This is a modern-English version of The Quest of the Historical Jesus: A Critical Study of its Progress from Reimarus to Wrede, originally written by Schweitzer, Albert. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.



The Quest of the Historical Jesus

The Search for the Historical Jesus

A Critical Study of its Progress From Reimarus to Wrede

A Comprehensive Overview of Its Development From Reimarus to Wrede

By

By

Albert Schweitzer

Albert Schweitzer

Privatdocent in New Testament Studies in the University of Strassburg

Privatdocent in New Testament Studies at the University of Strasbourg

Translated By

Translated By

W. Montgomery, B.A., B.D.

W. Montgomery, B.A., B.D.

With a Preface by

With a Preface by

F. C. Burkitt, M.A., D.D.

F. C. Burkitt, M.A., D.D.

Norrisian Professor of Divinity in the University of Cambridge

Norrisian Professor of Divinity at the University of Cambridge

Second English Edition

2nd English Edition

London

London

Adam and Charles Black

Adam and Charles Black

1911

1911


Cover Art
[pg iv]

First Edition published March 1910

First Edition published March 1910

[pg v]

Introduction

The book here translated is offered to the English-speaking public in the belief that it sets before them, as no other book has ever done, the history of the struggle which the best-equipped intellects of the modern world have gone through in endeavouring to realise for themselves the historical personality of our Lord.

This book, now translated, is offered to English-speaking readers with the hope that it effectively highlights the history of the challenges faced by the brightest minds of our time as they seek to understand the historical figure of our Lord.

Every one nowadays is aware that traditional Christian doctrine about Jesus Christ is encompassed with difficulties, and that many of the statements in the Gospels appear incredible in the light of modern views of history and nature. But when the alternative of Jesus or Christis put forward, as it has been in a recent publication, or when we are bidden to choose between the Jesus of history and the Christ of dogma, few except professed students know what a protean and kaleidoscopic figure the Jesus of history is. Like the Christ in the Apocryphal Acts of John, He has appeared in different forms to different minds. We know Him right well, says Professor Weinel.1What a claim!

Everyone today recognizes that traditional Christian beliefs about Jesus Christ come with challenges, and that many statements in the Gospels can seem unbelievable when viewed through the lens of modern history and science. However, when confronted with the choice of Jesus or Christ, as mentioned in a recent publication, or when asked to choose between the historical Jesus and the doctrinal Christ, few outside of dedicated scholars truly grasp how adaptable and diverse the Jesus of history really is. Just like the Christ depicted in the Apocryphal Acts of John, He has appeared in various forms for different people. We know Him very well, says Professor Weinel.1What a claim!

Among the many bold paradoxes enunciated in this history of the Quest, there is one that meets us at the outset, about which a few words may be said here, if only to encourage those to persevere to the end who might otherwise be repelled halfway—the paradox that the greatest attempts to write a Life of Jesus have been written with hate.2 It is in full accordance with this faith that Dr. Schweitzer gives, in paragraph after paragraph, the undiluted expression of the views of men who agree only in their unflinching desire to attain historical truth. We are not accustomed to be so ruthless in England. We sometimes tend to forget that the Gospel has moved the world, and we think our faith and devotion to it so tender and delicate a thing that it will break, if it be not handled with the utmost circumspection. So we become dominated [pg vi]by phrases and afraid of them. Dr. Schweitzer is not afraid of phrases, if only they have been beaten out by real contact with facts. And those who read to the end will see that the crude sarcasm of Reimarus and the unflinching scepticism of Bruno Bauer are not introduced merely to shock and by way of contrast. Each in his own way made a real contribution to our understanding of the greatest historical problem in the history of our race. We see now that the object of attack was not the historical Jesus after all, but a temporary idea of Him, inadequate because it did not truly represent Him or the world in which He lived. And by hearing the writers' characteristic phrases, uncompromising as they may be, by looking at things for a moment from their own point of view, different as it may be from ours, we are able to be more just, not only to these men of a past age, but also to the great Problem that occupied them, as it also occupies us.

Among the many striking contradictions highlighted in this history of the Quest, one stands out right from the beginning that deserves mention, especially to encourage those who might be discouraged halfway through to stick with it until the end—the contradiction that the most important efforts to write a Life of Jesus have been driven by hatred.2This perfectly reflects Dr. Schweitzer's viewpoint, who tirelessly shares the thoughts of those united solely by their steadfast dedication to historical truth, paragraph after paragraph. In England, we aren't used to being so straightforward. We often forget that the Gospel has transformed the world, and we treat our faith and commitment to it as something fragile that could break if not handled with great care. So, we become influenced by certain phrases and wary of them. Dr. Schweitzer isn’t intimidated by phrases, as long as they've come from genuine engagement with facts. Those who read all the way through will understand that the biting sarcasm of Reimarus and the unwavering skepticism of Bruno Bauer aren't merely there to provoke or to contrast. Each, in their own way, contributed a real understanding of the most significant historical issue in our history. We now see that the target of their critique wasn’t the historical Jesus himself, but a temporary understanding of Him, which was inadequate because it did not accurately reflect Him or the world He inhabited. By engaging with the authors' unique phrases, no matter how unyielding they may be, and by briefly viewing things from their perspective—even if it differs from ours—we become fairer—not just to these historical figures, but also to the important Problem that concerned them, as it continues to concern us.

For, as Father Tyrrell has been pointing out in his last most impressive message to us all, Christianity is at the Cross Roads. If the Figure of our Lord is to mean anything for us we must realise it for ourselves. Most English readers of the New Testament have been too long content with the rough and ready Harmony of the Four Gospels that they unconsciously construct. This kind of Harmonyis not a very convincing picture when looked into, if only because it almost always conflicts with inconvenient statements of the Gospels themselves, statements that have been omitted from the Harmony, not on any reasoned theory, but simply from inadvertence or the difficulty of fitting them in. We treat the Life of our Lord too much as it is treated in the Liturgical Gospels, as a simple series of disconnected anecdotes.

As Father Tyrrell pointed out in his latest impactful message to all of us, Christianity is at a pivotal moment. If the figure of our Lord is to mean anything to us, we need to grasp it on our own terms. Many English readers of the New Testament have been too complacent with the rough and ready combination of the Four Gospels that they unintentionally create. This kind of harmony isn't a convincing depiction when we look closely, mainly because it often conflicts with inconvenient statements from the Gospels themselves—statements that have been omitted from the harmony, not for any thoughtful reason, but simply due to oversight or the difficulty of fitting them in. We tend to view the life of our Lord too much like it's presented in the liturgical Gospels, as just a collection of disconnected stories.

Dr. Schweitzer's book does not pretend to be an impartial survey. He has his own solution of the problems, and it is not to be expected that English students will endorse the whole of his view of the Gospel History, any more than his German fellow-workers have done. But valuable and suggestive as I believe his constructive work to be in its main outlines, I venture to think his grasp of the nature and complexity of the great Quest is even more remarkable, and his exposition of it cannot fail to stimulate us in England. Whatever we may think of Dr. Schweitzer's solution or that of his opponents, we too have to reckon with the Son of Man who was expected to come before the apostles had gone over the cities of Israel, the Son of Man who would come in His Kingdom before some that heard our Lord speak should taste death, the Son of Man who came to give His life a ransom for many, whom [pg vii]they would see hereafter coming with the clouds of heaven. Who is this Son of Man? Dr. Schweitzer's book is an attempt to give the full historical value and the true historical setting to these fundamental words of the Gospel of Jesus.

Dr. Schweitzer's book doesn’t claim to be an unbiased summary. He has his own perspective on the issues, and it’s unlikely that English readers will agree with all his views on Gospel History, just as his German peers have not. However, I believe his main ideas are valuable and thought-provoking. I also think his grasp of the nature and complexity of the great Quest is even more impressive, and his explanation is sure to inspire us in England. Regardless of our opinions on Dr. Schweitzer's solution or those of his critics, we must also consider the Son of Man, who was expected to arrive before the apostles traveled through the cities of Israel, the Son of Man who would come in His Kingdom before some of those who heard our Lord speak would experience death, the Son of Man who came to give His life as a ransom for many, whom [pg vii]they would eventually see coming with the clouds of heaven. Who is this Son of Man? Dr. Schweitzer's book aims to present the full historical significance and true historical context of these fundamental words of the Gospel of Jesus.

Our first duty, with the Gospel as with every other ancient document, is to interpret it with reference to its own time. The true view of the Gospel will be that which explains the course of events in the first century and the second century, rather than that which seems to have spiritual and imaginative value for the twentieth century. Yet I cannot refrain from pointing out here one feature of the theory of thoroughgoing eschatology, which may appeal to those who are accustomed to the venerable forms of ancient Christian aspiration and worship. It may well be that absolute truth cannot be embodied in human thought and that its expression must always be clothed in symbols. It may be that we have to translate the hopes and fears of our spiritual ancestors into the language of our new world. We have to learn, as the Church in the second century had to learn, that the End is not yet, that New Jerusalem, like all other objects of sense, is an image of the truth rather than the truth itself. But at least we are beginning to see that the apocalyptic vision, the New Age which God is to bring in, is no mere embroidery of Christianity, but the heart of its enthusiasm. And therefore the expectations of vindication and judgment to come, the imagery of the Messianic Feast, the other-worldliness against which so many eloquent words were said in the nineteenth century, are not to be regarded as regrettable accretions foisted on by superstition to the pure morality of the original Gospel. These ideas are the Christian Hope, to be allegorised and spiritualised by us for our own use whenever necessary, but not to be given up so long as we remain Christians at all. Books which teach us boldly to trust the evidence of our documents, and to accept the eschatology of the Christian Gospel as being historically the eschatology of Jesus, help us at the same time to retain a real meaning and use for the ancient phrases of the Te Deum, and for the mediaeval strain of Jerusalem the Golden.

Our primary responsibility, like with any ancient text, is to interpret the Gospel in the context of its time. A true understanding of the Gospel will explain the events of the first and second centuries instead of just reflecting the spiritual and imaginative values of the twentieth century. However, I should highlight one aspect of the theory of complete eschatology that may resonate with those familiar with the cherished traditions of early Christian aspiration and worship. It might be that absolute truth can’t be fully grasped by human thought and that its expression must always be in symbols. We may need to translate the hopes and fears of our spiritual ancestors into the language of today's world. We must learn, just as the Church in the second century did, that the End is not yet here, and that the New Jerusalem, like all other sensory experiences, is an image of truth rather than truth itself. Yet, we're starting to understand that the apocalyptic vision, the New Age that God will bring, is not just an embellishment of Christianity but its core passion. Therefore, the expectations of vindication and future judgment, the imagery of the Messianic Feast, the other-worldliness that many eloquent critics spoke against in the nineteenth century should not be seen as unfortunate additions imposed by superstition onto the pure morality of the original Gospel. These ideas represent the Christian Hope, meant to be interpreted and spiritualised by us for our own purposes whenever necessary, but we shouldn't abandon them as long as we remain Christians. Books that encourage us to confidently trust the evidence of our texts and to accept the eschatology of the Christian Gospel as historically connected with the eschatology of Jesus help us maintain real meaning and relevance for the ancient phrases of the Te Deum, as well as for the medieval refrain of Jerusalem the Golden.

F. C. Burkitt.

F. C. Burkitt.

Cambridge, 1910.

Cambridge, 1910.

[pg 001]

I. The Issue

When, at some future day, our period of civilisation shall lie, closed and completed, before the eyes of later generations, German theology will stand out as a great, a unique phenomenon in the mental and spiritual life of our time. For nowhere save in the German temperament can there be found in the same perfection the living complex of conditions and factors—of philosophic thought, critical acumen, historical insight, and religious feeling—without which no deep theology is possible.

When, in the future, our period of civilization is viewed as complete by later generations, German theology will stand out as a significant and unique phenomenon in the intellectual and spiritual life of our time. For nowhere else but in the German mindset can one find the same perfect combination of conditions and factors—philosophical thought, critical insight, historical awareness, and religious sentiment—without which no profound theology is achievable.

And the greatest achievement of German theology is the critical investigation of the life of Jesus. What it has accomplished here has laid down the conditions and determined the course of the religious thinking of the future.

And the greatest achievement of German theology is the critical examination of the life of Jesus. What it has achieved in this area has set the foundation and shaped the direction of future religious thought.

In the history of doctrine its work has been negative; it has, so to speak, cleared the site for a new edifice of religious thought. In describing how the ideas of Jesus were taken possession of by the Greek spirit, it was tracing the growth of that which must necessarily become strange to us, and, as a matter of fact, has become strange to us.

In the history of doctrine, its work has been about clearing the way for a new structure of religious thought. By explaining how the ideas of Jesus were embraced by the Greek mindset, it was outlining the development of something that must inevitably become unfamiliar to us, and, in fact, has become unfamiliar to us.

Of its efforts to create a new dogmatic we scarcely need to have the history written; it is alive within us. It is no doubt interesting to trace how modern thoughts have found their way into the ancient dogmatic system, there to combine with eternal ideas to form new constructions; it is interesting to penetrate into the mind of the thinker in which this process is at work; but the real truth of that which here meets us as history we experience within ourselves. As in the monad of Leibnitz the whole universe is reflected, so we intuitively experience within us, even apart from any clear historical knowledge, the successive stages of the progress of modern dogma, from rationalism to Ritschl. This experience is true knowledge, all the truer because we are conscious of the whole [pg 002] as something indefinite, a slow and difficult movement towards a goal which is still shrouded in obscurity. We have not yet arrived at any reconciliation between history and modern thought—only between half-way history and half-way thought. What the ultimate goal towards which we are moving will be, what this something is which shall bring new life and new regulative principles to coming centuries, we do not know. We can only dimly divine that it will be the mighty deed of some mighty original genius, whose truth and rightness will be proved by the fact that we, working at our poor half thing, will oppose him might and main—we who imagine we long for nothing more eagerly than a genius powerful enough to open up with authority a new path for the world, seeing that we cannot succeed in moving it forward along the track which we have so laboriously prepared.

Of its efforts to create a new set of beliefs, we hardly need a written history; it's alive within us. It's certainly interesting to see how modern ideas have integrated into the ancient belief system, merging with timeless concepts to form new frameworks; it's intriguing to delve into the mind of the thinker where this process unfolds. However, the real essence of history as we encounter it is something we feel within ourselves. Just as Leibniz's monad reflects the entire universe, we intuitively sense within us, even without a clear historical understanding, the various stages of modern beliefs evolving from rationalism to Ritschl. This experience is genuine knowledge, especially since we recognize the entire journey as something vague, a slow and challenging movement toward a goal that remains unclear. We haven't yet achieved reconciliation between history and modern thought—only between partial history and partial thought. We don’t know what the ultimate destination of our journey will be, or what this new element will be that brings fresh life and guiding principles for future generations. We can only vaguely sense that it will be the significant work of some extraordinary genius, whose truth and correctness will be validated by the fact that we, toiling at our imperfect efforts, will fiercely resist him—even though we believe we long for nothing more than a genius strong enough to confidently pave a new way for the world, knowing we cannot advance it along the path we have painstakingly prepared.

For this reason the history of the critical study of the life of Jesus is of higher intrinsic value than the history of the study of ancient dogma or of the attempts to create a new one. It has to describe the most tremendous thing which the religious consciousness has ever dared and done. In the study of the history of dogma German theology settled its account with the past; in its attempt to create a new dogmatic, it was endeavouring to keep a place for the religious life in the thought of the present; in the study of the life of Jesus it was working for the future—in pure faith in the truth, not seeing whereunto it wrought.

For this reason, the history of the critical study of Jesus's life holds more intrinsic value than the history of studying ancient dogma or the attempts to create a new one. It needs to describe the most incredible thing that religious consciousness has ever attempted and achieved. In the study of the history of dogma, German theology reconciled its past; in trying to create a new dogmatic, it aimed to maintain a place for religious life in contemporary thought; in studying the life of Jesus, it was working for the future—guided by pure faith in the truth, without realizing the direction in which it was heading.

Moreover, we are here dealing with the most vital thing in the world's history. There came a Man to rule over the world; He ruled it for good and for ill, as history testifies; He destroyed the world into which He was born; the spiritual life of our own time seems like to perish at His hands, for He leads to battle against our thought a host of dead ideas, a ghostly army upon which death has no power, and Himself destroys again the truth and goodness which His Spirit creates in us, so that it cannot rule the world. That He continues, notwithstanding, to reign as the alone Great and alone True in a world of which He denied the continuance, is the prime example of that antithesis between spiritual and natural truth which underlies all life and all events, and in Him emerges into the field of history.

Moreover, we are dealing with the most important thing in the history of the world. A Man came to govern the world; He ruled it for better and for worse, as history shows; He shattered the world into which He was born; the spiritual life of our time seems to be fading away at His hands, as He wages war against our thoughts with a host of outdated ideas, a ghostly army that death has no power over, and He destroys once again the truth and goodness that His Spirit brings to us, so it cannot govern the world. That He continues to reign, nonetheless, as the one Great and the one True in a world He proclaimed would not last, is the prime example of the conflict between spiritual and natural truth that underpins all life and all events, and in Him it becomes evident in the realm of history.

It is only at first sight that the absolute indifference of early Christianity towards the life of the historical Jesus is disconcerting. When Paul, representing those who recognise the signs of the times, did not desire to know Christ after the flesh, that was the first expression of the impulse of self-preservation by which Christianity continued to be guided for centuries. It felt that with the introduction of the historic Jesus into its faith, there would arise something new, something which had not been foreseen in the thoughts of the Master Himself, and that thereby a contradiction [pg 003] would be brought to light, the solution of which would constitute one of the great problems of the world.

At first, it seems surprising that early Christianity was completely indifferent to the life of the historical Jesus. When Paul, speaking for those who understood the current situation, chose not to know Christ in a physical sense, this was the first sign of the instinct for self-preservation that would guide Christianity for centuries. It sensed that by incorporating the historical Jesus into its beliefs, something new and unforeseen would emerge, creating a contradiction [pg 003] that would reveal one of the great challenges of the world.

Primitive Christianity was therefore right to live wholly in the future with the Christ who was to come, and to preserve of the historic Jesus only detached sayings, a few miracles, His death and resurrection. By abolishing both the world and the historical Jesus it escaped the inner division described above, and remained consistent in its point of view. We, on our part, have reason to be grateful to the early Christians that, in consequence of this attitude they have handed down to us, not biographies of Jesus but only Gospels, and that therefore we possess the Idea and the Person with the minimum of historical and contemporary limitations.

Primitive Christianity was right to focus entirely on the future with the Christ who was to come, and to keep only isolated sayings, a few miracles, His death, and resurrection from the historical Jesus. By disregarding both the world and the historical Jesus, it avoided the internal conflicts previously mentioned and maintained consistency in its perspective. We should be thankful to the early Christians for this approach, as they passed down not biographies of Jesus but only Gospels, which means we have the Idea and the Person with the least amount of historical and contemporary constraints.

But the world continued to exist, and its continuance brought this one-sided view to an end. The supra-mundane Christ and the historical Jesus of Nazareth had to be brought together into a single personality at once historical and raised above time. That was accomplished by Gnosticism and the Logos Christology. Both, from opposite standpoints, because they were seeking the same goal, agreed in sublimating the historical Jesus into the supra-mundane Idea. The result of this development, which followed on the discrediting of eschatology, was that the historical Jesus was again introduced into the field of view of Christianity, but in such a way that all justification for, and interest in, the investigation of His life and historical personality were done away with.

But the world kept going, and its ongoing existence brought an end to this one-sided perspective. The divine Christ and the historical Jesus of Nazareth needed to be united into one figure who was both historical and transcendent. Gnosticism and Logos Christology achieved this, each from different viewpoints but aiming for the same goal, agreeing to elevate the historical Jesus into the divine Idea. The outcome of this shift, which came after the decline of eschatology, was that the historical Jesus was reintroduced into Christianity, but in such a way that all reasons for and interest in studying His life and historical identity were eliminated.

Greek theology was as indifferent in regard to the historical Jesus who lives concealed in the Gospels as was the early eschatological theology. More than that, it was dangerous to Him; for it created a new supernatural-historical Gospel, and we may consider it fortunate that the Synoptics were already so firmly established that the Fourth Gospel could not oust them; instead, the Church, as though from the inner necessity of the antitheses which now began to be a constructive element in her thought, was obliged to set up two antithetic Gospels alongside of one another.

Greek theology was just as indifferent to the historical Jesus hidden in the Gospels as early eschatological theology was. In fact, it posed a real danger to Him; it created a new supernatural-historical Gospel. It's lucky that the Synoptics were already so well established that the Fourth Gospel couldn't replace them. Instead, the Church, compelled by the contradictions that were becoming a key part of her thinking, was forced to maintain two opposing Gospels side by side.

When at Chalcedon the West overcame the East, its doctrine of the two natures dissolved the unity of the Person, and thereby cut off the last possibility of a return to the historical Jesus. The self-contradiction was elevated into a law. But the Manhood was so far admitted as to preserve, in appearance, the rights of history. Thus by a deception the formula kept the Life prisoner and prevented the leading spirits of the Reformation from grasping the idea of a return to the historical Jesus.

When the West defeated the East at Chalcedon, its belief in the two natures separated the unity of the Person, effectively eliminating any chance of going back to the historical Jesus. This self-contradiction became accepted as a principle. However, the humanity of Jesus was acknowledged enough to maintain, at least in appearance, the legitimacy of history. As a result, the formula misleadingly kept the Life trapped and hindered the key figures of the Reformation from understanding the possibility of returning to the historical Jesus.

This dogma had first to be shattered before men could once more go out in quest of the historical Jesus, before they could even grasp the thought of His existence. That the historic Jesus is something [pg 004] different from the Jesus Christ of the doctrine of the Two Natures seems to us now self-evident. We can, at the present day, scarcely imagine the long agony in which the historical view of the life of Jesus came to birth. And even when He was once more recalled to life, He was still, like Lazarus of old, bound hand and foot with grave-clothes—the grave-clothes of the dogma of the Dual Nature. Hase relates, in the preface to his first Life of Jesus (1829), that a worthy old gentleman, hearing of his project, advised him to treat in the first part of the human, in the second of the divine Nature. There was a fine simplicity about that. But does not the simplicity cover a presentiment of the revolution of thought for which the historical method of study was preparing the way—a presentiment which those who were engaged in the work did not share in the same measure? It was fortunate that they did not; for otherwise how could they have had the courage to go on?

This belief had to be broken down before people could once again seek the historical Jesus, before they could even begin to understand the idea of His existence. The distinction between the historic Jesus and the Jesus Christ of the Two Natures doctrine seems obvious to us now. Nowadays, we can hardly imagine the long struggle through which the historical understanding of Jesus’ life emerged. And even when He was brought back to life, He was still, like Lazarus of old, wrapped in burial clothes—the burial clothes of the Dual Nature doctrine. Hase mentions in the preface to his first Life of Jesus (1829) that a respectable old gentleman, upon hearing about his project, suggested he discuss the human nature in the first part and the divine nature in the second. There was a certain straightforwardness to that idea. But doesn’t that simplicity hint at the significant shift in thought that the historical study method was paving the way for—a shift that those involved in the work didn’t fully perceive? It was probably a good thing they didn’t; otherwise, how could they have found the courage to continue?

The historical investigation of the life of Jesus did not take its rise from a purely historical interest; it turned to the Jesus of history as an ally in the struggle against the tyranny of dogma. Afterwards when it was freed from this πάθος it sought to present the historic Jesus in a form intelligible to its own time. For Bahrdt and Venturini He was the tool of a secret order. They wrote under the impression of the immense influence exercised by the Order of the Illuminati3 at the end of the eighteenth century. For Reinhard, Hess, Paulus, and the rest of the rationalistic writers He is the admirable revealer of true virtue, which is coincident with right reason. Thus each successive epoch of theology found its own thoughts in Jesus; that was, indeed, the only way in which it could make Him live.

The historical investigation of Jesus' life didn't start from a purely historical perspective; it turned to the historical Jesus as an ally in the fight against the oppression of dogma. Later, once it was freed from this passion, it aimed to present the historical Jesus in a way that made sense for its own time. For Bahrdt and Venturini, He was the tool of a secret society. They were influenced by the significant impact of the Order of the Illuminati at the end of the 18th century. For Reinhard, Hess, Paulus, and other rational writers, He is the impressive bearer of true virtue, which aligns with reason. In this way, each theological era found its own ideas in Jesus; that was essentially the only way to keep Him alive.

But it was not only each epoch that found its reflection in Jesus; each individual created Him in accordance with his own character. There is no historical task which so reveals a man's true self as the writing of a Life of Jesus. No vital force comes into the figure unless a man breathes into it all the hate or all the love of which he is capable. The stronger the love, or the stronger the hate, the more life-like is the figure which is produced. For hate as well as love can write a Life of Jesus, and the greatest of them are written with hate: that of Reimarus, the Wolfenbüttel Fragmentist, and that of David Friedrich Strauss. It was not so much hate of the Person of Jesus as of the supernatural nimbus with which it was so easy to surround Him, and with which He had in fact been surrounded. They were eager to picture Him as truly and purely human, to strip from Him the robes of splendour with which He [pg 005] had been apparelled, and clothe Him once more with the coarse garments in which He had walked in Galilee.

But it wasn't just that each era reflected in Jesus; every individual created their own version of Him based on their own character. There's no historical task that reveals a person's true self more than writing a Life of Jesus. No energy comes into the portrayal unless a person infuses it with all the hate or all the love they can muster. The stronger the love or hate, the more lifelike the depiction becomes. Both hate and love can write a Life of Jesus, and the most significant ones are often written with hate: like those by Reimarus, the Wolfenbüttel Fragmentist, and David Friedrich Strauss. It wasn't so much the hatred of Jesus Himself but rather of the supernatural aura that it was so easy to associate with Him, and which He had indeed been surrounded by. They were eager to portray Him as truly and purely human, to remove the robes of glory that He had been dressed in and to once again clothe Him in the simple garments He wore while walking through Galilee.

And their hate sharpened their historical insight. They advanced the study of the subject more than all the others put together. But for the offence which they gave, the science of historical theology would not have stood where it does to-day. “It must needs be that offences come; but woe to that man by whom the offence cometh.” Reimarus evaded that woe by keeping the offence to himself and preserving silence during his lifetime—his work, “The Aims of Jesus and His Disciples,” was only published after his death, by Lessing. But in the case of Strauss, who, as a young man of twenty-seven, cast the offence openly in the face of the world, the woe fulfilled itself. His “Life of Jesus” was his ruin. But he did not cease to be proud of it in spite of all the misfortune that it brought him. “I might well bear a grudge against my book,” he writes twenty-five years later in the preface to the “Conversations of Ulrich von Hutten,”4 “for it has done me much evil (‘And rightly so!’ the pious will exclaim). It has excluded me from public teaching in which I took pleasure and for which I had perhaps some talent; it has torn me from natural relationships and driven me into unnatural ones; it has made my life a lonely one. And yet when I consider what it would have meant if I had refused to utter the word which lay upon my soul, if I had suppressed the doubts which were at work in my mind—then I bless the book which has doubtless done me grievous harm outwardly, but which preserved the inward health of my mind and heart, and, I doubt not, has done the same for many others also.”

And their hate sharpened their historical understanding. They pushed the study of the subject further than all the others combined. If it weren't for the controversy they caused, the field of historical theology wouldn’t be where it is today. "Offenses will happen; but shame on the person through whom the offense comes." Reimarus avoided that woe by keeping the controversy to himself and staying silent during his life—his work, "The Goals of Jesus and His Disciples," was only published after his death, by Lessing. However, in the case of Strauss, who, at just twenty-seven, boldly confronted the world with the controversy, the woe came to pass. His "Life of Jesus" led to his downfall. Yet, despite all the trouble it brought him, he remained proud of it. "I could easily hold a grudge against my book," he wrote twenty-five years later in the preface to the “Discussions of Ulrich von Hutten,” 4 “because it has caused me a lot of trouble (‘And rightly so!’ the devoted will say). It has kept me from teaching in public, which I enjoyed and was maybe somewhat good at; it has pulled me away from natural relationships and pushed me into unnatural ones; it has made my life a lonely one. Yet, when I think about what it would have meant if I had chosen not to share the thoughts weighing on my soul, if I had suppressed the doubts swirling in my mind—then I feel thankful for the book that, while it has definitely caused me serious external harm, has preserved the internal health of my mind and heart, and, I’m sure, has done the same for many others too.”

Before him, Bahrdt had his career broken in consequence of revealing his beliefs concerning the Life of Jesus; and after him, Bruno Bauer.

Before him, Bahrdt had his career ruined because he revealed his beliefs about the Life of Jesus; and after him, Bruno Bauer.

It was easy for them, resolved as they were to open the way even with seeming blasphemy. But the others, those who tried to bring Jesus to life at the call of love, found it a cruel task to be honest. The critical study of the life of Jesus has been for theology a school of honesty. The world had never seen before, and will never see again, a struggle for truth so full of pain and renunciation as that of which the Lives of Jesus of the last hundred years contain the cryptic record. One must read the successive Lives of Jesus with which Hase followed the course of the study from the 'twenties to the 'seventies of the nineteenth century to get an inkling of what it must have cost the men who lived through that decisive period really to maintain that “courageous freedom of investigation” which the great Jena professor, in the preface to his first Life of Jesus, claims for his researches. One sees in him the marks of the struggle with which he gives up, bit by bit, things [pg 006] which, when he wrote that preface, he never dreamed he would have to surrender. It was fortunate for these men that their sympathies sometimes obscured their critical vision, so that, without becoming insincere, they were able to take white clouds for distant mountains. That was the kindly fate of Hase and Beyschlag.

It was easy for them, determined as they were to pave the way even with what might seem like blasphemy. But the others, those who tried to bring Jesus back to life through love, found it brutally honest work. The critical study of Jesus' life has served as a school of honesty for theology. The world has never seen, and will never again see, a struggle for truth as painful and self-denying as the one recorded in the Lives of Jesus over the last hundred years. To get a sense of what it cost the people who lived through that pivotal period to genuinely uphold that "brave freedom of exploration" claimed by the great professor from Jena in the preface to his first Life of Jesus, one must read the successive Lives of Jesus that Hase published from the '20s to the '70s of the nineteenth century. In him, you can see the marks of the struggle as he gradually relinquishes things [pg 006] which, when he wrote that preface, he never imagined he would have to give up. It was lucky for these men that their sympathies sometimes clouded their critical perspective, allowing them, without being insincere, to mistake white clouds for distant mountains. That was the kind fate of Hase and Beyschlag.

The personal character of the study is not only due, however, to the fact that a personality can only be awakened to life by the touch of a personality; it lies in the essential nature of the problem itself. For the problem of the life of Jesus has no analogue in the field of history. No historical school has ever laid down canons for the investigation of this problem, no professional historian has ever lent his aid to theology in dealing with it. Every ordinary method of historical investigation proves inadequate to the complexity of the conditions. The standards of ordinary historical science are here inadequate, its methods not immediately applicable. The historical study of the life of Jesus has had to create its own methods for itself. In the constant succession of unsuccessful attempts, five or six problems have emerged side by side which together constitute the fundamental problem. There is, however, no direct method of solving the problem in its complexity; all that can be done is to experiment continuously, starting from definite assumptions; and in this experimentation the guiding principle must ultimately rest upon historical intuition.

The personal aspect of the study is not only because a personality can only come to life through the influence of another personality; it is also rooted in the core nature of the problem itself. The issue of Jesus' life has no parallel in history. No historical school has ever established rules for investigating this problem, and no professional historian has ever collaborated with theologians on it. Every standard method of historical research falls short when faced with the complexity of the situation. The criteria of traditional historical science are insufficient here, and its methods can't be directly applied. The historical study of Jesus' life has had to develop its own methods. Through a series of failed attempts, five or six key problems have emerged that together make up the fundamental issue. However, there is no straightforward way to resolve the problem in its entirety; all that's possible is to continually experiment from specific assumptions, and this experimentation must ultimately rely on historical intuition as a guiding principle.

The cause of this lies in the nature of the sources of the life of Jesus, and in the character of our knowledge of the contemporary religious world of thought. It is not that the sources are in themselves bad. When we have once made up our minds that we have not the materials for a complete Life of Jesus, but only for a picture of His public ministry, it must be admitted that there are few characters of antiquity about whom we possess so much indubitably historical information, of whom we have so many authentic discourses. The position is much more favourable, for instance, than in the case of Socrates; for he is pictured to us by literary men who exercised their creative ability upon the portrait. Jesus stands much more immediately before us, because He was depicted by simple Christians without literary gift.

The reason for this lies in the nature of the sources about Jesus's life and in how we understand the contemporary religious mindset. It's not that the sources are inherently flawed. Once we realize that we don't have enough material for a complete Life of Jesus, but only for an overview of His public ministry, we must acknowledge that there are few historical figures from ancient times about whom we have such reliable historical information and so many authentic teachings. The situation is much more favorable than, for instance, with Socrates; he is portrayed by writers who added their creative flair to his image. Jesus is depicted much more directly because He was portrayed by ordinary Christians who lacked literary skills.

But at this point there arises a twofold difficulty. There is first the fact that what has just been said applies only to the first three Gospels, while the fourth, as regards its character, historical data, and discourse material, forms a world of its own. It is written from the Greek standpoint, while the first three are written from the Jewish. And even if one could get over this, and regard, as has often been done, the Synoptics and the Fourth Gospel as standing in something of the same relation to one another as Xenophon does to Plato as sources for the life of Socrates, yet the complete irreconcilability of the historical data would compel the critical [pg 007] investigator to decide from the first in favour of one source or the other. Once more it is found true that “No man can serve two masters.” This stringent dilemma was not recognised from the beginning; its emergence is one of the results of the whole course of experiment.

But at this point, there are two main difficulties. First, what has just been said applies only to the first three Gospels, while the fourth Gospel, in terms of its character, historical information, and content, is in a category all its own. It’s written from a Greek perspective, while the first three are from a Jewish one. Even if we could overlook this and consider the Synoptics and the Fourth Gospel as somewhat similar to how Xenophon relates to Plato as sources for the life of Socrates, the complete incompatibility of the historical data would force a critical investigator to choose one source over the other. Once again, it proves true that “No man can serve two masters.” This strict dilemma wasn’t recognized at the beginning; its emergence is one of the results of the entire process of study.

The second difficulty regarding the sources is the want of any thread of connexion in the material which they offer us. While the Synoptics are only collections of anecdotes (in the best, historical sense of the word), the Gospel of John—as stands on record in its closing words—only professes to give a selection of the events and discourses.

The second challenge related to the sources is the lack of any connection in the material they provide. While the Synoptics are just collections of stories (in the best, historical sense of the word), the Gospel of John—according to its closing words—only claims to present a selection of events and teachings.

From these materials we can only get a Life of Jesus with yawning gaps. How are these gaps to be filled? At the worst with phrases, at the best with historical imagination. There is really no other means of arriving at the order and inner connexion of the facts of the life of Jesus than the making and testing of hypotheses. If the tradition preserved by the Synoptists really includes all that happened during the time that Jesus was with His disciples, the attempt to discover the connexion must succeed sooner or later. It becomes more and more clear that this presupposition is indispensable to the investigation. If it is merely a fortuitous series of episodes that the Evangelists have handed down to us, we may give up the attempt to arrive at a critical reconstruction of the life of Jesus as hopeless.

From these materials, we can only piece together a Life of Jesus with significant gaps. How do we fill these gaps? At worst, with clichés; at best, with historical imagination. There’s really no other way to understand the order and connection of the facts of Jesus' life than by creating and testing hypotheses. If the tradition preserved by the Synoptists includes everything that happened while Jesus was with His disciples, the effort to uncover the connections must eventually succeed. It’s becoming increasingly clear that this assumption is essential for the investigation. If it’s just a random series of events that the Evangelists have passed down to us, we might as well give up on trying to critically reconstruct the life of Jesus as a lost cause.

But it is not only the events which lack historical connexion; we are without any indication of a thread of connexion in the actions and discourses of Jesus, because the sources give no hint of the character of His self-consciousness. They confine themselves to outward facts. We only begin to understand these historically when we can mentally place them in an intelligible connexion and conceive them as the acts of a clearly defined personality. All that we know of the development of Jesus and of His Messianic self-consciousness has been arrived at by a series of working hypotheses. Our conclusions can only be considered valid so long as they are not found incompatible with the recorded facts as a whole.

But it’s not just the events that lack historical connections; we also don’t have any clues about a connection in Jesus' actions and teachings, because the sources don’t provide any insight into the nature of His self-awareness. They only focus on external facts. We can only start to understand these events historically when we can mentally link them together in a way that makes sense and see them as actions of a clearly defined individual. Everything we know about Jesus' development and His Messianic self-awareness has come from a series of working hypotheses. Our conclusions can only be considered valid as long as they don’t conflict with the overall recorded facts.

It may be maintained by the aid of arguments drawn from the sources that the self-consciousness of Jesus underwent a development during the course of His public ministry; it may, with equally good grounds, be denied. For in both cases the arguments are based upon little details in the narrative in regard to which we do not know whether they are purely accidental, or whether they belong to the essence of the facts. In each case, moreover, the experimental working out of the hypothesis leads to a conclusion which compels the rejection of some of the actual data of the sources. Each view equally involves a violent treatment of the text.

It can be argued, using evidence from different sources, that Jesus's self-awareness evolved during His public ministry, and there are also strong reasons to refute this. In both scenarios, the arguments rely on small details in the narrative, and we can't determine if they are just coincidences or if they are crucial to the actual events. Additionally, testing each hypothesis results in a conclusion that forces us to dismiss some of the factual evidence from the sources. Both perspectives require a significant reinterpretation of the text.

Furthermore, the sources exhibit, each within itself, a striking [pg 008] contradiction. They assert that Jesus felt Himself to be the Messiah; and yet from their presentation of His life it does not appear that He ever publicly claimed to be so. They attribute to Him, that is, an attitude which has absolutely no connexion with the consciousness which they assume that He possessed. But once admit that the outward acts are not the natural expression of the self-consciousness and all exact historical knowledge is at an end; we have to do with an isolated fact which is not referable to any law.

Furthermore, the sources show, each in its own way, a striking [pg 008] contradiction. They claim that Jesus believed He was the Messiah; yet based on their portrayal of His life, it seems He never publicly declared that. They ascribe to Him an attitude that has no real connection with the awareness they say He had. But once we accept that His outward actions aren't a natural expression of His self-awareness, all precise historical understanding comes to a halt; we are left with an isolated fact that cannot be linked to any rule.

This being so, the only way of arriving at a conclusion of any value is to experiment, to test, by working them out, the two hypotheses—that Jesus felt Himself to be the Messiah, as the sources assert, or that He did not feel Himself to be so, as His conduct implies; or else to try to conjecture what kind of Messianic consciousness His must have been, if it left His conduct and His discourses unaffected. For one thing is certain: the whole account of the last days at Jerusalem would be unintelligible, if we had to suppose that the mass of the people had a shadow of a suspicion that Jesus held Himself to be the Messiah.

Given this, the only way to reach a meaningful conclusion is to experiment, to test the two hypotheses by working them out: that Jesus believed He was the Messiah, as the sources claim, or that He did not see Himself this way, as His behavior suggests; or we could speculate about what His sense of being the Messiah must have been like if it didn't influence His actions or teachings. One thing is clear: the entire account of the last days in Jerusalem would be confusing if we had to assume that the general public had any inkling that Jesus thought of Himself as the Messiah.

Again, whereas in general a personality is to some extent defined by the world of thought which it shares with its contemporaries, in the case of Jesus this source of information is as unsatisfactory as the documents.

Again, while generally a personality is somewhat shaped by the shared thoughts of its time, in Jesus' case, this source of information is just as inadequate as the existing documents.

What was the nature of the contemporary Jewish world of thought? To that question no clear answer can be given. We do not know whether the expectation of the Messiah was generally current or whether it was the faith of a mere sect. With the Mosaic religion as such it had nothing to do. There was no organic connexion between the religion of legal observance and the future hope. Further, if the eschatological hope was generally current, was it the prophetic or the apocalyptic form of that hope? We know the Messianic expectations of the prophets; we know the apocalyptic picture as drawn by Daniel, and, following him, by Enoch and the Psalms of Solomon before the coming of Jesus, and by the Apocalypses of Ezra and Baruch about the time of the destruction of Jerusalem. But we do not know which was the popular form; nor, supposing that both were combined into one picture, what this picture really looked like. We know only the form of eschatology which meets us in the Gospels and in the Pauline epistles; that is to say, the form which it took in the Christian community in consequence of the coming of Jesus. And to combine these three—the prophetic, the Late-Jewish apocalyptic, and the Christian—has not proved possible.

What was the nature of the contemporary Jewish world of thought? There isn’t a clear answer to that question. We don’t know if the expectation of the Messiah was commonly held or just a belief of a small group. It had nothing to do with the Mosaic religion itself. There was no real connection between religious observance and future hope. Additionally, if the idea of eschatological hope was widespread, was it based on prophetic or apocalyptic beliefs? We know the Messianic expectations from the prophets and the apocalyptic visions presented by Daniel, as well as the works of Enoch and the Psalms of Solomon before Jesus arrived, along with the Apocalypses of Ezra and Baruch around the time of Jerusalem's destruction. But we don’t know which of these was the most popular; nor can we determine what a combined vision of both might have actually looked like. The only version of eschatology we are familiar with comes from the Gospels and the Pauline epistles, meaning the form it took in the Christian community as a result of Jesus' coming. Trying to merge these three perspectives—the prophetic, the Late-Jewish apocalyptic, and the Christian—has turned out to be impossible.

Even supposing we could obtain more exact information regarding the popular Messianic expectations at the time of Jesus, we should still not know what form they assumed in the self-consciousness [pg 009] of One who knew Himself to be the Messiah but held that the time was not yet come for Him to reveal Himself as such. We only know their aspect from without, as a waiting for the Messiah and the Messianic Age; we have no clue to their aspect from within as factors in the Messianic self-consciousness. We possess no psychology of the Messiah. The Evangelists have nothing to tell us about it, because Jesus told them nothing about it; the sources for the contemporary spiritual life inform us only concerning the eschatological expectation. For the form of the Messianic self-consciousness of Jesus we have to fall back upon conjecture.

Even if we could get more precise information about the popular Messianic expectations during Jesus's time, we still wouldn’t understand how they played out in the self-awareness [pg 009] of someone who recognized themselves as the Messiah but believed it wasn’t the right time to reveal that. We only see them as an external waiting for the Messiah and the Messianic Age; we lack insight into how they influenced the internal Messianic self-awareness. We don’t have a psychology of the Messiah. The Evangelists don’t provide details about it because Jesus never discussed it with them; the sources related to the spiritual life of the time only tell us about eschatological expectations. To understand the nature of Jesus's Messianic self-awareness, we have to rely on speculation.

Such is the character of the problem, and, as a consequence, historical experiment must here take the place of historical research. That being so, it is easy to understand that to take a survey of the study of the life of Jesus is to be confronted, at first sight, with a scene of the most boundless confusion. A series of experiments are repeated with constantly varying modifications suggested by the results furnished by the subsidiary sciences. Most of the writers, however, have no suspicion that they are merely repeating an experiment which has often been made before. Some of them discover this in the course of their work to their own great astonishment—it is so, for instance, with Wrede, who recognises that he is working out, though doubtless with a clearer consciousness of his aim, an idea of Bruno Bauer's.5 If old Reimarus were to come back again, he might confidently give himself out to be the latest of the moderns, for his work rests upon a recognition of the exclusive importance of eschatology, such as only recurs again in Johannes Weiss.

Such is the nature of the problem, and as a result, historical experiments must replace historical research here. Given that, it's easy to see that surveying the study of Jesus's life initially confronts us with a scene of immense confusion. A series of experiments are conducted with constantly changing modifications based on results from related fields. However, most writers are unaware that they are just repeating an experiment that has been done many times before. Some of them realize this during their work, often to their own surprise—Wrede, for example, comes to understand that he is developing an idea originally proposed by Bruno Bauer, though with a clearer awareness of his intentions. If old Reimarus were to return, he could confidently claim to be among the latest modern thinkers, as his work emphasizes the exclusive significance of eschatology, an idea that only resurfaces with Johannes Weiss.

Progress, too, is curiously fitful, with long intervals of marking time between the advances. From Strauss down to the 'nineties there was no real progress, if one takes into consideration only the complete Lives of Jesus which appeared. But a number of separate problems took a more clearly defined form, so that in the end the general problem suddenly moved forward, as it seemed, with a jerk.

Progress is also oddly inconsistent, with long periods of stagnation between advancements. From Strauss to the 1890s, there wasn't any significant progress if we only consider the complete Lives of Jesus that were published. However, several individual issues became more clearly defined, so in the end, the overall problem suddenly seemed to advance with a jolt.

There is really no common standard by which to judge the works with which we have to do. It is not the most orderly narratives, those which weave in conscientiously every detail of the text, which have advanced the study of the subject, but precisely the eccentric ones, those that take the greatest liberties with the text. It is not by the mass of facts that a writer sets down alongside of one another as possible—because he writes easily and there is no one there to contradict him, and because facts on paper do not come into collision so sharply as they do in reality—it is not in that way that he shows his power of reconstructing history, but by that which he recognises as impossible. The constructions [pg 010] of Reimarus and Bruno Bauer have no solidity; they are mere products of the imagination. But there is much more historical power in their clear grasp of a single definite problem, which has blinded them to all else, than there is in the circumstantial works of Beyschlag and Bernard Weiss.

There really isn’t a common standard to judge the works we’re dealing with. It’s not the most organized narratives, the ones that carefully include every detail of the text, that have pushed the study of the subject forward, but the unusual ones, those that take the most liberties with the text. It’s not by piling up facts side by side as possible—just because a writer is able to do so easily with no one there to challenge him, and because facts on paper don’t clash as sharply as they do in real life—that he demonstrates his ability to reconstruct history, but by what he recognizes as impossible. The constructions [pg 010] of Reimarus and Bruno Bauer lack substance; they are merely products of imagination. However, there’s much more historical insight in their clear understanding of a single specific problem, which has blinded them to everything else, than there is in the detailed works of Beyschlag and Bernard Weiss.

But once one has accustomed oneself to look for certain definite landmarks amid this apparent welter of confusion one begins at last to discover in vague outline the course followed, and the progress made, by the critical study of the life of Jesus.

But once you get used to looking for specific landmarks in this sea of confusion, you finally start to see, in broad strokes, the path taken and the progress made by the critical study of Jesus's life.

It falls, immediately, into two periods, that before Strauss and that after Strauss. The dominant interest in the first is the question of miracle. What terms are possible between a historical treatment and the acceptance of supernatural events? With the advent of Strauss this problem found a solution, viz., that these events have no rightful place in the history, but are simply mythical elements in the sources. The way was thus thrown open. Meanwhile, alongside of the problem of the supernatural, other problems had been dimly apprehended. Reimarus had drawn attention to the contemporary eschatological views; Hase, in his first Life of Jesus (1829), had sought to trace a development in the self-consciousness of Jesus.

It divides right away into two periods: before Strauss and after Strauss. The main focus in the first period is the question of miracles. What kind of relationship can exist between a historical approach and the acceptance of supernatural events? With the arrival of Strauss, this issue was addressed, namely, that these events don’t truly belong in history but are merely mythical elements found in the sources. This opened the door for further exploration. At the same time, alongside the question of the supernatural, other issues were starting to be recognized. Reimarus highlighted the contemporary views on eschatology; Hase, in his first Life of Jesus (1829), aimed to outline changes in Jesus’ self-awareness.

But on this point a clear view was impossible, because all the students of the subject were still basing their operations upon the harmony of the Synoptics and the Fourth Gospel; which means that they had not so far felt the need of a historically intelligible outline of the life of Jesus. Here, too, Strauss was the light-bringer. But the transient illumination was destined to be obscured by the Marcan hypothesis,6 which now came to the front. The necessity of choosing between John and the Synoptists was first fully established by the Tübingen school; and the right relation of this question to the Marcan hypothesis was subsequently shown by Holtzmann.

But on this point, it was hard to get a clear view because all the students studying the subject were still relying on the harmony of the Synoptics and the Fourth Gospel. This means they hadn’t yet realized the need for a historically clear outline of Jesus's life. In this area, Strauss was the one who brought new insights. However, the temporary clarity became overshadowed by the Marcan hypothesis, which then came into focus. The necessity of choosing between John and the Synoptists was first clearly established by the Tübingen school, and Holtzmann later demonstrated the correct relationship between this question and the Marcan hypothesis.

While these discussions of the preliminary literary questions were in progress the main historical problem of the life of Jesus was slowly rising into view. The question began to be mooted: what was the significance of eschatology for the mind of Jesus? With this problem was associated, in virtue of an inner connexion which was not at first suspected, the problem of the self-consciousness of Jesus. At the beginning of the 'nineties it was generally felt that, in the solution given to this dual problem, an in some measure assured knowledge of the outward and inward course of the life of Jesus had been reached. At this point Johannes Weiss revived the comprehensive claim of Reimarus on behalf of [pg 011] eschatology; and scarcely had criticism adjusted its attitude to this question when Wrede renewed the attempt of Bauer and Volkmar to eliminate altogether the Messianic element from the life of Jesus.

While these discussions about the initial literary questions were happening, the main historical issue regarding the life of Jesus was gradually coming into focus. The question started to arise: what was the significance of eschatology for Jesus's mindset? This issue was linked, in a way that wasn’t initially recognized, to the question of Jesus's self-awareness. In the early '90s, it was widely believed that this dual problem had led to a fairly certain understanding of both the external and internal aspects of Jesus's life. At this point, Johannes Weiss brought back the comprehensive argument made by Reimarus concerning eschatology; and just as criticism was adjusting its stance on this issue, Wrede reignited the efforts of Bauer and Volkmar to completely remove the Messianic aspect from Jesus’s life.

We are now once more in the midst of a period of great activity in the study of the subject. On the one side we are offered a historical solution, on the other a literary. The question at issue is: Is it possible to explain the contradiction between the Messianic consciousness of Jesus and His non-Messianic discourses and actions by means of a conception of His Messianic consciousness which will make it appear that He could not have acted otherwise than as the Evangelists describe; or must we endeavour to explain the contradiction by taking the non-Messianic discourses and actions as our fixed point, denying the reality of His Messianic self-consciousness and regarding it as a later interpolation of the beliefs of the Christian community into the life of Jesus? In the latter case the Evangelists are supposed to have attributed these Messianic claims to Jesus because the early Church held Him to be the Messiah, but to have contradicted themselves by describing His life as it actually was, viz., as the life of a prophet, not of one who held Himself to be the Messiah. To put it briefly: Does the difficulty of explaining the historical personality of Jesus lie in the history itself, or only in the way in which it is represented in the sources?

We are currently in a time of intense activity around the study of this topic. On one side, we have a historical explanation, and on the other, a literary one. The main question is: Can we explain the contradiction between Jesus' Messianic consciousness and His non-Messianic teachings and actions by suggesting that His Messianic awareness made it impossible for Him to act any differently than the Evangelists describe? Or should we try to explain the contradiction by taking His non-Messianic statements and actions as the primary reference point, rejecting the reality of His Messianic self-awareness and viewing it as a later addition of the beliefs of the Christian community projected onto Jesus' life? In this latter case, the Evangelists are seen as having attributed these Messianic claims to Jesus because the early Church believed He was the Messiah, while also contradicting themselves by depicting His life as it actually was—as the life of a prophet, not someone who saw Himself as the Messiah. To summarize: Is the challenge of explaining the historical figure of Jesus found in the history itself, or only in how it is portrayed in the sources?

This alternative will be discussed in all the critical studies of the next few years. Once clearly posed it compels a decision. But no one can really understand the problem who has not a clear notion of the way in which it has shaped itself in the course of the investigation; no one can justly criticise, or appraise the value of, new contributions to the study of this subject unless he knows in what forms they have been presented before.

This alternative will be examined in all the critical studies over the next few years. Once it's clearly defined, it forces a decision. However, no one can truly grasp the issue without a clear understanding of how it has developed throughout the investigation; no one can fairly critique or evaluate the significance of new contributions to this subject unless they know how they have been presented before.

The history of the study of the life of Jesus has hitherto received surprisingly little attention. Hase, in his Life of Jesus of 1829, briefly records the previous attempts to deal with the subject. Friedrich von Ammon, himself one of the most distinguished students in this department, in his “Progress of Christianity,”7 gives some information “regarding the most notable biographies of Jesus of the last fifty years.” In the year 1865 Uhlhorn treated together the Lives of Jesus of Renan, Schenkel, and Strauss; in 1876 Hase, in his “History of Jesus,” gave the only complete literary history of the subject;8 in 1892 Uhlhorn extended his former lecture to include the works of Keim, Delff, Beyschlag, and Weiss;9 in 1898 [pg 012] Frantzen described, in a short essay, the progress of the study since Strauss;10 in 1899 and 1900 Baldensperger gave, in the Theologische Rundschau, a survey of the most recent publications;11 Weinel's book, “Jesus in the Nineteenth Century,” naturally only gives an analysis of a few classical works; Otto Schmiedel's lecture on the “Main Problems of the Critical Study of the Life of Jesus” (1902) merely sketches the history of the subject in broad outline.12

The history of studying the life of Jesus has received surprisingly little attention until now. Hase, in his Life of Jesus from 1829, briefly notes the previous attempts to explore the subject. Friedrich von Ammon, one of the leading scholars in this field, in his “Advancement of Christianity,”7 shares some details "about the most notable biographies of Jesus from the past fifty years." In 1865, Uhlhorn looked at the Lives of Jesus by Renan, Schenkel, and Strauss together; in 1876, Hase, in his "Life of Jesus," provided the only complete literary history on the topic; 8 in 1892 Uhlhorn expanded his earlier lecture to include the works of Keim, Delff, Beyschlag, and Weiss; 9 in 1898 [pg 012] Frantzen outlined, in a short essay, the advancements in the study since Strauss; 10 in 1899 and 1900, Baldensperger provided a summary of the latest publications in the Theological Review; 11 Weinel's book, “Jesus in the 1800s,” naturally offers an analysis of only a few classic works; Otto Schmiedel's lecture on the “Main Issues in the Critical Study of Jesus’ Life” (1902) only outlines the history of the topic in broad strokes.12

Apart from scattered notices in histories of theology this is practically all the literature of the subject. There is room for an attempt to bring order into the chaos of the Lives of Jesus. Hase made ingenious comparisons between them, but he was unable to group them according to inner principles, or to judge them justly. Weisse is for him a feebler descendant of Strauss, Bruno Bauer is the victim of a fantastic imagination. It would indeed have been difficult for Hase to discover in the works of his time any principle of division. But now, when the literary and eschatological methods of solution have led to complementary results, when the post-Straussian period of investigation seems to have reached a provisional close, and the goal to which it has been tending has become clear, the time seems ripe for the attempt to trace genetically in the successive works the shaping of the problem as it now confronts us, and to give a systematic historical account of the critical study of the life of Jesus. Our endeavour will be to furnish a graphic description of all the attempts to deal with the subject; and not to dismiss them with stock phrases or traditional labels, but to show clearly what they really did to advance the formulation of the problem, whether their contemporaries recognised it or not. In accordance with this principle many famous Lives of Jesus which have prolonged an honoured existence through many successive editions, will make but a poor figure, while others, which have received scant notice, will appear great. Behind Success comes Truth, and her reward is with her.

Aside from scattered mentions in the history of theology, this is pretty much all the literature on the topic. There's a need for an attempt to organize the confusion around the Lives of Jesus. Hase made clever comparisons between them, but he couldn't categorize them based on their internal principles or evaluate them fairly. Weisse is a weaker version of Strauss, and Bruno Bauer is caught up in a wild imagination. It would indeed have been tough for Hase to find any dividing principle in the works of his time. But now, as literary and eschatological methods of exploring the topic have led to complementary outcomes, and the post-Straussian era of research seems to have reached a temporary conclusion with a clearer understanding of its goal, the time is right to trace the development of the problem as it stands today in various works and provide a systematic historical overview of the critical study of Jesus's life. Our goal will be to provide a vivid description of all the attempts to tackle the subject; we won't brush them off with cliché phrases or traditional labels but will clearly illustrate what they contributed to the formulation of the problem, regardless of whether their contemporaries acknowledged it. Following this approach, many well-known Lives of Jesus that have enjoyed a long-standing presence through numerous editions will seem less impressive, while others that have received little attention will stand out. In the end, Truth follows Success, and her reward comes with her.

[pg 013]

II. Hermann Samuel Reimarus

Von dem Zwecke Jesu und seiner Jünger. Noch ein Fragment des Wolfenbüttelschen Ungenannten. Herausgegeben von Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. Braunschweig, 1778, 276 pp. (The Aims of Jesus and His Disciples. A further Instalment of the anonymous Wolfenbüttel Fragments. Published by Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. Brunswick, 1778.)

The Purpose of Jesus and His Disciples. Another piece from the anonymous Wolfenbüttel papers. Published by Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. Brunswick, 1778, 276 pages. (The Goals of Jesus and His Disciples. A continuation of the anonymous Wolfenbüttel Fragments. Published by Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. Brunswick, 1778.)

Johann Salomo Semler. Beantwortung der Fragmente eines Ungenannten insbesondere vom Zwecke Jesu und seiner Jünger. (Reply to the anonymous Fragments, especially to that entitled The Aims of Jesus and His Disciples.) Halle, 1779, 432 pp.

Johann Salomo Semler. Response to the Anonymous Fragments, particularly regarding the purpose of Jesus and His Disciples. (Reply to the anonymous Fragments, especially the one titled __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__) The Objectives of Jesus and His Followers.Halle, 1779, 432 pages.

Before Reimarus, no one had attempted to form a historical conception of the life of Jesus. Luther had not so much as felt that he cared to gain a clear idea of the order of the recorded events. Speaking of the chronology of the cleansing of the Temple, which in John falls at the beginning, in the Synoptists near the close, of Jesus' public life, he remarks: “The Gospels follow no order in recording the acts and miracles of Jesus, and the matter is not, after all, of much importance. If a difficulty arises in regard to the Holy Scripture and we cannot solve it, we must just let it alone.” When the Lutheran theologians began to consider the question of harmonising the events, things were still worse. Osiander (1498-1552), in his “Harmony of the Gospels,” maintained the principle that if an event is recorded more than once in the Gospels, in different connexions, it happened more than once and in different connexions. The daughter of Jairus was therefore raised from the dead several times; on one occasion Jesus allowed the devils whom He cast out of a single demoniac to enter into a herd of swine, on another occasion, those whom He cast out of two demoniacs; there were two cleansings of the Temple, and so forth.13 The correct view of the Synoptic Gospels as being interdependent was first formulated by Griesbach.

Before Reimarus, no one had tried to create a historical understanding of Jesus’ life. Luther didn’t even seem interested in getting a clear picture of the order of the recorded events. When discussing the timing of the cleansing of the Temple, which appears at the beginning in John’s account but near the end in the Synoptics, he noted: "The Gospels don't follow a specific sequence in detailing the actions and miracles of Jesus, and that's not really a big deal. If we come across a confusing issue in the Holy Scripture and can't find an answer, we should just leave it alone." When Lutheran theologians began to tackle the idea of harmonizing the events, the situation was even more problematic. Osiander (1498-1552), in his “Harmony of the Gospels” argued that if an event is mentioned multiple times in different contexts in the Gospels, it must have happened more than once in different contexts. So, the daughter of Jairus was raised from the dead several times; at one point, Jesus let the demons he cast out of a single possessed man enter a herd of pigs, and in another instance, he cast demons out of two possessed men; there were two different cleansings of the Temple, and so on.13 The first person to articulate the correct understanding of the Synoptic Gospels as being interconnected was Griesbach.

The only Life of Jesus written prior to the time of Reimarus which has any interest for us, was composed by a Jesuit in the [pg 014] Persian language. The author was the Indian missionary Hieronymus Xavier, nephew of Francis Xavier, and it was designed for the use of Akbar, the Moghul Emperor, who, in the latter part of the sixteenth century, had become the most powerful potentate in Hindustan. In the seventeenth century the Persian text was brought to Europe by a merchant, and was translated into Latin by Louis de Dieu, a theologian of the Reformed Church, whose intention in publishing it was to discredit Catholicism.14 It is a skilful falsification of the life of Jesus in which the omissions, and the additions taken from the Apocrypha, are inspired by the sole purpose of presenting to the open-minded ruler a glorious Jesus, in whom there should be nothing to offend him.

The only account of Jesus' life written before Reimarus that interests us was created by a Jesuit in the [pg 014] Persian language. The author was the Indian missionary Hieronymus Xavier, the nephew of Francis Xavier, and it was meant for Akbar, the Moghul Emperor, who had become the most powerful ruler in Hindustan in the late sixteenth century. In the seventeenth century, a merchant brought the Persian text to Europe, where it was translated into Latin by Louis de Dieu, a theologian from the Reformed Church, who aimed to undermine Catholicism.14 It is a cleverly crafted version of Jesus' life, where omissions and additions from the Apocrypha are made solely to present a glorious Jesus to the open-minded ruler, ensuring nothing would offend him.

Thus there had been nothing to prepare the world for a work of such power as that of Reimarus. It is true, there had appeared earlier, in 1768, a Life of Jesus by Johann Jakob Hess15 (1741-1828), written from the standpoint of the older rationalism, but it retains so much supernaturalism and follows so much the lines of a paraphrase of the Gospels, that there was nothing to indicate to the world what a master-stroke the spirit of the time was preparing.

Thus there had been nothing to prepare the world for a work of such power as that of Reimarus. It's true that earlier, in 1768, a Life of Jesus by Johann Jakob Hess15 (1741-1828) was published, written from the perspective of older rationalism. However, it still has a lot of supernatural elements and closely resembles a paraphrase of the Gospels, so it didn't hint to the world about the groundbreaking work the spirit of the time was getting ready to unleash.

Not much is known about Reimarus. For his contemporaries he had no existence, and it was Strauss who first made his name known in literature.16 He was born in Hamburg on the 22nd of December, 1694, and spent his life there as a professor of Oriental Languages. He died in 1768. Several of his writings appeared during his lifetime, all of them asserting the claims of rational religion as against the faith of the Church; one of them, for example, being an essay on “The Leading Truths of Natural Religion.” His magnum opus, however, which laid the historic basis of his attacks, was only circulated, during his lifetime, among his acquaintances, as an anonymous manuscript. In 1774 Lessing began to publish the most important portions of it, and up to 1778 had published seven fragments, thereby involving himself in a quarrel with Goetze, the Chief Pastor of Hamburg. The manuscript of the whole, which runs to 4000 pages, is preserved in the Hamburg municipal library.

Not much is known about Reimarus. For his contemporaries, he didn’t exist, and it was Strauss who first brought his name into the spotlight. He was born in Hamburg on December 22, 1694, and spent his life there as a professor of Oriental Languages. He died in 1768. Several of his writings were published during his lifetime, all asserting the claims of rational religion against the faith of the Church; one of these was an essay titled "The Key Principles of Natural Religion." His masterpiece, however, which laid the historical foundation for his criticisms, was only shared among his acquaintances as an anonymous manuscript. In 1774, Lessing began publishing the most important sections of it, and by 1778, he had published seven fragments, which led to a dispute with Goetze, the Chief Pastor of Hamburg. The complete manuscript, which consists of 4000 pages, is kept in the Hamburg municipal library.

The following are the titles of Fragments which he published:

The following are the titles of the fragments that he published:

The Toleration of the Deists.

The Acceptance of the Deists.

The Decrying of Reason in the Pulpit.

The Denouncement of Reason in the Pulpit.

The impossibility of a Revelation which all men should have good grounds for believing.

The impossibility of a Revelation that everyone would have solid reasons to believe.

[pg 015]

The Passing of the Israelites through the Red Sea.

The Crossing of the Israelites through the Red Sea.

Showing that the books of the Old Testament were not written to reveal a Religion.

Showing that the books of the Old Testament weren't written to reveal a religion.

Concerning the story of the Resurrection.

Concerning the story of the Resurrection.

The Aims of Jesus and His disciples.

The Goals of Jesus and His Disciples.

The monograph on the passing of the Israelites through the Red Sea is one of the ablest, wittiest, and most acute which has ever been written. It exposes all the impossibilities of the narrative in the Priestly Codex, and all the inconsistencies which arise from the combination of various sources; although Reimarus has not the slightest inkling that the separation of these sources would afford the real solution of the problem.

The monograph on the Israelites' journey through the Red Sea is one of the smartest, most clever, and insightful pieces ever written. It reveals all the impossibilities in the account found in the Priestly Codex and highlights the inconsistencies that come from merging different sources; however, Reimarus has no idea that separating these sources would provide the true answer to the problem.

To say that the fragment on “The Aims of Jesus and His Disciples” is a magnificent piece of work is barely to do it justice. This essay is not only one of the greatest events in the history of criticism, it is also a masterpiece of general literature. The language is as a rule crisp and terse, pointed and epigrammatic—the language of a man who is not “engaged in literary composition” but is wholly concerned with the facts. At times, however, it rises to heights of passionate feeling, and then it is as though the fires of a volcano were painting lurid pictures upon dark clouds. Seldom has there been a hate so eloquent, so lofty a scorn; but then it is seldom that a work has been written in the just consciousness of so absolute a superiority to contemporary opinion. And withal, there is dignity and serious purpose; Reimarus's work is no pamphlet.

To say that the fragment on "The Goals of Jesus and His Disciples" is an impressive piece of work is really an understatement. This essay is not only one of the biggest moments in the history of criticism, but it’s also a masterpiece of literature. The language is usually crisp and clear, sharp and succinct—the voice of someone who is not “writing literature” but is completely focused on the facts. However, at times, it reaches intense emotional heights, almost like the flames of a volcano creating vivid images against dark clouds. It’s rare to find such an eloquent expression of hate and such high disdain; but then, it’s rare for a work to be written with such a strong sense of complete superiority over current opinions. Throughout, there’s also dignity and a serious intent; Reimarus's work is no mere pamphlet.

Lessing could not, of course, accept its standpoint. His idea of revelation, and his conception of the Person of Jesus, were much deeper than those of the Fragmentist. He was a thinker; Reimarus only a historian. But this was the first time that a really historical mind, thoroughly conversant with the sources, had undertaken the criticism of the tradition. It was Lessing's greatness that he grasped the significance of this criticism, and felt that it must lead either to the destruction or to the re-casting of the idea of revelation. He recognised that the introduction of the historical element would transform and deepen rationalism. Convinced that the fateful moment had arrived, he disregarded the scruples of Reimarus's family and the objections of Nicolai and Mendelssohn, and, though inwardly trembling for that which he himself held sacred, he flung the torch with his own hand.

Lessing couldn't, of course, accept that viewpoint. His understanding of revelation and his view of Jesus were much more profound than those of the Fragmentist. He was a thinker; Reimarus was just a historian. But this was the first time a truly historical mind, well-versed in the sources, had taken on the critique of the tradition. Lessing's greatness lay in his ability to see the importance of this critique and realize that it could lead either to the dismantling or the reshaping of the concept of revelation. He understood that introducing the historical element would change and deepen rationalism. Believing the critical moment had arrived, he set aside the concerns of Reimarus's family and the objections of Nicolai and Mendelssohn, and, though he felt anxious about what he held sacred, he took the bold step to push forward.

Semler, at the close of his refutation of the fragment, ridicules its editor in the following apologue. “A prisoner was once brought before the Lord Mayor of London on a charge of arson. He had been seen coming down from the upper story of the burning house. ‘Yesterday,’ so ran his defence, ‘about four o'clock I went into my neighbour's store-room and saw there a burning candle which the servants had carelessly forgotten. In [pg 016] the course of the night it would have burned down, and set fire to the stairs. To make sure that the fire should break out in the day-time, I threw some straw upon it. The flames burst out at the sky-light, the fire-engines came hurrying up, and the fire, which in the night might have been dangerous, was promptly extinguished.’ ‘Why did you not yourself pick up the candle and put it out?’ asked the Lord Mayor. ‘If I had put out the candle the servants would not have learned to be more careful; now that there has been such a fuss about it, they will not be so careless in future.’ ‘Odd, very odd,’ said the Lord Mayor, ‘he is not a criminal, only a little weak in the head.’ So he had him shut up in the mad-house, and there he lies to this day.”

Semler, at the end of his rebuttal of the fragment, mocks its editor with the following fable. A prisoner was once brought before the Lord Mayor of London on a charge of arson. He had been seen coming down from the upper floor of the burning house. ‘Yesterday,’ his defense went, ‘around four o'clock, I walked into my neighbor's storage room and found a burning candle that the servants had carelessly left behind. If it had burned through the night, it could have set fire to the stairs. To make sure the fire would start during the day, I put some straw on it. The flames burst through the skylight, the fire engines rushed in, and the fire, which could have been dangerous at night, was quickly put out.’ ‘Why didn’t you just pick up the candle and put it out?’ asked the Lord Mayor. ‘If I had put out the candle, the servants wouldn’t have learned to be more careful; now that there's been such a fuss about it, they won't be so careless in the future.’ ‘Strange, very strange,’ said the Lord Mayor, ‘he is not a criminal, just a bit off in the head.’ So he had him committed to the asylum, and there he remains to this day.

The story is extraordinarily apposite—only that Lessing was not mad; he knew quite well what he was doing. His object was to show how an unseen enemy had pushed his parallels up to the very walls, and to summon to the defence “some one who should be as nearly the ideal defender of religion as the Fragmentist was the ideal assailant.” Once, with prophetic insight into the future, he says: “The Christian traditions must be explained by the inner truth of Christianity, and no written traditions can give it that inner truth, if it does not itself possess it.”

The story is extraordinarily relevant—it's just that Lessing wasn't crazy; he was fully aware of his actions. His goal was to demonstrate how an unseen enemy had pushed his arguments right up to the walls, and to call for support “from someone who should be as close to the ideal defender of religion as the Fragmentist was the perfect attacker.” Once, with a prophetic understanding of the future, he states: "The Christian traditions need to be understood through the core truth of Christianity, and no written traditions can convey that core truth unless they embody it themselves."

Reimarus takes as his starting-point the question regarding the content of the preaching of Jesus. “We are justified,” he says, “in drawing an absolute distinction between the teaching of the Apostles in their writings and what Jesus Himself in His own lifetime proclaimed and taught.” What belongs to the preaching of Jesus is clearly to be recognised. It is contained in two phrases of identical meaning, “Repent, and believe the Gospel,” or, as it is put elsewhere, “Repent, for the Kingdom of Heaven is at hand.”

Reimarus starts with the question about what Jesus preached. "We're justified," he says, "by clearly distinguishing between the teachings of the Apostles in their writings and what Jesus actually proclaimed and taught during His lifetime." It’s clear what Jesus’ preaching is. It’s captured in two phrases that mean the same thing: “Repent and believe the Gospel,” or, as stated in another way, "Repent, because the Kingdom of Heaven is near."

The Kingdom of Heaven must however be understood “according to Jewish ways of thought.” Neither Jesus nor the Baptist ever explain this expression; therefore they must have been content to have it understood in its known and customary sense. That means that Jesus took His stand within the Jewish religion, and accepted its Messianic expectations without in any way correcting them. If He gives a new development to this religion it is only in so far that He proclaims as near at hand the realisation of ideals and hopes which were alive in thousands of hearts.

The Kingdom of Heaven needs to be understood "based on Jewish perspectives." Neither Jesus nor John the Baptist ever explain this phrase; so they must have been fine with it being understood in its familiar and traditional sense. This means Jesus positioned Himself within the Jewish faith and accepted its Messianic expectations without challenging them. If He does introduce a new aspect to this faith, it’s only in that He announces the realization of ideals and hopes that were already present in the hearts of many.

There was thus no need for detailed instruction regarding the nature of the Kingdom of Heaven; the catechism and confession of the Church at its commencement consisted of a single phrase. Belief was not difficult: “they need only believe the Gospel, namely that Jesus was about to bring in the Kingdom of God.”17

There was no need for extensive teaching about the Kingdom of Heaven; the catechism and confession of the Church at its start were summed up in a single phrase. Belief was simple: "they just needed to believe the Gospel, particularly that Jesus was about to create the Kingdom of God."17

[pg 017]

As there were many among the Jews who were already waiting for the Kingdom of God, it was no wonder that in a few days, nay in a few hours, some thousands believed, although they had been told only that Jesus was the promised prophet.

As there were many people among the Jews who were already anticipating the Kingdom of God, it was no surprise that within just a few days, or even a few hours, thousands believed, even though they had only been told that Jesus was the promised prophet.

This was the sum total of what the disciples knew about the Kingdom of God when they were sent out by their Master to proclaim its coming. Their hearers would naturally think of the customary meaning of the term and the hopes which attached themselves to it. “The purpose of sending out such propagandists could only be that the Jews who groaned under the Roman yoke and had long cherished the hope of deliverance should be stirred up all over Judaea and assemble themselves in their thousands.”

This was everything the disciples understood about the Kingdom of God when they were sent out by their Master to announce its arrival. The people listening would most likely think of the usual meaning of the term and the hopes associated with it. “The purpose of sending out these messengers was to unite the Jews, who were enduring Roman oppression and had long hoped for freedom, so they would come together in large groups across Judea.”

Jesus must have known, too, that if the people believed His messengers they would look about for an earthly deliverer and turn to Him for this purpose. The Gospel, therefore, meant nothing more or less to all who heard it than that, under the leadership of Jesus, the Kingdom of Messiah was about to be brought in. For them there was no difficulty in accepting the belief that He was the Messiah, the Son of God, for this belief did not involve anything metaphysical. The nation was the Son of God; the kings of the covenant-people were Sons of God; the Messiah was in a pre-eminent sense the Son of God. Thus even in His Messianic claims Jesus remained “within the limits of humanity.”

Jesus probably understood that if people believed His messengers, they would start looking for a worldly savior and turn to Him for that purpose. The Gospel, therefore, meant nothing more or less to everyone who heard it than that, under Jesus' leadership, the Kingdom of the Messiah was about to be established. For them, there was no issue in accepting the belief that He was the Messiah, the Son of God, because this belief didn’t require anything beyond the physical realm. The nation was the Son of God; the rulers of the covenant people were Sons of God; the Messiah, in a significant sense, was the Son of God. Thus, even with His claims of being the Messiah, Jesus remained "within the bounds of humanity."

The fact that He did not need to explain to His contemporaries what He meant by the Kingdom of God constitutes a difficulty for us. The parables do not enlighten us, for they presuppose a knowledge of the conception. “If we could not gather from the writings of the Jews some further information as to what was understood at that time by the Messiah and the Kingdom of God, these points of primary importance would be very obscure and incomprehensible.”

The fact that He didn't need to explain to His peers what He meant by the Kingdom of God creates a challenge for us. The parables don't clarify things, as they assume a familiarity with the concept. "If we couldn't get more details from Jewish writings about what people understood at that time concerning the Messiah and the Kingdom of God, these main points would be quite unclear and difficult to understand."

“If, therefore, we desire to gain a historical understanding of Jesus' teaching, we must leave behind what we learned in our catechism regarding the metaphysical Divine Sonship, the Trinity, and similar dogmatic conceptions, and go out into a wholly Jewish world of thought. Only those who carry the teachings of the catechism back into the preaching of the Jewish Messiah will arrive at the idea that He was the founder of a new religion. To all unprejudiced persons it is manifest that Jesus had not the slightest intention of doing away with the Jewish religion and putting another in its place.”

“To really grasp Jesus' teachings in their historical context, we need to put aside what we've learned in catechism about Divine Sonship, the Trinity, and similar doctrines, and fully immerse ourselves in a Jewish mindset. Only those who try to apply catechism teachings to the message of the Jewish Messiah will think He started a new religion. It's obvious to anyone who is objective that Jesus never meant to replace the Jewish faith with something new.”

From Matt. v. 18 it is evident that Jesus did not break with the Law, but took His stand upon it unreservedly. If there was anything at all new in His preaching, it was the righteousness which was requisite for the Kingdom of God. The righteousness of the Law will no longer suffice in the time of the coming Kingdom; a [pg 018] new and deeper morality must come into being. This demand is the only point in which the preaching of Jesus went beyond the ideas of His contemporaries. But this new morality does not do away with the Law, for He explains it as a fulfilment of the old commandments. His followers, no doubt, broke with the Law later on. They did so, however, not in pursuance of a command of Jesus, but under the pressure of circumstances, at the time when they were forced out of Judaism and obliged to found a new religion.

From Matt. v. 18, it's clear that Jesus didn't reject the Law; instead, He fully embraced it. If there was anything new in His teachings, it was the kind of righteousness necessary for the Kingdom of God. The righteousness defined by the Law won’t be enough in the coming Kingdom; a new, deeper sense of morality has to emerge. This demand is the only aspect in which Jesus’ message surpassed the beliefs of His time. However, this new morality doesn't eliminate the Law; He interprets it as a fulfillment of the old commandments. His followers eventually distanced themselves from the Law, but they did so not because Jesus commanded it, but due to circumstances that forced them out of Judaism and into establishing a new religion.

Jesus shared the Jewish racial exclusiveness wholly and unreservedly. According to Matt. x. 5 He forbade His disciples to declare to the Gentiles the coming of the Kingdom of God. Evidently, therefore, His purpose did not embrace them. Had it been otherwise, the hesitation of Peter in Acts x. and xi., and the necessity of justifying the conversion of Cornelius, would be incomprehensible.

Jesus fully shared the Jewish belief in racial exclusivity. According to Matt. x. 5, He instructed His disciples not to tell the Gentiles about the coming of the Kingdom of God. Clearly, His mission didn’t include them. If it had, Peter's uncertainty in Acts x. and xi., as well as the need to justify Cornelius's conversion, would make no sense.

Baptism and the Lord's Supper are no evidence that Jesus intended to found a new religion. In the first place the genuineness of the command to baptize in Matt. xxviii. 19 is questionable, not only as a saying ascribed to the risen Jesus, but also because it is universalistic in outlook, and because it implies the doctrine of the Trinity and, consequently, the metaphysical Divine Sonship of Jesus. In this it is inconsistent with the earliest traditions regarding the practice of baptism in the Christian community, for in the earliest times, as we learn from the Acts and from Paul, it was the custom to baptize, not in the name of the Trinity, but in the name of Jesus, the Messiah.

Baptism and the Lord's Supper don't prove that Jesus intended to start a new religion. First of all, the authenticity of the command to baptize in Matt. xxviii. 19 is questionable, not just as a saying attributed to the risen Jesus, but also because it has a universal perspective and suggests the doctrine of the Trinity, which implies the metaphysical Divine Sonship of Jesus. This is inconsistent with the earliest traditions surrounding baptism in the Christian community, since we learn from the Acts and from Paul that in the early days, the practice was to baptize not in the name of the Trinity, but in the name of Jesus, the Messiah.

But, furthermore, it is questionable whether Baptism really goes back to Jesus at all. He Himself baptized no one in His own lifetime, and never commanded any of His converts to be baptized. So we cannot be sure about the origin of Baptism, though we can be sure of its meaning. Baptism in the name of Jesus signified only that Jesus was the Messiah. “For the only change which the teaching of Jesus made in their religion was that whereas they had formerly believed in a Deliverer of Israel who was to come in the future, they now believed in a Deliverer who was already present.”

But, moreover, it’s debatable whether Baptism actually goes back to Jesus at all. He didn’t baptize anyone during His lifetime and never instructed any of His followers to be baptized. So we can’t be certain about the origin of Baptism, although we can be confident in its meaning. Baptism in the name of Jesus meant simply that Jesus was the Messiah. “The only change that Jesus’ teaching brought to their religion was that, while they had previously believed in a future Deliverer of Israel, they now believed in a Deliverer who was already present.”

The “Lord's Supper,” again, was no new institution, but merely an episode at the last Paschal Meal of the Kingdom which was passing away, and was intended “as an anticipatory celebration of the Passover of the New Kingdom.” A Lord's Supper in our sense, “cut loose from the Passover,” would have been inconceivable to Jesus, and not less so to His disciples.

The "Communion," was not a new practice, but rather a moment during the last Passover Meal of the old Kingdom that was fading away. It was meant "as a forward-looking celebration of the Passover of the New Kingdom." A Lord's Supper, in the way we understand it today, “break free from the Passover,” would have been unimaginable to Jesus and equally so to His disciples.

It is useless to appeal to the miracles, any more than to the “Sacraments,” as evidence for the founding of a new religion. In the first place, we have to remember what happens in the case of miracles handed down by tradition. That Jesus effected cures, [pg 019] which in the eyes of His contemporaries were miraculous, is not to be denied. Their purpose was to prove Him to be the Messiah. He forbade these miracles to be made known, even in cases where they could not possibly be kept hidden, “with the sole purpose of making people more eager to talk of them.” Other miracles, however, have no basis in fact, but owe their place in the narrative to the feeling that the miracle-stories of the Old Testament must be repeated in the case of Jesus, but on a grander scale. He did no really miraculous works; otherwise, the demands for a sign would be incomprehensible. In Jerusalem when all the people were looking eagerly for an overwhelming manifestation of His Messiahship, what a tremendous effect a miracle would have produced! If only a single miracle had been publicly, convincingly, undeniably, performed by Jesus before all the people on one of the great days of the Feast, such is human nature that all the people would at once have flocked to His standard.

It's pointless to reference miracles, just like the “Sacraments,” as proof for starting a new religion. First, we need to consider what happens with miracles passed down through tradition. It's undeniable that Jesus performed healings that seemed miraculous to His contemporaries. Their purpose was to establish Him as the Messiah. He even prohibited these miracles from being publicized, even in situations where they could not be hidden, “to make people more eager to talk about them.” However, some miracles have no factual basis and are included in the narrative simply because it felt necessary to echo the miracle stories from the Old Testament, but on a grander scale. He didn’t perform any truly miraculous acts; otherwise, the demands for a sign wouldn’t make sense. In Jerusalem, when everyone was eagerly anticipating a clear demonstration of His Messiahship, just imagine the impact a miracle would have had! If even one convincing, undeniable miracle had been performed by Jesus in front of everyone during one of the major feast days, human nature being what it is, people would have rushed to support Him immediately.

For this popular uprising, however, He waited in vain. Twice He believed that it was near at hand. The first time was when He was sending out the disciples and said to them: “Ye shall not have gone over the cities of Israel before the Son of Man comes” (Matt. x. 23). He thought that, at the preaching of the disciples, the people would flock to Him from every quarter and immediately proclaim Him Messiah; but His expectation was disappointed.

For this popular uprising, though, He waited in vain. Twice He thought it was close. The first time was when He was sending out the disciples and told them: "You won’t have traveled through the cities of Israel before the Son of Man arrives." (Matt. x. 23). He believed that as the disciples preached, people would come to Him from all directions and immediately declare Him the Messiah; but His hopes were dashed.

The second time, He thought to bring about the decisive issue in Jerusalem. He made His entry riding on an ass's colt, that the Messianic prophecy of Zechariah might be fulfilled. And the people actually did cry “Hosanna to the Son of David!” Relying on the support of His followers He might now, He thought, bid defiance to the authorities. In the temple He arrogates to Himself supreme power, and in glowing words calls for an open revolt against the Sanhedrin and the Pharisees, on the ground that they have shut the doors of the Kingdom of Heaven and forbidden others to go in. There is no doubt, now, that He will carry the people with Him! Confident in the success of His cause, He closes the great incendiary harangue in Matt. xxiii. with the words “Truly from henceforth ye shall not see me again until ye shall say Blessed is he that cometh in the name of the Lord”; that is, until they should hail Him as Messiah.

The second time, He aimed to address the critical issue in Jerusalem. He entered riding on a donkey's colt to fulfill the Messianic prophecy of Zechariah. And the people actually shouted "Cheers to the Son of David!" With the support of His followers, He thought He could now stand up to the authorities. In the temple, He claimed supreme power for Himself, passionately calling for an open revolt against the Sanhedrin and the Pharisees, arguing that they had closed the doors to the Kingdom of Heaven and prevented others from entering. There was no doubt that He would rally the people behind Him! Confident in the success of His message, He concluded the powerful speech in Matt. xxiii. with the words "From now on, you won’t see me again until you say, 'Blessed is he who comes in the name of the Lord.'"; meaning, until they acknowledged Him as Messiah.

But the people in Jerusalem refused to rise, as the Galilaeans had refused at the time when the disciples were sent out to rouse them. The Council prepared for vigorous action. The voluntary concealment by which Jesus had thought to whet the eagerness of the people became involuntary. Before His arrest He was overwhelmed with dread, and on the cross He closed His life with the words “My God! my God! why hast Thou forsaken me?” “This avowal cannot, without violence, be interpreted otherwise than as [pg 020] meaning that God had not aided Him in His aim and purpose as He had hoped. That shows that it had not been His purpose to suffer and die, but to establish an earthly kingdom and deliver the Jews from political oppression—and in that God's help had failed Him.”

But the people in Jerusalem refused to respond, just like the Galileans had when the disciples were sent to wake them up. The Council got ready for strong action. The voluntary hiding that Jesus thought would spark the people's interest turned into something forced. Before His arrest, He was filled with fear, and on the cross, He ended His life with the words “My God! My God! Why have You forsaken me?” "This statement can't be understood any other way without twisting it, which means that God didn't assist Him in His goals and plans as He had wished. This shows that His aim was not to suffer and die, but to establish an earthly kingdom and liberate the Jews from political oppression—and in that, God’s support fell short."

For the disciples this turn of affairs meant the destruction of all the dreams for the sake of which they had followed Jesus. For if they had given up anything on His account, it was only in order to receive it again an hundredfold when they should openly take their places in the eyes of all the world as the friends and ministers of the Messiah, as the rulers of the twelve tribes of Israel. Jesus never disabused them of this sensuous hope, but, on the contrary, confirmed them in it. When He put an end to the quarrel about pre-eminence, and when He answered the request of the sons of Zebedee, He did not attack the assumption that there were to be thrones and power, but only addressed Himself to the question how men were in the present to establish their claims to that position of authority.

For the disciples, this change meant the end of all the dreams for which they had followed Jesus. They had sacrificed so much for Him, hoping to be rewarded a hundred times over when they would finally be recognized as friends and ministers of the Messiah, as the leaders of the twelve tribes of Israel. Jesus never corrected them about this hopeful expectation; instead, He reinforced it. When He settled the argument about who would be the greatest and responded to the request from the sons of Zebedee, He didn’t challenge the idea that there would be thrones and power. He simply focused on how people could claim that position of authority in the present.

All this implies that the time of the fulfilment of these hopes was not thought of by Jesus and His disciples as at all remote. In Matt. xvi. 28, for example, He says: “Truly I say unto you there are some standing here who shall not taste of death, till they see the Son of man coming in his kingdom.” There is no justification for twisting this about or explaining it away. It simply means that Jesus promises the fulfilment of all Messianic hopes before the end of the existing generation.

All this suggests that Jesus and His disciples believed the time for realizing these hopes was not far off at all. In Matt. xvi. 28, for example, He says: “Honestly, I tell you, some of the people here will not die before they see the Son of Man coming in His kingdom.” There's no reason to twist or disregard this. It simply means that Jesus promises to fulfill all Messianic hopes before the end of the current generation.

Thus the disciples were prepared for anything rather than that which actually happened. Jesus had never said a word to them about His dying and rising again, otherwise they would not have so played the coward at His death, nor have been so astonished at His “resurrection.” The three or four sayings referring to these events must therefore have been put into His mouth later, in order to make it appear that He had foreseen these events in His original plan.

Thus the disciples were ready for anything except what actually happened. Jesus had never mentioned anything about His death and resurrection; otherwise, they wouldn’t have acted so cowardly at His death, nor would they have been so shocked by His “resurrection.” The few statements referring to these events must have been added later to suggest that He had predicted them in His original plan.

How, then, did they get over this apparently annihilating blow? By falling back upon the second form of the Jewish Messianic hope. Hitherto their thoughts, like those of their Master, had been dominated by the political ideal of the prophets—the scion of David's line who should appear as the political deliverer of the nation. But alongside of that there existed another Messianic expectation which transferred everything to the supernatural sphere. Appearing first in Daniel, this expectation can still be traced in the Apocalypses, in Justin's “Dialogue with Trypho,” and in certain Rabbinic sayings. According to these—Reimarus makes use especially of the statements of Trypho—the Messiah is to appear twice; once in human lowliness, the second time upon the clouds of heaven. When the first [pg 021] systema, as Reimarus calls it, was annihilated by the death of Jesus, the disciples brought forward the second, and gathered followers who shared their expectation of a second coming of Jesus the Messiah. In order to get rid of the difficulty of the death of Jesus, they gave it the significance of a spiritual redemption—which had not previously entered their field of vision or that of Jesus Himself.

How did they overcome this seemingly devastating blow? By relying on the second form of the Jewish Messianic hope. Until then, their thoughts, like those of their Master, had been focused on the political ideal of the prophets—the descendant of David who would appear as the political savior of the nation. However, there was also another Messianic expectation that shifted everything to the supernatural realm. This idea first appeared in Daniel and can still be found in the Apocalypses, in Justin's "Chat with Trypho," and in certain Rabbinic sayings. According to these—Reimarus particularly emphasizes Trypho's statements—the Messiah is expected to appear twice; first in human humility, and then again on the clouds of heaven. When the first [pg 021] system, as Reimarus puts it, was shattered by Jesus's death, the disciples introduced the second expectation and gathered followers who shared their hope for Jesus the Messiah's second coming. To address the challenge posed by Jesus's death, they assigned it the meaning of spiritual redemption—which had not previously been considered by them or even by Jesus Himself.

But this spiritual interpretation of His death would not have helped them if they had not also invented the resurrection. Immediately after the death of Jesus, indeed, such an idea was far from their thoughts. They were in deadly fear and kept close within doors. “Soon, however, one and another ventures to slip out. They learn that no judicial search is being made for them.” Then they consider what is to be done. They did not take kindly to the idea of returning to their old haunts; on their journeyings the companions of the Messiah had forgotten how to work. They had seen that the preaching of the Kingdom of God will keep a man. Even when they had been sent out without wallet or money they had not lacked. The women who are mentioned in Luke viii. 2, 3, had made it their business to make good provision for the Messiah and His future ministers.

