.

The happiness and prosperity of humanity, stemming from the social virtue of kindness and its various aspects, can be likened to a wall constructed by many hands, which continues to rise with every stone added to it, growing in proportion to the effort and care of each worker. In the same way, happiness built on the social virtue of justice and its components can be compared to a vault, where each individual stone would simply fall if left alone; the entire structure stands only through the mutual support and collaboration of its interconnected parts.

All the laws of nature, which regulate property, as well as all civil laws, are general, and regard alone some essential circumstances of the case, without taking into consideration the characters, situations, and connexions of the person concerned, or any particular consequences which may result from the determination of these laws in any particular case which offers. They deprive, without scruple, a beneficent man of all his possessions, if acquired by mistake, without a good title; in order to bestow them on a selfish miser, who has already heaped up immense stores of superfluous riches. Public utility requires that property should be regulated by general inflexible rules; and though such rules are adopted as best serve the same end of public utility, it is impossible for them to prevent all particular hardships, or make beneficial consequences result from every individual case. It is sufficient, if the whole plan or scheme be necessary to the support of civil society, and if the balance of good, in the main, do thereby preponderate much above that of evil. Even the general laws of the universe, though planned by infinite wisdom, cannot exclude all evil or inconvenience in every particular operation.

All the laws of nature that govern property, as well as all civil laws, are general and only consider some essential circumstances of each case, without taking into account the traits, situations, and connections of the person involved, or any specific consequences that may arise from applying these laws to any given case. They carelessly strip a good person of all their possessions if acquired mistakenly and without a valid title, just to hand them over to a greedy miser who has already accumulated vast amounts of unnecessary wealth. Public good demands that property should be regulated by general, strict rules, and although these rules are designed to best serve the public good, it’s impossible for them to avoid all individual hardships or ensure that every single case leads to beneficial outcomes. It’s enough if the overall plan is essential for maintaining civil society and if the overall benefits significantly outweigh the drawbacks. Even the universal laws, despite being created by infinite wisdom, cannot eliminate all evil or inconvenience in every specific situation.

It has been asserted by some, that justice arises from Human Conventions, and proceeds from the voluntary choice, consent, or combination of mankind. If by CONVENTION be here meant a PROMISE (which is the most usual sense of the word) nothing can be more absurd than this position. The observance of promises is itself one of the most considerable parts of justice, and we are not surely bound to keep our word because we have given our word to keep it. But if by convention be meant a sense of common interest, which sense each man feels in his own breast, which he remarks in his fellows, and which carries him, in concurrence with others, into a general plan or system of actions, which tends to public utility; it must be owned, that, in this sense, justice arises from human conventions. For if it be allowed (what is, indeed, evident) that the particular consequences of a particular act of justice may be hurtful to the public as well as to individuals; it follows that every man, in embracing that virtue, must have an eye to the whole plan or system, and must expect the concurrence of his fellows in the same conduct and behaviour. Did all his views terminate in the consequences of each act of his own, his benevolence and humanity, as well as his self-love, might often prescribe to him measures of conduct very different from those which are agreeable to the strict rules of right and justice.

Some people argue that justice comes from human agreements and results from the voluntary choices, consent, or collaboration of people. If "agreement" here refers to a "promise" (which is the most common interpretation), then this idea is completely ridiculous. Keeping promises is one of the key aspects of justice, and we aren’t obligated to uphold our word simply because we said we would. However, if "agreement" means a sense of shared interest that each person feels deep down and recognizes in others, guiding them, together, into a collective plan or system of actions that aims for the common good, then it must be acknowledged that, in this sense, justice indeed comes from human agreements. If we accept (what is actually clear) that the specific outcomes of any single act of justice can harm both the public and individuals, it follows that everyone, in practicing that virtue, must consider the larger plan or system and expect cooperation from others in the same actions and behaviors. If all his considerations were limited to the outcomes of his own actions, his kindness and compassion, as well as his self-interest, could often lead him to choose behaviors that differ significantly from what aligns with strict rules of right and justice.

Thus, two men pull the oars of a boat by common convention for common interest, without any promise or contract; thus gold and silver are made the measures of exchange; thus speech and words and language are fixed by human convention and agreement. Whatever is advantageous to two or more persons, if all perform their part; but what loses all advantage if only one perform, can arise from no other principle There would otherwise be no motive for any one of them to enter into that scheme of conduct.

So, two guys row a boat together by mutual agreement for mutual benefit, without any promise or contract; that's why gold and silver are used as currency; that's also how language and communication are established through collective agreement. Anything that benefits two or more people, if everyone does their part, but loses its benefit if only one person participates, can only come from this idea. Otherwise, there would be no reason for any of them to engage in that way of acting.

     [Footnote: This theory concerning the origin of property, and
consequently of justice, is, in the main, the same with that hinted at
and adopted by Grotius, 'Hinc discimus, quae fuerit causa, ob quam a
primaeva communione rerum primo mobilium, deinde et immobilinm discessum
est: nimirum quod cum non contenti homines vesci sponte natis, antra
habitare, corpore aut nudo agere, aut corticibus arborum ferarumve
pellibus vestito, vitae genus exquisitius delegissent, industria opus
fuit, quam singuli rebus singulls adhiberent. Quo minus autem fructus
in commune conferrentur, primum obstitit locorum, in quae homines
discesserunt, distantia, deinde justitiae et amoris defectus, per quem
fiebat, ut nee in labore, nee in consumtione fructuum, quae debebat,
aequalitas servaretur. Simul discimus, quomodo res in proprietatem
iverint; non animi actu solo, neque enim scire alii poterant, quid alil
suum esse vellent, ut eo abstinerent, et idem velle plures poterant;
sed pacto quodam aut expresso, ut per divisionem, aut tacito, ut per
occupationem.' De jure belli et pacis. Lib. ii. cap. 2. sec. 2. art. 4
and 5.]
[Footnote: This theory about the origin of property, and consequently of justice, is largely the same as what Grotius suggested. 'From this, we learn the reason why people initially moved away from the original communal ownership of things, first with movable goods, and then with real estate: namely, because humans were not satisfied living off what nature provided, dwelling in caves, engaging in physical activities, or wearing only tree bark or animal skins. They chose a more refined way of living, which required effort that individuals could contribute to specific things. However, the sharing of benefits began to break down, first due to the distance to which people moved apart, and then because of a lack of justice and love, leading to inequalities in labor and in the distribution of the goods that were due. At the same time, we learn how things shifted into private ownership; it wasn't just a matter of mindset, nor could individuals know what others considered their own, so they could abstain from it, though many could desire the same things; but it happened either through a clear agreement, like when dividing things, or implicitly, like when occupying them.' De jure belli et pacis. Lib. ii. cap. 2. sec. 2. art. 4 and 5.]

The word NATURAL is commonly taken in so many senses and is of so loose a signification, that it seems vain to dispute whether justice be natural or not. If self-love, if benevolence be natural to man; if reason and forethought be also natural; then may the same epithet be applied to justice, order, fidelity, property, society. Men's inclination, their necessities, lead them to combine; their understanding and experience tell them that this combination is impossible where each governs himself by no rule, and pays no regard to the possessions of others: and from these passions and reflections conjoined, as soon as we observe like passions and reflections in others, the sentiment of justice, throughout all ages, has infallibly and certainly had place to some degree or other in every individual of the human species. In so sagacious an animal, what necessarily arises from the exertion of his intellectual faculties may justly be esteemed natural.

The term NATURAL is often interpreted in many ways and has such a vague meaning that it seems pointless to argue about whether justice is natural or not. If self-love and benevolence are natural to humans; if reason and foresight are also natural; then we can apply the same description to justice, order, loyalty, property, and society. People's inclinations and needs drive them to come together; their understanding and experience show them that this cooperation is impossible if everyone acts solely on their own terms without considering the rights of others. From these feelings and reflections, as soon as we notice similar feelings and thoughts in others, the sense of justice has consistently and inevitably existed to some degree in every individual throughout human history. In such a clever species, what naturally results from using our intellectual abilities can rightly be considered natural.

     [Footnote: Natural may be opposed, either to what is UNUSUAL,
MIRACULOUS or ARTIFICIAL. In the two former senses, justice and property
are undoubtedly natural. But as they suppose reason, forethought,
design, and a social union and confederacy among men, perhaps that
epithet cannot strictly, in the last sense, be applied to them. Had
men lived without society, property had never been known, and neither
justice nor injustice had ever existed. But society among human
creatures had been impossible without reason and forethought. Inferior
animals, that unite, are guided by instinct, which supplies the place
for reason. But all these disputes are merely verbal.]
     [Footnote: Natural can be contrasted with what is UNUSUAL, MIRACULOUS, or ARTIFICIAL. In the first two senses, justice and property are certainly natural. However, since they rely on reason, foresight, design, and a social bond among people, it might be said that this term can't strictly apply to them in the final sense. If humans had lived without society, property would never have existed, and neither would justice or injustice. But society among humans would have been impossible without reason and foresight. Lower animals that form groups are guided by instinct, which takes the place of reason. Yet, all these debates are just semantic.]

Among all civilized nations it has been the constant endeavour to remove everything arbitrary and partial from the decision of property, and to fix the sentence of judges by such general views and considerations as may be equal to every member of society. For besides, that nothing could be more dangerous than to accustom the bench, even in the smallest instance, to regard private friendship or enmity; it is certain, that men, where they imagine that there was no other reason for the preference of their adversary but personal favour, are apt to entertain the strongest ill-will against the magistrates and judges. When natural reason, therefore, points out no fixed view of public utility by which a controversy of property can be decided, positive laws are often framed to supply its place, and direct the procedure of all courts of judicature. Where these too fail, as often happens, precedents are called for; and a former decision, though given itself without any sufficient reason, justly becomes a sufficient reason for a new decision. If direct laws and precedents be wanting, imperfect and indirect ones are brought in aid; and the controverted case is ranged under them by analogical reasonings and comparisons, and similitudes, and correspondencies, which are often more fanciful than real. In general, it may safely be affirmed that jurisprudence is, in this respect, different from all the sciences; and that in many of its nicer questions, there cannot properly be said to be truth or falsehood on either side. If one pleader bring the case under any former law or precedent, by a refined analogy or comparison; the opposite pleader is not at a loss to find an opposite analogy or comparison: and the preference given by the judge is often founded more on taste and imagination than on any solid argument. Public utility is the general object of all courts of judicature; and this utility too requires a stable rule in all controversies: but where several rules, nearly equal and indifferent, present themselves, it is a very slight turn of thought which fixes the decision in favour of either party.

Among all civilized nations, there has always been a consistent effort to eliminate anything arbitrary or biased from property decisions and to establish judges' rulings based on general principles that apply equally to every member of society. After all, nothing could be more dangerous than allowing judges, even in minor cases, to consider personal friendships or hostilities; it's clear that when people believe their opponent’s advantage is solely due to personal favoritism, they often develop strong resentment toward the magistrates and judges. Therefore, when common sense does not indicate a clear public benefit for resolving a property dispute, specific laws are frequently created to fill that gap and guide the operation of all courts. When these laws are lacking, as often occurs, precedents are sought; a prior decision, even if made without adequate reasoning, rightfully becomes enough justification for a new ruling. If there are no explicit laws or precedents, imperfect and indirect ones are introduced, and the disputed case is categorized under them through analogies, comparisons, and similarities, which can often be more imaginative than factual. Generally, it can be safely stated that the field of law is different from all other sciences; and that in many of its more delicate matters, there isn’t necessarily a right or wrong on either side. If one attorney uses a past law or precedent through a nuanced analogy, the opposing attorney will easily find a contrasting analogy or comparison. The preference given by the judge often relies more on personal taste and imagination than on solid argumentation. Public utility is the primary goal of all courts; and this utility also requires a consistent rule in all disputes: however, when multiple rules that are nearly equal and indifferent arise, it only takes a slight shift in perspective to determine the ruling in favor of one side or the other.

     [Footnote: That there be a separation or distinction of
     possessions, and that this separation be steady and
     constant; this is absolutely required by the interests of
     society, and hence the origin of justice and property. What
     possessions are assigned to particular persons; this is,
     generally speaking, pretty indifferent; and is often
     determined by very frivolous views and considerations. We
     shall mention a few particulars.

     Were a society formed among several independent members, the
     most obvious rule, which could be agreed on, would be to
     annex property to PRESENT possession, and leave every one a
     right to what he at present enjoys. The relation of
     possession, which takes place between the person and the
     object, naturally draws on the relation of property.

     For a like reason, occupation or first possession becomes
     the foundation of property.

     Where a man bestows labour and industry upon any object,
     which before belonged to no body; as in cutting down and
     shaping a tree, in cultivating a field, &c., the
     alterations, which he produces, causes a relation between
     him and the object, and naturally engages us to annex it to
     him by the new relation of property. This cause here concurs
     with the public utility, which consists in the encouragement
     given to industry and labour.

     Perhaps too, private humanity towards the possessor concurs,
     in this instance, with the other motives, and engages us to
     leave with him what he has acquired by his sweat and labour;
     and what he has flattered himself in the constant enjoyment
     of. For though private humanity can, by no means, be the
     origin of justice; since the latter virtue so often
     contradicts the former; yet when the rule of separate and
     constant possession is once formed by the indispensable
     necessities of society, private humanity, and an aversion to
     the doing a hardship to another, may, in a particular
     instance, give rise to a particular rule of property.