But this spiritual understanding of His death wouldn't have helped them if they hadn't also come up with the idea of the resurrection. Right after Jesus died, this concept was the last thing on their minds. They were terrified and stayed shut inside. "However, soon one or another dares to sneak out. They discover that there’s no official search for them." Then they start to think about what to do next. They weren't keen on the idea of going back to their old lives; during their time with the Messiah, they had forgotten how to work. They realized that preaching the Kingdom of God is enough to sustain a person. Even when they had been sent out without any supplies or money, they hadn't gone without. The women mentioned in Luke viii. 2, 3 had taken it upon themselves to ensure that the Messiah and His future ministers were well provided for.

Why not, then, continue this mode of life? They would surely find a sufficient number of faithful souls who would join them in directing their hopes towards a second coming of the Messiah, and while awaiting the future glory, would share their possessions with them. So they stole the body of Jesus and hid it, and proclaimed to all the world that He would soon return. They prudently waited, however, for fifty days before making this announcement, in order that the body, if it should be found, might be unrecognisable.

Why not continue living like this? They would definitely find enough loyal followers who would join them in hoping for the Messiah's return, and while waiting for the future glory, they would share their belongings with them. So, they took Jesus's body and hid it, claiming to everyone that He would come back soon. They wisely waited for fifty days before making this announcement, so that if the body was discovered, it would be unrecognizable.

What was much in their favour was the complete disorganisation of the Jewish state. Had there been an efficient police administration the disciples would not have been able to plan this fraud and organise their communistic fellowship. But, as it was, the new society was not even subjected to any annoyance in consequence of the remarkable death of a married couple who were buried from the apostles' house, and the brotherhood was even allowed to confiscate their property to its own uses.

What really worked in their favor was the total chaos of the Jewish state. If there had been an effective police force, the disciples wouldn't have been able to plan this scam and set up their communal lifestyle. But, as things stood, the new group faced no trouble at all because of the strange death of a married couple who were buried from the apostles' home, and the community was even permitted to seize their belongings for its own use.

It appears, then, that the hope of the Parousia was the fundamental thing in primitive Christianity, which was a product of that hope much more than of the teaching of Jesus. Accordingly, the main problem of primitive dogmatics was the delay of the Parousia. Already in Paul's time the problem was pressing, and he had to set to work in 2 Thessalonians to discover all possible and impossible reasons why the Second Coming should be delayed. Reimarus mercilessly exposes the position of the apostle, who was obliged to fob people off somehow or other. The author of 2 Peter [pg 022] has a much clearer notion of what he would be at, and undertakes to restore the confidence of Christendom once for all with the sophism of the thousand years which are in the sight of God as one day, ignoring the fact that in the promise the reckoning was by man's years, not by God's. “Nevertheless it served the turn of the Apostles so well with those simple early Christians, that after the first believers had been bemused with it, and the period originally fixed had elapsed, the Christians of later generations, including Fathers of the Church, could continue ever after to feed themselves with empty hopes.” The saying of Christ about the generation which should not die out before His return clearly fixes this event at no very distant date. But since Jesus has not yet appeared upon the clouds of heaven “these words must be strained into meaning, not that generation, but the Jewish people. Thus by exegetical art they are saved for ever, for the Jewish race will never die out.”

It seems that the hope of the Second Coming was the core of early Christianity, which stemmed more from that hope than from Jesus' teachings. Consequently, the primary challenge for early Christian doctrine was the delay of the Second Coming. By Paul's time, this issue was urgent, prompting him to explore in 2 Thessalonians all the possible (and impossible) reasons for the postponement. Reimarus sharply criticizes the apostle, who had to find some way to appease people. The author of 2 Peter [pg 022] has a much clearer idea of what he aims to achieve and attempts to restore the faith of Christians once and for all with the argument that a thousand years is like a day in God's eyes, overlooking the fact that the promise was measured in human years, not divine. Still, this worked so effectively for the Apostles with those early Christians that after the first believers had been misled by it, and the originally expected time had come and gone, later generations of Christians, including Church Fathers, were able to hold onto empty hopes. Jesus' statement about the generation that would not pass away before His return clearly places this event in the near future. But since Jesus has not yet come down from the clouds "These words should be understood to refer not to that generation, but to the Jewish people. Therefore, through interpretation, they are kept alive forever, as the Jewish race will never vanish."

In general, however, “the theologians of the present day skim lightly over the eschatological material in the Gospels because it does not chime in with their views, and assign to the coming of Christ upon the clouds quite a different purpose from that which it bears in the teaching of Christ and His apostles.” Inasmuch as the non-fulfilment of its eschatology is not admitted, our Christianity rests upon a fraud. In view of this fact, what is the evidential value of any miracle, even if it could be held to be authentic? “No miracle would prove that two and two make five, or that a circle has four angles; and no miracles, however numerous, could remove a contradiction which lies on the surface of the teachings and records of Christianity.” Nor is there any weight in the appeal to the fulfilment of prophecy, for the cases in which Matthew countersigns it with the words “that the Scripture might be fulfilled” are all artificial and unreal; and for many incidents the stage was set by Jesus, or His disciples, or the Evangelists, with the deliberate purpose of presenting to the people a scene from the fulfilment of prophecy.

In general, however, "Today's theologians often overlook the apocalyptic themes in the Gospels because they don't fit their beliefs, and they interpret the return of Christ on the clouds as having a different purpose than what Christ and His apostles taught." Since the failure to fulfill its apocalyptic expectations is not acknowledged, our Christianity is based on a deception. Given this fact, what’s the real value of any miracle, even if it could be considered genuine? “No miracle would show that two and two make five, or that a circle has four angles; and no amount of miracles could solve a contradiction that is clear in the teachings and records of Christianity.” Moreover, the argument for the fulfillment of prophecy doesn't hold much weight, because the instances where Matthew emphasizes it with the phrase "so that the Scripture could be fulfilled" are all artificial and contrived; in many cases, the setting was created by Jesus, His disciples, or the Evangelists with the intentional aim of showcasing a scene from the fulfillment of prophecy.

The sole argument which could save the credit of Christianity would be a proof that the Parousia had really taken place at the time for which it was announced; and obviously no such proof can be produced.

The only argument that could redeem the credibility of Christianity would be evidence that the Parousia actually occurred at the time it was said to happen; and clearly, no such evidence can be provided.

Such is Reimarus' reconstruction of the history. We can well understand that his work must have given offence when it appeared, for it is a polemic, not an objective historical study. But we have no right simply to dismiss it in a word, as a Deistic production, as Otto Schmiedel, for example, does;18 it is time that Reimarus came to his own, and that we should recognise a historical performance of no mean order in this piece of Deistic polemics. [pg 023] His work is perhaps the most splendid achievement in the whole course of the historical investigation of the life of Jesus, for he was the first to grasp the fact that the world of thought in which Jesus moved was essentially eschatological. There is some justification for the animosity which flames up in his writing. This historical truth had taken possession of his mind with such overwhelming force that he could no longer understand his contemporaries, and could not away with their profession that their beliefs were, as they professed to be, directly derived from the preaching of Jesus.

This is Reimarus' reconstruction of history. It's clear that his work must have caused some offense when it was published, as it's a polemic rather than an impartial historical study. However, we shouldn't just dismiss it as a Deistic piece, as Otto Schmiedel does; it’s time that Reimarus gets the recognition he deserves, and we acknowledge that this piece of Deistic polemics represents a significant historical contribution. [pg 023] His work might be the most impressive achievement in the whole historical analysis of Jesus' life since he was the first to understand that the intellectual climate Jesus was part of was fundamentally eschatological. There’s some justification for the passionate hostility found in his writings. This historical truth had such a powerful grip on his mind that he could no longer relate to his contemporaries, nor could he accept their claims that their beliefs were directly derived from Jesus' teachings.

What added to the offence was that he saw the eschatology in a wrong perspective. He held that the Messianic ideal which dominated the preaching of Jesus was that of the political ruler, the son of David. All his other mistakes are the consequence of this fundamental error. It was, of course, a mere makeshift hypothesis to derive the beginnings of Christianity from an imposture. Historical science was not at that time sufficiently advanced to lead even the man who had divined the fundamentally eschatological character of the preaching of Jesus onward to the historical solution of the problem; it needed more than a hundred and twenty years to fill in the chasm which Reimarus had been forced to bridge with that makeshift hypothesis of his.

What made the offense worse was that he viewed eschatology in a misguided way. He believed that the Messianic ideal that shaped Jesus' preaching was that of a political leader, the son of David. All his other mistakes stemmed from this basic misunderstanding. It was merely a temporary theory to suggest that the origins of Christianity came from deceit. At that time, historical science wasn't advanced enough to guide even someone who recognized the fundamentally eschatological nature of Jesus' teachings toward a historical solution to the problem; it took more than one hundred twenty years to fill the gap that Reimarus had to cross with his makeshift theory.

In the light of the clear perception of the elements of the problem which Reimarus had attained, the whole movement of theology, down to Johannes Weiss, appears retrograde. In all its work the thesis is ignored or obscured that Jesus, as a historical personality, is to be regarded, not as the founder of a new religion, but as the final product of the eschatological and apocalyptic thought of Late Judaism. Every sentence of Johannes Weiss's Die Predigt Jesu vom Reiche Gottes (1892) is a vindication, a rehabilitation, of Reimarus as a historical thinker.

In light of the clear understanding of the elements of the problem that Reimarus achieved, the entire movement of theology, up to Johannes Weiss, seems to be moving backward. In all of its work, the main idea is ignored or obscured—that Jesus, as a historical figure, should not be seen as the founder of a new religion, but rather as the end result of the eschatological and apocalyptic thinking of Late Judaism. Every sentence of Johannes Weiss's The Sermon of Jesus on the Kingdom of God (1892) defends and rehabilitates Reimarus as a historical thinker.

Even so the traveller on the plain sees from afar the distant range of mountains. Then he loses sight of them again. His way winds slowly upwards through the valleys, drawing ever nearer to the peaks, until at last, at a turn of the path, they stand before him, not in the shapes which they had seemed to take from the distant plain, but in their actual forms. Reimarus was the first, after eighteen centuries of misconception, to have an inkling of what eschatology really was. Then theology lost sight of it again, and it was not until after the lapse of more than a hundred years that it came in view of eschatology once more, now in its true form, so far as that can be historically determined, and only after it had been led astray, almost to the last, in all its historical researches by the sole mistake of Reimarus—the assumption that the eschatology was earthly and political in character. Thus theology shared at least the error of the man whom it knew only as a Deist, not as an [pg 024] historian, and whose true greatness was not recognised even by Strauss, though he raised a literary monument to him.

Even so, the traveler on the plain sees the distant mountain range from afar. Then he loses sight of them again. His path slowly winds upward through the valleys, getting closer to the peaks, until finally, at a bend in the trail, they stand before him, not in the shapes they seemed to take from the distant plain, but in their true forms. Reimarus was the first, after eighteen centuries of misunderstanding, to have an idea of what eschatology really was. Then theology lost sight of it again, and it wasn't until over a hundred years later that it came back into view, now in its true form, as far as that can be historically determined, and only after being misled almost to the end in all its historical research by Reimarus's single mistake—the assumption that eschatology was earthly and political in nature. Thus, theology shared at least the error of the man it only knew as a Deist, not as a historian, and whose true significance was not recognized even by Strauss, though he created a literary tribute to him.

The solution offered by Reimarus may be wrong; the data of observation from which he starts out are, beyond question, right, because the primary datum of all is genuinely historical. He recognised that two systems of Messianic expectation were present side by side in Late Judaism. He endeavoured to bring them into mutual relations in order to represent the actual movement of the history. In so doing he made the mistake of placing them in consecutive order, ascribing to Jesus the political Son-of-David conception, and to the Apostles, after His death, the apocalyptic system based on Daniel, instead of superimposing one upon the other in such a way that the Messianic King might coincide with the Son of Man, and the ancient prophetic conception might be inscribed within the circumference of the Daniel-descended apocalyptic, and raised along with it to the supersensuous plane. But what matters the mistake in comparison with the fact that the problem was really grasped?

The solution presented by Reimarus might be incorrect; however, the observational data he starts with is undoubtedly accurate, as the fundamental fact is genuinely historical. He recognized that two systems of Messianic expectation coexisted in Late Judaism. He tried to relate them to each other to illustrate the actual movements in history. In doing this, he mistakenly arranged them in a sequential order, attributing the political Son-of-David idea to Jesus and to the Apostles, after His death, the apocalyptic system based on Daniel. Instead, he should have layered one over the other so that the Messianic King was aligned with the Son of Man, and the ancient prophetic idea was incorporated within the broader framework of Daniel’s apocalyptic vision, elevated alongside it to a spiritual level. But what really matters is not the mistake, but the fact that the problem was genuinely understood.

Reimarus felt that the absence in the preaching of Jesus of any definition of the principal term (the Kingdom of God), in conjunction with the great and rapid success of His preaching constituted a problem, and he formulated the conception that Jesus was not a religious founder and teacher, but purely a preacher.

Reimarus believed that the lack of a clear definition of the main term (the Kingdom of God) in Jesus' teachings, along with the swift and widespread success of His messages, posed a problem. He concluded that Jesus was not a religious founder and teacher, but simply a preacher.

He brought the Synoptic and Johannine narratives into harmony by practically leaving the latter out of account. The attitude of Jesus towards the law, and the process by which the disciples came to take up a freer attitude, was grasped and explained by him so accurately that modern historical science does not need to add a word, but would be well pleased if at least half the theologians of the present day had got as far.

He reconciled the Synoptic and Johannine accounts by basically ignoring the latter. He understood and explained Jesus' views on the law and how the disciples developed a more relaxed approach so well that modern historical research has nothing to add, and would be happy if at least half of today’s theologians reached the same understanding.

Further, he recognised that primitive Christianity was not something which grew, so to speak, out of the teaching of Jesus, but that it came into being as a new creation, in consequence of events and circumstances which added something to that preaching which it did not previously contain; and that Baptism and the Lord's Supper, in the historical sense of these terms, were not instituted by Jesus, but created by the early Church on the basis of certain historical assumptions.

Furthermore, he understood that primitive Christianity wasn't simply an offshoot of Jesus' teachings, but emerged as something entirely new, resulting from events and situations that introduced elements to that message that weren't there before. He also noted that Baptism and the Lord's Supper, in their historical context, weren't established by Jesus but were developed by the early Church based on certain historical understandings.

Again, Reimarus felt that the fact that the “event of Easter” was first proclaimed at Pentecost constituted a problem, and he sought a solution for it. He recognised, further, that the solution of the problem of the life of Jesus calls for a combination of the methods of historical and literary criticism. He felt that merely to emphasise the part played by eschatology would not suffice, but that it was necessary to assume a creative element in the tradition, to which he ascribed the miracles, the stories which turn on the [pg 025] fulfilment of Messianic prophecy, the universalistic traits and the predictions of the passion and the resurrection. Like Wrede, too, he feels that the prescription of silence in the case of miracles of healing and of certain communications to the disciples constitutes a problem which demands solution.

Again, Reimarus felt that the fact that the "Easter event" was first announced at Pentecost was an issue, and he sought a solution for it. He also recognized that solving the problem of Jesus’s life requires combining historical and literary criticism methods. He believed that simply stressing the role of eschatology wasn’t enough; it was necessary to consider a creative aspect in the tradition, which he attributed to the miracles and stories focused on the [pg 025] fulfillment of Messianic prophecy, the universal traits, and the predictions of the passion and resurrection. Like Wrede, he also felt that the silence regarding healing miracles and certain communications to the disciples posed a challenge that needed addressing.

Still more remarkable is his eye for exegetical detail. He has an unfailing instinct for pregnant passages like Matt. x. 23, xvi. 28, which are crucial for the interpretation of large masses of the history. The fact is there are some who are historians by the grace of God, who from their mother's womb have an instinctive feeling for the real. They follow through all the intricacy and confusion of reported fact the pathway of reality, like a stream which, despite the rocks that encumber its course and the windings of its valley, finds its way inevitably to the sea. No erudition can supply the place of this historical instinct, but erudition sometimes serves a useful purpose, inasmuch as it produces in its possessors the pleasing belief that they are historians, and thus secures their services for the cause of history. In truth they are at best merely doing the preliminary spade-work of history, collecting for a future historian the dry bones of fact, from which, with the aid of his natural gift, he can recall the past to life. More often, however, the way in which erudition seeks to serve history is by suppressing historical discoveries as long as possible, and leading out into the field to oppose the one true view an army of possibilities. By arraying these in support of one another it finally imagines that it has created out of possibilities a living reality.

Even more impressive is his eye for detailed interpretation. He has an unerring instinct for significant passages like Matt. x. 23 and xvi. 28, which are essential for understanding large parts of history. The truth is, some people are historians by divine grace, born with an intuitive sense of what’s real. They navigate the complexity and confusion of reported facts, finding the path of reality like a stream that, despite the rocks in its way and the twists of its valley, inevitably reaches the sea. No amount of knowledge can replace this historical instinct, but knowledge can sometimes be useful, as it gives its holders the satisfying belief that they are historians, thus securing their contribution to the study of history. In reality, they are often just doing the preliminary work for history, gathering the bare facts for a future historian who can bring the past back to life with his natural talent. More frequently, though, the way knowledge tries to serve history is by delaying meaningful historical discoveries as long as possible, and leading out into the field to counter the one true perspective with a multitude of possibilities. By supporting these possibilities, it eventually convinces itself that it has created a living reality from mere potential.

This obstructive erudition is the special prerogative of theology, in which, even at the present day, a truly marvellous scholarship often serves only to blind the eyes to elementary truths, and to cause the artificial to be preferred to the natural. And this happens not only with those who deliberately shut their minds against new impressions, but also with those whose purpose is to go forward, and to whom their contemporaries look up as leaders. It was a typical illustration of this fact when Semler rose up and slew Reimarus in the name of scientific theology.19

This obstructive knowledge is a unique privilege of theology, where, even today, remarkable scholarship often ends up blinding people to basic truths and making the artificial seem more desirable than the natural. This occurs not just with those who intentionally close their minds to new ideas, but also with those who aim to progress and are viewed by their peers as leaders. A clear example of this was when Semler attacked Reimarus in the name of scientific theology.19

Reimarus had discredited progressive theology. Students—so Semler tells us in his preface—became unsettled and sought other callings. The great Halle theologian—born in 1725—the pioneer of the historical view of the Canon, the precursor of Baur in the reconstruction of primitive Christianity, was urged to do away with the offence. As Origen of yore with Celsus, so Semler takes Reimarus sentence by sentence, in such a way that if his work were lost it could be recovered from the refutation. The fact was that Semler had nothing in the nature of a complete or well-articulated [pg 026] argument to oppose to him; therefore he inaugurated in his reply the “Yes, but” theology, which thereafter, for more than three generations, while it took, itself, the most various modifications, imagined that it had finally got rid of Reimarus and his discovery.

Reimarus had discredited progressive theology. Students—so Semler tells us in his preface—became unsettled and sought other careers. The great Halle theologian—born in 1725—the pioneer of the historical perspective on the Canon, and the precursor of Baur in reconstructing primitive Christianity, was urged to remove the offense. Just as Origen once did with Celsus, Semler examines Reimarus' work sentence by sentence, so thoroughly that if his work were lost, it could be reconstructed from the refutation. The truth was that Semler had no complete or well-structured [pg 026] argument to counter him; hence, he launched the "Yeah, but" theology in his response, which, for over three generations, while it underwent various modifications, believed it had finally rid itself of Reimarus and his discovery.

Reimarus—so ran the watchword of the guerrilla warfare which Semler waged against him—cannot be right, for he is one-sided. Jesus and His disciples employed two methods of teaching: one sensuous, pictorial, drawn from the sphere of Jewish ideas, by which they adapted their meaning to the understanding of the multitude, and endeavoured to raise them to a higher way of thinking; and alongside of that a purely spiritual teaching which was independent of that kind of imagery. Both methods of teaching continued to be used side by side, because there were always contemporary representatives of the two degrees of capability and the two kinds of temperament. “This is historically so certain that the Fragmentist's attack must inevitably be defeated at this point, because he takes account only of the sensuous representation.” But his attack was not defeated. What happened was that, owing to the respect in which Semler was held, and the absolute incapacity of contemporary theology to overtake the long stride forward made by Reimarus, his work was neglected, and the stimulus which it was capable of imparting failed to take effect. He had no predecessors; neither had he any disciples. His work is one of those supremely great works which pass and leave no trace, because they are before their time; to which later generations pay a just tribute of admiration, but owe no gratitude. Indeed it would be truer to say that Reimarus hung a mill-stone about the neck of the rising theological science of his time. He avenged himself on Semler by shaking his faith in historical theology and even in the freedom of science in general. By the end of the eighth decade of the century the Halle professor was beginning to retrace his steps, was becoming more and more disloyal to the cause which he had formerly served; and he finally went so far as to give his approval to Wöllner's edict for the regulation of religion (1788). His friends attributed this change of front to senility—he died 1791.

Reimarus—this was the catchphrase of the guerrilla warfare that Semler fought against him—can’t be right because he’s too one-sided. Jesus and His disciples used two methods of teaching: one was sensory and visual, drawn from Jewish ideas, which they used to relate their message to the understanding of the people and aimed to elevate them to a higher way of thinking; alongside this, they used a purely spiritual teaching that didn’t rely on that kind of imagery. Both teaching methods continued to be used together because there were always contemporary representatives of the two levels of ability and two types of temperament. "This is historically so certain that the Fragmentist's attack will inevitably be defeated at this point, because he only considers the sensory representation." But his attack wasn’t defeated. What happened was that, due to Semler’s respected status and the complete inability of contemporary theology to catch up with the significant progress made by Reimarus, his work was overlooked, and the potential impact it could have had was lost. He had no predecessors; he also had no followers. His work is one of those exceptionally great contributions that pass by without leaving any trace because they are ahead of their time; later generations may admire them, but they owe no gratitude to them. In fact, it might be more accurate to say that Reimarus burdened the developing theological science of his time. He took revenge on Semler by undermining his confidence in historical theology and even in the freedom of science in general. By the end of the 1780s, the Halle professor began to reconsider his stance, becoming increasingly disloyal to the cause he had once supported; he ultimately even endorsed Wöllner’s edict for regulating religion (1788). His friends blamed this shift on old age—he died in 1791.

Thus the magnificent overture in which are announced all the motifs of the future historical treatment of the life of Jesus breaks off with a sudden discord, remains isolated and incomplete, and leads to nothing further.

Thus the magnificent opening, which introduces all the motifs for the upcoming historical exploration of Jesus's life, abruptly ends with a jarring note, feels isolated and unfinished, and goes nowhere from there.

[pg 027]

III. The Lives of Jesus in Early Rationalism

Johann Jakob Hess. Geschichte der drei letzten Lebensjahre Jesu. (History of the Last Three Years of the Life of Jesus.) 3 vols., 1400 pp. Leipzig-Zurich, 1768-1772; 3rd ed., 1774 ff.; 7th ed., 1823 ff.

Johann Jakob Hess. History of the Last Three Years of the Life of Jesus. 3 volumes, 1400 pages. Leipzig-Zurich, 1768-1772; 3rd edition, 1774 and later; 7th edition, 1823 and later.

Franz Volkmar Reinhard. Versuch über den Plan, welchen der Stifter der christlichen Religion zum Besten der Menschheit entwarf. (Essay upon the Plan which the Founder of the Christian Religion adopted for the Benefit of Mankind.) 500 pp. 1781; 4th ed., 1798; 5th ed., 1830. Our account is based on the 4th ed. The 5th contains supplementary matter by Heubner.

Franz Volkmar Reinhard. Essay on the Plan the Founder of the Christian Religion Created for the Benefit of Humanity. (Essay on the Plan that the Founder of the Christian Religion Adopted for the Benefit of Mankind.) 500 pages. 1781; 4th edition, 1798; 5th edition, 1830. Our account is based on the 4th edition. The 5th includes extra material by Heubner.

Ernst August Opitz. Preacher at Zscheppelin. Geschichte und Characterzüge Jesu. (History of Jesus, with a Delineation of His Character.) Jena and Leipzig, 1812. 488 pp.

Ernst August Opitz. Preacher at Zscheppelin. The History of Jesus and a Portrait of His Character. Jena and Leipzig, 1812. 488 pages.

Johann Adolph Jakobi. Superintendent at Waltershausen. Die Geschichte Jesu für denkende und gemütvolle Leser, 1816. (The History of Jesus for thoughtful and sympathetic readers.) A second volume, containing the history of the apostolic age, followed in 1818.

Johann Adolph Jakobi. Superintendent in Waltershausen. The History of Jesus for reflective and compassionate readers, 1816. A second volume, discussing the history of the apostolic age, was published in 1818.

Johann Gottfried Herder. Vom Erlöser der Menschen. Nach unsern drei ersten Evangelien. (The Redeemer of men, as portrayed in our first three Gospels.) 1796. Von Gottes Sohn, der Welt Heiland. Nach Johannes Evangelium. (The Son of God, the Saviour of the World, as portrayed by John's Gospel.) Accompanied by a rule for the harmonisation of our Gospels on the basis of their origin and order. Riga, published by Hartknoch, 1797. See Herder's complete works, ed. Suphan, vol. xix.

Johann Gottfried Herder. The Redeemer of Humanity. Based on our first three Gospels. 1796. The Son of God, the Savior of the World. Based on the Gospel of John. Includes guidelines for harmonizing our Gospels based on their origin and order. Riga, published by Hartknoch, 1797. Refer to Herder's complete works, edited by Suphan, vol. xix.

That thorough-going theological rationalism which accepts only so much of religion as can justify itself at the bar of reason, and which conceives and represents the origin of religion in accordance with this principle, was preceded by a rationalism less complete, as yet not wholly dissociated from a simple-minded supernaturalism. Its point of view is one at which it is almost impossible for the modern man to place himself. Here, in a single consciousness, orthodoxy and rationalism lie stratified in successive layers. Here, to change the metaphor, rationalism surrounds religion without touching it, and, like a lake surrounding some ancient castle, mirrors its image with curious refractions.

That thorough theological rationalism which accepts only the parts of religion that can be justified by reason, and which understands and explains the origin of religion based on this principle, was preceded by a less complete form of rationalism, still somewhat connected to a naive supernaturalism. It's a perspective that modern individuals find nearly impossible to adopt. In this mindset, orthodoxy and rationalism coexist in different layers within a single consciousness. To use another metaphor, rationalism surrounds religion without affecting it, like a lake surrounding an ancient castle, reflecting its image with intriguing distortions.

This half-developed rationalism was conscious of an impulse—it is the first time in the history of theology that this impulse [pg 028] manifests itself—to write the Life of Jesus; at first without any suspicion whither this undertaking would lead it. No rude hands were to be laid upon the doctrinal conception of Jesus; at least these writers had no intention of laying hands upon it. Their purpose was simply to gain a clearer view of the course of our Lord's earthly and human life. The theologians who undertook this task thought of themselves as merely writing an historical supplement to the life of the God-Man Jesus. These “Lives” are, therefore, composed according to the prescription of the “good old gentleman” who in 1829 advised the young Hase to treat first of the divine, and then of the human side of the life of Jesus.

This half-formed rationalism recognized a drive—it’s the first time in theology’s history that this drive [pg 028] shows up—to write the Life of Jesus; initially without any idea of where this venture would lead. No harsh changes were to be made to the doctrinal view of Jesus; at least, these writers didn't plan to interfere with it. Their goal was simply to gain a better understanding of our Lord's earthly and human life. The theologians who took on this task considered themselves to be merely adding a historical account to the life of the God-Man Jesus. These “Life” are, therefore, structured according to the advice of the “good old dude” who in 1829 suggested to the young Hase to first discuss the divine, and then the human aspects of Jesus's life.

The battle about miracle had not yet begun. But miracle no longer plays a part of any importance; it is a firmly established principle that the teaching of Jesus, and religion in general, hold their place solely in virtue of their inner reasonableness, not by the support of outward evidence.

The debate about miracles hadn’t started yet. However, miracles are no longer significant; it’s a well-established principle that the teachings of Jesus and religion, in general, exist solely based on their inherent reasonableness, not because of external evidence.

The only thing that is really rationalistic in these older works is the treatment of the teaching of Jesus. Even those that retain the largest share of supernaturalism are as completely undogmatic as the more advanced in their reproduction of the discourses of the Great Teacher. All of them make it a principle to lose no opportunity of reducing the number of miracles; where they can explain a miracle by natural causes, they do not hesitate for a moment. But the deliberate rejection of all miracles, the elimination of everything supernatural which intrudes itself into the life of Jesus, is still to seek. That principle was first consistently carried through by Paulus. With these earlier writers it depends on the degree of enlightenment of the individual whether the irreducible minimum of the supernatural is larger or smaller.

The only thing that really showcases rationalism in these older works is how they handle the teachings of Jesus. Even those that still hold on to the most supernatural elements are just as open-minded as the more progressive ones in their retelling of the Great Teacher's discourses. They all make it a point to seize every chance to minimize the number of miracles; whenever they can explain a miracle through natural causes, they don’t hesitate for a second. However, the intentional rejection of all miracles and the removal of anything supernatural related to the life of Jesus is still yet to be found. That principle was first applied consistently by Paulus. With these earlier writers, it varies based on how enlightened the individual author is, determining whether the unavoidable supernatural elements are larger or smaller.

Moreover, the period of this older rationalism, like every period when human thought has been strong and vigorous, is wholly unhistorical. What it is looking for is not the past, but itself in the past. For it, the problem of the life of Jesus is solved the moment it succeeds in bringing Jesus near to its own time, in portraying Him as the great teacher of virtue, and showing that His teaching is identical with the intellectual truth which rationalism deifies.

Moreover, the period of this older rationalism, like every time when human thought has been strong and vigorous, is completely unhistorical. What it seeks is not the past, but rather its own identity in the past. For it, the issue of the life of Jesus is resolved the moment it manages to connect Jesus to its own time, portraying Him as the great teacher of virtue, and demonstrating that His teachings align with the intellectual truth that rationalism worships.

The temporal limits of this half-and-half rationalism are difficult to define. For the historical study of the life of Jesus the first landmark which it offers is the work of Hess, which appeared in 1768. But it held its ground for a long time side by side with rationalism proper, which failed to drive it from the field. A seventh edition of Hess's Life of Jesus appeared as late as 1823; while a fifth edition of Reinhard's work saw the light in 1830. And when Strauss struck the death-blow of out-and-out rationalism, the half-and-half rationalism did not perish with it, but allied itself [pg 029] with the neo-supernaturalism which Strauss's treatment of the life of Jesus had called into being; and it still prolongs an obscure existence in a certain section of conservative literature, though it has lost its best characteristics, its simple-mindedness and honesty.

The time limits of this mixed rationalism are hard to pinpoint. In the historical study of Jesus' life, the first significant contribution it made was Hess's work, which came out in 1768. However, it remained relevant for a long time alongside proper rationalism, which couldn't push it out. A seventh edition of Hess's Life of Jesus was published as late as 1823, and a fifth edition of Reinhard's work came out in 1830. When Strauss delivered the final blow to outright rationalism, this mixed rationalism didn’t fade away. Instead, it partnered with the neo-supernaturalism that Strauss's approach to Jesus' life had inspired; it still lingers in a certain corner of conservative literature, although it has lost its best traits, including its straightforwardness and honesty.

These older rationalistic Lives of Jesus are, from the aesthetic point of view, among the least pleasing of all theological productions. The sentimentality of the portraiture is boundless. Boundless, also, and still more objectionable, is the want of respect for the language of Jesus. He must speak in a rational and modern fashion, and accordingly all His utterances are reproduced in a style of the most polite modernity. None of the speeches are allowed to stand as they were spoken; they are taken to pieces, paraphrased, and expanded, and sometimes, with the view of making them really lively, they are recast in the mould of a freely invented dialogue. In all these Lives of Jesus, not a single one of His sayings retains its authentic form.

These older rationalistic accounts of Jesus are, from an aesthetic standpoint, some of the least appealing theological works. The sentimental portrayal is excessive. Equally problematic, and even more so, is the lack of respect for Jesus' language. He has to speak in a rational and modern way, so all His words are presented in a very polite, contemporary style. None of His speeches are left as they were spoken; they are dissected, paraphrased, and expanded, and sometimes, to make them feel more engaging, they are rewritten as a freely invented dialogue. In all these accounts of Jesus, not a single one of His sayings keeps its original form.

And yet we must not be unjust to these writers. What they aimed at was to bring Jesus near to their own time, and in so doing they became the pioneers of the historical study of His life. The defects of their work in regard to aesthetic feeling and historical grasp are outweighed by the attractiveness of the purposeful, unprejudiced thinking which here awakens, stretches itself, and begins to move with freedom.

And still, we shouldn't be unfair to these writers. Their goal was to connect Jesus to their own time, and in doing so, they became the forerunners of the historical study of His life. Any flaws in their work related to artistic sensibility and historical understanding are overshadowed by the appeal of the thoughtful, unbiased perspective that emerges, expands, and starts to move freely.

Johann Jakob Hess was born in 1741 and died in 1828. After working as a curate for seventeen years he became one of the assistant clergy at the Frauminster at Zurich, and later “Antistes,” president, of the cantonal synod. In this capacity he guided the destinies of the Church in Zurich safely through the troublous times of the Revolution. He was not a deep thinker, but was well read and not without ability. As a man, he did splendid work.

Johann Jakob Hess was born in 1741 and died in 1828. After serving as a curate for seventeen years, he became one of the assistant clergy at the Fraumünster in Zurich, and later the “Antistes,” president, of the cantonal synod. In this role, he successfully navigated the challenges faced by the Church in Zurich during the tumultuous times of the Revolution. He wasn't a profound thinker, but he was well-read and capable. As a person, he did excellent work.

His Life of Jesus still keeps largely to the lines of a paraphrase of the Gospels; indeed, he calls it a paraphrasing history. It is based upon a harmonizing combination of the four Gospels. The matter of the Synoptic narratives is, as in all the Lives of Jesus prior to Strauss—with the sole exception of Herder's—fitted more or less arbitrarily into the intervals between the Passovers in the fourth Gospel.

His Life of Jesus still follows the basic format of a paraphrase of the Gospels; in fact, he refers to it as a paraphrased history. It is built on a blended version of the four Gospels. The content of the Synoptic accounts is, like in all the Lives of Jesus that came before Strauss—with the only exception being Herder's—arranged somewhat randomly into the gaps between the Passovers in the fourth Gospel.

In regard to miracles, he admits that these are a stumbling-block. But they are essential to the Gospel narrative and to revelation; had Jesus been only a moral teacher and not the Son of God they would not have been necessary. We must be careful, however, not to prize miracles for their own sake, but to look primarily to their ethical teaching. It was, he remarks, the mistake of the Jews to regard all the acts of Jesus solely from the point of view of their strange and miraculous character, and to forget their moral teaching; whereas we, from distaste for miracle as such, run the risk of [pg 030] excluding from the Gospel history events which are bound up with the Gospel revelation.

When it comes to miracles, he acknowledges that they can be a challenge to accept. However, they are crucial to the Gospel story and to revelation; if Jesus had merely been a moral teacher and not the Son of God, they wouldn't have been needed. We need to be careful not to value miracles just for their own sake, but to focus primarily on their ethical teachings. He points out that the mistake of the Jews was to view all of Jesus's actions only through the lens of their unusual and miraculous nature, disregarding their moral message; meanwhile, we risk excluding from the Gospel history events that are tied to the Gospel revelation because of our aversion to miracles as such.

Above all, we must retain the supernatural birth and the bodily resurrection, because on the former depends the sinlessness of Jesus, on the latter the certainty of the general resurrection of the dead. The temptation of Jesus in the wilderness was a stratagem of Satan by which he hoped to discover “whether Jesus of Nazareth was really so extraordinary a person that he would have cause to fear Him.” The resurrection of Lazarus is authentic.

Above all, we must keep the miraculous birth and the physical resurrection, because the former is what affirms Jesus' sinlessness, and the latter assures us of the eventual resurrection of the dead. The temptation of Jesus in the wilderness was a scheme by Satan to find out "whether Jesus of Nazareth was truly such an extraordinary person that he would have reason to fear Him." The resurrection of Lazarus is genuine.

But the Gospel narrative is rationalised whenever it can be done. It was not the demons, but the Gadarene demoniacs themselves, who rushed among the swine. Alarmed by their fury the whole herd plunged over the precipice into the lake and were drowned; while by this accommodation to the fixed idea of the demoniacs, Jesus effected their cure. Perhaps, too, Hess conjectures, the Lord desired to test the Gadarenes, and to see whether they would attach greater importance to the good deed done to two of their number than to the loss of their swine. This explanation, reinforced by its moral, held its ground in theology for some sixty years and passed over into a round dozen Lives of Jesus.

But the Gospel narrative is explained in a way that makes sense whenever possible. It wasn't the demons, but the Gadarene demoniacs themselves, who ran among the pigs. Frightened by their rage, the entire herd jumped over the cliff into the lake and drowned; by accommodating the fixed idea of the demoniacs, Jesus was able to heal them. Perhaps, Hess suggests, the Lord wanted to test the Gadarenes to see if they would value the good deed done for two of their community more than the loss of their pigs. This explanation, along with its moral message, remained influential in theology for about sixty years and was included in around a dozen Lives of Jesus.

This plan of “presenting each occurrence in such a way that what is valuable and instructive in it immediately strikes the eye” is followed out by Hess so faithfully that all clearness of impression is destroyed. The parables are barely recognisable, swathed, as they are, in the mummy-wrappings of his paraphrase; and in most cases their meaning is completely travestied by the ethical or historical allusions which he finds in them. The parable of the pounds is explained as referring to a man who went, like Archelaus, to Rome to obtain the kingship, while his subjects intrigued behind his back.

This plan of “presenting each occurrence in a way that what is valuable and informative stands out immediately” is followed so closely by Hess that it completely obscures the clarity of the original. The parables are barely recognizable, wrapped up like mummies in his paraphrase; and in most cases, their meaning is entirely misrepresented by the ethical or historical references he finds in them. The parable of the pounds is interpreted as being about a man who went to Rome to seek kingship, similar to Archelaus, while his subjects plotted against him.

Of the peculiar beauty of the speech of Jesus not a trace remains. The parable of the Sower, for instance, begins: “A countryman went to sow his field, which lay beside a country-road, and was here and there rather rocky, and in some places weedy, but in general was well cultivated, and had a good sort of soil.” The beatitude upon the mourners appears in the following guise: “Happy are they who amid the adversities of the present make the best of things and submit themselves with patience; for such men, if they do not see better times here, shall certainly elsewhere receive comfort and consolation.” The question addressed by the Pharisees to John the Baptist, and his answer, are given dialogue-wise, in fustian of this kind:—The Pharisees: “We are directed to enquire of you, in the name of our president, who you profess to be? As people are at present expecting the Messiah, and seem not indisposed to accept you in that capacity, we are the more anxious that you should declare yourself with regard to your vocation and person.” [pg 031] John: “The conclusion might have been drawn from my discourses that I was not the Messiah. Why should people attribute such lofty pretensions to me?” etc. In order to give the Gospels the true literary flavour, a characterisation is tacked on to each of the persons of the narrative. In the case of the disciples, for instance, this runs: “They had sound common sense, but very limited insight; the capacity to receive teaching, but an incapacity for reflective thought; a knowledge of their own weakness, but a difficulty in getting rid of old prejudices; sensibility to right feeling, but weakness in following out a pre-determined moral plan.”

Of the unique beauty of Jesus' speech, there isn't a trace left. The parable of the Sower, for example, starts: A farmer headed out to plant his field, which was alongside a country road. The area was a bit rocky in some spots and had weeds in others, but overall, it was well-maintained and had good soil. The beatitude for those who mourn is presented like this: “Blessed are those who, despite current challenges, make the most of their circumstances and persevere with patience; for those individuals, if they don’t find better times here, will definitely find comfort and solace elsewhere.” The question posed by the Pharisees to John the Baptist, and his response, are presented in this kind of dialogue:—The Pharisees: "We've been asked to inquire, on behalf of our leader, who you say you are. Since people are currently looking for the Messiah and seem willing to accept you in that role, we are especially keen for you to explain your purpose and identity." [pg 031] John: "Based on my teachings, it should be evident that I am not the Messiah. Why would anyone think I have such lofty claims?" etc. To give the Gospels the right literary flavor, a characterization is attached to each person in the narrative. For the disciples, for instance, it states: "They had good common sense but a very limited understanding; they were able to learn but found it difficult to think critically; they recognized their own weaknesses but had a hard time letting go of old biases; they were aware of the right feelings but struggled to stick to a moral plan."

The simplest occurrences give occasion for sentimental portraiture. The saying “Except ye become as little children” is introduced in the following fashion: “Jesus called a boy who was standing near. The boy came. Jesus took his hand and told him to stand beside Him, nearer than any of His disciples, so that he had the foremost place among them. Then Jesus threw His arm round the boy and pressed him tenderly to His breast. The disciples looked on in astonishment, wondering what this meant. Then He explained to them,” etc. In these expansions Hess does not always escape the ludicrous. The saying of Jesus in John x. 9, “I am the door,” takes on the following form: “No one, whether he be sheep or shepherd, can come into the fold (if, that is to say, he follows the right way) except in so far as he knows me and is admitted by me, and included among the flock.”

The simplest events provide a chance for sentimental portrayals. The saying "Unless you become like little children" is introduced like this: “Jesus called over a boy who was standing nearby. The boy came over. Jesus took his hand and told him to stand beside Him, closer than any of His disciples, giving him a special place among them. Then Jesus wrapped His arm around the boy and held him gently to His chest. The disciples watched in amazement, curious about what this meant. Then He explained to them,” etc. In these expansions, Hess sometimes veers into the ridiculous. The saying of Jesus in John x. 9, “I am the gateway,” is rephrased as: "Nobody, whether a sheep or a shepherd, can enter the fold (as long as they're on the right path) unless they know me, are accepted by me, and are part of the flock."


Reinhard's work is on a distinctly higher level. The author was born in 1753. In 1792, after he had worked for fourteen years as Docent in Wittenberg, he was appointed Senior Court Chaplain at Dresden. He died in 1812.

Reinhard's work is on a clearly higher level. The author was born in 1753. In 1792, after he had worked for fourteen years as a lecturer in Wittenberg, he was appointed Senior Court Chaplain in Dresden. He passed away in 1812.

“I am, as you know, a very prosaic person,” writes Reinhard to a friend, and in these words he has given an admirable characterisation of himself. The writers who chiefly appeal to him are the ancient moralists; he acknowledges that he has learned more from them than from a “collegium homileticum.” In his celebrated “System of Christian Ethics” (5 vols., 1788-1815) he makes copious use of them. His sermons—they fill thirty-five volumes, and in their day were regarded as models—show some power and depth of thought, but are all cast in the same mould. He seems to have been haunted by a fear that it might some time befall him to admit into his mind a thought which was mystical or visionary, not justifiable by the laws of logic and the canons of the critical reason. With all his philosophising and rationalising, however, certain pillars of the supernaturalistic view of history remain for him immovable.

"As you know, I’m a really down-to-earth person," Reinhard writes to a friend, and with these words, he accurately describes himself. The writers he primarily connects with are the ancient moralists; he admits that he has gained more knowledge from them than from a “homiletics group.” In his well-known "Christian Ethics System" (5 vols., 1788-1815), he makes extensive use of their work. His sermons—spanning thirty-five volumes and considered models in their time—exhibit significant power and depth of thought, but they all follow the same pattern. He seems to have been troubled by the fear that he might one day allow a thought that was mystical or visionary into his mind, one that couldn’t be justified by the rules of logic and the standards of critical reasoning. Despite all his philosophizing and rationalizing, however, certain foundational aspects of the supernatural view of history remain unshakeable for him.

At first sight one might be inclined to suppose that he frankly shared the belief in miracle. He mentions the raising of the [pg 032] widow's son, and of Lazarus, and accepts as an authentic saying the command of the risen Jesus to baptize all nations. But if we look more closely, we find that he deliberately brings very few miracles into his narrative, and the definition by which he disintegrates the conception of miracle from within leaves no doubt as to his own position. What he says is this: “All that which we call miraculous and supernatural is to be understood as only relatively so, and implies nothing further than an obvious exception to what can be brought about by natural causes, so far as we know them and have experience of their capacity. A cautious thinker will not venture in any single instance to pronounce an event to be so extraordinary that God could not have brought it about by the use of secondary causes, but must have intervened directly.”

At first glance, one might think that he openly believed in miracles. He talks about the raising of the widow's son and Lazarus, and considers the command from the risen Jesus to baptize all nations as genuine. However, if we examine more closely, we see that he intentionally includes very few miracles in his narrative, and his definition, which breaks down the idea of miracle from within, clearly shows his own viewpoint. He states: "Everything we think of as miraculous or supernatural should be seen as just relatively so, meaning it's simply an obvious exception to what natural causes can achieve based on our knowledge and experience. A thoughtful person wouldn't insist that any event is so remarkable that God couldn't have brought it about through secondary causes and must have intervened directly."

The case stands similarly with regard to the divinity of Christ. Reinhard assumes it, but his “Life” is not directed to prove it; it leads only to the conclusion that the Founder of Christianity is to be regarded as a wonderful “divine” teacher. In order to prove His uniqueness, Reinhard has to show that His plan for the welfare of mankind was something incomparably higher than anything which hero or sage has ever striven for. Reinhard makes the first attempt to give an account of the teaching of Jesus which should be historical in the sense that all dogmatic considerations should be excluded. “Above all things, let us collect and examine the indications which we find in the writings of His companions regarding the designs which He had in view.”

The situation is similar when it comes to the divinity of Christ. Reinhard assumes it but his "Life" doesn’t aim to prove it; it only leads to the conclusion that the Founder of Christianity should be seen as an extraordinary "heavenly" teacher. To demonstrate His uniqueness, Reinhard needs to show that His vision for the well-being of humanity was something vastly greater than anything any hero or sage has ever pursued. Reinhard makes the first attempt to provide a historical account of Jesus's teachings, ensuring that all dogmatic considerations are excluded. "First and foremost, let’s gather and analyze the clues we find in the writings of His companions about the intentions He had."

The plan of Jesus shows its greatness above all in its universality. Reinhard is well aware of the difficulty raised in this connexion by those sayings which assert the prerogative of Israel, and he discusses them at length. He finds the solution in the assumption that Jesus in His own lifetime naturally confined Himself to working among His own people, and was content to indicate the future universal development of His plan.

The plan of Jesus shows its greatness primarily in its universality. Reinhard understands the challenges posed by the statements that emphasize Israel's special status, and he discusses these at length. He believes the solution lies in the idea that Jesus focused on His own people during His lifetime and was satisfied to point out the future global expansion of His plan.

With the intention “of introducing a universal change, tending to the benefit of the whole human race,” Jesus attaches His teaching to the Jewish eschatology. It is only the form of His teaching, however, which is affected by this, since He gives an entirely different significance to the terms Kingdom of Heaven and Kingdom of God, referring them to a universal ethical reorganisation of mankind. But His plan was entirely independent of politics. He never based His claims upon His Davidic descent. This was, indeed, the reason why He held aloof from His family. Even the entry into Jerusalem had no Messianic significance. His plan was so entirely non-political that He would, on the contrary, have welcomed the severance of all connexion between the state and religion, in order to avoid the risk of a conflict between these two powers. Reinhard explains the voluntary death of Jesus as due to [pg 033] this endeavour. “He quitted the stage of the world by so early and shameful a death because He wished to destroy at once and for ever the mistaken impression that He was aiming at the foundation of an earthly kingdom, and to turn the thoughts, wishes, and efforts of His disciples and companions into another channel.”

With the intention "to bring about a universal change that aims to benefit all of humanity," Jesus connects His teachings to Jewish eschatology. However, this only affects the form of His teachings, as He gives a completely different meaning to the concepts of the Kingdom of Heaven and the Kingdom of God, linking them to a universal ethical reorganization of humanity. But His plan was entirely separate from politics. He never justified His claims based on His lineage from David. In fact, this was why He distanced Himself from His family. Even His entry into Jerusalem didn’t carry any Messianic meaning. His approach was so non-political that he would have actually preferred a separation between church and state, to avoid any potential conflict between the two powers. Reinhard interprets Jesus's voluntary death as a result of [pg 033] this effort. "He left the stage of the world due to such an early and shameful death because He wanted to put an end to the false belief that He intended to create an earthly kingdom and to shift the thoughts, desires, and efforts of His disciples and companions toward a different purpose."

In order to make the Kingdom of God a practical reality, it was necessary for Him to dissociate it from all the forces of this world, and to bring morality and religion into the closest connexion. “The law of love was the indissoluble bond by which Jesus for ever united morality with religion.” “Moral instruction was the principal content and the very essence of all His discourses.” His efforts “were directed to the establishment of a purely ethical organisation.”

To make the Kingdom of God a reality, He needed to separate it from all the influences of this world and closely connect morality and religion. "The law of love was the unbreakable connection that Jesus used to permanently link morality with religion." “Moral teaching was the central focus and the core of all His teachings.” His efforts "were focused on establishing a completely ethical organization."

It was important, therefore, to overthrow superstition and to bring religion within the domain of reason. First of all the priesthood must be deprived for ever of its influence. Then an improvement of the social condition of mankind must be introduced, since the level of morality depends upon social conditions. Jesus was a social reformer. Through the attainment of “the highest perfection of which Society is capable, universal peace” was “gradually to be brought about.”

It was crucial, therefore, to challenge superstition and bring religion into the realm of reason. First, the priesthood must be permanently stripped of its influence. Then, there needs to be an improvement in the social conditions of humanity, as morality is tied to these conditions. Jesus was a social reformer. Through achieving "the greatest level of perfection that society can achieve, universal peace", "was gradually to be achieved."

But the point of primary importance for Him was the alliance of religion with reason. Reason was to maintain its freedom by the aid of religion, and religion was not to be withdrawn from the critical judgment of reason: all things were to be tested, and only the best retained.

But the main thing that mattered to Him was the connection between religion and reason. Reason was meant to keep its freedom with the help of religion, and religion was not to be exempt from the critical examination of reason: everything was to be evaluated, and only the best would be kept.

“From these data it is easy to determine the characteristics of a religion which is to be the religion of all mankind: it must be ethical, intelligible, and spiritual.”

"This information clearly outlines the characteristics of a religion that’s meant for everyone: it should be ethical, easy to understand, and spiritual."

After the plan of Jesus has been expounded on these lines, Reinhard shows, in the second part of his work, that, prior to Jesus, no great man of antiquity had devised a plan of beneficence of a scope commensurate with the whole human race. In the third part the conclusion is drawn that Jesus is the uniquely divine Teacher.

After outlining Jesus' plan in this way, Reinhard demonstrates in the second part of his work that, before Jesus, no significant figure from ancient times had created a charitable plan that was as expansive as that for all of humanity. In the third part, the conclusion is reached that Jesus is the one and only divine Teacher.

But before the author can venture to draw this conclusion, he feels it necessary first to show that the plan of Jesus was no chimera. If we were obliged to admit its impracticability Jesus would have to be ranked with the visionaries and enthusiasts; and these, however noble and virtuous, can only injure the cause of rational religion. “Visionary enthusiasm and enlightened reason—who that knows anything of the human mind can conceive these two as united in a single soul?” But Jesus was no visionary enthusiast. “With what calmness, self-mastery, and cool determination does He think out and pursue His divine purpose?” By the truths which He revealed and declared to be divine communications He [pg 034] did not desire to put pressure upon the human mind, but only to guide it. “It would be impossible to show a more conscientious respect and a more delicate consideration for the rights of human reason than is shown by Jesus. He will conquer only by convincing.” “He is willing to bear with contradiction, and condescends to meet the most irrational objections and the most ill-natured misrepresentations with the most incredible patience.”

But before the author can reach this conclusion, he feels it's important to first demonstrate that Jesus's plan was no fantasy. If we had to accept its impracticality, Jesus would have to be grouped with the dreamers and zealots; and while those individuals can be admirable and virtuous, they only hinder the cause of rational religion. "Visionary enthusiasm and clear thinking—who that understands the human mind can imagine these two coming together in one person?" But Jesus was not a dreamer or a zealot. "With what calmness, self-control, and steady determination does He contemplate and follow His divine purpose?" The truths He revealed and claimed as divine messages were not meant to pressure the human mind, but rather to guide it. "It’s impossible to show more genuine respect and more thoughtful consideration for the rights of human reason than what Jesus shows. He will prevail only through persuasion." “He is open to opposing views and responds to the most unreasonable objections and the most deceptive misrepresentations with incredible patience.”

It was well for Reinhard that he had no suspicion how full of enthusiasm Jesus was, and how He trod reason under His feet!

It was fortunate for Reinhard that he had no idea how full of enthusiasm Jesus was, and how He disregarded reason completely!

But what kind of relation was there between this rational religion taught by Jesus and the Christian theology which Reinhard accepted? How does he harmonise the symbolical view of Baptism and the Lord's Supper which he here expounds with ecclesiastical doctrine? How does he pass from the conception of the divine teacher to that of the Son of God?

But what kind of relationship existed between the rational religion that Jesus taught and the Christian theology that Reinhard accepted? How does he reconcile the symbolic view of Baptism and the Lord's Supper that he explains here with church doctrine? How does he transition from the idea of the divine teacher to that of the Son of God?

This is a question which he does not feel himself obliged to answer. For him the one circle of thought revolves freely within the other, but they never come into contact with each other.

This is a question that he doesn’t feel he has to answer. For him, one circle of thought spins freely within the other, but they never touch each other.


So far as concerns the presentation of the teaching, the Life of Jesus by Opitz follows the same lines as that of Reinhard. It is disfigured, however, by a number of lapses of taste, and by a crass supernaturalism in the description of the miracles and experiences of the Great Teacher.

As for how the teaching is presented, Opitz's Life of Jesus follows a similar approach to Reinhard’s. However, it is marred by several instances of bad taste and a blatant supernaturalism in the portrayal of the miracles and experiences of the Great Teacher.


Jakobi writes “for thoughtful and sympathetic readers.” He recognises that much of the miraculous is a later addition to the facts, but he has a rooted distrust of thoroughgoing rationalism, “whose would-be helpful explanations are often stranger than the miracles themselves.” A certain amount of miracle must be maintained, but not for the purpose of founding belief upon it: “the miracles were not intended to authenticate the teaching of Jesus, but to surround His life with a guard of honour.”20

Jakobi writes "for caring and understanding readers." He understands that a lot of the miraculous elements are later additions to the facts, but he has a deep skepticism towards extreme rationalism, "whose so-called helpful explanations are often stranger than the miracles themselves." Some level of miracle has to be preserved, but not to establish belief on it: "The miracles weren't meant to prove Jesus' teachings but to give His life a sense of reverence."20


Whether Herder, in his two Lives of Jesus, is to be classed with the older rationalists is a question to which the answer must be “Yes, and No,” as in the case of every attempt to classify those men of lonely greatness who stand apart from their contemporaries, but who nevertheless are not in all points in advance of them.

Whether Herder, in his two Lives of Jesus, should be grouped with the older rationalists is a question that can be answered with "Yes and No," just like with every effort to categorize those individuals of unique brilliance who are distinct from their peers but are not entirely ahead of them in every aspect.

Properly speaking, he has really nothing to do with the rationalists, since he is distinguished from them by the depth of his insight and his power of artistic apprehension, and he is far from sharing their lack of taste. Further, his horizon embraces problems of which rationalism, even in its developed form, never [pg 035] came in sight. He recognises that all attempts to harmonise the Synoptists with John are unavailing; a conclusion which he had avowed earlier in his “Letters referring to the Study of Theology.”21 He grasps this incompatibility, it is true, rather by the aid of poetic, than of critical insight. “Since they cannot be united,” he writes in his “Life of Jesus according to John,” “they must be left standing independently, each evangelist with his own special merit. Man, Ox, Lion, and Eagle, they advance together, supporting the throne of glory, but they refuse to coalesce into a single form, to unite into a Diatessaron.” But to him belongs the honour of being the first and the only scholar, prior to Strauss, to recognise that the life of Jesus can be construed either according to the Synoptists, or according to John, but that a Life of Jesus based on the four Gospels is a monstrosity. In view of this intuitive historical grasp, it is not surprising that the commentaries of the theologians were an abomination to him.

Properly speaking, he really has nothing to do with the rationalists, as he stands apart from them due to the depth of his insight and his ability for artistic understanding; he definitely doesn’t share their lack of taste. Moreover, his perspective includes problems that rationalism, even in its most developed form, never really considered. He recognizes that all attempts to reconcile the Synoptic Gospels with John are futile; a conclusion he had stated earlier in his “Letters referring to the Study of Theology.” He understands this incompatibility more through poetic than critical insight. “Since they cannot be united,” he writes in his “Life of Jesus according to John,” “they must be left standing independently, each evangelist with his own special merit. Man, Ox, Lion, and Eagle, they move together, supporting the throne of glory, but they refuse to merge into a single form, to unite into a Diatessaron.” He deserves the credit of being the first and only scholar, before Strauss, to see that the life of Jesus can be interpreted either through the Synoptists or through John, but that a Life of Jesus based on all four Gospels is a monstrosity. Given this intuitive historical understanding, it’s no surprise that the commentaries of theologians were detestable to him.

The fourth Gospel is, in his view, not a primitive historical source, but a protest against the narrowness of the “Palestinian Gospels.” It gives free play, as the circumstances of the time demanded, to Greek ideas. “There was need, in addition to those earlier, purely historical Gospels, of a Gospel at once theological and historical, like that of John,” in which Jesus should be presented, not as the Jewish Messiah, “but as the Saviour of the World.”

The fourth Gospel is, in his opinion, not a basic historical source but a response to the limitations of the “Palestinian Gospels.” It allows for the expression of Greek ideas, as the times required. "There was a need, in addition to the earlier, purely historical Gospels, for a Gospel that was both theological and historical, similar to that of John." where Jesus is portrayed not just as the Jewish Messiah, "but as the Savior of the World."

The additions and omissions of this Gospel are alike skilfully planned. It retains only those miracles which are symbols of a continuous permanent miracle, through which the Saviour of the World works constantly, unintermittently, among men. The Johannine miracles are not there for their own sakes. The cures of demoniacs are not even represented among them. These had no interest for the Graeco-Roman world, and the Evangelist was unwilling “that this Palestinian superstition should become a permanent feature of Christianity, to be a reproach of scoffers or a belief of the foolish.” His recording of the raising of Lazarus is, in spite of the silence of the Synoptists, easily explicable. The latter could not yet tell the story “without exposing a family which was still living near Jerusalem to the fury of that hatred which had sworn with an oath to put Lazarus to death.” John, however, could recount it without scruple, “for by this time Jerusalem was probably in ruins, and the hospitable family of Bethany were perhaps already with their Friend in the other world.” This most naïve of explanations is reproduced in a whole series of Lives of Jesus.

The additions and omissions in this Gospel are skillfully designed. It only includes those miracles that symbolize a continuous, ongoing miracle through which the Savior of the World works constantly and tirelessly among people. The Johannine miracles are not included for their own sake. The cures of demoniacs are not even mentioned among them. These had no appeal to the Graeco-Roman world, and the Evangelist didn’t want “this Palestinian superstition to become a lasting part of Christianity, serving as a target for mockery for skeptics or a belief for the naive.” His account of Lazarus being raised from the dead is, despite the silence of the Synoptists, easily understandable. The latter couldn’t tell the story “without putting a family still living near Jerusalem in danger from those who had vowed to kill Lazarus.” John, however, could share it without hesitation, "By this point, Jerusalem was likely in ruins, and the welcoming family from Bethany was probably already reunited with their Friend in the afterlife." This very simplistic explanation is repeated in a whole series of Lives of Jesus.

In dealing with the Synoptists, Herder grasps the problem with [pg 036] the same intuitive insight. Mark is no epitomist, but the creator of the archetype of the Synoptic representation. “The Gospel of Mark is not an epitome; it is an original Gospel. What the others have, and he has not, has been added by them, not omitted by him. Consequently Mark is a witness to an original, shorter Gospel-scheme, to which the additional matter of the others ought properly to be regarded as a supplement.”

In dealing with the Synoptists, Herder understands the issue with the same intuitive insight. Mark is not simply summarizing; he's the creator of the archetype of the Synoptic representation. “The Gospel of Mark is not a summary; it is an original Gospel. What the others include that he does not has been added by them, not left out by him. Therefore, Mark is a witness to an original, shorter Gospel framework, and the additional material from the others should be seen as a supplement.”

Mark is the “unornamented central column, or plain foundation stone, on which the others rest.” The birth-stories of Matthew and Luke are “a new growth to meet new needs.” The different tendencies, also, point to a later period. Mark is still comparatively friendly towards the Jews, because Christianity had not yet separated itself from Judaism. Matthew is more hostile towards them because his Gospel was written at a time when Christians had given up the hope of maintaining amicable relations with the Jews and were groaning under the pressure of persecution. It is for that reason that the Jesus of the Matthaean discourses lays so much stress upon His second coming, and presupposes the rejection of the Jewish nation as something already in being, a sign of the approaching end.

Mark is the "simple central pillar, or fundamental foundation stone, on which the others depend." The birth narratives in Matthew and Luke are "a new growth to address new needs." The different perspectives also suggest a later time period. Mark remains relatively friendly towards the Jews because Christianity hadn't yet distanced itself from Judaism. Matthew, on the other hand, is more critical of them because his Gospel was written when Christians had given up hope of maintaining good relations with the Jews and were suffering from persecution. This is why the Jesus of Matthew's teachings emphasizes His second coming so much and assumes the rejection of the Jewish nation as something that has already happened, signaling the impending end.

Pure history, however, is as little to be looked for in the first three Gospels as in the fourth. They are the sacred epic of Jesus the Messiah, and model the history of their hero upon the prophetic words of the Old Testament. In this view, also, Herder is a precursor of Strauss.

Pure history, however, is just as unlikely to be found in the first three Gospels as it is in the fourth. They are the sacred narrative of Jesus the Messiah and shape the story of their hero based on the prophetic words of the Old Testament. From this perspective, Herder is also a forerunner of Strauss.

In essence, however, Herder represents a protest of art against theology. The Gospels, if we are to find the life of Jesus in them, must be read, not with pedantic learning, but with taste. From this point of view, miracles cease to offend. Neither Old Testament prophecies, nor predictions of Jesus, nor miracles, can be adduced as evidence for the Gospel; the Gospel is its own evidence. The miracles stand outside the possibility of proof, and belong to mere “Church belief,” which ought to lose itself more and more in the pure Gospel. Yet miracles, in a limited sense, are to be accepted on the ground of the historic evidence. To refuse to admit this is to be like the Indian king who denied the existence of ice because he had never seen anything like it. Jesus, in order to help His miracle-loving age, reconciled Himself to the necessity of performing miracles. But, in any case, the reality of a miracle is of small moment in comparison with its symbolic value.

In essence, however, Herder expresses a rebellion of art against theology. To truly understand Jesus' life through the Gospels, we must approach them not with dry scholarship but with an appreciation for their beauty. From this perspective, miracles lose their ability to shock. Old Testament prophecies, Jesus' predictions, and miracles shouldn't be cited as proof for the Gospel; the Gospel stands on its own as proof. Miracles lie beyond the scope of verification and are merely part of “Church belief,” which should fade away into the essence of the pure Gospel. Still, miracles should be acknowledged to some extent based on historical evidence. To deny this is like the Indian king who refused to believe in ice because he had never seen it. To support His miracle-loving generation, Jesus accepted the need to perform miracles. However, the actual occurrence of a miracle is less important than its symbolic significance.

In this, therefore, Herder, though in his grasp of many problems he was more than a generation in advance of his time, belongs to the primitive rationalists. He allows the supernatural to intrude into the events of the life of Jesus, and does not feel that the adoption of the historical standpoint involves the necessity of doing away with miracle. He contributed much to the clearing up of [pg 037] ideas, but by evading the question of miracle he slurred over a difficulty which needed to be faced and solved before it should be possible to entertain the hope of forming a really historical conception of the life of Jesus. In reading Herder one is apt to fancy that it would be possible to pass straight on to Strauss. In reality, it was necessary that a very prosaic spirit, Paulus, should intervene, and should attack the question of miracle from a purely historical standpoint, before Strauss could give expression to the ideas of Herder in an effectual way, i.e. in such a way as to produce offence. The fact is that in theology the most revolutionary ideas are swallowed quite readily so long as they smooth their passage by a few small concessions. It is only when a spicule of bone stands out obstinately and causes choking that theology begins to take note of dangerous ideas. Strauss is Herder with just that little bone sticking out—the absolute denial of miracle on historical grounds. That is to say, Strauss is a Herder who has behind him the uncompromising rationalism of Paulus.

In this, Herder, despite being over a generation ahead of his time in understanding many issues, fits into the category of early rationalists. He allows the supernatural to play a role in the events of Jesus' life and believes that taking a historical view doesn’t necessarily mean rejecting miracles. He made significant contributions to clarifying ideas, but by dodging the issue of miracles, he overlooked a challenge that needed to be confronted and resolved before it would be possible to hope for a truly historical understanding of Jesus' life. When reading Herder, one might think it's easy to jump straight to Strauss. In reality, it was essential for the very pragmatic Paulus to step in and address the question of miracles from a purely historical perspective before Strauss could effectively articulate Herder's ideas—in a way that stirred controversy. The truth is that in theology, the most radical ideas are often accepted as long as they ease their way in with a few small compromises. It’s only when a stubborn splinter emerges and causes discomfort that theology begins to pay attention to dangerous ideas. Strauss is basically Herder with that annoying splinter sticking out—his outright denial of miracles based on historical reasoning. In other words, Strauss is a Herder backed by Paulus's absolute rationalism.

[pg 038]

IV. The First Fictional Accounts of Jesus

Karl Friedrich Bahrdt. Briefe über die Bibel im Volkston. Eine Wochenschrift von einem Prediger auf dem Lande. (Popular Letters about the Bible. A weekly paper by a country clergyman.) J. Fr. Dost, Halle, 1782. 816 pp.

Karl Friedrich Bahrdt. Letters about the Bible in Everyday Language. A weekly publication by a rural pastor, J. Fr. Dost, Halle, 1782. 816 pages.

Ausführung des Plans und Zwecks Jesu. In Briefen an Wahrheit suchende Leser. (An Explanation of the Plans and Aims of Jesus. In letters addressed to readers who seek the truth.) 11 vols., embracing 3000 pp. August Mylius, Berlin, 1784-1792. This work is a sequel to the Popular Letters about the Bible.

Explanation of the Plans and Goals of Jesus. In letters to readers looking for the truth. 11 volumes, totaling 3000 pages. August Mylius, Berlin, 1784-1792. This work follows the Popular Letters Regarding the Bible.

Die sämtlichen Reden Jesu aus den Evangelisten ausgezogen. (The Whole of the Discourses of Jesus, extracted from the Gospels.) Berlin, 1786.

All the speeches of Jesus taken from the Gospels. Berlin, 1786.

Karl Heinrich Venturini. Natürliche Geschichte des grossen Propheten von Nazareth. (A Non-supernatural History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth.) Bethlehem (Copenhagen), 1st ed., 1800-1802; 2nd ed., 1806. 4 vols., embracing 2700 pp. The work appeared anonymously. The description given below is based on the 2nd ed., which shows dependence, in some of the exegetical details, upon the then recently published commentaries of Paulus.

Karl Heinrich Venturini. Natural History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth. (A Non-supernatural History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth.) Bethlehem (Copenhagen), 1st edition, 1800-1802; 2nd edition, 1806. 4 volumes, totaling 2700 pages. This work was published anonymously. The description below is based on the 2nd edition, which shows some reliance on the recently published commentaries of Paulus for certain interpretative details.

It is strange to notice how often in the history of our subject a few imperfectly equipped free-lances have attacked and attempted to carry the decisive positions before the ordered ranks of professional theology have pushed their advance to these decisive points.

It's odd to see how frequently, throughout the history of our topic, a few poorly equipped independent thinkers have launched attacks and tried to seize key positions before the organized ranks of professional theology have advanced to these critical points.

Thus, it was the fictitious “Lives” of Bahrdt and Venturini which, at the end of the eighteenth and beginning of the nineteenth centuries, first attempted to apply, with logical consistency, a non-supernatural interpretation to the miracle stories of the Gospel. Further, these writers were the first who, instead of contenting themselves with the simple reproduction of the successive sections of the Gospel narrative, endeavoured to grasp the inner connexion of cause and effect in the events and experiences of the life of Jesus. Since they found no such connexion indicated in the Gospels, they had to supply it for themselves. The particular form which their explanation takes—the hypothesis of a secret society of which Jesus is the tool—is, it is true, rather a sorry makeshift. Yet, in a sense, these Lives of Jesus, for all their colouring of fiction, are the first which deserve the name. The rationalists, and even Paulus, confine themselves to describing the teaching of Jesus; Bahrdt and Venturini make a bold attempt to paint the portrait of Jesus Himself. It is [pg 039] not surprising that their portraiture is at once crude and fantastic, like the earliest attempts of art to represent the human figure in living movement.

Thus, it was the fictitious “Lives” of Bahrdt and Venturini that, at the end of the eighteenth and beginning of the nineteenth centuries, first tried to logically apply a non-supernatural interpretation to the miracle stories of the Gospel. Additionally, these writers were the first to go beyond just replicating the various sections of the Gospel narrative; they made an effort to understand the underlying connections of cause and effect in the events and experiences of Jesus’ life. Since they found no such connections indicated in the Gospels, they had to create them themselves. The specific way they explained it—the idea of a secret society with Jesus as its tool—is, admittedly, a pretty flimsy workaround. Still, in a way, these Lives of Jesus, despite their fictional embellishments, are the first that truly deserve the title. The rationalists, and even Paulus, limit themselves to outlining Jesus' teachings; Bahrdt and Venturini boldly attempt to illustrate Jesus Himself. It is [pg 039] not surprising that their portrayal is both crude and fantastical, much like the earliest artistic efforts to portray the human figure in motion.

Karl Friedrich Bahrdt was born in 1741 at Bischofswerda. Endowed with brilliant abilities, he made, owing to a bad upbringing and an undisciplined sensuous nature, a miserable failure. After being first Catechist and afterwards Professor Extraordinary of Sacred Philology at Leipzig, he was, in 1766, requested to resign on account of scandalous life. After various adventures, and after holding for a time a professorship at Giessen, he received under Frederick's minister Zedlitz authorisation to lecture at Halle. There he lectured to nearly nine hundred students who were attracted by his inspiring eloquence. The government upheld him, in spite of his serious failings, with the double motive of annoying the faculty and maintaining the freedom of learning. After the death of Frederick the Great, Bahrdt had to resign his post, and took to keeping an inn at a vineyard near Halle. By ridiculing Wöllner's edict (1788), he brought on himself a year of confinement in a fortress. He died in disrepute, in 1792.

Karl Friedrich Bahrdt was born in 1741 in Bischofswerda. Gifted with exceptional talents, he ultimately faced failure due to a poor upbringing and a lack of self-discipline. After serving as a Catechist and later as an Extraordinary Professor of Sacred Philology at Leipzig, he was asked to resign in 1766 due to his scandalous lifestyle. Following various escapades, and after briefly holding a professorship at Giessen, he was granted permission by Frederick's minister Zedlitz to lecture at Halle. There, he taught nearly nine hundred students who were drawn to his inspiring speeches. The government supported him despite his significant flaws, partly to frustrate the faculty and partly to uphold academic freedom. After Frederick the Great's death, Bahrdt had to step down from his position and ended up running an inn at a vineyard near Halle. By mocking Wöllner's edict (1788), he brought about a year of imprisonment in a fortress. He died in disgrace in 1792.

Bahrdt had begun as an orthodox cleric. In Halle he gave up his belief in revelation, and endeavoured to explain religion on the ground of reason. To this period belong the “Popular Letters about the Bible,” which were afterwards continued in the further series, “An Explanation of the Plans and Aims of Jesus.”

Bahrdt had started out as a traditional clergyman. In Halle, he lost his faith in revelation and tried to explain religion through reason. This period includes the "Popular Letters on the Bible," which were later followed up with the series, "An Overview of Jesus' Plans and Goals."

His treatment of the life of Jesus has been too severely censured. The work is not without passages which show a real depth of feeling, especially in the continually recurring explanations regarding the relation of belief in miracle to true faith, in which the actual description of the life of Jesus lies embedded. And the remarks about the teaching of Jesus are not always commonplace. But the paraphernalia of dialogues of portentous length make it, as a whole, formless and inartistic. The introduction of a galaxy of imaginary characters—Haram, Schimah, Avel, Limmah, and the like—is nothing less than bewildering.

His portrayal of Jesus' life has faced too much criticism. The work contains sections that demonstrate genuine emotion, particularly in the repetitive explanations about how belief in miracles connects to true faith, which are woven into the actual narrative of Jesus' life. Additionally, the comments on Jesus' teachings are not always ordinary. However, the lengthy dialogues make the overall structure formless and unartistic. The introduction of a host of fictional characters—Haram, Schimah, Avel, Limmah, and others—is nothing short of confusing.

Bahrdt finds the key to the explanation of the life of Jesus in the appearance in the Gospel narrative of Nicodemus and Joseph of Arimathea. They are not disciples of Jesus, but belong to the upper classes; what rôle, then, can they have played in the life of Jesus, and how came they to intercede on His behalf? They were Essenes. This Order had secret members in all ranks of society, even in the Sanhedrin. It had set itself the task of detaching the nation from its sensuous Messianic hopes and leading it to a higher knowledge of spiritual truths. It had the most widespread ramifications, extending to Babylon and to Egypt. In order to deliver the people from the limitations of the national faith, which could only lead to disturbance and insurrection, they must find a [pg 040] Messiah who would destroy these false Messianic expectations. They were therefore on the look-out for a claimant of the Messiahship whom they could make subservient to their aims.

Bahrdt believes that the key to understanding the life of Jesus lies in the appearances of Nicodemus and Joseph of Arimathea in the Gospel narrative. They aren't disciples of Jesus but are from the upper classes; so, what role could they have played in His life, and how did they come to advocate for Him? They were Essenes. This Order had secret members across all levels of society, even within the Sanhedrin. Their goal was to steer the nation away from its physical Messianic hopes and towards a deeper understanding of spiritual truths. They had wide-ranging influence, reaching as far as Babylon and Egypt. To free the people from the confines of the national faith, which only led to unrest and rebellion, they needed to find a Messiah who would dismantle these false Messianic expectations. Thus, they were searching for a Messiah figure whom they could manipulate to serve their objectives.

Jesus came under the notice of the Order immediately after His birth. As a child He was watched over at every step by the Brethren. At the feasts at Jerusalem Alexandrian Jews, secret members of the Essene Order, put themselves into communication with Him, explained to Him the falsity of the priests, inspired Him with a horror of the bloody sacrifices of the Temple, and made him acquainted with Socrates and Plato. This is set forth in dialogues of a hundred pages long. At the story of the death of Socrates, the boy bursts into a tempest of sobs which His friends are unable to calm. He longs to emulate the martyr-death of the great Athenian.

Jesus came to the attention of the Order right after He was born. As a child, He was watched over closely by the Brethren. During the festivals in Jerusalem, Alexandrian Jews, who were secret members of the Essene Order, communicated with Him, explained the falsehoods of the priests, instilled in Him a strong aversion to the bloody sacrifices at the Temple, and introduced Him to Socrates and Plato. This is detailed in dialogues that span a hundred pages. Upon hearing the story of Socrates' death, the boy bursts into uncontrollable tears that His friends can't soothe. He yearns to follow in the footsteps of the great Athenian martyr.

On the market-place at Nazareth a mysterious Persian gives Him two sovereign remedies—one for affections of the eye, the other for nervous disorders.

On the market square in Nazareth, a mysterious Persian hands Him two powerful remedies—one for eye issues, the other for nervous problems.

His father does his best for Him, teaching Him, along with His cousin John, afterwards the Baptist, about virtue and immortality. A priest belonging to the Essene Order, who makes their acquaintance disguised as a shepherd, and takes part in their conversations, leads the lads deeper into the knowledge of wisdom. At twelve years old, Jesus is already so far advanced that He argues with the Scribes in the Temple concerning miracles, maintaining the thesis that they are impossible.

His father does his best for Him, teaching Him, along with His cousin John, later known as the Baptist, about virtue and immortality. A priest from the Essene Order, who meets them while disguised as a shepherd, joins their conversations and guides the boys deeper into the understanding of wisdom. By the age of twelve, Jesus is already so advanced that He debates with the Scribes in the Temple about miracles, arguing that they are impossible.

When they feel themselves ready to appear in public the two cousins take counsel together how they can best help the people. They agree to open the eyes of the people regarding the tyranny and hypocrisy of the priests. Through Haram, a prominent member of the Essene Order, Luke the physician is introduced to Jesus and places all his science at His disposal.

When they feel ready to go public, the two cousins consult with each other on how to best assist the people. They decide to enlighten the public about the tyranny and hypocrisy of the priests. Through Haram, a well-known member of the Essene Order, Luke the physician meets Jesus and offers all his knowledge for His benefit.

In order to produce any effect they were obliged to practise accommodation to the superstitions of the people, and introduce their wisdom to them under the garb of folly, in the hope that, beguiled by its attractive exterior, the people would admit into their minds the revelation of rational truth, and after a time be able to emancipate themselves from superstition. Jesus, therefore, sees Himself obliged to appear in the rôle of the Messiah of popular expectation, and to make up His mind to work by means of miracles and illusions. About this He felt the gravest scruples. He was obliged, however, to obey the Order; and His scruples were quieted by the reminder of the lofty end which was to be reached by these means. At last, when it is pointed out to Him that even Moses had followed the same plan, He submits to the necessity. The influential Order undertakes the duty of stage-managing the miracles, and that of maintaining His father. On the reception of Jesus into the number of the Brethren of the First [pg 041] Degree of the Order it is made known to Him that these Brethren are bound to face death in the cause of the Order; but that the Order, on its part, undertakes so to use the machinery and influence at its disposal that the last extremity shall always be avoided and the Brother mysteriously preserved from death.

To have any impact, they had to adapt to the people's superstitions and present their wisdom disguised as foolishness. They hoped that, drawn in by its appealing facade, people would accept rational truths into their minds and eventually free themselves from superstition. Jesus, therefore, felt he had to take on the role of the Messiah that people expected and decided to perform miracles and illusions. He had serious doubts about this, but he knew he had to comply with the Order, and his concerns were eased by the reminder of the noble goal they aimed to achieve through these methods. Eventually, when it was pointed out that even Moses had taken a similar approach, he accepted the necessity. The influential Order took on the responsibility of orchestrating the miracles and supporting his father. When Jesus was welcomed as one of the Brethren of the First [pg 041] Degree of the Order, he was informed that these Brethren were committed to facing death for the Order's cause; however, the Order promised to use its resources and influence to ensure that the final moments would always be avoided, keeping the Brother mysteriously safe from death.

Then begins the cleverly staged drama by means of which the people are to be converted to rational religion. The members of the Order are divided into three classes: The Baptized, The Disciples, The Chosen Ones. The Baptized receive only the usual popular teaching; the Disciples are admitted to further knowledge, but are not entrusted with the highest mysteries; the Chosen Ones, who in the Gospels are also spoken of as “Angels,” are admitted into all wisdom. As the Apostles were only members of the Second Degree, they had not the smallest suspicion of the secret machinery which was at work. Their part in the drama of the Life of Jesus was that of zealous “supers.” The Gospels which they composed therefore report, in perfect good faith, miracles which were really clever illusions produced by the Essenes, and they depict the life of Jesus only as seen by the populace from the outside.

Then begins the cleverly staged drama through which the people are to be converted to rational religion. The members of the Order are divided into three classes: The Baptized, The Disciples, and The Chosen Ones. The Baptized receive only the usual popular teaching; the Disciples are given access to further knowledge, but aren’t entrusted with the highest mysteries; the Chosen Ones, who in the Gospels are also referred to as “Angels” are granted access to all wisdom. Since the Apostles were only members of the Second Degree, they had no idea of the secret machinery that was at work. Their role in the drama of the Life of Jesus was that of enthusiastic "superheroes." The Gospels they wrote, therefore, faithfully report miracles that were actually clever illusions created by the Essenes, and they portray the life of Jesus only as seen from the outside by the general public.

It is therefore not always possible for us to discover how the events which they record as miracles actually came about. But whether they took place in one way or another—and as to this we can sometimes get a clue from a hint in the text—it is certain that in all cases the process was natural. With reference to the feeding of the five thousand, Bahrdt remarks: “It is more reasonable here to think of a thousand ways by which Jesus might have had sufficient supplies of bread at hand, and by the distribution of it have shamed the disciples' lack of courage, than to believe in a miracle.” The explanation which he himself prefers is that the Order had collected a great quantity of bread in a cave and this was gradually handed out to Jesus, who stood at the concealed entrance and took some every time the apostles were occupied in distributing the former supply to the multitude. The walking on the sea is to be explained by supposing that Jesus walked towards the disciples over the surface of a great floating raft; while they, not being able to see the raft, must needs suppose a miracle. When Peter tried to walk on the water he failed miserably. The miracles of healing are to be attributed to the art of Luke. He also called the attention of Jesus to remarkable cases of apparent death, which He then took in hand, and restored the apparently dead to their sorrowing friends. In such cases, however, the Lord never failed expressly to inform the disciples that the persons were not really dead. They, however, did not permit this assurance to deprive them of their faith in the miracle which they felt they had themselves witnessed.

It’s not always possible for us to figure out how the events recorded as miracles actually happened. But whether they occurred this way or that way—which we can sometimes guess from a hint in the text—it’s clear that the process was natural in all cases. Regarding the feeding of the five thousand, Bahrdt notes: "It makes more sense to consider a thousand ways that Jesus could have had enough bread available and distributed it to challenge the disciples' lack of courage than to believe in a miracle." His preferred explanation is that the Order had gathered a large amount of bread in a cave, and this was gradually given to Jesus, who stood at the hidden entrance and took some whenever the apostles were busy distributing the previous supply to the crowd. The walking on the sea can be explained by suggesting that Jesus walked towards the disciples over the surface of a large floating raft; since they couldn’t see the raft, they assumed it was a miracle. When Peter tried to walk on the water, he failed badly. The healing miracles can be attributed to Luke’s skill. He also pointed out notable cases of apparent death, which Jesus then addressed and brought the seemingly dead back to their grieving friends. However, in such cases, the Lord always made sure to inform the disciples that the individuals were not really dead. Still, this assurance didn’t take away their faith in the miracle they believed they had witnessed.

[pg 042]

In teaching, Jesus had two methods: one, exoteric, simple, for the world; the other, esoteric, mystic, for the initiate. “No attentive reader of the Bible,” says Bahrdt, “can fail to notice that Jesus made use of two different styles of speech. Sometimes He spoke so plainly and in such universally intelligible language, and declared truths so simple and so well adapted to the general comprehension of mankind that even the simplest could follow Him. At other times he spoke so mystically, so obscurely, and in so veiled a fashion that words and thoughts alike baffled the understandings of ordinary people, and even by more practised minds were not to be grasped without close reflection, so that we are told in John vi. 60 that ‘many of His disciples, when they heard this, said, This is an hard saying; who can hear it?’ And Jesus Himself did not deny it, but only told them that the reason of their not understanding His sayings lay in their prejudices, which made them interpret everything literally and materially, and overlook the ethical meaning which underlay His figurative language.” Most of these mystical discourses are to be found in John, who seems to have preserved for us the greater part of the secret teaching imparted to the initiate. The key to the understanding of this esoteric teaching is to be found, therefore, in the prologue to John's Gospel, and in the sayings about the new birth. “To be born again” is identical with the degree of perfection which was attained in the highest class of the Brotherhood.

In teaching, Jesus had two approaches: one, straightforward and simple, aimed at the general public; the other, mystical and complex, designed for those who were more spiritually aware. "No careful reader of the Bible," says Bahrdt, Many fail to realize that Jesus used two different ways of speaking. Sometimes He spoke very clearly and used language that everyone could understand, expressing ideas that were simple and relatable for all people, so much so that even those with little education could follow Him. At other times, He spoke in a mystical, obscure, and veiled way that left ordinary people confused, and even those more knowledgeable found it difficult to comprehend without deep reflection. In John 6:60, we read that ‘many of His disciples, when they heard this, said, This is a hard saying; who can hear it?’ Jesus didn’t argue with this; instead, He pointed out that their inability to understand stemmed from their biases, which led them to interpret everything literally and materially, causing them to miss the ethical meaning behind His figurative language. Most of these mystical teachings are found in John, who seems to have preserved much of the secret instruction given to the initiate. The key to understanding this esoteric teaching lies in the prologue to John's Gospel and in the discussions about being born anew. "Born again" is the same as achieving the level of perfection reached in the highest tier of the Brotherhood.

The members of the Order met on appointed days in caves among the hills. When we are told in the Gospels that Jesus went alone into a mountain to pray, this means that He repaired to one of these secret gatherings, but the disciples, of course, knew nothing about that. The Order had its hidden caves everywhere; in Galilee as well as in the neighbourhood of Jerusalem.

The members of the Order met on set days in caves in the hills. When we read in the Gospels that Jesus went up a mountain to pray, it means He went to one of these secret gatherings, but the disciples, of course, had no idea about it. The Order had hidden caves everywhere; in Galilee as well as around Jerusalem.

“Only by sensuous means can sensuous ideas be overcome.” The Jewish Messiah must die and rise again, in order that the false conceptions of the Messiah which were cherished by the multitude might be destroyed in the moment of their fulfilment—that is, might be spiritualised. Nicodemus, Haram, and Luke met in a cave in order to take counsel how they might bring about the death of Jesus in a way favourable to their plans. Luke guaranteed that by the aid of powerful drugs which he would give Him the Lord should be enabled to endure the utmost pain and suffering and yet resist death for a long time. Nicodemus undertook so to work matters in the Sanhedrin that the execution should follow immediately upon the sentence, and the crucified remain only a short time upon the cross. At this moment Jesus rushed into the cave. He had scarcely had time to replace the stone which concealed the entrance, so closely had He been pursued over the rocks by hired assassins. He Himself is firmly resolved [pg 043] to die, but care must be taken that He shall not be simply assassinated, or the whole plan fails. If He falls by the assassin's knife, no resurrection will be possible.

"Physical ideas can only be overcome through physical means." The Jewish Messiah has to die and rise again so that the false ideas about the Messiah held by the masses can be destroyed at the moment of their fulfillment—that is, elevated to a spiritual level. Nicodemus, Haram, and Luke gathered in a cave to discuss how they could ensure Jesus' death worked in their favor. Luke promised that with the help of powerful drugs he would provide, Jesus would be able to endure immense pain and suffering while delaying death for a long time. Nicodemus promised to manage things in the Sanhedrin so that the execution would happen immediately after the sentence, and the crucified would stay on the cross for only a short time. Just then, Jesus burst into the cave. He barely had time to close the stone that covered the entrance, as he had been closely chased over the rocks by hired killers. He is determined [pg 043] to die, but it’s crucial that he isn’t simply murdered, or the entire plan will fail. If he dies by an assassin's knife, there won’t be a chance for resurrection.

In the end, the piece is staged to perfection. Jesus provokes the authorities by His triumphal Messianic entry. The unsuspected Essenes in the council urge on His arrest and secure His condemnation—though Pilate almost frustrates all their plans by acquitting Him. Jesus, by uttering a loud cry and immediately afterwards bowing His head, shows every appearance of a sudden death. The centurion has been bribed not to allow any of His bones to be broken. Then comes Joseph of Ramath, as Bahrdt prefers to call Joseph of Arimathea, and removes the body to the cave of the Essenes, where he immediately commences measures of resuscitation. As Luke had prepared the body of the Messiah by means of strengthening medicines to resist the fearful ill-usage which He had gone through—the being dragged about and beaten and finally crucified—these efforts were crowned with success. In the cave the most strengthening nutriment was supplied to Him. “Since the humours of the body were in a thoroughly healthy condition, His wounds healed very readily, and by the third day He was able to walk, in spite of the fact that the wounds made by the nails were still open.”

In the end, the piece is staged to perfection. Jesus challenges the authorities with His triumphal Messianic entry. The unsuspecting Essenes in the council push for His arrest and secure His condemnation—although Pilate nearly ruins their plans by acquitting Him. Jesus, by letting out a loud cry and then bowing His head, gives every indication of a sudden death. The centurion has been paid off not to allow any of His bones to be broken. Then comes Joseph of Ramath, as Bahrdt prefers to call Joseph of Arimathea, who takes the body to the cave of the Essenes, where he immediately begins measures for resuscitation. Luke had prepared the body of the Messiah with strengthening medicines to withstand the terrible abuse He had endured—the dragging, the beating, and finally, the crucifixion— and these efforts were successful. In the cave, the most nourishing sustenance was provided to Him. "Since the body's humors were in excellent condition, His wounds healed quickly, and by the third day He was able to walk, even though the wounds from the nails were still open."

On the morning of the third day they forced away the stone which closed the mouth of the grave. As Jesus was descending the rocky slopes the watch awakened and took to flight in alarm. One of the Essenes appeared, in the garb of an angel, to the women and announced to them the resurrection of Jesus. Shortly afterwards the Lord appeared to Mary. At the sound of His voice she recognises Him. “Thereupon Jesus tells her that He is going to His Father (to heaven—in the mystic sense of the word—that is to say, to the Chosen Ones in their peaceful dwellings of truth and blessedness—to the circle of His faithful friends, among whom He continued to live, unseen by the world, but still working for the advancement of His purpose). He bade her tell His disciples that He was alive.”

On the morning of the third day, they rolled away the stone that sealed the entrance of the tomb. As Jesus was coming down the rocky slopes, the guards woke up and fled in fear. One of the Essenes appeared, dressed like an angel, to the women and announced Jesus' resurrection. Shortly after, the Lord appeared to Mary. Upon hearing His voice, she recognized Him. “Then Jesus told her that He was going to His Father (to heaven—in a spiritual sense, meaning to the Chosen Ones in their peaceful places of truth and happiness—to the circle of His loyal friends, among whom He continued to exist, unseen by the world, but still working towards His purpose). He instructed her to inform His disciples that He was alive.”