     I am much inclined to think, that the right succession or
     inheritance much depends on those connexions of the
     imagination, and that the relation to a former proprietor
     begetting a relation to the object, is the cause why the
     property is transferred to a man after the death of his
     kinsman. It is true; industry is more encouraged by the
     transference of possession to children or near relations:
     but this consideration will only have place in a cultivated
     society; whereas the right of succession is regarded even
     among the greatest Barbarians.

     Acquisition of property by accession can be explained no way
     but by having recourse to the relations and connexions of
     the imaginations.

     The property of rivers, by the laws of most nations, and by
     the natural turn of our thoughts, is attributed to the
     proprietors of their banks, excepting such vast rivers as
     the Rhine or the Danube, which seem too large to follow as
     an accession to the property of the neighbouring fields. Yet
     even these rivers are considered as the property of that
     nation, through whose dominions they run; the idea of a
     nation being of a suitable bulk to correspond with them, and
     bear them such a relation in the fancy.

     The accessions, which are made to land, bordering upon
     rivers, follow the land, say the civilians, provided it be
     made by what they call alluvion, that is, insensibly and
     imperceptibly; which are circumstances, that assist the
     imagination in the conjunction.

     Where there is any considerable portion torn at once from
     one bank and added to another, it becomes not his property,
     whose land it falls on, till it unite with the land, and
     till the trees and plants have spread their roots into both.
     Before that, the thought does not sufficiently join them.

     In short, we must ever distinguish between the necessity of
     a separation and constancy in men's possession, and the
     rules, which assign particular objects to particular
     persons. The first necessity is obvious, strong, and
     invincible: the latter may depend on a public utility more
     light and frivolous, on the sentiment of private humanity
     and aversion to private hardship, on positive laws, on
     precedents, analogies, and very fine connexions and turns of
     the imagination.]
[Footnote: There needs to be a clear separation of possessions, and this separation must be consistent; this is essential for the welfare of society and thus the foundation of justice and property. Which possessions are assigned to specific individuals is generally quite arbitrary and often determined by trivial reasons. We will mention a few specifics.

If a society were formed among several independent individuals, the most straightforward rule they could agree on would be to tie property to current possession, allowing everyone to keep what they are currently enjoying. The relationship of possession that occurs between a person and an object naturally leads to the property relationship.

For similar reasons, taking possession or being the first to possess something becomes the basis of property.

When a person puts labor and effort into an object that previously belonged to no one—like cutting down and shaping a tree, or cultivating a field—the changes they create establish a connection between them and the object, which leads us to assign property rights to them based on this new relationship. This rationale also aligns with the public good, which lies in encouraging hard work and effort.

Additionally, a sense of personal humanity towards the possessor might play a role here as well, leading us to allow them to keep what they have earned through their effort and what they have enjoyed consistently. While personal humanity can never be the source of justice (since justice often contradicts it), once the rule of separate and consistent possession is established by the essential needs of society, personal humanity and a desire to avoid causing hardship to others might create a specific property rule in some cases.

I strongly believe that the rightful succession or inheritance significantly depends on these imaginative connections, and the relationship to a former owner links to the object, which explains why property is transferred to someone after a family member's death. While it's true that the transfer of possession to children or close relatives encourages industry, this consideration only applies in a developed society; however, the right of succession is acknowledged even among the most uncivilized peoples.

Acquiring property through addition can only be understood by referring to the relationships and connections of the imagination.

In most countries, the ownership of rivers, and our natural thought processes, attribute them to the owners of their banks, except for large rivers like the Rhine or the Danube, which seem too vast to be considered merely an addition to the neighboring fields. Yet even these rivers are deemed the property of the nation through which they flow since the concept of a nation aligns well with their scale and holds a related sense in our minds.

According to legal experts, any additions made to land bordering rivers are considered part of that land, as long as they occur through what they call gradual alluvion—insignificantly and imperceptibly. These circumstances help our imagination in making that connection.

When a significant piece of land is abruptly taken from one bank and added to another, it doesn't become the property of the owner of the land it falls on until it merges with the land and the trees and plants have established their roots in both. Until that point, our thoughts do not sufficiently connect them.

In summary, we must always differentiate between the need for a separation and stability in people's possessions and the rules that assign specific objects to specific individuals. The first necessity is clear, strong, and undeniable; the latter may rely on lighter and more trivial public interests, private humanity sentiments, aversions to hardship, positive laws, precedents, analogies, and subtle connections and nuances of the imagination.]

We may just observe, before we conclude this subject, that after the laws of justice are fixed by views of general utility, the injury, the hardship, the harm, which result to any individual from a violation of them, enter very much into consideration, and are a great source of that universal blame which attends every wrong or iniquity. By the laws of society, this coat, this horse is mine, and OUGHT to remain perpetually in my possession: I reckon on the secure enjoyment of it: by depriving me of it, you disappoint my expectations, and doubly displease me, and offend every bystander. It is a public wrong, so far as the rules of equity are violated: it is a private harm, so far as an individual is injured. And though the second consideration could have no place, were not the former previously established: for otherwise the distinction of MINE and THINE would be unknown in society: yet there is no question but the regard to general good is much enforced by the respect to particular. What injures the community, without hurting any individual, is often more lightly thought of. But where the greatest public wrong is also conjoined with a considerable private one, no wonder the highest disapprobation attends so iniquitous a behaviour.

Before we wrap up this topic, it’s worth noting that once the principles of justice are established based on general utility, the injury, hardship, and harm that affect any individual due to a violation of these principles are very important to consider. They contribute significantly to the universal condemnation that follows every wrongdoing or injustice. According to the laws of society, this coat, this horse belongs to me and should always stay in my possession. I expect to enjoy them safely; when you take them from me, you crush my expectations and upset me even more, offending everyone who witnesses it. It constitutes a public wrong, as the rules of fairness are breached, and it represents a private harm, as an individual suffers. Although the second consideration wouldn’t matter if the first hadn’t been established, since otherwise, the distinction between MINE and YOURS wouldn’t exist in society, it’s clear that concern for the common good is significantly strengthened by regard for individual interests. What harms the community without affecting any single person is often seen as less serious. However, when a significant public wrong coincides with a substantial private one, it’s no surprise that such immoral behavior attracts the strongest disapproval.





APPENDIX IV. OF SOME VERBAL DISPUTES.

Nothing is more usual than for philosophers to encroach upon the province of grammarians; and to engage in disputes of words, while they imagine that they are handling controversies of the deepest importance and concern. It was in order to avoid altercations, so frivolous and endless, that I endeavoured to state with the utmost caution the object of our present enquiry; and proposed simply to collect, on the one hand, a list of those mental qualities which are the object of love or esteem, and form a part of personal merit; and on the other hand, a catalogue of those qualities which are the object of censure or reproach, and which detract from the character of the person possessed of them; subjoining some reflections concerning the origin of these sentiments of praise or blame. On all occasions, where there might arise the least hesitation, I avoided the terms VIRTUE and VICE; because some of those qualities, which I classed among the objects of praise, receive, in the English language, the appellation of TALENTS, rather than of virtues; as some of the blameable or censurable qualities are often called defects, rather than vices. It may now, perhaps, be expected that before we conclude this moral enquiry, we should exactly separate the one from the other; should mark the precise boundaries of virtues and talents, vices and defects; and should explain the reason and origin of that distinction. But in order to excuse myself from this undertaking, which would, at last, prove only a grammatical enquiry, I shall subjoin the four following reflections, which shall contain all that I intend to say on the present subject.

Nothing is more common than for philosophers to intrude into the area of grammarians and to get into debates over words, believing they are tackling issues of great importance. To avoid pointless and endless arguments, I tried to clearly outline the focus of our current inquiry. I aimed to compile, on one hand, a list of mental qualities that are admired or valued and contribute to a person's worth; and on the other hand, a list of qualities that are criticized or scorned and diminish a person's character, along with some thoughts on the origin of these feelings of praise or blame. Whenever there was even a little uncertainty, I steered clear of the terms VIRTUE and VICE because some of the qualities I listed as praiseworthy are called TALENTS in English rather than virtues, just as some blameworthy qualities are often referred to as defects instead of vices. It might be expected that before we wrap up this moral inquiry, we would clearly distinguish between the two; delineate the exact boundaries of virtues and talents, vices and defects; and explain the reason and origin of that distinction. However, to excuse myself from this task, which would ultimately just become a grammatical discussion, I will add the following four reflections that include everything I intend to address on this topic.

First, I do not find that in the English, or any other modern tongue, the boundaries are exactly fixed between virtues and talents, vices and defects, or that a precise definition can be given of the one as contradistinguished from the other. Were we to say, for instance, that the esteemable qualities alone, which are voluntary, are entitled to the appellations of virtues; we should soon recollect the qualities of courage, equanimity, patience, self-command; with many others, which almost every language classes under this appellation, though they depend little or not at all on our choice. Should we affirm that the qualities alone, which prompt us to act our part in society, are entitled to that honourable distinction; it must immediately occur that these are indeed the most valuable qualities, and are commonly denominated the SOCIAL virtues; but that this very epithet supposes that there are also virtues of another species. Should we lay hold of the distinction between INTELLECTUAL and MORAL endowments, and affirm the last alone to be the real and genuine virtues, because they alone lead to action; we should find that many of those qualities, usually called intellectual virtues, such as prudence, penetration, discernment, discretion, had also a considerable influence on conduct. The distinction between the heart and the head may also be adopted: the qualities of the first may be defined such as in their immediate exertion are accompanied with a feeling of sentiment; and these alone may be called the genuine virtues: but industry, frugality, temperance, secrecy, perseverance, and many other laudable powers or habits, generally stilled virtues are exerted without any immediate sentiment in the person possessed of them, and are only known to him by their effects. It is fortunate, amidst all this seeming perplexity, that the question, being merely verbal, cannot possibly be of any importance. A moral, philosophical discourse needs not enter into all these caprices of language, which are so variable in different dialects, and in different ages of the same dialect. But on the whole, it seems to me, that though it is always allowed, that there are virtues of many different kinds, yet, when a man is called virtuous, or is denominated a man of virtue, we chiefly regard his social qualities, which are, indeed, the most valuable. It is, at the same time, certain, that any remarkable defect in courage, temperance, economy, industry, understanding, dignity of mind, would bereave even a very good-natured, honest man of this honourable appellation. Who did ever say, except by way of irony, that such a one was a man of great virtue, but an egregious blockhead?

First, I don’t think that in English, or any other modern language, the lines are clearly drawn between virtues and talents, vices and flaws, nor can we give a precise definition that distinguishes one from the other. For instance, if we were to say that only voluntary admirable qualities are worthy of being called virtues, we would quickly remember qualities like courage, calmness, patience, and self-control; along with many others that almost every language classifies as virtues, even though they rely little or not at all on our choice. If we claim that only the qualities that motivate us to play our roles in society deserve that honorable title, it must immediately be noted that these are indeed the most valuable qualities, commonly referred to as SOCIAL virtues; but this very term implies that there are also virtues of a different kind. If we focus on the difference between INTELLECTUAL and MORAL traits, and assert that only the latter are true virtues because they lead to action, we would find that many traits usually called intellectual virtues, like wisdom, insight, discernment, and discretion, also have a significant impact on behavior. We could also adopt the distinction between the heart and the head: the qualities of the heart can be defined as those that, when directly exercised, come with a feeling of sentiment, and these alone might be termed genuine virtues. Yet qualities like hard work, thrift, self-control, secrecy, perseverance, and many other commendable traits or habits, commonly still considered virtues, are often displayed without any immediate feeling by the person who possesses them and are only recognized through their effects. It’s fortunate, amidst all this apparent confusion, that the question is merely one of wording and can’t possibly be important. A moral or philosophical discussion doesn’t need to delve into all these quirks of language, which vary widely across different dialects and across different times in the same dialect. Overall, it seems to me that while it's always acknowledged that there are many different kinds of virtues, when someone is called virtuous or is described as a person of virtue, we primarily think of their social qualities, which are indeed the most valuable. At the same time, it's certain that any noticeable shortcoming in courage, temperance, frugality, diligence, understanding, or dignity would strip even a very kind and honest person of this honorable title. Who has ever said, except in jest, that someone was a person of great virtue but an incredible fool?