From His place of concealment He appeared several times to His disciples. Finally He bade them meet Him at the Mount of Olives, near Bethany, and there took leave of them. After exhorting them, and embracing each of them in turn, He tore Himself away from them and walked away up the mountain. “There stood those poor men, amazed—beside themselves with sorrow—and looked after Him as long as they could. But as He mounted higher, He entered ever deeper into the cloud which lay upon the hill-top, until finally He was no longer to be seen. The cloud received Him out of their sight.”

From His hiding place, He appeared several times to His disciples. Finally, He asked them to meet Him at the Mount of Olives, near Bethany, and there He said goodbye to them. After encouraging them and hugging each of them in turn, He reluctantly left them and walked up the mountain. "Those poor men stood there, stunned—overcome with sadness—and watched Him for as long as they could. But as He rose higher, He entered the cloud that surrounded the hilltop, until finally He was no longer visible. The cloud hid Him from their view."

From the mountain He returned to the chief lodge of the [pg 044] Brotherhood. Only at rare intervals did He again intervene in active life—as on the occasion when He appeared to Paul upon the road to Damascus. But, though unseen, He continued to direct the destinies of the community until His death.

From the mountain, He returned to the main lodge of the [pg 044] Brotherhood. He only occasionally got involved in active life again—like when He appeared to Paul on the road to Damascus. But, even though He was unseen, He kept guiding the community's fate until His death.


Venturini's “Non-supernatural History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth” is related to Bahrdt's work as the finished picture to the sketch.

Venturini's "Non-supernatural History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth" is connected to Bahrdt's work like a completed image is to a rough draft.

Karl Heinrich Venturini was born at Brunswick in 1768. On the completion of his theological studies he vainly endeavoured to secure a post as Docent in the theological faculty at Helmstadt, or as Librarian at Wolfenbüttel.

Karl Heinrich Venturini was born in Brunswick in 1768. After finishing his theological studies, he unsuccessfully tried to land a position as a lecturer in the theological faculty at Helmstadt or as a librarian at Wolfenbüttel.

His life was blameless and his personal piety beyond reproach, but he was considered to be too free in his ideas. The Duke of Brunswick was personally well disposed towards him, but did not venture to give him a post on the teaching staff in face of the opposition of the consistories. He was reduced to earning a bare pittance by literary work, and finally in 1806 was thankful to accept a small living in Hordorf near Brunswick. He then abandoned theological writing and devoted his energies to recording the events of contemporary history, of which he published a yearly chronicle—a proceeding which under the Napoleonic régime was not always unattended with risk, as he more than once had occasion to experience. He continued this undertaking till 1841. In 1849 death released him from his tasks.

His life was spotless, and his personal devotion was above criticism, but people thought he was too open-minded. The Duke of Brunswick liked him personally but didn’t dare give him a teaching position because of the opposition from the consistories. He was stuck earning very little from his writing and finally, in 1806, was grateful to accept a small position in Hordorf near Brunswick. He then stopped writing theology and focused on documenting contemporary history, publishing an annual chronicle—a task that under the Napoleonic diet was not always without danger, as he learned more than once. He continued this work until 1841. In 1849, death freed him from his responsibilities.

Venturini's fundamental assumption is that it was impossible, even for the noblest spirit of mankind, to make Himself understood by the Judaism of His time except by clothing His spiritual teaching in a sensuous garb calculated to please the oriental imagination, “and, in general, by bringing His higher spiritual world into such relations with the lower sensuous world of those whom He wished to teach as was necessary to the accomplishment of His aims.” “God's Messenger was morally bound to perform miracles for the Jews. These miracles had an ethical purpose, and were especially designed to counteract the impression made by the supposed miracles of the deceivers of the people, and thus to hasten the overthrow of the kingdom of Satan.”

Venturini's fundamental belief is that it was impossible, even for the highest spirit of humanity, to be understood by the Judaism of His time unless He presented His spiritual teachings in a way that appealed to the Eastern imagination. "And, overall, by linking His higher spiritual realm with the lower sensory world of those He aimed to teach in a way that was essential for accomplishing His objectives." "God's Messenger had a moral duty to perform miracles for the Jews. These miracles had an ethical purpose and were specifically meant to counteract the effects of the so-called miracles done by deceivers among the people, thereby hastening the downfall of the kingdom of Satan."

For modern medical science the miracles are not miraculous. He never healed without medicaments and always carried His “portable medicine chest” with Him. In the case of the Syro-phoenician woman's daughter, for example, we can still detect in the narrative a hint of the actual course of events. The mother explains the case to Jesus. After enquiring where her dwelling was he made a sign to John, and continued to hold her in conversation. The disciple went to the daughter and gave her a sedative, and when the mother returned she found her child cured.

For modern medical science, miracles aren't really miraculous. He never healed without medicine and always had His “portable medicine kit” with Him. In the story of the Syro-Phoenician woman's daughter, we can still see hints of what actually happened. The mother explained the situation to Jesus. After asking where she lived, He signaled to John and kept talking to her. The disciple went to the daughter and gave her a sedative, and when the mother returned, she found her child healed.

[pg 045]

The raisings from the dead were cases of coma. The nature-miracles were due to a profound acquaintance with the powers of Nature and the order of her processes. They involve fore-knowledge rather than control.

The instances of raising people from the dead were actually cases of coma. The nature miracles stemmed from a deep understanding of the powers of nature and how her processes work. They rely on foresight rather than control.

Many miracle stories rest on obvious misunderstandings. Nothing could be simpler than the explanation of the miracle at Cana. Jesus had brought with Him as a wedding-gift some jars of good wine and had put them aside in another room. When the wine was finished and His mother became anxious, He still allowed the guests to wait a little, as the stone vessels for purification had not yet been filled with water. When that had been done He ordered the servants to pour out some of his wine, but to tell no one whence it came. When John, as an old man, wrote his Gospel, he got all this rather mixed up—had not indeed observed it very closely at the time, “had perhaps been the least thing merry himself,” says Venturini, and had believed in the miracle with the rest. Perhaps, too, he had not ventured to ask Jesus for an explanation, for he had only become His disciple a few days before.

Many miracle stories are based on clear misunderstandings. The explanation of the miracle at Cana is quite straightforward. Jesus brought some jars of good wine as a wedding gift and set them aside in another room. When the wine ran out and His mother became worried, He still let the guests wait a bit because the stone purification vessels hadn’t been filled with water yet. Once that was done, He instructed the servants to pour out some of the wine but to keep its source a secret. When John, as an older man, wrote his Gospel, he got this story somewhat confused—having not observed it very carefully at the time, "had maybe been the least merry person himself," as Venturini puts it, and had believed in the miracle along with everyone else. Perhaps he also hadn’t felt comfortable asking Jesus for clarification since he had only become His disciple a few days earlier.

The members of the Essene Order had watched over the child Jesus even in Egypt. As He grew older they took charge of His education along with that of His cousin, John, and trained them both for their work as deliverers of the people. Whereas the nation as a whole looked to an insurrection as the means of its deliverance, they knew that freedom could only be achieved by means of a spiritual renewal. Once Jesus and John met a band of insurgents: Jesus worked on them so powerfully by His fervid speech that they recognised the impiousness of their purpose. One of them sprang towards Him and laid down his arms; it was Simon, who afterwards became His disciple.

The members of the Essene Order watched over the child Jesus even while in Egypt. As He grew older, they took charge of His education alongside that of His cousin, John, training both of them for their roles as liberators of the people. While the nation as a whole hoped for an uprising as the way to freedom, they understood that true liberation could only come through a spiritual awakening. One time, Jesus and John encountered a group of rebels: Jesus spoke to them with such passion that they realized the wrongness of their cause. One of the rebels rushed towards Him and laid down his weapons; it was Simon, who later became His disciple.

When Jesus was about thirty years old, and, owing to the deep experiences of His inner life, had really far outgrown the aims of the Essene Order, He entered upon His office by demanding baptism from John. Just as this was taking place a thunderstorm broke, and a dove, frightened by the lightning, fluttered round the head of Jesus. Both Jesus and John took this as a sign that the hour appointed by God had come.

When Jesus was about thirty years old and had moved beyond the goals of the Essene Order due to his profound inner experiences, he began his mission by asking John for baptism. At that moment, a thunderstorm erupted, and a dove, startled by the lightning, flew around Jesus' head. Both Jesus and John interpreted this as a sign that the time set by God had arrived.

The temptations in the wilderness, and upon the pinnacle of the Temple, were due to the machinations of the Pharisee Zadok, who pretended to enter into the plans of Jesus and feigned admiration for Him in order the more surely to entrap Him. It was Zadok, too, who stirred up opposition to Him in the Sanhedrin.

The temptations in the wilderness and on the top of the Temple were caused by the schemes of the Pharisee Zadok, who pretended to support Jesus and faked admiration for Him to trap Him more effectively. It was also Zadok who incited opposition against Him in the Sanhedrin.

But Jesus did not succeed in destroying the old Messianic belief with its earthly aims. The hatred of the leading circles against Him grew, although He avoided everything “that could offend their prejudices.” It was for this reason that He even forbade His disciples to preach the Gospel beyond the borders of Jewish [pg 046] territory. He paid the temple-tax, also, although he had no fixed abode. When the collector went to Peter about it, the following dialogue took place.

But Jesus couldn’t shake the old Messianic beliefs that focused on earthly goals. The leaders’ dislike for Him grew, even though He tried to avoid anything that might “offend their biases.” For this reason, He even told His disciples not to spread the Gospel beyond Jewish [pg 046] territory. He also paid the temple tax, even though He didn’t have a permanent home. When the collector approached Peter about it, this conversation happened.

Tax-collector (drawing Peter aside). Tell me, Simon, does the Rabbi pay the didrachma to the Temple treasury, or should we not trouble Him about it?

Tax agent (pulling Peter aside). Hey Simon, does the Rabbi pay the didrachma to the Temple treasury, or should we not bother Him about it?

Peter. Why shouldn't He pay it? Why do you ask?

Peter. Why shouldn't He pay it? What's the reason for your question?

Tax-collector. It's been owing from both of you since last Nisan, as our books show. We did not like to remind your Master, out of reverence.

Tax agent. It's been due from both of you since last Nisan, according to our records. We didn't want to bring it up with your Master out of respect.

Peter. I'll tell Him at once. He will certainly pay the tax. You need have no fear about that.

Peter. I'll let Him know right away. He’ll definitely pay the tax. You don’t have to worry about that.

Tax-collector. That's good. That will put everything straight, and we shall have no trouble over our accounts. Good-bye!

Tax collector. That's great. That will clear everything up, and we won't have any issues with our accounts. Goodbye!

When Jesus hears of it He commands Peter to go and catch a fish, and to take care, in removing the hook, not to tear its mouth, that it may be fit for salting (!) In that case it will doubtless be worth a stater.

When Jesus hears about it, He tells Peter to go catch a fish and to be careful when removing the hook so that it doesn't tear its mouth, making it suitable for salting. In that case, it will definitely be worth a stater.

The time arrived when an important move must be made. In full conclave of the Secret Society it was resolved that Jesus should go up to Jerusalem and there publicly proclaim Himself as the Messiah. Then He was to endeavour to disabuse the people of their earthly Messianic expectations.

The time came when a significant decision needed to be made. In a full gathering of the Secret Society, it was decided that Jesus should head to Jerusalem and publicly announce Himself as the Messiah. After that, He would try to correct the people's worldly expectations of a Messiah.

The triumphal entry succeeded. The whole people hailed Him with acclamations. But when He tried to substitute for their picture of the Messiah one of a different character, and spoke of times of severe trial which should come upon all, when He showed Himself but seldom in the Temple, instead of taking His place at the head of the people, they began to doubt Him.

The triumphant entry was a success. Everyone celebrated Him with cheers. But when He tried to replace their image of the Messiah with a different one, talking about tough times ahead for everyone, and when He appeared only occasionally in the Temple instead of leading the people, they started to lose faith in Him.

Jesus was suddenly arrested and put to death. Here, then, the death is not, as in Bahrdt, a piece of play-acting, stage-managed by the Secret Society. Jesus really expected to die, and only to meet His disciples again in the eternal life of the other world. But when He so soon gave up the ghost, Joseph of Arimathea was moved by some vague premonition to hasten at once to Pontius Pilate and make request for His body. He offers the Procurator money. Pilate (sternly and emphatically): “Dost thou also mistake me? Am I, then, such an insatiable miser? Still, thou art a Jew—how could this people do me justice? Know, then, that a Roman can honour true nobility wherever he may find it. (He sits down and writes some words on a strip of parchment.) Give this to the captain of the guard. Thou shall be permitted to remove the body. I ask nothing for this. It is granted to thee freely.”

Jesus was suddenly arrested and put to death. Here, the death isn’t, as in Bahrdt, just a performance orchestrated by the Secret Society. Jesus truly expected to die and only to reunite with His disciples in the eternal life of the afterworld. But when He quickly passed away, Joseph of Arimathea felt a vague sense of urgency and hurried to Pontius Pilate to request His body. He offers the Procurator money. Pilate (firmly and clearly): "Do you also misjudge me? Am I really that greedy and selfish? Still, you are a Jew—how can this people treat me fairly? Just understand that a Roman can recognize true nobility wherever he sees it. (He sits down and writes something on a strip of parchment.) Give this to the captain of the guard. You'll be allowed to take the body. I want nothing in return for this. It is given to you freely."

“A tender embrace from his wife rewarded the noble deed of the Roman, while Joseph left the Praetorium, and with Nicodemus, who was impatiently awaiting him, hastened to Golgotha.” There [pg 047] he received the body; he washed it, anointed it with spices, and laid it on a bed of moss in the rock-hewn grave. From the blood which was still flowing from the wound in the side, he ventured to draw a hopeful augury, and sent word to the Essene Brethren. They had a hold close by, and promised to watch over the body. In the first four-and-twenty hours no movement of life showed itself. Then came the earthquake. In the midst of the terrible commotion a Brother, in the white robes of the Order, was making his way to the grave by a secret path. When he, illumined by a flash of lightning, suddenly appeared above the grave, and at the same moment the earth shook violently, panic seized the watch, and they fled. In the morning the Brother hears a sound from the grave: Jesus is moving. The whole Order hastens to the spot, and Jesus is removed to their Lodge. Two brethren remain at the grave—these were the “angels” whom the women saw later. Jesus, in the dress of a gardener, is afterwards recognised by Mary Magdalene. Later, He comes out at intervals from the hiding-place, where He is kept by the Brethren, and appears to the disciples. After forty days He took His leave of them: His strength was exhausted. The farewell scene gave rise to the mistaken impression of His Ascension.

A warm hug from his wife recognized the honorable deed of the Roman, while Joseph left the Praetorium and hurried to Golgotha with Nicodemus, who was anxiously waiting for him. There [pg 047] he took the body; he washed it, anointed it with spices, and laid it on a bed of moss in the rock-cut grave. From the blood still flowing from the wound in the side, he dared to draw a hopeful sign and sent word to the Essene Brethren. They had a nearby hold and promised to watch over the body. In the first twenty-four hours, there was no sign of life. Then came the earthquake. Amid the violent chaos, a Brother in the white robes of the Order made his way to the grave by a hidden path. When he suddenly appeared above the grave, illuminated by a flash of lightning, the earth shook violently at the same moment, causing panic among the guards, who fled. In the morning, the Brother heard a noise from the grave: Jesus was moving. The entire Order rushed to the site, and Jesus was taken to their Lodge. Two brethren remained at the grave—these were the "angels" that the women saw later. Jesus, dressed as a gardener, was later recognized by Mary Magdalene. He occasionally emerged from the hideout where the Brethren kept him and appeared to the disciples. After forty days, He said goodbye to them: His strength was exhausted. The farewell scene led to the mistaken belief in His Ascension.

From the historical point of view these lives are not such contemptible performances as might be supposed. There is much penetrating observation in them. Bahrdt and Venturini are right in feeling that the connexion of events in the life of Jesus has to be discovered; the Gospels give only a series of occurrences, and offer no explanation why they happened just as they did. And if, in making Jesus subservient to the plans of a secret society, they represented Him as not acting with perfect freedom, but as showing a certain passivity, this assumption of theirs was to be brilliantly vindicated, a hundred years later, by the eschatological school, which asserts the same remarkable passivity on the part of Jesus, in that He allows His actions to be determined, not indeed by a secret society, but by the eschatological plan of God. Bahrdt and Venturini were the first to see that, of all Jesus' acts, His death was most distinctively His own, because it was by this that He purposed to found the kingdom.

From a historical standpoint, these lives are not as worthless as one might think. There is a lot of insightful observation in them. Bahrdt and Venturini are correct in believing that we need to uncover the connection of events in the life of Jesus; the Gospels only present a series of events and don’t explain why they happened the way they did. And if, by presenting Jesus as serving the agenda of a secret society, they portrayed Him as not acting completely freely, but rather showing a degree of passivity, this idea was later compellingly supported, a hundred years later, by the eschatological school, which claims the same notable passivity on Jesus' part, in that He allows His actions to be guided, not by a secret society, but by God's eschatological plan. Bahrdt and Venturini were the first to recognize that, among all of Jesus' actions, His death was the most uniquely His, as it was through this that He intended to establish the kingdom.

Venturini's “Non-supernatural History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth” may almost be said to be reissued annually down to the present day, for all the fictitious “Lives” go back directly or indirectly to the type which he created. It is plagiarised more freely than any other Life of Jesus, although practically unknown by name.

Venturini's "History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth Without Supernatural Elements" could almost be considered to be released every year up to today, because all the fictional “Lives” trace back directly or indirectly to the model he established. It's copied more frequently than any other account of Jesus, even though it's mostly unknown by name.

[pg 048]

V. Fully Developed Rationalism—Paulus

Heinrich Eberhard Gottlob Paulus. Das Leben Jesu als Grundlage einer reinen Geschichte des Urchristentums. Heidelberg, C. F. Winter. (The Life of Jesus as the Basis of a purely Historical Account of Early Christianity.) 1828. 2 vols., 1192 pp.

Heinrich Eberhard Gottlob Paulus. The Life of Jesus as the Foundation for a Completely Historical Account of Early Christianity. Heidelberg, C. F. Winter. 1828. 2 volumes, 1192 pages.

Rejoice with devotion to God when it is granted to you,
Dem, as brief as it was, world-changing life journey
After centuries of following from afar,
Think, believe, follow the path of the example!
(Closing words of vol. 2.)
(Rejoice with thankful devotion, if it is allowed for you,
Even after centuries have passed, still to follow from a distance.
That life, short as it was, changed the course of history;
Think carefully and believe; follow the path of our Pattern.

Paulus was not the mere dry-as-dust rationalist that he is usually represented to have been, but a man of very versatile abilities. His limitation was that, like Reinhard, he had an unconquerable distrust of anything that went outside the boundaries of logical thought. That was due in part to the experiences of his youth. His father, a deacon in Leonberg, half-mystic, half-rationalist, had secret difficulties about the doctrine of immortality, and made his wife promise on her death-bed that, if it were possible, she would appear to him after her death in bodily form. After she was dead he thought he saw her raise herself to a sitting posture, and again sink down. From that time onwards he firmly believed himself to be in communication with departed spirits, and he became so dominated by this idea that in 1771 he had to be removed from his office. His children suffered sorely from a régime of compulsory spiritualism, which pressed hardest upon Heinrich Eberhard Gottlob, born in 1761, who, for the sake of peace, was obliged to pretend to his father that he was in communication with his mother's spirit.

Paulus wasn’t just the dry rationalist he’s often portrayed as; he was a person with diverse skills. His limitation was that, like Reinhard, he had an unshakeable distrust of anything that fell outside logical reasoning. This was partly due to his childhood experiences. His father, a deacon in Leonberg, was a mix of mystic and rationalist and struggled secretly with the concept of immortality. He made his wife promise on her deathbed that, if possible, she would come back to him in physical form after she died. After her passing, he believed he saw her sit up and then lie back down. From that moment on, he was convinced he was in touch with spirits of the deceased, and this belief consumed him so much that in 1771, he had to be removed from his position. His children endured a strict regime of enforced spiritualism, which affected Heinrich Eberhard Gottlob, born in 1761, the most, as he had to pretend to his father that he was communicating with his mother's spirit for the sake of family peace.

He himself had inherited only the rationalistic side of his father's temperament. As a student at the Tübingen Stift (theological institute) he formed his views on the writings of [pg 049] Semler and Michaelis. In 1789 he was called to Jena as Professor of Oriental Languages, and succeeded in 1793 to the third ordinary professorship of theology. The naturalistic interpretation of miracles which he upheld in his commentary on the Synoptic Gospels, published in 1800-1802, aroused the indignation of the consistories of Meiningen and Eisenach. But their petition for his removal from the professorship was unsuccessful, since Herder, who was president of the consistorium, used his influence to protect him. In 1799 Paulus, as Pro-rector, used his influence on behalf of his colleague Fichte, who was attacked on the ground of atheism; but in vain, owing to the passionate conduct of the accused.

He had only inherited the rational side of his father's personality. While studying at the Tübingen Stift (theological institute), he developed his views based on the writings of [pg 049] Semler and Michaelis. In 1789, he was appointed as Professor of Oriental Languages in Jena, and in 1793, he took over the third ordinary professorship of theology. The naturalistic interpretation of miracles that he presented in his commentary on the Synoptic Gospels, published between 1800 and 1802, sparked outrage among the consistories of Meiningen and Eisenach. However, their attempt to have him removed from his position failed, as Herder, the president of the consistorium, used his influence to protect him. In 1799, Paulus, as Pro-rector, tried to advocate for his colleague Fichte, who was under attack for atheism; unfortunately, his efforts were in vain due to Fichte's emotional response.

With Goethe, Schiller, and Wieland, Paulus and his wife, a lively lady of some literary talents, stood in the most friendly relations.

With Goethe, Schiller, and Wieland, Paulus and his wife, who was a lively woman with some literary skills, had a very friendly relationship.

When the Jena circle began to break up, he accepted, in 1803, an invitation from the Elector of Bavaria, Maximilian Joseph II., to go to Würzburg as Konsistorialrat and professor. There the liberal minister, Montgelas, was desirous of establishing a university founded on the principles of illuminism—Schelling, Hufeland, and Schleiermacher were among those whom he contemplated appointing as Docents. Here the Catholic theological students were obliged to attend the lectures of the Protestant professor of theology, as there were no Protestants to form an audience. His first course was on “Encyclopädie” (i.e. introduction to the literature of theology).

When the Jena circle started to break up, he accepted an invitation in 1803 from the Elector of Bavaria, Maximilian Joseph II, to go to Würzburg as a Konsistorialrat and professor. There, the liberal minister, Montgelas, wanted to establish a university based on the principles of enlightenment—Schelling, Hufeland, and Schleiermacher were among those he considered appointing as faculty members. Catholic theology students were required to attend lectures by the Protestant theology professor, as there were no Protestants to form an audience. His first course was on "Encyclopedia" (i.e. introduction to the literature of theology).

The plan failed. Paulus resigned his professorship and became in 1807 a member of the Bavarian educational council (Schulrat). In this capacity he worked at the reorganisation of the Bavarian school system at the time when Hegel was similarly engaged. He gave four years to this task, which he felt to be laid upon him as a duty. Then, in 1811, he went to Heidelberg as professor of theology; and he remained there until his death, in 1851, at the age of ninety. One of his last sayings, a few hours before he died, was, “I am justified before God, through my desire to do right.” His last words were, “There is another world.”

The plan failed. Paulus resigned from his teaching position and became a member of the Bavarian educational council (School Board) in 1807. In this role, he worked on reorganizing the Bavarian school system, at the same time Hegel was doing similar work. He dedicated four years to this task, which he saw as his duty. Then, in 1811, he moved to Heidelberg as a professor of theology, where he remained until his death in 1851 at the age of ninety. One of his last statements, just a few hours before he died, was, "I am justified before God because I want to do what’s right." His final words were, "There's another world."

The forty years of his Heidelberg period were remarkably productive; there was no department of knowledge on which he did not write. He expressed his views about homoeopathy, about the freedom of the Press, about academic freedom, and about the duelling nuisance. In 1831, he wrote upon the Jewish Question; and there the veteran rationalist showed himself a bitter anti-Semite, and brought upon himself the scorn of Heine. On politics and constitutional questions he fought for his opinions so openly and manfully that he had to be warned to be more discreet. In philosophy he took an especially keen interest. When in Jena he had, in conjunction with Schiller, busied himself in the study [pg 050] of Kant. He did a particularly meritorious service in preparing an edition of Spinoza's writings, with a biography of that thinker, in 1803, at the time when neo-Spinozism was making its influence felt in German philosophy. He constituted himself the special guardian of philosophy, and the moment he detected the slightest hint of mysticism, he sounded the alarm. His pet aversion was Schelling, who was born fourteen years later than he, in the very same house at Leonberg, and whom he had met as colleague at Jena and at Würzburg. The works, avowed and anonymous, which he directed against this “charlatan, juggler, swindler, and obscurantist,” as he designated him, fill an entire library.

The forty years of his time in Heidelberg were incredibly productive; he wrote about every field of knowledge. He shared his opinions on homeopathy, the freedom of the press, academic freedom, and the issue of dueling. In 1831, he wrote about the Jewish Question, and there the seasoned rationalist revealed himself to be a harsh anti-Semite, earning the disdain of Heine. He fought for his political beliefs so openly and boldly that he had to be advised to exercise more discretion. He had a particularly strong interest in philosophy. While in Jena, he worked alongside Schiller to study Kant. He made significant contributions by preparing an edition of Spinoza's writings, including a biography of that philosopher, in 1803, during the rise of neo-Spinozism in German philosophy. He positioned himself as a staunch defender of philosophy and immediately raised concerns whenever he encountered even a hint of mysticism. His greatest dislike was for Schelling, who was born fourteen years after him in the same house in Leonberg and with whom he had worked as a colleague in Jena and Würzburg. The numerous works, both openly published and anonymous, that he directed against this “charlatan, juggler, swindler, and obscurantist,” as he referred to him, could fill an entire library.

In 1841, Schelling was called to the chair of philosophy in Berlin, and in the winter of 1841-1842 he gave his lectures on “The Philosophy of Revelation” which caused the Berlin reactionaries to hail him as their great ally. The veteran rationalist—he was eighty years old—was transported with rage. He had had the lectures taken down for him, and he published them with critical remarks under the title “The Philosophy of Revelation at length Revealed, and set forth for General Examination, by Dr. H. E. G. Paulus” (Darmstadt, 1842). Schelling was furious, and dragged “the impudent scoundrel” into a court of law on the charge of illicit publication. In Prussia the book was suppressed. But the courts decided in favour of Paulus, who coolly explained that “the philosophy of Schelling appeared to him an insidious attack upon sound reason, the unmasking of which by every possible means was a work of public utility, nay, even a duty.” He also secured the result at which he aimed; Schelling resigned his lectureship.

In 1841, Schelling was appointed to the philosophy chair in Berlin, and during the winter of 1841-1842, he delivered his lectures on “Revelation Philosophy”, which led the Berlin reactionaries to view him as their significant ally. The seasoned rationalist—he was eighty years old—was infuriated. He had the lectures transcribed and published them with critical comments under the title “The Philosophy of Revelation Fully Unveiled and Presented for General Review by Dr. H. E. G. Paulus” (Darmstadt, 1842). Schelling was livid and took “the cheeky scoundrel” to court for unauthorized publication. In Prussia, the book was banned. However, the courts ruled in favor of Paulus, who calmly stated that "To him, Schelling's philosophy seemed like a sneaky assault on common sense, and exposing it by any means possible was a service to the public, even a responsibility." He also achieved his goal; Schelling resigned from his lectureship.

In his last days the veteran rationalist was an isolated survival from an earlier age into a period which no longer understood him. The new men reproached him for standing in the old ways; he accused them of a want of honesty. It was just in his immobility and his one-sidedness that his significance lay. By his consistent carrying through of the rationalistic explanation he performed a service to theology more valuable than those who think themselves so vastly his superiors are willing to acknowledge.

In his final days, the veteran rationalist was a lonely relic from a time that no longer understood him. The new generation criticized him for clinging to outdated beliefs; he called them out for their lack of integrity. His significance resided in his stubbornness and narrow perspective. By consistently upholding the rational explanation, he provided a service to theology that was more valuable than what those who consider themselves far superior are willing to admit.

His Life of Jesus is awkwardly arranged. The first part gives a historical exposition of the Gospels, section by section. The second part is a synopsis interspersed with supplementary matter. There is no attempt to grasp the life of Jesus as a connected whole. In that respect he is far inferior to Venturini. Strictly regarded, his work is only a harmony of the gospels with explanatory comments, the ground plan of which is taken from the Fourth Gospel.22

His Life of Jesus is poorly organized. The first part provides a historical overview of the Gospels, section by section. The second part is a summary mixed with additional information. There’s no effort to understand the life of Jesus as a unified whole. In that regard, he is much less capable than Venturini. Strictly speaking, his work is just a collection of the gospels with explanatory notes, based on the structure of the Fourth Gospel. 22

[pg 051]

The main interest centres in the explanations of the miracles, though the author, it must be admitted, endeavoured to guard against this. “It is my chief desire,” he writes in his preface, “that my views regarding the miracle stories should not be taken as by any means the principal thing. How empty would devotion or religion be if one's spiritual well-being depended on whether one believed in miracles or no!” “The truly miraculous thing about Jesus is Himself, the purity and serene holiness of His character, which is, notwithstanding, genuinely human, and adapted to the imitation and emulation of mankind.”

The main focus is on explaining the miracles, although the author tries to steer away from that. "My primary goal," he writes in his preface, "My perspective on the miracle stories shouldn't be seen as the most important part. How pointless would faith or religion be if our spiritual well-being relied on whether we believe in miracles or not?" "The truly amazing thing about Jesus is Himself, the pure and peaceful holiness of His character, which remains genuinely human and is meant to be a model for people to follow and imitate."

The question of miracle is therefore a subsidiary question. Two points of primary importance are certain from the outset: (1) that unexplained alterations of the course of nature can neither overthrow nor attest a spiritual truth, (2) that everything which happens in nature emanates from the omnipotence of God.

The question of miracles is therefore a secondary issue. Two main points are clear from the beginning: (1) that unexplained changes in the natural order can neither disprove nor confirm a spiritual truth, and (2) that everything that occurs in nature comes from God's all-powerful will.

The Evangelists intended to relate miracles; of that there can be no doubt. Nor can any one deny that in their time miracles entered into the plan of God, in the sense that the minds of men were to be astounded and subdued by inexplicable facts. This effect, however, is past. In periods to which the miraculous makes less appeal, in view of the advance in intellectual culture of the nations which have been led to accept Christianity, the understanding must be satisfied if the success of the cause is to be maintained.

The Evangelists aimed to share miracles; there's no doubt about that. No one can deny that during their time, miracles were part of God’s plan, meant to astonish and humble people with inexplicable events. However, that impact has faded. In times when miracles resonate less, given the intellectual advancement of the nations that have embraced Christianity, understanding must be fulfilled if the cause is to continue succeeding.

Since that which is produced by the laws of nature is really produced by God, the Biblical miracles consist merely in the fact that eyewitnesses report events of which they did not know the secondary causes. Their knowledge of the laws of nature was insufficient to enable them to understand what actually happened. For one who has discovered the secondary causes, the fact remains, as such, but not the miracle.

Since what is created by the laws of nature is ultimately created by God, the Biblical miracles are simply eyewitness reports of events they didn’t understand the underlying causes of. Their understanding of the laws of nature was not enough for them to grasp what actually occurred. For someone who has identified the underlying causes, the event remains as it is, but it’s no longer considered a miracle.

The question of miracle, therefore, does not really exist, or exists only for those “who are under the influence of the sceptical delusion that it is possible really to think any kind of natural powers as existing apart from God, or to think the Being of God apart from the primal potentialities which unfold themselves in the never-ceasing process of Becoming.” The difficulty arises from the “original sin” of dissolving the inner unity of God and nature, of denying the equivalence implied by Spinoza in his “Deus sive Natura.”

The question of miracles, therefore, doesn't really exist or only exists for those who are under the skeptical illusion that it's possible to think about any natural powers as existing separately from God, or to consider God's existence apart from the fundamental possibilities that unfold in the never-ending process of Becoming. The issue comes from the "original sin" of breaking the inner unity of God and nature, of denying the equivalence that Spinoza implied in his "Deus sive Natura."

For the normal intelligence the only problem is to discover the secondary causes of the “miracles” of Jesus. It is true there is one miracle which Paulus retains—the miracle of the birth, or at least the possibility of it; in the sense that it is through holy [pg 052] inspiration that Mary receives the hope and the power of conceiving her exalted Son, in whom the spirit of the Messiah takes up its dwelling. Here he indirectly denies the natural generation, and regards the conception as an act of the self-consciousness of the mother.

For the average person, the main challenge is figuring out the secondary causes of the "miracles" of Jesus. It's true that there’s one miracle that Paulus accepts—the miracle of the birth, or at least the possibility of it; in the sense that it is through holy [pg 052] inspiration that Mary gains the hope and ability to conceive her extraordinary Son, in whom the spirit of the Messiah resides. Here, he indirectly denies natural birth and views the conception as an act of the mother’s self-awareness.

With the miracles of healing, however, the case is very simple. Sometimes Jesus worked through His spiritual power upon the nervous system of the sufferer; sometimes He used medicines known to Him alone. The latter applies, for instance, to the cures of the blind. The disciples, too, as appears from Mark vi. 7 and 13, were not sent out without medicaments, for the oil with which they were to anoint the sick was, of course, of a medicinal character; and the casting out of evil spirits was effected partly by means of sedatives.

With the miracles of healing, the situation is quite straightforward. Sometimes Jesus used His spiritual power to influence the nervous system of the person suffering; other times, He relied on medicines that He alone knew about. This is particularly true for the cures of the blind. As seen in Mark 6:7 and 13, the disciples weren’t sent out without medications, since the oil they used to anoint the sick had medicinal properties; casting out evil spirits was also done partially with sedatives.

Diet and after-treatment played a great part, though the Evangelists say little about this because directions on these points would not be given publicly. Thus, the saying, “This kind goeth not out save by prayer and fasting,” is interpreted as an instruction to the father as to the way in which he could make the sudden cure of the epileptic into a permanent one, viz. by keeping him to a strict diet and strengthening his character by devotional exercises.

Diet and aftercare were really important, though the Evangelists don't say much about this because guidance on these topics wouldn't be shared openly. So, the saying, "This kind can only come out through prayer and fasting," is understood as advice to the father on how to turn the epileptic's sudden cure into a lasting one, specifically by following a strict diet and strengthening his character through spiritual practices.

The nature miracles suggest their own explanation. The walking on the water was an illusion of the disciples. Jesus walked along the shore, and in the mist was taken for a ghost by the alarmed and excited occupants of the boat. When Jesus called to them, Peter threw himself into the water, and was drawn to shore by Jesus just as he was sinking. Immediately after taking Jesus into the boat they doubled a headland and drew clear of the storm centre; they therefore supposed that He had calmed the sea by His command. It was the same in the case where He was asleep during the storm. When they waked Him He spoke to them about the wind and the weather. At that moment they gained the shelter of a hill which protected them from the wind that swept down the valley; and they marvelled among themselves that even the winds and the sea obeyed their Messiah.

The nature of miracles suggests their own explanation. The disciples thought they saw Jesus walking on water, but it was just an illusion. He was actually walking along the shore, and the frightened people in the boat mistook Him for a ghost. When Jesus called to them, Peter jumped into the water and was pulled to shore by Jesus just as he was starting to sink. As soon as they brought Jesus into the boat, they rounded a headland and got out of the storm's reach; they thought He had calmed the sea with His command. It was similar when He was asleep during the storm. When they woke Him, He talked to them about the wind and the weather. At that moment, they found shelter behind a hill that shielded them from the wind coming down the valley, and they marveled at how even the winds and the sea obeyed their Messiah.

The feeding of the five thousand is explained in the following way. When Jesus saw the multitude all hungered, He said to His disciples, “We will set the rich people among them a good example, that they may share their supplies with the others,” and he began to distribute His own provisions, and those of the disciples, to the people who were sitting near them. The example had its effect, and soon there was plenty for every one.

The feeding of the five thousand is explained in the following way. When Jesus saw the crowd hungry, He said to His disciples, “We will set a good example for the rich, so they’ll share their resources with others,” and He started handing out His own food, along with what the disciples had, to the people sitting near them. The example worked, and soon there was plenty for everyone.

The explanation of the transfiguration is somewhat more complicated. While Jesus was lingering with a few followers in this mountainous district He had an interview upon a high mountain at night with two dignified-looking men whom His three companions took for Moses and Elias. These unknown persons, [pg 053] as we learn from Luke ix. 31, informed Him of the fate which awaited Him at Jerusalem. In the early morning, as the sun was rising, the three disciples, only half awake, looked upwards from the hollow in which they had been sleeping and saw Jesus with the two strangers upon the higher part of the mountain, illuminated by the beams of the rising sun, and heard them speak, now of the fate which threatened Him in the capital, now of the duty of steadfastness and the hopes attached thereto, and finally heard an exhortation addressed to themselves, bidding them ever to hold Jesus to be the beloved Son of the Deity, whom they must obey.... Their drowsiness, and the clouds which in an autumnal sunrise float to and fro over those mountains,23 left them no clear recollection of what had happened. This only added to the wonder of the vague undefined impression of having been in contact with apparitions from a higher sphere. The three who had been with Him on the mount never arrived at any more definite knowledge of the facts, because Jesus forbade them to speak of what they had seen until the end should come.

The explanation of the transfiguration is a bit more complex. While Jesus was spending time with a few followers in this mountainous area, He had an encounter at night on a high mountain with two dignified-looking men, whom His three companions believed to be Moses and Elijah. These unknown figures, [pg 053] as we learn from Luke 9:31, informed Him about the fate that awaited Him in Jerusalem. In the early morning, as the sun was rising, the three disciples, only half awake, looked up from the dip where they had been sleeping and saw Jesus with the two strangers on the higher part of the mountain, lit up by the rays of the rising sun. They heard them discussing the fate that loomed over Him in the capital, the duty of steadfastness, and the hopes tied to it, and finally received a message directed to them, urging them to always regard Jesus as the beloved Son of God, whom they must obey. Their grogginess and the clouds that drifted lazily across the mountains at autumn sunrise left them with no clear memory of what had happened. This only added to the wonder of the vague, undefined feeling of having encountered beings from a higher realm. The three who had been with Him on the mountain never gained any clearer understanding of the details because Jesus instructed them not to speak about what they had witnessed until the end would come.

In dealing with the raisings from the dead the author is in his element. Here he is ready with the unfailing explanation taken over from Bahrdt that they were only cases of coma. These narratives should not be headed “raisings from the dead,” but “deliverances from premature burial.” In Judaea, interment took place three hours after death. How many seemingly dead people may have returned to consciousness in their graves, and then have perished miserably! Thus Jesus, owing to a presentiment suggested to Him by the father's story, saves the daughter of Jairus from being buried while in a cataleptic trance. A similar presentiment led Him to remove the covering of the bier which He met at the gate of Nain, and to discover traces of life in the widow's son. A similar instinct moved Him to ask to be taken to the grave of Lazarus. When the stone is rolled away He sees His friend standing upright and calls to him joyfully, “Come forth!”

In discussing the people who came back to life, the author is clearly in his element. He confidently references an explanation from Bahrdt, stating these were just cases of coma. These stories should not be labeled “raising from the dead,” but instead “rescues from premature burial.” In Judaea, burials happened three hours after death. How many people who seemed dead might have regained consciousness in their graves, only to suffer horribly! Thus, Jesus, prompted by a feeling inspired by the father's story, saves Jairus's daughter from being buried while in a cataleptic trance. A similar intuition led Him to uncover the bier He encountered at the gate of Nain, revealing signs of life in the widow's son. The same instinct urged Him to visit Lazarus's grave. When the stone is rolled away, He sees His friend standing up and joyfully calls out, “Come here!”

The Jewish love of miracle “caused everything to be ascribed immediately to the Deity, and secondary causes to be overlooked; consequently no thought was unfortunately given to the question of how to prevent these horrible cases of premature burial from taking place!” But why does it not appear strange to Paulus that Jesus did not enlighten His countrymen as to the criminal character of over-hasty burial, instead of allowing even his closest followers to believe in miracle? Here the hypothesis condemns itself, although it has a foundation of fact, in so far as cases of premature burial are abnormally frequent in the East.

The Jewish love of miracles “led people to directly link everything to God, overlooking other factors; as a result, sadly, no one thought about how to prevent these awful cases of premature burial from occurring!” But why doesn’t Paulus find it strange that Jesus didn’t clarify to His people the criminal aspect of hasty burials, instead of letting even His closest followers believe in miracles? Here, the hypothesis discredits itself, even though it’s based on the fact that cases of premature burial are unusually common in the East.

[pg 054]

The resurrection of Jesus must be brought under the same category if we are to hold fast to the facts that the disciples saw Him in His natural body with the print of the nails in His hands, and that He took food in their presence. Death from crucifixion was in fact due to a condition of rigor, which extended gradually inwards. It was the slowest of all deaths. Josephus mentions in his Contra Apionem that it was granted to him as a favour by Titus, at Tekoa, that he might have three crucified men whom he knew taken down from the cross. Two of them died, but one recovered. Jesus, however, “died” surprisingly quickly. The loud cry which he uttered immediately before His head sank shows that His strength was far from being exhausted, and that what supervened was only a death-like trance. In such trances the process of dying continues until corruption sets in. “This alone proves that the process is complete and that death has actually taken place.”

The resurrection of Jesus needs to be viewed in the same light if we are to accept the facts that the disciples saw Him in His physical body with the marks of the nails in His hands, and that He ate food in front of them. Death by crucifixion was actually caused by a condition of rigor that gradually moved inwards. It was the slowest of all deaths. Josephus mentions in his Against Apion that Titus allowed him to take down three crucified men he knew from the cross as a favor at Tekoa. Two of them died, but one recovered. However, Jesus “passed away” surprisingly quickly. The loud cry He gave just before His head dropped shows that His strength was far from exhausted, and that what followed was merely a death-like trance. In such trances, the dying process continues until decay begins. “This alone shows that the process is complete and that death has actually occurred.”

In the case of Jesus, as in that of others, the vital spark would have been gradually extinguished, had not Providence mysteriously effected on behalf of its favourite that which in the case of others was sometimes effected in more obvious ways by human skill and care. The lance-thrust, which we are to think of rather as a mere surface wound, served the purpose of a phlebotomy. The cool grave and the aromatic unguents continued the process of resuscitation, until finally the storm and the earthquake aroused Jesus to full consciousness. Fortunately the earthquake also had the effect of rolling away the stone from the mouth of the grave. The Lord stripped off the grave-clothes and put on a gardener's dress which He managed to procure. That was what made Mary, as we are told in John xx. 15, take Him for the gardener. Through the women, He sends a message to His disciples bidding them meet Him in Galilee, and Himself sets out to go thither. At Emmaus, as the dusk was falling, He met two of His followers, who at first failed to recognise Him because His countenance was so disfigured by His sufferings. But His manner of giving thanks at the breaking of bread, and the nail-prints in His uplifted hands, revealed to them who He was. From them He learns where His disciples are, returns to Jerusalem, and appears unexpectedly among them. This is the explanation of the apparent contradiction between the message pointing to Galilee and the appearances in Jerusalem. Thomas was not present at this first appearance, and at a later interview was suffered to put his hand into the marks of the wounds. It is a misunderstanding to see a reproach in the words which Jesus addresses to him. What, then, is the meaning of “Blessed are they that have not seen and have believed”? It is a benediction upon Thomas for what he has done in the interests of later generations. “Now,” Jesus says, “thou, Thomas, art convinced because thou hast so unmistakably seen Me. It is [pg 055] well for those who now or in the future shall not see Me; for after this they can feel a firm conviction, because thou hast convinced thyself so completely that to thee, whose hands have touched Me, no possible doubt can remain of My corporeal reanimation.” Had it not been for Thomas's peculiar mental constitution we should not have known whether what was seen was a phantom or a real appearance of the reanimated Jesus.

In Jesus’ case, like with others, the vital spark would have slowly faded away if Providence hadn’t mysteriously intervened for its favorite, doing what was sometimes accomplished by human skill and care. The lance wound, which we should think of more as a surface injury, functioned like a bloodletting. The cool tomb and the aromatic ointments continued the process of reviving Him, until finally, the storm and the earthquake brought Jesus back to full awareness. Fortunately, the earthquake also rolled the stone away from the entrance of the tomb. The Lord took off the burial cloths and changed into a gardener's outfit that He found. That’s why Mary, as mentioned in John xx. 15, mistook Him for the gardener. Through the women, He sent a message to His disciples telling them to meet Him in Galilee, and He set out to go there. At Emmaus, as night was falling, He encountered two of His followers, who initially didn’t recognize Him because His face was so marred from His sufferings. However, His way of giving thanks at the breaking of bread, along with the nail marks in His raised hands, revealed His identity to them. From these two, He learned where His disciples were, returned to Jerusalem, and appeared unexpectedly among them. This clarifies the apparent contradiction between the message directing them to Galilee and His appearances in Jerusalem. Thomas wasn’t there for this first appearance, and during a later meeting, he was allowed to place his hand into the marks of the wounds. It’s a misunderstanding to see any reproach in the words Jesus spoke to him. So, what does "Blessed are those who have not seen and yet have believed." mean? It’s a blessing for Thomas because of his role for future generations. “Right now,” Jesus says, "You, Thomas, believe because you have seen Me clearly. It is good for those who won't see Me now or in the future; because after this, they can have strong faith, thanks to your absolute certainty that you, who have touched Me, can have no doubts about My physical resurrection." If it weren’t for Thomas’s unique mental makeup, we wouldn’t know whether what was seen was a ghost or a genuine appearance of the resurrected Jesus.

In this way Jesus lived with them for forty days, spending part of that time with them in Galilee. In consequence of the ill-treatment which He had undergone, He was not capable of continuous exertion. He lived quietly and gathered strength for the brief moments in which He appeared among His own followers and taught them. When He felt his end drawing near He returned to Jerusalem. On the Mount of Olives, in the early sunlight, He assembled His followers for the last time. He lifted up His hands to bless them, and with hands still raised in benediction He moved away from them. A cloud interposes itself between them and Him, so that their eyes cannot follow Him. As he disappeared there stood before them, clothed in white, the two dignified figures whom the three disciples who were present at the transfiguration had taken for Moses and Elias, but who were really among the secret adherents of Jesus in Jerusalem. These men exhorted them not to stand waiting there but to be up and doing.

In this way, Jesus lived with them for forty days, spending part of that time in Galilee. Because of the mistreatment He had suffered, He wasn't able to exert Himself continuously. He lived quietly and gained strength for the brief moments He spent with His followers, teaching them. When He sensed that His end was near, He returned to Jerusalem. On the Mount of Olives, in the early morning light, He gathered His followers for the last time. He raised His hands to bless them, and with His hands still lifted in blessing, He moved away from them. A cloud came between them and Him, preventing them from seeing Him. As He vanished, two dignified figures appeared before them, dressed in white. These were the same men whom the three disciples at the transfiguration had thought were Moses and Elijah, but they were actually among Jesus' secret supporters in Jerusalem. They urged them not to just stand there but to get moving.

Where Jesus really died they never knew, and so they came to describe His departure as an ascension.

Where Jesus truly died, they never found out, so they began to describe His departure as an ascension.

This Life of Jesus is not written without feeling. At times, in moments of exaltation, the writer even dashes into verse. If only the lack of all natural aesthetic feeling did not ruin everything! Paulus constantly falls into a style that sets the teeth on edge. The episode of the death of the Baptist is headed “Court-and-Priest intrigues enhance themselves to a judicial murder.” Much is spoiled by a kind of banality. Instead of “disciples,” he always says “pupils,” instead of “faith,” “sincerity of conviction.” The appeal which the father of the lunatic boy addresses to Jesus, “Lord, I believe, help thou my unbelief,” runs “I am sincerely convinced; help me, even if there is anything lacking in the sincerity of my conviction.”

This Life of Jesus is not written without emotion. At times, during moments of inspiration, the writer even jumps into verse. If only the total lack of natural aesthetic sense didn’t ruin everything! Paulus often slips into a style that’s grating. The section about the death of the Baptist is titled “Court and priest conspiracies result in a wrongful execution.” A lot is ruined by a sort of dullness. Instead of "followers," he always says "students," instead of "belief," he uses “genuine belief.” The plea from the father of the troubled boy to Jesus, "Lord, I believe; please help me with my doubts." turns into "I truly believe; help me, even if there’s something lacking in the sincerity of my belief."

The beautiful saying in the story of Martha and Mary, “One thing is needful,” is interpreted as meaning that a single course will be sufficient for the meal.24 The scene in the home at Bethany rejoices in the heading, “Geniality of Jesus among sympathetic friends in a hospitable family circle at Bethany. A Messiah with no stiff solemnity about Him.” The following is the explanation [pg 056] which Paulus discovers for the saying about the tribute-money: “So long as you need the Romans to maintain some sort of order among you,” says Jesus, “you must provide the means thereto. If you were fit to be independent you would not need to serve any one but God.”

The lovely saying in the story of Martha and Mary, “One thing is necessary,” is understood to mean that just one dish will be enough for the meal.24 The scene at the home in Bethany is beautifully titled, “The warmth of Jesus among caring friends in a welcoming family environment at Bethany. A Messiah without stiff solemnity.” The following is the explanation [pg 056] that Paulus finds for the saying about the tribute money: "As long as you need the Romans to maintain some sort of order among you," Jesus says, "You need to provide the means for that. If you were ready to be independent, you wouldn't have to answer to anyone except God."

Among the historical problems, Paulus is especially interested in the idea of the Messiahship, and in the motives of the betrayal. His sixty-five pages on the history of the conception of the Messiah are a real contribution to the subject. The Messianic idea, he explains, goes back to the Davidic kingdom; the prophets raised it to a higher religious plane; in the times of the Maccabees the ideal of the kingly Messiah perished and its place was taken by that of the super-earthly deliverer. The only mistake which Paulus makes is in supposing that the post-Maccabean period went back to the political ideal of the Davidic king. On the other hand, he rightly interprets the death of Jesus as the deed by which He thought to win the Messiahship proper to the Son of Man.

Among the historical issues, Paulus is particularly focused on the concept of the Messiah and the reasons behind the betrayal. His sixty-five-page discussion on the history of the Messiah's conception is a significant contribution to the topic. He explains that the idea of the Messiah originates from the Davidic kingdom; the prophets elevated it to a higher spiritual level. During the time of the Maccabees, the ideal of a kingly Messiah faded away and was replaced by the notion of a transcendent deliverer. The only mistake Paulus makes is believing that the post-Maccabean period reverted to the political ideal of the Davidic king. However, he correctly interprets Jesus's death as the act through which He intended to secure the Messiahship meant for the Son of Man.

With reference to the question of the High Priest at the trial, he remarks that it does not refer to the metaphysical Divine Sonship, but to the Messiahship in the ancient Jewish sense, and accordingly Jesus answers by pointing to the coming of the Son of Man.

With regard to the question posed by the High Priest at the trial, he notes that it doesn’t pertain to the metaphysical Divine Sonship, but rather to the Messiahship in the traditional Jewish sense. In response, Jesus indicates the arrival of the Son of Man.

The importance of eschatology in the preaching of Jesus is clearly recognised, but Paulus proceeds to nullify this recognition by making the risen Lord cut short all the questions of the disciples in regard to this subject with the admonition “that in whatever way all this should come about, and whether soon or late, their business was to see that they had done their own part.”

The significance of eschatology in Jesus' preaching is widely acknowledged, but Paulus undermines this recognition by having the risen Lord dismiss all the disciples' questions on the topic with the reminder "no matter how this all unfolds, whether it’s soon or later, it was their responsibility to make sure they had done their part."

How did Judas come to play the traitor? He believed in the Messiahship of Jesus and wanted to force Him to declare Himself. To bring about His arrest seemed to Judas the best means of rousing the people to take His side openly. But the course of events was too rapid for him. Owing to the Feast the news of the arrest spread but slowly. In the night “when people were sleeping off the effects of the Passover supper,” Jesus was condemned; in the morning, before they were well awake, He was hurried away to be crucified. Then Judas was overcome with despair, and went and hanged himself. “Judas stands before us in the history of the Passion as a warning example of those who allow their cleverness to degenerate into cunning, and persuade themselves that it is permissible to do evil that good may come—to seek good objects, which they really value, by intrigue and chicanery. And the underlying cause of their errors is that they have failed to overcome their passionate desire for self-advancement.”

How did Judas become the traitor? He believed in Jesus as the Messiah and wanted to force Him to reveal Himself. Judas thought that getting Jesus arrested would be the best way to get the people to support Him openly. But things moved too fast for him. Because of the Feast, news of the arrest spread slowly. At night, "when people were recovering from the effects of the Passover dinner," Jesus was condemned; in the morning, before people had fully woken up, He was rushed away to be crucified. Then Judas was overwhelmed with despair and went and hanged himself. “Judas is a cautionary figure in the story of the Passion, showing us the danger of letting our intelligence turn into deceit. He leads himself to believe that it's okay to do something wrong if it leads to a good outcome—pursuing what they truly care about through manipulation and trickery. The root of their mistakes is their inability to control their intense desire for personal gain.”

Such was the consistently rationalistic Life of Jesus, which evoked so much opposition at the time of its appearance, and [pg 057] seven years later received its death-blow at the hands of Strauss. The method is doomed to failure because the author only saves his own sincerity at the expense of that of his characters. He makes the disciples of Jesus see miracles where they could not possibly have seen them; and makes Jesus Himself allow miracles to be imagined where He must necessarily have protested against such a delusion. His exegesis, too, is sometimes violent. But in this, who has the right to judge him? If the theologians dragged him before the Lord, He would command, as of old, “Let him that is without sin among you cast the first stone at him,” and Paulus would go forth unharmed.

The life of Jesus was consistently rationalistic, which faced a lot of opposition when it first emerged, and seven years later, it was ultimately undermined by Strauss. This approach is destined to fail because the author preserves his own sincerity at the cost of that of his characters. He makes Jesus' disciples witness miracles that couldn't possibly have happened, and he makes Jesus himself let people believe in miracles that he would have had to challenge. His interpretations can also be pretty extreme. But really, who has the right to judge him? If theologians brought him before God, He would once again say, “Let him that is without sin among you cast the first stone at him,” and Paulus would walk away unscathed.

Moreover, a number of his explanations are right in principle. The feeding of the multitudes and the walking on the sea must be explained somehow or other as misunderstandings of something that actually happened. And how many of Paulus' ideas are still going about in all sorts of disguises, and crop up again and again in commentaries and Lives of Jesus, especially in those of the “anti-rationalists”! Nowadays it belongs to the complete duty of the well-trained theologian to renounce the rationalists and all their works; and yet how poor our time is in comparison with theirs—how poor in strong men capable of loyalty to an ideal, how poor, so far as theology is concerned, in simple commonplace sincerity!

Moreover, several of his explanations are fundamentally correct. The feeding of the multitudes and walking on water need to be understood as some kind of misunderstandings of actual events. Many of Paulus' ideas still circulate in various forms and frequently appear in commentaries and biographies of Jesus, especially in those by the "anti-rationalists"! Today, it is considered a complete duty for a well-trained theologian to reject rationalists and all their works; yet how lacking our time is compared to theirs—how lacking in strong individuals who are dedicated to an ideal, and how lacking, in terms of theology, in straightforward, sincere honesty!

[pg 058]

VI. The Final Stage of Rationalism—Hase and Schleiermacher

Karl August Hase. Das Leben Jesu zunächst für akademische Studien. (The Life of Jesus, primarily for the use of students.) 1829. 205 pp. This work contains a bibliography of the earliest literature of the subject. 5th ed., 1865.

Karl August Hase. The Life of Jesus, primarily for academic studies. 1829. 205 pages. This book features a bibliography of the earliest literature on the subject. 5th edition, 1865.

Friedrich Ernst Daniel Schleiermacher. Das Leben Jesu. 1864. Edited by Rütenik. The edition is based upon a student's note-book of a course of lectures delivered in 1832.

Friedrich Ernst Daniel Schleiermacher. The Life of Jesus, 1864. Edited by Rütenik. This edition is based on a student's notes from a lecture series held in 1832.

David Friedrich Strauss. Der Christus des Glaubens und der Jesus der Geschichte. Eine Kritik des Schleiermacher'schen Lebens Jesu. (The Christ of Faith and the Jesus of History. A criticism of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus.) 1865.

David Friedrich Strauss. The Christ of Faith and the Jesus of History: A critique of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus. (The Christ of Faith and the Jesus of History: A critique of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus.) 1865.

In their treatment of the life of Jesus, Hase and Schleiermacher are in one respect still wholly dominated by rationalism. They still cling to the rationalistic explanation of miracle; although they have no longer the same ingenuous confidence in it as their predecessors, and although at the decisive cases they are content to leave a question-mark instead of offering a solution. They might, in fact, be described as the sceptics of rationalism. In another respect, however, they aim at something beyond the range of rationalism, inasmuch as they endeavour to grasp the inner connexion of the events of Jesus' ministry, which in Paulus had entirely fallen out of sight. Their Lives of Jesus are transitional, in the good sense of the word as well as in the bad. In respect of progress, Hase shows himself the greater of the two.

In their approach to the life of Jesus, Hase and Schleiermacher are still largely influenced by rationalism. They hold onto the rational explanation of miracles, though they no longer have the same naive confidence in it as their predecessors did, and in crucial cases, they prefer to leave questions unanswered instead of providing solutions. They could be seen as skeptics of rationalism. However, in another way, they strive for something beyond rationalism, as they try to understand the deeper connections within the events of Jesus' ministry, which Paulus had completely overlooked. Their Lives of Jesus serve as a transition, both in a positive way and a negative way. In terms of progress, Hase proves to be the stronger of the two.

Scarcely thirteen years have elapsed since the death of the great Jena professor, his Excellency von Hase, and already we think of him as a man of the past. Theology has voted to inscribe his name upon its records in letters of gold—and has passed on to the order of the day. He was no pioneer like Baur, and he does not meet the present age on the footing of a contemporary, offering it problems raised by him and still unsolved. Even his “Church History,” with its twelve editions, has already had its day, although it is still the most brilliantly written work in this department, and conceals beneath its elegance of form a massive erudition. He [pg 059] was more than a theologian; he was one of the finest monuments of German culture, the living embodiment of a period which for us lies under the sunset glow of the past, in the land of “once upon a time.”

Scarcely thirteen years have passed since the death of the great Jena professor, his Excellency von Hase, and already we think of him as a figure from the past. Theology has decided to honor his name in its records in letters of gold—and has moved on to the next agenda. He was not a trailblazer like Baur, and he doesn’t resonate with the current era as a contemporary, presenting it with the unsolved issues he raised. Even his “History of the Church,” which has been published in twelve editions, has already had its time, even though it remains the most eloquently written work in this field, hiding beneath its polished style a wealth of knowledge. He [pg 059] was more than just a theologian; he was one of the finest examples of German culture, the living representation of an era that now seems like a distant memory, in the land of “Once upon a time.”

His path in life was unembarrassed; he knew toil, but not disappointment. Born in 1800, he finished his studies at Tübingen, where he qualified as a Privat-Docent in 1823. In 1824-1825 he spent eleven months in the fortress of Hohenasperg, where he was confined for taking the part of the Burschenschaften,25 and had leisure for meditation and literary plans. In 1830 he went to Jena, where, with a yearly visit to Italy to lay in a store of sunshine and renewed strength, he worked until 1890.

His life path was clear; he knew hard work but not disappointment. Born in 1800, he completed his studies at Tübingen, where he became a Privat-Docent in 1823. From 1824 to 1825, he spent eleven months in the fortress of Hohenasperg, where he was locked up for supporting the Burschenschaften, and had time for reflection and literary projects. In 1830, he moved to Jena, where he worked until 1890, making yearly trips to Italy to gather some sunshine and recharge.

Not without a certain reverence does one take this little text-book of 205 pages into one's hands. This is the first attempt by a fully equipped scholar to reconstruct the life of Jesus on a purely historical basis. There is more creative power in it than in almost any of his later works. It manifests already the brilliant qualities of style for which he was distinguished—clearness, terseness, elegance. What a contrast with that of Bahrdt, Venturini, or Paulus!

Not without a certain respect does one take this little textbook of 205 pages into one's hands. This is the first attempt by a fully equipped scholar to reconstruct the life of Jesus based solely on history. There is more creativity in it than in almost any of his later works. It already shows the brilliant qualities of style for which he became known—clarity, conciseness, elegance. What a contrast to the works of Bahrdt, Venturini, or Paulus!

And yet the keynote of the work is rationalistic, since Hase has recourse to the rationalistic explanation of miracles wherever that appears possible. He seeks to make the circumstances of the baptism intelligible by supposing the appearance of a meteor. In the story of the transfiguration, the fact which is to be retained is that Jesus, in the company of two unknown persons, appeared to the disciples in unaccustomed splendour. Their identification of His companions as Moses and Elias is a conclusion which is not confirmed by Jesus, and owing to the position of the eyewitnesses, is not sufficiently guaranteed by their testimony. The abrupt breaking off of the interview by the Master, and the injunction of silence, point to some secret circumstance in His history. By this hint Hase seems to leave room for the “secret society” of Bahrdt and Venturini.

And yet the main point of the work is rationalistic, as Hase resorts to rational explanations for miracles whenever possible. He tries to make sense of the circumstances surrounding the baptism by suggesting that a meteor appeared. In the account of the transfiguration, the key takeaway is that Jesus appeared to the disciples in a remarkable way, accompanied by two unknown figures. Their assumption that these companions were Moses and Elijah is not confirmed by Jesus, and considering the perspective of the witnesses, it isn't strongly supported by their testimony. The sudden end to the conversation by Jesus and his command for silence hint at some hidden aspect of his history. This indication seems to allow for the existence of the "secret group" mentioned by Bahrdt and Venturini.

He makes no difficulty about the explanation of the story of the stater. It is only intended to show “how the Messiah avoided offence in submitting Himself to the financial burdens of the community.” In regard to the stilling of the storm, it seems uncertain whether Jesus through His knowledge of nature was enabled to predict the end of the storm or whether He brought it about by the possession of power over nature. The “sceptic of rationalism” thus leaves open the possibility of miracle. He proceeds somewhat similarly in explaining the raisings from the dead. They can be made intelligible by supposing that they were cases of coma, but it is also possible to look upon them as [pg 060] supernatural. For the two great Johannine miracles, the change of the water into wine and the increase of the loaves, no naturalistic explanation can be admitted. But how unsuccessful is his attempt to make the increase of the bread intelligible! “Why should not the bread have been increased?” he asks. “If nature every year in the period between seed-time and harvest performs a similar miracle, nature might also, by unknown laws, bring it about in a moment.” Here crops up the dangerous anti-rationalistic intellectual supernaturalism which sometimes brings Hase and Schleiermacher very close to the frontiers of the territory occupied by the disingenuous reactionaries.

He has no trouble explaining the story of the state. It’s only meant to show “how the Messiah steered clear of conflict by addressing the community's financial obligations.” Regarding the calming of the storm, it's unclear whether Jesus, due to His understanding of nature, could predict the end of the storm or if He caused it with His power over nature. The "skeptic of rationalism" thus leaves room for the possibility of a miracle. He explains the instances of raising the dead in a somewhat similar way. They could be understood as cases of coma, but they can also be viewed as [pg 060] supernatural. For the two major miracles in John, the turning of water into wine and the multiplication of the loaves, no natural explanation can be accepted. Yet, his attempt to explain the bread multiplication falls flat. "Why wasn't the bread multiplied?" he asks. "If nature works a similar miracle every year from planting to harvest, then it could also happen instantly through unknown laws." Here arises the troubling anti-rationalistic intellectual supernaturalism that sometimes brings Hase and Schleiermacher dangerously close to the territory of the insincere reactionaries.

The crucial point is the explanation of the resurrection of Jesus. A stringent proof that death had actually taken place cannot, according to Hase, be given, since there is no evidence that corruption had set in, and that is the only infallible sign of death. It is possible, therefore, that the resurrection was only a return to consciousness after a trance. But the direct impression made by the sources points rather to a supernatural event. Either view is compatible with the Christian faith. “Both the historically possible views—either that the Creator gave new life to a body which was really dead, or that the latent life reawakened in a body which was only seemingly dead—recognise in the resurrection a manifest proof of the care of Providence for the cause of Jesus, and are therefore both to be recognised as Christian, whereas a third view—that Jesus gave Himself up to his enemies in order to defeat them by the bold stroke of a seeming death and a skilfully prepared resurrection—is as contrary to historical criticism as to Christian faith.”

The key point is the explanation of Jesus' resurrection. According to Hase, we can't provide strict proof that death actually occurred, since there's no evidence that decomposition had started, and that’s the only undeniable sign of death. Therefore, it’s possible that the resurrection was simply a return to awareness after a trance. However, the immediate impression from the sources suggests a supernatural event. Both perspectives fit within the Christian faith. Both historically plausible perspectives—either that the Creator gave new life to a body that was genuinely dead, or that the dormant life was revived in a body that merely seemed dead—see the resurrection as clear evidence of God's support for Jesus' mission, and are therefore both considered Christian. Meanwhile, a third perspective—that Jesus surrendered to his enemies to overcome them through a deceptive death and a cleverly orchestrated resurrection—faces equal challenges from historical examination and from Christian faith.

Hase, however, quietly lightens the difficulty of the miracle question in a way which must not be overlooked. For the rationalists all miracles stood on the same footing, and all must equally be abolished by a naturalistic explanation. If we study Hase carefully, we find that he accepts only the Johannine miracles as authentic, whereas those of the Synoptists may be regarded as resting upon a misunderstanding on the part of the authors, because they are not reported at first hand, but from tradition. Thus the discrimination of the two lines of Gospel tradition comes to the aid of the anti-rationalists, and enables them to get rid of some of the greatest difficulties. Half playfully, it might almost be said, they sketch out the ideas of Strauss, without ever suspecting what desperate earnest the game will become, if the authenticity of the Fourth Gospel has to be given up.

Hase, however, quietly simplifies the challenge posed by the miracle question in a way that shouldn’t be ignored. For rationalists, all miracles were treated the same, and all needed to be explained away through a naturalistic lens. If we examine Hase closely, we find that he only considers the miracles in John’s Gospel as authentic, while those in the Synoptic Gospels might be seen as based on a misunderstanding by the authors, since they are not reported from direct witness but from tradition. This distinction between the two strands of Gospel tradition helps those against rationalism, allowing them to bypass some of the biggest challenges. Almost in a playful manner, they outline Strauss's ideas without realizing how serious the situation will become if the authenticity of the Fourth Gospel has to be abandoned.

Hase surrenders the birth-story and the “legends of the Childhood”—the expression is his own—almost without striking a blow. The same fate befalls all the incidents in which angels figure, and the miracles at the time of the death of Jesus. He [pg 061] describes these as “mythical touches.” The ascension is merely “a mythical version of His departure to the Father.”

Hase gives up the birth story and the “Childhood Legends”—a term he coined—almost without a fight. The same thing happens to all the events involving angels and the miracles surrounding Jesus' death. He [pg 061] refers to these as "mythical vibes." The ascension is just "a legendary account of His departure to the Father."

Hase's conception even of the non-miraculous portion of the history of Jesus is not free from rationalistic traits. He indulges in the following speculations with regard to the celibacy of the Lord. “If the true grounds of the celibacy of Jesus do not lie hidden in the special circumstances of His youth, the conjecture may be permitted that He from whose religion was to go forth the ideal view of marriage, so foreign to the ideas of antiquity, found in His own time no heart worthy to enter into this covenant with Him.” It is on rationalistic lines also that Hase explains the betrayal by Judas. “A purely intellectual, worldly, and unscrupulous character, he desired to compel the hesitating Messiah to found His Kingdom upon popular violence.... It is possible that Judas in his terrible blindness took that last word addressed to him by Jesus, ‘What thou doest, do quickly,’ as giving consent to his plan.”

Hase's understanding of even the non-miraculous parts of Jesus's story isn't free from rationalistic elements. He speculates about the Lord's celibacy, saying, "If the true reasons for Jesus's celibacy aren’t hidden in the specific circumstances of His youth, it makes sense to consider that He, whose teachings aimed to present an ideal view of marriage—so different from the ancient perspective—found no one in His own time who was worthy to enter into that covenant with Him." Hase also takes a rationalistic approach to explain Judas's betrayal. “Judas, being entirely intellectual, worldly, and unprincipled, sought to urge the reluctant Messiah into creating His Kingdom through popular violence.... It’s possible that, in his deep blindness, Judas understood Jesus's last words to him, ‘What thou doest, do quickly,’ as a green light for his plan.”

But Hase again rises superior to this rationalistic conception of the history when he refuses to explain away the Jewish elements in the plan and preaching of Jesus as due to mere accommodation, and maintains the view that the Lord really, to a certain extent, shared this Jewish system of ideas. According to Hase there are two periods in the Messianic activity of Jesus. In the first He accepted almost without reservation the popular ideas regarding the Messianic age. In consequence, however, of His experience of the practical results of these ideas, He was led to abandon this error, and in the second period He developed His own distinctive views. Here we meet for the first time the idea of two different periods in the life of Jesus, which, especially through the influence of Holtzmann and Keim, became the prevailing view, and down to Johannes Weiss, determined the plan of all Lives of Jesus. Hase created the modern historico-psychological picture of Jesus. The introduction of this more penetrating psychology would alone suffice to place him in advance of the rationalists.

But Hase rises above this rationalist view of history when he refuses to dismiss the Jewish elements in Jesus' plan and teachings as merely accommodating, and instead argues that Jesus genuinely, to some extent, embraced this Jewish system of ideas. According to Hase, there are two phases in Jesus' Messianic activity. In the first phase, He accepted almost without question the popular beliefs about the Messianic age. However, due to His experience with the practical outcomes of these beliefs, He eventually realized this was a mistake, and in the second phase, He developed His own distinct views. This is the first time we encounter the idea of two different phases in Jesus' life, which, particularly influenced by Holtzmann and Keim, became the dominant perspective and shaped the approach of all Lives of Jesus up to Johannes Weiss. Hase created the modern historico-psychological portrayal of Jesus. The introduction of this deeper psychological insight alone is enough to set him apart from the rationalists.

Another interesting point is the thorough way in which he traces out the historical and literary consequences of this idea of development. The apostles, he thinks, did not understand this progress of thought on the part of Jesus, and did not distinguish between the sayings of the first and second periods. They remained wedded to the eschatological view. After the death of Jesus this view prevailed so strongly in the primitive community of disciples that they interpolated their expectations into the last discourses of Jesus. According to Hase, the apocalyptic discourse in Matt. xxiv. was originally only a prediction of the judgment upon and destruction of Jerusalem, but this was obscured later by the influx of the eschatological views of the apostolic community. Only John remained free from this error. Therefore the non-eschatological [pg 062] Fourth Gospel preserves in their pure form the ideas of Jesus in His second period.

Another interesting point is the detailed way he outlines the historical and literary impacts of this idea of development. He believes that the apostles didn’t grasp this evolution of thought from Jesus and failed to differentiate between his sayings from the first and second periods. They remained attached to the eschatological view. After Jesus died, this perspective was so dominant in the early community of disciples that they integrated their own expectations into Jesus's final teachings. According to Hase, the apocalyptic discourse in Matt. xxiv. was initially just a prediction of the judgment and destruction of Jerusalem, but this became muddled later due to the influx of eschatological beliefs from the apostolic community. Only John managed to avoid this misunderstanding. As a result, the non-eschatological [pg 062] Fourth Gospel retains the ideas of Jesus in their pure form from his second period.

Hase rightly observes that the Messiahship of Jesus plays next to no part in His preaching, at any rate at first, and that, before the incident at Caesarea Philippi, it was only in moments of enthusiastic admiration, rather than with settled conviction, that even the disciples looked on Him as the Messiah. This indication of the central importance of the declaration of the Messiahship at Caesarea Philippi is another sign-post pointing out the direction which the future study of the life of Jesus was to follow.

Hase correctly notes that Jesus’ role as the Messiah doesn’t feature much in His preaching, at least initially, and that, before the event at Caesarea Philippi, it was only during moments of great admiration that even the disciples considered Him to be the Messiah, rather than with firm belief. This emphasis on the key importance of declaring the Messiahship at Caesarea Philippi is another sign marking the path that future studies of Jesus' life would take.


Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus introduces us to quite a different order of transitional ideas. Its value lies in the sphere of dogmatics, not of history. Nowhere, indeed, is it so clear that the great dialectician had not really a historical mind than precisely in his treatment of the history of Jesus.

Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus presents us with a different set of transitional ideas. Its significance is in the realm of dogmatics, not history. Nowhere is it more evident that the great dialectician did not truly possess a historical mindset than in his approach to the history of Jesus.

From the first it was no favourable star which presided over this undertaking. It is true that in 1819 Schleiermacher was the first theologian who had ever lectured upon this subject. But his Life of Jesus did not appear until 1864. Its publication had been so long delayed, partly because it had to be reconstructed from students' note-books, partly because immediately after Schleiermacher, in 1832, had delivered the course for the last time, it was rendered obsolete by the work of Strauss. For the questions raised by the latter's Life of Jesus, published in 1835, Schleiermacher had no answer, and for the wounds which it made, no healing. When, in 1864, Schleiermacher's work was brought forth to view like an embalmed corse, Strauss accorded to the dead work of the great theologian a dignified and striking funeral oration.

From the beginning, there was no good fortune associated with this endeavor. It's true that in 1819, Schleiermacher was the first theologian to lecture on this topic. However, his Life of Jesus wasn’t published until 1864. Its release was delayed for so long partly because it had to be pieced together from students' notes, and partly because right after Schleiermacher delivered the course for the last time in 1832, it became outdated due to Strauss's work. Schleiermacher had no answers to the questions raised by Strauss’s Life of Jesus, published in 1835, and he offered no healing for the wounds it caused. When Schleiermacher's work was finally revealed in 1864, like a preserved corpse, Strauss delivered a dignified and powerful eulogy for the deceased work of the great theologian.

Schleiermacher is not in search of the historical Jesus, but of the Jesus Christ of his own system of theology; that is to say, of the historic figure which seems to him appropriate to the self-consciousness of the Redeemer as he represents it. For him the empirical has simply no existence. A natural psychology is scarcely attempted. He comes to the facts with a ready-made dialectic apparatus and sets his puppets in lively action. Schleiermacher's dialectic is not a dialectic which generates reality, like that of Hegel, of which Strauss availed himself, but merely a dialectic of exposition. In this literary dialectic he is the greatest master that ever lived.

Schleiermacher isn't looking for the historical Jesus, but for the Jesus Christ that fits his own theological system; in other words, the historical figure that he believes reflects the self-awareness of the Redeemer as he interprets it. To him, the empirical just doesn’t exist. There's barely any attempt at natural psychology. He approaches the facts with a pre-existing dialectical framework and brings his ideas to life. Schleiermacher's dialectic isn’t one that creates reality, like Hegel's, which Strauss used, but is simply a dialectic of explanation. In this literary dialectic, he is the greatest master to have ever existed.

The limitations of the historical Jesus both in an upward and downward direction are those only which apply equally to the Jesus of dogma. The uniqueness of His Divine self-consciousness is not to be tampered with. It is equally necessary to avoid Ebionism which does away with the Divine in Him, and Docetism [pg 063] which destroys His humanity. Schleiermacher loves to make his hearers shudder by pointing out to them that the least false step entails precipitation into one or other of these abysses; or at least would entail it for any one who was not under the guidance of his infallible dialectic.

The limits of the historical Jesus, both upwards and downwards, are just as applicable to the Jesus of dogma. His unique Divine self-awareness should not be compromised. It's also important to steer clear of Ebionism, which denies the Divine aspect in Him, and Docetism [pg 063] which undermines His humanity. Schleiermacher often makes his audience uncomfortable by reminding them that even the smallest misstep can lead to falling into one of these extremes; or at least would lead to that for anyone not following his infallible reasoning.

In the course of this dialectic treatment, all the historical questions involved in the life of Jesus come into view one after another, but none of them is posed or solved from the point of view of the historian; they are “moments” in his argument.

During this analytical approach, all the historical questions related to the life of Jesus are presented one by one, but none are asked or answered from the historian's perspective; they are "moments" in his argument.

He is like a spider at work. The spider lets itself down from aloft, and after making fast some supporting threads to points below, it runs back to the centre and there keeps spinning away. You look on fascinated, and before you know it, you are entangled in the web. It is difficult even for a reader who is strong in the consciousness of possessing a sounder grasp of the history than Schleiermacher to avoid being caught in the toils of that magical dialectic.

He is like a spider at work. The spider lowers itself down from above, and after securing some supporting threads to points below, it scurries back to the center and keeps spinning. You watch in fascination, and before you realize it, you’re caught in the web. It’s hard for even a reader who is confident in their understanding of history to avoid getting trapped in that enchanting dialectic.

And how loftily superior the dialectician is! Paulus had shown that, in view of the use of the title Son of Man, the Messianic self-consciousness of Jesus must be interpreted in accordance with the passage in Daniel. On this Schleiermacher remarks: “I have already said that it is inherently improbable that such a predilection (sc. for the Book of Daniel) would have been manifested by Christ, because the Book of Daniel does not belong to the prophetic writings properly so-called, but to the third division of the Old Testament literature.”

And how superior the dialectician is! Paulus argued that, considering the use of the title Son of Man, Jesus' awareness of his Messianic identity should be understood in light of the passage in Daniel. In response, Schleiermacher comments: "I've already mentioned that it's pretty unlikely that Christ would have shown such a preference (for the Book of Daniel), because the Book of Daniel doesn’t really fit into the prophetic writings; instead, it belongs to the third section of the Old Testament literature."

In his estimate of the importance to be attached to the story of the baptism, too, he falls behind the historical knowledge of his day. “To lay such great stress upon the baptism,” he says, “leads either to the Gnostic view that it was only there that the λόγος united itself with Jesus, or to the rationalistic view that it was only at the baptism that He became conscious of His vocation.” But what does history care whether a view is gnostic or rationalistic if only it is historical!

In his assessment of the importance of the baptism story, he also falls short of the historical understanding of his time. "Putting so much focus on the baptism," he says, “leads to either the Gnostic view that the λόγος only united with Jesus at that point, or to the rationalistic view that He only became aware of His mission during the baptism.” But what does history matter if a belief is Gnostic or rationalistic, as long as it is historical!

This dialectic, so fatal often to sound historical views, might have been expressly created to deal with the question of miracle. Compared with Schleiermacher's discussions all that has been written since upon this subject is mere honest—or dishonest—bungling. Nothing new has been added to what he says, and no one else has succeeded in saying it with the same amazing subtlety. It is true, also, that no one else has shown the same skill in concealing how much in the way of miracle he ultimately retains and how much he rejects. His solution of the problem is, in fact, not historical, but dialectical, an attempt to transcend the necessity for a rationalistic explanation of miracle which does not really succeed in getting rid of it.

This argument, often detrimental to solid historical perspectives, may have been specifically designed to tackle the question of miracles. In comparison to Schleiermacher's discussions, everything written on this topic since then is just clumsy—whether honestly or dishonestly. Nothing new has been added to his insights, and no one else has managed to express it with the same remarkable nuance. It's also true that no one else has quite matched his ability to hide how much of the miraculous he ultimately accepts and how much he discards. His approach to the problem is not truly historical but dialectical, aiming to go beyond the need for a rational explanation of miracles, which ultimately fails to eliminate that need.

[pg 064]

Schleiermacher arranges the miracles in an ascending scale of probability according to the degree in which they can be seen to depend on the known influence of spirit upon organic matter. The most easily explained are the miracles of healing “because we are not without analogies to show that pathological conditions of a purely functional nature can be removed by mental influence.” But where, on the other hand, the effect produced by Christ lies outside the sphere of human life, the difficulties involved become insoluble. To get rid, in some measure, of these difficulties he makes use of two expedients. In the first place, he admits that in particular cases the rationalistic method may have a certain limited application; in the second place he, like Hase, recognises a difference between the miracle stories themselves, retaining the Johannine miracles, but surrendering, more or less completely, the Synoptic miracles as not resting on evidence of the same certainty and exactness.

Schleiermacher organizes the miracles by how likely they are, based on how much they rely on the known effects of the spirit on physical matter. The easiest ones to explain are the healing miracles, “because we have examples that show how purely functional medical conditions can be treated through mental influence.” However, when it comes to the effects that Christ had that are beyond human experience, the challenges become impossible to solve. To address these challenges to some extent, he uses two strategies. First, he acknowledges that the rational approach may be somewhat applicable in specific cases. Second, like Hase, he recognizes a difference between the miracle accounts themselves; he keeps the miracles from John but mostly discards the Synoptic miracles because they don't have the same level of certainty and precision in evidence.

That he is still largely under the sway of rationalism can be seen in the fact that he admits on an equal footing, as conceptions of the resurrection of Jesus, a return to consciousness from a trance-state, or a supernatural restoration to life, thought of as a resurrection. He goes so far as to say that the decision of this question has very little interest for him. He fully accepts the principle of Paulus that apart from corruption there is no certain indication of death.

That he is still largely influenced by rationalism is evident in the fact that he acknowledges both a return to consciousness from a trance state and a supernatural restoration to life as possible interpretations of the resurrection of Jesus. He even claims that deciding between these views isn’t particularly important to him. He completely embraces Paulus's principle that, aside from decay, there is no definitive proof of death.

“All that we can say on this point,” he concludes, “is that even to those whose business it was to ensure the immediate death of the crucified, in order that the bodies might at once be taken down, Christ appeared to be really dead, and this, moreover, although it was contrary to their expectations, for it was a subject of astonishment. It is no use going any further into the matter, since nothing can be ascertained in regard to it.”

“All we can say about this is,” he concludes, "Even for those whose job was to ensure that the crucified person died quickly so the bodies could be taken down, Christ appeared completely dead. This surprised them, even though it contradicted their expectations. There's no point in discussing it further since nothing more can be concluded about it."

What is certain is that Jesus in His real body lived on for a time among His followers; that the Fourth Gospel requires us to believe. The reports of the resurrection are not based upon “apparitions.” Schleiermacher's own opinion is what really happened was reanimation after apparent death. “If Christ had only eaten to show that He could eat, while He really had no need of nourishment, it would have been a pretence—something docetic. This gives us a clue to all the rest, teaching us to hold firmly to the way in which Christ intends Himself to be represented, and to put down all that is miraculous in the accounts of the appearances to the prepossessions of the disciples.”

What’s clear is that Jesus, in His actual body, spent some time living among His followers; that’s what the Fourth Gospel tells us to believe. The accounts of the resurrection aren’t based on "ghosts." Schleiermacher believed that what really happened was reanimation after appearing dead. “If Christ had only eaten to prove that He could eat, even though He didn’t actually need food, it would have been an act of pretense—something that feels artificial. This helps us understand everything else, teaching us to confidently accept how Christ wants to be portrayed and to disregard all the miraculous aspects in the stories of His appearances as the biases of the disciples.”

When He revealed himself to Mary Magdalene He had no certainty that He would frequently see her again. “He was conscious that His present condition was that of genuine human life, but He had no confidence in its continuance.” He bade His [pg 065] disciples meet Him in Galilee because He could there enjoy greater privacy and freedom from observation in His intercourse with them. The difference between the present and the past was only that He no longer showed Himself to the world. “It was possible that a movement in favour of an earthly Messianic Kingdom might break out, and we need only take this possibility into account in order to explain completely why Jesus remained in such close retirement.” “It was the premonition of the approaching end of this second life which led Him to return from Galilee to Jerusalem.”

When He revealed Himself to Mary Magdalene, He wasn't sure if He would see her again. "He knew that his current situation was real human life, but he had no guarantee it would continue." He told His [pg 065] disciples to meet Him in Galilee because there He could have more privacy and freedom from being watched while interacting with them. The main difference between now and before was that He no longer presented Himself to the world. “There was a chance that a movement supporting an earthly Messianic Kingdom could arise, and just considering this possibility helps us understand why Jesus chose to remain so hidden.” "The sense of an approaching end to this second life is what drove Him to return from Galilee to Jerusalem."

Of the ascension he says: “Here, therefore, something happened, but what was seen was incomplete, and has been conjecturally supplemented.” The underlying rationalistic explanation shows through!

Of the ascension he says: "Something happened here, but what was observed was partial and has been filled in with speculation." The basic rational explanation is evident!

But if the condition in which Jesus lived on after His crucifixion was “a condition of reanimation,” by what right does Schleiermacher constantly speak of it as a “resurrection,” as if resurrection and reanimation were synonymous terms? Further, is it really true that faith has no interest whatever in the question whether it was as risen from the dead, or merely as recovered from a state of suspended animation, that Jesus showed Himself to His disciples? In regard to this, it might seem, the rationalists were more straightforward.

But if the condition in which Jesus existed after His crucifixion was “a state of revival,” how can Schleiermacher keep referring to it as a "revival," as if resurrection and reanimation mean the same thing? Also, is it really true that faith has no interest in whether Jesus appeared to His disciples as someone risen from the dead or simply as someone who came back from a state of suspended animation? In this regard, the rationalists might have been more straightforward.

The moment one tries to take hold of this dialectic it breaks in one's fingers. Schleiermacher would not indeed have ventured to play so risky a game if he had not had a second position to retire to, based on the distinction between the Synoptic and the Johannine miracle stories. In this respect he simplified matters for himself, as compared with the rationalists, even more than Hase. The miracle at the baptism is only intelligible in the narrative of the Fourth Gospel, where it is not a question of an external occurrence, but of a purely subjective experience of John, with which we have nothing to do. The Synoptic story of the temptation has no intelligible meaning. “To change stones into bread, if there were need for it, would not have been a sin.” “A leap from the Temple could have had no attraction for any one.”

The moment you try to grasp this dialectic, it slips through your fingers. Schleiermacher wouldn't have dared to play such a risky game if he didn't have a fallback position based on the difference between the Synoptic and the Johannine miracle stories. In this way, he made things simpler for himself compared to the rationalists, even more than Hase. The miracle at the baptism only makes sense in the narrative of the Fourth Gospel, where it's not about an external event but rather a purely subjective experience of John, which has nothing to do with us. The Synoptic story of the temptation doesn't have a clear meaning. "Turning stones into bread, if it were needed, wouldn't have been a sin." "Jumping from the Temple wouldn’t have sounded appealing to anyone."

The miracles of the birth and childhood are given up without hesitation; they do not belong to the story of the life of Jesus; and it is the same with the miracles at His death. One might fancy it was Strauss speaking when Schleiermacher says: “If we give due consideration to the fact that we have certainly found in these for the most part simple narratives of the last moments of Christ two incidents, such as the rending of the veil of the Temple and the opening of the graves, in reference to which we cannot possibly suppose that they are literal descriptions of actual facts, then we are bound to ask the question whether the same does not apply to many other points. Certainly the mention of [pg 066] the sun's light failing and the consequent great darkness looks very much as if it had been imported by poetic imagination into the simple narrative.”

The miracles surrounding the birth and childhood of Jesus are easily dismissed; they aren't part of His life story. The same goes for the miracles associated with His death. One could think it was Strauss speaking when Schleiermacher mentions: “If we really think about it, we mostly find straightforward accounts of Christ's final moments that include two events: the tearing of the Temple veil and the opening of the graves. We can't take these as literal descriptions of actual events. This makes us wonder if the same reasoning applies to many other details. In fact, the mention of the sun’s light fading and the ensuing darkness seems to have been added through poetic imagination to the simple narrative.”

A rebuke could have no possible effect upon the wind and sea. Here we must suppose either an alteration of the facts or a different causal connexion.

A reprimand wouldn’t have any effect on the wind and sea. Here, we have to consider either a change in the facts or a different cause-and-effect relationship.

In this way Schleiermacher—and it was for this reason that these lectures on the life of Jesus became so celebrated—enabled dogmatics, though not indeed history, to take a flying leap over the miracle question.

In this way, Schleiermacher—and this is why these lectures on the life of Jesus became so well-known—allowed dogmatics, though not really history, to skip over the miracle question.

What is chiefly fatal to a sound historical view is his one-sided preference for the Fourth Gospel. It is, according to him, only in this Gospel that the consciousness of Jesus is truly reflected. In this connexion he expressly remarks that of a progress in the teaching of Jesus, and of any “development” in Him, there can be no question. His development is the unimpeded organic unfolding of the idea of the Divine Sonship.

What mainly harms a solid understanding of history is his biased preference for the Fourth Gospel. According to him, only in this Gospel is Jesus's consciousness truly portrayed. In this context, he specifically states that there can be no discussion of progress in Jesus's teaching or any "development" in Him. His development is simply the smooth, organic unfolding of the idea of being the Divine Son.

For the outline of the life of Jesus, also, the Fourth Gospel is alone authoritative. “The Johannine representation of the way in which the crisis of His fate was brought about is the only clear one.” The same applies to the narrative of the resurrection in this Gospel. “Accordingly, on this point also,” so he concludes his discussion, “I take it as established that the Gospel of John is the narrative of an eyewitness and forms an organic whole. The first three Gospels are compilations formed out of various narratives which had arisen independently; their discourses are composite structures, and their presentation of the history is such that one can form no idea of the grouping of events.” The “crowded days,” such as that of the sermon on the mount and the day of the parables, exist only in the imagination of the Evangelists. In reality there were no such days. Luke is the only one of them who has some semblance of historical order. His Gospel is compiled with much insight and critical tact out of a number of independent documents, as Schleiermacher believed himself to have shown convincingly in his critical study of Luke's Gospel, published in 1817.