But, Secondly, it is no wonder that languages should not be very precise in marking the boundaries between virtues and talents, vices and defects; since there is so little distinction made in our internal estimation of them. It seems indeed certain, that the SENTIMENT of conscious worth, the self-satisfaction proceeding from a review of a man's own conduct and character; it seems certain, I say, that this sentiment, which, though the most common of all others, has no proper name in our language,

But, secondly, it’s not surprising that languages aren’t very precise in distinguishing between virtues and talents, or vices and shortcomings; because there’s so little difference made in how we perceive them internally. It really does seem certain that the feeling of self-worth, the self-satisfaction that comes from reflecting on a person’s own actions and character; it seems certain, I mean, that this feeling, which, although the most common of all, has no specific name in our language,

     [Footnote: The term, pride, is commonly taken in a bad sense; but
this sentiment seems indifferent, and may be either good or bad,
according as it is well or ill founded, and according to the other
circumstances which accompany it. The French express this sentiment by
the term, AMOUR PROPRE, but as they also express self-love as well
as vanity by the same term, there arises thence a great confusion in
Rochefoucault, and many of their moral writers.]
[Footnote: The term "pride" is often viewed negatively; however, this feeling can be neutral and can be either positive or negative depending on its foundation and the accompanying circumstances. The French use the phrase AMOUR PROPRE to express this feeling, but since they also use it to describe self-love and vanity, this leads to a lot of confusion in Rochefoucault and many of their moral writers.]

arises from the endowments of courage and capacity, industry and ingenuity, as well as from any other mental excellencies. Who, on the other hand, is not deeply mortified with reflecting on his own folly and dissoluteness, and feels not a secret sting or compunction whenever his memory presents any past occurrence, where he behaved with stupidity of ill-manners? No time can efface the cruel ideas of a man's own foolish conduct, or of affronts, which cowardice or impudence has brought upon him. They still haunt his solitary hours, damp his most aspiring thoughts, and show him, even to himself, in the most contemptible and most odious colours imaginable.

arises from the gifts of bravery and ability, hard work and creativity, as well as from any other mental strengths. Who, on the other hand, isn’t deeply embarrassed when reflecting on their own foolishness and bad behavior, and doesn’t feel a secret sting or guilt whenever they recall a moment from the past where they acted stupidly or rudely? No amount of time can erase the painful memories of a person’s own poor choices or of insults brought upon them by their own cowardice or shamelessness. They continue to haunt their quiet moments, dampen their most ambitious thoughts, and present them, even to themselves, in the most despicable and repulsive ways imaginable.

What is there too we are more anxious to conceal from others than such blunders, infirmities, and meannesses, or more dread to have exposed by raillery and satire? And is not the chief object of vanity, our bravery or learning, our wit or breeding, our eloquence or address, our taste or abilities? These we display with care, if not with ostentation; and we commonly show more ambition of excelling in them, than even in the social virtues themselves, which are, in reality, of such superior excellence. Good-nature and honesty, especially the latter, are so indispensably required, that, though the greatest censure attends any violation of these duties, no eminent praise follows such common instances of them, as seem essential to the support of human society. And hence the reason, in my opinion, why, though men often extol so liberally the qualities of their heart, they are shy in commending the endowments of their head: because the latter virtues, being supposed more rare and extraordinary, are observed to be the more usual objects of pride and self-conceit; and when boasted of, beget a strong suspicion of these sentiments.

What do we tend to hide from others more than our mistakes, weaknesses, and unkindnesses, or dread having them exposed through mockery and sarcasm? Isn't the main focus of vanity our courage or knowledge, our humor or upbringing, our eloquence or charm, our taste or skills? We showcase these with care, if not with showiness; and we usually have more desire to excel in these than even in the social virtues, which are, in truth, of much greater importance. Good nature and honesty, especially the latter, are so essential that, although there is a significant backlash for violating these duties, there’s not much praise for those common displays, which are crucial for maintaining human society. This is, in my view, why, although people often praise their heart's qualities, they are hesitant to commend the qualities of their mind: because the latter are seen as rarer and more exceptional, and they tend to be the usual sources of pride and self-importance; boasting about them raises strong suspicions about those feelings.

It is hard to tell, whether you hurt a man's character most by calling him a knave or a coward, and whether a beastly glutton or drunkard be not as odious and contemptible, as a selfish, ungenerous miser. Give me my choice, and I would rather, for my own happiness and self-enjoyment, have a friendly, humane heart, than possess all the other virtues of Demosthenes and Philip united: but I would rather pass with the world for one endowed with extensive genius and intrepid courage, and should thence expect stronger instances of general applause and admiration. The figure which a man makes in life, the reception which he meets with in company, the esteem paid him by his acquaintance; all these advantages depend as much upon his good sense and judgement, as upon any other part of his character. Had a man the best intentions in the world, and were the farthest removed from all injustice and violence, he would never be able to make himself be much regarded, without a moderate share, at least, of parts and understanding.

It's tough to say whether calling a man a jerk or a coward hurts his character more, or if a glutton or a drunk is as disgusting and contemptible as a selfish miser. If I had to choose, I'd prefer to have a kind, compassionate heart for my own happiness and enjoyment rather than all the virtues of Demosthenes and Philip combined. However, I'd rather be seen by the world as someone with great talent and brave courage, as that would likely earn me more general applause and admiration. The impression a man makes in life, the way he's received in social settings, and the respect he gets from his peers all depend as much on his common sense and judgment as on any other aspect of his character. Even if a man had the best intentions and was completely free of injustice and violence, he wouldn't be able to gain much respect without at least a moderate amount of intelligence and understanding.

What is it then we can here dispute about? If sense and courage, temperance and industry, wisdom and knowledge confessedly form a considerable part of PERSONAL MERIT: if a man, possessed of these qualities, is both better satisfied with himself, and better entitled to the good-will, esteem, and services of others, than one entirely destitute of them; if, in short, the SENTIMENTS are similar which arise from these endowments and from the social virtues; is there any reason for being so extremely scrupulous about a WORD, or disputing whether they be entitled to the denomination of virtues? It may, indeed, be pretended, that the sentiment of approbation, which those accomplishments produce, besides its being INFERIOR, is also somewhat DIFFERENT from that which attends the virtues of justice and humanity. But this seems not a sufficient reason for ranking them entirely under different classes and appellations. The character of Caesar and that of Cato, as drawn by Sallust, are both of them virtuous, in the strictest and most limited sense of the word; but in a different way: nor are the sentiments entirely the same which arise from them. The one produces love, the other esteem: the one is amiable, the other awful: we should wish to meet the one character in a friend; the other we should be ambitious of in ourselves. In like manner the approbation, which attends temperance or industry or frugality, may be somewhat different from that which is paid to the social virtues, without making them entirely of a different species. And, indeed, we may observe, that these endowments, more than the other virtues, produce not, all of them, the same kind of approbation. Good sense and genius beget esteem and regard: wit and humour excite love and affection.

What can we really argue about here? If qualities like sense and courage, temperance and hard work, wisdom and knowledge clearly make up a significant part of PERSONAL MERIT: if a person with these traits is both more satisfied with themselves and more deserving of goodwill, respect, and help from others than someone who lacks them entirely; if, in short, the FEELINGS that come from these qualities and from social virtues are similar; is there any reason to be so picky about a WORD, or to debate if they deserve to be called virtues? It might be argued that the feeling of approval generated by those qualities, besides being INFERIOR, is also somewhat DIFFERENT from that which comes with the virtues of justice and humanity. But that doesn’t seem like a strong enough reason to place them in completely different categories and labels. The characters of Caesar and Cato, as described by Sallust, are both virtuous in the strictest sense; but in different ways: and the feelings they evoke aren’t entirely the same. One inspires love, while the other inspires respect: one is charming, the other intimidating: we would want the first character as a friend; the second is what we would aspire to be. Similarly, the approval we give to temperance, hard work, or frugality may feel a bit different from the approval given to social virtues, without making them a completely different type of virtue. In fact, we can see that these qualities, more than other virtues, don’t always produce the same kind of approval. Good judgment and talent inspire respect and appreciation: wit and humor evoke love and affection.