For the outline of Jesus's life, the Fourth Gospel is the only authoritative account. "The way the Gospel of John presents the crisis about His fate is the only clear depiction." The same goes for the resurrection story in this Gospel. "Because of this, on this issue as well," he concludes his discussion, "I believe it's clear that the Gospel of John is a story from someone who witnessed the events and forms a complete narrative. The first three Gospels are compilations made up of different independently developed stories; their accounts are blended, and their depiction of events makes it hard to understand the sequence of what happened." The “busy days” like the day of the Sermon on the Mount and the day filled with parables, exist only in the minds of the Evangelists. In reality, there were no such days. Luke is the only one who has some form of historical order. His Gospel is carefully put together with insight and critical finesse from several independent documents, as Schleiermacher convincingly argued in his critical study of Luke's Gospel, published in 1817.

It is only on the ground of such a valuation of the sources that we can arrive at a just estimate of the different representations of the locality of the life of Jesus. “The contradictions,” Schleiermacher proceeds, “could not be explained if all our Gospels stood equally close to Jesus. But if John stands closer than the others, we may perhaps find the key in the fact that John, too, mentions it as a prevailing opinion in Jerusalem that Jesus was a Galilaean, and that Luke, when he has got to the end of the sections which show skilful arrangement and are united by similarity of subject, gathers all the rest into the framework of a journey to Jerusalem. Following this analogy, and not remembering that Jesus had occasion to go [pg 067] several times a year to Jerusalem, the other two gathered into one mass all that happened there on various occasions. This could only have been done by Hellenists.”26

It’s only by valuing the sources that we can accurately assess the different accounts of where Jesus lived. "The contradictions," Schleiermacher continues, It can't be explained if all our Gospels are equally close to Jesus. But if John is more accurate than the others, we might find the clue in the fact that John highlights the common belief in Jerusalem that Jesus was from Galilee. Meanwhile, Luke, after wrapping up well-organized sections linked by themes, combines everything else into a journey to Jerusalem. By following this method and not taking into account that Jesus went to [pg 067] Jerusalem several times a year, the other two Gospel writers merged all the events that took place there on different occasions. This could only have been done by Hellenists.26

Schleiermacher is quite insensible to the graphic realism of the description of the last days at Jerusalem in Mark and Matthew, and has no suspicion that if only a single one of the Jerusalem sayings in the Synoptists is true Jesus had never before spoken in Jerusalem.

Schleiermacher is completely indifferent to the vivid realism of the accounts of the last days in Jerusalem found in Mark and Matthew, and he doesn't realize that if even one of the sayings attributed to Jesus in the Synoptic Gospels is true, then Jesus had never spoken in Jerusalem before.

The ground of Schleiermacher's antipathy to the Synoptists lies deeper than a mere critical view as to their composition. The fact is that their “picture of Christ” does not agree with that which he wishes to insert into the history. When it serves his purpose, he does not shrink from the most arbitrary violence. He abolishes the scene in Gethsemane because he infers from the silence of John that it cannot have taken place. “The other Evangelists,” he explains, “give us an account of a sudden depression and deep distress of spirit which fell upon Jesus, and which He admitted to His disciples, and they tell us how He sought relief from it in prayer, and afterwards recovered His serenity and resolution. John passes over this in silence, and his narrative of what immediately precedes is not consistent with it.” It is evidently a symbolical story, as the thrice-repeated petition shows. “If they speak of such a depression of spirit, they have given the story that form in order that the example of Christ might be the more applicable to others in similar circumstances.”

The basis of Schleiermacher's dislike for the Synoptics goes beyond just a critical viewpoint on their composition. The truth is, their “Image of Christ” doesn’t match what he wants to include in the narrative. When it benefits him, he isn’t afraid to take extreme liberties. He removes the scene in Gethsemane because he infers from John's silence that it couldn’t have happened. "The other Gospels," he explains, "give an account of a sudden sadness and deep emotional distress that came over Jesus, which He shared with His disciples, and they explain how He sought comfort through prayer, ultimately regaining His peace and resolve. John leaves this out, and his version of the events right before doesn’t match with it." Clearly, it’s a symbolic story, as shown by the repeated plea. "If they discuss such a state of distress, they've crafted the story to make Christ's example more relatable to others facing similar situations."

On these premises it is possible to write a Life of Christ; it is not possible to write a Life of Jesus. It is, therefore, not by accident that Schleiermacher regularly speaks, not of Jesus, but of Christ.

On these grounds, it's possible to write a Life of Christ; it's not possible to write a Life of Jesus. Therefore, it’s not by coincidence that Schleiermacher often refers, not to Jesus, but to Christ.

[pg 068]

VII. David Friedrich Strauss—The Man and His Destiny

In order to understand Strauss one must love him. He was not the greatest, and not the deepest, of theologians, but he was the most absolutely sincere. His insight and his errors were alike the insight and the errors of a prophet. And he had a prophet's fate. Disappointment and suffering gave his life its consecration. It unrolls itself before us like a tragedy, in which, in the end, the gloom is lightened by the mild radiance which shines forth from the nobility of the sufferer.

To understand Strauss, you have to appreciate him. He wasn't the greatest or the deepest theologian, but he was completely sincere. His insights and mistakes were both those of a prophet. He experienced a prophet's fate, as disappointment and suffering gave meaning to his life. It unfolds like a tragedy, where, in the end, the darkness is brightened by the gentle light that comes from the dignity of the one who suffers.

Strauss was born in 1808 at Ludwigsburg. His father was a merchant, whose business, however, was unsuccessful, so that his means steadily declined. The boy took his ability from his mother, a good, self-controlled, sensible, pious woman, to whom he raised a monument in his “Memorial of a Good Mother” written in 1858, to be given to his daughter on her confirmation-day.

Strauss was born in 1808 in Ludwigsburg. His father was a merchant, but his business was unsuccessful, so their financial situation steadily got worse. The boy inherited his talents from his mother, a kind, composed, sensible, and religious woman. He honored her with a tribute in his "Memorial for a Good Mom", which he wrote in 1858 to present to his daughter on her confirmation day.

From 1821 to 1825 he was a pupil at the “lower seminary” at Blaubeuren, along with Friedrich Vischer, Pfizer, Zimmermann, Märklin, and Binder. Among their teachers was Ferdinand Christian Baur, whom they were to meet with again at the university.

From 1821 to 1825, he was a student at the “junior seminary” in Blaubeuren, alongside Friedrich Vischer, Pfizer, Zimmermann, Märklin, and Binder. One of their teachers was Ferdinand Christian Baur, whom they would encounter again at the university.

His first year at the university was uninteresting, as it was only in the following year that the reorganisation of the theological faculty took place, in consequence of the appointment of Baur. The instruction in the philosophical faculty was almost equally unsatisfactory, so that the friends would have gained little from the two years of philosophical propaedeutic which formed part of the course prescribed for theological students, if they had not combined to prosecute their philosophical studies for themselves. The writings of Hegel began to exercise a powerful influence upon them. For the philosophical faculty, Hegel's philosophy was as yet non-existent.

His first year at the university was pretty dull, as it wasn't until the following year that the reorganization of the theology department happened due to Baur's appointment. The classes in the philosophy department were nearly as disappointing, so the friends would have gotten little out of the two years of philosophical basics required for theology students if they hadn't worked together to pursue their philosophical studies on their own. The writings of Hegel started to have a significant impact on them. At that time, Hegel's philosophy was basically nonexistent in the philosophy department.

These student friends were much addicted to poetry. Two [pg 069] journeys which Strauss made along with his fellow-student Binder to Weinsberg to see Justinus Kerner made a deep impression upon him. He had to make a deliberate effort to escape from the dream-world of the “Prophetess of Prevorst.” Some years later, in a Latin note to Binder, he speaks of Weinsberg as “Mecca nostra.”27

These student friends were really into poetry. Two [pg 069] trips that Strauss took with his classmate Binder to Weinsberg to meet Justinus Kerner left a strong impression on him. He had to consciously try to break free from the dream-like world of the "Prevorst Prophetess." A few years later, in a Latin note to Binder, he referred to Weinsberg as "Our Mecca."27

According to Vischer's picture of him, the tall stripling made an impression of great charm, though he was rather shy except with intimates. He attended lectures with pedantic regularity.

According to Vischer's picture of him, the tall young man had a captivating charm, though he was quite shy except around close friends. He attended lectures with an almost obsessive regularity.

Baur was at that time still immersed in the prolegomena to his system; but Strauss already suspected the direction which the thoughts of his young teacher were to take.

Baur was still deep into the groundwork of his system, but Strauss already had an inkling of the direction his young teacher's thoughts were heading.

When Strauss and his student friends entered on their duties as clergymen, the others found great difficulty in bringing their theological views into line with the popular beliefs which they were expected to preach. Strauss alone remained free from inner struggles. In a letter to Binder28 of the year 1831, he explains that in his sermons—he was then assistant at Klein-Ingersheim near Ludwigsburg—he did not use “representative notions” (Vorstellungen, used as a philosophical technicality) such as that of the Devil, which the people were already prepared to dispense with; but others which still appeared to be indispensable, such as those of an eschatological character, he merely endeavoured to present in such a way that the “intellectual concept” (Begriff) which lay behind, might so far as possible shine through. “When I consider,” he continues, “how far even in intellectual preaching the expression is inadequate to the true essence of the concept, it does not seem to me to matter much if one goes even a step further. I at least go about the matter without the least scruple, and cannot ascribe this to a mere want of sincerity in myself.”

When Strauss and his student friends began their roles as clergymen, the others struggled to align their theological beliefs with the popular ideas they were supposed to preach. Strauss, however, was free from this internal conflict. In a letter to Binder28 from 1831, he explains that in his sermons—he was then an assistant at Klein-Ingersheim near Ludwigsburg—he didn’t use “representative notions” (Vorstellungen, a philosophical term) like the concept of the Devil, which people were already ready to let go of; instead, for other ideas that still seemed essential, especially those related to eschatology, he tried to present them in a way that made the underlying “intellectual concept” (Begriff) shine through as much as possible. “When I consider,” he continues, “how inadequate even intellectual preaching is to capture the true essence of a concept, it doesn’t seem to matter much if one goes a step further. I at least approach the matter without the slightest hesitation and can’t attribute this to a lack of sincerity on my part.”

That is Hegelian logic.

That's Hegelian logic.

After being for a short time Deputy-professor at Maulbronn, he took his doctor's degree with a dissertation on the ἀποκατάστασις πάντων (restoration of all things, Acts iii. 21). This work is lost. From his letters it appears that he treated the subject chiefly from the religious-historical point of view.29

After a brief stint as a Deputy Professor at Maulbronn, he earned his doctorate with a dissertation on the ἀποκατάστασις πάντων (restoration of all things, Acts iii. 21). This work is lost. From his letters, it seems he approached the topic mainly from a religious-historical perspective.29

When Binder took his doctorate with a philosophical thesis on the immortality of the soul, Strauss, in 1832, wrote to him expressing the opinion that the belief in personal immortality could not properly be regarded as a consequence of the Hegelian system, since according [pg 070] to Hegel, it was not the subjective spirit of the individual person, but only the objective Spirit, the self-realising Idea which constantly embodies itself in new creations, to which immortality belongs.30

When Binder earned his doctorate with a philosophical thesis on the immortality of the soul, Strauss wrote to him in 1832, sharing his view that the belief in personal immortality shouldn't be seen as a result of the Hegelian system. According to Hegel, it wasn't the subjective spirit of the individual that achieved immortality, but rather the objective Spirit, the self-realizing Idea that continually manifests itself in new creations, that holds immortality. 30

In October 1831 he went to Berlin to hear Hegel and Schleiermacher. On the 14th of November Hegel, whom he had visited shortly before, was carried off by cholera. Strauss heard the news in Schleiermacher's house, from Schleiermacher himself, and is said to have exclaimed, with a certain want of tact, considering who his informant was: “And it was to hear him that I came to Berlin!”

In October 1831, he went to Berlin to listen to Hegel and Schleiermacher. On November 14th, Hegel, whom he had visited just before, died from cholera. Strauss heard the news at Schleiermacher's house, directly from Schleiermacher, and reportedly exclaimed, somewhat insensitively given his informant's identity: "And it was to hear him that I came to Berlin!"

There was no satisfactory basis for a relationship between Schleiermacher and Strauss. They had nothing in common. That did not prevent Strauss's Life of Jesus being sometimes described by opponents of Schleiermacher as a product of the latter's philosophy of religion. Indeed, as late as the 'sixties, Tholuck thought it necessary to defend the memory of the great theologian against this reproach.

There was no solid foundation for a relationship between Schleiermacher and Strauss. They had nothing in common. However, that didn’t stop Strauss’s Life of Jesus from being referred to by critics of Schleiermacher as a result of Schleiermacher’s philosophy of religion. In fact, as late as the '60s, Tholuck felt it was necessary to defend the reputation of the great theologian against this accusation.

As a matter of fact, the plan of the Life of Jesus arose during Strauss's intercourse with Vatke, to whom he felt himself strongly drawn. Moreover, what was first sketched out was not primarily the plan of a Life of Jesus, but that of a history of the ideas of primitive Christianity, intended to serve as a standard by which to judge ecclesiastical dogma. The Life of Jesus was originally designed, it might almost be said, as a mere prologue to this work, the plan of which was subsequently carried out under the title, “Christian Theology in its Historical Development and in its Antagonism with Modern Scientific Knowledge” (published in 1840-1841).

As a matter of fact, the plan for the Life of Jesus came about during Strauss's discussions with Vatke, to whom he felt a strong connection. Additionally, what was initially outlined was not mainly the plan for a Life of Jesus, but rather a history of the ideas of early Christianity, meant to serve as a benchmark for evaluating church doctrine. The Life of Jesus was originally meant, one could almost say, as just an introduction to this work, which was later fully developed under the title, "Christian Theology: Its Historical Development and Conflict with Modern Scientific Knowledge" (published in 1840-1841).

When in the spring of 1832 he returned to Tübingen to take up the position of “Repetent”31 in the theological college (Stift), these plans were laid on the shelf in consequence of his pre-occupation with philosophy, and if things had gone according to Strauss's wishes, they would perhaps never have come to fulfilment. The “Repetents” had the right to lecture upon philosophy. Strauss felt himself called upon to come forward as an apostle of Hegel, and lectured upon Hegel's logic with tremendous success. Zeller, who attended these lectures, records the unforgettable impression which they made on him. Besides championing Hegel, Strauss also lectured upon Plato, and upon the history of modern philosophy. These were three happy semesters.

When he returned to Tübingen in the spring of 1832 to take the position of "Repeater"31 at the theological college (Pen), his plans were put on hold because he was so focused on philosophy. If things had gone as Strauss envisioned, those plans might never have happened. The "Repeaters" had the right to teach philosophy. Strauss felt it was his calling to step up as an advocate for Hegel and achieved great success with his lectures on Hegel's logic. Zeller, who attended these lectures, noted the lasting impression they left on him. In addition to supporting Hegel, Strauss also lectured on Plato and the history of modern philosophy. These were three great semesters.

“In my theology,” he writes in a letter of 1833,32 “philosophy occupies such a predominant position that my theological views can only be worked out to completeness by means of a more thorough study of philosophy, and this course of study I am now [pg 071] going to prosecute uninterruptedly and without concerning myself whether it leads me back to theology or not.” Further on he says: “If I know myself rightly, my position in regard to theology is that what interests me in theology causes offence, and what does not cause offence is indifferent to me. For this reason I have refrained from delivering lectures on theology.”

"In my beliefs," he writes in a letter from 1833, 32 "Philosophy is so crucial that I can only fully shape my theological views through a deeper exploration of philosophy, and this is the path I’m going to pursue relentlessly, regardless of whether it brings me back to theology or not." Further on he says: “If I know myself well, my view on theology is that I’m mainly interested in the controversial aspects, and the non-controversial ones don’t interest me. Because of this, I’ve steered clear of giving lectures on theology.”

The philosophical faculty was not altogether pleased at the success of the apostle of Hegel, and wished to have the right of the “Repetents” to lecture on philosophy curtailed. The latter, however, took their stand upon the tradition. Strauss was desired to intermit his lectures until the matter should be settled. He would have liked best to end the situation by entering the philosophical faculty. The other “Repetents,” however, begged him not to do so, but to continue to champion their rights. It is possible also that obstacles were placed in the way of his plan by the philosophical faculty. However that may be, it was in any case not carried through. Strauss was forced back upon theology.

The philosophy department wasn’t too happy about the success of Hegel’s follower and wanted to limit the right of the "Repetents" to teach philosophy. However, they insisted on their tradition. Strauss was asked to pause his lectures until this issue was resolved. He would have preferred to settle the situation by joining the philosophy department. However, the other “Repeaters,” urged him not to do that and to keep fighting for their rights. It’s also possible that the philosophy department put obstacles in his way for this plan. Regardless, it didn’t happen. Strauss was pushed back into theology.

According to Hase,33 Strauss began his studies for the Life of Jesus by writing a detailed critical review of his (Hase's) text-book. He sent this to Berlin to the Jahrbücher für wissenschaftliche Kritik, which, however, refused it. His resolve to publish first, instead of the general work on the genesis of Christian doctrine, a critical study on the life of Jesus was doubtless determined by Schleiermacher's lectures on this subject. When in Berlin he had procured a copy of a lecture note-book, and the reading of it incited him to opposition.

According to Hase, Strauss started his studies on the Life of Jesus by writing a detailed critical review of his (Hase's) textbook. He sent this to Berlin to the Scientific Critique Yearbooks, which, however, rejected it. His decision to publish a critical study on the life of Jesus first, instead of the general work on the origins of Christian doctrine, was undoubtedly influenced by Schleiermacher's lectures on this topic. While in Berlin, he managed to get a hold of a lecture notebook, and reading it sparked his desire to respond critically.

Considering its character, the work was rapidly produced. He wrote it sitting at the window of the Repetents' room, which looks out upon the gateway-arch. When its two volumes appeared in 1835 the name of the author was wholly unknown, except for some critical studies upon the Gospels. This book, into which he had poured his youthful enthusiasm, rendered him famous in a moment—and utterly destroyed his prospects. Among his opponents the most prominent was Steudel, a member of the theological faculty, who, as president of the Stift, made representations against him to the Ministry, and succeeded in securing his removal from the post of “Repetent.” The hopes which Strauss had placed upon his friends were disappointed. Only two or three at most dared to publish anything in his defence.

Considering its character, the work was quickly produced. He wrote it while sitting at the window of the Repetents' room, which looks out onto the gateway-arch. When its two volumes were released in 1835, the author was entirely unknown, except for a few critical studies on the Gospels. This book, into which he had poured his youthful enthusiasm, made him famous overnight—and completely ruined his career prospects. Among his opponents, the most notable was Steudel, a member of the theological faculty, who, as president of the Pen, lodged complaints against him with the Ministry and managed to get him dismissed from his position as "Repeater." The hopes Strauss had placed in his friends were dashed. Only two or three at most had the courage to publish anything in his defense.

He first accepted a transfer to the post of Deputy-professor at Ludwigsburg, but in less than a year he was glad to give it up, and he then returned to Stuttgart. There he lived for several years, busying himself in the preparation of new editions [pg 072] of the Life of Jesus, and in writing answers to the attacks which were made upon him.

He initially accepted a transfer to the position of Deputy Professor in Ludwigsburg, but in less than a year, he was happy to give it up and returned to Stuttgart. There, he spent several years focusing on preparing new editions [pg 072] of the Life of Jesus and responding to the criticisms aimed at him.

Towards the end of the 'thirties he became conscious of a growing impulse towards more positive views. The criticisms of his opponents had made some impression upon him. The second volume of polemics was laid aside. In its place appeared the third edition of the Life of Jesus, 1838-1839, containing a series of amazing concessions. Strauss explains that in consequence of reading de Wette's commentary and Neander's Life of Jesus he had begun to feel some hesitation about his former doubts regarding the genuineness and credibility of the Fourth Gospel. The historic personality of Jesus again began to take on intelligible outlines for him. These inconsistencies he removed in the next edition, acknowledging that he did not know how he could so have temporarily vacillated in his point of view. The matter admits, however, of a psychological explanation. He longed for peace, for he had suffered more than his enemies suspected or his friends knew. The ban of the outlaw lay heavy upon his soul. In this spirit he composed in 1839 the monologues entitled Vergängliches und Bleibendes im Christentum (“Transient and Permanent Elements in Christianity”), which appeared again in the following year under the title Friedliche Blätter (“Leaves of Peace”).

Towards the end of the 1930s, he became aware of a growing urge to adopt more positive views. His opponents' criticisms had impacted him. The second volume of polemics was set aside. In its place came the third edition of the Life of Jesus, 1838-1839, featuring a series of remarkable concessions. Strauss explains that after reading de Wette's commentary and Neander's Life of Jesus, he started to feel uncertain about his previous doubts concerning the authenticity and reliability of the Fourth Gospel. The historical figure of Jesus began to take on clear outlines for him again. He resolved these inconsistencies in the next edition, admitting that he was unsure how he could have wavered in his perspective for a time. This situation can be understood psychologically. He yearned for peace, having suffered more than his enemies realized or his friends knew. The weight of being an outcast was heavy on his soul. In this mindset, he wrote the monologues titled The Temporary and Eternal in Christianity ("Temporary and Lasting Aspects of Christianity"), which were published again the following year under the title Peaceful Leaves ("Leaves of Peace").

For a moment it seemed as though his rehabilitation would be accomplished. In January 1839 the noble-minded Hitzig succeeded in getting him appointed to the vacant chair of dogmatics in Zurich. But the orthodox and pietist parties protested so vehemently that the Government was obliged to revoke the appointment. Strauss was pensioned off, without ever entering on his office.

For a moment, it seemed like his rehabilitation would actually happen. In January 1839, the honorable Hitzig managed to get him appointed to the open position of dogmatics in Zurich. However, the orthodox and pietist groups protested so strongly that the government had to take back the appointment. Strauss was given a pension, never having started his job.

About that time his mother died. In 1841 he lost his father. When the estate came to be settled up, it was found that his affairs were in a less unsatisfactory condition than had been feared. Strauss was secure against want. The success of his second great work, his “Christian Theology” (published in 1840-41), compensated him for his disappointment at Zurich. In conception it is perhaps even greater than the Life of Jesus; and in depth of thought it is to be classed with the most important contributions to theology. In spite of that it never attracted so much attention as the earlier work. Strauss continued to be known as the author of the Life of Jesus. Any further ground of offence which he might give was regarded as quite subsidiary.

Around that time, his mother passed away. In 1841, he lost his father. When the estate was settled, it turned out that his affairs were in better shape than expected. Strauss was secure from financial hardship. The success of his second major work, his “Christian Theology” (published in 1840-41), made up for his disappointment in Zurich. In concept, it might even be greater than the Life of Jesus, and in terms of depth of thought, it ranks among the most significant contributions to theology. Despite this, it never received as much attention as the earlier work. Strauss remained primarily known as the author of the Life of Jesus. Any further issues he might cause were seen as relatively minor.

And the book contains matter for offence in no common degree. The point to which Strauss applies his criticism is the way in which the Christian theology which grew out of the ideas of the ancient world has been brought into harmony with [pg 073] the Christianity of rationalism and of speculative philosophy. Either, to use his own expression, both are so finely pulverised in the process—as in the case of Schleiermacher's combination of Spinozism with Christianity—that it needs a sharp eye to rediscover the elements of the mixture; or the two are shaken together like water and oil, in which case the semblance of combination is only maintained so long as the shaking continues. For this crude procedure he desires to substitute a better method, based upon a preliminary historical criticism of dogma, in order that thought may no longer have to deal with the present form of Church theology, but with the ideas which worked as living forces in its formation.

And the book contains a lot of controversial material. Strauss focuses his critique on how the Christian theology that emerged from ancient ideas has been aligned with the Christianity of rationalism and speculative philosophy. As he puts it, in some cases, both are so finely ground down in the process—like Schleiermacher's blend of Spinozism with Christianity—that it's hard to identify the individual elements; or they are mixed together like oil and water, where the illusion of a combination lasts only as long as they're being stirred. He wants to replace this rough approach with a better method that starts with a thorough historical critique of dogma, so that thought can engage with the original ideas that shaped its development, rather than just the current form of Church theology.

This is brilliantly worked out in detail. The result is not a positive, but a negative Hegelian theology. Religion is not concerned with supra-mundane beings and a divinely glorious future, but with present spiritual realities which appear as “moments” in the eternal being and becoming of Absolute Spirit. At the end of the second volume, where battle is joined on the issue of personal immortality, all these ideas play their part in the struggle. Personal immortality is finally rejected in every form, for the critical reasons which Strauss had already set forth in the letters of 1832. Immortality is not something which stretches out into the future, but simply and solely the present quality of the spirit, its inner universality, its power of rising above everything finite to the Idea. Here the thought of Hegel coincides with that of Schleiermacher. “The saying of Schleiermacher, ‘In the midst of finitude to be one with the Infinite, and to be eternal in a moment,’ is all that modern thought can say about immortality.” But neither Schleiermacher nor Hegel was willing to draw the natural inferences from their ultimate position, or at least they did not give them any prominence.

This is brilliantly detailed. The outcome is not a positive belief, but a negative Hegelian theology. Religion isn’t about otherworldly beings and a glorious future but focuses on present spiritual realities that show up as "memories" in the eternal existence and evolution of Absolute Spirit. At the end of the second volume, where the debate about personal immortality intensifies, all these ideas come into play. Personal immortality is ultimately dismissed in every form, for the critical reasons that Strauss had already outlined in the letters of 1832. Immortality isn’t something that extends into the future, but is simply and solely the current quality of the spirit, its inner universality, its ability to rise above everything finite to the Idea. Here, Hegel’s thought aligns with that of Schleiermacher. “The saying of Schleiermacher, ‘In the midst of finitude to be one with the Infinite, and to be eternal in a moment,’ captures everything modern thought can express about immortality.” However, neither Schleiermacher nor Hegel was ready to draw the natural conclusions from their ultimate stance, or at least they didn’t highlight those conclusions.

It is not the application of the mythological explanation to the Gospel history which irrevocably divides Strauss from the theologians, but the question of personal immortality. It would be well for them if they had only to deal with the Strauss of the Life of Jesus, and not with the thinker who posed this question with inexorable trenchancy. They might then face the future more calmly, relieved of the anxiety lest once more Hegel and Schleiermacher might rise up in some pious but critical spirit, not to speak smooth things, but to ask the ultimate questions, and might force theology to fight its battle with Strauss all over again.

It's not the application of mythological explanations to the Gospel history that separates Strauss from the theologians, but the issue of personal immortality. It would be easier for them if they only had to contend with Strauss from the Life of Jesus, rather than the thinker who raised this question with such undeniable sharpness. They could then approach the future more peacefully, free from the worry that Hegel and Schleiermacher might emerge again in some devout yet critical way, not to say comforting things but to ask the tough questions, compelling theology to confront Strauss's challenges once more.

At the very time when Strauss was beginning to breathe freely once more, had turned his back upon all attempts at compromise, and reconciled himself to giving up teaching; and when, after settling his father's affairs, he had the certainty of being secure [pg 074] against penury; at that very time he sowed for himself the seeds of a new, immitigable suffering by his marriage with Agnese Schebest, the famous singer.

At the exact moment when Strauss was starting to breathe easy again, had completely rejected any attempts at compromise, and accepted that he would stop teaching; and when, after taking care of his father's affairs, he knew for sure he was safe from poverty; at that very moment, he planted the seeds of a new, unbearable suffering by marrying Agnese Schebest, the famous singer.

They were not made for one another. He could not look to her for any sympathy with his plans, and she on her part was repelled by the pedantry of his disposition. Housekeeping difficulties and the trials of a limited income added another element of discord. They removed to Sontheim near Heilbronn with the idea of learning to adapt themselves to one another far from the distractions of the town; but that did not better matters. They lived apart for a time, and after some years they procured a divorce, custody of the children being assigned to the father. The lady took up her residence in Stuttgart, and Strauss paid her an allowance up to her death in 1870.

They weren't right for each other. He couldn't expect her to understand his plans, and she was put off by his overly scholarly nature. Struggles with household responsibilities and the challenges of a tight budget added to their issues. They moved to Sontheim near Heilbronn, hoping to learn to get along away from the distractions of the city, but that didn't improve things. They spent some time living separately, and after a few years, they got a divorce, with custody of the kids going to the father. She moved to Stuttgart, and Strauss provided her with an allowance until her death in 1870.

What he suffered may be read between the lines in the passage in “The Old Faith and the New” where he speaks of the sacredness of marriage and the admissibility of divorce. The wound bled inwardly. His mental powers were disabled. At this time he wrote little. Only in the apologue “Julian the Apostate, or the Romanticist on the throne of the Caesars”—that brilliant satire upon Frederic William IV., written in 1847—is there a flash of the old spirit.

What he went through can be seen in the lines from “The Old Faith and the New” where he talks about the sanctity of marriage and the acceptability of divorce. The pain was internal. His mental abilities were impaired. During this period, he didn't write much. The only exception is the allegory "Julian the Apostate, or the Romantic on the throne of the Caesars"—that sharp satire about Frederic William IV., written in 1847—where a hint of his old spirit shines through.

But in spite of his antipathy to the romantic disposition of the King of Prussia he entered the lists in 1848 on behalf of the efforts of the smaller German states to form a united Germany, apart from Austria, under the hegemony of Prussia. He did not suffer his political acumen to be blunted either by personal antipathies or by particularism. The citizens of Ludwigsburg wished to have him as their representative in the Frankfort parliament, but the rural population, who were pietistic in sympathies, defeated his candidature. Instead, his native town sent him to the Würtemberg Chamber of Deputies. But here his philistinism came to the fore again. The phrase-mongering revolutionary party in the chamber disgusted him. He saw himself more and more forced to the “right,” and was obliged to act politically with men whose reactionary sympathies he was far from sharing. His constituents, meanwhile, were thoroughly discontented with his attitude. In the end the position became intolerable. It was also painful to him to have to reside in Stuttgart, where he could not avoid meeting the woman who had brought so much misery into his life. Further—he himself mentions this point in his memoirs—he had no practice in speaking without manuscript, and cut a poor figure as a debater. Then came the “Blum Case.” Robert Blum, a revolutionary, had been shot by court martial in Vienna. The Würtemberg Chamber desired to vote a public celebration of his funeral. [pg 075] Strauss did not think there was any ground for making a hero of this agitator, merely because he had been shot, and was not inclined to blame the Austrian Government very severely for meting out summary justice to a disturber of the peace. His attitude brought on him a vote of censure from his constituents. When, subsequently, the President of the Chamber called him to order for asserting that a previous speaker had “concealed by sleight of hand” (wegeskamotiert, “juggled away”) an important point in the debate, he refused to accept the vote of censure, resigned his membership, and ceased to attend the diets. As he himself put it, he “jumped out of the boat.” Then began a period of restless wandering, during which he beguiled his time with literary work. He wrote, inter alia, upon Lessing, Hutten, and Reimarus, rediscovering the last-named for his fellow-countrymen.

But despite his dislike for the romantic views of the King of Prussia, he got involved in 1848 to support the efforts of the smaller German states to create a united Germany, separate from Austria, under Prussian leadership. He didn't let personal dislikes or regional interests dull his political insight. The citizens of Ludwigsburg wanted him as their representative in the Frankfort parliament, but the rural population, who had more conservative views, defeated his candidacy. Instead, his hometown sent him to the Württemberg Chamber of Deputies. However, his narrow-mindedness showed up again. The rhetoric-heavy revolutionary party in the chamber repulsed him. He increasingly felt pushed to the “right” and had to work politically with people whose conservative views he did not share. Meanwhile, his constituents were very unhappy with his stance. Eventually, the situation became unbearable. It was also painful for him to live in Stuttgart, where he couldn’t avoid seeing the woman who had caused him so much suffering. Additionally—he mentions this in his memoirs—he wasn't practiced at speaking without a script and struggled as a debater. Then came the “Blum Case.” Robert Blum, a revolutionary, was executed by court martial in Vienna. The Württemberg Chamber wanted to vote for a public celebration of his funeral. Strauss didn’t see any reason to turn this agitator into a hero just because he had been shot and wasn’t inclined to severely criticize the Austrian Government for enforcing quick justice on a troublemaker. His stance earned him a vote of censure from his constituents. Later, when the President of the Chamber reprimanded him for claiming that a previous speaker had “concealed by sleight of hand” an important point in the debate, he refused to accept the censure, resigned from his position, and stopped attending the meetings. As he put it, he “jumped out of the boat.” This led to a period of restless wandering, during which he spent his time writing. He wrote, among other things, about Lessing, Hutten, and Reimarus, rediscovering the last for his fellow countrymen.

At the end of the 'sixties he returned once more to theology. His “Life of Jesus adapted for the German People” appeared in 1864. In the preface he refers to Renan, and freely acknowledges the great merits of his work.

At the end of the '60s, he returned to theology again. His “Life of Jesus tailored for the German Audience” was published in 1864. In the preface, he mentions Renan and openly recognizes the significant value of his work.

The Prusso-Austrian war placed him in a difficult position. His historical insight made it impossible for him to share the particularism of his friends; on the contrary, he recognised that the way was now being prepared for the realisation of his dream of 1848—an alliance of the smaller German States under the hegemony of Prussia. As he made no secret of his opinions, he had the bitter experience of receiving the cold shoulder from men who had hitherto loyally stood by him.

The Prusso-Austrian war put him in a tough spot. His understanding of history made it impossible for him to agree with the narrow views of his friends; instead, he saw that the path was being paved for the realization of his 1848 dream—a coalition of the smaller German States under Prussia's leadership. Since he openly expressed his views, he faced the harsh reality of being ignored by those who had previously supported him.

In the year 1870 it was granted to him to become the spokesman of the German people; through a publication on Voltaire which had appeared not long before he had become acquainted with Renan. In a letter to Strauss, written after the first battles, Renan made a passing allusion to these great events. Strauss seized the opportunity to explain to him, in a vigorous “open letter” of the 12th of August, Germany's reason and justification for going to war. Receiving an answer from Renan, he then, in a second letter, of the 29th of September, took occasion to defend Germany's right to demand the cession of Alsace, not on the ground of its having formerly been German territory, but for the defence of her natural frontiers. The resounding echo evoked by these words, inspired, as they were, by the enthusiasm of the moment, compensated him for much of the obloquy which he had had to bear.

In 1870, he was appointed as the spokesperson for the German people; shortly after a publication about Voltaire, he met Renan. In a letter to Strauss, written after the initial battles, Renan briefly referenced these major events. Strauss took this chance to clarify, in a powerful "open letter" dated August 12, Germany's reasons and justifications for going to war. After receiving a response from Renan, he then, in a second letter on September 29, took the opportunity to defend Germany's right to ask for the return of Alsace, not by claiming it had once been German land, but for protecting her natural borders. The strong reaction to these words, inspired by the excitement of the moment, made up for much of the criticism he had faced.

His last work, “The Old Faith and the New,” appeared in 1872. Once more, as in the work on theology published in 1840-1841, he puts to himself the question, What is there of permanence in this artificial compound of theology and philosophy, faith and thought? [pg 076] But he puts the question with a certain bitterness, and shows himself too much under the influence of Darwinism, by which his mind was at that time dominated. The Hegelian system of thought, which served as a firm basis for the work of 1840, has fallen in ruins. Strauss is alone with his own thoughts, endeavouring to raise himself above the new scientific world-view. His powers of thought, never, for all his critical acumen, strong on the creative side, and now impaired by age, were unequal to the task. There is no force and no greatness in the book.

His last work, “The Old Faith and the New,” was published in 1872. Once again, like in the theological work from 1840-1841, he asks himself the question, What is permanent in this artificial mix of theology and philosophy, faith and thought? [pg 076] But he poses this question with a certain bitterness and is heavily influenced by Darwinism, which dominated his thinking at that time. The Hegelian system of thought that supported the work from 1840 has collapsed. Strauss is left alone with his ideas, trying to rise above the new scientific worldview. His critical thinking skills, although sharp, were never very creative, and now, with age, they are unable to meet the challenge. The book lacks power and greatness.

To the question, “Are we still Christians?” he answers, “No.” But to his second question, “Have we still a religion?” he is prepared to give an affirmative answer, if the assumption is granted that the feeling of dependence, of self-surrender, of inner freedom, which has sprung from the pantheistic world-view, can be called religion. But instead of developing the idea of this deep inner freedom, and presenting religion in the form in which he had experienced it, he believes himself obliged to offer some new construction based upon Darwinism, and sets himself to answer the two questions, “How are we to understand the world?” and “How are we to regulate our lives?”—the form of the latter is somewhat lacking in distinction—in a quite impersonal way. It is only the schoolmaster and pedant in him—who was always at the elbow of the thinker even in his greatest works—that finds expression here.

To the question, “Are we still Christian?” he replies, “No.” But to his second question, "Do we still have a religion?" he is ready to say yes, if we agree that the feelings of dependence, self-surrender, and inner freedom that come from the pantheistic worldview can be considered religion. However, instead of exploring the concept of this profound inner freedom and sharing religion as he has experienced it, he feels compelled to present a new framework based on Darwinism and sets out to answer two questions: "How should we make sense of the world?" and "How should we live our lives?"—the latter lacking some clarity—in a rather impersonal manner. It’s just the schoolmaster and pedant within him—who always accompanied the thinker even in his most significant works—that comes through here.

It was a dead book, in spite of the many editions which it went through, and the battle which raged over it was, like the fiercest of the Homeric battles, a combat over the dead.

It was a lifeless book, despite the numerous editions it went through, and the struggle surrounding it was, like the fiercest battles of Homer, a fight over something dead.

The theologians declared Strauss bankrupt, and felt themselves rich because they had made sure of not being ruined by a similar unimaginative honesty. Friedrich Nietzsche, from the height of his would-be Schopenhauerian pessimism, mocked at the fallen hero.

The theologians declared Strauss bankrupt and felt prosperous because they had ensured they wouldn’t suffer a similar lack of creativity. Friedrich Nietzsche, from his position of supposed Schopenhauerian pessimism, ridiculed the fallen hero.

Before the year was out Strauss began to suffer from an internal ulcer. For many months he bore his sufferings with quiet resignation and inner serenity, until on the 8th of February 1874, in his native town of Ludwigsburg, death set him free.

Before the year ended, Strauss began to suffer from an internal ulcer. For many months, he endured his pain with quiet acceptance and inner peace, until on February 8, 1874, in his hometown of Ludwigsburg, death freed him.

A few weeks earlier, on the 29th of December 1873, his sufferings and his thoughts received illuminating expression in the following poignant verses:—

A few weeks earlier, on December 29, 1873, his pain and thoughts were powerfully expressed in these moving verses:—

Wem ich das klage,
I don't complain;
To whom I say this,
Fühl' ich, zögere nicht.
Heute heißt's verglimmen,
Like a fading light,
Fade into the air,
Like a sound fading away.
[pg 077]
May it be weak as always,
But bright and pure,
This last glimmer
This sound is just his.34

He was buried on a stormy February day.

He was buried on a rainy February day.

[pg 078]

VIII. Strauss's First “Life of Jesus”

First edition, 1835 and 1836. 2 volumes, 1480 pages.
The second edition was unchanged.
3rd edition, with updates, 1838-1839.
Fourth edition, consistent with the first, 1840.

Considered as a literary work, Strauss's first Life of Jesus is one of the most perfect things in the whole range of learned literature. In over fourteen hundred pages he has not a superfluous phrase; his analysis descends to the minutest details, but he does not lose his way among them; the style is simple and picturesque, sometimes ironical, but always dignified and distinguished.

Seen as a literary piece, Strauss's first Life of Jesus is one of the finest works in all of scholarly literature. Across more than fourteen hundred pages, there isn't a single unnecessary phrase; his analysis goes into the smallest details, yet he never gets lost in them; the writing style is straightforward and vivid, occasionally ironic, but always dignified and distinguished.

In regard to the application of the mythological explanation to Holy Scripture, Strauss points out that De Wette, Eichhorn, Gabler, and others of his predecessors had long ago freely applied it to the Old Testament, and that various attempts had been made to portray the life of Jesus in accordance with the critical assumptions upon which his undertaking was based. He mentions especially Usteri as one who had helped to prepare the way for him. The distinction between Strauss and those who had preceded him upon this path consists only in this, that prior to him the conception of myth was neither truly grasped nor consistently applied. Its application was confined to the account of Jesus' coming into the world and of His departure from it, while the real kernel of the evangelical tradition—the sections from the Baptism to the Resurrection—was left outside the field of its application. Myth formed, to use Strauss's illustration, the lofty gateways at the entrance to, and at the exit from, the Gospel history; between these two lofty gateways lay the narrow and crooked streets of the naturalistic explanation.

In terms of applying mythological explanations to the Bible, Strauss notes that De Wette, Eichhorn, Gabler, and others before him had already started using this approach with the Old Testament. He specifically highlights Usteri as someone who helped pave the way for his work. The main difference between Strauss and his predecessors is that they didn't fully understand or consistently apply the concept of myth. Their focus was mainly on the story of Jesus' birth and death, while ignoring the core of the evangelical tradition—the parts from His Baptism to His Resurrection. As Strauss illustrates, myth served as the grand doorways at both the start and end of Gospel history; in between these two grand entrances lay the narrow, winding pathways of naturalistic explanations.

The principal obstacle, Strauss continues, which barred the way to a comprehensive application of myth, consisted in the supposition that two of our Gospels, Matthew and John, were reports of eyewitnesses; and a further difficulty was the offence caused by [pg 079] the word myth, owing to its associations with the heathen mythology. But that any of our Evangelists was an eyewitness, or stood in such relations with eyewitnesses as to make the intrusion of myth unthinkable, is a thesis which there is no extant evidence sufficient to prove. Even though the earthly life of the Lord falls within historic times, and even if only a generation be assumed to have elapsed between His death and the composition of the Gospels; such a period would be sufficient to allow the historical material to become intermixed with myth. No sooner is a great man dead than legend is busy with his life.

The main barrier, Strauss argues, to fully applying myth was the belief that two of our Gospels, Matthew and John, were written by people who witnessed the events firsthand. Another issue was the discomfort caused by the term "myth," due to its connections with pagan mythology. However, there is no sufficient evidence to support the idea that any of our Evangelists was an eyewitness or had such close ties to eyewitnesses that the introduction of myth would be impossible. Even though Jesus' life took place in historical times, and even assuming that only one generation passed between His death and the writing of the Gospels, that timeframe is enough for historical facts to blend with myth. As soon as a prominent person dies, legends start to shape their story.

Then, too, the offence of the word myth disappears for any one who has gained an insight into the essential character of religious myth. It is nothing else than the clothing in historic form of religious ideas, shaped by the unconsciously inventive power of legend, and embodied in a historic personality. Even on a priori grounds we are almost compelled to assume that the historic Jesus will meet us in the garb of old Testament Messianic ideas and primitive Christian expectations.

Then, the negativity around the word myth vanishes for anyone who understands the true nature of religious myth. It’s simply the historic representation of religious ideas, crafted by the unintentional creativity of legend, and represented in a historical figure. Even based on our assumptions, we almost have to believe that the historical Jesus will appear dressed in the old Testament Messianic concepts and early Christian expectations.

The main distinction between Strauss and his predecessors consisted in the fact that they asked themselves anxiously how much of the historical life of Jesus would remain as a foundation for religion if they dared to apply the conception of myth consistently, while for him this question had no terrors. He claims in his preface that he possessed one advantage over all the critical and learned theologians of his time without which nothing can be accomplished in the domain of history—the inner emancipation of thought and feeling in regard to certain religious and dogmatic prepossessions which he had early attained as a result of his philosophic studies. Hegel's philosophy had set him free, giving him a clear conception of the relationship of idea and reality, leading him to a higher plane of Christological speculation, and opening his eyes to the mystic interpenetration of finitude and infinity, God and man.

The main difference between Strauss and those who came before him was that they worried about how much of Jesus's historical life would still support religion if they fully embraced the idea of myth, while he found that question irrelevant. In his preface, he states that he had one advantage over all the critical and knowledgeable theologians of his time, which is essential for achieving anything in the field of history—his mental and emotional freedom from certain religious and dogmatic beliefs that he had developed early on through his philosophical studies. Hegel's philosophy liberated him, providing him with a clear understanding of the relationship between ideas and reality, allowing him to explore deeper Christological theories, and revealing the mystical connection between the finite and the infinite, God and humanity.

God-manhood, the highest idea conceived by human thought, is actually realised in the historic personality of Jesus. But while conventional thinking supposes that this phenomenal realisation must be perfect, true thought, which has attained by genuine critical reasoning to a higher freedom, knows that no idea can realise itself perfectly on the historic plane, and that its truth does not depend on the proof of its having received perfect external representation, but that its perfection comes about through that which the idea carries into history, or through the way in which history is sublimated into idea. For this reason it is in the last analysis indifferent to what extent God-manhood has been realised in the person of Jesus; the important thing is that the idea is now alive in the common consciousness of those who have been [pg 080] prepared to receive it by its manifestation in sensible form, and of whose thought and imagination that historical personality took such complete possession, that for them the unity of Godhood and manhood assumed in Him enters into the common consciousness, and the “moments” which constitute the outward course of His life reproduce themselves in them in a spiritual fashion.

God-manhood, the highest idea conceived by human thought, is actually realized in the historic figure of Jesus. However, while conventional thinking assumes that this remarkable realization must be perfect, true thought, which has reached a higher level of freedom through genuine critical reasoning, understands that no idea can completely realize itself in history. Its truth does not rely on how perfectly it has been represented externally, but on what the idea brings to history and how history elevates into idea. For this reason, in the end, it doesn't matter how much God-manhood has been realized in Jesus; what truly matters is that the idea is now alive in the shared consciousness of those who are prepared to receive it through its tangible manifestation. In their thoughts and imagination, that historical figure has taken such complete possession that for them, the unity of divinity and humanity as embodied in Him has entered into the collective consciousness, and the “moments” that make up the external events of His life are spiritually echoed within them.

A purely historical presentation of the life of Jesus was in that first period wholly impossible; what was operative was a creative reminiscence acting under the impulse of the idea which the personality of Jesus had called to life among mankind. And this idea of God-manhood, the realisation of which in every personality is the ultimate goal of humanity, is the eternal reality in the Person of Jesus, which no criticism can destroy.

A purely historical account of Jesus's life was completely impossible during that initial period; what was at play was a creative memory influenced by the idea that Jesus’s personality had inspired in people. This concept of God-manhood, which is the ultimate goal of humanity realized in each individual, is the timeless truth found in the Person of Jesus that no criticism can erase.

However far criticism may go in proving the reaction of the idea upon the presentment of the historical course of the life of Jesus, the fact that Jesus represented that idea and called it to life among mankind is something real, something that no criticism can annul. It is alive thenceforward—to this day, and for ever more.

However far criticism may go in showing how the idea reacted to the way the history of Jesus is presented, the fact that Jesus embodied that idea and brought it to life among people is something real—something that no criticism can erase. It's alive from then on—to this day, and forever more.

It is in this emancipation of spirit, and in the consciousness that Jesus as the creator of the religion of humanity is beyond the reach of criticism, that Strauss goes to work, and batters down the rubble, assured that his pick can make no impression on the stone. He sees evidence that the time has come for this undertaking in the condition of exhaustion which characterised contemporary theology. The supernaturalistic explanation of the events of the life of Jesus had been followed by the rationalistic, the one making everything supernatural, the other setting itself to make all the events intelligible as natural occurrences. Each had said all that it had to say. From their opposition now arises a new solution—the mythological interpretation. This is a characteristic example of the Hegelian method—the synthesis of a thesis represented by the supernaturalistic explanation with an antithesis represented by the rationalistic interpretation.

It is in this emancipation of spirit and in the awareness that Jesus, as the creator of the religion of humanity, is beyond criticism that Strauss begins his work, confidently knowing that his efforts cannot affect the solid foundation. He recognizes that the time has come for this endeavor, given the exhausted state of contemporary theology. The supernatural explanation of Jesus' life events was followed by a rational one—a perspective that made everything supernatural versus another that aimed to explain all events as natural occurrences. Each perspective has exhausted its arguments. From their conflict now arises a new approach—the mythological interpretation. This exemplifies the Hegelian method: the synthesis of a dissertation represented by the supernatural explanation and an contrast represented by the rational interpretation.

Strauss's Life of Jesus is, therefore, like Schleiermacher's, the product of antithetic conceptions. But whereas in the latter the antitheses Docetism and Ebionism are simply limiting conceptions, between which his view is statically suspended, the synthesis with which Strauss operates represents a composition of forces, of which his view is the dynamic resultant. The dialectic is in the one case descriptive, in the other creative. This Hegelian dialectic determines the method of the work. Each incident of the life of Jesus is considered separately; first as supernaturally explained, and then as rationalistically explained, and the one explanation is refuted by the other. “By this means,” says Strauss in his preface, “the incidental advantage is secured that [pg 081] the work is fitted to serve as a repertory of the leading views and discussions of all parts of the Gospel history.”

Strauss's Life of Jesus is, like Schleiermacher's, the result of conflicting ideas. However, while Schleiermacher sees Docetism and Ebionism as just limiting concepts his view is stuck between, Strauss's synthesis represents a blend of forces, with his perspective being the dynamic outcome of that blend. The dialectic in one case is descriptive, while in the other, it's creative. This Hegelian dialectic shapes the method of the work. Each event in the life of Jesus is examined separately; first from a supernatural perspective, and then from a rational perspective, with each explanation countering the other. "In this way," Strauss states in his preface, "The incidental benefit is gained that the work is designed to act as a collection of the main ideas and discussions from all sections of the Gospel history."

In every case the whole range of representative opinions is reviewed. Finally the forced interpretations necessitated by the naturalistic explanation of the narrative under discussion drives the reader back upon the supernaturalistic. That had been recognised by Hase and Schleiermacher, and they had felt themselves obliged to make a place for inexplicable supernatural elements alongside of the historic elements of the life of Jesus. Contemporaneously there had sprung up in all directions new attempts to return by the aid of a mystical philosophy to the supernaturalistic point of view of our forefathers. But in these Strauss recognises only the last desperate efforts to make the past present and to conceive the inconceivable; and in direct opposition to the reactionary ineptitudes by means of which critical theology was endeavouring to work its way out of rationalism, he sets up the hypothesis that these inexplicable elements are mythical.

In every case, the full range of representative opinions is examined. Ultimately, the forced interpretations that come from the naturalistic explanation of the narrative in question push the reader back towards the supernatural. This was acknowledged by Hase and Schleiermacher, who felt they needed to include inexplicable supernatural elements alongside the historical aspects of Jesus' life. At the same time, many new attempts arose to reach back to the supernatural viewpoint of our ancestors through a mystical philosophy. However, Strauss sees these as merely desperate attempts to make the past relevant and to grasp the ungraspable; in direct contrast to the misguided efforts of critical theology trying to escape rationalism, he proposes that these inexplicable elements are mythical.

In the stories prior to the baptism, everything is myth. The narratives are woven on the pattern of Old Testament prototypes, with modifications due to Messianic or messianically interpreted passages. Since Jesus and the Baptist came into contact with one another later, it is felt necessary to represent their parents as having been connected. The attempts to construct Davidic genealogies for Jesus, show us that there was a period in the formation of the Gospel History during which the Lord was simply regarded as the son of Joseph and Mary, otherwise genealogical studies of this kind would not have been undertaken. Even in the story of the twelve-year-old Jesus in the temple, there is scarcely more than a trace of historical material.

In the stories before the baptism, everything is myth. The narratives are shaped by the patterns of Old Testament examples, with adjustments influenced by Messianic or messianically interpreted texts. Since Jesus and the Baptist only met later, it seems necessary to show their parents as having a connection. The efforts to create Davidic lineages for Jesus indicate that there was a time in the development of the Gospel History when Jesus was simply seen as the son of Joseph and Mary; otherwise, such genealogical studies wouldn't have been pursued. Even in the story of the twelve-year-old Jesus in the temple, there’s hardly more than a hint of historical evidence.

In the narrative of the baptism we may take it as certainly unhistorical that the Baptist received a revelation of the Messianic dignity of Jesus, otherwise he could not later have come to doubt this. Whether his message to Jesus is historical must be left an open question; its possibility depends on whether the nature of his confinement admitted of such communication with the outer world. Might not a natural reluctance to allow the Baptist to depart this life without at least a dawning recognition of the Messiahship of Jesus have here led to the insertion of a legendary trait into the tradition? If so, the historical residuum would be that Jesus was for a time one of the adherents of the Baptist, and was baptized by him, and that He soon afterwards appeared in Galilee with the same message which John had proclaimed, and even when He had outgrown his influence, never ceased to hold John in high esteem, as is shown by the eulogy which He pronounced upon him. But if the baptism of John was a baptism of [pg 082] repentance with a view to “him who was to come,” Jesus cannot have held Himself to be sinless when He submitted to it. Otherwise we should have to suppose that He did it merely for appearance' sake. Whether it was in the moment of the baptism that the consciousness of His Messiahship dawned upon Him, we cannot tell. This only is certain, that the conception of Jesus as having been endowed with the Spirit at His baptism, was independent of, and earlier than, that other conception which held Him to have been supernaturally born of the Spirit. We have, therefore, in the Synoptists several different strata of legend and narrative, which in some cases intersect and in some are superimposed one upon the other.

In the story of the baptism, we can confidently say that it’s not historical that John the Baptist received a revelation about Jesus' Messianic status; if he had, he wouldn’t have later doubted it. Whether his message to Jesus is historical remains uncertain; its likelihood depends on whether his imprisonment allowed for contact with the outside world. Perhaps a natural reluctance to let John leave this life without at least some recognition of Jesus as the Messiah led to the addition of a legendary element into the story. If that's the case, the historical fact would be that Jesus was initially one of John’s followers and was baptized by him. Shortly after, He appeared in Galilee preaching the same message that John had shared, and even when He surpassed John's influence, He continued to respect him, as evidenced by the praise He spoke of him. However, if John's baptism was a baptism of repentance in preparation for "him who was to come," Jesus couldn’t have considered Himself sinless by undergoing it. Otherwise, we would have to assume He did it just for show. We can't determine if His awareness of His Messianic identity appeared at the moment of baptism. What is certain, however, is that the idea of Jesus receiving the Spirit at His baptism existed independently and earlier than the belief that He was born of the Spirit in a supernatural way. Thus, the Synoptic Gospels contain several layers of legend and narrative that sometimes intersect and at other times overlap.

The story of the temptation is equally unsatisfactory, whether it be interpreted as supernatural, or as symbolical either of an inward struggle or of external events (as for example in Venturini's interpretation of it, where the part of the Tempter is played by a Pharisee); it is simply primitive Christian legend, woven together out of Old Testament suggestions.

The story of the temptation is equally lacking, regardless of whether it's seen as supernatural or as a symbol for internal conflict or external events (like in Venturini's interpretation, where a Pharisee takes on the role of the Tempter); it’s just a basic Christian legend, pieced together from Old Testament ideas.

The call of the first disciples cannot have happened as it is narrated, without their having known anything of Jesus beforehand; the manner of the call is modelled upon the call of Elisha by Elijah. The further legend attached to it—Peter's miraculous draught of fishes—has arisen out of the saying about “fishers of men,” and the same idea is reflected, at a different angle of refraction, in John xxi. The mission of the seventy is unhistorical.

The call of the first disciples couldn’t have happened as described if they didn’t know anything about Jesus beforehand; the way they were called is based on how Elisha was called by Elijah. The additional story attached to it—Peter’s miraculous catch of fish—comes from the saying about “fishers of people,” and the same idea appears, from a different perspective, in John 21. The mission of the seventy is not historical.

Whether the cleansing of the temple is historical, or whether it arose out of a Messianic application of the text, “My house shall be called a house of prayer,” cannot be determined. The difficulty of forming a clear idea of the circumstances is not easily to be removed. How freely the historical material has been worked up, is seen in the groups of stories which have grown out of a single incident; as, for example, the anointing of Jesus at Bethany by an unknown woman, out of which Luke has made an anointing by a penitent sinner, and John an anointing by Mary of Bethany.

Whether the cleansing of the temple actually happened or if it came from a Messianic interpretation of the text, "My house will be known as a house of prayer," is uncertain. It’s challenging to form a clear understanding of the circumstances. The extent to which the historical details have been modified is evident in the different versions of stories that have emerged from a single event; for instance, the anointing of Jesus at Bethany by an unknown woman has been transformed by Luke into an anointing by a repentant sinner, and by John into an anointing by Mary of Bethany.

As regards the healings, some of them are certainly historical, but not in the form in which tradition has preserved them. The recognition of Jesus as Messiah by the demons immediately arouses suspicion. It is doubtless rather to be ascribed to the tendency which grew up later to represent Him as receiving, in His Messianic character, homage even from the world of evil spirits, than to any advantage in respect of clearness of insight which distinguished the mentally deranged, in comparison with their contemporaries. The cure of the demoniac in the synagogue at Capernaum may well be historical, but, in other cases, the procedure is so often raised into the region of the miraculous that a psychical influence of Jesus upon the sufferer no longer suffices [pg 083] to explain it; the creative activity of legend must have come in to confuse the account of what really happened.

Regarding the healings, some of them are definitely historical, but not in the way tradition has kept them. The acknowledgment of Jesus as the Messiah by the demons immediately raises questions. This is likely more attributed to the later trend of depicting Him as receiving recognition for His Messianic role, even from the realm of evil spirits, rather than any clarity of insight that set the mentally ill apart from their peers. The healing of the demoniac in the synagogue at Capernaum may indeed be historical, but in other instances, the events are often elevated to the miraculous to the point that a psychological influence of Jesus on the afflicted person is no longer sufficient to explain it; the creative power of legend must have intervened to distort the account of what truly happened.

One cure has sometimes given rise to three or four narratives. Sometimes we can still recognise the influences which have contributed to mould a story. When, for example, the disciples are unable to heal the lunatic boy during Jesus' absence on the Mount of Transfiguration, we are reminded of 2 Kings iv., where Elisha's servant Gehazi tries in vain to bring the dead boy to life by using the staff of the prophet. The immediate healing of leprosy has its prototype in the story of Naaman the Syrian. The story of the ten lepers shows so clearly a didactic tendency that its historic value is thereby rendered doubtful.

One cure has sometimes inspired three or four different stories. Sometimes we can still see the influences that have shaped a narrative. For example, when the disciples can't heal the boy with seizures while Jesus is away on the Mount of Transfiguration, it reminds us of 2 Kings 4, where Elisha's servant Gehazi unsuccessfully tries to bring a dead boy back to life by using the prophet's staff. The immediate healing of leprosy has its counterpart in the story of Naaman the Syrian. The account of the ten lepers shows such a clear teaching purpose that its historical value is called into question.

The cures of blindness all go back to the case of the blind man at Jericho. But who can say how far this is itself historical? The cures of paralytics, too, belong rather to the equipment of the Messiah than to history. The cures through touching clothes, and the healings at a distance, have myth written on their foreheads. The fact is, the Messiah must equal, nay, surpass, the deeds of the prophets. That is why raisings from the dead figure among His miracles.

The healing of blindness all traces back to the story of the blind man at Jericho. But who can say how much of this is actually historical? The healings of paralytics also seem more like part of the Messiah's role than actual history. The healings that happen through touching clothing and the miracles performed from afar clearly carry a mythical quality. The truth is, the Messiah has to match, and even exceed, the actions of the prophets. That’s why miracles like bringing people back to life are included among His works.

The nature miracles, over a collection of which Strauss puts the heading “Sea-Stories and Fish-Stories,” have a much larger admixture of the mythical. His opponents took him severely to task for this irreverent superscription.

The nature miracles, which Strauss titles “Sea Tales and Fish Tales,” contain a much greater mix of the mythical. His critics harshly criticized him for this disrespectful title.

The repetition of the story of the feeding of the multitude arouses suspicion regarding the credibility of what is narrated, and at once invalidates the hypothesis of the apostolic authorship of the Gospel of Matthew. Moreover, the incident was so naturally suggested by Old Testament examples that it would have been a miracle if such a story had not found its way into the Life of Jesus. An explanation on the analogy of an expedited process of nature, is here, as in the case of the miracle at Cana also, to be absolutely rejected. Strauss allows it to be laughed out of court. The cursing of the fig-tree and its fulfilment go back in some way or other to a parable of Jesus, which was afterwards made into history.

The repeated story of feeding the thousands raises doubts about the credibility of the account, undermining the idea that the Apostle Matthew wrote the Gospel. Additionally, the story aligns so closely with examples from the Old Testament that it would be surprising if it hadn’t made its way into the narrative of Jesus’s life. Any explanation suggesting it was just a natural phenomenon should be completely dismissed, much like with the miracle at Cana. Strauss dismisses such explanations as laughable. The incident of the cursed fig tree and its outcome can be traced back to a parable of Jesus that was later turned into a historical event.

More important than the miracles heretofore mentioned are those which have to do with Jesus Himself and mark the crises of His history. The transfiguration had to find a place in the life of Jesus, because of the shining of Moses' countenance. In dealing with the narratives of the resurrection it is evident that we must distinguish two different strata of legend, an older one, represented by Matthew, which knew only of appearances in Galilee, and a later, in which the Galilaean appearances are excluded in favour of appearances in Jerusalem. In both cases, however, the narratives are mythical. In any attempt to explain [pg 084] them we are forced on one horn of the dilemma or the other—if the resurrection was real, the death was not real, and vice versa. That the ascension is a myth is self-evident.

More important than the previously mentioned miracles are those that relate to Jesus Himself and mark critical moments in His life. The transfiguration needed to be part of Jesus' experience because of Moses' glowing face. When looking at the resurrection stories, it's essential to differentiate between two layers of tradition: the earlier one, as seen in Matthew, which only mentions appearances in Galilee, and the later version, where Galilean appearances are left out in favor of those in Jerusalem. In both cases, however, the stories are mythical. Any attempt to explain them forces us into a dilemma—if the resurrection was real, then the death wasn't real, and vice versa. It's clear that the ascension is a myth.

Such, and so radical, are the results at which Strauss's criticism of the supernaturalistic and the rationalistic explanations of the life of Jesus ultimately arrives.

Such, and so extreme, are the results that Strauss's criticism of the supernatural and rational explanations of Jesus's life ultimately reaches.

In reading Strauss's discussions one is not so much struck with their radical character, because of the admirable dialectic skill with which he shows the total impossibility of any explanation which does not take account of myth. On the whole, the supernaturalistic explanation, which at least represents the plain sense of the narratives, comes off much better than the rationalistic, the artificiality of which is everywhere remorselessly exposed.

In reading Strauss's discussions, it's not so much the radical nature of his ideas that stands out, but rather the impressive way he demonstrates the complete inability to provide an explanation that ignores myth. Overall, the supernatural explanation, which at least reflects the straightforward meaning of the narratives, holds up much better than the rational explanation, the artificiality of which is relentlessly revealed everywhere.

The sections which we have summarised are far from having lost their significance at the present day. They marked out the ground which is now occupied by modern critical study. And they filled in the death-certificates of a whole series of explanations which, at first sight, have all the air of being alive, but are not really so. If these continue to haunt present-day theology, it is only as ghosts, which can be put to flight by simply pronouncing the name of David Friedrich Strauss, and which would long ago have ceased to “walk,” if the theologians who regard Strauss's book as obsolete would only take the trouble to read it.

The sections we've summarized are still quite relevant today. They laid the groundwork for what is now modern critical study. They clarified the death certificates of several explanations that, at first glance, seem valid but aren't really. If these explanations continue to linger in today's theology, it's just as ghosts that can be dispelled by merely mentioning David Friedrich Strauss. They would have faded away long ago if the theologians who think Strauss's book is outdated would just take the time to read it.

The results so far considered do not represent the elements of the life of Jesus which Strauss was prepared to accept as historical. He sought to make the boundaries of the mythical embrace the widest possible area; and it is clear that he extended them too far.

The results so far don't reflect the aspects of Jesus' life that Strauss was willing to acknowledge as historical. He aimed to widen the scope of the mythical to cover as much as possible, and it’s evident that he went overboard.

For one thing, he overestimates the importance of the Old Testament motives in reference to the creative activity of the legend. He does not see that while in many cases he has shown clearly enough the source of the form of the narrative in question, this does not suffice to explain its origin. Doubtless, there is mythical material in the story of the feeding of the multitude. But the existence of the story is not explained by referring to the manna in the desert, or the miraculous feeding of a multitude by Elisha.35 The story in the Gospel has far too much individuality for that, and stands, moreover, in much too closely articulated an historical connexion. It must have as its basis some historical fact. It is not a myth, though there is myth in it. Similarly with the account of the transfiguration. The substratum of historical fact in the life of Jesus is much more extensive than Strauss is prepared to admit. Sometimes he fails to see the foundations, because he proceeds like an explorer who, in working on the ruins of an Assyrian city, should cover up the most valuable [pg 085] evidence with the rubbish thrown out from another portion of the excavations.

For one thing, he overestimates the significance of the Old Testament themes when it comes to the creative aspects of the legend. He doesn’t realize that while he has clearly identified the source of the form of the narrative in many instances, that alone doesn’t explain its origin. Sure, there is mythical content in the story of feeding the multitude. But the existence of this story isn’t explained just by pointing to the manna in the desert or Elisha miraculously feeding a crowd. The story in the Gospel has too much individuality for that and is also tied too closely to historical context. It must be based on some historical fact. It isn’t a myth, even though it contains mythological elements. The same goes for the account of the transfiguration. The underlying historical facts in Jesus's life are much more extensive than Strauss is willing to acknowledge. Sometimes he fails to recognize the foundations because he acts like an explorer who, while working on the ruins of an Assyrian city, would bury the most valuable evidence under the debris from another part of the excavation.

Again, he sometimes rules out statements by assuming their impossibility on purely dialectical grounds, or by playing off the narratives one against another. The Baptist's message to Jesus is a case in point. This is connected with the fact that he often fails to realise the strong confirmation which the narratives derive from their connexion with the preceding and following context.

Again, he sometimes dismisses statements by assuming they can't be true based on purely argumentative reasons or by contrasting different narratives against each other. The Baptist's message to Jesus is a perfect example. This is linked to the fact that he often doesn't recognize the strong validation that the narratives get from their connection with the surrounding context.

That, however, was only to be expected. Who ever discovered a true principle without pressing its application too far?

That, however, was just to be expected. Who ever found a real principle without applying it too broadly?

What really alarmed his contemporaries was not so much the comprehensive application of the mythical theory, as the general mining and sapping operations which they were obliged to see brought to bear upon the Gospels.

What truly worried his contemporaries wasn’t just the widespread use of the mythical theory, but the extensive digging and undermining efforts they had to witness being applied to the Gospels.

In section after section Strauss cross-examines the reports on every point, down to the minutest detail, and then pronounces in what proportion an alloy of myth enters into each of them. In every case the decision is unfavourable to the Gospel of John. Strauss was the first to take this view. It is true that, at the end of the eighteenth century, many doubts as to the authenticity of this Gospel had been expressed, and Bretschneider, the famous General Superintendent at Gotha (1776-1848), had made a tentative collection of them in his Probabilia.36 The essay made some stir at the time. But Schleiermacher threw the aegis of his authority over the authenticity of the Gospel, and it was the favourite Gospel of the rationalists because it contained fewer miracles than the others. Bretschneider himself declared that he had been brought to a better opinion through the controversy.

In section after section, Strauss questions the reports on every point, down to the smallest detail, and then states how much myth is present in each of them. In every case, the conclusion is unfavorable to the Gospel of John. Strauss was the first to take this position. It’s true that by the end of the eighteenth century, many doubts about the authenticity of this Gospel had been raised, and Bretschneider, the well-known General Superintendent at Gotha (1776-1848), had made a tentative collection of them in his Probabilities.36 The essay caused quite a stir at the time. However, Schleiermacher supported the authenticity of the Gospel, and it became the preferred Gospel among rationalists because it included fewer miracles than the others. Bretschneider himself stated that he had come to a better opinion after the debate.

After this episode the Johannine question had been shelved for fifteen years. The excitement was, therefore, all the greater when Strauss reopened the discussion. He was opposing a dogma of critical theology, which, even at the present day, is wont to defend its dogmas with a tenacity beyond that of the Church itself.

After this episode, the Johannine question was put aside for fifteen years. So, the excitement was even greater when Strauss brought the discussion back up. He was challenging a core belief of critical theology, which, even today, tends to defend its principles with more stubbornness than the Church itself.

The luminous haze of apparent circumstantiality which had hitherto prevented men from recognising the true character of this Gospel is completely dissipated. Strauss shows that the Johannine representation of the life of Jesus is dominated by a theory, and that its portraiture shows the further development of the tendencies which are perceptible even in the Synoptists. He shows this, for example, in the case of the Johannine narrative of the baptism of Jesus, in which critics had hitherto seen the most credible account of what occurred, pointing out that it is just in this pseudo-simplicity that the process of bringing Jesus and the Baptist into the closest possible relations reaches its limit. [pg 086] Similarly, in regard to the call of the first disciples, it is, according to Strauss, a later postulate that they came from the Baptist's following and were brought by him to the Lord. Strauss does not scruple even to assert that John introduces imaginary characters. If this Gospel relates fewer miracles, the miracles which it retains are proportionately greater; so great, indeed, that their absolutely miraculous character is beyond the shadow of doubt; and, moreover, a moral or symbolical significance is added.

The bright haze of seeming circumstance that has kept people from seeing the true nature of this Gospel has completely lifted. Strauss demonstrates that the way John portrays the life of Jesus is shaped by a theory, and that his depiction shows the further development of tendencies already noticeable in the Synoptic Gospels. He illustrates this, for instance, in the Johannine account of Jesus' baptism, where critics have previously considered it the most reliable version of events, highlighting that it is precisely in this false simplicity that the effort to closely connect Jesus and the Baptist reaches its peak. [pg 086] Likewise, regarding the call of the first disciples, Strauss argues that it is a later assumption that they were followers of the Baptist and were brought to Jesus by him. Strauss even boldly claims that John creates fictional characters. While this Gospel features fewer miracles, the ones it does include are significantly greater; indeed, their miraculous nature is beyond question, and they also carry moral or symbolic significance.

Here, therefore, it is no longer the unconscious action of legend which selects, creates, or groups the incidents, but a clearly-determined apologetic and dogmatic purpose.

Here, then, it's no longer the unconscious action of legend that chooses, creates, or arranges the events, but a clearly defined apologetic and dogmatic intention.

The question regarding the different representations of the locality and chronology of the life of Jesus, had always been decided, prior to Strauss, in favour of the Fourth Gospel. De Wette makes it an argument against the genuineness of Matthew's Gospel that it mistakenly confines the ministry of Jesus to Galilee. Strauss refuses to decide the question by simply weighing the chronological and geographical statements one against the other, lest he should be as one-sided in his own way as the defenders of the authenticity of the Fourth Gospel were in theirs. On this point, he contents himself with remarking that if Jesus had really taught in Jerusalem on several occasions, it is absolutely unintelligible how all knowledge of this could have so completely disappeared from the Synoptic tradition; for His going up to the Passover at which He met His death is there represented as His sole journey to Jerusalem. On the other hand, it is quite conceivable that if Jesus had only once been in Jerusalem there would be a tendency for legend gradually to make several journeys out of this one, on the natural assumption that He regularly went up to the Feasts, and that He would proclaim His Gospel not merely in the remote province, but also in the capital.

The question about the different depictions of the location and timing of Jesus' life was always settled, before Strauss, in favor of the Fourth Gospel. De Wette argues against the authenticity of Matthew's Gospel by pointing out that it wrongly limits Jesus' ministry to Galilee. Strauss, however, avoids making a decision by simply comparing the chronological and geographical details, fearing he would be as biased in his own way as the supporters of the Fourth Gospel's authenticity were in theirs. He simply notes that if Jesus really did teach in Jerusalem multiple times, it's completely baffling how all knowledge of this could have vanished from the Synoptic tradition; His trip to Jerusalem for Passover, where He was arrested, is depicted as His only visit. Conversely, it's entirely possible that if Jesus had only been to Jerusalem once, legends would evolve to suggest several visits, based on the assumption that He regularly attended the Feasts and would share His message not just in the distant regions, but also in the capital.

From the triumphal entry to the resurrection, the difference between the Synoptic and Johannine narratives is so great that all attempts to harmonise them are to be rejected. How are we to reconcile the statement of the Synoptists that the ovation at the triumphal entry was offered by Galilaeans who accompanied him, with that of John, according to which it was offered by a multitude from Jerusalem which came out to welcome Jesus—who, moreover, according to John, was not coming from Galilee and Jericho—and escorted Him into the city. To suppose that there were two different triumphal entries is absurd.

From the triumphal entry to the resurrection, the differences between the Synoptic and Johannine accounts are so significant that any attempts to harmonize them should be dismissed. How can we reconcile the Synoptists' claim that the celebration at the triumphal entry was given by Galileans who were with Him, with John's version, which states it was given by a crowd from Jerusalem that came out to greet Jesus—who, according to John, wasn't coming from Galilee and Jericho—and led Him into the city? Assuming there were two separate triumphal entries is ridiculous.

But the decision between John and the Synoptists is not based solely upon their representation of the facts; the decisive consideration is found in the ideas by which they are respectively dominated. John represents a more advanced stage of the mythopoeic process, inasmuch as he has substituted for the Jewish Messianic conception, [pg 087] the Greek metaphysical conception of the Divine Sonship, and, on the basis of his acquaintance with the Alexandrian Logos doctrine, even makes Jesus apply to Himself the Greek speculative conception of pre-existence. The writer is aware of an already existing danger from the side of a Gnostic docetism, and has himself an apologetic Christology to propound, thus fighting the Gnostics as a Gnostic of another kind. That he is free from eschatological conceptions is not, from the historical point of view, an advantage, but very much the reverse. He is not unacquainted with eschatology, but deliberately transforms it, endeavouring to substitute for the expectation of the Second Coming of Christ, as an external event of the future, the thought of His inward presence.

But the choice between John and the Synoptists isn't just about how they present the facts; the key factor lies in the ideas that each is influenced by. John reflects a more developed stage in the myth-making process, as he has replaced the Jewish Messianic idea with the Greek philosophical concept of Divine Sonship. Drawing from his knowledge of the Alexandrian Logos doctrine, he even allows Jesus to refer to Himself using the Greek speculative idea of pre-existence. The writer is aware of the existing threat from Gnostic docetism and presents his own apologetic Christology, thereby countering the Gnostics while being a different type of Gnostic himself. His lack of eschatological views is not an advantage from a historical perspective; in fact, it's quite the opposite. He's familiar with eschatology but intentionally transforms it, attempting to shift the expectation of Christ's Second Coming as an external future event to the idea of His internal presence.

The most decisive evidence of all is found in the farewell discourses and in the absence of all mention of the spiritual struggle in Gethsemane. The intention here is to show that Jesus not only had a foreknowledge of His death, but had long overcome it in anticipation, and went to meet His tragic fate with perfect inward serenity. That, however, is no historical narrative, but the final stage of reverent idealisation.

The most conclusive evidence of all is in the farewell speeches and in the complete lack of any mention of the spiritual struggle in Gethsemane. The purpose here is to show that Jesus not only knew His death was coming, but had already come to terms with it and faced His tragic fate with total inner peace. However, that isn't a historical account; it's the last phase of respectful idealization.

The question is decided. The Gospel of John is inferior to the Synoptics as a historical source just in proportion as it is more strongly dominated than they by theological and apologetic interests. It is true that the assignment of the dominant motives is for Strauss's criticism mainly a matter of conjecture. He cannot define in detail the attitude and tendency of this Gospel, because the development of dogma in the second century was still to a great extent obscure. He himself admits that it was only subsequently, through the labours of Baur, that the positions which he had taken up in 1835 were rendered impregnable. And yet it is true to say that Johannine study has added in principle nothing new to what was said by Strauss. He recognised the decisive point. With critical acumen he resigned the attempt to base a decision on a comparison of the historical data, and allowed the theological character of the two lines of tradition to determine the question. Unless this is done the debate is endless, for an able man who has sworn allegiance to John will always find a thousand ways in which the Johannine data can be reconciled with those of the Synoptists, and is finally prepared to stake his life upon the exact point at which the missing account of the institution of the Lord's Supper must be inserted into the narrative.

The question is decided. The Gospel of John is less reliable as a historical source compared to the Synoptics because it is more influenced by theological and apologetic concerns. It’s true that identifying the main motivations is largely speculative in Strauss's critique. He can’t define the attitude and trends of this Gospel in detail since the development of doctrine in the second century remains largely unclear. He himself acknowledges that it was only later, through Baur's work, that the arguments he presented in 1835 became solid. Yet, it is accurate to say that Johannine studies have fundamentally added nothing new to what Strauss stated. He recognized the key issue. With sharp insight, he abandoned the attempt to base a conclusion on a comparison of the historical facts and let the theological nature of the two traditions shape the discussion. If this isn’t done, the debate goes on forever, because a skilled supporter of John will always find countless ways to reconcile the Johannine accounts with those of the Synoptics and will ultimately be ready to bet everything on the exact spot where the missing account of the institution of the Lord's Supper should be placed in the narrative.

This changed estimate of John carries with it a reversal of the order in which the Gospels are supposed to have originated. Instead of John, Luke, Matthew, we have Matthew, Luke, and John—the first is last, and the last first. Strauss's unsophisticated instinct freed Matthew from the humiliating vassalage to which [pg 088] Schleiermacher's aesthetic had consigned him. The practice of differentiating between John and the Synoptists, which in the hands of Schleiermacher and Hase had been an elegant amusement, now received unexpected support, and it at last became possible for the study of the life of Jesus to go forward.

This new estimate of John changes the order in which the Gospels are thought to have been written. Instead of John, Luke, Matthew, we now have Matthew, Luke, and John—the first becomes last, and the last becomes first. Strauss's straightforward insight freed Matthew from the embarrassing subordination to which Schleiermacher's aesthetic had subjected him. The practice of distinguishing between John and the Synoptics, which had been a sophisticated pastime for Schleiermacher and Hase, now gained unexpected backing, and it finally became possible for the study of Jesus's life to progress.

But no sooner had Strauss opened up the way than he closed it again, by refusing to admit the priority of Mark. His attitude towards this Gospel at once provokes opposition. For him Mark is an epitomising narrator, a mere satellite of Matthew with no independent light. His terse and graphic style makes on Strauss an impression of artificiality. He refuses to believe this Evangelist when he says that on the first day at Capernaum “the whole town” (Mark i. 33) came together before Peter's door, and that, on other occasions (Mark iii. 20, vi. 31), the press was so great that Jesus and His disciples had no leisure so much as to eat. “All very improbable traits,” he remarks, “the absence of which in Matthew is entirely to his advantage, for what else are they than legendary exaggerations?” In this criticism he is at one with Schleiermacher, who in his essay on Luke37 speaks of the unreal vividness of Mark “which often gives his Gospel an almost apocryphal aspect.”

But no sooner had Strauss opened the door than he shut it again by refusing to acknowledge Mark's importance. His view on this Gospel immediately stirs up opposition. To him, Mark is just a summarizing storyteller, a mere follower of Matthew with no original insight. Mark's concise and vivid writing style strikes Strauss as artificial. He doesn't believe the Evangelist when he claims that on the first day in Capernaum “the entire town” (Mark i. 33) gathered at Peter's door, or that at other times (Mark iii. 20, vi. 31) the crowd was so overwhelming that Jesus and His disciples didn’t even have time to eat. “All very unlikely traits,” he notes, "Not having those in Matthew works to his benefit, because what are they other than exaggerated legends?" In this critique, he agrees with Schleiermacher, who in his essay on Luke37 refers to the unrealistic vividness of Mark “which often gives his Gospel a nearly apocryphal appearance.”

This prejudice against Mark has a twofold cause. In the first place, this Gospel with its graphic details had rendered great service to the rationalistic explanation of miracle. Its description of the cure of the blind man at Bethsaida (Mark viii. 22-26)—whose eyes Jesus first anointed with spittle, whereupon he at first saw things dimly, and then, after he had felt the touch of the Lord's hand upon his eyes a second time, saw more clearly—was a veritable treasure-trove for rationalism. As Strauss is disposed to deal much more peremptorily with the rationalists than with the supernaturalists, he puts Mark upon his trial, as their accessory before the fact, and pronounces upon him a judgment which is not entirely unprejudiced. Moreover, it is not until the Gospels are looked at from the point of view of the plan of the history and the inner connexion of events that the superiority of Mark is clearly realised. But this way of looking at the matter does not enter into Strauss's purview. On the contrary, he denies that there is any traceable connexion of events at all, and confines his attention to determining the proportion of myth in the content of each separate narrative.

This bias against Mark has two main reasons. First, this Gospel, with its vivid details, has greatly contributed to the rational explanation of miracles. Its account of the healing of the blind man at Bethsaida (Mark viii. 22-26)—where Jesus first applied spittle to the man's eyes, causing him to see things only vaguely at first, and then, after feeling the Lord's hand on his eyes a second time, seeing more clearly—has been a real goldmine for rationalists. Strauss tends to criticize rationalists more harshly than supernaturalists, and he places Mark on trial as if he’s an accomplice in their views, delivering a judgment that isn’t completely unbiased. Furthermore, it’s only when the Gospels are examined in terms of the historical plan and the connections between events that Mark’s superiority becomes clear. However, this perspective isn’t part of Strauss’s approach. Instead, he claims there’s no discernible connection between events at all and focuses only on determining how much myth exists in each individual narrative.

Of the Synoptic question he does not, strictly speaking, take any account. That was partly due to the fact that when he wrote it was in a thoroughly unsatisfactory position. There was a confused welter of the most various hypotheses. The priority of Mark, [pg 089] which had had earlier champions in Koppe,38 Storr,39 Gratz,40 and Herder,41 was now maintained by Credner and Lachmann, who saw in Matthew a combination of the logia-document with Mark. The “primitive Gospel” hypothesis of Eichhorn, according to which the first three Gospels went back to a common source, not identical with any of them, had become somewhat discredited. There had been much discussion and various modifications of Griesbach's “dependence theory,” according to which Mark was pieced together out of Matthew and Luke, and Schleiermacher's Diegesentheorie,42 which saw the primary material not in a gospel, but in unconnected notes; from these, collections of narrative passages were afterwards formed, which in the post-apostolic period coalesced into continuous descriptions of the life of Jesus such as the three which have been preserved in our Synoptic Gospels.

Of the Synoptic question, he doesn't really take it into account. This was partly because, at the time he wrote, the situation was quite unsatisfactory. There was a chaotic mix of various hypotheses. The idea that Mark was the first Gospel, which had previously been supported by Koppe, Storr, Gratz, and Herder, was now backed by Credner and Lachmann, who believed that Matthew combined the logia document with Mark. Eichhorn's "primitive Gospel" hypothesis, which suggested that the first three Gospels stemmed from a common, unidentified source, had lost some credibility. There had been extensive discussion and various changes to Griesbach's "dependence theory," which proposed that Mark was compiled from Matthew and Luke, as well as Schleiermacher's “Diegesentheorie,” which argued that the main material wasn't in a gospel but in separate notes; from these notes, collections of narrative passages were eventually created, which in the post-apostolic period merged into continuous accounts of the life of Jesus, like the three that we have in our Synoptic Gospels.

In this matter Strauss is a sceptical eclectic. In the main he may be said to combine Griesbach's theory of the secondary origin of Mark with Schleiermacher's Diegesentheorie, the latter answering to his method of treating the sections separately. But whereas Schleiermacher had used the plan of John's Gospel as a framework into which to fit the independent narratives, Strauss's rejection of the Fourth Gospel left him without any means of connecting the sections. He makes a point, indeed, of sharply emphasising this want of connexion; and it was just this that made his work appear so extreme.

In this matter, Strauss is a skeptical eclectic. Primarily, he combines Griesbach's theory about the secondary origin of Mark with Schleiermacher's Diegesis theory, the latter corresponding to his method of treating the sections separately. However, while Schleiermacher used the structure of John's Gospel as a framework to fit the independent narratives, Strauss's rejection of the Fourth Gospel left him without any way to connect the sections. He actually emphasizes this lack of connection, which is exactly what made his work seem so extreme.

The Synoptic discourses, like the Johannine, are composite structures, created by later tradition out of sayings which originally belonged to different times and circumstances, arranged under certain leading ideas so as to form connected discourses. The sermon on the mount, the discourse at the sending forth of the twelve, the great parable-discourse, the polemic against the Pharisees, have all been gradually formed like geological deposits. So far as the original juxtaposition may be supposed to have been here and there preserved, Matthew is doubtless the most trustworthy authority for it. “From the comparison which we have been making,” says Strauss in one passage, “we can already see that the hard grit of these sayings of Jesus (die körnigen Reden Jesu) has not indeed been dissolved by the flood of oral tradition, but they have often been washed away from their original position and like rolling pebbles (Gerölle) have been deposited in places to which [pg 090] they do not properly belong.”43 And, moreover, we find this distinction between the first three Evangelists, viz. that Matthew is a skilful collector who, while he is far from having been able always to give the original connexion, has at least known how to bring related passages aptly together, whereas in the other two many fragmentary sayings have been left exactly where chance had deposited them, which was generally in the interstices between the larger masses of discourse. Luke, indeed, has in some cases made an effort to give them an artistic setting, which is, however, by no means a satisfactory substitute for the natural connexion.

The Synoptic discourses, similar to the Johannine, are made up of different parts that were put together later from sayings that originally came from various times and situations. These were organized around certain key ideas to create cohesive discourses. The Sermon on the Mount, the discourse during the sending out of the twelve, the significant parable discourse, and the critical remarks against the Pharisees have all gradually formed like geological layers. Matthew is likely the most reliable source for preserving any original connections that may still be evident. "Based on the comparison we've been doing," Strauss notes in one section, "We can see that the essential meaning of these sayings of Jesus (die körnigen Reden Jesu) hasn't really been lost in the vast amount of oral tradition. However, they have often been relocated from their original contexts and, like rolling stones (Gerölle), they have ended up in places where [pg 090] they don't quite belong." 43 Additionally, we see a distinction among the first three Evangelists: Matthew is a skilled collector who, while not always able to maintain the original connections, has at least managed to bring related passages together effectively. In contrast, the other two evangelists often left many fragmented sayings exactly where chance placed them, which was typically in the gaps between larger sections of discourse. Luke has, in some instances, tried to give them a more artistic arrangement, but that doesn’t really serve as a satisfactory substitute for the natural connections.

It is in his criticism of the parables that Strauss is most extreme. He starts out from the assumption that they have mutually influenced one another, and that those which may possibly be genuine have only been preserved in a secondary form. In the parable of the marriage supper of the king's son, for example, he confidently assumes that the conduct of the invited guests, who finally ill-treated and slew the messengers, and the question why the guest is not wearing a wedding-garment are secondary features.

It is in his criticism of the parables that Strauss is the most radical. He begins with the belief that they have influenced each other and that any that might be authentic have only survived in a secondary form. In the parable about the marriage feast of the king’s son, for example, he confidently assumes that the behavior of the invited guests, who ultimately mistreated and killed the messengers, as well as the question of why the guest isn’t wearing a wedding garment, are secondary elements.

How external he supposes the connexion of the narratives to be is clear from the way in which he explains the juxtaposition of the story of the transfiguration with the “discourse while descending the mountain.” They have, he says, really nothing to do with one another. The disciples on one occasion asked Jesus about the coming of Elijah as forerunner; Elijah also appears in the story of the transfiguration: accordingly tradition simply grouped the transfiguration and the discourse together under the heading “Elijah,” and, later on, manufactured a connexion between them.

How external he thinks the connection between the narratives is clear from how he explains the placement of the story of the transfiguration alongside the “talking while going down the mountain.” He claims they really have nothing to do with each other. The disciples once asked Jesus about the coming of Elijah as a forerunner; Elijah also appears in the transfiguration story. Therefore, tradition simply grouped the transfiguration and the discourse together under the heading “Elijah,” and later created a connection between them.

The tendency of the work to purely critical analysis, the ostentatious avoidance of any positive expression of opinion, and not least, the manner of regarding the Synoptists as mere bundles of narratives and discourses, make it difficult—indeed, strictly speaking, impossible—to determine Strauss's own distinctive conception of the life of Jesus, to discover what he really thinks is moving behind the curtain of myth. According to the view taken in regard to this point his work becomes either a negative or a positive life of Jesus. There are, for instance, a number of incidental remarks which contain the suggestion of a positive construction of the life of Jesus. If they were taken out of their context and brought together they would yield a picture which would have points of contact with the latest eschatological view. Strauss, however, deliberately restricts his positive suggestions to these few detached remarks. He follows out no line to its conclusion. Each separate problem is indeed considered, and light is thrown upon it from various quarters with much critical [pg 091] skill. But he will not venture on a solution of any of them. Sometimes, when he thinks he has gone too far in the way of positive suggestion, he deliberately wipes it all out again with some expression of scepticism.

The tendency of the work towards purely critical analysis, the obvious avoidance of any clear expression of opinion, and especially the way it treats the Synoptists as just collections of stories and teachings, makes it hard—actually, nearly impossible—to grasp Strauss's unique view of Jesus's life, or to find out what he really believes lies behind the myth. Depending on how one interprets this, his work can be seen as either a negative or a positive portrayal of Jesus's life. For example, there are several incidental comments that hint at a positive understanding of Jesus's life. If these were taken out of their context and compiled, they would create a picture that aligns with the latest eschatological views. However, Strauss intentionally limits his positive suggestions to just these few scattered remarks. He doesn't follow any line of thought to its conclusion. Each specific issue is indeed examined, and insights are drawn from various perspectives with considerable critical skill. But he won't commit to a solution for any of them. Sometimes, when he feels he has suggested too much positively, he consciously retracts it with a statement of skepticism.

As to the duration of the ministry he will not even offer a vague conjecture. As to the connexion of certain events, nothing can, according to him, be known, since the Johannine outline cannot be accepted and the Synoptists arrange everything with an eye to analogies and association of ideas, though they flattered themselves that they were giving a chronologically arranged narrative. From the contents of the narratives, however, and from the monotonous recurrence of certain formulae of connexion, it is evident that no clear view of an organically connected whole can be assumed to be present in their work. We have no fixed points to enable us to reconstruct even in a measure the chronological order.