     [Footnote: Love and esteem are nearly the same passion, and arise
from similar causes. The qualities, which produce both, are such as
communicate pleasures. But where this pleasure is severe and serious;
or where its object is great, and makes a strong impression, or where
it produces any degree of humility and awe; in all these cases, the
passion, which arises from the pleasure, is more properly denominated
esteem than love. Benevolence attends both; but is connected with love
in a more eminent degree. There seems to be still a stronger mixture of
pride in contempt than of humility in esteem; and the reason would not
be difficulty to one, who studied accurately the passions. All these
various mixtures and compositions and appearances of sentiment from
a very curious subject of speculation, but are wide for our present
purpose. Throughout this enquiry, we always consider in general, what
qualities are a subject of praise or of censure, without entering
into all the minute differences of sentiment, which they excite. It is
evident, that whatever is contemned, is also disliked, as well as what
is hated; and we here endeavour to take objects, according to their most
simple views and appearances. These sciences are but too apt to appear
abstract to common readers, even with all the precautions which we can
take to clear them from superfluous speculations, and bring them down to
every capacity.]
[Footnote: Love and respect are almost the same feeling, stemming from similar sources. The traits that create both are those that bring pleasure. However, when this pleasure is intense and serious; when its object is significant and leaves a strong impact, or when it evokes any level of humility and awe; in those cases, the feeling that arises from this pleasure is more accurately called respect than love. Kindness is a part of both, but it's more closely tied to love. There seems to be a stronger element of pride in contempt than humility in respect; and this wouldn't be hard to see for someone who looks closely at feelings. All these different combinations and manifestations of emotions provide a fascinating topic for discussion, but they are too broad for our current purpose. Throughout this inquiry, we generally focus on what qualities are praiseworthy or blameworthy, without diving into all the minor differences in feelings they provoke. It is clear that anything that is scorned is also disliked, just like what is hated; and here we aim to consider things in their simplest forms and appearances. These subjects can seem overly abstract to everyday readers, even with all the effort we make to strip them of unnecessary speculation and make them accessible to everyone.]

Most people, I believe, will naturally, without premeditation, assent to the definition of the elegant and judicious poet:

Most people, I think, will naturally, without thinking it through, agree with the definition of the stylish and thoughtful poet:

Virtue (for mere good-nature is a fool) Is sense and spirit with humanity.

Virtue (because just being kind is foolish) is wisdom and energy combined with humanity.

     [Footnote: The Art of preserving Health. Book 4]
     [Footnote: The Art of Preserving Health. Book 4]

What pretensions has a man to our generous assistance or good offices, who has dissipated his wealth in profuse expenses, idle vanities, chimerical projects, dissolute pleasures or extravagant gaming? These vices (for we scruple not to call them such) bring misery unpitied, and contempt on every one addicted to them.

What claims does a man have to our generous help or support if he has wasted his wealth on lavish spending, pointless pursuits, unrealistic plans, reckless pleasures, or excessive gambling? These vices (and we don’t hesitate to call them that) lead to misery without compassion and scorn for anyone who is caught up in them.

Achaeus, a wise and prudent prince, fell into a fatal snare, which cost him his crown and life, after having used every reasonable precaution to guard himself against it. On that account, says the historian, he is a just object of regard and compassion: his betrayers alone of hatred and contempt [Footnote: Polybius, lib. iii. cap. 2].

Achaeus, a wise and careful prince, fell into a deadly trap that cost him his crown and his life, despite taking every reasonable precaution to protect himself. For this reason, the historian says he deserves our sympathy and compassion; only his betrayers deserve hatred and contempt [Footnote: Polybius, lib. iii. cap. 2].

The precipitate flight and improvident negligence of Pompey, at the beginning of the civil wars, appeared such notorious blunders to Cicero, as quite palled his friendship towards that great man. In the same manner, says he, as want of cleanliness, decency, or discretion in a mistress are found to alienate our affections. For so he expresses himself, where he talks, not in the character of a philosopher, but in that of a statesman and man of the world, to his friend Atticus. [Lib. ix. epist. 10]. But the same Cicero, in imitation of all the ancient moralists, when he reasons as a philosopher, enlarges very much his ideas of virtue, and comprehends every laudable quality or endowment of the mind, under that honourable appellation. This leads to the THIRD reflection, which we proposed to make, to wit, that the ancient moralists, the best models, made no material distinction among the different species of mental endowments and defects, but treated all alike under the appellation of virtues and vices, and made them indiscriminately the object of their moral reasonings. The prudence explained in Cicero's Offices [Footnote: Lib. i. cap. 6.] is that sagacity, which leads to the discovery of truth, and preserves us from error and mistake. MAGNANIMITY, TEMPERANCE, DECENCY, are there also at large discoursed of. And as that eloquent moralist followed the common received division of the four cardinal virtues, our social duties form but one head, in the general distribution of his subject.

The hasty retreat and careless decisions of Pompey at the start of the civil wars seemed like such obvious mistakes to Cicero that it significantly strained his friendship with that great man. He likens it to how a lack of cleanliness, decency, or discretion in a partner can drive us away. This is how he expresses himself when he speaks not as a philosopher but as a politician and a savvy individual to his friend Atticus. [Lib. ix. epist. 10]. However, the same Cicero, following the example of ancient moralists, expands greatly on his ideas of virtue when he discusses philosophy and includes every admirable quality or mental trait under that noble term. This leads to the THIRD reflection we intended to address: namely, that the ancient moralists, as excellent models, made no significant distinctions among different types of mental strengths and weaknesses, treating them all similarly as virtues or vices, and made them all subjects of their moral discussions. The prudence outlined in Cicero's Offices [Footnote: Lib. i. cap. 6.] is the insight that helps us discover truth and protects us from errors and mistakes. MAGNANIMITY, TEMPERANCE, and DECENCY are also discussed in detail there. As that eloquent moralist adhered to the commonly accepted division of the four cardinal virtues, our social responsibilities fall under just one category in the overall organization of his topic.

     [Footnote: The following passage of Cicero is worth quoting, as
being the most clear and express to our purpose, that any thing can be
imagined, and, in a dispute, which is chiefly verbal, must, on account
of the author, carry an authority, from which there can be no appeal.
     [Footnote: The following passage from Cicero is worth quoting, as it is the clearest and most relevant to our purpose that one could imagine, and in a dispute that is mainly verbal, it must carry an authority from the author that cannot be challenged.]

'Virtus autem, quae est per se ipsa laudabilis, et sine qua nihil laudari potest, tamen habet plures partes, quarum alia est alia ad laudationem aptior. Sunt enim aliae virtutes, quae videntur in moribus hominum, et quadam comitate ac beneficentia positae: aliae quae in ingenii aliqua facultate, aut animi magnitudine ac robore. Nam clementia, justitia, benignitas, fides, fortitudo in periculis communibus, jucunda est auditu in laudationibus. Omnes enim hae virtutes non tam ipsis, qui eas in se habent, quam generi hominum fructuosae putantur. Sapientia et magnitude animi, qua omnes res humanae tenues et pro nihilo putantur, et in cogitando vis quaedam ingenii, et ipsa eloquentia admirationis habet non minus, jucunditatis minus. Ipsos enim magis videntur, quos laudamus, quam illos, apud quos laudamus ornare ac tueri: sed tamen in laudenda jungenda sunt eliam haec genera virtutum. Ferunt enim aures bominum, cum ilia quae jucunda et grata, tum etiam ilia, quae mirabilia sunt in virtute, laudari.' De orat. lib. ii. cap. 84.

'Virtue, which is commendable in itself and without which nothing can be praised, has several parts, some of which are more suited for praise than others. There are virtues that seem to be in people's character, manifesting in kindness and generosity: others that stem from intellectual ability or the strength and courage of the mind. For example, compassion, justice, kindness, faith, and bravery in common dangers are pleasing to hear in praises. All of these virtues are considered beneficial more for humanity as a whole than for the individuals who possess them. Wisdom and the greatness of spirit, which regard all human matters as insignificant, along with a certain intellectual capacity in thinking, and even eloquence, evoke admiration, though they offer less joy. Indeed, we seem to praise those whom we admire more than those among whom we seek to adorn and support: yet, all these types of virtues should also be connected in praise. For it is claimed that people's ears welcome not only what is pleasant and agreeable but also what is wonderful in virtue.' De orat. lib. ii. cap. 84.

I suppose, if Cicero were now alive, it would be found difficult to fetter his moral sentiments by narrow systems; or persuade him, that no qualities were to be admitted as virtues, or acknowledged to be a part of PERSONAL MERIT, but what were recommended by The Whole Duty of Man.]

I guess if Cicero were alive today, it would be tough to limit his moral views to rigid systems or convince him that only the qualities recommended by The Whole Duty of Man could be considered virtues or part of PERSONAL MERIT.

We need only peruse the titles of chapters in Aristotle's Ethics to be convinced that he ranks courage, temperance, magnificence, magnanimity, modesty, prudence, and a manly openness, among the virtues, as well as justice and friendship.

We only need to look at the chapter titles in Aristotle's Ethics to see that he considers courage, temperance, magnificence, generosity, modesty, wisdom, and a straightforward honesty as virtues, alongside justice and friendship.

To SUSTAIN and to ABSTAIN, that is, to be patient and continent, appeared to some of the ancients a summary comprehension of all morals.

To SUSTAIN and to ABSTAIN, meaning to be patient and self-controlled, seemed to some of the ancients a complete understanding of all morals.

Epictetus has scarcely ever mentioned the sentiment of humanity and compassion, but in order to put his disciples on their guard against it. The virtue of the Stoics seems to consist chiefly in a firm temper and a sound understanding. With them, as with Solomon and the eastern moralists, folly and wisdom are equivalent to vice and virtue.

Epictetus hardly ever talked about feelings of humanity and compassion, but only to warn his students about them. The Stoics’ virtue seems to mainly lie in a strong mindset and clear thinking. For them, just like with Solomon and the Eastern moralists, foolishness and wisdom are seen as the same as vice and virtue.

Men will praise thee, says David, [Footnote: Psalm 49th.] when thou dost well unto thyself. I hate a wise man, says the Greek poet, who is not wise to himself [Footnote: Here, Hume quotes Euripedes in Greek]. Plutarch is no more cramped by systems in his philosophy than in his history. Where he compares the great men of Greece and Rome, he fairly sets in opposition all their blemishes and accomplishments of whatever kind, and omits nothing considerable, which can either depress or exalt their characters. His moral discourses contain the same free and natural censure of men and manners.

Men will praise you, says David, [Footnote: Psalm 49th.] when you do well for yourself. I dislike a wise man, says the Greek poet, who isn’t wise for himself [Footnote: Here, Hume quotes Euripides in Greek]. Plutarch isn’t restricted by systems in his philosophy any more than in his history. When he compares the great figures of Greece and Rome, he honestly lays out all their flaws and achievements of any kind and leaves out nothing significant that could either bring down or elevate their characters. His moral essays also offer the same open and straightforward critique of people and their behaviors.

The character of Hannibal, as drawn by Livy, [Footnote: Lib. xxi. cap. 4] is esteemed partial, but allows him many eminent virtues. Never was there a genius, says the historian, more equally fitted for those opposite offices of commanding and obeying; and it were, therefore, difficult to determine whether he rendered himself DEARER to the general or to the army. To none would Hasdrubal entrust more willingly the conduct of any dangerous enterprize; under none did the soldiers discover more courage and confidence. Great boldness in facing danger; great prudence in the midst of it. No labour could fatigue his body or subdue his mind. Cold and heat were indifferent to him: meat and drink he sought as supplies to the necessities of nature, not as gratifications of his voluptuous appetites. Waking or rest he used indiscriminately, by night or by day.—These great Virtues were balanced by great Vices; inhuman cruelty; perfidy more than punic; no truth, no faith, no regard to oaths, promises, or religion.

The character of Hannibal, as portrayed by Livy, [Footnote: Lib. xxi. cap. 4] is seen as biased, yet he possesses many outstanding qualities. Never was there a mind, says the historian, better suited for the conflicting roles of leading and following; therefore, it's hard to say whether he was more beloved by the general or the army. Hasdrubal would more willingly trust him with the leadership of any risky mission; under him, the soldiers displayed more courage and confidence. He showed great boldness in the face of danger and great prudence in the midst of it. No amount of labor could wear him out or break his spirit. He was indifferent to cold and heat; he viewed food and drink merely as necessities of life, not as indulgences for pleasure. He used waking and resting interchangeably, whether it was day or night. —These great virtues were matched by great vices: inhuman cruelty, betrayal worse than that of the Punics; no truth, no faith, no respect for oaths, promises, or religion.