Regarding the length of the ministry, he won’t even make a vague guess. As for the connections between certain events, he believes that nothing can be known, since the framework in the Gospel of John can’t be relied upon and the Synoptic Gospels organize things based on similarities and related ideas, even though they thought they were providing a timeline that made sense. However, from the content of their accounts and the repetitive nature of certain linking phrases, it’s clear that there isn’t a coherent view of a connected whole in their writings. We lack definite points that would allow us to reconstruct any portion of the chronological order.

Especially interesting is his discussion of the title “Son of Man.” In the saying “the Son of Man is Lord also of the Sabbath day” (Matt. xii. 8), the expression might, according to Strauss, simply denote “man.” In other passages one gets the impression that Jesus spoke of the Son of Man as a supernatural person, quite distinct from Himself, but identified with the Messiah. This is the most natural explanation of the passage in Matt. x. 23, where he promises the disciples, in sending them forth, that they shall not have gone over the cities of Israel before the Son of Man shall come. Here Jesus speaks of the Messiah as if He Himself were his forerunner. These sayings would, therefore, fall in the first period, before He knew Himself to be the Messiah. Strauss does not suspect the significance of this incidental remark; it contains the germ of the solution of the problem of the Son of Man on the lines of Johannes Weiss. But immediately scepticism triumphs again. How can we tell, asks Strauss, where the title Son of Man is genuine in the sayings of Jesus, and where it has been inserted without special significance, merely from habit?

Especially interesting is his discussion of the title "Son of Man." In the saying "The Son of Man is also the Lord of the Sabbath." (Matt. xii. 8), the term might, according to Strauss, simply mean “dude.” In other passages, it seems that Jesus referred to the Son of Man as a supernatural figure, separate from Himself, yet associated with the Messiah. This is the most straightforward interpretation of the passage in Matt. x. 23, where he tells the disciples, as he sends them out, that they won’t have traveled through the cities of Israel before the Son of Man arrives. Here, Jesus refers to the Messiah as if He Himself were the forerunner. Therefore, these statements would fall into the first period, before He recognized Himself as the Messiah. Strauss doesn’t realize the importance of this casual remark; it holds the key to solving the problem of the Son of Man along the lines of Johannes Weiss. But skepticism quickly returns. How can we determine, Strauss asks, where the title Son of Man is authentic in Jesus' sayings, and where it has been added without special meaning, just out of habit?

Not less insoluble, in his opinion, is the question regarding the point of time at which Jesus claimed the Messianic dignity for Himself. “Whereas in John,” Strauss remarks, “Jesus remains constant in His avowal, his disciples and followers constant in their conviction, that He is the Messiah; in the Synoptics, on the other hand, there are, so to speak, relapses to be observed; so that, in the case of the disciples and the people generally, the conviction of Jesus' Messiahship expressed on earlier occasions, sometimes, in the course of the narrative, disappears again and gives place to a much lower view of Him; and even Jesus Himself, in comparison with His earlier unambiguous declaration, is more reserved on later occasions.” The account of the confession of the Messiahship at Caesarea Philippi, where Jesus pronounces Peter blessed because of [pg 092] his confession, and at the same time forbids the Twelve to speak of it, is unintelligible, since according to this same Gospel His Messiahship had been mooted by the disciples on several previous occasions, and had been acknowledged by the demoniacs. The Synoptists, therefore, contradict themselves. Then there are the further cases in which Jesus forbids the making known of His Messiahship, without any reason whatever. It would, no doubt, be historically possible to assume that it only gradually dawned upon Him that He was the Messiah—in any case not until after His baptism by John, as otherwise He would have to be supposed to have made a pretence upon that occasion—and that as often as the thought that He might be the Messiah was aroused in others by something that occurred, and was suggested to Him from without, He was immediately alarmed at hearing spoken, aloud and definitely, that which He Himself had scarcely dared to cherish as a possibility, or in regard to which He had only lately attained to a clear conviction.

Not less complicated, in his view, is the question of when Jesus claimed the Messianic title for Himself. “While with John,” Strauss notes, "Jesus consistently acknowledges His role, and His disciples and followers truly believe He is the Messiah. However, in the Synoptic Gospels, we see some setbacks. For the disciples and the general public, the earlier belief in Jesus' Messianic identity sometimes diminishes and is replaced by a much lower opinion of Him. Even Jesus Himself, compared to His earlier clear statements, is more reserved in later instances." The account of the confession of His Messiahship at Caesarea Philippi, where Jesus calls Peter blessed because of [pg 092] his confession, while at the same time forbidding the Twelve to share it, is confusing, since according to this same Gospel, His Messiahship had been mentioned by the disciples on several earlier occasions and had even been recognized by demoniacs. Therefore, the Synoptists contradict themselves. Then there are further instances where Jesus prohibits revealing His Messiahship for no apparent reason. It might be historically plausible to assume that He gradually realized He was the Messiah—certainly not until after His baptism by John; otherwise, we would have to think He was pretending at that time—and that whenever others suggested that He might be the Messiah based on what was happening, He would quickly become alarmed at hearing aloud and definitively what He had scarcely dared to consider as a possibility, or which He had only recently come to a clear understanding of.

From these suggestions one thing is evident, namely, that for Strauss the Messianic consciousness of Jesus was an historical fact, and is not to be referred, as has sometimes been supposed, to myth. To assert that Strauss dissolved the life of Jesus into myth is, in fact, an absurdity which, however often it may be repeated by people who have not read his book, or have read it only superficially, does not become any the less absurd by repetition.

From these suggestions, one thing is clear: for Strauss, Jesus' Messianic consciousness was a historical fact and shouldn’t be dismissed as myth, as some have mistakenly believed. Claiming that Strauss turned Jesus' life into myth is actually nonsensical, and no matter how often it's said by those who haven't thoroughly read his book or have only skimmed it, it doesn't become any less ridiculous with repetition.

To come to detail, Jesus thought of His Messiahship, according to Strauss, in the form that He, although of human parentage, should after His earthly life be taken up into heaven, and thence should come again to bring in His Kingdom. “As, moreover, in the higher Jewish theology, immediately after the time of Jesus, the idea of the pre-existence of the Messiah was present, the conjecture naturally suggests itself that it was also present at the time when Jesus' thoughts were being formed, and that consequently, if He once began to think of Himself as the Messiah, He might also have referred to Himself this feature of the Messianic conception. Whether Jesus had been initiated, as Paul was, into the wisdom of the schools in such a way that He could draw this conception from it, is no doubt open to question.”

To get into the details, Jesus viewed His role as the Messiah, according to Strauss, in the sense that, despite being of human descent, He would be taken up into heaven after His life on earth and would return to establish His Kingdom. Moreover, in the progressive Jewish theology that developed shortly after Jesus, the idea of the Messiah's pre-existence became acknowledged, which naturally suggests that this concept may have influenced Jesus as He was developing His thoughts. So, if He started to view Himself as the Messiah, He might have incorporated this aspect of the Messianic idea. Whether Jesus had been educated, like Paul, in the wisdom of the schools to the point where He could draw this concept from it is definitely a topic for debate.

In his treatment of the eschatology Strauss makes a valiant effort to escape from the dilemma either spiritual or political” in regard to the Messianic plans of Jesus, and to make the eschatological expectation intelligible as one which did not set its hopes upon human aid, but on Divine intervention. This is one of the most important contributions to a real understanding of the eschatological problem. Sometimes one almost seems to be reading Johannes Weiss; as, for example, when Strauss explains that Jesus could promise His followers that they should sit on thrones without [pg 093] thinking of a political revolution, because He expected a reversal of present conditions to be brought about by God, and referred this judicial authority and kingly rule to the time of the παλιγγενεσία. “Jesus, therefore, certainly expected to restore the throne of David, and, with His disciples, to rule over a people freed from political bondage, but in this expectation He did not set His hopes on the sword of human followers (Luke xxii. 38, Matt. xxvi. 52), but upon the legions of angels which His heavenly Father could give Him (Matt. xxvi. 53). When He speaks of the coming of His Messianic glory, it is with angels and heavenly powers that He surrounds Himself (Matt. xvi. 27, xxiv. 30 ff., xxv. 31). Before the majesty of the Son of Man coming in the clouds of heaven the nations will submit without striking a blow, and at the sound of the angel's trumpet-blast will, with the dead who shall then arise, range themselves before Him and His disciples for judgment. All this Jesus did not purpose to bring about by any arbitrary action of His own, but left it to His heavenly Father, who alone knew the right moment for this catastrophic change (Mark xiii. 32), to give Him the signal of its coming; and He did not waver in His faith even when death came upon Him before its realisation. Any one who shrinks from adopting this view of the Messianic background of Jesus' plans, because he fears by so doing to make Jesus a visionary enthusiast, must remember how exactly these hopes corresponded to the long-cherished Messianic expectation of the Jews; and how easily, on the supernaturalistic assumptions of the period and among a people which preserved so strict an isolation as the Jews, an ideal which was in itself fantastic, if it were the national ideal and had some true and good features, could take possession of the mind even of one who was not inclined to fanaticism.”

In his exploration of eschatology, Strauss makes a strong effort to break free from the dilemma of “either spiritual or political” regarding Jesus' Messianic plans, aiming to explain eschatological expectation as one that relies not on human assistance but on Divine intervention. This is one of the key contributions to genuinely understanding the eschatological issue. At times, it almost feels like reading Johannes Weiss; for instance, when Strauss clarifies that Jesus could assure His followers they would sit on thrones without considering a political revolution because He anticipated a change in current conditions brought about by God, attributing this judicial authority and royal rule to the time of the παλιγγενεσία. “Jesus, therefore, certainly expected to restore the throne of David and, along with His disciples, to govern a people liberated from political oppression, but in this expectation, He did not rely on the strength of human followers (Luke xxii. 38, Matt. xxvi. 52), but on the armies of angels His heavenly Father could provide for Him (Matt. xxvi. 53). When He discusses the arrival of His Messianic glory, He surrounds Himself with angels and heavenly powers (Matt. xvi. 27, xxiv. 30 ff., xxv. 31). Before the majesty of the Son of Man coming in the clouds of heaven, nations will yield without engaging in conflict, and at the sound of the angel's trumpet, will stand before Him and His disciples for judgment, along with the dead who will rise. Jesus did not intend to bring about all this through any arbitrary action of His own; He left it to His heavenly Father, who alone knew the perfect moment for this dramatic change (Mark xiii. 32), to signal its arrival. He remained steadfast in His faith even when death approached before its realization. Anyone hesitant to embrace this view of Jesus' Messianic plans, fearing it portrays Him as a whimsical dreamer, should remember how closely these hopes aligned with the long-held Messianic expectations of the Jews. It’s easy to see how, within the supernatural beliefs of the time and among a people as isolated as the Jews, an ideal could take root in someone not inclined to fanaticism, especially if it was a national ideal with some genuine admirable aspects.”

One of the principal proofs that the preaching of Jesus was eschatologically conditioned is the Last Supper. “When,” says Strauss, “He concluded the celebration with the saying, ‘I will not drink henceforth of the fruit of the vine until I drink it new with you in my Father's kingdom,’ He would seem to have expected that in the Messianic kingdom the Passover would be celebrated with peculiar solemnity. Therefore, in assuring them that they shall next partake of the Feast, not in the present age, but in the new era, He evidently expects that within a year's time the pre-Messianic dispensation will have come to an end and the Messianic age will have begun.” But it must be admitted, Strauss immediately adds, that the definite assurance which the Evangelists put into His mouth may after all only have been in reality an expression of pious hope. In a similar way he qualifies his other statements regarding the eschatological ideas of Jesus by recalling that we cannot determine the part which the expectations of primitive Christianity may have had in moulding these sayings.

One of the main pieces of evidence that Jesus' preaching was influenced by eschatology is the Last Supper. “When” says Strauss, “He wrapped up the celebration by saying, ‘I will not drink from the fruit of the vine again until I drink it new with you in my Father's kingdom,’ He seemed to think that in the Messianic kingdom, the Passover would be celebrated differently. So, when he tells them that they will next take part in the Feast, not in this current time, but in the new era, it’s clear he expects the pre-Messianic period to end and the Messianic age to begin within a year.” However, it must be acknowledged, Strauss quickly adds, that the definite assurance the Evangelists attribute to Him might actually just reflect a hopeful wish. He similarly qualifies his other remarks about Jesus' eschatological ideas by noting that we can’t determine how much the expectations of early Christianity influenced these statements.

[pg 094]

Thus, for example, the opinions which he expresses on the great Parousia discourse in Matt. xxiv. are extremely cautious. The detailed prophecies regarding the Second Coming which the Synoptists put into the mouth of Jesus cannot be derived from Jesus Himself. The question suggests itself, however, whether He did not cherish the hope, and make the promise, that He would one day appear in glory as the Messiah? “If in any period of His life He held Himself to be the Messiah—and that there was a period when He did so there can be no doubt—and if He described Himself as the Son of Man, He must have expected the coming in the clouds which Daniel had ascribed to the Son of Man; but it may be questioned whether He thought of this as an exaltation which should take place even in His lifetime, or as something which was only to take place after His death. Utterances like Matt. x. 23, xvi. 28 rather suggest the former, but the possibility remains that later, when he had begun to feel that His death was certain, his conception took the latter form, and that Matt. xxvi. 64 was spoken with this in view.” Thus, even for Strauss, the problem of the Son of Man is already the central problem in which are focused all the questions regarding the Messiahship and eschatology.

So, for example, the views he shares about the great Parousia discourse in Matt. xxiv. are very careful. The specific prophecies about the Second Coming that the Synoptists attribute to Jesus can’t be traced back to Jesus Himself. However, one might wonder if He didn't hold the belief, and make the promise, that He would eventually return in glory as the Messiah. “If at any point in His life He considered Himself the Messiah—and there’s no doubt that there was a time He did—and if He referred to Himself as the Son of Man, He must have anticipated the return in the clouds that Daniel mentioned for the Son of Man; however, it's unclear whether He thought this would happen during His life or only after His death. Statements like Matt. x. 23 and xvi. 28 suggest the former, but it’s possible that later, as He started to realize His death was approaching, His perspective shifted to the latter, and that Matt. xxvi. 64 was expressed with this understanding in mind.” Thus, even for Strauss, the issue of the Son of Man is already the central question that encompasses all the inquiries regarding the Messiahship and eschatology.

From all this it may be seen how strongly he had been influenced by Reimarus, whom, indeed, he frequently mentions. It would be still more evident if he had not obscured his historical views by constantly bringing the mythological explanation into play.

From all this, it's clear how much he was influenced by Reimarus, whom he often mentions. It would be even more obvious if he hadn't clouded his historical views by continually introducing the mythological explanation.

The thought of the supernatural realisation of the Kingdom of God must also, according to Strauss, be the starting-point of any attempt to understand Jesus' attitude towards the Law and the Gentiles, so far as that is possible in view of the conflicting data. The conservative passages must carry most weight. They need not necessarily fall at the beginning of His ministry, because it is questionable whether the hypothesis of a later period of increasing liberality in regard to the law and the Gentiles can be made probable. There would be more chance of proving that the conservative sayings are the only authentic ones, for unless all the indications are misleading the terminus a quo for this change of attitude is the death of Jesus. He no doubt looked forward to the abolition of the Law and the removal of the barriers between Jew and Gentile, but only in the future Kingdom. “If that be so,” remarks Strauss, “the difference between the views of Jesus and of Paul consisted only in this, that while Jesus expected these limitations to fall away when, at His second coming, the earth should be renewed, Paul believed himself justified in doing away with them in consequence of the first coming of the Messiah, upon the still unregenerated earth.”

The idea of the supernatural realization of the Kingdom of God must also, according to Strauss, be the starting point for any attempt to understand Jesus' attitude toward the Law and the Gentiles, as far as that is possible given the conflicting evidence. The conservative passages must be given the most weight. They don't necessarily have to be from the beginning of His ministry because it's uncertain whether the idea of a later period of increased openness regarding the Law and the Gentiles can be made likely. It might be more plausible to argue that the conservative sayings are the only authentic ones; unless all the signs are misleading, the starting point for this change in attitude is the death of Jesus. He certainly anticipated the end of the Law and the removal of the barriers between Jew and Gentile, but only in the future Kingdom. “If that’s the case,” Strauss notes, “the difference between the views of Jesus and Paul was simply this: while Jesus expected these limitations to disappear when, at His second coming, the earth would be renewed, Paul felt justified in abolishing them because of the first coming of the Messiah, on the still unregenerated earth.”

The eschatological passages are therefore the most authentic of all. If there is anything historic about Jesus, it is His assertion [pg 095] of the claim that in the coming kingdom He would be manifested as the Son of Man.

The eschatological passages are therefore the most genuine of all. If there's anything historical about Jesus, it's His declaration [pg 095] of the belief that in the future kingdom, He would be revealed as the Son of Man.

On the other hand, in the predictions of the passion and resurrection we are on quite uncertain ground. The detailed statements regarding the manner of the catastrophe place it beyond doubt that we have here vaticinia ex eventu. Otherwise the despair of the disciples when the events occurred could not be explained. Yet it is possible that Jesus had a prevision of His death. Perhaps the resolve to die was essential to His conception of the Messiahship and He was not forced thereto by circumstances. This we might be able to determine with certainty if we had more exact information regarding the conception of the suffering Messiah in contemporary Jewish theology; which is, however, not available. We do not even know whether the conception had ever existed in Judaism. “In the New Testament it almost looks as if no one among the Jews had ever thought of a suffering or dying Messiah.” The conception can, however, certainly be found in later passages of Rabbinic literature.

On the other hand, the predictions about the passion and resurrection are quite uncertain. The detailed accounts of how the events unfolded clearly indicate that we have here prophecy after the event. Otherwise, the disciples' despair when these events happened wouldn't make sense. However, it's possible that Jesus foresaw His death. Maybe the decision to die was crucial to how He viewed the Messiah role, and He wasn't just forced into it by circumstances. We could figure this out for sure if we had more precise information about the idea of the suffering Messiah in contemporary Jewish theology, which isn’t available. We don’t even know if this concept ever existed in Judaism. "In the New Testament, it almost seems like none of the Jews ever considered a Messiah who would suffer or die." However, this idea can definitely be found in later sections of Rabbinic literature.

The question is therefore insoluble. We must be content to work with possibilities. The result of a full discussion of the resolve to suffer and the significance attached to the suffering is summed up by Strauss in the following sentences. “In view of these considerations it is possible that Jesus might, by a natural process of thought, have come to see how greatly such a catastrophe would contribute to the spiritual development of His disciples, and in accordance with national conceptions, interpreted in the light of some Old Testament passages, might have arrived at the idea of an atoning power in His Messianic death. At the same time the explicit utterance which the Synoptists attribute to Jesus describing His death as an atoning sacrifice, might well belong rather to the system of thought which grew up after the death of Jesus, and the saying which the Fourth Gospel puts into His mouth regarding the relation of His death to the coming of the Paraclete might seem to be prophecy after the event. So that even in these sayings of Jesus regarding the purpose of His death, it is necessary to distinguish between the particular and the general.”

The question is therefore unsolvable. We have to be content working with possibilities. Strauss summarizes the results of a thorough discussion on the decision to endure suffering and its significance in the following sentences. Taking these points into account, it's possible that Jesus may have realized how much such a tragedy would contribute to the spiritual growth of His disciples. When viewed through the lens of national beliefs and certain Old Testament passages, He may have formed the idea that His Messianic death had the power to atone for sins. At the same time, the specific words that the Synoptists attribute to Jesus, describing His death as a sacrificial atonement, might actually reflect a perspective that developed after His death. The statement in the Fourth Gospel about His death and its link to the coming of the Paraclete could appear as a prophecy made retrospectively. Therefore, even in these statements from Jesus regarding the purpose of His death, it’s crucial to distinguish between the specific and the general.

Strauss's “Life of Jesus” has a different significance for modern theology from that which it had for his contemporaries. For them it was the work which made an end of miracle as a matter of historical belief, and gave the mythological explanation its due.

Strauss's "Life of Jesus" holds a different meaning for modern theology compared to what it meant for his contemporaries. For them, it was the work that put an end to believing in miracles as historical facts and gave proper recognition to mythological explanations.

We, however, find in it also an historical aspect of a positive character, inasmuch as the historic Personality which emerges from the mist of myth is a Jewish claimant of the Messiahship, whose world of thought is purely eschatological. Strauss is, therefore, no mere destroyer of untenable solutions, but also the prophet of a coming advance in knowledge.

We also see a positive historical aspect in it, as the historical figure that emerges from the haze of myth is a Jewish claimant to the Messiah, whose worldview is entirely focused on eschatology. Therefore, Strauss is not just a destroyer of flawed solutions, but also a harbinger of future knowledge advancements.

[pg 096]

It was, however, his own fault that his merit in this respect was not recognised in the nineteenth century, because in his “Life of Jesus for the German People” (1864), where he undertook to draw a positive historic picture of Jesus, he renounced his better opinions of 1835, eliminated eschatology, and, instead of the historic Jesus, portrayed the Jesus of liberal theology.

It was, however, his own fault that his contributions in this regard weren't recognized in the nineteenth century. In his "Life of Jesus for the German People" (1864), where he aimed to create a positive historical picture of Jesus, he abandoned his earlier views from 1835, removed eschatology, and instead of depicting the historical Jesus, he represented the Jesus of liberal theology.

[pg 097]

IX. Strauss's Critics and Supporters

David Friedrich Strauss. Streitschriften zur Verteidigung meiner Schrift über das Leben-Jesu und zur Charakteristik der gegenwärtigen Theologie. (Replies to criticisms of my work on the Life of Jesus; with an estimate of present-day theology.) Tübingen, 1837.

David Friedrich Strauss. Pamphlets supporting my work on the Life of Jesus and describing modern theology. (Responses to critiques of my work on the Life of Jesus; includes an evaluation of current theology.) Tübingen, 1837.

Das Leben-Jesu, 3te verbesserte Auflage (3rd revised edition). 1838-1839, Tübingen.

The Life of Jesus, 3rd revised edition. 1838-1839, Tübingen.

August Tholuck. Die Glaubwürdigkeit der evangelischen Geschichte, zugleich eine Kritik des Lebens Jesu von Strauss. (The Credibility of the Gospel History, with an incidental criticism of Strauss's Leben-Jesu.) Hamburg, 1837.

August Tholuck. The Reliability of Gospel History, along with a critique of Strauss's “Life of Jesus.”Hamburg, 1837.

Aug. Wilh. Neander. Das Leben Jesu-Christi. Hamburg, 1837.

Aug. Wilh. Neander. The Life of Jesus Christ. Hamburg, 1837.

Dr. Neanders auf höhere Veranlassung abgefasstes Gutachten über das Buch des Dr. Strauss' Leben-Jesu und das in Beziehung auf die Verbreitung desselben zu beachtende Verfahren. (Dr. Neander's report, drawn up at the request of the authorities, upon Dr. Strauss's Leben-Jesu and the measures to be adopted in regard to its circulation.) 1836.

Dr. Neander's report, created at the request of the authorities, about Dr. Strauss’s __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ “Life of Jesus” and the steps to be taken concerning its distribution. (Dr. Neander's report, prepared at the request of the authorities, about Dr. Strauss's "Life of Jesus" and the actions to be taken concerning its circulation.) 1836.

Leonhard Hug. Gutachten über das Leben-Jesu, kritisch bearbeitet von D. Fr. Strauss. (Report on D. Fr. Strauss's critical work upon the Life of Jesus.) Freiburg, 1840.

Leonhard Hug. Report on the Life of Jesus, critically edited by Dr. Fr. Strauss. Freiburg, 1840.

Christian Gottlob Wilke. Tradition und Mythe. Ein Beitrag zur historischen Kritik der kanonischen Evangelien überhaupt, wie insbesondere zur Würdigung des mythischen Idealismus im Leben-Jesu von Strauss. (Tradition and Myth. A Contribution to the General Historical Criticism of the Gospels; with special reference to the mythical idealism of Strauss's Leben-Jesu.) Leipzig, 1837.

Christian Gottlob Wilke. Tradition and Myth: A Contribution to the General Historical Criticism of the Gospels, with a particular emphasis on the mythical idealism in Strauss's __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. “Life of Jesus.”Leipzig, 1837.

August Ebrard. Wissenschaftliche Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte. (Scientific Criticism of the Gospel History.) Frankfort, 1842.

August Ebrard. Scientific Criticism of the Gospel History. Frankfurt, 1842.

Georg Heinr. Aug. Ewald. Geschichte Christus' und seiner Zeit. (History of Christ and His Times.) 1855. Fifth volume of the Geschichte des Volkes Israel.

Georg Heinr. Aug. Ewald. History of Christ and His Times. 1855. Fifth volume of the The History of the People of Israel.

Christoph Friedrich von Ammon. Die Geschichte des Lebens Jesu mit steter Rücksicht auf die vorhandenen Quellen. (History of the Life of Jesus with constant reference to the extant sources.) 3 vols. 1842-1847.

Christoph Friedrich von Ammon. The History of the Life of Jesus with a continuous emphasis on the available sources. 3 vols. 1842-1847.

Scarcely ever has a book let loose such a storm of controversy; and scarcely ever has a controversy been so barren of immediate result. The fertilising rain brought up a crop of toad-stools. Of the forty or fifty essays on the subject which appeared in the next [pg 098] five years, there are only four or five which are of any value, and even of these the value is very small.

Hardly ever has a book sparked such a whirlwind of debate; and hardly ever has a debate been so lacking in immediate outcome. The refreshing rain brought a surge of useless ideas. Out of the forty or fifty essays on the topic that came out in the next [pg 098] five years, only four or five are worthwhile, and even those have very little real value.

Strauss's first idea was to deal with each of his opponents separately, and he published in 1837 three successive Streitschriften.44 In the preface to the first of these he states that he has kept silence for two years from a rooted objection to anything in the nature of reply or counter-criticism, and because he had little expectation of any good results from such controversy. These essays are able, and are often written with biting scorn, especially that directed against his inveterate enemy, Steudel of Tübingen, the representative of intellectual supernaturalism, and that against Eschenmayer, a pastor, also of Tübingen. To a work of the latter, “The Iscariotism of our Days” (1835), he had referred in the preface to the second volume of his Life of Jesus in the following remark: “This offspring of the legitimate marriage between theological ignorance and religious intolerance, blessed by a sleep-walking philosophy, succeeds in making itself so completely ridiculous that it renders any serious reply unnecessary.”

Strauss's first idea was to address each of his opponents individually, and in 1837 he published three consecutive Pamphlets.44 In the preface to the first one, he mentions that he had remained silent for two years due to a deep-rooted objection to any sort of reply or counter-criticism, and because he didn’t expect any positive outcomes from such debates. These essays are skillful and often written with sharp sarcasm, especially aimed at his persistent foe, Steudel from Tübingen, who represents intellectual supernaturalism, and also at Eschenmayer, a pastor from Tübingen. Regarding the latter's work, “The Betrayal in Our Time” (1835), he made a reference in the preface to the second volume of his Life of Jesus, stating: "This result of the genuine union of theological ignorance and religious intolerance, endorsed by a mindless philosophy, manages to be so utterly absurd that a serious response is unnecessary."

But for all his sarcasm Strauss does not show himself an adroit debater in this controversy, any more than in later times in the Diet.

But despite all his sarcasm, Strauss doesn't come off as a skilled debater in this controversy, just like he didn't in later times at the Diet.

It is indeed remarkable how unskilled in polemics is this man who had produced a critical work of the first importance with almost playful ease. If his opponents made no effort to understand him rightly—and many of them certainly wrote without having carefully studied the fourteen hundred pages of his two volumes—Strauss on his part seemed to be stricken with a kind of uncertainty, lost himself in a maze of detail, and failed to keep continually re-formulating the main problems which he had set up for discussion, and so compelling his adversaries to face them fairly.

It's truly amazing how this guy, who created a hugely important critical work with what seemed like effortless ease, is so inexperienced in debates. If his opponents didn’t bother to understand him properly—and many certainly wrote without carefully going through the fourteen hundred pages of his two volumes—Strauss, on the other hand, appeared to be caught up in confusion, got lost in a tangle of details, and didn’t consistently reframe the key issues he had presented for discussion, failing to make his critics confront them head-on.

Of these problems there were three. The first was composed of the related questions regarding miracle and myth; the second concerned the connexion of the Christ of faith with the Jesus of [pg 099] history; the third referred to the relation of the Gospel of John to the Synoptists.

Of these problems, there were three. The first involved the related questions about miracle and myth; the second dealt with the connection between the Christ of faith and the Jesus of [pg 099] history; the third referred to the relationship between the Gospel of John and the Synoptic Gospels.

It was the first that attracted most attention; more than half the critics devoted themselves to it alone. Even so they failed to get a thorough grasp of it. The only thing that they clearly see is that Strauss altogether denies the miracles; the full scope of the mythological explanation as applied to the traditional records of the life of Jesus, and the extent of the historical material which Strauss is prepared to accept, is still a riddle to them. That is in some measure due, it must in fairness be said, to the arrangement of Strauss's own work, in which the unconnected series of separate investigations makes the subject unnecessarily difficult even for one who wishes to do the author justice.

It was the first that drew the most attention; more than half the critics focused solely on it. Despite this, they struggled to fully understand it. The only thing they clearly see is that Strauss completely rejects the miracles; the full scope of the mythological explanation applied to the traditional accounts of Jesus's life, as well as the extent of the historical evidence that Strauss is willing to accept, remains a mystery to them. This is partly due, it must be noted, to the organization of Strauss's own work, where the disjointed series of individual studies makes the topic unnecessarily complicated, even for those who want to give the author a fair assessment.

The attitude towards miracle assumed in the anti-Strauss literature shows how far the anti-rationalistic reaction had carried professedly scientific theology in the direction of supernaturalism. Some significant symptoms had begun to show themselves even in Hase and Schleiermacher of a tendency towards the overcoming of rationalism by a kind of intellectual gymnastic which ran some risk of falling into insincerity. The essential character of this new kind of historical theology first came to light when Strauss put it to the question, and forced it to substitute a plain yes or no for the ambiguous phrases with which this school had only too quickly accustomed itself to evade the difficulties of the problem of miracle. The mottoes with which this new school of theology adorned the works which it sent forth against the untimely troubler of their peace manifest its complete perplexity, and display the coquettish resignation with which the sacred learning of the time essayed to cover its nakedness, after it had succumbed to the temptation of the serpent insincerity. Adolf Harless of Erlangen chose the melancholy saying of Pascal: “Tout tourne bien pour les élus, jusqu'aux obscurités de l'écriture, car ils les honorent à cause des clartés divines qu'ils y voient; et tout tourne en mal aux reprouvés, jusqu'aux clartés, car ils les blasphèment à cause des obscurités qu'ils n'entendent pas.”45

The attitude towards miracles found in the anti-Strauss literature shows how far the reaction against rationalism has pushed supposedly scientific theology toward supernaturalism. Some noticeable signs had already appeared in Hase and Schleiermacher, indicating a trend to overcome rationalism through a sort of intellectual gymnastics that risked veering into insincerity. The true nature of this new form of historical theology became clear when Strauss challenged it, forcing it to provide straightforward yes or no answers instead of the vague phrases this school had quickly used to dodge the challenges of the miracle problem. The mottos that this new theological school used in their works against the unwelcome disruptor of their peace highlight their utter confusion and reveal the affected resignation with which the religious scholarship of the time tried to hide its shortcomings after succumbing to the allure of insincerity. Adolf Harless from Erlangen chose the somber saying of Pascal: "Everything goes well for the elected officials, even the ambiguities in writing, because they honor them for the divine clarity they perceive in them; and everything goes wrong for the rejected, even the clarity, because they blaspheme it due to the ambiguities they don't understand."45

Herr Wilhelm Hoffmann,46 deacon at Winnenden, selected Bacon's aphorism: “Animus ad amplitudinem mysteriorum pro modulo suo dilatetur, non mysteria ad angustias animi constringantur.” (Let the mind, so far as possible, be expanded to the greatness of the mysteries, not the mysteries contracted to the compass of the mind.)

Herr Wilhelm Hoffmann,46 deacon at Winnenden, chose Bacon's saying: "Let your mind be as open as possible to the vastness of the mysteries, rather than confining those mysteries to the boundaries of your understanding."

[pg 100]

Professor Ernst Osiander,47 of the seminary at Maulbronn, appeals to Cicero: “O magna vis veritatis, quae contra hominum ingenia, calliditatem, sollertiam facillime se per ipsam defendit.” (O mighty power of truth, which against all the ingenious devices, the craft and subtlety, of men, easily defends itself by its own strength!)

Professor Ernst Osiander,47 of the seminary at Maulbronn, appeals to Cicero: “O mighty power of truth, which effortlessly defends itself against all the clever schemes, tricks, and cunning of men with its own strength!”

Franz Baader, of Munich,48 ornaments his work with the reflection: “Il faut que les hommes soient bien loin de toi, ô Vérité! puisque tu supporte (sic!) leur ignorance, leurs erreurs, et leurs crimes.” (Men must indeed be far from thee, O Truth, since thou art able to bear with their ignorance, their errors, and their crimes!)

Franz Baader, of Munich, 48 ornaments his work with the reflection: “Truth, men must be really distant from you! You can tolerate (sic!) their ignorance, mistakes, and wrongdoings.”

Tholuck49 girds himself with the Catholic maxim of Vincent of Lerins: “Teneamus quod semper, quod ubique, quod ab omnibus creditum est.” (Let us hold that which has been believed always, everywhere, by all.)

Tholuck49 prepares himself with the Catholic principle from Vincent of Lerins: “Let's hold onto what has always been believed, everywhere, by everyone.”

The fear of Strauss had, indeed, a tendency to inspire Protestant theologians with catholicising ideas. One of the most competent reviewers of his book, Dr. Ullmann in the Studien und Kritiken, had expressed the wish that it had been written in Latin to prevent its doing harm among the people.50 An anonymous dialogue of the period shows us the schoolmaster coming in distress to the clergyman. He has allowed himself to be persuaded into reading the book by his acquaintance the Major, and he is now anxious to get rid of the doubts which it has aroused in him. When his cure has been safely accomplished, the reverend gentleman dismisses him with the following exhortation: “Now I hope that after the experience which you have had you will for the future refrain from reading books of this kind, which are not written for you, and of which there is no necessity for you to take any notice; and for the refutation of which, should that be needful, you have no [pg 101] equipment. You may be quite sure that anything useful or profitable for you which such books may contain will reach you in due course through the proper channel and in the right way, and, that being so, you are under no necessity to jeopardise any part of your peace of mind.”

The fear of Strauss did seem to inspire Protestant theologians to adopt more Catholic ideas. One of the most qualified reviewers of his book, Dr. Ullmann in the Studies and Critiques, wished it had been written in Latin to prevent it from causing harm among the public.50 An anonymous dialogue from that time shows a schoolmaster coming to the clergyman in distress. He allowed himself to be convinced by his friend the Major to read the book, and now he is eager to resolve the doubts it has raised in him. Once the clergyman has successfully helped him, he sends him off with this advice: “Now I hope that after what you've gone through, you’ll steer clear of books like these in the future—books that aren’t for you and don’t deserve your attention; and for which, if you ever need to refute them, you’re not equipped. Rest assured that anything useful or beneficial from these books will eventually reach you through the right sources, so you don’t have to jeopardize your peace of mind.”

Tholuck's work professedly aims only at presenting a “historical argument for the credibility of the miracle stories of the Gospels.” “Even if we admit,” he says in one place, “the scientific position that no act can have proceeded from Christ which transcends the laws of nature, there is still room for the mediating view of Christ's miracle-working activity. This leads us to think of mysterious powers of nature as operating in the history of Christ—powers such as we have some partial knowledge of, as, for example, those magnetic powers which have survived down to our own time, like ghosts lingering on after the coming of day.” From the standpoint of this spurious rationalism he proceeds to take Strauss to task for rejecting the miracles. “Had this latest critic been able to approach the Gospel miracles without prejudice, in the Spirit of Augustine's declaration, ‘dandum est deo, eum aliquid facere posse quod nos investigare non possumus,’ he would certainly—since he is a man who in addition to the acumen of the scholar possesses sound common sense—have come to a different conclusion in regard to these difficulties. As it is, however, he has approached the Gospels with the conviction that miracles are impossible; and on that assumption, it was certain before the argument began that the Evangelists were either deceivers or deceived.”

Tholuck's work supposedly aims only at presenting a "historical argument for the reliability of the miracle stories in the Gospels." "Even if we agree," he says at one point, “From the scientific perspective that no action can be attributed to Christ that exceeds the laws of nature, there remains space for a balanced understanding of Christ's miracle-working ability. This prompts us to think about mysterious natural forces as shaping the narrative of Christ—forces that we have some limited understanding of, like those magnetic powers that have continued into our own era, similar to ghosts that linger after the morning light.” From this flawed rational perspective, he criticizes Strauss for dismissing the miracles. “If this latest critic had been able to look at the Gospel miracles without bias, in the spirit of Augustine's statement, ‘dandum est deo, eum aliquid facere posse quod nos investigare non possumus,’ he would have definitely—since he is not only insightful as a scholar but also has good common sense—arrived at a different conclusion about these challenges. However, he approached the Gospels with the belief that miracles are impossible; and because of that assumption, it was clear even before the argument began that the Evangelists were either liars or misled.”

Neander, in his Life of Jesus,51 handles the question with more delicacy of touch, rather in the style of Schleiermacher. “Christ's miracles,” he explains, “are to be understood as an influencing of nature, human or material.” He does not, however, give so much [pg 102] prominence as Schleiermacher had done to the difficulty involved in the supposition of an influence exercised upon material nature. He repeats Schleiermacher's assertions, but without the imposing dialectic which in Schleiermacher's hands almost commands assent. In regard to the miracle at Cana he remarks: “We cannot indeed form any clear conception of an effect brought about by the introduction of a higher creative principle into the natural order, since we have no experience on which to base such a conception, but we are by no means compelled to take this extreme view as to what happened; we may quite well suppose that Christ by an immediate influence upon the water communicated to it a higher potency which enabled it to produce the effects of strong wine.” In the case of all the miracles he makes a point of seeking not only the explanation, but the higher symbolical significance. The miracle of the fig-tree—which is sui generis—has only this symbolical significance, seeing that it is not beneficent and creative but destructive. “It can only be thought of as a vivid illustration of a prediction of the Divine judgment, after the manner of the symbolic actions of the Old Testament prophets.”

Neander, in his Life of Jesus, approaches the topic with more sensitivity, somewhat like Schleiermacher. "Miracles of Christ," he explains, "should be seen as an influence on nature, whether it's human or material." However, he doesn't emphasize the challenges related to the idea of influencing the material world as much as Schleiermacher did. He reiterates Schleiermacher's points, but without the compelling arguments that made them hard to disagree with in Schleiermacher's writing. Regarding the miracle at Cana, he comments: "We can't really imagine an effect coming from introducing a higher creative principle into the natural world, since we don't have any experience to support this idea. However, we don't have to assume that this extreme interpretation is necessary; we can also consider that Christ, through a direct influence on the water, gave it a greater power that enabled it to produce the effects of strong wine." With all the miracles, he emphasizes finding not only the explanation but also the deeper symbolic meaning. The miracle of the fig tree— which is unique —has only this symbolic meaning, as it is not beneficial and creative but rather destructive. "It can only be viewed as a powerful example of a prediction of Divine judgment, similar to the symbolic actions of the Old Testament prophets."

With reference to the ascension and the resurrection he writes: “Even though we can form no clear idea of the exact way in which the exaltation of Christ from the earth took place—and indeed there is much that is obscure in regard to the earthly life of Christ after His resurrection—yet, in its place in the organic unity of the Christian faith, it is as certain as the resurrection, which apart from it cannot be recognised in its true significance.”

With reference to the ascension and the resurrection, he writes: "Even though we can't clearly envision exactly how Christ's ascension occurred—and much about His life on earth after His resurrection remains unclear—still, within the framework of the unified belief of Christianity, it is as certain as the resurrection itself, which can't be fully understood without it."

That extract is typical of Neander's Life of Jesus, which in its time was hailed as a great achievement, calculated to provide a learned refutation of Strauss's criticism, and of which a seventh edition appeared as late as 1872. The real piety of heart with which it is imbued cannot conceal the fact that it is a patchwork of unsatisfactory compromises. It is the child of despair, and has perplexity for godfather. One cannot read it without pain.

That excerpt is typical of Neander's Life of Jesus, which was considered a significant accomplishment in its time, aiming to offer a scholarly rebuttal to Strauss's criticism, and a seventh edition was released as recently as 1872. The genuine piety it expresses cannot hide the truth that it's a mix of unsatisfactory compromises. It is born out of despair and has confusion as its inspiration. Reading it is a painful experience.

Neander, however, may fairly claim to be judged, not by this work, but by his personal attitude in the Strauss controversy. And here he appears as a magnanimous and dignified representative of theological science. Immediately after the appearance of Strauss's book, which, it was at once seen, would cause much offence, the Prussian Government asked Neander to report upon it, with a view to prohibiting the circulation, should there appear to be grounds for doing so. He presented his report on the 15th of November 1835, and, an inaccurate account of it having appeared in the Allgemeine Zeitung, subsequently published it.52 In it he censures the work as being written from a too purely rationalistic point of view, but strongly urges the Government not to suppress it by an edict. He [pg 103] describes it as “a book which, it must be admitted, constitutes a danger to the sacred interests of the Church, but which follows the method of endeavouring to produce a reasoned conviction by means of argument. Hence any other method of dealing with it than by meeting argument with argument will appear in the unfavourable light of an arbitrary interference with the freedom of science.”

Neander, however, can rightfully be assessed not by this work but by his personal stance in the Strauss controversy. In this context, he comes across as a generous and dignified representative of theological science. Shortly after Strauss's book was published—which was quickly recognized as potentially offensive—the Prussian Government requested Neander to evaluate it to determine if its circulation should be banned. He submitted his report on November 15, 1835, and after an inaccurate version of it was published in the General Newspaper, he later released it himself.52 In his report, he criticizes the work for being too focused on rationalism but strongly advises the Government against suppressing it through an edict. He [pg 103] describes it as "A book that, you have to admit, threatens the Church's sacred interests, but tries to build a logical case through reasoning. So, any response to it that isn't addressing arguments with arguments looks like an unreasonable violation of academic freedom."

In holding that scientific theology will be able by its own strength to overthrow whatever in Strauss's Life of Jesus deserves to be overthrown, Neander is at one with the anonymous writer of “Aphorisms in Defence of Dr. Strauss and his Work,”53 who consoles himself with Goethe's saying—

In asserting that scientific theology can alone dismantle any elements of Strauss's Life of Jesus that need to be challenged, Neander aligns with the unnamed author of "Aphorisms in Support of Dr. Strauss and His Work,"53 who finds comfort in Goethe's quote—

The competent, even if it's wrong,
Works day by day, from house to house;
The capable, when it's truly
Works beyond all time.54
Work hard, and even if your goal is misguided,
Your work will have its moment;
Work hard and stand strong for the truth.
Your work will live on and continue to grow forever.

“Dr. Strauss,” says this anonymous writer, “does not represent the author's views, and he on his part cannot undertake to defend Dr. Strauss's conclusions. But it is clear to him that Dr. Strauss's work considered as a scientific production is more scientific than the works opposed to it from the side of religion are religious. Otherwise why are they so passionate, so apprehensive, so unjust?”

"Dr. Strauss," says this anonymous writer, “Does not represent the author's views, and he can't defend Dr. Strauss's conclusions. However, it's clear to him that Dr. Strauss's work, viewed as a scientific contribution, is more scientific than the religious counterarguments are religious. Otherwise, why are they so passionate, so anxious, so unfair?”

This confidence in pure critical science was not shared by Herr Privat-Docent Daniel Schenkel of Basle, afterwards Professor at Heidelberg. In a dreary work dedicated to his Göttingen teacher Lücke, on “Historical Science and the Church,”55 he looks for future salvation towards that middle region where faith and science interpenetrate, and hails the new supernaturalism which approximates to a scientific treatment of these subjects “as a hopeful phenomenon.” He rejoices in the violent opposition at Zurich which led to the cancelling of Strauss's appointment, regarding it as likely to exercise an elevating influence. A similarly lofty position is taken up by the anonymous author of “Dr. Strauss and the Zurich Church,”56 to which De Wette contributed a preface. [pg 104] Though professing great esteem for Strauss, and admitting that from the purely historical point of view he is in the right, the author feels bound to congratulate the Zurichers on having refused to admit him to the office of teacher.

This confidence in pure critical science wasn't shared by Herr Privat-Docent Daniel Schenkel from Basle, who later became a Professor at Heidelberg. In a dreary work dedicated to his Göttingen teacher Lücke, on “History, Science, and the Church,”55 he looks for future salvation towards that middle ground where faith and science overlap, and praises the new supernaturalism that approaches a scientific treatment of these subjects "as a promising phenomenon." He takes pleasure in the fierce opposition at Zurich that led to the cancellation of Strauss's appointment, viewing it as likely to have a positive impact. A similarly elevated stance is taken by the anonymous author of “Dr. Strauss and the Zurich Church,”56 which De Wette prefaced. [pg 104] Although expressing great respect for Strauss and acknowledging that he is correct from a purely historical perspective, the author feels compelled to congratulate the Zurichers for rejecting him from the teaching position.

The pure rationalists found it much more difficult than did the mediating theologians, whether of the older or younger school, to adjust their attitude to the new solution of the miracle question. Strauss himself had made it difficult for them by remorselessly exposing the absurd and ridiculous aspects of their method, and by refusing to recognise them as allies in the battle for truth, as they really were. Paulus would have been justified in bearing him a grudge. But the inner greatness of that man of hard exterior comes out in the fact that he put his personal feelings in the background, and when Strauss became the central figure in the battle for the purity and freedom of historical science he ignored his attacks on rationalism and came to his defence. In a very remarkable letter to the Free Canton of Zurich, on “Freedom in Theological Teaching and in the Choice of Teachers for Colleges,”57 he urges the council and the people to appoint Strauss because of the principle at stake, and in order to avoid giving any encouragement to the retrograde movement in historical science. It is as though he felt that the end of rationalism had come, but that, in the person of the enemy who had defeated it, the pure love of truth, which was the only thing that really mattered, would triumph over all the forces of reaction.

The pure rationalists found it much harder than the mediating theologians, whether from the older or younger school, to adjust their stance on the new approach to the miracle issue. Strauss had complicated things for them by relentlessly exposing the absurd and ridiculous sides of their method while refusing to acknowledge them as allies in the fight for truth, which they genuinely were. Paulus would have been justified in resenting him. However, the inner strength of that tough exterior man is revealed in his ability to set aside his personal feelings. When Strauss became the focal point in the struggle for the purity and freedom of historical science, he overlooked Strauss's attacks on rationalism and came to his defense. In a remarkable letter to the Free Canton of Zurich, on “Freedom in Theological Education and in the Selection of Instructors for Colleges,”57, he urges the council and the public to appoint Strauss because of the principle at stake, to avoid encouraging any backward movement in historical science. It's as if he sensed that the era of rationalism was ending, but that, through the very enemy who had defeated it, the pure love of truth—what truly mattered—would ultimately triumph over all the forces of reaction.

It would not, however, be true to say that Strauss had beaten rationalism from the field. In Ammon's famous Life of Jesus,58 in which the author takes up a very respectful attitude towards Strauss, there is a vigorous survival of a peculiar kind of rationalism inspired by Kant. For Ammon, a miraculous event can only exist when its natural causes have been discovered. “The sacred history is subject to the same laws as all other narratives of antiquity.” Lücke, in dealing with the raising of Lazarus, had thrown out the question whether Biblical miracles could be thought of historically at all, and in so doing supposed that he was putting their absolute character on a firmer basis. “We,” says Ammon, “give the opposite answer from that which is expected; only historically conceivable miracles can be admitted.” He cannot away with the constant confusion of faith and knowledge found in [pg 105] so many writers “who swim in an ocean of ideas in which the real and the illusory are as inseparable as salt and sea-water in the actual ocean.” In every natural process, he explains, we have to suppose, according to Kant, an interpenetration of natural and supernatural. For that very reason the purely supernatural does not exist for our experience. “It is no doubt certain,” so he lays it down on the lines of Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft, “that every act of causation which goes forth from God must be immediate, universal, and eternal, because it is thought as an effect of His will, which is exalted above space and time and interpenetrates both of them, but without abolishing them, leaving them undisturbed in their continuity and succession. For us men, therefore, all action of God is mediate, because we are completely surrounded by time and space, as the fish is by the sea or the bird by the air, and apart from these relations we should be incapable of apperception, and therefore of any real experience. As free beings we can, indeed, think of miracle as immediately Divine, but we cannot perceive it as such, because that would be impossible without seeing God, which for wise reasons is forbidden to us.” “In accordance with these principles, we shall hold it to be our duty in what follows to call attention to the natural side even of the miracles of Jesus, since apart from this no fact can become an object of belief.”

It wouldn't be accurate to say that Strauss had completely defeated rationalism. In Ammon's well-known *Life of Jesus,* in which the author shows a respectful attitude towards Strauss, there's a strong continuation of a unique form of rationalism influenced by Kant. For Ammon, a miraculous event can only be acknowledged when its natural causes are uncovered. “Sacred history follows the same principles as all other historical accounts.” Lücke, when discussing the raising of Lazarus, raised the question of whether biblical miracles can even be considered historically, and in doing so thought that he was solidifying their absolute nature. "We," says Ammon, "Provide the opposite answer to what people expect; only miracles that can be imagined within a historical context are acceptable." He struggles with the frequent mix-up of faith and knowledge found in [pg 105] many writers “who are lost in a sea of ideas where reality and illusion are as inseparable as salt and seawater in the real ocean.” In every natural process, he explains, we must assume, following Kant, a blending of natural and supernatural. For this reason, pure supernatural occurrences don't exist in our experience. "It's definitely true," he asserts along the lines of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, "Every act of causation from God must be immediate, universal, and eternal, understood as an effect of His will, which goes beyond space and time while still influencing both, without eliminating them, allowing them to remain continuous and in sequence. For us humans, all of God's actions are indirect, since we are completely surrounded by time and space, just like fish are in the sea or birds in the air. Without these relationships, we wouldn't be able to perceive anything, leading to no genuine experience. As free beings, we can think of miracles as directly from God, but we can't experience them that way, since that would mean seeing God, which is wisely forbidden to us." "Based on these principles, we consider it our duty to emphasize the natural aspect of the miracles of Jesus in what follows, because without this, no fact can become something to believe in."

It is only in this intelligible sense that the cures of Jesus are to be thought of as “miracles.” The magnetic force, with which the mediating theology makes play, is to be rejected. “The cure of psychical diseases by the power of the word and of faith is the only kind of cure in which the student of natural science can find any basis for a conjecture regarding the way in which the cures of Jesus were effected.”

It’s only in this understandable sense that Jesus’ healings are to be seen as "miracles." The idea of a magnetic force that the mediating theology promotes should be dismissed. “The healing of psychological disorders through the power of words and belief is the only type of healing that a natural science student can use as a basis for speculating about how Jesus healed people.”

In the case of the other miracles Ammon assumes a kind of Occasionalism, in the sense that it may have pleased the Divine Providence “to fulfil in fact the confidently spoken promises of Jesus, and in that way to confirm His personal authority, which was necessary to the establishment of His doctrine of the Divine salvation.”

In the case of the other miracles, Ammon takes on a sort of Occasionalism, meaning that it may have pleased Divine Providence "to actually fulfill the confidently made promises of Jesus, and in doing so to confirm His personal authority, which was essential for establishing His doctrine of Divine salvation."

In most cases, however, he is content to repeat the rationalistic explanation, and portrays a Jesus who makes use of medicines, allows the demoniac himself to rush upon the herd of swine, helps a leper, whom he sees to be suffering only from one of the milder forms of the disease, to secure the public recognition of his being legally clean, and who exerts himself to prevent by word and act the premature burial of persons in a state of trance. The story of the feeding of the multitude is based on some occasion when there was “a bountiful display of hospitality, a generous sharing of provisions, inspired by Jesus' prayer of thanksgiving and the [pg 106] example which He set when the disciples were inclined selfishly to hold back their own supply.” The story of the miracle at Cana rests on a mere misunderstanding, those who report it not having known that the wine which Jesus caused to be secretly brought forth was the wedding-gift which he was presenting in the name of the family. As a disciple of Kant, however, Ammon feels obliged to refute the imputation that Jesus could have done anything to promote excess, and calculates that the present of wine which Jesus had intended to give the bridal pair may be estimated as equivalent to not more than eighteen bottles.59 He explains the walking on the sea by claiming for Jesus an acquaintance with “the art of treading water.”

In most cases, however, he is happy to stick to a logical explanation and presents a Jesus who uses medicine, lets the possessed man run into the herd of pigs, helps a leper, who he sees is only dealing with a milder form of the disease, to gain public recognition of being clean, and actively works to prevent the premature burial of people in a trance state. The story of feeding the multitude is based on an occasion when there was “A generous show of hospitality, sharing food, inspired by Jesus' prayer of thanks and the example he set when the disciples wanted to selfishly hoard their supplies.” The miracle at Cana relies on a simple misunderstanding, as those reporting it didn't realize that the wine Jesus had secretly brought out was actually a wedding gift he was giving on behalf of the family. As a follower of Kant, Ammon feels it necessary to deny the suggestion that Jesus could have encouraged excess, estimating that the wine gift he intended for the newlyweds was no more than the equivalent of eighteen bottles.59 He explains Jesus walking on water by saying he had learned “the skill of treading water.”

Only in regard to the explanation of the resurrection does Ammon break away from rationalism. He decides that the reality of the death of Jesus is historically proved. But he does not venture to suppose a real reawakening to life, and remains at the standpoint of Herder.

Only regarding the explanation of the resurrection does Ammon deviate from rationalism. He concludes that the historical evidence for Jesus's death is solid. However, he doesn't dare to propose a genuine return to life and stays aligned with Herder's perspective.

But the way in which, in spite of the deeper view of the conception of miracle which he owes to Kant, he constantly falls back upon the most pedestrian naturalistic explanations, and his failure to rid himself of the prejudice that an actual, even if not a miraculous fact must underlie all the recorded miracles, is in itself sufficient to prove that we have here to do with a mere revival of rationalism: that is, with an untenable theory which Strauss's refutation of Paulus had already relegated to the past.

But despite his deeper understanding of the concept of miracles thanks to Kant, he keeps relying on very ordinary, natural explanations, and his inability to let go of the belief that a real, even if not miraculous, fact must support all the recorded miracles clearly shows that this is just a revival of rationalism. This is an unsustainable theory that Strauss's refutation of Paulus had already pushed into the past.

It was an easier task for pure supernaturalism than for pure rationalism to come to terms with Strauss. For the former Strauss was only the enemy of the mediating theology—there was nothing to fear from him and much to gain. Accordingly Hengstenberg's Evangelische Kirchenzeitung hailed Strauss's book as “one of the most gratifying phenomena in the domain of recent theological literature,” and praises the author for having carried out with logical consistency the application of the mythical theory which had formerly been restricted to the Old Testament and certain parts only of the Gospel tradition. “All that Strauss has done is to bring the spirit of the age to a clear consciousness of itself and of the necessary consequences which flow from its essential [pg 107] character. He has taught it how to get rid of foreign elements which were still present in it, and which marked an imperfect stage of its development.”

It was easier for pure supernaturalism than for pure rationalism to deal with Strauss. To supernaturalism, Strauss was merely the opponent of mediating theology—there was nothing to fear from him and a lot to gain. As a result, Hengstenberg's Evangelical Church Newspaper praised Strauss's book as “one of the most rewarding developments in recent theological literature,” and commended the author for logically applying the mythical theory that had previously been limited to the Old Testament and certain parts of the Gospel tradition. "All Strauss has done is make the spirit of the age clearly aware of itself and the necessary consequences that come from its essential character. He has demonstrated how to eliminate foreign elements that were still present, reflecting an incomplete stage of its development."

He has been the most influential factor in the necessary process of separation. There is no one with whom Hengstenberg feels himself more in agreement than with the Tübingen scholar. Had he not shown with the greatest precision how the results of the Hegelian philosophy, one may say, of philosophy in general, reacted upon Christian faith? “The relation of speculation to faith has now come clearly to light.”

He has been the most influential factor in the essential process of separation. There’s no one with whom Hengstenberg feels more aligned than with the Tübingen scholar. Had he not demonstrated with great clarity how the results of Hegelian philosophy, or philosophy in general, impacted Christian faith? "The connection between speculation and faith is now obvious."

“Two nations,” writes Hengstenberg in 1836, “are struggling in the womb of our time, and two only. They will be ever more definitely opposed to one another. Unbelief will more and more cast off the elements of faith to which it still clings, and faith will cast off its elements of unbelief. That will be an inestimable advantage. Had the Time-spirit continued to make concessions, concessions would constantly have been made to it in return.” Therefore the man who “calmly and deliberately laid hands upon the Lord's anointed, undeterred by the vision of the millions who have bowed the knee, and still bow the knee, before His appearing,” has in his own way done a service.

"Two countries," writes Hengstenberg in 1836, "are grappling in the context of our time, and only two. They will become more and more opposed to each other. Unbelief will slowly let go of the last bits of faith it clings to, while faith will eliminate its doubts. This will be a significant advantage. If the spirit of the times had kept compromising, it would have repeatedly encountered new compromises in return." Therefore, the person who "calmly and purposefully placed hands on the Lord's anointed, undeterred by the sight of the millions who have bowed their knees, and continue to bow their knees, before His presence," has contributed in his own way.

Strauss on his part escaped with relief from the musty atmosphere of the study—beloved by theology in carpet-slippers—to the bracing air of Hengstenberg's Kirchenzeitung. In his “Replies” he devotes to it some fifty-four pages. “I must admit,” he says, “that it is a satisfaction to me to have to do with the Evangelische Kirchenzeitung. In dealing with it one knows where one is and what one has to expect. If Herr Hengstenberg condemns, he knows why he condemns, and even one against whom he launches his anathema must admit that the attitude becomes him. Any one who, like the editor of the Evangelische Kirchenzeitung, has taken upon him the yoke of confessional doctrine with all its implications, has paid a price which entitles him to the privilege of condemning those who differ from his opinions.”60

Strauss, for his part, felt a sense of relief as he left the musty atmosphere of the study—favored by theologians in their cozy slippers—for the refreshing air of Hengstenberg's Church Newspaper. In his “Responses”, he dedicates around fifty-four pages to it. “I have to admit,” he says, "I find it satisfying to engage with the Evangelische Kirchenzeitung. When you interact with it, you know where you stand and what to expect. If Herr Hengstenberg issues a condemnation, he knows exactly why he does it, and even the individual targeted by his anathema must acknowledge that his position fits him well. Anyone, like the editor of the Evangelische Kirchenzeitung, who has taken on the burden of confessional doctrine along with all its implications has paid a price that gives him the right to condemn those who disagree with him."60

Hengstenberg's only complaint against Strauss is that he does not go far enough. He would have liked to force upon him the rôle of the Wolfenbüttel Fragmentist, and considers that if Strauss did not, like the latter, go so far as to suppose the apostles guilty of deliberate deceit, that is not so much from any regard for the historical kernel of Christianity as in order to mask his attack.

Hengstenberg's only issue with Strauss is that he doesn't go far enough. He wishes he could push Strauss into the role of the Wolfenbüttel Fragmentist and believes that Strauss's reluctance to accuse the apostles of intentional deceit isn't due to a respect for the historical core of Christianity, but rather a way to hide his criticism.

Even in Catholic theology Strauss's work caused a great sensation. Catholic theology in general did not at that time take up an attitude of absolute isolation from Protestant scholarship; [pg 108] it had adopted from the latter numerous rationalistic ideas, and had been especially influenced by Schleiermacher. Thus, Catholic scholars were almost prepared to regard Strauss as a common enemy, against whom it was possible to make common cause with Protestants. In 1837 Joseph Mack, one of the Professors of the Catholic faculty at Tübingen, published his “Report on Herr Dr. Strauss's Historical Study of the Life of Jesus.”61 In 1839 appeared “Dr. Strauss's Life of Jesus, considered from the Catholic point of view,”62 by Dr. Maurus Hagel, Professor of Theology at the Lyceum at Dillingen; in 1840 that lover of hypotheses and doughty fighter, Johann Leonhard Hug,63 presented his report upon the work.64

Even in Catholic theology, Strauss's work made a big impact. At that time, Catholic theology generally didn't completely isolate itself from Protestant scholarship; it had adopted many rationalistic ideas from the latter and had been particularly influenced by Schleiermacher. As a result, Catholic scholars were almost ready to see Strauss as a common adversary, enabling them to join forces with Protestants against him. In 1837, Joseph Mack, a professor at the Catholic faculty in Tübingen, published his “Report on Dr. Strauss's Historical Study of the Life of Jesus.”61 In 1839, “Dr. Strauss's Life of Jesus, viewed from the Catholic perspective,”62 was published by Dr. Maurus Hagel, Professor of Theology at the Lyceum in Dillingen; and in 1840, that lover of theories and bold fighter, Johann Leonhard Hug,63 presented his report on the work.64

Even French Catholicism gave some attention to Strauss's work. This marks an epoch—the introduction of the knowledge of German critical theology into the intellectual world of the Latin nations. In the Revue des deux mondes for December 1838, Edgar Quinet gave a clear and accurate account of the influence of the Hegelian philosophy upon the religious ideas of cultured Germany.65 In an eloquent peroration he lays bare the danger which was menacing the Church from the nation of Strauss and Hegel. His countrymen need not think that it could be charmed away by some ingenious formula; a mighty effort of the Catholic spirit was necessary, if it was to be successfully opposed. “A new barbarian invasion was rolling up against sacred Rome. The barbarians were streaming from every quarter of the horizon, bringing their strange gods with them and preparing to beleaguer the holy city. As, of yore, Leo went forth to meet Attila, so now let the Papacy put on its purple and come forth, while yet there is time, to wave back with an authoritative gesture the devastating hordes into that moral wilderness which is their native home.”

Even French Catholicism paid some attention to Strauss's work. This marks a significant moment—the introduction of German critical theology into the intellectual landscape of Latin nations. In the Review of Two Worlds for December 1838, Edgar Quinet provided a clear and precise account of how Hegelian philosophy influenced the religious views of educated Germany.65 In a powerful conclusion, he reveals the threat that Strauss and Hegel posed to the Church. His fellow countrymen shouldn’t think it could be dismissed with some clever formula; a strong effort from the Catholic spirit was necessary to effectively counter it. “A new barbarian invasion was rising against sacred Rome. The barbarians were approaching from all sides, bringing their unfamiliar gods and getting ready to attack the holy city. Just as Leo once confronted Attila, let the Papacy now wear its purple and step forward, while there’s still time, to firmly push back the destructive hordes into the moral wilderness that is their true home.”

Quinet might have done better still if he had advised the Pope to issue, as a counterblast to the unbelieving critical work of [pg 109] Strauss, the Life of Jesus which had been revealed to the faith of the blessed Anna Katharina Emmerich.66 How thoroughly this refuted Strauss can be seen from the fragment issued in 1834, “The Bitter Sufferings of Our Lord Jesus Christ,” where even the age of Jesus on the day of His death is exactly given. On that Maundy Thursday the 13th Nisan, it was exactly thirty-three years and eighteen weeks less one day. The “pilgrim” Clement Brentano would certainly have consented, had he been asked, to allow his note-books to be used in the sacred cause, and to have given to the world the Life of Jesus as it was revealed to him by this visionary from the end of July 1820 day by day for three years, instead of allowing this treasure to remain hidden for more than twenty years longer. He himself ascribed to these visions the most strictly historical character, and insisted on considering them not merely as reflections on what had happened, but as the immediate reflex of the facts themselves, so that the picture of the life of Jesus is given in them as in a mirror. Hug, it may be mentioned, in his lectures, called attention to the exact agreement of the topography of the passion story in Katharina's vision with the description of the locality in Josephus. If he had known her complete Life of Jesus he would doubtless have expressed his admiration for the way in which she harmonises John and the Synoptists; and with justice, for the harmony is really ingenious and skilfully planned.

Quinet could have done even better if he had suggested that the Pope release, as a response to the skeptical criticism of [pg 109] Strauss, the Life of Jesus that was unveiled to the faith of the blessed Anna Katharina Emmerich.66 The extent to which this refutes Strauss can be seen in the fragment published in 1834, "The Painful Sufferings of Our Lord Jesus Christ," which even states Jesus' age on the day of His death precisely. On that Maundy Thursday, the 13th Nisan, He was exactly thirty-three years, eighteen weeks, and one day old. The “traveler” Clement Brentano would surely have agreed, if asked, to let his notebooks be used for this sacred cause and to reveal to the world the Life of Jesus as it was shown to him by this visionary daily from late July 1820 over three years, instead of letting this treasure remain hidden for more than twenty additional years. He attributed the most strictly historical nature to these visions and insisted on viewing them not just as reflections of what happened, but as direct reflections of the facts themselves, so that the portrayal of Jesus' life is presented in them like a mirror. It’s worth mentioning that Hug pointed out in his lectures the precise agreement between the topography of the passion story in Katharina's vision and the description of the area in Josephus. If he had known her complete Life of Jesus, he would likely have praised the way in which she harmonizes John and the Synoptic Gospels; and rightly so, as the harmony is genuinely clever and skillfully crafted.

Apart from these merits, too, this Life of Jesus, written, it should be observed, earlier than Strauss's, contains a wealth of interesting information. John at first baptized at Aenon, but later was directed to remove to Jericho. The baptisms took place in “baptismal springs.”

Apart from these benefits, this Life of Jesus, written earlier than Strauss's, includes a lot of fascinating information. John initially baptized at Aenon, but later was told to move to Jericho. The baptisms occurred in "baptism springs."

Peter owned three boats, of which one was fitted up especially [pg 110] for the use of Jesus, and carried a complement of ten persons. Forward and aft there were covered-in spaces where all kinds of gear could be kept, and where also they could wash their feet; along the sides of the boat were hung receptacles for the fish.

Peter owned three boats, one of which was specially equipped for Jesus and could accommodate ten people. There were covered areas at the front and back of the boat for storing various gear and for washing their feet. Along the sides of the boat, there were containers for the fish.

When Judas Iscariot became a disciple of Jesus he was twenty-five years old. He had black hair and a red beard, but could not be called really ugly. He had had a stormy past. His mother had been a dancing-woman, and Judas had been born out of wedlock, his father being a military tribune in Damascus. As an infant he had been exposed, but had been saved, and later had been taken charge of by his uncle, a tanner at Iscariot. At the time when he joined the company of Jesus' disciples he had squandered all his possessions. The disciples at first liked him well enough because of his readiness to make himself useful; he even cleaned the shoes.

When Judas Iscariot became a disciple of Jesus, he was twenty-five years old. He had black hair and a reddish beard, but he wasn’t exactly ugly. He had a turbulent past. His mother was a dancer, and he was born out of wedlock; his father was a military tribune in Damascus. As an infant, he had been abandoned, but was rescued and later taken in by his uncle, a tanner in Iscariot. By the time he joined Jesus' group of disciples, he had wasted all his money. The other disciples initially liked him well enough because he was eager to help; he even cleaned their shoes.

The fish with the stater in its mouth was so large that it made a full meal for the whole company.

The fish with the state in its mouth was so big that it could feed the entire group.

A work to which Jesus devoted special attention—though this is not mentioned in the Gospels—was the reconciliation of unhappy married couples. Another matter which is not mentioned in the Gospels is the voyage of Jesus to Cyprus, upon which He entered after a farewell meal with His disciples at the house of the Canaanitish woman. This voyage took place during the war between Herod and Aretas while the disciples were making their missionary journey in Palestine. As they could not give an eyewitness report of it they were silent; nor did they make any mention of the feast to which the Proconsul at Salamis invited the Saviour. In regard to another journey, also, which Jesus made to the land of the wise men of the East, the “pilgrim's” oracle has the advantage of knowing more than the Evangelists.

A task that Jesus paid special attention to—although this isn’t mentioned in the Gospels—was helping unhappy married couples reconcile. Another event that isn’t mentioned in the Gospels is Jesus’ trip to Cyprus, which He took after having a farewell meal with His disciples at the home of a Canaanite woman. This trip happened during the conflict between Herod and Aretas while the disciples were on their missionary journey in Palestine. Since they couldn't provide an eyewitness account, they chose not to speak about it; neither did they mention the feast the Proconsul in Salamis invited Jesus to. Regarding another journey Jesus took to the land of the wise men from the East, the pilgrim's oracle knows more than the Evangelists.

In spite of these additional traits a certain monotony is caused by the fact that the visionary, in order to fill in the tale of days in the three years, makes the persons known to us from the Gospel history meet with the Saviour on several occasions previous to the meeting narrated in the Gospels. Here the artificial character of the composition comes out too clearly, though in general a lively imagination tends to conceal this. And yet these naïve embellishments and inventions have something rather attractive about them; one cannot handle the book without a certain reverence when one thinks amid what pains these revelations were received. If Brentano had published his notes at the time of the excitement produced by Strauss's Life of Jesus, the work would have had a tremendous success. As it was, when the first two volumes appeared at the end of the 'fifties, there were sold in one year three thousand and several hundred copies, without reckoning the French edition which appeared contemporaneously.

Despite these additional traits, a certain monotony arises from the fact that the visionary, to flesh out the narrative of three years, brings characters we know from the Gospel accounts together with the Savior on several occasions before the meeting described in the Gospels. Here, the artificial nature of the composition becomes too apparent, although a lively imagination usually masks this. Still, these naïve embellishments and inventions have an oddly appealing quality; you can’t handle the book without feeling a certain reverence when you consider the struggles involved in these revelations. If Brentano had published his notes during the excitement generated by Strauss's Life of Jesus, the work would have been incredibly successful. As it turned out, when the first two volumes were released at the end of the '50s, over three thousand copies sold in just one year, not including the French edition that came out at the same time.

[pg 111]

In the end, however, all the efforts of the mediating theology, of rationalism and supernaturalism, could do nothing to shake Strauss's conclusion that it was all over with supernaturalism as a factor to be reckoned with in the historical study of the Life of Jesus, and that scientific theology, instead of turning back from rationalism to supernaturalism, must move straight onward between the two and seek out a new path for itself. The Hegelian method had proved itself to be the logic of reality. With Strauss begins the period of the non-miraculous view of the Life of Jesus; all other views exhausted themselves in the struggle against him, and subsequently abandoned position after position without waiting to be attacked. The separation which Hengstenberg had hailed with such rejoicing was really accomplished; but in the form that supernaturalism practically separated itself from the serious study of history. It is not possible to date the stages of this process. After the first outburst of excitement everything seems to go on as quietly as before; the only difference is that the question of miracle constantly falls more and more into the background. In the modern period of the study of the Life of Jesus, which begins about the middle of the 'sixties, it has lost all importance.

In the end, however, all the work done by mediating theology, rationalism, and supernaturalism couldn’t change Strauss's conclusion that supernaturalism was no longer a relevant factor in the historical study of the Life of Jesus. Instead of moving back from rationalism to supernaturalism, scientific theology had to forge a new path between the two. The Hegelian method had shown itself to be the logic of reality. With Strauss, we enter the era of the non-miraculous perspective on the Life of Jesus; all other viewpoints seemed to exhaust themselves in opposition to him and soon gave up ground without waiting for a fight. The separation that Hengstenberg had celebrated was indeed realized, but it took the form of supernaturalism effectively distancing itself from serious historical study. It’s hard to pinpoint the exact stages of this process. After the initial wave of excitement, everything appeared to settle down as before; the only change was that the question of miracles started to fade more and more into the background. In the modern phase of the study of the Life of Jesus, beginning around the mid-1860s, it completely lost its significance.

That does not mean that the problem of miracle is solved. From the historical point of view it is really impossible to solve it, since we are not able to reconstruct the process by which a series of miracle stories arose, or a series of historical occurrences were transformed into miracle stories, and these narratives must simply be left with a question mark standing against them. What has been gained is only that the exclusion of miracle from our view of history has been universally recognised as a principle of criticism, so that miracle no longer concerns the historian either positively or negatively. Scientific theologians of the present day who desire to show their “sensibility,” ask no more than that two or three little miracles may be left to them—in the stories of the childhood, perhaps, or in the narratives of the resurrection. And these miracles are, moreover, so far scientific that they have at least no relation to those in the text, but are merely spiritless, miserable little toy-dogs of criticism, flea-bitten by rationalism, too insignificant to do historical science any harm, especially as their owners honestly pay the tax upon them by the way in which they speak, write, and are silent about Strauss.

That doesn’t mean the issue of miracles is resolved. From a historical perspective, it’s really impossible to settle it, as we can’t reconstruct how a series of miracle stories came about or how a series of historical events were turned into miracle tales, and these narratives must just be left with a question mark. What has been achieved is that the exclusion of miracles from our understanding of history has been widely recognized as a critical principle, so miracles no longer concern historians either positively or negatively. Modern scientific theologians who want to show their “sensitivity” ask for just a couple of small miracles to be preserved—in the childhood stories, perhaps, or in the resurrection narratives. Moreover, these miracles are so scientifically vetted that they have no connection to those in the text and are merely lifeless, pitiful little replicas of criticism, nibbled at by rationalism—too trivial to harm historical science, especially since their owners honestly acknowledge them when they speak, write, and remain silent about Strauss.

But even that is better than the delusive fashion in which some writers of the present day succeed in discussing the narratives of the resurrection “as pure historians” without betraying by a single word whether they themselves believe it to be possible or not. But the reason modern theology can allow itself these liberties is that the foundation laid by Strauss is unshakable.

But even that is better than the misleading way some writers today manage to talk about the resurrection accounts “as objective historians” without revealing in any way whether they actually believe it's possible or not. The reason modern theology can take such liberties is that the foundation laid by Strauss is solid.

Compared with the problem of miracle, the question regarding [pg 112] the mythical explanation of the history takes a very subordinate place in the controversy. Few understood what Strauss's real meaning was; the general impression was that he entirely dissolved the life of Jesus into myth.

Compared to the issue of miracles, the discussion about the mythical explanation of history is much less significant in the debate. Few people grasped what Strauss actually meant; most believed he completely turned the life of Jesus into a myth.

There appeared, indeed, three satires ridiculing his method. One showed how, for the historical science of the future, the life of Luther would also become a mere myth,67 the second treated the life of Napoleon in the same way;68 in the third, Strauss himself becomes a myth.69

There were definitely three satirical pieces mocking his approach. One depicted how, for future historical studies, Luther's life would turn into just a myth,67 the second did the same with Napoleon's life;68 in the third, Strauss himself becomes a myth.69

M. Eugène Mussard, “candidat au saint ministère,” made it his business to set at rest the minds of the premier faculty at Geneva by his thesis, Du système mythique appliqué à l'histoire de la vie de Jésus, 1838, which bears the ingenious motto οὐ σεσοφισμένοις μύθοις (not ... in cunningly devised myths, 2 Peter i. 16). He certainly did not exaggerate the difficulties of his task, but complacently followed up an “Exposition of the Mythical Theory,” with a “Refutation of the Mythical Theory as applied to the Life of Jesus.”

M. Eugène Mussard, "candidate for the ministry," made it his goal to ease the concerns of the leading faculty at Geneva with his thesis, On the Mythical System Used in the History of Jesus' Life, 1838, which features the clever motto οὐ σεσοφισμένοις μύθοις (not ... in cleverly devised myths, 2 Peter i. 16). He certainly didn't downplay the challenges of his task, but confidently followed up an "Explaining the Mythical Theory," with a "Disproving the Mythical Theory Related to the Life of Jesus."

The only writer who really faced the problem in the form in which it had been raised by Strauss was Wilke in his work “Tradition and Myth.”70 He recognises that Strauss had given an exceedingly valuable impulse towards the overcoming of rationalism and supernaturalism and to the rejection of the abortive [pg 113] mediating theology. “A keener criticism will only establish the truth of the Gospel, putting what is tenable on a firmer basis, sifting out what is untenable, and showing up in all its nakedness the counterfeit theology of the new evangelicalism with its utter lack of understanding and sincerity.” Again, “the approval which Strauss has met with, and the excitement which he has aroused, sufficiently show what an advantage rationalistic speculation possesses over the theological second-childishness of the new evangelicals.” The time has come for a rational mysticism, which shall preserve undiminished the honesty of the old rationalism, making no concessions to supernaturalism, but, on the other hand, overcoming the “truculent rationalism of the Kantian criticism” by means of a religious conception in which there is more warmth and more pious feeling.

The only writer who truly tackled the issue in the way Strauss raised it was Wilke in his work “Tradition and Myth.”70 He acknowledges that Strauss provided a highly valuable push toward moving beyond rationalism and supernaturalism, as well as rejecting the ineffective [pg 113] mediating theology. "A stronger critique will only reinforce the truth of the Gospel, establishing what's valid on a firmer foundation, discarding what's not valid, and revealing the flawed theology of the new evangelicalism, which demonstrates a total lack of understanding and sincerity." Furthermore, "The support Strauss has received and the excitement he has created clearly show the advantage of rational thinking over the naive theology of the new evangelicals." The time has arrived for a rational mysticism that preserves the integrity of old rationalism, making no concessions to supernaturalism, while also overcoming the “intense rationalism of Kant's critique” through a religious understanding that incorporates more warmth and genuine piety.

This rational mysticism makes it a reproach against the “mythical idealism” of Strauss that in it philosophy does violence to history, and the historic Christ only retains His significance as a mere ideal. A new examination of the sources is necessary to decide upon the extent of the mythical element.

This rational mysticism criticizes Strauss's "mythical idealism" for allowing philosophy to distort history, reducing the historic Christ to just an ideal with no real significance. A fresh look at the sources is required to determine how much of this is mythical.

The Gospel of Matthew cannot, Wilke agrees, have been the work of an eyewitness. “The principal argument against its authenticity is the absence of the characteristic marks of an eyewitness, which must necessarily have been present in a gospel actually composed by a disciple of the Lord, and which are not present here. The narrative is lacking in precision, fragmentary and legendary, tradition everywhere manifest in its very form.” There are discrepancies in the legends of the first and second chapters, as well as elsewhere, e.g. the stories of the baptism, the temptation, and the transfiguration. In other cases, where there is a basis of historic fact, there is an admixture of legendary material, as in the narratives of the death and resurrection of Jesus.

The Gospel of Matthew, as Wilke agrees, can't have been written by someone who witnessed the events. “The primary argument against its authenticity is the absence of clear signs from an eyewitness, which should have been included in a gospel genuinely written by one of the Lord's disciples, but are not present here. The narrative is vague, incomplete, and mythical, with tradition apparent in its very structure.” There are inconsistencies in the stories of the first and second chapters, as well as in other places, e.g. the accounts of the baptism, the temptation, and the transfiguration. In other cases, where there is some historical basis, there's a mix of legendary content, as seen in the accounts of Jesus' death and resurrection.

In the Gospel of Mark, Wilke recognises the pictorial vividness of many of the descriptions, and conjectures that in some way or other it goes back to the Petrine tradition. The author of the Fourth Gospel is not an eyewitness; the κατά (according to) only indicates the origin of the tradition; the author received it, either directly or indirectly, from the Apostle, but he gave to it the gnosticising dialectical form of the Alexandrian theology.

In the Gospel of Mark, Wilke notes the striking imagery in many of the descriptions and speculates that it somehow traces back to the teachings of Peter. The author of the Fourth Gospel wasn't a firsthand witness; the κατά (according to) only points to the source of the tradition. The author received it, either directly or indirectly, from the Apostle, but presented it in the gnostic-influenced dialectical style of Alexandrian theology.

As against the Diegesentheorie71 Wilke defends the independence and originality of the individual Gospels. “No one of the Evangelists knew the writing of any of the others, each produced an independent work drawn from a separate source.”

As opposed to the Diegesis theory71 Wilke argues for the independence and originality of the individual Gospels. "None of the Evangelists knew about each other's writings; each produced an independent work based on different sources."

In the remarks on points of detail in this work of Wilke's there is evidence of a remarkable grasp of the critical data; we already get a hint of the “mathematician” of the Synoptic problem, [pg 114] who, two years later, was to work out convincingly the literary argument for the priority of Mark. But the historian is quite subordinated to the literary critic, and, when all is said, Wilke takes up no clearly defined position in regard to Strauss's main problem, as is evident from his seeking to retain, on more or less plausible grounds, a whole series of miracles, among them the miracle of Cana and the resurrection.

In the comments on specific details in Wilke's work, there is clear evidence of a strong understanding of the critical data; we already get a sense of the math expert of the Synoptic problem, [pg 114] who, two years later, would convincingly develop the literary argument for Mark's priority. However, the historian is largely overshadowed by the literary critic, and ultimately, Wilke does not take a clearly defined stance on Strauss's main issue, as seen from his attempt to maintain, on somewhat plausible grounds, a whole series of miracles, including the miracle at Cana and the resurrection.

For most thinkers of that period, however, the question “myth or history” yielded in interest to the philosophical question of the relation of the historical Jesus to the ideal Christ. That was the second problem raised by Strauss. Some thought to refute him by showing that his exposition of the relation of the Jesus of history to the ideal Christ was not justified even from the point of view of the Hegelian philosophy, arguing that the edifice which he had raised was not in harmony with the ground-plan of the Hegelian speculative system. He therefore felt it necessary, in his reply to the review in the Jahrbücher für wissenschaftliche Kritik, to expound “the general relationship of the Hegelian philosophy to theological criticism,”72 and to express in more precise form the thoughts upon speculative and historical Christology which he had suggested at the close of the second volume of his “Life of Jesus.”

For most thinkers of that time, however, the question "myth or reality" became less interesting than the philosophical issue of how the historical Jesus relates to the ideal Christ. This was the second problem raised by Strauss. Some tried to counter him by arguing that his explanation of the connection between the historical Jesus and the ideal Christ was not justified, even from a Hegelian perspective, claiming that the structure he built didn't align with the foundation of the Hegelian speculative system. Consequently, he felt it necessary, in his response to the review in the Yearbooks for Scientific Criticism, to explain "the overall connection between Hegelian philosophy and theological criticism,"72 and to clarify his thoughts on speculative and historical Christology that he had hinted at the end of the second volume of his "Life of Jesus."

He admits that Hegel's philosophy is ambiguous in this matter, since it is not clear “whether the evangelical fact as such, not indeed in its isolation, but together with the whole series of manifestations of the idea (of God-manhood) in the history of the world, is the truth; or whether the embodiment of the idea in that single fact is only a formula of which consciousness makes use in forming its concept.” The Hegelian “right,” he says, represented by Marheineke and Göschel, emphasises the positive side of the master's religious philosophy, implying that in Jesus the idea of God-manhood was perfectly fulfilled and in a certain sense intelligibly realised. “If these men,” Strauss explains, “appeal to Hegel and declare that he would not have recognised my book as an expression of his meaning, they say nothing which is not in accordance with my own convictions. Hegel was personally no friend to historical criticism. It annoyed him, as it annoyed Goethe, to see the historic figures of antiquity, on which their thoughts were accustomed lovingly to dwell, assailed by critical doubts. Even if it was in some cases wreaths of mist which they took for pinnacles of rock, they did not want to have this forced upon their attention, nor to [pg 115] be disturbed in the illusion from which they were conscious of receiving an elevating influence.”

He acknowledges that Hegel's philosophy is unclear on this issue, as it is not obvious "whether the evangelical fact itself—not on its own, but along with the whole range of expressions of the idea (of God-manhood) throughout history—is the truth; or if the way that idea is represented in that one fact is simply a concept that our consciousness uses to make sense of things." The Hegelian “correct,” he argues, as represented by Marheineke and Göschel, focuses on the positive aspect of Hegel's religious philosophy, suggesting that in Jesus, the idea of God-manhood was perfectly realized and meaningfully manifested. “If these people,” Strauss explains, “Referencing Hegel and claiming he wouldn’t have viewed my book as a reflection of his ideas isn’t contradicting my beliefs at all. Hegel personally wasn’t a fan of historical criticism. Like Goethe, he found it frustrating when the historical figures of the past, which they admired, were questioned through critical analysis. Even if it was sometimes just clouds they mistook for towering peaks, they didn’t want this pointed out or to [pg 115] be disturbed in the illusion that gave them a sense of uplift.”

But though prepared to admit that he had added to the edifice of Hegel's religious philosophy an annexe of historical criticism, of which the master would hardly have approved, Strauss is convinced that he is the only logical representative of Hegel's essential view. “The question which can be decided from the standpoint of the philosophy of religion is not whether what is narrated in the Gospels actually happened or not, but whether in view of the truth of certain conceptions it must necessarily have happened. And in regard to this, what I assert is that from the general system of the Hegelian philosophy it by no means necessarily follows that such an event must have happened, but that from the standpoint of the system the truth of that history from which actually the conception arose is reduced to a matter of indifference; it may have happened, but it may just as well not have happened, and the task of deciding on this point may be calmly handed over to historical criticism.”

But even though he is ready to acknowledge that he has added a layer of historical critique to Hegel's religious philosophy that the master probably wouldn't have liked, Strauss believes he is the only logical representative of Hegel's core ideas. The question that can be considered from the philosophy of religion isn't whether the events in the Gospels really happened, but whether, given the truth of certain ideas, they must have happened. In this regard, what I propose is that within the broader framework of Hegelian philosophy, it doesn't automatically mean that such an event must have occurred; instead, from this perspective, the truth of the history from which that idea came is irrelevant. It may have happened, but it also might not have happened, and figuring this out can be confidently left to historical criticism.

Strauss reminds us that, even according to Hegel, the belief in Jesus as God-made-man is not immediately given with His appearing in the world of sense, but only arose after His death and the removal of His sensible presence. The master himself had acknowledged the existence of mythical elements in the Life of Jesus; in regard to miracle he had expressed the opinion that the true miracle was “Spirit.” The conception of the resurrection and ascension as outward facts of sense was not recognised by him as true.

Strauss reminds us that, even according to Hegel, the belief in Jesus as God made flesh doesn’t just appear with His presence in the physical world; it only developed after His death and the absence of His tangible presence. The master himself acknowledged that there are mythical elements in the Life of Jesus; concerning miracles, he stated that the real miracle was “Spirit.” He did not accept the resurrection and ascension as actual physical events.

Hegel's authority may, no doubt, fairly be appealed to by those who believe, not only in an incarnation of God in a general sense, “but also that this manifestation of God in flesh has taken place in this man (Jesus) at this definite time and place.”... “In making the assertion,” concludes Strauss, “that the truth of the Gospel narrative cannot be proved, whether in whole or in part, from philosophical considerations, but that the task of inquiring into its truth must be left to historical criticism, I should like to associate myself with the ‘left wing’ of the Hegelian school, were it not that the Hegelians prefer to exclude me altogether from their borders, and to throw me into the arms of other systems of thought—only, it must be admitted, to have me tossed back to them like a ball.”

Hegel's authority can certainly be cited by those who believe not only in a general incarnation of God, “but also that this manifestation of God in human form happened in this man (Jesus) at this specific time and place.”... "In stating," concludes Strauss, "While the truth of the Gospel narrative can't be proven, either fully or partially, through philosophical reasoning, but rather needs to be assessed through historical analysis, I’d like to position myself with the ‘left wing’ of the Hegelian school. However, the Hegelians choose to completely exclude me from their group and push me towards other philosophies, only for me to bounce back to them like a ball."

In regard to the third problem which Strauss had offered for discussion, the relation of the Synoptists to John, there was practically no response. The only one of his critics who understood what was at stake was Hengstenberg. He alone perceived the significance of the fact that critical theology, having admitted mythical elements first in the Old Testament, and then in the beginning and [pg 116] end of the Gospel history, and having, in consequence of the latter admission, felt obliged to give up the first three Gospels, retaining only the fourth, was now being besieged by Strauss in its last stronghold. “They withdrew,” says the Evangelische Kirchenzeitung, “into the Gospel of John as into a fortress, and boasted that they were safe there, though they could not suppress a secret consciousness that they only held it at the enemy's pleasure; now the enemy has appeared before it; he is using the same weapons with which he was formerly victorious; the Gospel of John is in as desperate case as formerly the Synoptists. The time has come to make a bold resolve, a decisive choice; either they must give up everything, or else they must successively re-occupy the more advanced positions which at an earlier date they had successively abandoned.” It would be impossible to give a more accurate picture of the desperate position into which Hase and Schleiermacher had brought the mediating theology by their ingenious expedient of giving up the Synoptics in favour of the Gospel of John. Before any danger threatened, they had abandoned the outworks and withdrawn into the citadel, oblivious of the fact that they thereby exposed themselves to the danger of having their own guns turned upon them from the positions they had abandoned, and being obliged to surrender without striking a blow the position of which they had boasted as impregnable. It is impossible to emphasise strongly enough the fact that it was not Strauss, but Hase and Schleiermacher, who had brought the mediating theology into this hopeless position, in which the fall of the Fourth Gospel carried with it the surrender of the historical tradition as a whole.

Regarding the third issue Strauss put up for discussion—the relationship between the Synoptic Gospels and John—there was nearly no response. The only critic who grasped the significance was Hengstenberg. He recognized the importance of critical theology having first acknowledged mythical elements in the Old Testament, then at the start and end of the Gospel accounts, which led it to abandon the first three Gospels while keeping only the fourth. Now, Strauss was pressuring this last stronghold. “They withdrew,” says the Evangelical Church Newspaper, “into the Gospel of John like it was a fortress, boasting that they were safe there, although they couldn’t shake the secret awareness that they were only holding it at the enemy's pleasure; now the enemy has shown up; he is using the same weapons that once led him to victory; the Gospel of John is in as dire a situation as the Synoptics once were. The time has come for a bold decision, a definitive choice; either they must relinquish everything or gradually reclaim the more advanced positions they had previously abandoned.” It would be impossible to convey more accurately the desperate position that Hase and Schleiermacher had placed mediating theology in by cleverly giving up the Synoptics in favor of the Gospel of John. Before any threat arose, they had surrendered the outer defenses and retreated into the stronghold, unaware that they had exposed themselves to the risk of being attacked by their own abandoned positions, having to surrender without a fight the place they had claimed was invulnerable. It cannot be stated strongly enough that it wasn’t Strauss but Hase and Schleiermacher who had led mediating theology into this desperate plight, where the collapse of the Fourth Gospel would mean the loss of the historical tradition as a whole.

But there is no position so desperate that theology cannot find a way out of it. The mediating theologians simply ignored the problem which Strauss had raised. As they had been accustomed to do before, so they continued to do after, taking the Gospel of John as the authentic framework, and fitting into it the sections of the Synoptic narrative wherever place could best be found for them. The difference between the Johannine and Synoptic representations of Jesus' method of teaching, says Neander, is only apparently irreconcilable, and he calls out in support of this assertion all the reserves of old worn-out expedients and artifices, among others the argument that the Pauline Christology is only explicable as a combination of the Synoptic and Johannine views. Other writers who belong to the same apologetic school, such as Tholuck, Ebrard,73 [pg 117] Wieseler,74 Lange,75 and Ewald,76 maintain the same point of view, only that their defence is usually much less skilful.

But there is no situation so desperate that theology can't find a way out. The mediating theologians simply ignored the issue that Strauss had brought up. Just like before, they kept using the Gospel of John as the authentic framework, fitting in the sections of the Synoptic narrative wherever they could. The difference between the Johannine and Synoptic portrayals of Jesus' teaching method, Neander argues, is only apparently irreconcilable, and he draws on all the old, worn-out strategies and tricks to support this claim, including the idea that Pauline Christology can only be understood as a blend of the Synoptic and Johannine perspectives. Other authors from the same apologetic school, like Tholuck, Ebrard, 73 [pg 117] Wieseler, 74 Lange, 75 and Ewald, 76 share the same view, though their arguments usually lack the same finesse.

The only writer who really in some measure enters into the difficulties is Ammon. He, indeed, is fully conscious of the difference, and thinks we cannot rest content with merely recognising it, but must find a solution, even if rather a forced one, “by subordinating the indefinite chronological data of the Synoptists, of whom, after all, only one was, or could have been, an eyewitness, to the ordered narrative of John.” The fourth Evangelist makes so brief a reference to the Galilaean period because it was in accordance with his plan to give more prominence to the discourses of Jesus in the Temple and His dialogues with the Scribes as compared to the parables and teaching given to the people. The cleansing of the Temple falls at the outset of Jesus' ministry; Jesus begins His Messianic work in Jerusalem by this action of making an end of the unseemly chaffering in the court of the Temple. The question regarding the relative authenticity of the reports is decisively settled by a comparison of the two accounts of [pg 118] the triumphal entry, because there it is quite evident that “Matthew, the chief authority among the Synoptists, adapts his narrative to his special Jewish-Messianic standpoint.” According to Ammon's rationalistic view, the work of Jesus consisted precisely in the transformation of this Jewish-Messianic idea into the conception of a “Saviour of the world.” In this lies the explanation of the fate of Jesus: “The mass of the Jewish people were not prepared to receive a Christ so spiritual as Jesus was, since they were not ripe for so lofty a view of religion.”

The only writer who really understands the challenges involved is Ammon. He is fully aware of the difference and believes we can't just acknowledge it—we need to find a solution, even if it's somewhat forced, "by placing the indefinite chronological information from the Synoptists, of whom only one was an eyewitness or could have been, under the structured account of John." The fourth Evangelist briefly mentions the Galilean period because he intends to emphasize Jesus' discourses in the Temple and His dialogues with the Scribes more than the parables and teachings given to the public. The cleansing of the Temple occurs early in Jesus' ministry; He begins His Messianic work in Jerusalem by ending the inappropriate trading in the Temple courtyard. The issue of the relative authenticity of the accounts is clearly resolved by comparing the two stories of the [pg 118] triumphal entry, where it's clear that "Matthew, the main authority among the Synoptists, tailors his story to reflect his unique Jewish-Messianic perspective." According to Ammon's rationalistic perspective, Jesus' work was about transforming this Jewish-Messianic idea into the idea of a “Hero of the world.” This also explains Jesus' fate: "The majority of the Jewish people were not ready to accept a Christ as spiritual as Jesus, as they weren't prepared for such a high perspective on religion."

Ammon here turns his Kantian philosophy to account. It serves especially to explain to him the consciousness of pre-existence avowed by the Jesus of the Johannine narrative as something purely human. We, too, he explains, can “after the spirit” claim an ideal existence prior to the spatial creation without indulging any delusion, and without, on the other hand, thinking of a real existence. In this way Jesus is for Himself a Biblical idea, with which He has become identified. “The purer and deeper a man's self-consciousness is, the keener may his consciousness of God become, until time disappears for him, and his partaking in the Divine nature fills his whole soul.”

Ammon applies his Kantian philosophy here. It particularly helps him understand the acknowledgment of pre-existence by the Jesus in the Gospel of John as something entirely human. He explains that we can also claim an ideal existence before the physical creation “after the spirit,” without falling into any illusion, and without thinking of a real existence on the other hand. In this way, Jesus embodies a Biblical concept that He has come to identify with. “The purer and deeper a person's self-awareness is, the more intense their awareness of God can become, until time fades away for them, and their participation in the Divine nature fills their entire soul.”

But Ammon's support of the authenticity of John's Gospel is, even from a purely literary point of view, not so unreserved as in the case of the other opponents of Strauss. In the background stands the hypothesis that our Gospel is only a working-over of the authentic John, a suggestion in regard to which Ammon can claim priority, since he had made it as early as 1811,77 nine years before the appearance of Bretschneider's Probabilia. Were it not for the ingenuous fashion in which he works the Synoptic material into the Johannine plan, we might class him with Alexander Schweizer and Weisse, who in a similar way seek to meet the objections of Strauss by an elaborate theory of editing.78

But Ammon's support for the authenticity of John's Gospel isn't as strong, even from a purely literary perspective, compared to the other critics of Strauss. The underlying idea is that our Gospel is just a revised version of the real John, a notion that Ammon can claim to have originated since he proposed it as early as 1811, nine years before Bretschneider's *Probabilia* was published. If it weren't for the straightforward way he incorporates the Synoptic material into the Johannine framework, we might group him with Alexander Schweizer and Weisse, who similarly try to address Strauss's objections with a complex editing theory.

The first stage of the discussion regarding the relation of John to the Synoptists passed without result. The mediating theology continued to hold its positions undisturbed—and, strangest of all, Strauss himself was eager for a suspension of hostilities.

The first stage of the discussion about John’s relationship to the Synoptists ended without any conclusions. The mediating theology remained firmly in its position—and, oddly enough, Strauss himself was keen on pausing the conflict.

It is as though history took the trouble to countersign the [pg 119] genuineness of the great critical discoveries by letting the discoverers themselves attempt to cancel them. As Kant disfigures his critical idealism by making inconsistent additions in order to refute a reviewer who had put him in the same category with Berkeley, so Strauss inserts additions and retractations in the third edition of his Life of Jesus in deference to the uncritical works of Tholuck and Neander! Wilke, the only one of his critics from whom he might have learned something, he ignores. “From the lofty vantage ground of Tholuck's many-sided knowledge I have sometimes, in spite of a slight tendency to vertigo, gained a juster point of view from which to look at one matter or another,” is the avowal which he makes in the preface to this ill-starred edition.

It’s like history made a point to confirm the authenticity of significant critical discoveries by allowing the discoverers to try and undo them. Just as Kant muddles his critical idealism with inconsistent additions to counter a reviewer who lumped him together with Berkeley, Strauss adds and retracts in the third edition of his Life of Jesus to align with the uncritical works of Tholuck and Neander! He completely overlooks Wilke, the one critic from whom he might have learned something. "From the high perspective of Tholuck's extensive knowledge, I have occasionally, despite a slight tendency to feel dizzy, gained a clearer viewpoint to examine various issues." is the admission he makes in the preface to this unfortunate edition.

It would, indeed, have done no harm if he had confined himself to stating more exactly here and there the extent of the mythical element, had increased the number of possible cures, had inclined a little less to the negative side in examining the claims of reported facts to rank as historical, and had been a little more circumspect in pointing out the factors which produced the myths; the serious thing was that he now began to hesitate in his denial of the historical character of the Fourth Gospel—the very foundation of his critical view.

It really wouldn't have hurt if he had just been more precise about the extent of the myths here and there, added more possible cures, leaned a bit less towards skepticism when evaluating the claims of reported facts as historical, and been a bit more careful in highlighting the factors that created the myths. The serious issue was that he was starting to waver in his denial of the historical nature of the Fourth Gospel—the very basis of his critical perspective.

A renewed study of it, aided by De Wette's commentary and Neander's Life of Jesus, had made him “doubtful about his doubts regarding the genuineness and credibility of this Gospel.” “Not that I am convinced of its genuineness,” he admits, “but I am no longer convinced that it is not genuine.”

A fresh look at it, supported by De Wette's commentary and Neander's Life of Jesus, had made him "uncertain about his concerns over the authenticity and reliability of this Gospel." "I'm not convinced it's real," he acknowledges, "but I'm no longer sure that it's not real."

He feels bound, therefore, to state whatever makes in its favour, and to leave open a number of possibilities which formerly he had not recognised. The adhesion of the first disciples may, he now thinks, have happened essentially in the form in which it is reported in the Fourth Gospel; in transferring the cleansing of the Temple to the first period of Jesus' ministry, John may be right as against the Synoptic tradition “which has no decisive evidence in its favour”; in regard to the question whether Jesus had been only once, or several times, in Jerusalem, his opinion now is that “on this point the superior circumstantiality of the Fourth Gospel cannot be contested.”

He feels compelled to highlight whatever supports his case and to consider several possibilities he hadn't recognized before. He now believes that the commitment of the first disciples might have happened in the way it's described in the Fourth Gospel; in moving the cleansing of the Temple to the earlier part of Jesus' ministry, John might actually be correct compared to the Synoptic accounts, which lack strong evidence in its favor; regarding whether Jesus had been to Jerusalem only once or multiple times, he now thinks that the Fourth Gospel's detailed account cannot be disputed.

As regards the prominence allowed to the eschatology also all is toned down and softened. Everywhere feeble compromises! But what led Strauss to place his foot upon this shelving path was the essentially just perception that the Synoptists gave him no clearly ordered plan to set against that of the Fourth Gospel; consequently he felt obliged to make some concessions to its strength in this respect.

As for the emphasis given to eschatology, everything is toned down and softened. There are weak compromises everywhere! What motivated Strauss to choose this uncertain path was the fundamentally accurate realization that the Synoptists didn’t provide him with a clearly organized framework to compare with that of the Fourth Gospel; as a result, he felt the need to make some concessions to its strength in this area.

Yet he recognised almost immediately that the result was a mere patchwork. Even in the summer of 1839 he complained [pg 120] to Hase in conversation that he had been deafened by the clamour of his opponents, and had conceded too much to them.79 In the fourth edition he retracted all his concessions. “The Babel of voices of opponents, critics, and supporters,” he says in his preface, “to which I had felt it my duty to listen, had confused me in regard to the idea of my work; in my diligent comparison of various views I had lost sight of the thing itself. In this way I was led to make alterations which, when I came to consider the matter calmly, surprised myself; and in making which it was obvious that I had done myself an injustice. In all these passages the earlier text has been restored, and my work has therefore consisted, it might be said, in removing from my good sword the notches which had not so much been hewn in it by the enemy as ground into it by myself.”

Yet he recognized almost immediately that the result was just a mishmash. Even in the summer of 1839, he complained [pg 120] to Hase during a conversation that he had been overwhelmed by the uproar from his opponents and had given in too much to them.79 In the fourth edition, he took back all his concessions. "The loud mix of voices from opponents, critics, and supporters," he states in his preface, "Listening to it made me unsure about the purpose of my work; in my careful comparison of different viewpoints, I lost track of the main point. This caused me to make changes that surprised me when I later looked back on them calmly; and in making those changes, it was obvious that I had done myself a disservice. In all these sections, I have restored the original text, so my work has mainly involved polishing my good sword, which had not been damaged by the enemy but rather worn down by my own actions."

Strauss's vacillation had, therefore, not even been of any indirect advantage to him. Instead of endeavouring to find a purposeful connexion in the Synoptic Gospels by means of which he might test the plan of the Fourth Gospel, he simply restores his former view unaltered, thereby showing that in the decisive point it was incapable of development. In the very year in which he prepared his improved edition, Weisse, in his Evangelische Geschichte, had set up the hypothesis that Mark is the ground-document, and had thus carried criticism past the “dead-point” which Strauss had never been able to overcome. Upon Strauss, however, the new suggestion made no impression. He does, it is true, mention Weisse's book in the preface to his third edition, and describes it as “in many respects a very satisfactory piece of work.” It had appeared too late for him to make use of it in his first volume; but he did not use it in his second volume either. He had, indeed, a distinct antipathy to the Marcan hypothesis.

Strauss's indecision had, therefore, not helped him at all. Instead of trying to find a meaningful connection in the Synoptic Gospels to test the framework of the Fourth Gospel, he simply returned to his previous viewpoint unchanged, proving that, at a critical point, it couldn’t develop further. In the same year he prepared his revised edition, Weisse, in his Protestant History, proposed the theory that Mark is the foundational document, pushing criticism beyond the “deadlock” that Strauss had never managed to overcome. However, the new suggestion had no impact on Strauss. He does mention Weisse's book in the preface to his third edition, calling it “in many ways a very satisfactory piece of work.” It came out too late for him to incorporate it into his first volume; still, he didn’t use it in his second volume either. In fact, he had a strong dislike for the Marcan hypothesis.

It was unfortunate that in this controversy the highly important suggestions in regard to various historical problems which had been made incidentally in the course of Strauss's work were never discussed at all. The impulse in the direction of progress which might have been given by his treatment of the relation of Jesus to the law, of the question regarding His particularism, of the eschatological conception, the Son of Man, and the Messiahship of Jesus, wholly failed to take effect, and it was only after long and circuitous wanderings that theology again came in sight of these problems from an equally favourable point of view. In this respect Strauss shared the fate of Reimarus; the positive solutions of which the outlines were visible behind their negative criticism escaped observation in consequence of the offence caused by the negative side of their work; and even the authors themselves failed to realise their full significance.

It was unfortunate that in this debate, the important suggestions about various historical issues that were made incidentally during Strauss's work were never discussed at all. The push for progress that could have come from his exploration of the relationship between Jesus and the law, the question of His particularism, the eschatological concept, the Son of Man, and Jesus's Messiahship completely failed to take effect. It wasn't until after a long and winding journey that theology began to view these issues again from a similarly favorable perspective. In this way, Strauss faced the same fate as Reimarus; the positive solutions that were hinted at behind their negative critiques went unnoticed because of the offense caused by the negative aspects of their work, and even the authors themselves didn’t fully realize their significance.

[pg 121]

X. The Marcan Theory

Christian Hermann Weisse. Die evangelische Geschichte kritisch und philosophisch bearbeitet. (A Critical and Philosophical Study of the Gospel History.) 2 vols. Leipzig, Breitkopf and Härtel, 1838. Vol. i. 614 pp. Vol. ii. 543 pp.

Christian Hermann Weisse. The Protestant History Analyzed Critically and Philosophically. 2 vols. Leipzig, Breitkopf and Härtel, 1838. Vol. I: 614 pages. Vol. II: 543 pages.

Christian Gottlob Wilke. Der Urevangelist. (The Earliest Evangelist.) 1838. Dresden and Leipzig. 694 pp.

Christian Gottlob Wilke. The Urevangelist. (The First Evangelist.) 1838. Dresden and Leipzig. 694 pages.

Christian Hermann Weisse. Die Evangelienfrage in ihrem gegenwärtigen Stadium. (The Present Position of the Problem of the Gospels.) Leipzig, 1856.

Christian Hermann Weisse. The Question of the Gospels in Its Current State. Leipzig, 1856.

The “Gospel History” of Weisse was written, like Strauss's Life of Jesus, by a philosopher who had been driven out of philosophy and forced back upon theology. Weisse was born in 1801 at Leipzig, and became Professor Extraordinary of Philosophy in the university there in 1828. In 1837, finding his advance to the Ordinary Professorship barred by the Herbartians, he withdrew from academic teaching and gave himself to the preparation of this work, the plan of which he had had in mind for some time. Having brought it to a satisfactory completion, he began again in 1841 as a Privat-Docent in Philosophy, and became Ordinary Professor in 1845. From 1848 onwards he lectured on Theology also. His work on “Philosophical Dogmatics, or the Philosophy of Christianity,”80 is well known. He died in 1866, of cholera. Lotze and Lipsius were both much influenced by him.

The "Gospel History" by Weisse was written, like Strauss's Life of Jesus, by a philosopher who had been pushed out of philosophy and drawn back into theology. Weisse was born in 1801 in Leipzig and became an Associate Professor of Philosophy at the university there in 1828. In 1837, when he found his promotion to Full Professor blocked by the Herbartians, he stepped away from teaching and focused on preparing this work, which he had been planning for some time. After completing it to his satisfaction, he returned in 1841 as a Privat-Docent in Philosophy and became a Full Professor in 1845. Starting in 1848, he also lectured on Theology. His work on "Philosophical Dogmatics, or the Philosophy of Christianity,"80 is well known. He died in 1866 from cholera. Lotze and Lipsius were both greatly influenced by him.

Weisse admired Strauss and hailed his Life of Jesus as a forward step towards the reconciliation of religion and philosophy. He expresses his gratitude to him for clearing the ground of the primeval forest of theology, thus rendering it possible for him (Weisse) to develop his views without wasting time upon polemics, “since most of the views which have hitherto prevailed may be regarded as having received the coup de grâce from Strauss.” He is at one with Strauss also in his general view of the relations of philosophy and religion, holding that it is only if philosophy, by following its own path, attains independently to the conviction of the truth of Christianity that its alliance with theology and religion [pg 122] can be welcomed as advantageous.81 His work, therefore, like that of Strauss, leads up finally to a philosophical exposition in which he shows how for us the Jesus of history becomes the Christ of faith.82

Weisse admired Strauss and praised his Life of Jesus as a positive step toward bringing together religion and philosophy. He expresses his gratitude for clearing away the dense underbrush of theology, making it possible for him (Weisse) to develop his ideas without getting bogged down in debates, “since most of the perspectives that have prevailed until now can be seen as having received the coup de grâce from Strauss.” He shares Strauss's general perspective on the relationship between philosophy and religion, believing that philosophy must independently reach the conviction of Christianity's truth for its partnership with theology and religion [pg 122] to be seen as beneficial.81 Therefore, his work, like Strauss's, ultimately leads to a philosophical explanation that shows how the historical Jesus becomes the Christ of faith for us.82

Weisse is the direct continuator of Strauss. Standing outside the limitations of the Hegelian formulae, he begins at the point where Strauss leaves off. His aim is to discover, if possible, some thread of general connexion in the narratives of the Gospel tradition, which, if present, would represent a historically certain element in the Life of Jesus, and thus serve as a better standard by which to determine the extent of myth than can possibly be found in the subjective impression upon which Strauss relies. Strauss, by way of gratitude, called him a dilettante. This was most unjust, for if any one deserved to share Strauss's place of honour, it was certainly Weisse.

Weisse is the direct successor of Strauss. He steps outside the limits of the Hegelian formulas and picks up where Strauss left off. His goal is to find, if possible, a thread of common connection in the stories of the Gospel tradition that would represent a historically certain element in the life of Jesus, thus providing a better standard for determining the extent of myth than the subjective impressions that Strauss relied on. In gratitude, Strauss referred to him as a dilettante. This was completely unfair, because if anyone deserved to share Strauss's place of honor, it was definitely Weisse.

The idea that Mark's Gospel might be the earliest of the four, first occurred to Weisse during the progress of his work. In March 1837, when he reviewed Tholuck's “Credibility of the Gospel History,” he was as innocent of this discovery as Wilke was at the same period. But when once he had observed that the graphic details of Mark, which had hitherto been regarded as due to an attempt to embellish an epitomising narrative, were too insignificant to have been inserted with this purpose, it became clear to him that only one other possibility remained open, viz., that their absence in Matthew and Luke was due to omission. He illustrates this from the description of the first day of Jesus' ministry at Capernaum. “The relation of the first Evangelist to Mark,” he avers, “in those portions of the Gospel which are common to both is, with few exceptions, mainly that of an epitomiser.”

The idea that Mark's Gospel might be the earliest of the four first came to Weisse during his work. In March 1837, when he reviewed Tholuck's "Credibility of the Gospel Story," he was just as unaware of this discovery as Wilke was at that time. However, once he noticed that the detailed descriptions in Mark, which had previously been thought to stem from an attempt to enhance a summarized narrative, were too minor to serve that purpose, it became clear to him that the only other option was that their absence in Matthew and Luke was due to omission. He illustrates this with the account of the first day of Jesus' ministry in Capernaum. "The relationship of the first Evangelist to Mark," he claims, "In the parts of the Gospel that both share, it is, with few exceptions, primarily that of a summarizer."

The decisive argument for the priority of Mark is, even more than his graphic detail, the composition and arrangement of the whole. “It is true, the Gospel of Mark shows very distinct traces of having arisen out of spoken discourses, which themselves were by no means ordered and connected, but disconnected and fragmentary”—being, he means, in its original form based on notes of the incidents related by Peter. “It is not the work of an eyewitness, nor even of one who had had an opportunity of questioning eyewitnesses thoroughly and carefully; nor even of deriving assistance from inquirers who, on their part, had made a connected [pg 123] study of the subject, with a view to filling up the gaps and placing each individual part in its right position, and so articulating the whole into an organic unity which should be neither merely inward, nor on the other hand merely external.” Nevertheless the Evangelist was guided in his work by a just recollection of the general course of the life of Jesus. “It is precisely in Mark,” Weisse explains, “that a closer study unmistakably reveals that the incidental remarks (referring for the most part to the way in which the fame of Jesus gradually extended, the way the people began to gather round Him and the sick to besiege Him), far from shutting off and separating the different narratives, tend rather to unite them with each other, and so give the impression not of a series of anecdotes fortuitously thrown together, but of a connected history. By means of these remarks, and by many other connecting links which he works into the narration of the individual stories, Mark has succeeded in conveying a vivid impression of the stir which Jesus made in Galilee, and from Galilee to Jerusalem, of the gradual gathering of the multitudes to Him, of the growing intensity of loyalty in the inner circle of disciples, and as the counterpart of all this, of the growing enmity of the Pharisees and Scribes—an impression which mere isolated narratives, strung together without any living connexion, would not have sufficed to produce.” A connexion of this kind is less clearly present in the other Synoptists, and is wholly lacking in John. The Fourth Gospel, by itself, would give us a completely false conception of the relation of Jesus to the people. From the content of its narratives the reader would form the impression that the attitude of the people towards Jesus was hostile from the very first, and that it was only in isolated occasions, for a brief moment, that Jesus by His miraculous acts inspired the people with astonishment rather than admiration; that, surrounded by a little company of disciples he contrived for a time to defy the enmity of the multitude, and that, having repeatedly provoked it by intemperate invective, he finally succumbed to it.

The main point for prioritizing Mark is, even more than his vivid details, the overall composition and structure. "Indeed, the Gospel of Mark clearly shows signs of coming from spoken discussions that were not structured or coherent, but rather disconnected and fragmented."—meaning, in its original form, it was based on notes about incidents shared by Peter. “It is not based on the account of someone who actually witnessed the events, nor is it from someone who thoroughly and carefully questioned those who did. It doesn’t even benefit from input from researchers who have conducted a detailed study of the topic to fill in the gaps and properly align each part, creating an overall cohesive understanding that is neither just internal nor solely external.” Nevertheless, the Evangelist was guided in his work by a clear memory of the general course of Jesus' life. “It’s exactly in Mark,” Weisse explains, A closer look clearly shows that the incidental remarks (mainly about how Jesus’ fame gradually spread, how people started to gather around Him, and how the sick crowded around Him) do not split up and separate different narratives. Instead, they actually connect them, creating the impression of not just a random collection of anecdotes but a cohesive story. Through these comments, along with many other links that he weaves into the individual stories, Mark has effectively painted a lively picture of the impact Jesus had in Galilee, then from Galilee to Jerusalem, the slow gathering of crowds around Him, the growing loyalty from His closest disciples, and, in contrast, the increasing hostility from the Pharisees and Scribes—an impression that isolated stories thrown together without any meaningful connection could never have achieved. Such a connection is less clearly seen in the other Synoptic Gospels and is completely absent in John. The Fourth Gospel alone would mislead us about Jesus' relationship with the people. From its narratives, readers might think that the people's attitude toward Jesus was hostile from the very beginning and that only on rare occasions, briefly, did His miraculous acts astonish rather than just impress; that, surrounded by a small group of disciples, He managed to temporarily withstand the animosity of the crowd, only to ultimately fall victim to it after repeatedly provoking it with harsh criticism.

The simplicity of the plan of Mark is, in Weisse's opinion, a stronger argument for his priority than the most elaborate demonstration; one only needs to compare it with the perverse design of Luke, who makes Jesus undertake a journey through Samaria. “How,” asks Weisse, “in the case of a writer who does things of this kind can it be possible at this time of day to speak seriously of historical exactitude in the use of his sources?”

The simplicity of Mark's story, according to Weisse, is a stronger argument for his priority than the most complicated explanation; you just need to compare it with the distorted narrative of Luke, who makes Jesus travel through Samaria. “How,” Weisse asks, "Can we really discuss the historical accuracy of his sources when it comes to a writer who does things like this?"

To come down to detail, Weisse's argument for the priority of Mark rests mainly on the following propositions:—

To get into the specifics, Weisse's argument for the priority of Mark is mainly based on the following points:—

1. In the first and third Gospels, traces of a common plan are found only in those parts which they have in common [pg 124] with Mark, not in those which are common to them, but not to Mark also.

1. In the first and third Gospels, signs of a shared plan appear only in the sections they have in common with Mark, not in the parts they share with each other but not with Mark. [pg 124]

2. In those parts which the three Gospels have in common, the “agreement” of the other two is mediated through Mark.

2. In the sections that the three Gospels share, the "agreement" of the other two is conveyed through Mark.

3. In those sections which the First and Third Gospels have, but Mark has not, the agreement consists in the language and incidents, not in the order. Their common source, therefore, the “Logia” of Matthew, did not contain any type of tradition which gave an order of narration different from that of Mark.

3. In the parts that the First and Third Gospels include but Mark does not, the similarities are in the wording and events, not in the sequence. This means that their shared source, the “Logia” of Matthew, did not have any kind of tradition that presented a narrative order different from that of Mark.

4. The divergences of wording between the two other Synoptists is in general greater in the parts where both have drawn on the Logia document than where Mark is their source.

4. The differences in wording between the other two Synoptic Gospels are generally more pronounced in the sections where both have relied on the Logia document than in the parts where Mark is their source.

5. The first Evangelist reproduces this Logia-document more faithfully than Luke does; but his Gospel seems to have been of later origin.

5. The first Evangelist presents this Logia-document more accurately than Luke does; however, his Gospel appears to have been created later.

This historical argument for the priority of Mark was confirmed in the year in which it appeared by Wilke's work, “The Earliest Gospel,”83 which treated the problem more from the literary side, and, to take an illustration from astronomy, supplied the mathematical confirmation of the hypothesis.

This historical argument for the priority of Mark was confirmed in the year it was published by Wilke's work, "The Oldest Gospel,"83 which approached the issue more from a literary perspective and, using an analogy from astronomy, provided the mathematical validation of the hypothesis.

[pg 125]

In regard to the Gospel of John, Weisse fully shared the negative views of Strauss. What is the use, he asks, of keeping on talking about the plan of this Gospel, seeing that no one has yet succeeded in showing what that plan is? And for a very good reason: there is none. One would never guess from the Gospel of John that Jesus, until His departure from Galilee, had experienced almost unbroken success. It is no good trying to explain the want of plan by saying that John wrote with the purpose of supplementing and correcting his predecessors, and that his omissions and additions were determined by this purpose. Such a purpose is betrayed by no single word in the whole Gospel.

Regarding the Gospel of John, Weisse completely aligned with Strauss's negative views. He questions the point of discussing the structure of this Gospel when no one has successfully explained what that structure actually is. And there's a good reason for that: there isn't one. You wouldn't guess from the Gospel of John that Jesus had enjoyed almost untarnished success until He left Galilee. It's pointless to try to justify the lack of structure by claiming that John aimed to supplement and correct his predecessors, and that his omissions and additions were based on this intention. Not a single word in the entire Gospel supports such a purpose.

The want of plan lies in the very plan itself. “It is a fixed idea, one may say, with the author of this Gospel, who had heard that Jesus had fallen a victim in Jerusalem to the hatred of the Jewish rulers, especially the Scribes, that he must represent Jesus as engaged, from His first appearance onward, in an unceasing struggle with ‘the Jews’—whereas we know that the mass of the people, even to the last, in Jerusalem itself, were on the side of Jesus; so much so, indeed, that His enemies were only able to get Him into their power by means of a secret betrayal.”

The lack of a plan comes from the very plan itself. It's a fixed belief, you could say, for the author of this Gospel, who heard that Jesus became a target of the hatred from the Jewish leaders, especially the Scribes, that he felt compelled to show Jesus as being involved, from His very first appearance, in a constant conflict with ‘the Jews’—even though we know that most of the people, right until the end, in Jerusalem itself, were on Jesus's side; in fact, it was only through a secret betrayal that His enemies managed to capture Him.

In regard to the graphic descriptions in John, of which so much has been made, the case is no better. It is the graphic detail of a writer who desires to work up a vivid picture, not the natural touches of an eyewitness, and there are, moreover, actual inconsistencies, as in the case of the healing at the pool of Bethesda. The circumstantiality is due to the care of the author not to assume an acquaintance, on the part of his readers, with Jewish usages or the topography of Palestine. “A considerable proportion of the details are of such a character as inevitably to suggest that the narrator inserts them because of the trouble which it has cost him to orientate himself in regard to the scene of the action and the dramatis personae, his object being to spare his readers a similar difficulty; though he does not always go about it in the way best calculated to effect his purpose.”

Regarding the graphic descriptions in John, which have received much attention, the situation is no better. They are vivid details from a writer aiming to create a striking image, rather than the genuine observations of an eyewitness. Additionally, there are actual inconsistencies, such as with the healing at the pool of Bethesda. The detailed nature comes from the author's effort to ensure that his readers are familiar with Jewish customs and the geography of Palestine. A large part of the details suggests that the narrator shares them due to the effort he put into understanding the setting and characters, trying to spare his readers from the same confusion; however, he doesn’t always do this in the most effective way.

The impossibility also that the historic Jesus can have preached the doctrine of the Johannine Christ, is as clear to Weisse as to Strauss. “It is not so much a picture of Christ that John sets forth, as a conception of Christ; his Christ does not speak in His own Person, but of His own Person.”

The impossibility that the historical Jesus could have preached the doctrine of the Johannine Christ is just as clear to Weisse as it is to Strauss. “It’s not so much a depiction of Christ that John offers, but an idea of Christ; his Christ doesn’t speak in His own being, but about His own being.”

On the other hand, however, “the authority of the whole Christian Church from the second century to the nineteenth” carries too much weight with Weisse for him to venture altogether to deny the Johannine origin of the Gospel; and he seeks a [pg 126] middle path. He assumes that the didactic portions really, for the most part, go back to John the Apostle. “John,” he explains, “drawn on by the interest of a system of doctrine which had formed itself in his mind, not so much as a direct reflex of the teaching of his Master, as on the basis of suggestions offered by that teaching in combination with a certain creative activity of his own, endeavoured to find this system also in the teaching of his Master.”

On the other hand, however, "the authority of the entire Christian Church from the second century to the nineteenth" holds too much significance for Weisse to completely deny the Johannine origin of the Gospel; he looks for a [pg 126] middle ground. He suggests that the teaching parts mostly trace back to John the Apostle. "John," he explains, "Motivated by his fascination with a system of beliefs that had formed in his mind, not just as a straightforward reflection of his Master’s teachings but also incorporating insights from those teachings and his own creative ideas, he sought to identify this system within his Master’s teachings as well."

Accordingly, with this purpose, and originally for himself alone, not with the object of communicating it to others, he made an effort to exhibit, in the light of this system of thought, what his memory still retained of the discourses of the Lord. “The Johannine discourses, therefore, were recalled by a laborious effort of memory on the part of the disciple. When he found that his memory-image of his Master was threatening to dissolve into a mist-wraith, he endeavoured to impress the picture more firmly in his recollection, to connect and define its rapidly disappearing features, reconstructing it by the aid of a theory evolved by himself or drawn from elsewhere regarding the Person and work of the Master.” For the portrait of Christ in the Synoptic Gospels the mind of the disciples who describe Him is a neutral medium; for the portrait in John it is a factor which contributes to the production of the picture. The same portrait is outlined by the apostle in the first epistle which bears his name.

With this goal in mind, and originally for himself alone, not intending to share it with others, he made an effort to show, through this way of thinking, what he still remembered of the teachings of the Lord. The Johannine teachings were carefully remembered by the disciple. When he noticed that his memory of his Master was starting to fade, he made an effort to clearly fix that image in his mind, trying to connect and define the quickly disappearing details, reconstructing it using a theory he created himself or learned from other sources about the Person and work of the Master. In the Synoptic Gospels, the disciples' descriptions of Christ are a neutral reflection; in John, however, the perspective of the disciple actively shapes the image. The same depiction is outlined by the apostle in the first epistle that bears his name.

These tentative “essays,” not originally intended for publication, came, after the death of the apostle, into the hands of his adherents and disciples, and they chose the form of a complete Life of Jesus as that in which to give them to the world. They, therefore, added narrative portions, which they distributed here and there among the speeches, often doing some violence to the latter in the process. Such was the origin of the Fourth Gospel.

These drafts “essays,” which weren’t initially meant for publication, reached the hands of the apostle's followers and students after his death, and they decided to present them as a full Life of Jesus. They added narrative sections, which they scattered throughout the speeches, often altering the original context in the process. This is how the Fourth Gospel came to be.

Weisse is not blind to the fact that this hypothesis of a Johannine basis in the Gospel is beset with the gravest—one might almost say with insuperable—difficulties. Here is a man who was an immediate disciple of the Lord, one who, in the Synoptic Gospels, in Acts, and in the Pauline letters, appears in a character which gives no hint of a coming spiritual metamorphosis, one, moreover, who at a relatively late period, when it might well have been supposed that his development was in all essentials closed (at the time of Paul's visit to Jerusalem, which falls at least fourteen years after Paul's conversion), was chosen, along with James and Peter, and in contrast with the apostles of the Gentiles, Paul and Barnabas, as an apostle of the Jews—“how is it possible,” asks Weisse, “to explain and make it intelligible, that a man of these antecedents displays in his thought and speech, in fact in his whole mental attitude, a thoroughly Hellenistic stamp? How came he, the beloved disciple, who, according to this very Gospel which [pg 127] bears his name, was admitted more intimately than any other into the confidence of Jesus, how came he to clothe his Master in this foreign garb of Hellenistic speculation, and to attribute to Him this alien manner of speech? But, however difficult the explanation may be, whatever extreme of improbability may seem to us to be involved in the assumption of the Johannine authorship of the Epistle and of these essential elements of the Gospel, it is better to assent to the improbability, to submit to the burden of being forced to explain the inexplicable, than to set ourselves obstinately against the weight of testimony, against the authority of the whole Christian Church from the second century to the present day.”

Weisse is aware that the idea of a Johannine foundation in the Gospel comes with significant—almost insurmountable—challenges. Here is a man who was a direct disciple of the Lord, one who, in the Synoptic Gospels, in Acts, and in the Pauline letters, is portrayed in a way that gives no indication of a forthcoming spiritual transformation. Furthermore, at a relatively late stage in his life, when it could reasonably be assumed that his development was essentially complete (at the time of Paul's visit to Jerusalem, at least fourteen years after Paul's conversion), he was chosen, alongside James and Peter, in contrast to the apostles of the Gentiles, Paul and Barnabas, as an apostle for the Jews—“how is it possible,” asks Weisse, “to explain and make it understandable that someone with this background shows in his thoughts and speech, in fact in his entire mental attitude, a distinctly Hellenistic influence? How did he, the beloved disciple, who, according to this very Gospel that bears his name, was more intimately trusted by Jesus than anyone else, come to present his Master in this foreign framework of Hellenistic speculation, and attribute to Him this unfamiliar style of communication? Yet, no matter how challenging the explanation may seem and however improbable the assumption of Johannine authorship of the Epistle and these key elements of the Gospel might appear to us, it's better to accept that improbability, to carry the burden of trying to explain the unexplainable, than to stubbornly oppose the overwhelming evidence and the authority of the entire Christian Church from the second century to today.”

There could be no better argument against the genuineness of the Fourth Gospel than just such a defence of its genuineness as this. In this form the hypothesis may well be destined to lead a harmless and never-ending life. What matters for the historical study of the Life of Jesus is simply that the Fourth Gospel should be ruled out. And that Weisse does so thoroughly that it is impossible to imagine its being done more thoroughly. The speeches, in spite of their apostolic authority, are unhistorical, and need not be taken into account in describing Jesus' system of thought. As for the unhappy redactor, who by adding the narrative pictures created the Gospel, all possibility of his reports being accurate is roundly denied, and as if that was not enough, he must put up with being called a bungler into the bargain. “I have, to tell the truth, no very high opinion of the literary art of the editor of the Johannine Gospel-document,” says Weisse in his “Problem of the Gospels” of 1856, which is the best commentary upon his earlier work.

There could be no stronger argument against the authenticity of the Fourth Gospel than the kind of defense of its authenticity presented here. In this form, the hypothesis might be destined to live on endlessly without causing any harm. What’s important for the historical study of Jesus’ life is simply that the Fourth Gospel should be dismissed. And Weisse does this so thoroughly that it’s hard to imagine it being done any better. The speeches, despite their apostolic authority, are historically inaccurate and don't need to be considered when describing Jesus' thoughts. As for the unfortunate editor, who created the Gospel by adding the narrative elements, all chances of his accounts being accurate are completely ruled out, and as if that weren't enough, he has to endure being called a klutz as well. "To be honest, I don't have a very high opinion of the literary skill of the editor of the Johannine Gospel document." says Weisse in his "Gospel Quesiton" from 1856, which is the best commentary on his earlier work.

His treatment of the Fourth Gospel reminds us of the story that Frederic the Great once appointed an importunate office-seeker to the post of “Privy Councillor for War,” on condition that he would never presume to offer a syllable of advice!

His approach to the Fourth Gospel brings to mind a story about Frederic the Great, who once appointed a persistent job seeker as the “War Councillor,” with the condition that he would never dare to give any advice!


The hypothesis which was brought forward about the same time by Alexander Schweizer,84 with the intention of saving the genuineness of the Gospel of John, did not make any real contribution to the subject. The reading of the facts which form his starting-point is almost the exact converse of that of Weisse, since he regards, not the speeches, but certain parts of the narrative as Johannine. That which it is possible, in his opinion, to refer [pg 128] to the apostle is an account, not involving any miracles, of the ministry of Jesus at Jerusalem, and the discourses which He delivered there. The more or less miraculous events which occur in the course of it—such as, that Jesus had seen Nathanael under the fig-tree, knew the past life of the Samaritan woman, and healed the sick man at the Pool of Bethesda—are of a simple character, and contrast markedly with those which are represented to have occurred in Galilee, where Jesus turned water into wine and fed a multitude with a few crusts of bread. We must, therefore, suppose that this short, authentic, spiritual Jerusalem-Gospel has had a Galilaean Life of Jesus worked into it, and this explains the inconsistencies of the representation and the oscillation between a sensuous and a spiritual point of view.

The hypothesis that Alexander Schweizer proposed around the same time, aiming to defend the authenticity of the Gospel of John, didn’t really contribute anything significant to the topic. His interpretation of the facts he started with is almost the complete opposite of Weisse’s, as he sees certain narrative sections, rather than the speeches, as being Johannine. In his view, what can be attributed to the apostle is a straightforward account of Jesus' ministry in Jerusalem that doesn’t involve any miracles, along with the teachings He shared there. The more or less miraculous events that happen, like Jesus seeing Nathanael under the fig tree, knowing the Samaritan woman's past, and healing the sick man at the Pool of Bethesda, are pretty simple and stand in stark contrast to those in Galilee, where Jesus turned water into wine and fed a crowd with just a few loaves of bread. Therefore, we have to assume that this brief, authentic spiritual Jerusalem Gospel has been combined with a Galilean Life of Jesus, which clarifies the inconsistencies in the portrayal and the shifts between a sensory and spiritual perspective.

This distinction, however, cannot be made good. Schweizer was obliged to ascribe the reports of a material resurrection to the Galilaean source, whereas these, since they exclude the Galilaean appearances of Jesus, must belong to the Jerusalem Gospel; and accordingly, the whole distinction between a spiritual and material Gospel falls to the ground. Thus this hypothesis at best preserves the nominal authenticity of the Fourth Gospel, only to deprive it immediately of all value as a historical source.

This distinction, however, can't hold up. Schweizer had to attribute the accounts of a physical resurrection to the Galilean source, but since those accounts ignore the Galilean appearances of Jesus, they must belong to the Jerusalem Gospel. Therefore, the whole difference between a spiritual and a physical Gospel collapses. So this theory at best preserves the nominal authenticity of the Fourth Gospel, only to strip it of any real value as a historical source.


Had Strauss calmly examined the bearing of Weisse's hypothesis, he would have seen that it fully confirmed the line he had taken in leaving the Fourth Gospel out of account, and he might have been less unjust towards the hypothesis of the priority of Mark, for which he cherished a blind hatred, because, in its fully developed form, it first met him in conjunction with seemingly reactionary tendencies towards the rehabilitation of John. He never in the whole course of his life got rid of the prejudice that the recognition of the priority of Mark was identical with a retrograde movement towards an uncritical orthodoxy.

Had Strauss calmly examined Weisse's theory, he would have seen that it completely supported his decision to disregard the Fourth Gospel, and he might have been less unfair toward the hypothesis that Mark was written first, which he had an irrational dislike for. This was because the fully developed version first appeared to him alongside what seemed to be reactionary tendencies aimed at restoring the credibility of John. Throughout his life, he never shook off the belief that acknowledging Mark's priority was the same as a backward step toward an uncritical orthodoxy.

This is certainly not true as regards Weisse. He is far from having used Mark unreservedly as a historical source. On the contrary, he says expressly that the picture which this Gospel gives of Jesus is drawn by an imaginative disciple of the faith, filled with the glory of his subject, whose enthusiasm is consequently sometimes stronger than his judgment. Even in Mark the mythopoeic tendency is already actively at work, so that often the task of historical criticism is to explain how such myths could have been accepted by a reporter who stands as near the facts as Mark does.

This is definitely not the case when it comes to Weisse. He hasn't relied on Mark as an uncritical historical source. In fact, he explicitly states that the portrayal of Jesus in this Gospel comes from a creative disciple of the faith, whose excitement often overshadows his judgment. Even in Mark, the tendency to create myths is already present, meaning that the challenge for historical criticism is to understand how such myths could be accepted by a reporter who is as close to the facts as Mark is.

Of the miracula85—so Weisse denominates the “non-genuine” miracles, in contradistinction to the “genuine”—the feeding of [pg 129] the multitude is that which, above all others, cries aloud for an explanation. Its historical strength lies in its being firmly interwoven with the preceding and following context; and this applies to both the Marcan narratives. It is therefore impossible to regard the story, as Strauss proposes to do, as pure myth; it is necessary to show how, growing out of some incident belonging to that context, it assumed its present literary form. The authentic saying about the leaven of the Pharisees, which, in Mark viii. 14 and 15, is connected with the two miracles of feeding the multitude, gives ground for supposing that they rest upon a parabolic discourse repeated on two occasions, in which Jesus spoke, perhaps with allusion to the manna, of a miraculous food given through Him. These discourses were later transformed by tradition into an actual miraculous giving of food. Here, therefore, Weisse endeavours to substitute for Strauss's “unhistorical” conception of myth a different conception, which in each case seeks to discover a sufficient historical cause.

Of the miracles85—Weisse refers to the "fake" miracles, in contrast to the “authentic”—the feeding of the [pg 129] multitude is the one that most demands an explanation. Its historical strength comes from being deeply connected to the surrounding context; this applies to both of the stories in Mark. Therefore, it’s not feasible to see the account, as Strauss suggests, as mere myth; we need to demonstrate how it evolved from an event related to that context into its current literary form. The genuine statement regarding the leaven of the Pharisees, which is linked to the two feeding miracles in Mark viii. 14 and 15, supports the idea that they are based on a parabolic teaching given on two occasions, where Jesus possibly referenced the manna, discussing a miraculous food provided through Him. Over time, these teachings were transformed by tradition into an actual miraculous act of providing food. In this regard, Weisse seeks to replace Strauss's "historically inaccurate" notion of myth with an approach that aims to uncover a sufficient historical cause in each case.

The miracles at the baptism of Jesus are based upon His account of a vision which He experienced in that moment. The present form of the story of the transfiguration has a twofold origin. In the first place, it is partly based on a real experience shared by the three disciples. That there is an historical fact here is evident from the way in which it is connected with the context by a definite indication of time. The six days of Mark ix. 2 cannot really be connected, as Strauss would have us suppose, with Ex. xxiv. 16;86 the meaning is simply that between the previously reported discourse of Jesus and the event described there was an interval of six days. The three disciples had a waking, spiritual vision, not a dream-vision, and what was revealed in this vision was the Messiahship of Jesus. But at this point comes in the second, the mythico-symbolical element. The disciples see Jesus accompanied, according to the Jewish Messianic expectations, by those whom the people thought of as His forerunners. He, however, turns away from them, and Moses and Elias, for whom the disciples were about to build tabernacles, for them to abide in, disappear. The mythical element is a reflection of the teaching which Jesus imparted to them on that occasion, in consequence of which there dawned on them the spiritual “significance of those expectations and predictions, which they were to recognise as no longer pointing forward to a future fulfilment, but as already fulfilled.” The high mountain upon which, according to Mark, the event took place is not to be understood in a literal sense, but as symbolical of the sublimity of the revelation; it is to be sought not on the map of Palestine, but in the recesses of the spirit.

The miracles at the baptism of Jesus are based on His account of a vision He experienced at that moment. The current version of the transfiguration story comes from two sources. First, it’s partly based on a real experience shared by the three disciples. It’s clear there’s a historical fact here based on how it's tied to the context with a specific time indication. The six days mentioned in Mark ix. 2 can't really be linked, as Strauss suggests, to Ex. xxiv. 16; the implication is simply that there was a six-day gap between the previously reported conversation with Jesus and the event described. The three disciples had a waking, spiritual vision, not a dream, and what was revealed in this vision was the Messiahship of Jesus. However, this is where the second element, the mythico-symbolical aspect, comes in. The disciples see Jesus alongside those whom the Jewish people viewed as His forerunners. He, however, turns away from them, and Moses and Elijah, for whom the disciples were about to build shelters, vanish. The mythical aspect reflects the teaching Jesus shared with them during that time, leading them to understand the spiritual “importance of those expectations and predictions, which they were to realize were no longer looking forward to a future fulfillment, but were already fulfilled.” The high mountain where, according to Mark, the event occurred is not meant to be taken literally but symbolizes the greatness of the revelation; it's not located on a map of Palestine, but in the depths of the spirit.

[pg 130]

The most striking case of the formation of myth is the story of the resurrection. Here, too, myth must have attached itself to an historical fact. The fact in question is not, however, the empty grave. This only came into the story later, when the Jews, in order to counteract the Christian belief in the resurrection, had spread abroad the report that the body had been stolen from the grave. In consequence of this report the empty grave had necessarily to be taken up into the story, the Christian account now making use of the fact that the body of Jesus was not found as a proof of His bodily resurrection. The emphasis laid on the identity of the body which was buried with that which rose again, of which the Fourth Evangelist makes so much, belongs to a time when the Church had to oppose the Gnostic conception of a spiritual, incorporeal immortality. The reaction against Gnosticism is, as Weisse rightly remarks, one of the most potent factors in the development of myth in the Gospel history. As an additional instance of this he might have cited the anti-gnostic form of the Johannine account of the baptism of Jesus.

The most striking case of how myths are formed is the story of the resurrection. In this instance, myth seems to have connected itself to a historical event. However, the historical fact in question is not the empty tomb. That element entered the narrative later, when the Jews spread the rumor that the body had been stolen from the grave in an attempt to undermine the Christian belief in the resurrection. Because of this rumor, the empty tomb had to be woven into the narrative, with the Christian account using the fact that Jesus's body was missing as proof of His bodily resurrection. The emphasis on the identity of the body that was buried being the same as the one that rose again, which the Fourth Evangelist focuses heavily on, reflects a time when the Church needed to counter the Gnostic idea of a spiritual, non-physical immortality. The pushback against Gnosticism, as Weisse rightly points out, is one of the major factors in the evolution of myth in the Gospel narrative. As another example of this, he could have mentioned the anti-Gnostic version of the account of Jesus's baptism found in the Gospel of John.

What, then, is the historical fact in the resurrection? “The historical fact,” replies Weisse, “is only the existence of a belief—not the belief of the later Christian Church in the myth of the bodily resurrection of the Lord—but the personal belief of the Apostles and their companions in the miraculous presence of the risen Christ in the visions and appearances which they experienced.” “The question whether those extraordinary phenomena which, soon after the death of the Lord, actually and undeniably took place within the community of His disciples, rest upon fact or illusion—that is, whether in them the departed spirit of the Lord, of whose presence the disciples supposed themselves to be conscious, was really present, or whether the phenomena were produced by natural causes of a different kind, spiritual and psychical, is a question which cannot be answered without going beyond the confines of purely historical criticism.” The only thing which is certain is “that the resurrection of Jesus is a fact which belongs to the domain of the spiritual and psychic life, and which is not related to outward corporeal existence in such a way that the body which was laid in the grave could have shared therein.” When the disciples of Jesus had their first vision of the glorified body of their Lord, they were far from Jerusalem, far from the grave, and had no thought of bringing that spiritual corporeity into any kind of relation with the dead body of the Crucified. That the earliest appearances took place in Galilee is indicated by the genuine conclusion of Mark, according to which the angel charges the women with the message that the disciples were to await Jesus in Galilee.

What, then, is the historical fact about the resurrection? "The historical fact," replies Weisse, “is simply the existence of a belief—not the later Christian Church’s belief in the myth of the physical resurrection of the Lord—but the personal belief of the Apostles and their companions in the miraculous presence of the risen Christ through the visions and appearances they experienced.” "The question of whether the extraordinary events that clearly happened shortly after the Lord’s death among His disciples are rooted in reality or are illusions—that is, whether the sense of the Lord’s spirit, which the disciples felt, was genuinely present, or if these experiences were caused by various natural, spiritual, or psychological factors—is a question that cannot be answered without moving beyond simple historical criticism." The only thing we can be sure of is "the resurrection of Jesus is a fact that relates to spiritual and psychological life, and is not linked to physical existence in a way that the body that was buried could have been involved in it." When Jesus’ disciples first had their vision of the glorified body of their Lord, they were far from Jerusalem, far from the grave, and had no intention of linking that spiritual body to the dead body of the Crucified. The fact that the earliest appearances occurred in Galilee is confirmed by Mark’s authentic conclusion, which indicates that the angel instructs the women to tell the disciples to wait for Jesus in Galilee.

Strauss's conception of myth, which failed to give it any point [pg 131] of vital connexion with the history, had not provided any escape from the dilemma offered by the rationalistic and supernaturalistic views of the resurrection. Weisse prepared a new historical basis for a solution. He was the first to handle the problem from a point of view which combined historical with psychological considerations, and he is fully conscious of the novelty and the far-reaching consequences of his attempt. Theological science did not overtake him for sixty years; and though it did not for the most part share his one-sidedness in recognising only the Galilaean appearances, that does not count for much, since it was unable to solve the problem of the double tradition regarding the appearances. His discussion of the question is, both from the religious and from the historical point of view, the most satisfying treatment of it with which we are acquainted; the pompous and circumspect utterances of the very latest theology in regard to the “empty grave” look very poor in comparison. Weisse's psychology requires only one correction—the insertion into it of the eschatological premise.

Strauss's idea of myth, which didn't connect it meaningfully with history, didn't offer a way out of the dilemma posed by both rational and supernatural views of the resurrection. Weisse laid the groundwork for a new historical solution. He was the first to approach the issue by blending historical and psychological aspects and was fully aware of the originality and significant implications of his efforts. Theological scholarship didn't catch up with him for sixty years; while it largely didn't share his narrow focus on only the Galilean appearances, that hardly matters since it couldn’t resolve the issue of the two traditions regarding the appearances. His analysis of the question is, from both a religious and historical standpoint, the most satisfying treatment we know of; the grand and cautious statements from the latest theology about the “empty tomb” seem rather lackluster in comparison. Weisse's psychology just needs one adjustment—the addition of the eschatological premise.

It is not only the admixture of myth, but the whole character of the Marcan representation, which forbids us to use it without reserve as a source for the life of Jesus. The inventor of the Marcan hypothesis never wearies of repeating that even in the Second Gospel it is only the main outline of the Life of Jesus, not the way in which the various sections are joined together, which is historical. He does not, therefore, venture to write a Life of Jesus, but begins with a “General Sketch of the Gospel History” in which he gives the main outlines of the Life of Jesus according to Mark, and then proceeds to explain the incidents and discourses in each several Gospel in the order in which they occur.87

It’s not just the mix of myth, but the overall nature of the Marcan portrayal that prevents us from using it without caution as a source for Jesus’s life. The person who created the Marcan hypothesis keeps insisting that even in the Second Gospel, it’s only the main outline of Jesus’s life that is historical, not how the different sections are connected. Therefore, they don’t attempt to write a biography of Jesus; instead, they start with a “Overview of the Gospel Story” where they present the main outlines of Jesus’s life according to Mark and then go on to explain the events and speeches in each Gospel in the order they appear.87

He avoids the professedly historical forced interpretation of detail, which later representatives of the Marcan hypothesis, Schenkel in particular, employ in such distressing fashion that Wrede's book, by making an end of this inquisitorial method of extracting the Evangelist's testimony, may be said to have released the Marcan hypothesis from the torture-chamber. Weisse is free from these over-refinements. He refuses to divide the Galilaean ministry of Jesus into a period of success and a period of failure and gradual falling off of adherents, divided by the controversy [pg 132] about legal purity in Mark vii.; he does not allow this episode to counterbalance the general evidence that Jesus' public work was accompanied by a constantly growing success. Nor does it occur to him to conceive the sojourn of the Lord in Phoenician territory, and His journey to the neighbourhood of Caesarea Philippi, as a compulsory withdrawal from Galilee, an abandonment of His cause in that district, and to head the chapter, as was usual in the second period of the exegesis of Mark, “Flights and Retirements.” He is content simply to state that Jesus once visited those regions, and explicitly remarks that while the Synoptists speak of the Pharisees and Scribes as working actively against Him, there is nowhere any hint of a hostile movement on the part of the people, but that, on the contrary, in spite of the Scribes and Pharisees the people are always ready to approve Him and take His part; so much so that His enemies can only hope to get Him into their power by a secret betrayal.

He avoids the supposedly historical forced interpretation of detail that later followers of the Marcan hypothesis, especially Schenkel, use in such an upsetting way that Wrede's book, by ending this inquisitorial method of extracting the Evangelist's testimony, can be said to have freed the Marcan hypothesis from the torture chamber. Weisse steers clear of these over-complications. He refuses to separate Jesus' Galilean ministry into a period of success and a period of decline in followers, split by the debate about legal purity in Mark 7; he doesn’t let this episode undermine the overall evidence that Jesus' public work was marked by increasing success. He also doesn’t think of Jesus’ time in Phoenician territory and His journey to the area near Caesarea Philippi as a forced retreat from Galilee or a abandonment of His mission there, which typically would have been labeled as "Flights and Retirements" in the second period of Mark's exegesis. He simply notes that Jesus once visited those regions and explicitly points out that while the Synoptists mention the Pharisees and Scribes actively opposing Him, there is no indication of a hostile movement among the people. On the contrary, despite the Scribes and Pharisees, the people are always willing to support Him; so much so that His enemies can only hope to capture Him through a secret betrayal.

Weisse does not admit any failure in Jesus' work, nor that death came upon Him from without as an inevitable necessity. He cannot, therefore, regard the thought of suffering as forced upon Jesus by outward events. Later interpreters of Mark have often held that the essential thing in the Lord's resolve to die was that by His voluntary acceptance of a fate which was more and more clearly revealing itself as inevitable, He raised it into the sphere of ethico-religious freedom: this was not Weisse's view. Jesus, according to him, was not moved by any outward circumstances when He set out for Jerusalem in order to die there. He did it in obedience to a supra-rational higher necessity. We can at most venture to conjecture that a cessation of His miracle-working power, of which He had become aware, revealed to Him that the hour appointed by God had come. He did, in fact, no further miracle in Jerusalem.

Weisse does not accept any failure in Jesus' mission, nor does he believe that death came upon Him from external circumstances as an unavoidable necessity. Therefore, he cannot see the concept of suffering as something that was imposed on Jesus by outside events. Later interpreters of Mark have often suggested that the key aspect of the Lord's decision to die was that by voluntarily accepting a fate that was increasingly appearing to be inevitable, He transformed it into a matter of moral and religious freedom; this was not Weisse's perspective. According to him, Jesus was not influenced by any external factors when He decided to go to Jerusalem to die there. He did so in obedience to a higher necessity beyond human reasoning. We can only speculate that the end of His miracle-working ability, which He became aware of, indicated to Him that the time appointed by God had arrived. In fact, He performed no further miracles in Jerusalem.

How far Isaiah liii. may have contributed to suggest the conception of such a death being a necessary part of Messiah's work, it is impossible to discover. In the popular expectation there was no thought of the Messiah as suffering. The thought was conceived by Jesus independently, through His deep and penetrating spiritual insight. Without any external suggestion whatever He announces to His disciples that He is to die at Jerusalem, and that He is going thither with that end in view. He journeyed, not to the Passover, but to His death. The fact that it took place at the time of the Feast was, so far as Jesus was concerned, accidental. The circumstances of His entry were such as to suggest anything rather than the fulfilment of His predictions; but though the jubilant multitude surrounded Him day by day, as with a wall of defence, He did not let that make Him falter in His purpose; rather He forced the authorities to arrest Him; He preserved silence [pg 133] before Pilate with the deliberate purpose of rendering His death inevitable. The theory of later defenders of the Marcan hypothesis that Jesus, giving up His cause in Galilee for lost, went up to Jerusalem to conquer or die, is foreign to Weisse's conception. In his view, Jesus, breaking off His Galilaean work while the tide of success was still flowing strongly, journeyed to Jerusalem, in the scorn of consequence, with the sole purpose of dying there.

How much Isaiah liii. may have hinted at the idea of such a death being a necessary part of the Messiah's role is hard to tell. In the common expectation, nobody thought of the Messiah as suffering. This idea was developed by Jesus on His own, thanks to His deep and insightful spiritual understanding. Without any outside influence, He tells His disciples that He is going to die in Jerusalem and that He is going there with that purpose in mind. He traveled not for the Passover, but for His death. The fact that it happened during the Feast was, for Jesus, merely coincidental. The way He entered Jerusalem suggested anything but the fulfillment of His predictions; but even though the cheering crowd surrounded Him like a protective barrier day after day, He didn’t let that sway Him from His purpose; instead, He forced the authorities to arrest Him. He remained silent before Pilate with the deliberate intention of making His death unavoidable. The idea from later supporters of the Marcan hypothesis that Jesus, having given up on His mission in Galilee, went to Jerusalem to either conquer or die is not consistent with Weisse's view. In his opinion, Jesus, leaving behind His work in Galilee while the tide of success was still strong, journeyed to Jerusalem, disregarding the consequences, with the sole aim of dying there.

It is true there are some premonitions of the later course of Marcan exegesis. The Second Gospel mentions no Passover journeys as falling in the course of the public ministry of Jesus; consequently the most natural conclusion would be that no Passover journeys fall within that period; that is, that Jesus' ministry began after one Passover and closed with the next, thus lasting less than a full year. Weisse thinks, however, that it is impossible to understand the success of His teaching unless we assume a ministry of several years, of more than three years, indeed. Mark does not mention the Feasts simply because Jesus did not go up to Jerusalem. “Intrinsic probability is, in our opinion, so strongly in favour of a duration of a considerable number of years, that we are at a loss to explain how it is that at least a few unprejudiced investigators have not found in this a sufficient reason for departing from the traditional opinion.”

It's true that there are some hints about the later development of Marcan interpretation. The Second Gospel does not mention any Passover journeys during Jesus' public ministry; therefore, the most straightforward conclusion is that no Passover journeys occurred during that time. This suggests that Jesus' ministry started after one Passover and ended with the next, lasting less than a full year. However, Weisse believes it's hard to grasp the success of His teachings without assuming a ministry that lasted several years—more than three years, in fact. Mark doesn't mention the Feasts simply because Jesus didn't travel to Jerusalem. “We think that the chances of a ministry lasting many years are so high that it's surprising that at least a few impartial researchers haven’t considered this a valid reason to question the traditional perspective.”

The account of the mission of the Twelve is also, on the ground of “intrinsic probability,” explained in a way which is not in accordance with the plain sense of the words. “We do not think,” says Weisse, “that it is necessary to understand this in the sense that He sent all the twelve out at one time, two and two, remaining alone in the meantime; it is much more natural to suppose that He only sent them out two at a time, keeping the others about Him. The object of this mission was less the immediate spreading abroad of His teaching than the preparation of the disciples themselves for the independent activity which they would have to exercise after His death.” These are, however, the only serious liberties which he takes with the statements of Mark.

The story of the mission of the Twelve is also explained in a way that doesn't fit the clear meaning of the words, based on the idea of “intrinsic probability.” “We don't believe,” says Weisse, “that it’s necessary to interpret this as meaning that He sent all twelve out at once, two by two, while remaining alone; it makes much more sense to think that He sent them out two at a time, keeping the others close by. The goal of this mission was less about immediately spreading His teachings and more about preparing the disciples for the independent work they would have to do after His death.” These are, however, the only significant liberties he takes with Mark's statements.

When did Jesus begin to think of Himself as the Messiah? The baptism seems to have marked an epoch in regard to His Messianic consciousness, but that does not mean that He had not previously begun to have such thoughts about Himself. In any case He did not on that occasion arrive all at once at that point of His inward journey which He had reached at the time of His first public appearance. We must assume a period of some duration between the baptism and the beginning of His ministry—a longer period than we should suppose from the Synoptists—during which Jesus cast off the Messianic ideas of Judaism and attained to a spiritual conception of the Messiahship. When He began to [pg 134] teach, His “development” was already closed. Later interpreters of Mark have generally differed from Weisse in assuming a development in the thought of Jesus during His public ministry.

When did Jesus start to see Himself as the Messiah? His baptism seems to have marked a significant moment in His understanding of His role, but that doesn't mean He hadn't been thinking about it before. In any case, He didn't suddenly reach that point in His personal journey at the time of His first public appearance. We need to consider that there was some time between the baptism and the start of His ministry—a longer period than what we might think from the Synoptic Gospels—during which Jesus moved away from the Messianic ideas of Judaism and developed a spiritual understanding of what it meant to be the Messiah. By the time He began to [pg 134] teach, His “development” was already complete. Later interpreters of Mark generally differ from Weisse by suggesting that Jesus’s thoughts evolved during His public ministry.

His conception of the Messiahship was therefore fully formed when He began to teach in Capernaum; but He did not allow the people to see that He held Himself to be the Messiah until His triumphal entry. It was in order to avoid declaring His Messiahship that He kept away from Jerusalem. “It was only in Galilee and not in the Jewish capital that an extended period of teaching and work was possible for Him without being obliged to make an explicit declaration whether He were the Messiah or no. In Jerusalem itself the High Priests and Scribes would soon have put this question to Him in such a way that He could not have avoided answering it, whereas in Galilee He doubtless on more than one occasion cut short such attempts to question Him too closely by the incisiveness of His replies.” Like Strauss, Weisse recognises that the key to the explanation of the Messianic consciousness of Jesus lies in the self-designation “Son of Man.” “We are most certainly justified,” he says, with almost prophetic insight, in his “Problem of the Gospels,” published in 1856, “in regarding the question, what sense the Divine Saviour desired to attach to this predicate?—what, in fact, He intended to make known about Himself by using the title Son of Man—as an essential question for the right understanding of His teaching, and not of His teaching only, but also of the very heart and inmost essence of His personality.”

His understanding of the Messiahship was fully developed when He started teaching in Capernaum; however, He didn’t let people realize He considered Himself the Messiah until His triumphant entry. To avoid declaring His Messiahship, He stayed away from Jerusalem. “He was able to teach and work for a significant time in Galilee, but not in the Jewish capital, without being pressured to clearly state if He was the Messiah. In Jerusalem, the High Priests and Scribes would quickly have confronted Him with this question in a way that he could not ignore. However, in Galilee, He often responded so sharply that He was able to avoid overly close questioning.” Like Strauss, Weisse acknowledges that the key to understanding Jesus's Messianic consciousness lies in His self-designation "Son of Man." "We're definitely justified," he states, with almost prophetic insight, in his “Gospel Issue,” published in 1856, "In regarding the question of what meaning the Divine Savior wanted to associate with this title—what, in fact, He intended to reveal about Himself by using the title Son of Man—is an essential question for properly understanding His teaching, and not just His teaching but also the very heart and innermost essence of His personality."

But at this point Weisse lets in the cloven hoof of that fatal method of interpretation, by the aid of which the defenders of the Marcan hypothesis who succeeded him were to wage war, with a kind of dull and dogged determination, against eschatology, in the interests of an original and “spiritual” conception of the Messiahship supposed to be held by Jesus. Under the obsession of the fixed idea that it was their mission to defend the “originality” of Jesus by ascribing to Him a modernising transformation and spiritualisation of the eschatological system of ideas, the defenders of the Marcan hypothesis have impeded the historical study of the Life of Jesus to an almost unbelievable extent.

But at this point, Weisse opens the door to a flawed way of interpreting things, which later defenders of the Marcan hypothesis would use in a stubborn fight against eschatology, all in the name of a supposed original and "spiritual" understanding of what Jesus meant by being the Messiah. Obsessed with the idea that it was their job to protect the "originality" of Jesus by claiming He underwent a modernizing change and spiritual interpretation of eschatological beliefs, the defenders of the Marcan hypothesis have severely hindered the historical study of Jesus’s life to an almost unbelievable degree.

The explanation of the name Son of Man had, Weisse explains, hitherto oscillated between two extremes. Some had held the expression to be, even in the mouth of Jesus, equivalent to “man” in general, an interpretation which cannot be carried through; others had connected it with the Son of Man in Daniel, and supposed that in using the term Jesus was employing a Messianic title understood by and current among the Jews. But how came He to employ only this unusual periphrastic name for the Messiah? Further, if this name were really a Messianic title, how could He [pg 135] repeatedly have refused Messianic salutations, and not until the triumphal entry suffered the people to hail Him as Messiah?

The explanation of the name Son of Man has, as Weisse explains, shifted between two extremes. Some have argued that the term, even when used by Jesus, simply meant "man" in a general sense, an interpretation that doesn’t hold up. Others have linked it to the Son of Man in Daniel, suggesting that Jesus used this term as a Messianic title that was recognized and accepted by the Jews. But why did He choose this unusual phrase to refer to the Messiah? Furthermore, if this title were indeed a Messianic one, how could He have repeatedly rejected Messianic acknowledgments, allowing people to recognize Him as Messiah only during the triumphal entry?

The questions are rightly asked; it is therefore the more pity that they are wrongly answered. It follows, Weisse says, from the above considerations that Jesus did not assume an acquaintance on the part of His hearers with the Old Testament Messianic significance of the expression. “It was therefore incontestably the intention of Jesus—and any one who considers it unworthy betrays thereby his own want of insight—that the designation should have something mysterious about it, something which would compel His hearers to reflect upon His meaning.” The expression Son of Man was calculated to lead them on to higher conceptions of His nature and origin, and therefore sums up in itself the whole spiritualisation of the Messiahship.

The questions are rightly raised; it's unfortunate that they are answered incorrectly. Weisse argues that, based on the previous points, Jesus did not expect His audience to be familiar with the Old Testament's Messianic meaning of the term. "Therefore, it was clearly Jesus' intention—and anyone who disagrees shows a lack of understanding—that this title should have an air of mystery, prompting His listeners to think about its true meaning." The term Son of Man was meant to inspire them to think beyond and grasp a deeper understanding of His nature and origin, encapsulating the entire spiritual interpretation of the Messiahship.

Weisse, therefore, passionately rejects any suggestion, however modest, that Jesus' self-designation, Son of Man, implies any measure of acceptance of the Jewish apocalyptic system of ideas. Ewald had furnished forth his Life of Jesus88 with a wealth of Old Testament learning, and had made some half-hearted attempts to show the connexion of Jesus' system of thought with that of post-canonical Judaism, but without taking the matter seriously and without having any suspicion of the real character of the eschatology of Jesus. But even these parade-ground tactics excite Weisse's indignation; in his book, published in 1856, he reproaches Ewald with failing to understand his task.

Weisse strongly rejects any hint, no matter how slight, that Jesus' self-title, Son of Man, suggests any acceptance of Jewish apocalyptic ideas. Ewald had filled his Life of Jesus88 with extensive Old Testament knowledge and made some half-hearted attempts to link Jesus' thinking with that of post-canonical Judaism, but he didn’t take the matter seriously and lacked any awareness of the true nature of Jesus' eschatology. Even these superficial efforts outrage Weisse; in his book published in 1856, he criticizes Ewald for not grasping the significance of his task.

The real duty of criticism is, according to Weisse, to show that Jesus had no part in those fantastic errors which are falsely attributed to Him when a literal Jewish interpretation is given to His great sayings about the future of the Son of Man, and to remove all the obstacles which seem to have prevented hitherto the recognition of the novel character and special significance of the expression, Son of Man, in the mouth of Him who, of His own free choice, applied this name to Himself. “How long will it be,” he cries, “before theology at last becomes aware of the deep importance of its task? Historical criticism, exercised with all the thoroughness and impartiality which alone can produce a genuine conviction, must free the Master's own teaching from the imputation that lies upon it—the imputation of sharing the errors and false expectations in which, as we cannot deny, owing to imperfect or mistaken understanding of the suggestions of the Master, the Apostles, and with them the whole early Christian Church, became involved.”

The true role of criticism is, as Weisse suggests, to show that Jesus wasn’t involved in the strange mistakes that are wrongly attributed to Him when His significant statements about the future of the Son of Man are taken literally in a Jewish context. It should also clear away the barriers that have prevented, until now, a proper understanding of the unique nature and special significance of the term "Son of Man" as used by Him, who chose to call Himself this. "How long will it take?" he exclaims, "Before theology finally understands the vital importance of its mission? Historical criticism, done with the thoroughness and fairness needed to form a genuine belief, must separate the Master’s teachings from the negative associations they carry—associations tied to the errors and false hopes that, we cannot deny, have influenced the Apostles and, as a result, the entire early Christian Church because of misunderstandings of the Master’s guidance."

This fundamental position determines the remainder of Weisse's views. Jesus cannot have shared the Jewish particularism. He [pg 136] did not hold the Law to be binding. It was for this reason that He did not go up to the Feasts. He distinctly and repeatedly expressed the conviction that His doctrine was destined for the whole world. In speaking of the parousia of the Son of Man He was using a figure—a figure which includes in a mysterious fashion all His predictions of the future. He did not speak to His disciples of His resurrection, His ascension, and His parousia as three distinct acts, since the event to which He looked forward is not identical with any of the three, but is composed of them all. The resurrection is, at the same time, the ascension and parousia, and in the parousia the resurrection and the ascension are also included. “The one conclusion to which we believe we can point with certainty is that Jesus spoke of the future of His work and His teaching in a way that implied the consciousness of an influence to be continued after His death, whether unbrokenly or intermittently, and the consciousness that by this influence His work and teaching would be preserved from destruction and the final victory assured to it.”

This fundamental position shapes the rest of Weisse's views. Jesus couldn't have embraced Jewish particularism. He [pg 136] did not believe the Law was binding. That's why He didn't attend the Feasts. He clearly and repeatedly conveyed the belief that His message was meant for the entire world. When talking about the coming of the Son of Man, He was using a figure of speech that mysteriously encompasses all His future predictions. He didn't tell His disciples about His resurrection, ascension, and coming back as three separate events, because the event He anticipated isn’t identical to any of them individually; it's made up of all three. The resurrection is, at the same time, the ascension and the coming back, and within the coming back, the resurrection and ascension are also included. “We're confident in saying that Jesus talked about the future of His work and teachings in a way that indicated He knew there would be an ongoing influence after His death, whether consistent or occasional, and that through this influence, His work and teachings would be protected from destruction and ultimately succeed.”

The personal presence of Jesus which the disciples experienced after His death was in their view only a partial fulfilment of that general promise. The parousia appeared to them as still awaiting fulfilment. Thought of thus, as an isolated event, they could only conceive it from the Jewish apocalyptic standpoint, and they finally came to suppose that they had derived these fantastic ideas from the Master Himself.

The personal presence of Jesus that the disciples felt after His death was, in their opinion, just a partial fulfillment of that broader promise. They believed the second coming was still something that was yet to happen. Viewed in this way, as a singular event, they could only understand it from a Jewish apocalyptic perspective, and eventually, they started to think that they had gotten these incredible ideas directly from the Master Himself.

In his determined opposition to the recognition of eschatology in Strauss's first Life of Jesus, Weisse here lays down the lines which were to be followed by the “liberal” Lives of Jesus of the 'sixties and following years, which only differ from him, not always to their advantage, in their more elaborate interpretation of the detail of Mark. The only work, therefore, which was a conscious continuation of Strauss's, takes, in spite of its just appreciation of the character of the sources, a wrong path, led astray by the mistaken idea of the “originality” of Jesus, which it exalts into a canon of historical criticism. Only after long and devious wanderings did the study of the subject find the right road again. The whole struggle over eschatology is nothing else than a gradual elimination of Weisse's ideas. It was only with Johannes Weiss that theology escaped from the influence of Christian Hermann Weisse.

In his strong opposition to recognizing eschatology in Strauss's first Life of Jesus, Weisse outlines the principles that were later followed by the “liberal” Lives of Jesus from the 1860s and beyond, which only differ from him—sometimes to their detriment—in their more detailed interpretations of Mark. Therefore, the only work that was a deliberate continuation of Strauss's takes a wrong turn despite its proper understanding of the sources, being misled by the flawed idea of the “originality” of Jesus, which it promotes as a standard of historical criticism. Only after many twisting paths did the study of the subject return to the right direction. The entire debate over eschatology is essentially a gradual rejection of Weisse's ideas. It was only with Johannes Weiss that theology broke free from the influence of Christian Hermann Weisse.

[pg 137]

XI. Bruno Bauer. The First Skeptical Life of Jesus

Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte des Johannes. (Criticism of the Gospel History of John.) Bremen, 1840. 435 pp.

Critique of the Gospel History of John. Bremen, 1840. 435 pages.

Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte der Synoptiker. (Criticism of the Gospel History of the Synoptics.) 3 vols., Leipzig, 1841-1842; vol. i. 416 pp.; vol. ii. 392 pp.; vol. iii. 341 pp.

Critique of the Gospel History of the Synoptics. (Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte der Synoptiker.) 3 volumes, Leipzig, 1841-1842; volume I: 416 pages; volume II: 392 pages; volume III: 341 pages.

Kritik der Evangelien. (Criticism of the Gospels.) 2 vols., 1850-1851, Berlin.

Critique of the Gospels. 2 volumes, 1850-1851, Berlin.

Kritik der Apostelgeschichte. (Criticism of Acts.) 1850.

Critique of Acts. 1850.

Kritik der Paulinischen Briefe. Berlin, 1850-1852. In three parts.

Critique of the Pauline Letters. Berlin, 1850-1852. In three sections.

Philo, Strauss, Renan und das Urchristentum. (P., S., R., and Primitive Christianity.) Berlin, 1874. 155 pp.

Philo, Strauss, Renan, and Primitive Christianity. (P., S., R., and Primitive Christianity.) Berlin, 1874. 155 pages.

Christus und die Cäsaren. Der Ursprung des Christentums aus dem römischen Griechentum. (The Origin of Christianity from Graeco-Roman Civilisation.) Berlin, 1877. 387 pp.

Christ and the Caesars: The Origin of Christianity from Graeco-Roman Civilization. Berlin, 1877. 387 pages.

Bruno Bauer was born in 1809 at Eisenberg, in the duchy of Sachsen-Altenburg. In philosophy, he was at first associated entirely with the Hegelian “right.” Like Strauss, he received a strong impulse from Vatke. At this stage of his development he reviewed, in 1835 and 1836, Strauss's Life of Jesus in the Jahrbücher für wissenschaftliche Kritik, and wrote in 1838 a “Criticism of the History of Revelation.”89

Bruno Bauer was born in 1809 in Eisenberg, in the duchy of Sachsen-Altenburg. In philosophy, he was initially completely aligned with the Hegelian "Okay." Like Strauss, he was greatly influenced by Vatke. At this point in his development, he reviewed Strauss's *Life of Jesus* in the Yearbooks for Scientific Critique in 1835 and 1836, and in 1838 he wrote a "Critique of the History of Revelation."89

In 1834 he had become Privat-Docent in Berlin, but in 1839 he removed to Bonn. He was then in the midst of that intellectual crisis of which the evidence appeared in his critical works on John and the Synoptics. In August 1841 the Minister, Eichhorn, requested the Faculties of the Prussian Universities to report on the question whether Bauer should be allowed to retain the venia docendi. Most of them returned an evasive answer, Königsberg replied in the affirmative, and Bonn in the negative. In March 1842 Bauer was obliged to cease lecturing, and retired to Rixdorf near Berlin. In the first heat of his furious indignation over this treatment he wrote a work with the title “Christianity [pg 138] Exposed,”90 which, however, was cancelled before publication at Zurich in 1843.

In 1834, he became a Privat-Docent in Berlin, but in 1839 he moved to Bonn. He was then going through the intellectual crisis that was evident in his critical works on John and the Synoptics. In August 1841, the Minister, Eichhorn, asked the faculties of the Prussian universities to report on whether Bauer should be allowed to keep the teaching license. Most of them gave evasive answers; Königsberg replied yes, and Bonn said no. In March 1842, Bauer had to stop lecturing and retired to Rixdorf near Berlin. In the heat of his anger over this treatment, he wrote a work titled “Christianity Exposed,”90 which was canceled before publication in Zurich in 1843.

He then turned his attention to secular history and wrote on the French Revolution, on Napoleon, on the Illuminism of the Eighteenth Century, and on the party struggles in Germany during the years 1842-1846. At the beginning of the 'fifties he returned to theological subjects, but failed to exercise any influence. His work was simply ignored.

He then shifted his focus to secular history and wrote about the French Revolution, Napoleon, the Enlightenment of the 18th Century, and the political conflicts in Germany from 1842 to 1846. In the early 1850s, he returned to theological topics, but he didn't manage to make an impact. His work was largely overlooked.

Radical though he was in spirit, Bauer found himself fighting, at the end of the 'fifties and beginning of the 'sixties, in the ranks of the Prussian Conservatives—we are reminded how Strauss in the Würtemberg Chamber was similarly forced to side with the reactionaries. He died in 1882. His was a pure, modest, and lofty character.

Radical as he was in spirit, Bauer found himself fighting, at the end of the 1950s and the beginning of the 1960s, alongside the Prussian Conservatives—we are reminded how Strauss in the Würtemberg Chamber was similarly forced to align with the reactionaries. He died in 1882. He had a pure, humble, and noble character.

At the time of his removal from Berlin to Bonn he was just at the end of the twenties, that critical age when pupils often surprise their teachers, when men begin to find themselves and show what they are, not merely what they have been taught.

At the time of his move from Berlin to Bonn, he was just around twenty-nine, that pivotal age when students often astonish their teachers, when men start to discover who they are and reveal their true selves, not just what they've been taught.

In approaching the investigation of the Gospel history, Bauer saw, as he himself tells us, two ways open to him. He might take as his starting-point the Jewish Messianic conception, and endeavour to answer the question how the intuitive prophetic idea of the Messiah became a fixed reflective conception. That was the historical method; he chose, however, the other, the literary method. This starts from the opposite side of the question, from the end instead of the beginning of the Gospel history. Taking first the Gospel of John, in which it is obvious that reflective thought has fitted the life of the Jewish Messiah into the frame of the Logos conception, he then, starting as it were from the embouchure of the stream, works his way upwards to the high ground in which the Gospel tradition takes its rise. The decision in favour of the latter view determined the character of Bauer's life-work; it was his task to follow out, to its ultimate consequences, the literary solution of the problem of the life of Jesus.

In exploring the Gospel history, Bauer realized, as he mentioned, that he had two options. He could start with the Jewish Messianic idea and try to figure out how the intuitive prophetic concept of the Messiah developed into a solid reflective idea. That was the historical method; however, he opted for the literary method instead. This approach begins from the opposite side of the issue, starting from the end rather than the beginning of the Gospel history. He first took the Gospel of John, where it’s clear that reflective thought has shaped the life of the Jewish Messiah into the concept of the Logos. From there, as if starting from the mouth of a river, he worked his way upstream to the high ground where the Gospel tradition begins. His choice to go this route defined the nature of Bauer's life work; it became his mission to thoroughly explore the literary solution to the problem of Jesus' life.

How far this path would lead him he did not at first suspect. But he did suspect how strong was the influence upon the formation of history of a dominant idea which moulds and shapes it with a definite artistic purpose. His interest was especially arrested by Philo, who, without knowing or intending it, contributed to the fulfilment of a higher task than that with which he was immediately engaged. Bauer's view is that a speculative principle such as Philo's, when it begins to take possession of men's minds, influences them in the first glow of enthusiasm which it evokes [pg 139] with such overmastering power that the just claims of that which is actual and historical cannot always secure the attention which is their due. In Philo's pupil, John, we must look, not for history, but for art.

How far this path would take him, he didn’t realize at first. But he was aware of how strongly a dominant idea influences the development of history, shaping it with a clear artistic purpose. He was particularly intrigued by Philo, who, without knowing or intending, played a part in achieving a greater task than the one he was directly involved with. Bauer argues that a speculative principle like Philo's, once it starts to capture people's minds, affects them in the initial excitement it stirs up with such overwhelming force that the rightful significance of what is real and historical doesn’t always receive the attention it deserves. In Philo's student, John, we should look not for history, but for art.

The Fourth Gospel is in fact a work of art. This was now for the first time appreciated by one who was himself an artist. Schleiermacher, indeed, had at an earlier period taken up the aesthetic standpoint in considering this Gospel. But he had used it as an apologist, proceeding to exalt the artistic truth which he rightly recognised into historic reality, and his critical sense failed him, precisely because he was an aesthete and an apologist, when he came to deal with the Fourth Gospel. Now, however, there comes forward a true artist, who shows that the depth of religious and intellectual insight which Tholuck and Neander, in opposing Strauss, had urged on behalf of the Fourth Gospel, is—Christian art.

The Fourth Gospel is truly a work of art. For the first time, this was recognized by someone who was an artist himself. Schleiermacher had previously approached this Gospel from an aesthetic perspective, but he used it as a defense, elevating the artistic truth he rightly identified into historical reality. His critical judgment faltered because he was both an aesthete and an apologist when he addressed the Fourth Gospel. Now, however, a genuine artist emerges, demonstrating that the profound religious and intellectual insights that Tholuck and Neander advocated in opposition to Strauss for the Fourth Gospel are, in fact, Christian art.

In Bauer, however, the aesthete is at the same time a critic. Although much in the Fourth Gospel is finely “felt,” like the opening scenes referring to the Baptist and to Jesus, which Bauer groups together under the heading “The Circle of the Expectant,” yet his art is by no means always perfect. The author who conceived those discourses, of which the movement consists in a kind of tautological return upon itself, and who makes the parables trail out into dragging allegories, is no perfect artist. “The parable of the Good Shepherd,” says Bauer, “is neither simple, nor natural, nor a true parable, but a metaphor, which is, nevertheless, much too elaborate for a metaphor, is not clearly conceived, and, finally, in places shows much too clearly the skeleton of reflection over which it is stretched.”

In Bauer, however, the aesthete is also a critic. While a lot in the Fourth Gospel is deeply “felt,” like the opening scenes about the Baptist and Jesus, which Bauer groups under “The Circle of the Expectant,” his artistry isn’t always spot on. The author who created those discourses—where the movement tends to loop back on itself—and who lets the parables fade into long-winded allegories is not a flawless artist. “The parable of the Good Shepherd,” Bauer states, “is neither simple, nor natural, nor a true parable, but a metaphor that is, nonetheless, far too elaborate for a metaphor, isn’t clearly conceived, and, ultimately, in some places, shows way too clearly the underlying structure of thought it’s stretched over.”

Bauer treats, in his work of 1840,91 the Fourth Gospel only. The Synoptics he deals with only in a quite incidental fashion, “as opposing armies make demonstrations in order to provoke the enemy to a decisive conflict.”

Bauer focuses solely on the Fourth Gospel in his 1840 work, 91. He only mentions the Synoptics in a very incidental way, “like rival armies displaying their strength to lure the enemy into a final confrontation.”

He breaks off at the beginning of the story of the passion, because here it would be necessary to bring in the Synoptic parallels. “From the distant heights on which the Synoptic forces have taken up a menacing position, we must now draw them down into the plain; now comes the pitched battle between them and the Fourth Gospel, and the question regarding the historical character of that which we have found to be the ultimate basis of the last Gospel, can now at length be decided.”

He pauses at the start of the story of the passion because this is where we need to consider the Synoptic parallels. “From the far-off heights where the Synoptic forces have positioned themselves threateningly, we must now bring them out into the open; the intense conflict between them and the Fourth Gospel starts now, and we can finally address the question about the historical nature of what we've found to be the foundation of the last Gospel.”

If, in the Gospel of John, no smallest particle could be found which was unaffected by the creative reflection of the author, how will it stand with the Synoptists?

If, in the Gospel of John, no tiny detail could be found that wasn't influenced by the author's creative vision, how does that compare to the Synoptists?

When Bauer broke off his work upon John in this abrupt way—for [pg 140] he had not originally intended to conclude it at this point—how far did he still retain a belief in the historical character of the Synoptics? It looks as if he had intended to treat then as the solid foundation, in contrast with the fantastic structure raised upon it by the Fourth Gospel. But when he began to use his pick upon the rock, it crumbled away. Instead of a difference of kind he found only a difference of degree. The “Criticism of the Gospel History of the Synoptists” of 1841 is built on the site which Strauss had levelled. “The abiding influence of Strauss,” says Bauer, “consists in the fact that he has removed from the path of subsequent criticism the danger and trouble of a collision with the earlier orthodox system.”

When Bauer abruptly stopped working on John—since he hadn't originally planned to finish it at this point—how much did he still believe in the historical nature of the Synoptics? It seems like he intended to treat them as the reliable foundation, unlike the fanciful structure built by the Fourth Gospel. But when he started to dig into it, it fell apart. Instead of finding a fundamental difference, he discovered only a difference in degree. The “Criticism of the Gospel History of the Synoptists” from 1841 is based on the ground that Strauss had leveled. “The lasting impact of Strauss,” Bauer says, “lies in the fact that he has cleared away the danger and hassle of confronting the earlier orthodox system for future criticism.”

Bauer finds his material laid ready to his hand by Weisse and Wilke. Weisse had divined in Mark the source from which criticism—becoming barren in the work of Strauss—might draw a new spring of vigorous life; and Wilke, whom Bauer places above Weisse, had raised this happy conjecture to the level of a scientifically assured result. The Marcan hypothesis was no longer on its trial.

Bauer finds that Weisse and Wilke have prepared the material he needs. Weisse had figured out that Mark was the source from which criticism—having become stale in Strauss's work—could find a new source of energy; and Wilke, whom Bauer considers superior to Weisse, had elevated this fortunate idea to the status of a scientifically confirmed result. The Marcan hypothesis was no longer being tested.

But its bearing upon the history of Jesus had still to be determined. What position do Weisse and Wilke take up towards the hypothesis of a tradition lying behind the Gospel of Mark? If it be once admitted that the whole Gospel tradition, so far as concerns its plan, goes back to a single writer, who has created the connexion between the different events—for neither Weisse nor Wilke regards the connexion of the sections as historical—does not the possibility naturally suggest itself that the narrative of the events themselves, not merely the connexion in which they appear in Mark, is to be set down to the account of the author of the Gospel? Weisse and Wilke had not suspected how great a danger arises when, of the three witnesses who represent the tradition, only one is allowed to stand, and the tradition is recognised and allowed to exist in this one written form only. The triple embankment held; will a single one bear the strain?

But its impact on the history of Jesus still needed to be determined. What stance do Weisse and Wilke take regarding the idea of a tradition behind the Gospel of Mark? If it’s accepted that the entire Gospel tradition, concerning its structure, goes back to a single writer who created the connection between different events—since neither Weisse nor Wilke sees the connection of the sections as historical—doesn’t it naturally raise the question that the narrative of the events themselves, not just the connection they have in Mark, should also be attributed to the author of the Gospel? Weisse and Wilke had not realized how serious a risk there is when, out of the three witnesses representing the tradition, only one is acknowledged, allowing the tradition to be recognized and accepted in just this one written form. The triple support held; can a single one manage the pressure?

The following considerations have to be taken into account. The criticism of the Fourth Gospel compels us to recognise that a Gospel may have a purely literary origin. This discovery dawned upon Bauer at a time when he was still disinclined to accept Wilke's conclusions regarding Mark. But when he had recognised the truth of the latter he felt compelled by the combination of the two to accept the idea that Mark also might be of purely literary origin. For Weisse and Wilke the Marcan hypothesis had not implied this result, because they continued to combine with it the wider hypothesis of a general tradition, holding that Matthew and Luke used the collection of “Logia,” [pg 141] and also owed part of their supplementary matter to a free use of floating tradition, so that Mark, it might almost be said, merely supplied them with the formative principle by means of which they might order their material.