The character of Alexander the Sixth, to be found in Guicciardin, [Footnote: Lib. i.] is pretty similar, but juster; and is a proof that even the moderns, where they speak naturally, hold the same language with the ancients. In this pope, says he, there was a singular capacity and judgement: admirable prudence; a wonderful talent of persuasion; and in all momentous enterprizes a diligence and dexterity incredible. But these VIRTUES were infinitely overbalanced by his VICES; no faith, no religion, insatiable avarice, exorbitant ambition, and a more than barbarous cruelty.

The character of Alexander the Sixth, as described by Guicciardin, is quite similar but more accurate, showing that even modern writers, when they speak naturally, use the same language as the ancients. He notes that this pope had exceptional ability and judgment, remarkable prudence, a great talent for persuasion, and incredible diligence and skill in all important endeavors. However, these VIRTUES were far outweighed by his VICES: no faith, no religion, insatiable greed, extreme ambition, and a cruelty that was more than barbaric.

Polybius, [Footnote: Lib. xii.] reprehending Timaeus for his partiality against Agathocles, whom he himself allows to be the most cruel and impious of all tyrants, says: if he took refuge in Syracuse, as asserted by that historian, flying the dirt and smoke and toil of his former profession of a potter; and if proceeding from such slender beginnings, he became master, in a little time, of all Sicily; brought the Carthaginian state into the utmost danger; and at last died in old age, and in possession of sovereign dignity: must he not be allowed something prodigious and extraordinary, and to have possessed great talents and capacity for business and action? His historian, therefore, ought not to have alone related what tended to his reproach and infamy; but also what might redound to his Praise and Honour.

Polybius, [Footnote: Lib. xii.] criticizing Timaeus for being biased against Agathocles, whom he admits is the most cruel and godless of all tyrants, argues: if Agathocles really took refuge in Syracuse, as that historian claims, escaping the dirt, smoke, and hard work of his previous job as a potter; and if, starting from such humble beginnings, he quickly became the ruler of all Sicily; put the Carthaginian state in serious jeopardy; and ultimately died of old age while holding a position of power: shouldn't he be recognized for something remarkable and extraordinary, and acknowledged for his considerable skills and ability in business and action? Therefore, his historian shouldn't have only mentioned what cast him in a negative light, but also what could reflect positively on his reputation and honor.

In general, we may observe, that the distinction of voluntary or involuntary was little regarded by the ancients in their moral reasonings; where they frequently treated the question as very doubtful, WHETHER VIRTUE COULD BE TAUGHT OR NOT [Vid. Plato in Menone, Seneca de otio sap. cap. 31. So also Horace, Virtutem doctrina paret, naturane donet, Epist. lib. I. ep. 18. Aeschines Socraticus, Dial. I.]? They justly considered that cowardice, meanness, levity, anxiety, impatience, folly, and many other qualities of the mind, might appear ridiculous and deformed, contemptible and odious, though independent of the will. Nor could it be supposed, at all times, in every man's power to attain every kind of mental more than of exterior beauty.

Generally speaking, we can observe that the distinction between voluntary and involuntary actions was not highly regarded by the ancients in their moral discussions. They often debated the question of whether virtue could actually be taught or not [See Plato in Meno, Seneca on idle wisdom, chapter 31. Also Horace, Virtue is shaped by education or given by nature, Epistles, Book I, Epistle 18. Aeschines Socraticus, Dialogue I.] They rightly believed that qualities like cowardice, meanness, frivolity, anxiety, impatience, foolishness, and many other mental attributes could seem ridiculous and ugly, contemptible and detestable, even if they were not under one's control. It couldn’t be assumed that everyone had the ability to achieve every type of mental beauty, just as they might struggle with physical beauty.

And here there occurs the FOURTH reflection which I purposed to make, in suggesting the reason why modern philosophers have often followed a course in their moral enquiries so different from that of the ancients. In later times, philosophy of all kinds, especially ethics, have been more closely united with theology than ever they were observed to be among the heathens; and as this latter science admits of no terms of composition, but bends every branch of knowledge to its own purpose, without much regard to the phenomena of nature, or to the unbiassed sentiments of the mind, hence reasoning, and even language, have been warped from their natural course, and distinctions have been endeavoured to be established where the difference of the objects was, in a manner, imperceptible. Philosophers, or rather divines under that disguise, treating all morals as on a like footing with civil laws, guarded by the sanctions of reward and punishment, were necessarily led to render this circumstance, of VOLUNTARY or INVOLUNTARY, the foundation of their whole theory. Every one may employ TERMS in what sense he pleases: but this, in the mean time, must be allowed, that SENTIMENTS are every day experienced of blame and praise, which have objects beyond the dominion of the will or choice, and of which it behoves us, if not as moralists, as speculative philosophers at least, to give some satisfactory theory and explication.

And here we have the FOURTH reflection I intended to make, suggesting why modern philosophers often take a different approach in their moral inquiries compared to the ancients. In more recent times, philosophy of all types, especially ethics, has become more closely connected with theology than it was among the ancient pagans. Since theology doesn't allow for compromise and manipulates every area of knowledge to serve its goals, often ignoring the realities of nature and unbiased thoughts, reasoning—and even language—has been distorted from its natural path. Efforts have been made to create distinctions where the differences in the objects are almost unnoticeable. Philosophers, or rather theologians in disguise, treat all moral principles as being on the same level as civil laws, enforced by rewards and punishments. This has led them to base their entire theory on the distinction between VOLUNTARY and INVOLUNTARY actions. Everyone can use TERMS in any way they choose; however, it must be acknowledged that we frequently experience feelings of blame and praise that relate to matters beyond our control or choice. As moralists or at least as theoretical philosophers, we need to develop a satisfactory theory and explanation for these sentiments.

A blemish, a fault, a vice, a crime; these expressions seem to denote different degrees of censure and disapprobation; which are, however, all of them, at the bottom, pretty nearly all the same kind of species. The explication of one will easily lead us into a just conception of the others; and it is of greater consequence to attend to things than to verbal appellations. That we owe a duty to ourselves is confessed even in the most vulgar system of morals; and it must be of consequence to examine that duty, in order to see whether it bears any affinity to that which we owe to society. It is probable that the approbation attending the observance of both is of a similar nature, and arises from similar principles, whatever appellation we may give to either of these excellencies.

A flaw, a mistake, a wrongdoing, a crime; these terms seem to indicate different levels of criticism and disapproval, but at their core, they are all pretty much the same type of thing. Understanding one will easily help us grasp the others, and it's more important to focus on the concepts than on the specific words we use. We all acknowledge that we have a duty to ourselves, even in the simplest moral systems; therefore, it's important to examine that duty to see if it has any connection to the duty we owe to society. It’s likely that the approval associated with fulfilling both duties is of a similar kind and comes from similar principles, no matter what we choose to call these virtues.








Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!