The following considerations need to be taken into account. The criticism of the Fourth Gospel forces us to acknowledge that a Gospel might have a purely literary origin. This realization came to Bauer when he was still hesitant to accept Wilke's conclusions about Mark. However, once he recognized the validity of those conclusions, he felt compelled by the combination of the two to accept the idea that Mark might also have a purely literary origin. For Weisse and Wilke, the Marcan hypothesis did not suggest this outcome because they continued to connect it with a broader hypothesis of general tradition, believing that Matthew and Luke used the collection of “Logia” [pg 141] and also derived part of their additional content from a free use of floating tradition. Thus, it could almost be said that Mark merely provided them with the foundational principle necessary for organizing their material.

But what if Papias's statement about the collection of “Logia” were worthless, and could be shown to be so by the literary data? In that case Matthew and Luke would be purely literary expansions of Mark, and like him, purely literary inventions.

But what if Papias's claim about the collection of “Logia” turned out to be useless, and we could prove that using the literary evidence? In that situation, Matthew and Luke would simply be literary expansions of Mark, and like him, just literary creations.

In this connexion Bauer attaches decisive importance to the phenomena of the birth-stories. If these had been derived from tradition they could not differ from each other as they do. If it is suggested that tradition had produced a large number of independent, though mutually consistent, stories of the childhood, out of which the Evangelists composed their opening narratives, this also is found to be untenable, for these narratives are not composite structures. The separate stories of which each of these two histories of the childhood consists could not have been formed independently of one another; none of them existed by itself; each points to the others and is informed by a view which implies the whole. The histories of the childhood are therefore not literary versions of a tradition, but literary inventions.

In this connection, Bauer sees the birth stories as being extremely important. If these stories had come from tradition, they wouldn't differ from each other as much as they do. Even if we consider the idea that tradition produced many independent but consistent childhood stories, which the Evangelists used to create their opening narratives, this doesn't hold up either, because these narratives aren't just made up of different pieces. Each of the separate stories that make up these two childhood accounts couldn't have developed independently; none existed on its own. Each story refers to the others and is shaped by a perspective that includes the whole. Therefore, the childhood narratives are not just literary versions of a tradition, but rather literary creations.

If we go on to examine the discourse and narrative material, additional to that of Mark, which is found in Matthew and Luke, a similar result appears. The same standpoint is regulative throughout, showing that the additions do not consist of oral or written traditional material which has been worked into the Marcan plan, but of a literary development of certain fundamental ideas and suggestions found in the first author. These developments, as is shown by the accounts of the Sermon on the Mount and the charge to the Twelve, are not carried as far in Luke as in Matthew. The additional material in the latter seems indeed to be worked up from suggestions in the former. Luke thus forms the transition stage between Mark and Matthew. The Marcan hypothesis, accordingly, now takes on the following form. Our knowledge of the Gospel history does not rest upon any basis of tradition, but only upon three literary works. Two of these are not independent, being merely expansions of the first, and the third, Matthew, is also dependent upon the second. Consequently there is no tradition of the Gospel history, but only a single literary source.

If we continue to look at the discussions and narrative material beyond what Mark provides, which is also found in Matthew and Luke, we see a similar outcome. The same perspective is consistent throughout, indicating that the additions are not made up of oral or written traditional content integrated into Mark's framework, but rather a literary expansion of certain core ideas and suggestions from the first author. These expansions, as demonstrated by the accounts of the Sermon on the Mount and the commission to the Twelve, are less developed in Luke than in Matthew. The extra material in Matthew appears to have been derived from what is found in Luke. Therefore, Luke serves as the transitional phase between Mark and Matthew. The Marcan hypothesis, then, can be summarized as follows. Our understanding of the Gospel story does not rely on any tradition, but solely on three literary works. Two of these are not independent, as they are just elaborations on the first, and the third, Matthew, is also based on the second. As a result, there is no tradition of Gospel history, only a single literary source.

But, if so, who is to assure us that this Gospel history, with its assertion of the Messiahship of Jesus, was already a matter of common knowledge before it was fixed in writing, and did not first become known in a literary form? In the latter case, one man would have created out of general ideas the definite historical tradition in which these ideas are embodied. [pg 142] The only thing that could be set against this literary possibility, as a historical counter-possibility, would be a proof that at the period when the Gospel history is supposed to take place a Messianic expectation really existed among the Jews, so that a man who claimed to be the Messiah and was recognised as such, as Mark represents Jesus to have been, would be historically conceivable. This presupposition had hitherto been unanimously accepted by all writers, no matter how much opposed in other respects. They were all satisfied “that before the appearance of Jesus the expectation of a Messiah prevailed among the Jews”; and were even able to explain its precise character.

But if that's the case, who can guarantee that the Gospel story, with its claim of Jesus as the Messiah, was already widely known before it was written down and didn't only become known in a literary way? If that were true, then one person would have taken common ideas and turned them into the definite historical tradition that includes those ideas. [pg 142] The only thing that could challenge this literary possibility, as a historical counter-argument, would be proof that during the time the Gospel events are said to have occurred, a belief in the Messiah truly existed among the Jews. In that case, a man who claimed to be the Messiah and was recognized as such—like Mark describes Jesus—would be historically plausible. This assumption had previously been accepted by all writers, regardless of their other disagreements. They all agreed "before Jesus showed up, the Jews were expecting a Messiah"; and they could even clarify its specific nature.

But where—apart from the Gospels—did they get their information from? Where is the documentary evidence of the Jewish Messianic doctrine on which that of the Gospels is supposed to be based? Daniel was the last of the prophets. Everything tends to suggest that the mysterious content of his work remained without influence in the subsequent period. Jewish literature ends with the Wisdom writings, in which there is no mention of a Messiah. In the LXX there is no attempt to translate in accordance with a preconceived picture of the Messiah. In the Apocalypses, which are of small importance, there is reference to a Messianic Kingdom; the Messiah Himself, however, plays a quite subordinate part, and is, indeed, scarcely mentioned. For Philo He has no existence; the Alexandrian does not dream of connecting Him with his Logos speculation. There remain, therefore, as witnesses for the Jewish Messianic expectations in the time of Tiberius, only Mark and his imitators. This evidence, however, is of such a character that in certain points it contradicts itself.

But where—aside from the Gospels—did they get their information? Where is the documentary evidence of the Jewish Messianic doctrine that the Gospels are said to be based on? Daniel was the last of the prophets. Everything suggests that the mysterious content of his work had no influence in the following period. Jewish literature ends with the Wisdom writings, which don’t mention a Messiah. In the LXX, there’s no effort to translate with a preconceived image of the Messiah. In the Apocalypses, which are of little importance, there’s a mention of a Messianic Kingdom; however, the Messiah Himself plays a very minor role and is hardly mentioned. For Philo, He doesn’t exist; the Alexandrian philosopher doesn’t think to connect Him with his Logos theory. Therefore, the only witnesses for the Jewish Messianic expectations during the time of Tiberius are Mark and his followers. This evidence, however, is such that it contradicts itself in some respects.

In the first place, if at the time when the Christian community was forming its view of history and the religious ideas which we find in the Gospels, the Jews had already possessed a doctrine of the Messiah, there would have been already a fixed type of interpretation of the Messianic passages in the Old Testament, and it would have been impossible for the same passages to be interpreted in a totally different way, as referring to Jesus and His work, as we find them interpreted in the New Testament. Next, consider the representation of the Baptist's work. We should have expected him to connect his baptism with the preaching of “Him who was to come”—if this were really the Messiah—by baptizing in the name of this “Coming One.” He, however, keeps them separate, baptizing in preparation for the Kingdom, though referring in his discourses to “Him who was to come.”

First of all, if the Christian community was shaping its view of history and the religious ideas presented in the Gospels when it was forming, and the Jews already had a doctrine of the Messiah, there would have been an established way to interpret the Messianic passages in the Old Testament. It would have been impossible for those same passages to be understood in a completely different way, as referring to Jesus and His work, as they are interpreted in the New Testament. Additionally, look at how the Baptist's work is portrayed. We would have expected him to link his baptism with the proclamation of “The one who was coming”—if He were indeed the Messiah—by baptizing in the name of this "Coming Soon." Instead, he keeps them separate, baptizing in preparation for the Kingdom, while mentioning in his talks "The one who was coming."

The earliest Evangelist did not venture openly to carry back into the history the idea that Jesus had claimed to be the [pg 143] Messiah, because he was aware that in the time of Jesus no general expectation of the Messiah had prevailed among the people. When the disciples in Mark viii. 28 report the opinions of the people concerning Jesus they cannot mention any who hold Him to be the Messiah. Peter is the first to attain to the recognition of His Messiahship. But as soon as the confession is made the Evangelist makes Jesus forbid His disciples to tell the people who He is. Why is the attribution of the Messiahship to Jesus made in this surreptitious and inconsistent way? It is because the writer who gave the history its form well knew that no one had ever come forward publicly on Palestinian soil to claim the Messiahship, or had been recognised by the people as Messiah.

The earliest Evangelist didn't openly try to connect Jesus to the idea of being the Messiah because he knew that during Jesus' time, there wasn't a widespread expectation of a Messiah among the people. When the disciples in Mark viii. 28 share what people think about Jesus, they can't find anyone who sees Him as the Messiah. Peter is the first to realize and acknowledge Jesus' Messiahship. But right after this confession, the Evangelist has Jesus tell His disciples not to reveal who He really is. Why is the claim of Jesus being the Messiah presented in such a secretive and contradictory way? It's because the writer who shaped this history understood that no one had ever publicly declared themselves as Messiah in Palestine, nor had anyone been recognized as such by the people.

The “reflective conception of the Messiah” was not, therefore, taken over ready-made from Judaism; that dogma first arose along with the Christian community, or rather the moment in which it arose was the same in which the Christian community had its birth.

The "thoughtful idea of the Messiah" wasn’t simply borrowed from Judaism; that belief first emerged alongside the Christian community, or more accurately, it developed at the exact moment the Christian community was formed.

Moreover, how unhistorical, even on a priori grounds, is the mechanical way in which Jesus at this first appearance at once sets Himself up as the Messiah and says, “Behold I am He whom ye have expected.” In essence, Bauer thinks, there is not so much difference between Strauss and Hengstenberg. For Hengstenberg the whole life of Jesus is the living embodiment of the Old Testament picture of the Messiah; Strauss, a less reverent counterpart of Hengstenberg, made the image of the Messiah into a mask which Jesus Himself was obliged to assume, and which legend afterwards substituted for His real features.

Moreover, how unhistorical, even from a logical standpoint, is the mechanical way in which Jesus, at His first appearance, immediately claims to be the Messiah and states, "Look, I am the one you've been waiting for." Essentially, Bauer believes there isn't much difference between Strauss and Hengstenberg. For Hengstenberg, the entire life of Jesus serves as the living representation of the Old Testament image of the Messiah; Strauss, a less reverent counterpart to Hengstenberg, turned the Messiah's image into a mask that Jesus was forced to wear, and which later legends replaced with His true likeness.

“We save the honour of Jesus,” says Bauer, “when we restore His Person to life from the state of inanition to which the apologists have reduced it, and give it once more a living relation to history, which it certainly possessed—that can no longer be denied. If a conception was to become dominant which should unite heaven and earth, God and man, nothing more and nothing less was necessary as a preliminary condition, than that a Man should appear, the very essence of whose consciousness should be the reconciliation of these antitheses, and who should manifest this consciousness to the world, and lead the religious mind to the sole point from which its difficulties can be solved. Jesus accomplished this mighty work, but not by prematurely pointing to His own Person. Instead He gradually made known to the people the thoughts which filled and entered into the very essence of His mind. It was only in this indirect way that His Person—which He freely offered up in the cause of His historical vocation and of the idea for which He lived—continued to live on in so far as this idea was accepted. When, in the belief of His followers, He rose again and lived on in the [pg 144] Christian community, it was as the Son of God who had overcome and reconciled the great antithesis. He was that in which alone the religious consciousness found rest and peace, apart from which there was nothing firm, trustworthy, and enduring.”

"We honor Jesus," says Bauer, "When we revive His character from the emptiness imposed by the defenders and re-establish a genuine connection to history, which undeniably existed, we have a starting point. If we want a concept that brings together heaven and earth, God and humanity, all we need is a Man whose very awareness represents the reconciliation of these opposites, who can reveal this understanding to the world and lead the religious mind to the single point where its challenges can be resolved. Jesus accomplished this amazing feat, not by focusing on His own identity prematurely, but by gradually sharing the thoughts that filled and defined His mind. It was through this indirect approach that His identity—sacrificed for His historical mission and the purpose for which He lived—endured as long as this purpose was valued. When, through the faith of His followers, He rose again and continued in the __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ Christian community, it was as the Son of God who had triumphed and reconciled the great opposition. He embodied that in which religious consciousness found rest and peace, without which there was nothing solid, reliable, and enduring."

“It was only now that the vague, ill-defined, prophetic representations were focused into a point; were not only fulfilled, but were also united together by a common bond which strengthened and gave greater value to each of them. With His appearance and the rise of belief in Him, a clear conception, a definite mental picture of the Messiah became possible; and thus it was that a Christology92 first arose.”

“It was only now that the vague, unclear prophetic visions became focused; they were not only fulfilled but also linked by a common thread that added more significance to each of them. With His arrival and the growing faith in Him, a clear understanding, a specific mental image of the Messiah became possible; and so it was that a Christology__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ first emerged.”

While, therefore, at the close of Bauer's first work it might have seemed that it was only the Gospel of John which he held to be a literary creation, here the same thing is said of the original Gospel. The only difference is that we find more primitive reflection in the Synoptics, and later work in the representation given by the Fourth Evangelist; the former is of a more practical character, the latter more dogmatic.

While, therefore, at the end of Bauer's first work, it might have seemed that he believed only the Gospel of John was a literary creation, here the same claim is made about the original Gospel. The only difference is that the Synoptics show a more primitive reflection, while the Fourth Evangelist presents a later interpretation; the former is more practical, while the latter is more dogmatic.

Nevertheless it is false to assert that according to Bauer the earliest Evangelist invented the Gospel history and the personality of Jesus. That is to carry back the ideas of a later period and a further stage of development into the original form of his view. At the moment when, having disposed of preliminaries, he enters on his investigation, he still assumes that a great, a unique Personality, who so impressed men by His character that it lived on among them in an ideal form, had awakened into life the Messianic idea; and that what the original Evangelist really did was to portray the life of this Jesus—the Christ of the community which He founded—in accordance with the Messianic view of Him, just as the Fourth Evangelist portrayed it in accordance with the presupposition that Jesus was the revealer of the Logos. It was only in the course of his investigations that Bauer's opinion became more radical. As he goes on, his writing becomes ill-tempered, and takes the form of controversial dialogues with “the theologians,” whom he apostrophises in a biting and injurious fashion, and whom he continually reproaches with not daring, owing to their apologetic prejudices, to see things as they really are, and with declining to face the ultimate results of criticism from fear that the tradition might suffer more loss of historic value than religion could bear. In spite of this hatred of the theologians, which is pathological in character, like his meaningless punctuation, his critical analyses are always exceedingly acute. One has the impression of walking alongside a man who is reasoning quite intelligently, but who talks [pg 145] to himself as though possessed by a fixed idea. What if the whole thing should turn out to be nothing but a literary invention—not only the incidents and discourses, but even the Personality which is assumed as the starting-point of the whole movement? What if the Gospel history were only a late imaginary embodiment of a set of exalted ideas, and these were the only historical reality from first to last? This is the idea which obsesses his mind more and more completely, and moves him to contemptuous laughter. What, he mocks, will these apologists, who are so sure of everything, do then with the shreds and tatters which will be all that is left to them?

However, it’s not accurate to claim that Bauer believed the earliest Evangelist created the Gospel narrative and the persona of Jesus. That perspective imposes later ideas and further stages of development onto his original viewpoint. At the point when he moves beyond preliminary matters to begin his investigation, he still accepts that a great and unique person, whose character made a lasting impression on people and lived on among them in an idealized form, had given rise to the Messianic idea. He believes that the original Evangelist's role was to depict the life of this Jesus—the Christ of the community He established—according to the Messianic view of Him, just as the Fourth Evangelist represented it based on the premise that Jesus was the revealer of the Logos. It was during his inquiry that Bauer's views grew more radical. As he progresses, his writing becomes increasingly irritable, taking the shape of contentious dialogues with "theologians," whom he addresses in a sharply critical manner, continually accusing them of not daring, due to their apologetic biases, to recognize reality as it is, and of refusing to confront the ultimate consequences of criticism out of fear that tradition might lose more historical value than religion could withstand. Despite this pathological hatred for theologians, which is reflected in his erratic punctuation, his critical analyses remain exceptionally sharp. One gets the feeling of walking alongside someone who is thinking quite logically but conversing [pg 145] to himself as if consumed by a fixed idea. What if everything turned out to be merely a literary fabrication—not just the events and dialogues, but even the persona that is presumed to be the foundation of the whole movement? What if the Gospel narrative was just a later fantastical portrayal of a set of elevated ideas, and these were the only true historical reality from beginning to end? This thought increasingly obsesses him and evokes scornful laughter. What, he mocks, will those confident apologists do with the scraps that will remain?

But at the outset of his investigations Bauer was far from holding such views. His purpose was really only to continue the work of Strauss. The conception of myth and legend of which the latter made use is, Bauer thinks, much too vague to explain this deliberate “transformation” of a personality. In the place of myth Bauer therefore sets “reflection.” The life which pulses in the Gospel history is too vigorous to be explained as created by legend; it is real “experience,” only not the experience of Jesus, but of the Church. The representation of this experience of the Church in the Life of a Person is not the work of a number of persons, but of a single author. It is in this twofold aspect—as the composition of one man, embodying the experience of many—that the Gospel history is to be regarded. As religious art it has a profound truth. When it is regarded from this point of view the difficulties which are encountered in the endeavour to conceive it as real immediately disappear.

But at the beginning of his investigations, Bauer didn’t hold such views. His goal was really just to carry on Strauss's work. Bauer thinks that the idea of myth and legend used by Strauss is way too vague to account for this intentional "transformation" of a personality. Instead of myth, Bauer proposes "self-reflection." The life that pulses in the Gospel history is too strong to be explained as created by legend; it is real “experience” not the experience of Jesus, but of the Church. The way this experience of the Church is represented in the Life of a Person isn’t done by a group of people, but by a single author. It’s in this dual aspect—being the work of one person while conveying the experiences of many—that the Gospel history should be viewed. As religious art, it holds a deep truth. When seen from this perspective, the difficulties that arise in trying to understand it as real quickly vanish.

We must take as our point of departure the belief in the sacrificial death and the resurrection of Jesus. Everything else attaches itself to this as to its centre. When the need arose to fix definitely the beginning of the manifestation of Jesus as the Saviour—to determine the point of time at which the Lord issued forth from obscurity—it was natural to connect this with the work of the Baptist; and Jesus comes to his baptism. While this is sufficient for the earliest Evangelist, Matthew and Luke feel it to be necessary, in view of the important consequences involved in the connexion of Jesus with the Baptist, to bring them into relation once more by means of the question addressed by the Baptist to Jesus, although this addition is quite inconsistent with the assumptions of the earliest Evangelist. If he had conceived the story of the baptism with the idea of introducing the Baptist again on a later occasion, and this time, moreover, as a doubter, he would have given it a different form. This is a just observation of Bauer's; the story of the baptism with the miracle which took place at it, and the Baptist's question, understood as implying a doubt of the Messiahship of Jesus, mutually exclude one another.

We need to start with the belief in the sacrificial death and resurrection of Jesus. Everything else connects to this as its core. When the need arose to define the start of Jesus' role as the Savior — to pinpoint when He emerged from obscurity — it made sense to link this to the work of the Baptist; thus, Jesus comes to be baptized. While this is enough for the earliest Gospel writer, Matthew and Luke find it necessary, given the significant implications of Jesus' association with the Baptist, to connect them again through the question the Baptist asks Jesus, even though this addition contradicts the assumptions of the earliest Gospel writer. If he had intended the baptism story to reintroduce the Baptist later, especially as a doubter, he would have framed it differently. This is a valid point made by Bauer; the story of the baptism, along with the miracle that occurred, and the Baptist's question, which implies doubt about Jesus’ Messiahship, contradict each other.

[pg 146]

The story of the temptation embodies an experience of the early Church. This narrative represents her inner conflicts under the form of a conflict of the Redeemer. On her march through the wilderness of this world she has to fight with temptations of the devil, and in the story composed by Mark and Luke, and artistically finished by Matthew, she records a vow to build only on the inner strength of her constitutive principle. In the sermon on the mount also, Matthew has carried out with greater completeness that which was more vaguely conceived by Luke. It is only when we understand the words of Jesus as embodying experiences of the early Church that their deeper sense becomes clear and what would otherwise seem offensive disappears. The saying, “Let the dead bury their dead,” would not have been fitting for Jesus to speak, and had He been a real man, it could never have entered into His mind to create so unreal and cruel a collision of duties; for no command, Divine or human, could have sufficed to make it right for a man to contravene the ethical obligations of family life. So here again, the obvious conclusion is that the saying originated in the early Church, and was intended to inculcate renunciation of a world which was felt to belong to the kingdom of the dead, and to illustrate this by an extreme example.

The story of the temptation represents an experience of the early Church. This narrative illustrates its internal conflicts through the conflict faced by the Redeemer. As it navigates through the challenges of this world, it has to struggle against the devil's temptations. In the accounts written by Mark and Luke, and artistically completed by Matthew, it notes a commitment to rely solely on the inner strength of its core principles. In the Sermon on the Mount, Matthew elaborates on what was more vaguely expressed by Luke. It’s only when we see Jesus' words as reflecting the experiences of the early Church that their deeper meaning becomes clear, and what might otherwise be offensive fades away. The statement, "Let the dead take care of their own." wouldn’t have been appropriate for Jesus to say, and if He had been a real person, it would never have occurred to Him to create such an unrealistic and cruel clash of duties; no command, whether Divine or human, could justify violating the ethical responsibilities of family life. Therefore, it’s clear that this saying originated in the early Church, intended to promote the renunciation of a world perceived as belonging to the realm of the dead, illustrating this with an extreme example.

The mission of the Twelve, too, is, as an historical occurrence, simply inconceivable. It would have been different if Jesus had given them a definite teaching, or form of belief, or positive conception of any kind, to take with them as their message. But how ill the charge to the Twelve fulfils its purpose as a discourse of instruction! What the disciples needed to learn, namely, what and how they were to teach, they are not told; and the discourse which Matthew has composed, working on the basis of Luke, implies quite a different set of circumstances. It is concerned with the struggles of the Church with the world and the sufferings which it must endure. This is the explanation of the references to suffering which constantly recur in the discourses of Jesus, in spite of the fact that His disciples were not enduring any sufferings, and that the Evangelist cannot even make it conceivable as a possibility that those before whose eyes Jesus holds up the way of the Cross could ever come into such a position. The Twelve, at any rate, had no sufferings to encounter during their mission, and if they were merely being sent by Jesus into the surrounding districts they were not very likely to meet with kings and rulers there.

The mission of the Twelve is simply unimaginable in a historical context. It would have been different if Jesus had given them clear teachings, a specific belief system, or any solid idea to share as their message. But the charge to the Twelve falls short as a teaching moment! What the disciples needed to understand—what and how they should teach—isn't explained to them; and the narrative that Matthew has put together, based on Luke, suggests a completely different set of circumstances. It focuses on the Church's conflicts with the world and the sufferings it must face. This explains the frequent mentions of suffering in Jesus’s teachings, even though His disciples weren't experiencing any hardships, and the Evangelist can't even imagine that those who see Jesus demonstrating the path of the Cross would ever face such challenges. The Twelve certainly had no hardships to deal with during their mission, and if they were just being sent by Jesus into nearby areas, they were unlikely to encounter kings and rulers there.

That it is a case of invented history is also shown by the fact that nothing is said about the doings of the disciples, and they seem to come back again immediately, though the earliest Evangelist, it is true, to prevent this from being too apparent, inserts at this point the story of the execution of the Baptist.

That it is a case of made-up history is also evident from the fact that nothing is mentioned about the actions of the disciples, and they seem to return right away. However, the earliest Evangelist, to keep this from being too obvious, adds the story of the Baptist's execution at this point.

All this is just and acute criticism. The charge to the Twelve [pg 147] is not a discourse of instruction. What Jesus there sets before the disciples they could not at that time have understood, and the promises which He makes to them are not appropriate to their circumstances.

All this is fair and sharp criticism. The message to the Twelve [pg 147] is not a teaching session. What Jesus presents to the disciples, they couldn’t have grasped at that moment, and the promises He makes to them don't fit their situation.

Many of the discourses are mere bundles of heterogeneous sayings, though this is not so much the case in Mark as in the others. He has not forgotten that effective polemic consists of short, pointed, incisive arguments. The others, as advanced theologians, are of opinion that it is fitting to indulge in arguments which have nothing to do with the matter in hand, or only the most distant connexion with it. They form the transition to the discourses of the Fourth Gospel, which usually degenerate into an aimless wrangle. In the same connexion it is rightly observed that the discourses of Jesus do not advance from point to point by the logical development of an idea, the thoughts are merely strung together one after another, the only connexion, if connexion there is, being due to a kind of conventional mould in which the discourse is cast.

Many of the discussions are just a jumble of random sayings, but this is less true for Mark than for the others. He hasn’t forgotten that effective arguments are short, sharp, and to the point. The others, being more advanced theologians, believe it’s appropriate to include arguments that are completely irrelevant or only loosely related to the topic at hand. This leads into the discourses of the Fourth Gospel, which often turn into pointless debates. It’s also correctly noted that Jesus's discourses do not progress logically from one point to the next; the thoughts are simply lined up one after the other, with any connections—if there are any—being due to some sort of conventional structure the discourse follows.

The parables, Bauer continues, present difficulties no less great. It is an ineptitude on the part of the apologists to suggest that the parables are intended to make things clear. Jesus Himself contradicts this view by saying bluntly and unambiguously to His disciples that to them it was given to know the mysteries of the Kingdom of God, but to the people all His teaching must be spoken as parables, that “seeing they might see and not perceive, and hearing they might hear and not understand.” The parables were therefore intended only to exercise the intelligence of the disciples; and so far from being understood by the people, mystified and repelled them; as if it would not have been much better to exercise the minds of the disciples in this way when He was alone with them. The disciples, however, do not even understand the simple parable of the Sower, but need to have it interpreted to them, so that the Evangelist once more stultifies his own theory.

The parables, Bauer continues, present challenges that are just as significant. It's an oversight on the part of the apologists to claim that the parables are meant to clarify things. Jesus Himself contradicts this by telling His disciples directly that they are given the insight to understand the mysteries of the Kingdom of God, while to the crowds, all His teachings must be delivered as parables, so that “seeing they might see and not perceive, and hearing they might hear and not understand.” The parables were therefore meant only to engage the intelligence of the disciples; rather than being understood by the people, they confused and alienated them. It raises the question of whether it would have been better to stimulate the disciples' minds when He was alone with them. However, the disciples don’t even grasp the straightforward parable of the Sower and need it explained to them, which once again undermines the Evangelist's own theory.

Bruno Bauer is right in his observation that the parables offer a serious problem, seeing that they were intended to conceal and not to make plain, and that Jesus nevertheless taught only in parables. The character of the difficulty, however, is such that even literary criticism has no explanation ready. Bruno Bauer admits that he does not know what was in the mind of the Evangelist when he composed these parables, and thinks that he had no very definite purpose, or at least that the suggestions which were floating in his mind were not worked up into a clearly ordered whole.

Bruno Bauer is right in saying that the parables present a serious issue, as they were meant to hide meaning rather than clarify it, yet Jesus taught solely through parables. The nature of this difficulty is such that even literary critics struggle to explain it. Bruno Bauer acknowledges that he has no idea what the Evangelist intended when he wrote these parables and believes that he didn't have a clear aim, or at least that the ideas he had weren't developed into a coherent structure.

Here, therefore, Bauer's method broke down. He did not, however, allow this to shake his confidence in his reading of the facts, and he continued to maintain it in the face of a new difficulty [pg 148] which he himself brought clearly to light. Mark, according to him, is an artistic unity, the offspring of a single mind. How then is it to be explained that in addition to other less important doublets it contains two accounts of the feeding of the multitude? Here Bauer has recourse to the aid of Wilke, who distinguishes our Mark from an Ur-Markus,93 and ascribes these doublets to later interpolation. Later on he became more and more doubtful about the artistic unity of Mark, despite the fact that this was the fundamental assumption of his theory, and in the second edition of his “Criticism of the Gospels,” of 1851, he carried through the distinction between the canonical Mark and the Ur-Markus.

Here, then, Bauer's method failed. However, he didn't let that shake his confidence in his understanding of the facts and continued to defend it despite encountering a new challenge [pg 148] that he himself clearly highlighted. According to him, Mark is a cohesive work, the product of a single mind. So how can it be explained that besides other less significant duplicates, it contains two accounts of the feeding of the multitude? Here, Bauer turns to Wilke for support, who differentiates our Mark from an Ur-Markus,93 and suggests that these duplicates were added later. Over time, he became increasingly uncertain about the artistic unity of Mark, even though this was the core of his theory, and in the second edition of his “Gospel Criticism,” published in 1851, he made clear the distinction between the canonical Mark and the Ur-Markus.

But even supposing the assumption of a redaction were justified, how could the redactor have conceived the idea of adding to the first account of the feeding of the multitude a second which is identical with it almost to the very wording? In any case, on what principle can Mark be distinguished from Ur-Markus? There are no fundamental differences to afford a ready criterion. The distinction is purely one of subjective feeling, that is to say, it is arbitrary. As soon as Bauer admits that the artistic unity of Mark, on which he lays so much stress, has been tampered with, he cannot maintain his position except by shutting his eyes to the fact that it can only be a question of the weaving in of fragments of tradition, not of the inventions of an imitator. But if he once admits the presence of traditional materials, his whole theory of the earliest Evangelist's having created the Gospel falls to the ground.

But even if we assume that a revision was justified, how could the reviser have thought to add a second account of the feeding of the multitude that is almost identical to the first in wording? In any case, how can we distinguish Mark from Ur-Markus? There are no fundamental differences that provide a clear criterion. The distinction is purely based on subjective feeling, meaning it's arbitrary. Once Bauer acknowledges that the artistic unity of Mark, which he emphasizes, has been altered, he can't maintain his position without ignoring the fact that it can only involve the incorporation of fragments of tradition, not the creations of an imitator. However, if he admits the presence of traditional materials, his entire theory about the earliest Evangelist creating the Gospel collapses.

For the moment he succeeds in laying the spectre again, and continues to think of Mark as a work of art, in which the interpolation alters nothing.

For now, he manages to set the ghost aside again and keeps thinking of Mark as a piece of art, where the addition changes nothing.

Bauer discusses with great thoroughness those sayings of Jesus in which He forbids those whom He had healed to noise abroad their cure. In the form in which they appear these cannot, he argues, be historical, for Jesus imposes this prohibition in some cases where it is quite meaningless, since the healing had taken place in the presence of a multitude. It must therefore be derived from the Evangelist. Only when it is recognised as a free creation can its meaning be discerned. It finds its explanation in the inconsistent views regarding miracle which were held side by side in the early Church. No doubt was felt that Jesus had performed miracles, and by these miracles had given evidence of His Divine mission. On the other hand, by the introduction of the Christian principle, the Jewish demand for a sign had been so far limited, and the other, the spiritual line of evidence, had become so important, or at least so indispensable, that it was no longer possible to build on the miracles only, or to regard Jesus merely as a [pg 149] wonder-worker; so in some way or other the importance ascribed to miracle must be reduced. In the graphic symbolism of the Gospel history this antithesis takes the form that Jesus did miracles—there was no getting away from that—but on the other hand Himself declared that He did not wish to lay any stress upon such acts. As there are times when miracles must hide their light under a bushel, Jesus, on occasion, forbids that they should be made known. The other Synoptists no longer understood this theory of the first Evangelist, and introduced the prohibition in passages where it was absurd.

Bauer thoroughly examines the sayings of Jesus where He instructs those He healed not to spread the news about their healing. He argues that these sayings, as they appear, can't be historical because Jesus imposes this restriction in situations where it doesn't make sense, especially since the healing happened in front of a crowd. Therefore, it must originate from the Evangelist. Only when we see it as a creative interpretation can we understand its meaning. It reflects the conflicting views about miracles that existed in the early Church. There was no doubt that Jesus performed miracles, which demonstrated His Divine mission. However, with the introduction of the Christian principle, the Jewish demand for signs was limited, and the spiritual evidence became so essential that it was no longer enough to rely solely on miracles or view Jesus just as a miracle-worker; thus, the significance attributed to miracles had to be diminished. In the vivid imagery of the Gospel narrative, this contradiction is shown by the fact that Jesus performed miracles—there was no denying that—but He also declared that He didn’t want to emphasize these acts. Just as there are times when miracles need to be kept hidden, there were occasions when Jesus instructed that they shouldn't be disclosed. The other Synoptists didn't grasp this theory of the first Evangelist and included the prohibition in contexts where it was nonsensical.

The way in which Jesus makes known His Messiahship is based on another theory of the original Evangelist. The order of Mark can give us no information regarding the chronology of the life of Jesus, since this Gospel is anything rather than a chronicle. We cannot even assert that there is a deliberate logic in the way in which the sections are connected. But there is one fundamental principle of arrangement which comes quite clearly to light, viz. that it was only at Caesarea Philippi, in the closing period of His life, that Jesus made Himself known as the Messiah, and that, therefore, He was not previously held to be so either by His disciples or by the people. This is clearly shown in the answers of the disciples when Jesus asked them whom men took Him to be. The implied course of events, however, is determined by art, not history—as history it would be inconceivable.

The way Jesus reveals His role as the Messiah is based on a different idea from the original Evangelist. The order of Mark doesn't provide any details about the timeline of Jesus' life, since this Gospel is anything but a straightforward account. We can't even say there's a clear logic in how the sections are linked. However, one key principle of organization stands out: it was only at Caesarea Philippi, toward the end of His life, that Jesus declared Himself as the Messiah. Therefore, neither His disciples nor the people recognized Him as such before this moment. This is clearly illustrated in the disciples' responses when Jesus asked who people thought He was. The implied sequence of events, however, is shaped by artistry rather than actual history—because as history, it would be unimaginable.

Could there indeed be a more absurd impossibility? “Jesus,” says Bauer, “must perform these innumerable, these astounding miracles because, according to the view which the Gospels represent, He is the Messiah; He must perform them in order to prove Himself to be the Messiah—and yet no one recognises Him as the Messiah! That is the greatest miracle of all, that the people had not long ago recognised the Messiah in this wonder-worker. Jesus could only be held to be the Messiah in consequence of doing miracles; but He only began to do miracles when, in the faith of the early Church, He rose from the dead as Messiah, and the facts that He rose as Messiah and that He did miracles, are one and the same fact.”

Could there really be a more ridiculous impossibility? “Jesus,” says Bauer, "has to perform these countless, amazing miracles because, from the perspective shown in the Gospels, He is the Messiah; He needs to perform them to prove He is the Messiah—and yet, no one recognizes Him as the Messiah! That’s the biggest miracle of all, that people didn’t see the Messiah in this miracle worker long ago. Jesus could only be recognized as the Messiah by performing miracles; but He only began performing miracles when, according to the early Church's belief, He rose from the dead as the Messiah, and the truths that He rose as the Messiah and that He performed miracles are essentially the same truth."

Mark, however, represents a Jesus who does miracles and who nevertheless does not thereby reveal Himself to be the Messiah. He was obliged so to represent Him, because he was conscious that Jesus was not recognised and acknowledged as Messiah by the people, nor even by His immediate followers, in the unhesitating fashion in which those of later times imagined Him to have been recognised. Mark's conception and representation of the matter carried back into the past the later developments by which there finally arose a Christian community for which Jesus had become the Messiah. “Mark is also influenced by an artistic instinct which [pg 150] leads him to develop the main interest, the origin of the faith, gradually. It is only after the ministry of Jesus has extended over a considerable period, and is, indeed, drawing towards its close, that faith arises in the circle of the disciples; and it is only later still, when, in the person of the blind man at Jericho, a prototype of the great company of believers that was to be has hailed the Lord with a Messianic salutation, that, at the triumphal entry into Jerusalem, the faith of the people suddenly ripens and finds expression.”

Mark, however, portrays a Jesus who performs miracles yet doesn't clearly show Himself to be the Messiah. He had to depict Him this way because he knew that Jesus wasn't recognized or accepted as the Messiah by the people, not even by His closest followers, in the straightforward way that later generations thought He was. Mark's understanding and portrayal of the situation pushed back the later developments that ultimately led to a Christian community where Jesus was acknowledged as the Messiah. Mark is also influenced by a creative instinct that [pg 150] drives him to gradually develop the main focus, which is the origin of faith. Only after Jesus' ministry has been going on for a significant time and is nearing its end does faith begin to emerge among the disciples. Later, when the blind man in Jericho, representing the larger group of future believers, calls out to the Lord with a Messianic greeting, the faith of the people suddenly matures and finds its voice during the triumphal entry into Jerusalem.

It is true, this artistic design is completely marred when Jesus does miracles which must have made Him known to every child as the Messiah. We cannot, therefore, blame Matthew very much if, while he retains this plan in its external outlines in a kind of mechanical way, he contradicts it somewhat awkwardly by making Jesus at an earlier point clearly designate Himself as Messiah and many recognise Him as such. And the Fourth Evangelist cannot be said to be destroying any very wonderful work of art when he gives the impression that from the very first any one who wished could recognise Jesus as the Messiah.

It's true, this artistic design gets completely ruined when Jesus performs miracles that must have made Him known to every child as the Messiah. So, we can't blame Matthew too much if, while he keeps this plan in its basic form in a somewhat mechanical way, he awkwardly contradicts it by having Jesus clearly identify Himself as the Messiah earlier on and many people recognizing Him as such. And we can't say that the Fourth Evangelist is ruining any great work of art when he gives the impression that anyone who wanted to could recognize Jesus as the Messiah from the very beginning.

Mark himself does not keep strictly to his own plan. He makes Jesus forbid His disciples to make known His Messiahship; how then does the multitude at Jerusalem recognise it so suddenly, after a single miracle which they had not even witnessed, and which was in no way different from others which He had done before? If that “chance multitude” in Jerusalem was capable of such sudden enlightenment it must have fallen from heaven!

Mark himself doesn't stick strictly to his own plan. He has Jesus tell His disciples not to reveal His Messiahship; so how does the crowd in Jerusalem suddenly recognize it after just one miracle they didn't even see, which wasn’t any different from others He had performed before? If that “random crowd” in Jerusalem was capable of such sudden understanding, it must have come down from heaven!

The following remarks of Bauer, too, are nothing less than classical. The incident at Caesarea Philippi is the central fact of the Gospel history; it gives us a fixed point from which to group and criticise the other statements of the Gospel. At the same time it introduces a complication into the plan of the life of Jesus, because it necessitates the carrying through of the theory—often in the face of the text—that previously Jesus had never been regarded as the Messiah; and lays upon us the necessity of showing not only how Peter had come to recognise His Messiahship, but also how He subsequently became Messiah for the multitude—if indeed He ever did become Messiah for them. But the very fact that it does introduce this complication is in itself a proof that in this scene at Caesarea Philippi we have the one ray of light which history sheds upon the life of Jesus. It is impossible to explain how any one could come to reject the simple and natural idea that Jesus claimed from the first to be the Messiah, if that had been the fact, and accept this complicated representation in its place. The latter, therefore, must be the original version. In pointing this out, Bauer gave for the first time the real proof, from internal evidence, of the priority of Mark.

The following remarks of Bauer are nothing short of classic. The incident at Caesarea Philippi is the key event in the Gospel narrative; it provides a solid reference point from which we can organize and critique the other Gospel statements. At the same time, it complicates the story of Jesus' life because it requires us to confront the idea—often against the text—that Jesus was not previously seen as the Messiah. It also compels us to explain not just how Peter recognized His Messiahship, but also how He eventually became known as the Messiah to the crowd—if He ever did. However, the very introduction of this complication proves that this scene at Caesarea Philippi offers the clearest insight we have into Jesus' life. It's hard to understand how anyone could dismiss the straightforward notion that Jesus always claimed to be the Messiah if that were true, and instead accept this complicated version. Thus, the latter must be the original account. By highlighting this, Bauer provided the first real evidence, based on internal clues, for the priority of Mark.

[pg 151]

The difficulty involved in the conception of miracle as a proof of the Messiahship of Jesus is another discovery of Bauer's. Only here, instead of probing the question to the bottom, he stops half-way. How do we know, he should have gone on to ask, that the Messiah was expected to appear as an earthly wonder-worker? There is nothing to that effect in Jewish writings. And do not the Gospels themselves prove that any one might do miracles without suggesting to a single person the idea that he might be the Messiah? Accordingly the only inference to be drawn from the Marcan representation is that miracles were not among the characteristic marks of the Messiah, and that it was only later, in the Christian community, which made Jesus the miracle-worker into Jesus the Messiah, that this connexion between miracles and Messiahship was established. In dealing with the question of the triumphal entry, too, Bauer halts half-way. Where do we read that Jesus was hailed as Messiah upon that occasion? If He had been taken by the people to be the Messiah, the controversy in Jerusalem must have turned on this personal question; but it did not even touch upon it, and the Sanhedrin never thinks of setting up witnesses to Jesus' claim to be the Messiah. When once Bauer had exposed the historical and literary impossibility of Jesus' being hailed by the people as Messiah, he ought to have gone on to draw the conclusion that Jesus did not, according to Mark, make a Messianic entry into Jerusalem.

The challenge of understanding miracles as evidence of Jesus' role as the Messiah is another insight from Bauer. However, instead of fully exploring the issue, he only gets halfway. He should have asked, how do we know that the Messiah was expected to show up as a miracle worker? There's nothing in Jewish texts that suggests this. And don’t the Gospels themselves indicate that anyone could perform miracles without leading anyone to think they might be the Messiah? So, the only conclusion we can draw from Mark’s portrayal is that miracles weren’t a key feature of the Messiah, and it was only later, within the Christian community that labeled Jesus as a miracle worker, that the link between miracles and being the Messiah was made. When addressing the question of the triumphal entry, Bauer also falls short. Where does it say that Jesus was recognized as the Messiah in that moment? If the people had seen Him as the Messiah, the debate in Jerusalem would have revolved around that issue; but it never mentioned that, and the Sanhedrin didn’t even consider bringing in witnesses for Jesus’ supposed claim to be the Messiah. Once Bauer had pointed out the historical and literary impossibility of Jesus being declared the Messiah by the people, he should have concluded that, according to Mark, Jesus did not make a Messianic entry into Jerusalem.

It was, however, a remarkable achievement on Bauer's part to have thus set forth clearly the historical difficulties of the life of Jesus. One might suppose that between the work of Strauss and that of Bauer there lay not five, but fifty years—the critical work of a whole generation.

It was, however, a remarkable achievement on Bauer's part to have clearly outlined the historical challenges in the life of Jesus. One might think that between the work of Strauss and that of Bauer there was not five years, but fifty years—the critical work of an entire generation.

The stereotyped character of the thrice-repeated prediction of the passion, which, according to Bauer, betrays a certain poverty and feebleness of imagination on the part of the earliest Evangelist, shows clearly, he thinks, the unhistorical character of the utterance recorded. The fact that the prediction occurs three times, its definiteness increasing upon each occasion, proves its literary origin.

The clichéd character of the three-fold prediction of the passion, which, according to Bauer, reveals a lack of creativity and weakness of imagination on the part of the earliest Evangelist, clearly demonstrates the unhistorical nature of the statement documented. The fact that the prediction appears three times, with its clarity growing each time, indicates its literary origin.

It is the same with the transfiguration. The group in which the heroic representatives of the Law and the Prophets stand as supporters of the Saviour, was modelled by the earliest Evangelist. In order to place it in the proper light and to give becoming splendour to its great subject, he has introduced a number of traits taken from the story of Moses.

It’s the same with the transfiguration. The group where the heroic figures of the Law and the Prophets stand as supporters of the Savior was shaped by the earliest Evangelist. To highlight it appropriately and give it the grandeur it deserves, he included several elements taken from the story of Moses.

Bauer pitilessly exposes the difficulties of the journey of Jesus from Galilee to Jerusalem, and exults over the perplexities of the “apologists.” “The theologian,” he says, “must not boggle at this journey, he must just believe it. He must in faith follow the footsteps of his Lord! Through the midst of Galilee and Samaria—and [pg 152] at the same time, for Matthew also claims a hearing, through Judaea on the farther side of Jordan! I wish him Bon voyage!”

Bauer ruthlessly points out the challenges of Jesus' journey from Galilee to Jerusalem and revels in the confusion of the “apologists.” “The theologian,” he says, “shouldn’t doubt this journey; he just needs to believe it. He must faithfully follow the path of his Lord! Through the heart of Galilee and Samaria—and at the same time, since Matthew is also asking to be heard, through Judea on the far side of the Jordan! I wish him Bon voyage!”

The eschatological discourses are not history, but are merely an expansion of those explanations of the sufferings of the Church of which we have had a previous example in the charge to the Twelve. An Evangelist who wrote before the destruction of Jerusalem would have referred to the Temple, to Jerusalem, and to the Jewish people, in a very different way.

The eschatological discourses aren't history; they're just an extension of the explanations for the Church's sufferings, similar to what we saw in the charge to the Twelve. An Evangelist writing before the fall of Jerusalem would have talked about the Temple, Jerusalem, and the Jewish people in a very different manner.

The story of Lazarus deserves special attention. Did not Spinoza say that he would break his system in pieces if he could be convinced of the reality of this event? This is the decisive point for the question of the relation between the Synoptists and John. Vain are all the efforts of the apologists to explain why the Synoptists do not mention this miracle. The reason they ignore it is that it originated after their time in the mind of the Fourth Evangelist, and they were unacquainted with his Gospel. And yet it is the most valuable of all, because it shows clearly the concentric circles of progressive intensification by which the development of the Gospel history proceeds. “The Fourth Gospel,” remarks Bauer, “represents a dead man as having been restored to life after having been four days under the power of death, and having consequently become a prey to corruption; Luke represents the young man at Nain as being restored to life when his body was being carried to the grave; Mark, the earliest Evangelist, can only tell us of the restoration of a dead person who had the moment before succumbed to an illness. The theologians have a great deal to say about the contrast between the canonical and the apocryphal writings, but they might have found a similar contrast even within the four Gospels, if the light had not been so directly in their eyes.”

The story of Lazarus deserves special attention. Didn’t Spinoza say he would break his system apart if he could be convinced that this event was real? This is the crucial point in discussing the relationship between the Synoptists and John. All the efforts of the apologists to explain why the Synoptists don’t mention this miracle are pointless. The reason they overlook it is that it came after their time in the mind of the Fourth Evangelist, and they weren’t familiar with his Gospel. Yet, it is the most valuable of all because it clearly shows the concentric circles of progressive intensification through which the development of Gospel history unfolds. "The Gospel of John," notes Bauer, “presents a dead man brought back to life after being dead for four days and starting to decompose; Luke describes the young man at Nain being revived just as his body is taken to the grave; Mark, the earliest Evangelist, only refers to the revival of someone who has just died from an illness. Theologians often discuss the differences between canon and apocryphal texts, but they might have noticed a similar contrast even among the four Gospels if the differences hadn’t been so obvious.”

The treachery of Judas, as described in the Gospels, is inexplicable.

The betrayal of Judas, as described in the Gospels, is beyond explanation.

The Lord's Supper, considered as an historic scene, is revolting and inconceivable. Jesus can no more have instituted it than He can have uttered the saying, “Let the dead bury their dead.” In both cases the objectionableness arises from the fact that a tenet of the early Church has been cast into the form of an historical saying of Jesus. A man who was present in person, corporeally present, could not entertain the idea of offering others his flesh and blood to eat. To demand from others that they should, while he was actually present, imagine the bread and wine which they were eating to be his body and blood, would be for an actual man wholly impossible. It was only when Jesus' actual bodily presence had been removed, and only when the Christian community had existed for some time, that such a conception as is expressed in that formula could have arisen. A point which clearly betrays the [pg 153] later composition of the narrative is that the Lord does not turn to the disciples sitting with Him at table and say, “This is my blood which is shed for you,” but, since the words were invented by the early Church, speaks of the “many” for whom He gives Himself. The only historical fact is that the Jewish Passover was gradually transformed by the Christian community into a feast which had reference to Jesus.

The Lord's Supper, considered as a historical event, is shocking and hard to believe. Jesus couldn't have established it any more than he could have said, "Let the dead take care of burying their own." In both instances, the problem lies in the fact that a belief from the early Church has been presented as a historical statement by Jesus. A person who was physically present couldn’t possibly think of offering his flesh and blood for others to consume. Asking others to believe that the bread and wine they were eating represented his body and blood, while he was actually there, would be completely impossible for a real person. It was only after Jesus' physical presence was gone and after the Christian community had been around for a while that the concept expressed in that formula could arise. A clear indication of the later creation of the narrative is that the Lord doesn’t turn to the disciples at the table and say, “This is my blood, poured out for you.” but instead, since those words were made up by the early Church, refers to the numerous for whom he gives himself. The only historical fact is that the Jewish Passover was gradually changed by the Christian community into a feast that related to Jesus.

As regards the scene in Gethsemane, Mark, according to Bauer, held it necessary that in the moment when the last conflict and final catastrophe were coming upon Jesus, He should show clearly by His actions that He met this fate of His own free will. The reality of His choice could only be made clear by showing Him first engaged in an inner struggle against the acceptance of His vocation, before showing how He freely submitted to His fate.

Regarding the scene in Gethsemane, Mark, as Bauer suggests, believed it was important for Jesus to demonstrate through His actions that He faced His impending fate willingly when the final conflict and disaster approached. The authenticity of His choice could only be established by depicting Him first in an internal struggle against accepting His mission, followed by illustrating how He voluntarily accepted His destiny.

The last words ascribed to Jesus by Mark, “My God, my God, why hast Thou forsaken me?” were written without thinking of the inferences that might be drawn from them, merely with the purpose of showing that even to the last moment of His passion Jesus fulfilled the rôle of the Messiah, the picture of whose sufferings had been revealed to the Psalmist so long beforehand by the Holy Spirit.

The last words attributed to Jesus by Mark, “My God, my God, why have you left me?” were written without considering the implications they might have, simply to show that even in His final moments, Jesus fulfilled the role of the Messiah, whose sufferings had been foretold to the Psalmist long ago by the Holy Spirit.

It is scarcely necessary now, Bauer thinks, to go into the contradictions in the story of the resurrection, for “the doughty Reimarus, with his thorough-going honesty, has already fully exposed them, and no one has refuted him.”

It’s hardly even needed now, Bauer thinks, to discuss the contradictions in the resurrection story, because “The brave Reimarus, with his total honesty, has already fully exposed them, and no one has refuted him.”

The results of Bauer's analysis may be summed up as follows:—

The results of Bauer's analysis can be summarized as follows:—

The Fourth Evangelist has betrayed the secret of the original Gospel, namely, that it too can be explained on purely literary grounds. Mark has “loosed us from the theological lie.” “Thanks to the kindly fate,” cries Bauer, “which has preserved to us this writing of Mark by which we have been delivered from the web of deceit of this hellish pseudo-science!”

The Fourth Evangelist has revealed the secret of the original Gospel, which can also be understood purely from a literary perspective. Mark has “freed us from the theological falsehood.” “Thanks to good fortune,” exclaims Bauer, “that has kept this writing of Mark for us, by which we have been saved from the snare of this deceptive pseudo-science!”

In order to tear this web of falsehood the critic and historian must, despite his repugnance, once more take up the pretended arguments of the theologians in favour of the historicity of the Gospel narratives and set them on their feet, only to knock them down again. In the end Bauer's only feeling towards the theologians was one of contempt. “The expression of his contempt,” he declares, “is the last weapon which the critic, after refuting the arguments of the theologians, has at his disposal for their discomfiture; it is his right to use it; that puts the finishing touch upon his task and points forward to the happy time when the arguments of the theologians shall no more be heard of.”

To break this web of lies, the critic and historian must, despite their dislike, once again address the supposed arguments of the theologians supporting the factual basis of the Gospel narratives and expose their flaws, only to dismantle them again. In the end, Bauer held nothing but contempt for the theologians. "His look of disdain," he states, “is the ultimate tool the critic has after refuting the theologians’ arguments; he has the right to use it; it finishes his work and suggests a hopeful future when the theologians’ arguments will no longer matter.”

These outbreaks of bitterness are to be explained by the feeling of repulsion which German apologetic theology inspired in every genuinely honest and thoughtful man by the methods which it adopted in opposing Strauss. Hence the fiendish joy with which [pg 154] he snatches away the crutches of this pseudo-science, hurls them to a distance, and makes merry over its helplessness. A furious hatred, a fierce desire to strip the theologians absolutely bare, carried Bauer much farther than his critical acumen would have led him in cold blood.

These outbursts of bitterness can be traced back to the feelings of disgust that German apologetic theology stirred in every genuinely honest and thoughtful person through its methods in opposing Strauss. This explains the twisted delight with which [pg 154] he takes away the crutches of this pseudo-science, tosses them aside, and revels in its powerlessness. A raging hatred, a strong urge to expose the theologians completely, drove Bauer much further than his critical insight would have normally allowed.

Bauer hated the theologians for still holding fast to the barbarous conception that a great man had forced himself into a stereotyped and unspiritual system, and in that way had set in motion great ideas, whereas he held that that would have signified the death of both the personality and the ideas; but this hatred is only the surface symptom of another hatred, which goes deeper than theology, going down, indeed, to the very depths of the Christian conception of the world. Bruno Bauer hates not only the theologians, but Christianity, and hates it because it expresses a truth in a wrong way. It is a religion which has become petrified in a transitional form. A religion which ought to have led on to the true religion has usurped the place of the true religion, and in this petrified form it holds prisoner all the real forces of religion.

Bauer despised the theologians for clinging to the outdated belief that a great man had forced himself into a rigid and lifeless system, thereby igniting great ideas, while he believed that would signify the end of both the individual and the ideas. However, this hatred is just a surface symptom of a deeper resentment, one that goes beyond theology and reaches to the very core of the Christian worldview. Bruno Bauer doesn't just hate the theologians; he resents Christianity itself, because it conveys a truth in a flawed manner. It’s a religion that has become stuck in a transitional phase. A religion that was meant to lead to true faith has taken the place of genuine spirituality, and in this rigid form, it restricts all the real forces of religion.

Religion is the victory over the world of the self-conscious ego. It is only when the ego grasps itself in its antithesis to the world as a whole, and is no longer content to play the part of a mere “walking gentleman” in the world-drama, but faces the world with independence and reserve, that the necessary conditions of universal religion are present. These conditions came into being with the rise of the Roman Empire, in which the individual suddenly found himself helpless and unarmed in face of a world in which he could no longer find free play for his activities, but must stand prepared at any moment to be ground to powder by it.

Religion is the victory over the world of the self-conscious ego. It's only when the ego understands itself in contrast to the world as a whole and is no longer satisfied with just being a “walking gentleman” in the world-drama, but instead confronts the world with independence and restraint, that the necessary conditions for universal religion are present. These conditions emerged with the rise of the Roman Empire, where the individual suddenly found himself powerless and exposed in a world where he could no longer freely express his activities but had to be ready at any moment to be crushed by it.

The self-conscious ego, recognising this position, found itself faced by the necessity of breaking loose from the world and standing alone, in order in this way to overcome the world. Victory over the world by alienation from the world—these were the ideas out of which Christianity was born. But it was not the true victory over the world; Christianity remained at the stage of violent opposition to the world.

The self-aware ego, recognizing its situation, realized it had to detach from the world and stand on its own to conquer it. Winning against the world through alienation—these were the ideas that gave rise to Christianity. However, it wasn't a genuine victory over the world; Christianity stayed at a point of strong opposition to the world.

Miracle, to which the Christian religion has always appealed, and to which it gives a quite fundamental importance, is the appropriate symbol of this false victory over the world. There are some wonderfully deep thoughts scattered through Bauer's critical investigations. “Man's realisation of his personality,” he says, “is the death of Nature, but in the sense that he can only bring about this death by the knowledge of Nature and its laws, that is to say from within, being himself essentially the annihilation and negation of Nature.... Spirit honours and recognises the worth of the very thing which it negates.... Spirit does not fume and bluster, and rage and rave against Nature, as it is supposed to do [pg 155] in miracle, for that would be the denial of its inner law, but quietly works its way through the antithesis. In short the death of Nature implied in the conscious realisation of personality is the resurrection of Nature in a nobler form, not the maltreatment, mockery, and insult to which it would be exposed by miracle.” Not only miracle, however, but the portrait of Jesus Christ as drawn in the Gospels, is a stereotyping of that false idea of victory over the world. The Christ of the Gospel history, thought of as a really historic figure, would be a figure at which humanity would shudder, a figure which could only inspire dismay and horror. The historical Jesus, if He really existed, can only have been One who reconciled in His own consciousness the antithesis which obsessed the Jewish mind, namely the separation between God and Man; He cannot in the process of removing this antithesis have called into existence a new principle of religious division and alienation; nor can He have shown the way of escape, by the principle of inwardness, from the bondage of the Law only to impose a new set of legal fetters.

Miracle, which the Christian religion has always relied on and considers fundamentally important, symbolizes this false victory over the world. Bauer’s critical investigations contain some profound insights. He states, “Man's realization of his personality is the death of Nature, but in the sense that he can only achieve this death through the understanding of Nature and its laws, meaning from within, as he is essentially the annihilation and negation of Nature.... Spirit honors and recognizes the worth of the very thing it negates.... Spirit does not rage, fume, or complain against Nature, as it supposedly does in miracle, because that would contradict its inner law, but quietly works its way through the contradiction. In short, the death of Nature implied in the conscious realization of personality is the resurrection of Nature in a nobler form, not the mistreatment, mockery, and insult it would suffer from miracle.” However, it’s not just miracle; the portrayal of Jesus Christ in the Gospels also reinforces this false idea of victory over the world. The Christ of Gospel history, viewed as a real historical figure, would be someone humanity would find terrifying, someone who could only evoke fear and horror. The historical Jesus, if He truly existed, would have been One who reconciled in His own consciousness the conflict that troubled the Jewish mind, namely the separation between God and Man; in the process of eliminating this conflict, He could not have created a new principle of religious division and alienation; nor could He have shown a way to escape, through inwardness, from the bondage of the Law only to impose a new set of legal restrictions.

The Christ of the Gospel history, on the other hand, is Man exalted by the religious consciousness to heaven, who, even if He comes down to earth to do miracles, to teach, and to suffer, is no longer true man. The Son of Man of religion, even though His mission be to reconcile, is man as alienated from himself. This Christ of the Gospel history, the ego exalted to heaven and become God, overthrew antiquity, and conquered the world in the sense that He exhausted it of all its vitality. This magnified ego would have fulfilled its historical vocation if, by means of the terrible disorganisation into which it threw the real spirit of mankind, it had compelled the latter to come to a knowledge of itself, to become self-conscious with a thoroughness and decisiveness which had not been possible to the simple spirit of antiquity. It was disastrous that the figure which stood for the first emancipation of the ego, remained alive. That transformation of the human spirit which was brought about by the encounter of the world-power of Rome with philosophy was represented by the Gospels, under the influence of the Old Testament, as realised in a single historic Personality; and the strength of the spirit of mankind was swallowed up by the omnipotence of the pure absolute ego, an ego which was alien from actual humanity. The self-consciousness of humanity finds itself reflected in the Gospels, a self, indeed, in alienation from itself, and therefore a grotesque parody of itself, but, after all, in some sense, itself; hence the magical charm which attracted mankind and enchained it, and, so long as it had not truly found itself, urged it to sacrifice everything to grasp the image of itself, to prefer it to all other and all else, counting all, as the apostle says, but “dung” in comparison with it.

The Christ of the Gospel story, on the other hand, is a Man elevated by religious belief to the heavens, who, even if He comes down to earth to perform miracles, to teach, and to suffer, is no longer a true man. The Son of Man in religion, even though His mission is to reconcile, is a man who is alienated from himself. This Christ of the Gospel narrative, the self glorified to heaven and made God, overturned the ancient world and took over the globe in a way that drained it of all its vitality. This exalted self would have accomplished its historical purpose if, through the profound disruption it caused in the true spirit of humanity, it had forced people to become aware of themselves, achieving self-consciousness with a depth and determination that wasn’t possible for the simple spirit of antiquity. It was unfortunate that the figure representing the initial liberation of the self remained alive. The transformation of the human spirit, brought about by the clash between the world power of Rome and philosophy, was depicted by the Gospels, under the influence of the Old Testament, as realized in a single historical figure; and the strength of human spirit was consumed by the all-powerful pure absolute self, a self that was separate from actual humanity. Humanity’s self-consciousness is reflected in the Gospels, a self that is indeed alienated from itself, and thus a ridiculous parody of itself, but still, in some way, itself; hence the magical allure that drew people in and bound them, and as long as humanity had not truly found itself, it compelled them to sacrifice everything to seize the image of itself, to prefer it above all else, counting everything, as the apostle says, but manure in comparison to it.

Even when the Roman world was no more, and a new world [pg 156] had come into being, the Christ so created did not die. The magic of His enchantment became only more terrible, and as new strength came flooding into the old world, the time arrived when it was to accomplish its greatest work of destruction. Spirit, in its abstraction, became a vampire, the destroyer of the world. Sap and strength, blood and life, it sucked, to the last drop, out of humanity. Nature and art, family, nation, state, all were destroyed by it; and in the ruins of the fallen world the ego, exhausted by its efforts, remained the only surviving power.

Even when the Roman world was gone and a new world [pg 156] had emerged, the Christ that was created did not die. The power of His spell only grew stronger, and as new energy surged into the old world, the time came for it to unleash its greatest wave of destruction. Spirit, in its abstract form, became a vampire, a destroyer of the world. It drained sap and strength, blood and life, until every last drop was gone from humanity. Nature and art, family, nation, state—everything was obliterated by it; and in the wreckage of the fallen world, the ego, worn out from its struggles, stood as the only surviving force.

Having made a desert all about it, the ego could not immediately create anew, out of the depths of its inner consciousness, nature and art, nation and state; the awful process which now went on, the only activity of which it was now capable, was the absorption into itself of all that had hitherto had life in the world. The ego was now everything; and yet it was a void. It had become the universal power, and yet as it brooded over the ruins of the world it was filled with horror at itself and with despair at all that it had lost. The ego which had devoured all things and was still a void now shuddered at itself.

After creating a wasteland around itself, the ego couldn’t immediately rebuild anything from the depths of its inner self—no nature, no art, no nation, no state. The terrible process that was happening now, the only thing it could do, was to absorb everything that had once been alive in the world. The ego became everything; yet it was an emptiness. It had turned into a universal power, but as it reflected on the ruins of the world, it was filled with horror at itself and despair over everything it had lost. The ego that had consumed everything and remained empty now trembled at its own existence.

Under the oppression of this awful power the education of mankind has been going on; under this grim task-master it has been preparing for true freedom, preparing to rouse itself from the depths of its distress, to escape from its opposition to itself and cast out that alien ego which is wasting its substance. Odysseus has now returned to his home, not by favour of the gods, not laid on the shore in sleep, but awake, by his own thought and his own strength. Perchance, as of yore, he will have need to fight with the suitors who have devoured his substance and sought to rob him of all he holds most dear. Odysseus must string the bow once more.

Under the weight of this terrible power, the education of humanity has been ongoing; under this harsh taskmaster, it has been getting ready for true freedom, preparing to rise from the depths of its suffering, to break free from the conflict within itself and to eliminate that foreign ego that is draining its resources. Odysseus has now returned home, not by the grace of the gods, not washed ashore in sleep, but awake, using his own intellect and strength. Perhaps, as before, he will need to confront the suitors who have consumed his wealth and tried to take from him everything he values most. Odysseus must string the bow once more.

The baleful charm of the self-alienated ego is broken the moment any one proves to the religious sense of mankind that the Jesus Christ of the Gospels is its creation and ceases to exist as soon as this is recognised. The formation of the Church and the arising of the idea that the Jesus of the Gospels is the Messiah are not two different things, they are one and the same thing, they coincide and synchronise; but the idea was only the imaginative conception of the Church, the first movement of its life, the religious expression of its experience.

The harmful allure of a disconnected self is shattered the moment someone demonstrates to humanity's spiritual awareness that the Jesus Christ of the Gospels is a product of our own making and disappears as soon as this is acknowledged. The establishment of the Church and the emergence of the belief that the Jesus of the Gospels is the Messiah are not separate concepts; they are one and the same, perfectly aligned and in sync. However, this belief was merely an imaginative idea of the Church, the initial spark of its existence, reflecting the religious expression of its experiences.

The question which has so much exercised the minds of men—whether Jesus was the historic Christ (= Messiah)—is answered in the sense that everything that the historical Christ is, everything that is said of Him, everything that is known of Him, belongs to the world of imagination, that is, of the imagination of the Christian community, and therefore has nothing to do with any man who belongs to the real world.

The question that has occupied people's minds—is Jesus the historical Christ (Messiah)?—is answered in a way that suggests everything about the historical Christ, everything said about Him, and everything known about Him, belongs to the realm of imagination, specifically the imagination of the Christian community, and therefore has no connection to anyone who exists in the real world.

[pg 157]

The world is now free, and ripe for a higher religion in which the ego will overcome nature, not by self-alienation, but by penetrating it and ennobling it. To the theologian we may fling as a gift the shreds of his former science, when we have torn it to pieces; that will be something to occupy himself with, that time may not hang heavy upon his hands in the new world whose advent is steadily drawing nearer.

The world is now free and ready for a higher form of spirituality where the self transcends nature, not by rejecting it, but by understanding and uplifting it. We can offer the theologian what’s left of his old beliefs after we’ve dismantled them; that will give him something to focus on so he doesn't feel lost in the new world that's approaching.

Thus the task which Bauer had set himself at the beginning of his criticism of the Gospel history, turned, before he had finished, into something different. When he began, he thought to save the honour of Jesus and to restore His Person from the state of inanition to which the apologists had reduced it, and hoped by furnishing a proof that the historical Jesus could not have been the Jesus Christ of the Gospels, to bring Him into a living relation with history. This task, however, was given up in favour of the larger one of freeing the world from the domination of the Judaeo-Roman idol, Jesus the Messiah, and in carrying out this endeavour the thesis that Jesus Christ is a product of the imagination of the early Church is formulated in such a way that the existence of a historic Jesus becomes problematical, or, at any rate, quite indifferent.

Thus the task that Bauer had set for himself at the start of his critique of the Gospel history evolved into something different before he finished. When he began, he aimed to preserve the honor of Jesus and to bring His figure back from the state of insignificance that the apologists had placed it in. He hoped that by providing evidence that the historical Jesus could not have been the Jesus Christ of the Gospels, he could connect Him more meaningfully to history. However, this task was abandoned in favor of a bigger goal: liberating the world from the influence of the Judaeo-Roman idol, Jesus the Messiah. In pursuing this aim, the argument that Jesus Christ is a creation of the early Church's imagination is presented in such a way that the existence of a historical Jesus becomes questionable, or at least, largely irrelevant.

At the end of his study of the Gospels, Bauer is inclined to make the decision of the question whether there ever was a historic Jesus depend on the result of a further investigation which he proposed to make into the Pauline Epistles. It was not until ten years later (1850-1851) that he accomplished this task,94 and applied the result in his new edition of the “Criticism of the Gospel History.”95 The result is negative: there never was any historical Jesus. While criticising the four great Pauline Epistles, which the Tübingen school fondly imagined to be beyond the reach of criticism, Bauer shows, however, his inability to lay a positive historic foundation for his view of the origin of Christianity. The transference of the Epistles to the second century is effected in so arbitrary a fashion that it refutes itself. However, this work professes to be only a preliminary study for a larger one in which the new theory was to be fully worked out. This did not appear until 1877; it was entitled “Christ and the Caesars; How Christianity originated from Graeco-Roman Civilisation.”96 The historical basis for his theory, which he here offers, is even more unsatisfactory than that suggested in the preliminary work on the Pauline Epistles. There is no longer any pretence of following [pg 158] an historical method, the whole thing works out into an imaginary picture of the life of Seneca. Nero's tutor had, Bauer thinks, already in his inmost consciousness fully attained to inner opposition to the world. There are expressions in his works which, in their mystical emancipation from the world, prelude the utterances of Paul. The same thoughts, since they belong not to Seneca only, but to his time, are found also in the works of the three poets of the Neronian period, Persius, Lucan, and Petronius. Though they had but a feeble breath of the divine afflatus, they are interesting witnesses to the spiritual condition of the time. They, too, contributed to the making of Christianity.

At the end of his study of the Gospels, Bauer tends to base the question of whether a historical Jesus ever existed on the outcome of further research he planned to conduct on the Pauline Epistles. It wasn't until ten years later (1850-1851) that he completed this task,94 and incorporated the findings into his new edition of the “Critique of the Gospel History.”95 The outcome is negative: there was never a historical Jesus. While critiquing the four major Pauline Epistles, which the Tübingen school believed to be above reproach, Bauer reveals his inability to establish a solid historical basis for his perspective on the origin of Christianity. The transfer of the Epistles to the second century is done so arbitrarily that it undermines itself. However, this work claims to be just a preliminary study for a larger project in which the new theory would be fully developed. This larger work didn't come out until 1877; it was titled "Christ and the Caesars: How Christianity Began from Greco-Roman Civilization."96 The historical foundation for his theory presented here is even less convincing than what was proposed in the initial study of the Pauline Epistles. There’s no longer any pretense of adhering to a historical method; the entire argument transforms into a fictional portrayal of Seneca's life. Bauer believes that Nero's tutor had, in his deepest consciousness, already reached a state of inner conflict with the world. There are phrases in his works that, through their mystical detachment from material existence, foreshadow the teachings of Paul. These same ideas, being common to Seneca’s time and not exclusive to him, can also be found in the works of the three poets from the Neronian era, Persius, Lucan, and Petronius. Although they lacked a strong divine inspiration, they are interesting witnesses to the spiritual state of the period. They too played a part in the development of Christianity.

But Seneca, in spite of his inner alienation from the world, remained in active relations with the world. He desired to found a kingdom of virtue upon earth. At the courts of Claudius and Nero he used the arts of intrigue to further his ends, and even quietly approved deeds of violence which he thought likely to serve his cause. Finally, he grasped at the supreme power; and paid the supreme penalty. Stoicism had made an attempt to reform the world, and had failed. The great thinkers began to despair of exercising any influence upon history, the Senate was powerless, all public bodies were deprived of their rights. Then a spirit of resignation came over the world. The alienation from the world, which in Seneca had still been only half serious, was come in earnest. The time of Nero and Domitian was a great epoch in that hidden spiritual history which goes silently forward side by side with the noisy outward history of the world. When Stoicism, in this development, had been deepened by the introduction of neo-Platonic ideas, it was on its way to become the Gospel.

But Seneca, despite feeling disconnected from the world, stayed actively engaged with it. He wanted to create a kingdom of virtue on earth. At the courts of Claudius and Nero, he used political maneuvering to achieve his goals and even silently supported acts of violence that he believed would help his cause. Ultimately, he sought the highest power and paid the ultimate price. Stoicism attempted to change the world but failed. The great thinkers began to lose hope in their ability to influence history, the Senate had no power, and all public institutions lost their rights. Then a sense of resignation spread across the world. The feeling of alienation that had only been partially serious in Seneca became fully earnest. The time of Nero and Domitian marked a significant period in that hidden spiritual history that unfolds quietly alongside the loud external history of the world. Once Stoicism evolved with neo-Platonic ideas, it was on its way to becoming the Gospel.

But by itself it would not have given birth to that new thing. It attached itself as a formative principle to Judaism, which was then just breaking loose from the limitations of nationality. Bauer points to Josephus as a type of this new Roman Judaism. This “neo-Roman” lived in the conviction that his God, who had withdrawn from His Temple, would take possession of the world, and make the Roman Empire submit to His law. Josephus realised in his life that for which the way had been spiritually prepared by Philo. The latter did not merely effect a fusion of Jewish ideas with Greek speculations; he took advantage of the universal dominion established by the Romans to found upon it his spiritual world. Bauer had already pictured him in this rôle in his work “Philo, Strauss, and Renan, and Primitive Christianity.”

But on its own, it wouldn’t have led to that new thing. It became a shaping force within Judaism, which was then just beginning to break away from the constraints of nationality. Bauer points to Josephus as an example of this new Roman Judaism. This “neo-Roman” believed that his God, who had withdrawn from His Temple, would take over the world and make the Roman Empire adhere to His law. Josephus understood in his life what had been spiritually prepared by Philo. The latter didn't just blend Jewish ideas with Greek thoughts; he took advantage of the vast control established by the Romans to build his spiritual world upon it. Bauer had already portrayed him in this role in his work “Philo, Strauss, Renan, and Early Christianity.”

Thus was the new religion formed. The spirit of it came from the west, the outward frame was furnished by Judaism. The new movement had two foci, Rome and Alexandria. Philo's “Therapeutae” were real people; they were the forerunners of Christianity. Under Trajan the new religion began to be known. [pg 159] Pliny's letter asking for instructions as to how to deal with the new movement is its certificate of birth—the original form of the letter, it must be understood, not the present form, which has undergone editing at the hands of Christians.

Thus was the new religion formed. Its essence came from the west, while its structure was shaped by Judaism. The new movement had two main centers, Rome and Alexandria. Philo's “Therapists” were real individuals; they were the pioneers of Christianity. Under Trajan, the new religion started to gain recognition. [pg 159] Pliny's letter asking for guidance on how to handle this new movement serves as its birth certificate—the original version of the letter, it should be noted, not the current version, which has been edited by Christians.

The literary process by which the origin of the movement was thrown back to an earlier date in history lasted about fifty years.

The literary process that traced the origin of the movement back to an earlier date in history lasted about fifty years.

When this latest work of Bauer's appeared he had long been regarded by theologians as an extinct force; nay, more, had been forgotten. And he had not even kept his promise. He had not succeeded in showing what that higher form of victory over the world was, which he declared superior to Christianity; and in place of the personality of Jesus he had finally set up a hybrid thing, laboriously compounded out of two personalities of so little substance as those of Seneca and Josephus. That was the end of his great undertaking.

When Bauer's latest work came out, theologians had long considered him irrelevant and had even forgotten about him. He hadn't kept his promise either. He failed to demonstrate what that superior form of victory over the world was that he claimed was better than Christianity. Instead of presenting the personality of Jesus, he ended up creating a mix made from the weak personalities of Seneca and Josephus. That was the conclusion of his significant effort.

But it was a mistake to bury, along with the Bauer of the second period, also the Bauer of the first period, the critic—for the latter was not dead. It was, indeed, nothing less than a misfortune that Strauss and Bauer appeared within so short a time of one another. Bauer passed practically unnoticed, because every one was preoccupied with Strauss. Another unfortunate thing was that Bauer overthrew with his powerful criticism the hypothesis which attributed real historical value to Mark, so that it lay for a long time disregarded, and there ensued a barren period of twenty years in the critical study of the Life of Jesus.

But it was a mistake to dismiss, along with the Bauer of the second period, the Bauer of the first period, the critic—because the latter was not gone. It was truly unfortunate that Strauss and Bauer appeared so closely together. Bauer went largely unnoticed because everyone was focused on Strauss. Another unfortunate aspect was that Bauer's strong criticism refuted the idea that Mark had real historical significance, causing it to be ignored for a long time, leading to a dry spell of twenty years in the critical study of the Life of Jesus.

The only critic with whom Bauer can be compared is Reimarus. Each exercised a terrifying and disabling influence upon his time. No one else had been so keenly conscious as they of the extreme complexity of the problem offered by the life of Jesus. In view of this complexity they found themselves compelled to seek a solution outside the confines of verifiable history. Reimarus, by finding the basis of the story of Jesus in a deliberate imposture on the part of the disciples; Bauer, by postulating an original Evangelist who invented the history. On this ground it was just that they should lose their case. But in dismissing the solutions which they offered, their contemporaries also dismissed the problems which had necessitated such solutions; they dismissed them because they were as little able to grasp as to remove these difficulties.

The only critic that Bauer can be compared to is Reimarus. Both had a significant and disabling impact on their time. No one else was as acutely aware of the extreme complexity surrounding the life of Jesus. Given this complexity, they felt the need to look for answers outside the limits of verifiable history. Reimarus found the basis of Jesus' story in a deliberate deception by the disciples, while Bauer suggested that an original Evangelist fabricated the narrative. For this reason, it was reasonable for them to lose their case. However, by rejecting the solutions they proposed, their contemporaries also ignored the problems that made those solutions necessary; they dismissed them because they were equally unable to understand or resolve these difficulties.

But the time is past for pronouncing judgment upon Lives of Christ on the ground of the solutions which they offer. For us the great men are not those who solved the problems, but those who discovered them. Bauer's “Criticism of the Gospel History” is worth a good dozen Lives of Jesus, because his work, as we are only now coming to recognise, after half a century, is the ablest and most complete collection of the difficulties of the Life of Jesus which is anywhere to be found.

But the time has passed for judging the Lives of Christ based on the solutions they provide. For us, the important figures are not those who solved the problems, but those who identified them. Bauer's “Critique of the Gospel History” is worth a good twelve Lives of Jesus because his work, as we are just now beginning to realize after fifty years, is the most skilled and comprehensive collection of the challenges in the Life of Jesus that exists anywhere.

[pg 160]

Unfortunately, by the independent, the too loftily independent way in which he developed his ideas, he destroyed the possibility of their influencing contemporary theology. The shaft which he had driven into the mountain broke down behind him, so that it needed the work of a whole generation to lay bare once more the veins of ore which he had struck. His contemporaries could not suspect that the abnormality of his solutions was due to the intensity with which he grasped the problems as problems, and that he had become blind to history by examining it too microscopically. Thus for his contemporaries he was a mere eccentric.

Unfortunately, because of the overly independent and high-minded way he developed his ideas, he lost the chance for them to impact contemporary theology. The path he had carved into the mountain collapsed behind him, requiring a whole generation’s effort to reveal the veins of ore he had discovered. His peers couldn’t realize that the strangeness of his solutions stemmed from how passionately he engaged with the problems and that he became so focused on the details that he lost sight of the bigger historical picture. So, to his contemporaries, he was just considered an eccentric.

But his eccentricity concealed a penetrating insight. No one else had as yet grasped with the same completeness the idea that primitive Christianity and early Christianity were not merely the direct outcome of the preaching of Jesus, not merely a teaching put into practice, but more, much more, since to the experience of which Jesus was the subject there allied itself the experience of the world-soul at a time when its body—humanity under the Roman Empire—lay in the throes of death. Since Paul, no one had apprehended so powerfully the mystic idea of the super-sensible σῶμα Χριστοῦ. Bauer transferred it to the historical plane and found the “body of Christ” in the Roman Empire.

But his eccentricity hid a deep understanding. No one else had yet fully realized that primitive Christianity and early Christianity weren’t just the direct results of Jesus' teachings, nor were they simply a practice of those teachings, but much more than that. Their significance was tied to the experience that Jesus represented, which connected with the world-soul at a time when its physical embodiment—humankind under the Roman Empire—was on the verge of collapse. Since Paul, no one had captured the mystic idea of the super-sensible σῶμα Χριστοῦ as powerfully. Bauer moved this concept to a historical context and identified the “Christ's body” within the Roman Empire.

[pg 161]

XII. Additional Creative Interpretations of Jesus

Charles Christian Hennell. Untersuchungen über den Ursprung des Christentums. (An Inquiry concerning the Origin of Christianity.) 1840. With a preface by David Friedrich Strauss. English edition, 1838.

Charles Christian Hennell. Studies on the Origins of Christianity. (An Inquiry into the Origin of Christianity.) 1840. With a preface by David Friedrich Strauss. English edition, 1838.

Wichtige Enthüllungen über die wirkliche Todesart Jesu. Nach einem alten zu Alexandria gefundenen Manuskripte von einem Zeitgenossen Jesu aus dem heiligen Orden der Essäer. (Important Disclosures concerning the Manner of Jesus' Death. From an ancient MS. found at Alexandria, written by a contemporary of Jesus belonging to the sacred Order of the Essenes.) 1849. 5th ed., Leipzig. (Anonymous.)

Important revelations about the true way Jesus died. This is based on an ancient manuscript discovered in Alexandria, written by someone who lived at the same time as Jesus and was a member of the sacred Order of the Essenes. 1849. 5th ed., Leipzig. (Anonymous.)

Historische Enthüllungen über die wirklichen Ereignisse der Geburt und Jugend Jesu. Als Fortsetzung der zu Alexandria aufgefundenen alten Urkunden aus dem Essäerorden. (Historical Disclosures concerning the real circumstances of the Birth and Youth of Jesus. A Continuation of the ancient Essene MS. discovered at Alexandria.) 1849. 2nd ed., Leipzig.

Historical insights into the actual events surrounding the birth and early life of Jesus. A continuation of the ancient Essene manuscript discovered in Alexandria. 1849. 2nd ed., Leipzig.

August Friedrich Gfrörer. Kritische Geschichte des Urchristentums. (Critical History of Primitive Christianity.)

August Friedrich Gfrörer. Critical History of Early Christianity.

Vol. i. 1st ed., 1831; 2nd, 1835. Part i. 543 pp.; Part ii. 406 pp. Vol. ii. 1838. Part i. 452 pp.; Part ii. 417 pp.

Vol. I, 1st edition, 1831; 2nd edition, 1835. Part I: 543 pages; Part II: 406 pages. Vol. II, 1838. Part I: 452 pages; Part II: 417 pages.

Richard von der Alm. (Pseudonym of Friedrich Wilhelm Ghillany.) Theologische Briefe an die Gebildeten der deutschen Nation, 1863. (Theological Letters to the Cultured Classes of the German People, 1863.) Vol. i. 929 pp.; Vol. ii. 656 pp.; Vol. iii. 802 pp.

Richard von der Alm. (Pseudonym of Friedrich Wilhelm Ghillany.) Theological Letters to the Educated of the German Nation, 1863. (Theological Letters to the Cultured Classes of the German People, 1863.) Vol. i. 929 pages; Vol. ii. 656 pages; Vol. iii. 802 pages.

Ludwig Noack. Die Geschichte Jesu auf Grund freier geschichtlicher Untersuchungen über das Evangelium und die Evangelien. (The History of Jesus on the Basis of a free Historical Inquiry regarding the Gospel and the Gospels.) 2nd ed., 1876, Mannheim. Book i. 251 pp.; Book ii. 187 pp.; Book iii. 386 pp.; Book iv. 285 pp.

Ludwig Noack. The History of Jesus Based on Independent Historical Research on the Gospel and the Gospels. 2nd edition, 1876, Mannheim. Book I: 251 pages; Book II: 187 pages; Book III: 386 pages; Book IV: 285 pages.

Strauss can hardly be said to have done himself honour by contributing a preface to the translation of Hennell's work, which is nothing more than Venturini's “Non-miraculous History of the Great Prophet of Nazareth” tricked out with a fantastic paraphernalia of learning.97

Strauss can hardly be said to have honored himself by writing a preface for the translation of Hennell's work, which is essentially just Venturini's "Non-miraculous History of the Great Prophet from Nazareth" dressed up with an elaborate show of academic jargon.97

The two series of “Important Disclosures” also are really “conveyed” with no particular ability from that classic romance of [pg 162] the Life of Jesus, but that did not prevent their making something of a sensation at the time when they appeared.98 Jesus, according to his narrative, was the son of a member of the Essene Order. The child was watched over by the Order and prepared for His future mission. He entered on His public ministry as a tool of the Essenes, who after the crucifixion took Him down from the cross and resuscitated Him.

The two series of "Key Disclosures" also are really "shared" without any particular skill from that classic romance of [pg 162] the Life of Jesus, but that didn't stop them from causing quite a stir when they were released.98 Jesus, according to his story, was the son of a member of the Essene Order. The Order looked after the child and prepared Him for His future mission. He began His public ministry as an agent of the Essenes, who, after the crucifixion, took Him down from the cross and brought Him back to life.

These “Disclosures” only preserve the more external features of Venturini's representation. His Life of Jesus had been more than a mere romance, it had been an imaginative solution of problems which he had intuitively perceived. It may be regarded as the Forerunner of rationalistic criticism. The problems which Venturini had intuitively perceived were not solved either by the rationalists, or by Strauss, or by Weisse. These writers had not succeeded in providing that of which Venturini had dreamed—a living purposeful connexion between the events of the life of Jesus—or in explaining His Person and Work as having a relation, either positive or negative, to the circumstances of Late Judaism. Venturini's plan, however fantastic, connects the life of Jesus with Jewish history and contemporary thought much more closely than any other Life of Jesus, for that connexion is of course vital to the plot of the romance. In Weisse's “Gospel History” criticism had deliberately renounced the attempt to explain Jesus directly from Judaism, finding itself unable to establish any connexion between His teachings and contemporary Jewish ideas. The way was therefore once more open to the imagination. Accordingly several imaginative Lives preluded a new era in the study of the subject, in so far as they endeavoured to understand Jesus on the basis of purely Jewish ideas, in some cases as affirming these, in others as opposing them in favour of a more spiritual conception. In Gfrörer, Richard von der Alm, and Noack, begins the skirmishing preparatory to the future battle over eschatology.99

These “Releases” only capture the more superficial aspects of Venturini's representation. His Life of Jesus was more than just a story; it was an imaginative approach to solving issues he intuitively understood. It can be seen as the precursor to rationalistic criticism. The problems that Venturini recognized were not addressed by the rationalists, Strauss, or Weisse. These authors failed to provide what Venturini envisioned—a vibrant, meaningful connection between the events of Jesus' life—and did not explain His Person and Work in relation to the circumstances of Late Judaism, whether positively or negatively. Although Venturini's concept may seem far-fetched, it links Jesus' life with Jewish history and contemporary thought more closely than any other Life of Jesus, as that connection is essential to the storyline. In Weisse's "History of the Gospel", criticism had intentionally given up trying to explain Jesus directly from Judaism, as it found itself incapable of establishing any connection between His teachings and contemporary Jewish ideas. Thus, the path was once again open to the imagination. As a result, several imaginative Lives ushered in a new era in the study of the subject, striving to understand Jesus based solely on Jewish ideas—some affirming them, others opposing them in favor of a more spiritual view. In Gfrörer, Richard von der Alm, and Noack, the skirmishing began in preparation for the future conflict over eschatology.99

[pg 163]

August Friedrich Gfrörer, born in 1803 at Calw, was “Repetent” at the Tübingen theological seminary at the time when Strauss was studying there. After being curate at the principal church in Stuttgart for a year he gave up, in 1830, the clerical profession in order to devote himself wholly to his clerical studies.

August Friedrich Gfrörer, born in 1803 in Calw, was a "Repetent" at the Tübingen theological seminary when Strauss was studying there. After serving as a curate at the main church in Stuttgart for a year, he left the clerical profession in 1830 to focus entirely on his theological studies.

By that time he had abandoned Christianity. In the preface to the first edition of the first volume of his work, he describes Christianity as a system which now only maintains itself by the force of custom, after having commended itself to antiquity “by the hope of the mystic Kingdom of the future world and having ruled the middle ages by the fear of the same future.” By enunciating this view he has made an end, he thinks, of all high-flying Hegelian ideas, and being thus freed from all speculative prejudices he feels himself in a position to approach his task from a purely historical standpoint, with a view to showing how much of Christianity is the creation of one exceptional Personality, and how much belongs to the time in which it arose. In the first volume he describes how the transformation of Jewish theology in Alexandria reacted upon Palestinian theology, and how it came to its climax in Philo. The great Alexandrian anticipated, according to Gfrörer, the ideas of Paul. His “Therapeutae” are identical with the Essenes. At the same period Judaea was kept in a ferment by a series of risings, to all of which the incentive was found in Messianic expectations. Then Jesus appeared. The three points to be investigated in His history are: what end He had in view; why He died; and what modifications His work underwent at the hands of the Apostles.

By that time, he had given up Christianity. In the preface to the first edition of the first volume of his work, he describes Christianity as a system that now only survives because of tradition, after having proven itself to ancient times “by the hope of the mystic Kingdom of the future world and having ruled the middle ages by the fear of the same future.” By stating this view, he believes he has put to rest all lofty Hegelian ideas, and now freed from all speculative biases, he feels ready to approach his task from a purely historical perspective. He aims to show how much of Christianity is shaped by one exceptional person and how much is a product of the time in which it emerged. In the first volume, he describes how the transformation of Jewish theology in Alexandria influenced Palestinian theology, culminating in Philo. The great Alexandrian, according to Gfrörer, anticipated Paul’s ideas. His “Therapeutae” are the same as the Essenes. At the same time, Judaea was stirred up by a series of uprisings, all motivated by Messianic expectations. Then Jesus appeared. The three points to investigate in His history are: what goal He had in mind; why He died; and how His work was modified by the Apostles.

The second volume, entitled “The Sacred Legend,” does not, however, carry out this plan. The works of Strauss and Weisse necessitated a new method of treatment. The fame of Strauss's achievement stirred Gfrörer to emulation, and Weisse, with his priority of Mark and rejection of John, must be refuted. The work is therefore almost a polemic against Weisse for his “want of historic sense,” and ends in setting up views which had not entered into Gfrörer's mind at the time when he wrote his first volume.

The second volume, titled “The Holy Legend,” does not fulfill this plan. The works of Strauss and Weisse required a new approach. Strauss's success inspired Gfrörer to rise to the challenge, and Weisse’s focus on Mark and dismissal of John needed to be countered. This work is therefore largely a critique of Weisse for his “lack of historical understanding,” and concludes by presenting ideas that hadn’t occurred to Gfrörer when he wrote his first volume.

The statements of Papias regarding the Synoptists, which Weisse followed, are not deserving of credence. For a whole generation and more the tradition about Jesus had passed from mouth to mouth, and it had absorbed much that was legendary. Luke was the first—as his preface shows—who checked that process, and undertook to separate what was genuine from what was not. He is the most trustworthy of the Evangelists, for he keeps closely to his sources and adds nothing of his own, in contrast with Matthew who, writing at a later date, used sources of less value and invented matter of his own, which Gfrörer finds especially in the story of the passion in this Gospel. The lateness of Matthew is also evident [pg 164] from his tendency to carry over the Old Testament into the New. In Luke, on the other hand, the sources are so conscientiously treated that Gfrörer finds no difficulty in analysing the narrative into its component parts, especially as he always has a purely instinctive feeling “whenever a different wind begins to blow.”

The statements of Papias about the Synoptists, which Weisse followed, shouldn't be taken seriously. For over a generation, the story of Jesus was passed down verbally, accumulating a lot of legendary content. Luke was the first—as his introduction indicates—to check this process and try to distinguish what was real from what wasn't. He is the most reliable of the Evangelists because he closely follows his sources and doesn't add anything of his own, unlike Matthew, who wrote later, used less reliable sources, and included his own invented material, particularly in the passion narrative of this Gospel, as noted by Gfrörer. The delay in Matthew's writing is also evident from his tendency to carry over Old Testament references into the New. In contrast, Luke treats his sources so carefully that Gfrörer easily analyzes the narrative into its parts, especially since he always has an instinctive sense “whenever a different wind begins to blow.”

Both Gospels, however, were written long after the destruction of the holy city, since they do not draw their material from the Jerusalem tradition, but “from the Christian legends which had grown up in the neighbourhood of the Sea of Tiberias,” and in consequence “mistakenly transferred the scene of Jesus' ministry to Galilee.” For this reason it is not surprising “that even down into the second century many Christians had doubts about the truth of the Synoptics and ventured to express their doubts.” Such doubts only ceased when the Church became firmly established and began to use its authority to suppress the objections of individuals. Mark is the earliest witness to doubts within the primitive Christian community regarding the credibility of his predecessors. Luke and Matthew are for him not yet sacred books; he desires to reconcile their inconsistencies, and at the same time to produce “a Gospel composed of materials of which the authenticity could be maintained even against the doubters.” For this reason he omits most of the discourses, ignores the birth-story, and of the miracles retains only those which were most deeply embedded in the tradition. His Gospel was probably produced between 110 and 120. The “non-genuine” conclusion was a later addition, but by the Evangelist himself. Thus Mark proves that the Synoptists contain legendary matter even though they are separated from the events which they relate only by a generation and a half, or at most two generations. To show that there is nothing strange in this, Gfrörer gives a long catalogue of miracles found in historians who were contemporaries of the events which they describe, and in some cases were concerned in them—in this connexion Cortez affords him a rich storehouse of material. On the other hand, all objections against the genuineness of the Fourth Gospel collapse miserably. It is true that, like the others, it offers no historically accurate report of the discourses of Jesus. It pictures Him as the Logos-Christ and makes Him speak in this character; which Jesus certainly did not do. Inadvertently the author makes John the Baptist speak in the same way. That does not matter, however, for the historical conditions are rightly represented; rightly, because Jerusalem was the scene of the greater part of the ministry, and the five Johannine miracles are to be retained. The healing of the nobleman's son, that of the lame man at the pool of Bethesda, and that of the man blind from birth happened just as they are told. The story of the miracle at Cana rests on a misunderstanding, for the wine which Jesus provided was really the wedding-gift which He had brought [pg 165] with Him. In the raising of Lazarus a real case of apparent death is combined with a polemical exaggeration of it, the restoration to life becoming, in the course of controversy with the Jews, an actual resurrection. Having thus won free, dragging John along with him, from the toils of the Hegelian denial of miracle—only, it is true, by the aid of Venturini—and being prepared to explain the feeding of the multitude on the most commonplace rationalistic lines, he may well boast that he has “driven the doubt concerning the Fourth Gospel into a very small corner.”

Both Gospels, however, were written long after the destruction of the holy city, as they don't rely on the Jerusalem tradition, but "about the Christian legends that emerged around the Sea of Tiberias," and as a result "wrongly shifted the setting of Jesus' ministry to Galilee." For this reason, it’s not surprising "Even in the second century, many Christians doubted the truth of the Synoptics and were bold enough to express their concerns." Such doubts only disappeared when the Church became firmly established and began to use its authority to silence individual objections. Mark is the earliest source of doubt within the early Christian community regarding the reliability of his predecessors. Luke and Matthew aren’t yet sacred texts for him; he wants to resolve their inconsistencies while also creating "a Gospel composed of materials whose authenticity can hold up against criticism." For this reason, he leaves out most of the teachings, skips the birth story, and keeps only the miracles that were most deeply entrenched in the tradition. His Gospel was likely written between 110 and 120. The "fake" conclusion was added later, but by the Evangelist himself. Thus, Mark shows that the Synoptists contain legendary content even though they are separated from the events they describe by only one and a half generations, or at most two generations. To demonstrate that this isn't unusual, Gfrörer provides a long list of miracles recorded by historians who were contemporaries of the events they recount, and in some cases were involved in them—Cortez provides him with a wealth of material. On the other hand, all arguments against the authenticity of the Fourth Gospel fall apart. It is true that, like the others, it doesn't provide a historically accurate account of Jesus' teachings. It presents Him as the Logos-Christ and makes Him speak in that role; which Jesus certainly did not do. Accidentally, the author has John the Baptist speaking in the same way. However, that's not important, because the historical context is correctly represented; correctly, because Jerusalem was the location for most of the ministry, and the five Johannine miracles should be retained. The healing of the nobleman's son, the lame man at the pool of Bethesda, and the man born blind occurred just as they are described. The account of the miracle at Cana stems from a misunderstanding, as the wine Jesus provided was actually the wedding gift He had brought [pg 165] with Him. The raising of Lazarus combines a real case of apparent death with a polemical exaggeration of it, where the restoration to life becomes, during the controversy with the Jews, an actual resurrection. Having managed to escape, pulling John along with him, from the constraints of the Hegelian denial of miracles—only, admittedly, with Venturini's help—and being prepared to explain the feeding of the multitude in very ordinary rational terms, he can rightfully claim that he has "pushed the doubt about the Fourth Gospel into a tiny corner."

“The miserable era of negation,” cries Gfrörer, “is now at an end; affirmation begins. We are ascending the eastern mountains from which the pure airs of heaven breathe upon the spirit. Our guide shall be historical mathematics, a science which is as yet known to few, and has not been applied by any one to the New Testament.” This “mathematic” of Gfrörer's consists in developing his whole argument out of a single postulate. Let it be granted to him that all other claimants of the Messiahship—Gfrörer, in defiance of the evidence of Josephus, makes all the leaders of revolt in Palestine claimants of the Messiahship—were put to death by the Romans, whereas Jesus was crucified by His own people: it follows that the Messiahship of Jesus was not political, but spiritual. He had declared Himself to be in a certain sense the longed-for Messiah, but in another sense He was not so. His preaching moved in the sphere of Philonian ideas; although He did not as yet explicitly apply the Logos doctrine, it was implicit in His thought, so that the discourses of the Fourth Gospel have an essential truth. All Messianic conceptions, the Kingdom of God, the judgment, the future world, are sublimated into the spiritual region. The resurrection of the dead becomes a present eternal life. The saying in John v. 24, “He that heareth my word, and believeth on Him that sent me, hath eternal life and cometh not into judgment; but is passed from death into life,” is the only authentic part of that discourse. The reference which follows to the coming judgment and the resurrection of the dead is a Jewish interpolation. Jesus did not believe that He Himself was to rise from the dead. Nevertheless, the “resurrection” is historic; Joseph of Arimathea, a member of the Essene Order, whose tool Jesus unconsciously was, had bribed the Romans to make the crucifixion of Jesus only a pretence, and to crucify two others with Him in order to distract attention from Him. After He was taken down from the cross, Joseph removed Him to a tomb of his own which had been hewn out for the purpose in the neighbourhood of the cross, and succeeded in resuscitating Him. The Christian Church grew out of the Essene Order by giving a further development to its ideas, and it is impossible to explain the organisation of the Church without taking account of the regulations of the Order. [pg 166] The work closes with a rhapsody on the Church and its development into the Papal system.

"The awful time of denial," exclaims Gfrörer, “is now over; it's time for affirmation. We are ascending the eastern mountains where the fresh air of heaven refreshes the spirit. Our guide will be historical mathematics, a field that is still familiar to only a few and has yet to be applied to the New Testament by anyone.” Gfrörer’s "math" involves constructing his entire argument from a single premise. Let’s accept that all other claimants to the Messiahship—Gfrörer claims, despite Josephus’ evidence, that all leaders of revolt in Palestine were contenders for the Messiahship—were executed by the Romans, while Jesus was crucified by His own people. This implies that Jesus’ Messiahship was not political, but spiritual. He declared Himself, in a certain sense, to be the anticipated Messiah, but in another sense, He was not. His preaching operated within the framework of Philonian ideas; although He didn't explicitly use the Logos doctrine, it was inherently present in His thinking, lending essential truth to the discourses in the Fourth Gospel. All Messianic concepts, including the Kingdom of God, judgment, and the afterlife, are elevated into the spiritual realm. The resurrection of the dead transforms into present eternal life. The statement in John v. 24, "Anyone who hears my message and believes in the one who sent me has eternal life and will not face judgment; they have moved from death to life." represents the only authentic aspect of that discourse. The subsequent reference to the coming judgment and the resurrection of the dead is a Jewish addition. Jesus did not believe He would rise from the dead. Nevertheless, the “revival” is historical; Joseph of Arimathea, a member of the Essene Order, whom Jesus unwittingly relied upon, bribed the Romans to stage Jesus' crucifixion and executed two others alongside Him to divert attention. After Jesus was taken down from the cross, Joseph placed Him in a tomb he had prepared nearby and managed to bring Him back to life. The Christian Church emerged from the Essene Order by further developing its ideas, and it's impossible to explain the Church's organization without considering the Order's regulations. [pg 166] The work concludes with a rhapsody on the Church and its evolution into the Papal system.

Gfrörer thus works into Venturini's plan a quantity of material drawn from Philo. His first volume would have led one to expect a more original and scientific result. But the author is one of those “epileptics of criticism” for whom criticism is not a natural and healthy means of arriving at a result, but who, in consequence of the fits of criticism to which they are subject, and which they even endeavour to intensify, fall into a condition of exhaustion, in which the need for some fixed point becomes so imperative that they create it for themselves by self-suggestion—as they previously did their criticism—and then flatter themselves that they have really found it.

Gfrörer incorporates a lot of material from Philo into Venturini's plan. His first volume gave the impression that a more original and scientific outcome was expected. However, the author is one of those “critics with epilepsy” who don’t see criticism as a natural and healthy way to reach conclusions. Instead, due to the episodes of criticism they experience, which they even try to amplify, they end up in a state of exhaustion where the need for a solid foundation becomes so urgent that they create one through self-suggestion—just like they previously did with their criticism—and then convince themselves that they've genuinely found it.

This need for a fixed point carried the former rival of Strauss into Catholicism, for which his “General History of the Church” (1841-1846) already shows a strong admiration. After the appearance of this work Gfrörer became Professor of History in the University of Freiburg. In 1848 he was active in the German Parliament in endeavouring to promote a reunion of the Protestants with the Catholics. In 1853 he went over to the Roman Church. His family had already gone over, at Strassburg, during the revolutionary period. In the conflict of the church with the Baden Government he vehemently supported the claims of the Pope. He died in 1861.

This need for a fixed point led the former rival of Strauss to convert to Catholicism, for which his "General History of the Church" (1841-1846) already reflects a strong admiration. After this work was published, Gfrörer became a Professor of History at the University of Freiburg. In 1848, he participated in the German Parliament, working to promote a reunion of Protestants with Catholics. In 1853, he converted to the Roman Church. His family had already converted in Strassburg during the revolutionary period. In the conflict between the church and the Baden Government, he strongly supported the Pope's claims. He died in 1861.


Incomparably better and more thorough is the attempt to write a Life of Jesus embodied in the “Theological Letters to the Cultured Classes of the German Nation.” Their writer takes Gfrörer's studies as his starting-point, but instead of spiritualising unjustifiably he ventures to conceive the Jewish world of thought in which Jesus lived in its simple realism. He was the first to place the eschatology recognised by Strauss and Reimarus in an historical setting—that of Venturini's plan—and to write a Life of Jesus entirely governed by the idea of eschatology.

Incomparable better and more comprehensive is the effort to write a Life of Jesus found in the "Theological Letters to the Educated People of the German Nation." The author uses Gfrörer's studies as a starting point, but instead of unjustifiably spiritualizing, he dares to understand the Jewish world of thought in which Jesus lived in its straightforward realism. He was the first to place the eschatology recognized by Strauss and Reimarus in a historical context—that of Venturini's plan—and to write a Life of Jesus wholly focused on the concept of eschatology.

The author, Friedrich Wilhelm Ghillany, was born in 1807 at Erlangen. His first studies were in theology. His rationalistic views, however, compelled him to abandon the clerical profession. He became librarian at Nuremberg in 1841 and engaged in controversial writing of an anti-orthodox character, but distinguished himself also by historical work of outstanding merit. A year after the publication of the “Theological Letters,” which he issued under the pseudonym of Richard von der Alm, he published a collection of “The Opinions of Heathen and Christian Writers of the first Christian Centuries about Jesus Christ” (1864), a work which gives evidence of a remarkable range of reading. In 1855 he removed to Munich in the hope of obtaining a post in the diplomatic [pg 167] service, but in spite of his solid acquirements he did not succeed. No one would venture to appoint a man of such outspoken anti-ecclesiastical views. He died in 1876.

The author, Friedrich Wilhelm Ghillany, was born in 1807 in Erlangen. He initially studied theology, but his rationalistic views led him to leave the clerical profession. He became a librarian in Nuremberg in 1841 and wrote controversial pieces against orthodox beliefs while also producing notable historical work. A year after he published the “Theology Letters,” which he released under the pseudonym Richard von der Alm, he put out a collection titled “The Views of Pagan and Christian Writers from the Early Christian Centuries on Jesus Christ” (1864), showcasing a remarkable breadth of reading. In 1855, he moved to Munich, hoping to secure a position in the diplomatic [pg 167] service, but despite his strong qualifications, he was unsuccessful. No one was willing to appoint someone with such vocal anti-ecclesiastical views. He died in 1876.

As regards the question of the sources, Ghillany occupies very nearly the Tübingen standpoint, except that he holds Matthew to be later than Luke, and Mark to be extracted, not from these Gospels in their present form, but from their sources. John is not authentic.

As for the question of the sources, Ghillany is almost in line with the Tübingen perspective, except that he believes Matthew is later than Luke and that Mark is derived not from these Gospels in their current form, but from their original sources. John is not considered authentic.

The worship offered to Jesus after His death by the Christian community is, according to Ghillany, not derived from pure Judaism, but from a Judaism influenced by oriental religions. The influence of the cult of Mithra, for example, is unmistakable. In it, as in Christianity, we find the virgin-birth, the star, the wise men, the cross, and the resurrection. Were it not for the human sacrifice of the Mithra cult, the idea which is operative in the Supper, of eating and drinking the flesh and blood of the Son of Man, would be inexplicable.

The worship offered to Jesus after His death by the Christian community is, according to Ghillany, not exclusively based on pure Judaism, but rather on a form of Judaism that has been influenced by Eastern religions. The impact of the cult of Mithra, for example, is clear. In Mithraism, as in Christianity, we see themes like the virgin birth, the star, the wise men, the cross, and the resurrection. If it weren't for the human sacrifice in the Mithra cult, the concept behind the Supper, which involves consuming the flesh and blood of the Son of Man, would be hard to understand.

The whole Eastern world was at that time impregnated with Gnostic ideas, which centred in the revelation of the Divine in the human. In this way there arose, for example, a Samaritan Gnosis, independent of the Christian. Christianity itself is a species of Gnosis. In any case the metaphysical conception of the Divine Sonship of Jesus is of secondary origin. If He was in any sense the Son of God for the disciples, they can only have thought of this sonship in a Gnostic fashion, and supposed that the “highest angel,” the Son of God, had taken up His abode in Him.

The entire Eastern world was at that time filled with Gnostic ideas, which focused on the revelation of the Divine within the human. This led to the emergence of a Samaritan Gnosis, separate from Christianity. Christianity itself is a form of Gnosis. In any case, the metaphysical idea of Jesus's Divine Sonship comes from a secondary source. If the disciples considered Him the Son of God in any way, they must have viewed this sonship in a Gnostic sense, believing that the “top angel,” the Son of God, had lived within Him.

John the Baptist had probably come forth from among the Essenes, and he preached a spiritualised Kingdom of Heaven. He held himself to be Elias. Jesus' aims were originally similar; He came forward “in the cause of sound religious teaching for the people.” He made no claim to Davidic descent; that is to be credited to dogmatic theology. Similarly Papias is wrong in ascribing to Jesus the crude eschatological expectations implied in the saying about the miraculous vine in the Messianic Kingdom.

John the Baptist probably came from the Essenes, and he preached a more spiritual version of the Kingdom of Heaven. He believed he was Elias. Jesus initially had similar goals; he stepped forward "to encourage solid religious education for the community." He never claimed to be a descendant of David; that is a concept created by dogmatic theology. Likewise, Papias is mistaken in attributing the simplistic end-of-the-world expectations related to the saying about the miraculous vine in the Messianic Kingdom to Jesus.

It is certain, however, that Jesus held Himself to be Messiah and expected the early coming of the Kingdom. His teaching is Rabbinic; all His ideas have their source in contemporary Judaism, whose world of thought we can reconstruct from the Rabbinic writings; for even if these only became fixed at a later period, the thoughts on which they are based were already current in the time of Jesus. Another source of great importance is Justin's “Dialogue with the Jew Trypho.”

It is clear, however, that Jesus considered Himself to be the Messiah and anticipated the imminent arrival of the Kingdom. His teachings are rooted in Rabbinic tradition; all His ideas originate from contemporary Judaism, which we can understand through the Rabbinic texts. Even though these texts were finalized later, the concepts they reflect were already prevalent during Jesus' time. Another significant source is Justin's “Conversation with the Jew Trypho.”

The starting-point in interpreting the teaching of Jesus is the idea of repentance. In the tractate “Sanhedrin” we find: “The set time of the Messiah is already here; His coming depends now upon repentance and good works. Rabbi Eleazer says, ‘When the [pg 168] Jews repent they shall be redeemed.’ ” The Targum of Jonathan observes, on Zech. x. 3, 4,100 “The Messiah is already born, but remains in concealment because of the sins of the Hebrews.” We find the same thoughts put into the mouth of Trypho in Justin. In the same Targum of Jonathan, Isa. liii. is interpreted with reference to the sufferings of the Messiah. Judaism, therefore, was not unacquainted with the idea of a suffering Messiah. He was not identified, however, with the heavenly Messiah of Daniel. The Rabbis distinguished two Messiahs, one of Israel and one of Judah. First the Messiah of the Kingdom of Israel, denominated the Son of Joseph, was to come from Galilee to suffer death at the hands of the Gentiles in order to make atonement for the sins of the Hebrew nation. Only after that would the Messiah predicted by Daniel, the son of David, of the tribe of Judah, appear in glory upon the clouds of heaven. Finally, He also, after two-and-sixty weeks of years, should be taken away, since the Messianic Kingdom, even as conceived by Paul, was only a temporary supernatural condition of the world.

The starting point in understanding Jesus' teachings is the concept of repentance. In the tractate "Sanhedrin", we read: “The time for the Messiah is now; His coming relies on repentance and good actions. Rabbi Eleazer says, ‘When the [pg 168] Jews sincerely repent, they will be redeemed.’ ” The Targum of Jonathan notes on Zech. x. 3, 4, 100 "The Messiah has already been born, but stays hidden because of the sins of the Hebrews." Similar ideas are expressed by Trypho in Justin. In the same Targum of Jonathan, Isa. liii. is explained in relation to the suffering of the Messiah. Thus, Judaism was familiar with the notion of a suffering Messiah. However, He was not the same as the heavenly Messiah described in Daniel. The Rabbis recognized two Messiahs: one from Israel and one from Judah. First, the Messiah of the Kingdom of Israel, known as the Son of Joseph, was expected to come from Galilee and suffer death at the hands of the Gentiles to atone for the Hebrew nation's sins. Only after that would the Messiah predicted by Daniel, the son of David from the tribe of Judah, come in glory on the clouds of heaven. Ultimately, He too, after sixty-two weeks of years, would be taken away, as the Messianic Kingdom, even as Paul understood it, was seen as only a temporary supernatural state in the world.

The Messianic expectation, being directed to supernatural events, had no political character, and one who knew Himself to be the Messiah could never dream of using earthly means for the attainment of His ends; He would expect all things to be brought about by the Divine intervention. In this respect Ghillany grasps clearly the character of the eschatology of Jesus—more clearly than any one had ever done before.

The Messianic expectation, focused on supernatural events, had no political aspect, and someone who knew they were the Messiah would never think of using earthly methods to achieve their goals; they would expect everything to happen through Divine intervention. In this regard, Ghillany clearly understands the nature of Jesus’ eschatology—more clearly than anyone ever had before.

The rôle of the Messiah, who prior to His supernatural manifestation remains in concealment upon earth, is therefore passive. He who is conscious of a Messianic vocation does not seek to found a Kingdom among men. He waits with confidence. He issues forth from His passivity with the sole purpose of making atonement, by vicarious suffering, for the sins of the people, in order that it may be possible for God to bring about the new condition of things. If, in spite of the repentance of the people and the occurrence of the signs which pointed to its being at hand, the coming of the Kingdom should be delayed, the man who is conscious of a Messianic vocation must, by His death, compel the intervention of God. His vocation in this world is to die.

The role of the Messiah, who before His supernatural appearance stays hidden on Earth, is thus passive. The one who feels a Messianic calling doesn't try to establish a Kingdom among people. He waits with assurance. He steps out of His passivity solely to atone, through suffering for others, for the sins of the people, so that God can create a new state of affairs. If, despite the people's repentance and the signs that indicate it is coming, the arrival of the Kingdom is still postponed, the person who feels a Messianic calling must, through His death, prompt God's intervention. His purpose in this world is to die.

Brought within the lines of these reflections the Life of Jesus shapes itself as follows.

Brought within the lines of these reflections, the Life of Jesus takes shape as follows.

Jesus was the tool of a mystical sect allied to the Essenes, the head of which was doubtless that Joseph of Arimathea who makes so sudden and striking an appearance in the Gospel narrative. This party desired to bring about the coming of the Kingdom of Heaven by mystical means, whereas the mass of the people, led astray by the Pharisees, thought to force on its coming by means [pg 169] of a rising. In the preacher of a spiritual Kingdom of Heaven, who was resolved to go to death for His cause, the mystical party discovered Messiah the son of Joseph, and they recognised that His death was necessary to make possible the coming of the heavenly Messiah predicted by Daniel. That Jesus Himself was the Messiah of Daniel, that He would immediately rise again in order to ascend to His heavenly throne, and would come thence with the hosts of heaven to establish the Kingdom of Heaven, these people did not themselves believe. But they encouraged Him in this belief, thinking that He would hardly commit Himself to a sacrificial death from which there was to be no resurrection. It was left uncertain to His mind whether Jehovah would be content with the repentance of the people, in so far as it had taken place, as realising the necessary condition for the bringing in of the Kingdom of Heaven, or whether an atonement by blood, offered by the death of Messiah the son of Joseph, would be needful. It had been explained to Him that when the calculated year of grace arrived, He must go up to Jerusalem and endeavour to rouse the Jews to Messianic enthusiasm in order to compel Jehovah to come to their aid with His heavenly hosts. From the action of Jehovah it could then be discovered whether the preaching of repentance and baptism would suffice to make atonement for the people before God or not. If Jehovah did not appear, a deeper atonement must be made; Jesus must pay the penalty of death for the sins of the Jews, but on the third day would rise again from the dead and ascend to the throne of God and come again thence to found the Kingdom of Heaven. “Any one can see,” concludes Ghillany, “that our view affords a very natural explanation of the anxiety of the disciples, the suspense of Jesus Himself, and the prayer, ‘If it be possible let this cup pass from me.’ ”

Jesus was a part of a mystical group associated with the Essenes, likely led by Joseph of Arimathea, who makes a sudden and notable appearance in the Gospel stories. This group aimed to bring about the Kingdom of Heaven through mystical means, while most people, misled by the Pharisees, believed they could force its arrival through a rebellion. In the figure of the preacher promoting a spiritual Kingdom of Heaven, who was determined to die for His cause, the mystical group identified the Messiah, the son of Joseph, recognizing that His death was essential for the coming of the heavenly Messiah predicted by Daniel. They did not believe Jesus was the Messiah of Daniel, nor that He would rise again to ascend to His heavenly throne and return with the heavenly hosts to establish the Kingdom of Heaven. Yet, they encouraged Him in this belief, thinking He wouldn’t willingly face a sacrificial death without the hope of resurrection. Jesus was uncertain whether Jehovah would accept the people's repentance, as far as it had occurred, as sufficient to bring about the Kingdom of Heaven, or if a blood atonement through the death of the Messiah, the son of Joseph, would be necessary. He had been told that when the prophesied year of grace arrived, He needed to go to Jerusalem and try to inspire Messianic excitement among the Jews to compel Jehovah to come to their aid with His heavenly hosts. From Jehovah's action, it could be determined if preaching repentance and baptism would be enough to atone for the people before God. If Jehovah did not show up, a greater atonement would be needed; Jesus would have to die for the sins of the Jews, but on the third day, He would rise from the dead, ascend to God's throne, and return to establish the Kingdom of Heaven. “Anyone can tell,” concludes Ghillany, “our perspective offers a very natural explanation for the disciples' anxiety, the tension Jesus Himself experienced, and the prayer, ‘If it be possible, let this cup pass from me.’ ”

“It was apparently only towards the close of His life that Jesus revealed to the disciples the possibility that the Son of Man might have to suffer and die before He could found the Messianic Kingdom.”

"It appears that only towards the end of His life, Jesus told the disciples that the Son of Man might have to suffer and die before establishing the Messianic Kingdom."

With this possibility before Him, He came to Jerusalem and there awaited the Divine intervention. Meanwhile Joseph of Arimathea lent his aid towards securing His condemnation in the Sanhedrin. He must die on the day of the Passover; on the day of the Preparation He must be at hand and ready in Jerusalem. He held, with His disciples, a love-feast after the Essene custom, not a Paschal meal, and in doing so associated thoughts of His death with the breaking of bread and the pouring out of the wine. “He did not lay upon His disciples any injunction to continue the celebration of a feast of this kind until the time of His return, because He thought of His resurrection and His heavenly glory as about to take place after three days. But when His return was [pg 170] delayed the early Christians attached these sayings of His about the bread and wine to their Essene love-feast, and explained this common meal of the community as a commemoration of the Last Supper of Jesus and His disciples, a memorial Feast in honour of their Saviour, the celebration of which must be continued until His coming.”

With this possibility ahead of Him, He arrived in Jerusalem and waited for Divine intervention. Meanwhile, Joseph of Arimathea assisted in securing His condemnation in the Sanhedrin. He had to die on Passover; on the day of Preparation, He needed to be present and ready in Jerusalem. He held a love feast with His disciples after the Essene tradition, not a Passover meal, and in doing so, He connected thoughts of His death with the breaking of bread and the pouring of wine. "He didn't require His disciples to keep celebrating a feast like this until He returned because He knew His resurrection and heavenly glory would happen after three days. But when His return was [pg 170] delayed, the early Christians connected His words about the bread and wine to their Essene love feast, interpreting this shared meal of the community as a remembrance of the Last Supper of Jesus and His disciples, a memorial feast honoring their Savior, which should continue until His return."

When the armed band came to arrest Him, Jesus surrendered to His fate. Pilate almost set Him free, holding Him to be a mere enthusiast who placed His hopes only in the Divine intervention. Joseph of Arimathea, however, succeeded in averting this danger. “Even on the cross Jesus seems to have continued to hope for the Divine intervention, as is evidenced by the cry, ‘My God! My God! why hast thou forsaken me?’ ” Joseph of Arimathea provided for His burial.

When the armed group came to arrest Him, Jesus accepted His fate. Pilate nearly released Him, thinking He was just an enthusiast who relied solely on Divine intervention. However, Joseph of Arimathea managed to prevent this danger. “Even on the cross, Jesus still appeared to hope for Divine intervention, as demonstrated by His cry, ‘My God! My God! why have you forsaken me?’ ” Joseph of Arimathea took care of His burial.

The belief in His resurrection rests upon the visions of the disciples, which are to be explained by their intense desire for the Parousia, of which He had given them the promise. After setting their affairs in order in Galilee they returned at the Feast of Pentecost to Jerusalem, which they had left in alarm, in order there to await the Parousia in company with other Galilaean believers.

The belief in His resurrection is based on the visions of the disciples, which can be understood by their strong desire for the Second Coming, which He had promised them. After getting their affairs in order in Galilee, they returned to Jerusalem for the Feast of Pentecost, which they had left in fear, to wait for the Second Coming alongside other Galilean believers.

The confession of faith of the primitive Christian community was the simplest conceivable: Jesus the Messiah had come, not as a temporal conqueror, but as the Son of Man foretold by Daniel, and had died for the sins of the people. In other respects they were strict Jews, kept the Law, and were constantly in the Temple. Only the community of goods and the brotherhood-meal are of an Essene character.

The faith of the early Christian community was straightforward: Jesus the Messiah came, not as a worldly conqueror, but as the Son of Man mentioned by Daniel, and died for the sins of the people. In other ways, they were strict Jews, followed the Law, and regularly went to the Temple. Only the sharing of possessions and the communal meal have an Essene feel.

“The Christianity of the original community in Jerusalem was thus a mixture of Zealotism and Mysticism which did not include any wholly new element, and even in its conception of the Messiah had nothing peculiar to itself except the belief that the Son of Man predicted by Daniel had already come in the person of Jesus of Nazareth ... that He was now enthroned at the right hand of God, and would again appear as the expected Son of Man upon the clouds of heaven according to Daniel's prophecy.” Jesus, therefore, had triumphed over the mystical party who desired to make use of Him in the character of Messiah the son of Joseph—their Messiah, the heavenly Son of Man, had not come. Jesus, in virtue of what He had done, had taken His place both in heaven and in earth.

The early Christian community in Jerusalem combined Zealot and Mystical beliefs, without bringing anything entirely new to the table. Their concept of the Messiah wasn't original either, except for the notion that the Son of Man referred to by Daniel had already arrived in the form of Jesus of Nazareth... that He was now at the right hand of God and would return as the anticipated Son of Man on the clouds of heaven, just as Daniel prophesied. Therefore, Jesus had overcome the mystical group that wanted to use Him as the Messiah, the son of Joseph—their heavenly Son of Man had not arrived. Because of what Jesus accomplished, He had secured His place both in heaven and on earth.

How much of Venturini's plan is here retained? Only the “mystical part” which serves the purpose of setting the action of the drama in motion. All the rest of it, the rationalistic part, has been transmuted into an historical conception. Miracle and trickery, along with the stage-play resurrection, have been purged [pg 171] away in the fires of Strauss's criticism. There remains only a fundamental conception which has a certain greatness—a brotherhood which looks for the coming of the Kingdom of Heaven appoints one of its members to undergo as Messiah an atoning death, that the coming of the Kingdom, for which the time is at hand, may not be delayed. This brotherhood is the only fictitious element in the whole construction—much as in the primitive steam-engine the valves were still worked by hand while the rest of the machinery was actuated by its own motive-power. So in this Life of Jesus the motive-power is drawn entirely from historical sources, and the want of an automatic starting arrangement is a mere anachronism. Strike out the superfluous rôle of Joseph of Arimathea, and the distinction of the two Messiahs, which is not clear even in the Rabbis, and substitute the simple hypothesis that Jesus, in the course of His Messianic vocation, when He thinks the time for the coming of the Kingdom has arrived, goes freely to Jerusalem, and, as it were, compels the secular power to put Him to death, in order by this act of atonement to win for the world the immediate coming of the Kingdom, and for Himself the glory of the Son of Man—make these changes, and you have a life of Jesus in which the motive-power is a purely historical force. It is impossible to indicate briefly all the parts of which the seemingly complicated, but in reality impressively simple, mechanism of this Life of Jesus is composed. The conduct of Jesus, alike in its resolution and in its hesitation, becomes clear, and not less so that of the disciples. All far-fetched historical ingenuity is dispensed with. Jesus acts “because His hour is come.” This decisive placing of the Life of Jesus in the “last time” (cf. 1 Peter i. 20 φανερωθέντος δὲ ἐπ᾽ ἐσχάτων τῶν χρόνων δἰ ὑμᾶς) is an historical achievement without parallel. Not less so is the placing of the thought of the passion in its proper eschatological setting as an act of atonement. Where had the character and origin of the primitive community ever been brought into such clear connexion with the death of Jesus? Who had ever before so earnestly considered the problem why the Christian community arose in Jerusalem and not in Galilee? “But the solution is too simple, and, moreover, is not founded on a severely scientific chain of reasoning, but on historical intuition and experiment, the simple experiment of introducing the Life of Jesus into the Jewish eschatological world of thought”—so the theologians replied, or so, at least, they might have replied if they had taken this curious work seriously, if, indeed, they had read it at all. But how were they to suspect that in a book which seemed to aim at founding a new Deistic Church, and which went out with the Wolfenbüttel Fragmentist into the desert of the most barren natural religion, a valuable historical conception might be found? It is true that [pg 172] no one suspected at that time that in the forgotten work of Reimarus there lay a dangerous historical discovery, a kind of explosive material such as can only be collected by those who stand free from every responsibility towards historical Christianity, who have abandoned every prejudice, in the good sense as well as in the bad—and whose one desire in regard to the Gospel history is to be “spirits that constantly deny.”101 Such thinkers, if they have historical gifts, destroy artificial history in the cause of true history and, willing evil, do good—if it be admitted that the discovery of truth is good. If this negative work is a good thing, the author of the “Letters to the German People” performed a distinguished service, for his negation is radical. The new Church which was to be founded on this historic overcoming of historic Christianity was to combine “only what was according to reason in Judaism and Christianity.” From Judaism it was to take the belief in one sole, spiritual, perfect God; from Christianity the requirement of brotherly love to all men. On the other hand, it was to eliminate what was contrary to reason in each: from Judaism the ritual system and the sacrifices; from Christianity the deification of Jesus and the teaching of redemption through His blood. How comes so completely unhistorical a temperament to be combined with so historical an intellect? His Jesus, after all, has no individuality; He is a mere eschatological machine.

How much of Venturini's plan remains here? Only the “magical element” that gets the drama's action going. Everything else, the rational part, has been transformed into a historical concept. Miracle and deception, along with the staged resurrection, have been burned away by Strauss's criticism. What remains is a core idea that carries a certain greatness—a brotherhood that anticipates the arrival of the Kingdom of Heaven and designates one of its members to undergo atoning death as the Messiah, so the coming of the Kingdom, for which the time is ripe, is not delayed. This brotherhood is the only fictional element in the entire setup—much like how in the early steam engine, the valves were still operated by hand while the rest of the machinery was run by its own power. So, in this Life of Jesus, the driving force comes entirely from historical sources, and the lack of an automatic starting mechanism is just an anachronism. If you remove the unnecessary role of Joseph of Arimathea and the unclear distinction of the two Messiahs, which isn’t even clear among the Rabbis, and replace it with the simple concept that Jesus, during His Messianic journey, believes the moment for the Kingdom's arrival has come, goes willingly to Jerusalem, and effectively forces the secular authorities to execute Him. This act of atonement aims to achieve the imminent arrival of the Kingdom for the world, and for Himself, the glory of the Son of Man—make these adjustments, and you have a life of Jesus where the driving force is purely historical. It’s impossible to briefly outline all the elements that make up the seemingly complex, but actually impressively simple, mechanism of this Life of Jesus. Jesus's actions, both decisive and hesitant, become clear, as do the actions of the disciples. All convoluted historical ingenuity is eliminated. Jesus acts “because His time has come.” This critical placement of the Life of Jesus in the “last time” (cf. 1 Peter i. 20 φανερωθέντος δὲ ἐπ᾽ ἐσχάτων τῶν χρόνων δἰ ὑμᾶς) is an unmatched historical achievement. The contextualization of the passion within its right eschatological framework as an act of atonement is equally remarkable. Where has the character and origin of the early community been so clearly linked to the death of Jesus? Who has seriously considered why the Christian community emerged in Jerusalem and not in Galilee? "But the solution is too simple and is not based on a rigorous scientific reasoning process; rather, it's rooted in historical intuition and experimentation—the simple experiment of placing the Life of Jesus within the Jewish eschatological worldview."—thus the theologians responded, or at least they could have had they taken this intriguing work seriously, if they had indeed read it. But how could they suspect that in a book that seemed to seek to establish a new Deistic Church, venturing into the barren desert of pure natural religion, a valuable historical concept might exist? It is true that [pg 172] no one at that time realized that the forgotten work of Reimarus contained a dangerous historical discovery, a kind of explosive material that can only be gathered by those who are free from any responsibilities towards historical Christianity, who have abandoned all prejudices, in both the good and the bad sense—and whose sole desire regarding the Gospel history is to be “spirits that always deny.”101 Such thinkers, if gifted in history, dismantle artificial history in the name of true history and, whether intending harm or not, do good—if we consider that discovering truth is good. If this negative work holds value, the author of the "Messages to the German People" provided a significant service, for his negation is thorough. The new Church that was to be formed on this historic overcoming of historic Christianity was meant to unify “only what was reasonable in Judaism and Christianity.” From Judaism, it would embrace the belief in one singular, spiritual, perfect God; from Christianity, it would adopt the requirement of brotherly love for all people. Conversely, it would discard what was unreasonable in each: from Judaism, the ritual laws and sacrifices; from Christianity, the deification of Jesus and the doctrine of redemption through His blood. How does such an unhistorical mindset coexist with such a historical intellect? After all, His Jesus lacks individuality; He is merely an eschatological machine.

In accordance with the confession of faith of the new Church of which Ghillany dreamed, the calendar of the Feasts is to be transformed as follows:—

In line with the beliefs of the new Church that Ghillany envisioned, the schedule of the Feasts will be changed as follows:—

1. Feast of the Deity, the first and second of January.

1. Celebration of the Deity, January 1st and 2nd.

2. Feast of the Dignity of Man and Brotherly Love, first and second of April.

2. Celebration of the Dignity of Humanity and Brotherhood, April 1st and 2nd.

3. Feast of the Divine Blessing in Nature, first and second of July.

3. Celebration of the Divine Blessing in Nature, July 1st and 2nd.

4. Feast of Immortality, first and second of October.

4. Feast of Immortality, October 1st and 2nd.

Apart from these eight Feast days, and the Sundays, all the other days of the year are working days.

Aside from these eight Feast days and Sundays, all the other days of the year are workdays.

From the order of divine service we may note the following: “The sermon, which should begin with instruction and exhortation and close with consolation and encouragement, must not last longer than half an hour.”

From the schedule of divine service, we can observe the following: "The sermon should begin with teaching and encouragement and end with comfort and motivation, and it shouldn't be longer than thirty minutes."


The series of Lives of Jesus which combine criticism with fiction is closed by Noack's Story of Jesus. A freethinker like Ghillany, but lacking the financial independence which a kindly fate had conferred upon the latter, Noack led a life which may properly be described as a constant martyrdom, lightened only by his intense love of theological studies, which nevertheless were [pg 173] responsible for all his troubles. Born in 1819, of a clerical family in Hesse, he became in 1842 Pastor's assistant and teacher of religion at Worms in the Hessian Palatinate. The Darmstadt reactionaries drove him out of this position in 1844 without his having given any ground of offence. In 1849 he became “Repetent” in Philosophy at the University of Giessen at a salary of four hundred gulden. In 1855 he was promoted to be Professor Extraordinary without having his salary raised. In 1870, at the age of 51, he was appointed assistant at the University Library and received at the same time the title of Ordinary Professor. He died in 1885. He was an extremely prolific writer, always ingenious, and possessed of wide knowledge, but he never did anything of real permanent value either in philosophy or theology. He was not without critical acumen, but there was too much of the poet in him; a critical discovery was an incitement to an imaginative reconstruction of the history. In 1870-1871 he published, after many preliminary studies, his chief work, “From the Jordan Uplands to Golgotha; four books on the Gospel and the Gospels.”102 It passed unnoticed. Attributing its failure to the excitement aroused by the war, which ousted all other interests, he issued a revised edition in 1876 under the title “The History of Jesus, on the Basis of Free Historical Inquiry concerning the Gospel and the Gospels,”103 but with hardly greater success.

The series of Lives of Jesus, which blend criticism with fiction, is concluded by Noack's Story of Jesus. A free thinker like Ghillany, but lacking the financial independence that fortune had granted the latter, Noack had a life that can rightly be described as a constant struggle, eased only by his deep passion for theological studies, which nonetheless caused him all his troubles. Born in 1819 to a clerical family in Hesse, he became a pastor's assistant and religious teacher in 1842 at Worms in the Hessian Palatinate. The Darmstadt conservatives forced him out of this position in 1844 without any justification. In 1849, he took on the role of “Repetent” in Philosophy at the University of Giessen with a salary of four hundred gulden. In 1855, he was promoted to Extraordinary Professor without any increase in salary. In 1870, at the age of 51, he was appointed assistant at the University Library and simultaneously received the title of Ordinary Professor. He passed away in 1885. He was an incredibly prolific writer, always clever and knowledgeable, but he never produced anything of lasting value in philosophy or theology. While he had some critical insight, he was too much of a poet; a critical find inspired him to imaginatively reconstruct history. In 1870-1871, after extensive preliminary studies, he published his main work, “From the Jordan Uplands to Golgotha; four books on the Gospel and the Gospels.” It went largely unnoticed. Attributing its failure to the excitement generated by the war, which overshadowed all other interests, he released a revised edition in 1876 titled “The History of Jesus, on the Basis of Free Historical Inquiry concerning the Gospel and the Gospels,” but met with little more success.

And yet the fundamental critical ideas which can be detected beneath this narrative, in spite of its having the form of fiction, give this work a significance such as the contemporary Lives of Jesus which won the applause of theologians did not possess. It is the only Life of Jesus hitherto produced which is written consistently from the Johannine point of view from beginning to end. Strauss had not, after all, in Noack's opinion, conclusively shown the absolute incompatibility of the Synoptics with the Fourth Gospel; neither he nor any other critic had felt the full difficulty of the question why the Fourth Evangelist should be at pains to invent the numerous journeys to the Feasts, seeing that the development of the Logos Christology did not necessarily involve any alteration of the scene of the ministry; on the contrary, it would, one might think, have been the first care of the Evangelist to inweave his novel theory with the familiar tradition in order to avoid discrediting his narrative in advance by his innovations. Noack's conclusion is that the inconsistency is not due to a single author; it is the result of a long process of redaction in which various divergent tendencies have been at work. But as the Fourth Gospel is not the logical terminus of the process of [pg 174] alteration, the only alternative is to place it at the beginning. What we have to seek in it is the original Gospel from which the process of transforming the tradition started.

And yet the essential critical ideas that can be found beneath this narrative, despite its fictional format, give this work a significance that the contemporary Lives of Jesus, which received the praise of theologians, lacked. It is the only account of Jesus that has been produced so far that is consistently written from the Johannine perspective from start to finish. In Noack's view, Strauss did not definitively demonstrate the absolute incompatibility of the Synoptic Gospels with the Fourth Gospel; neither he nor any other critic had fully grasped the complexity of the question of why the Fourth Evangelist would go to such lengths to create the multiple journeys to the Feasts, considering that the development of the Logos Christology did not necessarily require any changes in the setting of the ministry. On the contrary, one might assume that the Evangelist would prioritize weaving his new theory into the familiar tradition to avoid undermining his narrative right from the start with his innovations. Noack concludes that the inconsistency is not the work of a single author; it is the result of a lengthy process of editing in which various conflicting tendencies have emerged. However, since the Fourth Gospel is not the final stage of this process of [pg 174] alteration, the only other option is to position it at the beginning. What we need to find in it is the original Gospel from which the transformation of the tradition began.

There is also another line of argument based on the contradictions in the Gospel tradition which leads to the hypothesis that we have to do with redactions of the Gospels. Either Jesus was the Jewish Messiah of the Synoptics, or a Son of God in the Greek, spiritual sense, whose self-consciousness must be interpreted by means of the Logos doctrine: He cannot have been both at the same time. But it is inconceivable that a Jewish claimant of the Messiahship would have been left unmolested up to the last, and have had virtually to force the authorities to put him to death. On the other hand, if He were a simple enthusiast claiming to be a Son of God, a man who lived only for his own “self-consciousness,” He might from the beginning have taken up this attitude without being in any way molested, except by the scorn of men. In this respect also, therefore, the primitive Gospel which we can recover from John has the advantage. It was only later that this “Son of God” became the Jewish Messiah.

There is also another argument based on the contradictions in the Gospel tradition that suggests we are dealing with revisions of the Gospels. Either Jesus was the Jewish Messiah as presented in the Synoptics, or he was a Son of God in the Greek, spiritual sense, whose self-awareness must be understood through the Logos doctrine: He cannot be both at the same time. It’s hard to believe that a Jewish claimant to the Messiahship would have been allowed to go unbothered until the end and would have had to practically force the authorities to execute him. On the other hand, if He were just a simple enthusiast claiming to be a Son of God, a man who only lived for his own self-awareness he could have adopted this stance from the beginning without facing any real trouble, aside from the ridicule of others. In this respect, the original Gospel that we can take from John has the advantage. It was only later that this "Son of God" was considered the Jewish Messiah.

We arrive at the primitive Johannine writing when we cancel in the Fourth Gospel all Jewish doctrine and all miracles.104 Its date is the year 60 and it was composed by—Judas, the beloved disciple. This primitive Gospel received little modification and still shows clearly “the wonderful reality of its history.” It aims only at giving a section of Jesus' history, a representation of His attitude of mind and spirit. With “simple ingenuousness” it gives, “along with the kernel of the historical material of the Gospel, Jesus' thoughts about His own Person in the mysterious oracular sayings and deeply thoughtful and moving discourses by which the Nazarene stirred rather than enlightened the world.” Events of a striking character were, however, absent from it. The feeding of the multitude was represented in it as effected by natural means. It was a philanthropic feeding of a multitude which certainly did not number thousands, the numbers are a later insertion; Jesus fed them with bread and fish which He purchased from a “sutler-lad.” The healing of the lame man at the pool of Bethesda was the unmasking of a malingerer, whom the Lord exposed and ordered to depart. As He had bidden him carry his bed, and it was on the Sabbath, this brought Him into conflict with the authorities. His only “acts” were acts of self-revelation—mystical sayings which He threw out to the people. “The problem which meets us in His history is in truth a psychological problem, how, namely, His exalted view of Himself came to be accepted as the purest and highest truth—in His lifetime, it is true, only by a limited circle of disciples, but after His departure by a constantly growing [pg 175] multitude of believing followers.” The gospel of the beloved disciple Judas made its way quietly into the world, understood by few, even as Jesus Himself had been understood by a few only.

We reach the basic Johannine text when we remove all Jewish teachings and miracles from the Fourth Gospel.104 It dates back to the year 60 and was written by—Judas, the beloved disciple. This early Gospel was not significantly changed and clearly shows "the amazing reality of its history." Its purpose is simply to provide a part of Jesus' story, reflecting His mindset and spirit. With “simple innocence” it offers, “along with the main historical content of the Gospel, Jesus' views on His own identity found in the enigmatic oracular sayings and profound speeches that the Nazarene used to inspire rather than explain the world.” However, dramatic events are absent. The feeding of the crowd is portrayed as accomplished through natural means. It was a charitable act of feeding a crowd that certainly didn’t reach thousands; those numbers were added later. Jesus fed them with bread and fish that He bought from a "merchant boy." The healing of the lame man at the pool of Bethesda was merely exposing a fraud, whom the Lord revealed and told to leave. When He instructed him to carry his bed on the Sabbath, it led to a confrontation with the authorities. His only “actions” were acts of self-disclosure—mystical sayings shared with the people. “The challenge we encounter in His story is essentially a psychological one: how His elevated self-view became seen as the highest and purest truth—during His life, indeed, only by a small group of disciples, but after His departure by an increasingly large [pg 175] number of believing followers.” The Gospel of the beloved disciple Judas quietly navigated into the world, understood by few, just as Jesus Himself had been understood by only a handful.

About ten years later, according to Noack, appeared the original form of Luke, which we can reconstruct from what is known of Marcion's Luke.105 This Evangelist is under Pauline influence, and writes with an apologetic purpose. He desires to refute the calumny that Jesus was “possessed of a devil,” and he does this by making Him cast out devils. It was in this way that miracle forced itself into the Gospel history.

About ten years later, according to Noack, the original version of Luke appeared, which we can piece together from what we know about Marcion's Luke. This Evangelist is influenced by Paul and writes with a defensive aim. He wants to counter the accusation that Jesus was “possessed by a devil,” and he does this by showing Him casting out demons. This is how miracles became a part of the Gospel story.

But this primitive Luke, as Noack reconstructs it by combining the statements of the Fathers regarding Marcion's Gospel, knows nothing of Jesus' journey to Jerusalem to die. This circumstance is of capital importance to Noack, because in the course of his attempt to bring the topography of the Fourth Gospel into harmony with that of the Synoptics he had arrived at the remarkable result that the Johannine Christ worked in Galilee, not in Judaea. On the basis of the Onomasticon of Eusebius—which Noack, with the aid of topographical traditions derived from the Crusaders and statements of Mohammedan writers, interprets with a recklessness which is nothing short of criminal—Cana and Bethany (Bethabara) were not in the latitude of Jerusalem, but “near the head-waters of the Jordan in the upper part of the Jordan valley before it flows into the lake of Huleh. There, in Coele-Syria, on the southern slope of Hermon, was the scene of John the Baptist's labours; there Jesus began His ministry; thither He returned to die.” “It is in the Galilaean district which forms the scene of the Song of Solomon that the reader of this book must be prepared to find the Golgotha of the cross.” That is the sentence with which Noack's account of the Life of Jesus opens. This alludes to an idea which had already been worked out in his “Studies on the Song of Solomon,”106 namely, that the mountain country surrounding the upper Jordan was the pre-exilic Judaea, and that the “city of David” was situated there. The Jews on their return from exile had at first endeavoured to rebuild that Coele-Syrian city of David with the ruins of Solomon's Temple, but had been driven away from it and had then taken the desperate resolution to build the temple of Zerubbabel upon the high plateau lying far to the south of ancient Israel. Ezra the Scribe interpolated the forgery on the ground of which this site began to be accepted as the former city of David. Under the Syrian oppression all remembrance of the ancient city of David entirely disappeared.

But this early version Luke, as Noack puts together by combining the statements of the Church Fathers about Marcion's Gospel, knows nothing of Jesus' trip to Jerusalem to die. This fact is extremely important to Noack, because in his effort to align the geography of the Fourth Gospel with that of the Synoptics, he came to the striking conclusion that the Johannine Christ operated in Galilee, not in Judea. Based on the Name directory by Eusebius—which Noack interprets with a recklessness that’s downright shocking, using topographical traditions from the Crusaders and statements from Muslim writers—Cana and Bethany (Bethabara) were not located in the latitude of Jerusalem, but "Near the source of the Jordan River in the upper part of the Jordan Valley before it flows into the Huleh Lake. There, in Coele-Syria, on the southern slope of Hermon, was where John the Baptist carried out his work; it’s where Jesus started His ministry; and it’s where He came back to die." "It is in the Galilean region, which serves as the backdrop for the Song of Solomon, that the reader of this book should expect to find the Golgotha of the cross." That’s how Noack starts his account of the Life of Jesus. This references an idea that he had already developed in his "Research on the Song of Solomon,"106 namely, that the mountainous area surrounding the upper Jordan was the pre-exilic Judea, and that the "City of David" was located there. The Jews returning from exile initially tried to rebuild that Coele-Syrian city of David using the ruins of Solomon's Temple but were driven away from it, leading them to make the desperate decision to construct the temple of Zerubbabel on the high plateau far to the south of ancient Israel. Ezra the Scribe inserted the forgery on the basis of which this site began to be recognized as the former city of David. During the Syrian oppression, all memory of the ancient city of David completely vanished.

This fantastic edifice, in the construction of which the wildest [pg 176] etymologies play a part, is founded on the just recognition that a reconciliation of John with the Synoptists can only be effected by transferring some of the Johannine localities to the North; but this involves not only finding Bethany, Arimathea and the other places, but even the scene of Jesus' death in this district. The brook Kedron conveniently becomes the “brook of Cedars.”

This amazing building, constructed with the wildest [pg 176] etymologies, is based on the understanding that reconciling John with the Synoptic Gospels can only happen by moving some of the Johannine locations to the North. However, this not only requires locating Bethany, Arimathea, and other places but also determining the site of Jesus' death in this area. The brook Kedron conveniently turns into the "Cedar Brook."

For fifty years the two earliest Evangelists, in spite of their poverty of incident, sufficed for the needs of the Christians. The “fire of Jesus” was fed chiefly by the Pauline Gospel. The original form of the Gospel of Luke accordingly became the starting-point of the next stage of development. Thus arose the Gospel of Mark. Mark was not a native of Palestine, but a man of Roman extraction living in Decapolis, who had not the slightest knowledge of the localities in which the life of Jesus was really passed. He undertook, about the year 130, “in the interest of the new Christian settlement at Jerusalem in Hadrian's time, deliberately and consciously to transform the original plan of the Gospel history and to represent the Lord as crucified at Jerusalem.” The man who from the year 132 onward, as Mark the Bishop, preached the word of the Crucified to a Gentile Christian community amid the ruins of the holy city, had previously, as Mark the Evangelist, taken care that a prophet should not perish out of Jerusalem. In composing his Gospel he made use, in addition to Luke, of a traditional source which he found in Decapolis. He deliberately omitted the frequent journeys to Jerusalem which were still found in the original Luke, and inserted instead Jesus' journey to His death. He it was, also, who made the Nazarite into the Nazarene, laying the scene of Jesus' youth in Nazareth. To the cures of demoniacs he added magical acts such as the feeding of the multitude and the resurrection.

For fifty years, the two earliest Evangelists, despite their lack of events, were enough for the needs of the Christians. The “Jesus's fire” was mainly fueled by the Pauline Gospel. The original version of the Gospel of Luke became the starting point for the next phase of development. This is how the Gospel of Mark came to be. Mark wasn't from Palestine; he was of Roman descent and lived in Decapolis, having no real knowledge of the places where Jesus actually lived. Around the year 130, he set out, “In order to benefit the new Christian settlement in Jerusalem during Hadrian's time, there was a deliberate and conscious effort to change the original narrative of the Gospel and to portray the Lord as crucified in Jerusalem.” From the year 132 onward, as Mark the Bishop, he preached the message of the Crucified to a Gentile Christian community among the ruins of the holy city. Before this, as Mark the Evangelist, he made sure that a prophet wouldn’t be lost from Jerusalem. In crafting his Gospel, he used, in addition to Luke, a traditional source he found in Decapolis. He intentionally left out the frequent trips to Jerusalem that were in the original Luke and instead focused on Jesus' journey to His death. He was also the one who turned the Nazarite into the Nazarene, placing Jesus' childhood in Nazareth. He added to the accounts of exorcisms magical acts like the feeding of the multitude and the resurrection.

In Matthew, who appeared about 135, legend and fiction riot unchecked. In addition, Jewish parables and sayings are put into the mouth of Jesus, whereas He really had nothing to do with the Jewish world of ideas. For if anything is certain, it is that the moral maxims of the latest Gospel are of a distinctively Jewish origin. About the middle of the second century the originals of John and Luke underwent redaction. The redaction of the Logos Gospel was completed by the addition of the twenty-first chapter; the last redaction of Luke was perhaps carried out by Justin Martyr, fresh from completing his “Dialogue with Trypho”! Thus John and Luke are, in this final form, which is full of contradictions, the latest Gospels, and the saying is fulfilled about the first being last, and the last first.

In Matthew, which appeared around 135, legend and fiction run wild. Additionally, Jewish parables and sayings are attributed to Jesus, despite His having no connection to the Jewish world of ideas. What is certain is that the moral teachings in the latest Gospel have a distinctly Jewish origin. Around the middle of the second century, the original texts of John and Luke were edited. The editing of the Logos Gospel was finalized with the addition of the twenty-first chapter; the final edits of Luke were possibly done by Justin Martyr, right after finishing his "Chat with Trypho"! As a result, John and Luke, in this final version filled with contradictions, are the latest Gospels, which fulfills the saying that the first will be last, and the last will be first.

Arbitrary as these suggestions are, there is nevertheless something impressive in the attempt to explain the remarkable inconsistencies which are found within the Gospel tradition by [pg 177] considerations relating to its origin and development. Despite all his far-fetched ideas, Noack really stands higher than some of his contemporaries who showed more prudence in their theological enterprises, and about that time were earning the applause of the faculty, and quieting the minds of the laity, by performing once more the old conjuring trick—assisted by some new feats of legerdemain—of harmonising John with the Synoptists in such a way as to produce a Life of Jesus which could be turned to the service of ecclesiastical theology.

As random as these suggestions may be, there is still something impressive about the effort to explain the striking contradictions found in the Gospel tradition by considering its origin and development. Even with all his far-fetched ideas, Noack truly stands above some of his peers, who were more cautious in their theological pursuits and, around that time, were receiving praise from the faculty while reassuring the public by revisiting the old trick—enhanced by some new sleight of hand—of reconciling John with the Synoptics to create a Life of Jesus that could serve ecclesiastical theology.

The outline of the public Life of Jesus, as reconstructed by Noack, is as follows. It lasted from early in the year 35 to the 14th Nisan of the year 37, and began in the moment when Jesus revealed His consciousness of what He was. We do not know how long previously He had cherished it in secret. It is certain that the Baptist helped to bring about this revelation. This is the only part which he plays in the Gospel of John. He was neither a preacher of repentance, nor an Elias, nor the forerunner of Jesus, nor a mere signpost pointing to the Messiah, such as the secondary tradition makes him out to be.

The outline of the public life of Jesus, as reconstructed by Noack, is as follows. It lasted from early in the year 35 to the 14th of Nisan in the year 37, beginning at the moment when Jesus became aware of who He was. We don’t know how long before that He had held this awareness in secret. It’s clear that John the Baptist played a role in this revelation. This is the only part he plays in the Gospel of John. He was neither a preacher of repentance, nor Elijah, nor just a forerunner of Jesus, nor merely a sign pointing to the Messiah, as later traditions might suggest.

Similarly everything that is Messianic in the consciousness of Jesus is secondary. The lines of His thought were guided by the Greek ideas about sons of God, for the soil of northern Galilee was saturated with these ideas. Other sources which contributed something were the personification of the Divine Wisdom in the “Wisdom Literature” and some of Philo's doctrines. Jesus became the son of God in an ecstatic trance! Had not Philo recognised ecstasy as the last and highest means of rising to union with the Divine?

Similarly, everything Messianic in Jesus' consciousness is secondary. His thoughts were influenced by Greek ideas about sons of God, as northern Galilee was rich with these concepts. Other factors that contributed included the personification of Divine Wisdom in the "Wisdom Literature" and some teachings from Philo. Jesus became the son of God during an ecstatic trance! Didn't Philo acknowledge ecstasy as the ultimate and highest way to achieve union with the Divine?

Jesus' temperament, according to Noack, was pre-disposed to ecstasy, since He was born out of wedlock. One who had this burden upon His spirit may well have early taken refuge in His own thoughts, above the clouds, in the presence of the God of His fathers. Assailed in a thousand ways by the cruelty of the world, it would seem to Him as though His Heavenly Father, though unseen, was stretching out to Him the arms of consolation. Imagination, which ever mercifully lightens for men the yoke of misery, charmed the fatherless child out of His earthly sufferings and put into His hand a coloured glass through which He saw the world and life in a false light. Ecstatic enthusiasm had carried Him up to the dizzy height of spiritual union with the Father in Heaven. A hundred times He was cast down out of His dreams into the hard world of reality, to experience once more His earthly distresses, but ever anew He won His way by fasting, vigil, and prayer to the starry heaven of ecstasy.

Jesus' temperament, according to Noack, was naturally inclined toward ecstasy because He was born out of wedlock. Someone carrying such a burden on His spirit might have sought refuge in His thoughts, above the clouds, in the presence of the God of His ancestors. Constantly attacked by the harshness of the world, it must have felt to Him as though His Heavenly Father, though unseen, was reaching out to Him with arms of comfort. Imagination, which often graciously alleviates the suffering of people, drew the fatherless child away from His earthly pains and handed Him a colored lens through which He viewed the world and life in a distorted light. Ecstatic enthusiasm lifted Him to dizzying heights of spiritual connection with the Father in Heaven. Time and again He found Himself pulled from His dreams back into the harsh reality of life, faced once more with His earthly hardships, but He consistently found His way back to the starry heights of ecstasy through fasting, watchfulness, and prayer.

“Jesus,” Noack explains, “had in thought projected Himself beyond His earthly nativity and risen to the conception that His [pg 178] ego had been in existence before this earthly body in which He stood visibly upon the stage of the world. He felt that His ego had had being and life before He became incarnate upon earth.... This new conception of Himself, born of His solitary musings, was incorporated into the very substance of His natural personal ego. A new ego had superseded the old natural, corporeally conditioned ego.”

"Jesus," Noack explains, He saw Himself not just as a person born on earth but as someone whose [pg 178] identity existed before this physical body in which He appeared in the world. He believed that His identity had life and existence before He became human on earth.... This new understanding of Himself, arising from his solitary reflections, became a key part of His true, personal identity. A new self had taken the place of the old, physical identity.

Ambition, too, came into play—the high ambition to do God a service by the offering up of Himself. The passion of self-sacrifice is characteristic of a consciousness such as this. According to the document which underlies the Johannine Gospel it was not in consequence of outward events that Jesus took His resolve to die. “It was the later Gospel tradition which exhibited His fate as an inevitable consequence of His conflict with a world impervious to spiritual impression.” In the original Gospel that fate was freely embraced from the outset as belonging to the vocation of the Son of God. Only by the constant presence of the thought of death could a life which for two years walked the razor edge of such dizzy dreams have been preserved from falling. The conviction, or perhaps rather the instinctive feeling, that the rôle of a Son of God upon earth was not one to be maintained for decades was the necessary counterpoise to the enthusiasm of Jesus' spirit. From the first He was as much at home with the thought of death as with His Heavenly Father.

Ambition also played a role—the strong desire to serve God by offering Himself. The drive for self-sacrifice is typical of a consciousness like this. According to the document that underpins the Johannine Gospel, Jesus didn’t decide to die because of external events. "The later Gospel tradition portrayed His fate as an unavoidable result of His struggle against a world that was resistant to spiritual influence." In the original Gospel, that fate was willingly accepted from the beginning as part of the mission of the Son of God. Only by constantly thinking about death could a life that for two years teetered on such dizzying dreams be kept from falling apart. The belief, or perhaps more accurately the instinctive feeling, that the role of a Son of God on earth wasn’t meant to last for decades served as the necessary balance to the passion of Jesus' spirit. From the start, He was as comfortable with the idea of death as He was with His Heavenly Father.

This Son of Man—according to Noack's interpretation the title is equivalent to Son of Hope—requires of the multitude that they shall take His lofty dream for solid reality. “He revealed His message from heaven to the world at the Paschal Feast of the year 35, by throwing out a challenge to the Sadducaean hierarchy in Jerusalem.” In the time between John's removal from the scene and John's death, there falls the visit of Jesus to Samaria and a sojourn in the neighbourhood of His Galilaean home. At the Feast of Tabernacles in Jerusalem in the autumn of that year, the healing of the lame man at the pool of Bethesda led to a breach with the Sabbatic regulations of the Pharisees. Later on, in consequence of His generous feeding of the multitude in the Gaulonite table-land, there is an attempt to make Him into a Messianic King; which He, however, repudiates. At the time of the Passover in Galilee in the year 36, in the synagogue at Capernaum, He tests the spiritual insight of those who may, He hopes, be ripe for the higher teaching concerning the Son of God made flesh, by the touchstone of His mystical words about the bread of life. At the next Feast of Tabernacles, in the city of Zion, He makes a last desperate attempt to move men's hearts by the parable of the Good Shepherd who is ready to lay down His life for His sheep, the people of Israel.

This Son of Man—according to Noack's interpretation, the title is equivalent to Son of Hope—demands that the crowd embraces His lofty vision as a concrete reality. “He delivered His message from heaven to the world during the Passover Feast in 35 AD, by challenging the Sadducaean authority in Jerusalem.” In the time between John's departure and his death, Jesus visits Samaria and stays near His hometown in Galilee. During the Feast of Tabernacles in Jerusalem that autumn, the healing of the lame man at the pool of Bethesda causes a rift with the Pharisees’ Sabbath rules. Later, due to His abundant feeding of the crowd in the Gaulonite region, there’s an attempt to elevate Him to a Messianic King, which He rejects. At Passover in Galilee in the year 36, in the Capernaum synagogue, He tests the spiritual understanding of those who may be ready for the deeper teachings about the Son of God in human form, using His mystical words about the bread of life as a gauge. At the next Feast of Tabernacles, in the city of Zion, He makes one last desperate effort to touch people's hearts with the parable of the Good Shepherd who is willing to sacrifice His life for His sheep, the people of Israel.

[pg 179]

But His adversaries are remorseless; they wound Him to the very depths of His spirit by bringing to Him the woman taken in adultery, and asking Him what they are to do with her. When this question was sprung upon Him, He saw in a moment the public humiliation designed by His adversaries. All eyes were turned upon Him, and for a few moments the embarrassment of One who was usually so self-possessed was patent to all. He stooped as though He desired to write with His finger upon the ground. Was it shame at His dishonourable birth that compelled Him thus to lower His gaze? But the painful silence of expectation among the spectators did not last long. His adversaries repeated their question, He raised His head and spoke the undying words: “Let him that is without sin among you cast the first stone at her.”

But His opponents are relentless; they strike at the very core of His spirit by bringing Him the woman caught in adultery and asking what should be done with her. When this question was thrown at Him, He instantly understood the public humiliation his adversaries intended. All eyes were on Him, and for a brief moment, the embarrassment of someone who is usually so composed was clear to everyone. He bent down as if He wanted to write with His finger in the dirt. Was it shame over His questionable birth that made Him lower His gaze? But the heavy silence of expectation among the spectators didn’t last long. His opponents repeated their question, He lifted His head and spoke the unforgettable words: “Whoever among you is without sin should throw the first stone at her.”

Incensed by His constant references to His heavenly Sonship, they endeavour at last to stone Him. He flees from the Temple and takes refuge in the Jordan uplands. His purpose is, at the next Passover, that of the year 37, here in the mountains which were blessed as Joseph's portion, to offer His atoning death as that of the true paschal lamb, and with this act to quit the stage of the world's history. He remained in hiding in order to avoid the risk of assassination by the emissaries of the Pharisees. In Bethany He receives the mysterious visit of the Greeks, who doubtless desired to tempt Him to raise the standard of revolt as a claimant of the Messiahship, but He refuses to be shaken in His determination to die. The washing of the disciples' feet signifies their baptism with water, that they might thereafter receive the baptism of the Holy Spirit.

Angered by His constant claims of being the Son of God, they finally try to stone Him. He escapes from the Temple and finds safety in the hills near the Jordan River. His plan for the upcoming Passover in the year 37 is to offer His sacrificial death as the true Passover lamb in these mountains, which are blessed as Joseph's inheritance, and with this act, He intends to leave the stage of history. He stays hidden to avoid the threat of assassination by the Pharisees’ agents. In Bethany, He receives a mysterious visit from some Greeks, who likely hoped to persuade Him to start a revolt as a potential Messiah, but He remains steadfast in His decision to die. The washing of the disciples' feet symbolizes their baptism with water so that they can later receive the baptism of the Holy Spirit.

Judas, the disciple whom Jesus loved, who was a man of much resource, helped Him to avoid being arrested as a disturber of the peace by arranging that the “betrayal” should take place on the evening before the Passover, in order that Jesus might die, as He desired, on the day of the Passover. For this service of love he was, in the secondary tradition, torn from the bosom of the Lord and branded as a traitor.

Judas, the disciple whom Jesus loved, who was a resourceful man, helped Him avoid being arrested as a troublemaker by planning for the "betrayal" to happen the evening before Passover, so that Jesus could die, as He intended, on the day of Passover. For this act of devotion, he was, in later stories, separated from the love of the Lord and labeled a traitor.

[pg 180]

XIII. Renan

Ernest Renan. La Vie de Jésus. 1863. Paris, Michel Lévy Frères. 462 pp.

Ernest Renan. The Life of Jesus. 1863. Paris, Michel Lévy Frères. 462 pages.

E. de Pressensé. Jésus-Christ, son temps, sa vie, son œuvre. Paris, 1865. 684 pp.

E. de Pressensé. Jesus Christ, his era, his life, his mission. Paris, 1865. 684 pages.

Ernest Renan was born in 1823 at Tréguier in Brittany. Intended for the priesthood, he entered the seminary of St. Sulpice in Paris, but there, in consequence of reading the German critical theology, he began to doubt the truth of Christianity and of its history. In October 1845, shortly before the time arrived for him to be ordained a sub-deacon, he left the seminary and began to work for his living as a private teacher. In 1849 he received a government grant to enable him to make a journey to Italy for the prosecution of his studies, the fruits of which appeared in his Averroès et l'Averroïsme (Paris, 1852); in 1856 he was made a member of the Académie des Inscriptions; in 1860 he received from Napoléon III. the means to make a journey to Phoenicia and Syria. After his return in 1862 he obtained the professorship of Semitic Languages at the Collège de France. But the widespread indignation aroused by his Life of Jesus, which appeared in the following year, forced the Government to remove him from his office. He refused a post as Librarian of the Imperial Library, and lived in retirement until the Republic of 1871 restored him to his professorship. In politics, as in religion, his position was somewhat indefinite. In religion he was no longer a Catholic; avowed free-thought was too plebeian for his taste, and in Protestantism the multiplicity of sects repelled him. Similarly in politics, in the period immediately following the fall of the Empire, he was in turn Royalist, Republican, and Bonapartist. At bottom he was a sceptic. He died in 1892, already half-forgotten by the public; until his imposing funeral and interment in the Panthéon recalled him to its memory.

Ernest Renan was born in 1823 in Tréguier, Brittany. Aimed at becoming a priest, he entered the St. Sulpice seminary in Paris, but while there, after reading German critical theology, he started to doubt the truth of Christianity and its history. In October 1845, just before he was supposed to be ordained as a sub-deacon, he left the seminary and began working as a private tutor. In 1849, he received a government grant that allowed him to travel to Italy for his studies, which resulted in his book Averroes and Averroism (Paris, 1852). In 1856, he became a member of the Académie des Inscriptions, and in 1860, Napoléon III provided him the means to travel to Phoenicia and Syria. After returning in 1862, he was appointed professor of Semitic Languages at the Collège de France. However, the backlash caused by his book Life of Jesus, published the following year, led the Government to remove him from his position. He turned down a role as Librarian of the Imperial Library and lived in seclusion until the Republic of 1871 restored him to his professorship. In both politics and religion, his views were rather ambiguous. In religion, he was no longer a Catholic; he found open free-thinking too common for his taste, and the many Protestant sects put him off. Likewise, in the political landscape right after the Empire's fall, he fluctuated between being a Royalist, a Republican, and a Bonapartist. Deep down, he was a skeptic. He died in 1892, already somewhat forgotten by the public, until his grand funeral and burial in the Panthéon brought him back to people's minds.

Like Strauss, Renan designed his Life of Jesus to form part of a complete account of the history and dogma of the early Church. His purpose, however, was purely historical; it was no part of his [pg 181] project to set up, on the basis of the history, a new system of dogma, as Strauss had desired to do. This plan was not only conceived, but carried out. Les Apôtres appeared in 1866; St. Paul in 1869; L'Anté-Christ in 1873; Les Évangiles in 1877; L'Église chrétienne in 1879; Marc-Aurèle et la fin du monde antique in 1881. Several of these works were more valuable than the one which opened the series, but for the world Renan continued to be the author of the Vie de Jésus, and of that alone.

Like Strauss, Renan created his Life of Jesus to be a part of a complete account of the history and beliefs of the early Church. However, his goal was purely historical; he didn't intend to establish a new system of beliefs based on history, as Strauss had aimed to do. This plan was not only conceived but also executed. *Les Apôtres* was published in 1866; *St. Paul* in 1869; *L'Anté-Christ* in 1873; *Les Évangiles* in 1877; *L'Église chrétienne* in 1879; *Marc-Aurèle et la fin du monde antique* in 1881. Several of these works were more valuable than the one that started the series, but to the world, Renan was still known as the author of the *Vie de Jésus*, and that alone.

He planned the work at Gaza, and he dedicated it to his sister Henriette, who died soon after, in Syria, and lies buried at Byblus.

He organized the work in Gaza and dedicated it to his sister Henriette, who passed away soon after in Syria and is buried at Byblus.

This was the first Life of Jesus for the Catholic world, which had scarcely been touched—the Latin peoples least of all—by the two and a half generations of critical study which had been devoted to the subject. It is true, Strauss's work had been translated into French,107 but it had made only a passing stir, and that only among a little circle of intellectuals. Now came a writer with the characteristic French mental accent, who gave to the Latin world in a single book the result of the whole process of German criticism.

This was the first Life of Jesus for the Catholic world, which had hardly been affected—the Latin peoples least of all—by the two and a half generations of critical study that had been focused on the topic. It’s true, Strauss's work had been translated into French, 107 but it had only created a brief impact, and that just among a small group of intellectuals. Now came a writer with a distinct French perspective, who presented to the Latin world in one book the outcomes of the entire process of German criticism.

But Renan's work marked an epoch, not for the Catholic world only, but for general literature. He laid the problem which had hitherto occupied only theologians before the whole cultured world. And not as a problem, but as a question of which he, by means of his historical science and aesthetic power of reviving the past, could provide a solution. He offered his readers a Jesus who was alive, whom he, with his artistic imagination, had met under the blue heaven of Galilee, and whose lineaments his inspired pencil had seized. Men's attention was arrested, and they thought to see Jesus, because Renan had the skill to make them see blue skies, seas of waving corn, distant mountains, gleaming lilies, in a landscape with the Lake of Gennesareth for its centre, and to hear with him in the whispering of the reeds the eternal melody of the Sermon on the Mount.

But Renan's work marked a turning point, not just for the Catholic world but for literature as a whole. He presented a problem that had previously only concerned theologians to the entire educated audience. And not just as an issue, but as a question he believed he could answer through his historical insights and artistic ability to bring the past to life. He introduced his readers to a living Jesus, someone he creatively envisioned meeting under the blue skies of Galilee, and whose features his inspired artistry captured. People were captivated, feeling as if they could see Jesus because Renan had the talent to make them envision blue skies, fields of swaying grain, distant mountains, and shimmering lilies, all centered around the Lake of Gennesareth, and to hear, alongside him, the eternal melody of the Sermon on the Mount carried in the rustling of the reeds.

Yet the aesthetic feeling for nature which gave birth to this Life of Jesus was, it must be confessed, neither pure nor profound. It is a standing enigma why French art, which in painting grasps nature with a directness and vigour, with an objectivity in the best sense of the word, such as is scarcely to be found in the art of any other nation, has in poetry treated it in a fashion which scarcely ever goes beyond the lyrical and sentimental, the artificial, the subjective, in the worst sense of the word. Renan is no exception to this rule, any more than Lamartine or Pierre Loti. He looks at the landscape with the eye of a decorative painter seeking a motif for a lyrical composition upon which he is engaged. But that was not noticed by the many, because they, after all, were accustomed to have [pg 182] nature dressed up for them, and had had their taste so corrupted by a certain kind of lyricism that they had lost the power of distinguishing between truth and artificiality. Even those who might have noticed it were so astonished and delighted at being shown Jesus in the Galilaean landscape that they were content to yield to the enchantment.

Yet the feeling for nature that inspired this Life of Jesus was, to be honest, neither pure nor deep. It’s a puzzling mystery why French art, which captures nature in painting with such directness, energy, and a clear-eyed objectivity that’s hard to find in the art of other nations, has treated it in poetry in a way that rarely goes beyond the lyrical and sentimental, or worse, the artificial and subjective. Renan is no exception to this, just like Lamartine or Pierre Loti. He views the landscape with the perspective of a decorative painter searching for a theme for a lyrical piece he’s working on. But most people didn’t notice this because they were used to having nature presented to them in an embellished way and had their taste so twisted by a certain type of lyricism that they lost the ability to tell the difference between reality and artifice. Even those who might have caught on were so surprised and pleased to see Jesus in the Galilean landscape that they happily fell under its spell.

Along with this artificial feeling for nature a good many other things were accepted without question. There is scarcely any other work on the subject which so abounds in lapses of taste—and those of the most distressing kind—as Renan's Vie de Jésus. It is Christian art in the worst sense of the term—the art of the wax image. The gentle Jesus, the beautiful Mary, the fair Galilaeans who formed the retinue of the “amiable carpenter,” might have been taken over in a body from the shop-window of an ecclesiastical art emporium in the Place St. Sulpice. Nevertheless, there is something magical about the work. It offends and yet it attracts. It will never be quite forgotten, nor is it ever likely to be surpassed in its own line, for nature is not prodigal of masters of style, and rarely is a book so directly born of enthusiasm as that which Renan planned among the Galilaean hills.

Along with this artificial appreciation for nature, many other things were accepted without question. There’s hardly any other work on the subject that is so full of lapses in taste—and especially the most distressing kind—than Renan's Life of Jesus. It represents Christian art in the worst possible way—the art of the wax figure. The gentle Jesus, the beautiful Mary, and the fair Galileans who accompanied the "friendly carpenter," could easily have been taken straight from the display window of a church art store in Place St. Sulpice. Still, there's something enchanting about the work. It offends yet attracts. It will never be fully forgotten, nor is it likely to be surpassed in its own genre, since nature doesn’t produce many masters of style, and it’s rare for a book to be born from such enthusiasm as that which Renan envisioned among the Galilean hills.

The essay on the sources of the Life of Jesus with which it opens is itself a literary masterpiece. With a kind of effortless ease he makes his readers acquainted with the criticism of Strauss, of Baur, of Reuss, of Colani. He does not argue, but simply sets the result vividly before the reader, who finds himself at once at home in the new world of ideas. He avoids any hard or glaring effects; by means of that skilful transition from point to point which Wagner in one of his letters praises as the highest art, everything is surrounded with atmosphere. But how much trickery and illusion there is in this art! In a few strokes he indicates the relation of John to the Synoptists; the dilemma is made clear, it seems as if one horn or the other must be chosen. Then he begins by artful touches to soften down the contrast. The discourses of John are not authentic; the historical Jesus cannot have spoken thus. But what about the statements of fact? Here Renan declares himself convinced by the graphic presentment of the passion story. Touches like “it was night,” “they had lighted a fire of coals,” “the coat was without seam,” cannot have been invented. Therefore the Gospel must in some way go back to the disciple whom Jesus loved. It is possible, nay certain, that when as an old man he read the other Gospels, he was displeased by certain inaccuracies, and perhaps vexed that he was given so small a place in the history. He began to dictate a number of things which he had better means of knowing than the others; partly, too, with the purpose of showing that in many cases where Peter only had been mentioned he also had played a part, and indeed the principal part. [pg 183] Sometimes his recollection was quite fresh, sometimes it had been modified by time. When he wrote down the discourses, he had forgotten the Lake of Gennesareth and the winsome words which he had listened to upon its shores. He was now living in quite a different world. The events of the year 70 destroyed his hopes of the return of his Master. His Jewish prejudices fell away, and as he was still young, he adapted himself to the syncretistic, philosophic, gnostic environment amid which he found himself in Ephesus. Thus even Jesus' world of thought took on a new shape for him; although the discourses are perhaps rather to be referred to his school than to himself. But, when all is said, John remains the best biographer. Or, to put it more accurately, while all the Gospels are biographies, they are legendary biographies, even though they come down from the first century. Their texts need interpretation, and the clue to the interpretation can be supplied by aesthetic feeling. They must be subjected to a gentle pressure to bring them together, and make them coalesce into a unity in which all the data are happily combined.

The essay on the sources of the Life of Jesus that it starts with is a literary masterpiece in its own right. With a sort of effortless ease, he introduces his readers to the critiques of Strauss, Baur, Reuss, and Colani. He doesn’t argue but simply presents the results vividly, allowing the reader to feel at home in this new world of ideas. He steers clear of any harsh or jarring effects; through a skilled transition from point to point—something Wagner praises in one of his letters as the highest art—everything is enveloped in atmosphere. But there’s a lot of trickery and illusion in this art! In a few strokes, he indicates the relationship of John to the Synoptists; the dilemma is laid out, as if one must choose between two options. Then he subtly begins to soften the contrast. The teachings of John aren't authentic; the historical Jesus couldn't have spoken this way. But what about the factual statements? Here, Renan expresses his conviction through the vivid presentation of the passion story. Phrases like “It was nighttime,” "they had lit a fire with coals," “the coat had no seams,” couldn’t have been fabricated. Thus, the Gospel must somehow trace back to the disciple whom Jesus loved. It’s possible, even likely, that as an old man he became frustrated with certain inaccuracies in the other Gospels and perhaps was annoyed that he had such a small role in the narrative. He started dictating things he knew better than they did; partly to show that in many cases where only Peter is mentioned, he also had a role, and indeed, a significant one. [pg 183] Sometimes his memories were quite fresh, and other times they were altered by time. When he wrote down the teachings, he had forgotten the Lake of Gennesareth and the beautiful words he had heard by its shores. He was now living in a totally different world. The events of 70 AD shattered his hopes for his Master’s return. His Jewish biases faded, and while still young, he adapted to the syncretistic, philosophical, and gnostic environment in Ephesus. Thus, even Jesus' way of thinking took on a new form for him; although the teachings likely pertain more to his school than to him personally. But in the end, John remains the best biographer. Or to put it more precisely, while all the Gospels are biographies, they are legendary biographies, even though they date back to the first century. Their texts require interpretation, and aesthetic feeling can provide the key to that interpretation. They need gentle pressure to bring them together, creating a unity where all the elements are harmoniously combined.

How this is to be done Renan shows later in his description of the death of Jesus. “Suddenly,” he says, “Jesus gave a terrible cry in which some thought they heard ‘Father, into thy hands I commend my spirit,’ but which others, whose thoughts were running on the fulfilment of prophecy, reported as ‘It is finished.’ ”

How this is to be done, Renan explains later in his description of the death of Jesus. "Out of nowhere," he says, “Jesus let out a chilling cry that some believed they heard as ‘Father, into thy hands I commend my spirit,’ while others, focused on the fulfillment of prophecy, reported it as ‘It is finished.’ ”

The authentic sayings of Jesus are more or less self-evidencing. Coming in contact with one of them amid the welter of heterogeneous traditions, you feel a thrill of recognition. They leap forth and take their proper place, where their vivid power becomes apparent. For one who writes the life of Jesus on His native soil, the Gospels are not so much sources of information as incentives to revelation. “I had,” Renan avows, “a fifth Gospel before my eyes, mutilated in parts, but still legible, and taking it for my guide I saw behind the narratives of Matthew and Mark, instead of an ideal Being of whom it might be maintained that He had never existed, a glorious human countenance full of life and movement.” It is this Jesus of the fifth Gospel that he desires to portray.

The true sayings of Jesus are pretty obvious. When you come across one of them amid the mix of different traditions, you feel a rush of recognition. They stand out and take their rightful place, where their striking power becomes clear. For someone writing about Jesus in His own environment, the Gospels aren’t just sources of information; they’re prompts for revelation. "I've had," Renan admits, "Like a fifth Gospel in front of me, flawed in some areas but still legible, I used it as my guide. I discovered behind the tales of Matthew and Mark, not an ideal Being that could be debated as never having existed, but a remarkable human presence filled with life and energy." It is this Jesus of the fifth Gospel that he wants to depict.

In looking at the picture, the reader must not allow the vexed question of miracle to distract him and disturb the proper frame of mind. The author refuses to assert either the possibility or the impossibility of miracle, but speaks only as an historian. “We do not say miracle is impossible, we say only that there has never been a satisfactorily authenticated miracle.”

While examining the picture, the reader should not let the tricky issue of miracles distract them or disrupt their mindset. The author doesn’t claim that miracles can or cannot happen; instead, they speak purely as a historian. "We're not saying miracles are impossible; we're just saying that there has never been a thoroughly verified miracle."

In view of the method of treatment adopted by Renan there can, of course, be no question of an historical plan. He brings in each saying at the point where it seems most appropriate. None of them is passed over, but none of them appears in its historical setting. He shifts individual incidents hither and thither in the [pg 184] most arbitrary fashion. For example, the coming of Jesus' mother to seek Him (in the belief that He is beside Himself) must belong to the later part of Jesus' life, since it is out of tone with the happy innocence of the earlier period. Certain scenes are transposed from the later period to the earlier, because they are not gloomy enough for the later time. Others again are made the basis of an unwarranted generalisation. It is not enough that Jesus once rode upon an ass while the disciples in the intoxication of joy cast their garments in the way; according to Renan, He constantly rode about, even in Galilee, upon a mule, “that favourite riding-animal of the East, which is so docile and sure-footed and whose great dark eyes, shaded by long lashes, are full of gentleness.” Sometimes the disciples surrounded Him with rustic pomp, using their garments by way of carpeting. They laid them upon the mule which carried Him, or spread them before Him on the way.

Given the treatment method used by Renan, there's clearly no historical plan involved. He includes each saying where it seems most fitting. None are overlooked, but none appear in their historical context. He moves individual incidents around in the [pg 184] in a very random way. For example, when Jesus' mother comes to find Him (thinking He has lost His mind), it must be from the later part of His life, as it doesn't match the joyful innocence of the earlier time. Some scenes are shifted from later periods to earlier ones because they don't match the somber tone of later times. Others are used as the basis for unsupported generalizations. It's not enough that Jesus once rode on a donkey while the disciples joyfully threw their garments on the road; according to Renan, He frequently rode around, even in Galilee, on a mule, "that beloved riding animal from the East, known for being so calm and sure-footed, and whose large dark eyes, framed by long lashes, are filled with kindness." Sometimes, the disciples surrounded Him with rustic flair, using their garments as a carpet. They laid them on the mule that carried Him or spread them on the ground in front of Him.

Scenes of little significance are sometimes elaborately described by Renan while more important ones are barely touched on. “One day, indeed,” he remarks in describing the first visit to Jerusalem, “anger seems to have, as the saying goes, overmastered Him; He struck some of the miserable chafferers with the scourge, and overthrew their tables.” Such is the incidental fashion in which the cleansing of the temple was brought in. In this way it is possible to smuggle in a miracle without giving any further explanation of it. The miracle at Cana is brought, by means of the following unobtrusive turn of phrase, into the account of the period of success in Galilee. “One of His miracles was done by Jesus for the sole purpose of increasing the happiness of a wedding-party in a little country town.”

Scenes of little significance are sometimes described in great detail by Renan, while more important events are only briefly mentioned. "One day, for sure," he notes when discussing the first visit to Jerusalem, "Anger, as the saying goes, seems to have taken over; he whipped some of the poor traders and overturned their tables." This shows how casually the cleansing of the temple is introduced. This way, a miracle can be included without any further explanation. The miracle at Cana is similarly woven into the story of the successful period in Galilee through the following understated phrase: "One of His miracles was performed by Jesus simply to make a wedding celebration in a small town happier."

This Life of Jesus is introduced by a kind of prelude. Jesus had been living in Galilee before He came to the Baptist; when He heard of the latter's success He went to him with His little company of followers. They were both young, and Jesus became the imitator of the Baptist. Fortunately the latter soon disappeared from the scene, for his influence on Jesus was in some respects injurious. The Galilaean teacher was on the verge of losing the sunny religion which He had learned from His only teacher, the glorious natural scenery which surrounded His home, and of becoming a gloomy Jewish fanatic. But this influence fell away from Him again; when He returned to Galilee He became Himself once more. The only thing which He had gained from John was some knowledge of the art of preaching. He had learned from him how to influence masses of men. From that time forward He preached with much more power and gained greater ascendancy over the people.

This Life of Jesus begins with a sort of prelude. Jesus had been living in Galilee before he came to John the Baptist; when he heard about John's success, he went to him with his small group of followers. They were both young, and Jesus started to copy John. Luckily, John soon vanished from the scene, as his influence on Jesus was, in some ways, harmful. The Galilean teacher was close to losing the positive faith he had learned from his only teacher, the beautiful natural scenery around his home, and was on the verge of becoming a gloomy Jewish extremist. But this influence eventually faded away; when he returned to Galilee, he became himself again. The only thing he gained from John was some knowledge of preaching. He learned how to reach and inspire large groups of people. From that point on, he preached with much more power and gained a stronger influence over the people.

With the return to Galilee begins the first act of the piece. The story of the rise of Christianity is a pastoral play. Bauer, in [pg 185] his “Philo, Strauss, and Renan,” writes with biting sarcasm: “Renan, who is at once the author of the play, the stage-manager, and the director of the theatre, gives the signal to begin, and at a sign from him the electric lights are put on full power, the Bengal fires flare up, the footlights are turned higher, and while the flutes and shawms of the orchestra strike up the overture, the people enter and take their places among the bushes and by the shore of the Lake.” And how confiding they were, this gentle and peaceful company of Galilaean fisher folk! And He, the young carpenter, conjured the Kingdom of Heaven down to earth for a year, by the spell of the infinite tenderness which radiated from Him. A company of men and women, all of the same youthful integrity and simple innocence, became His followers and constantly repeated “Thou art the Messiah.” By the women He was more beloved than He Himself liked, but from His passion for the glory of His Father He was content to attract these “fair creatures” (belles créatures) and suffered them to serve Him, and God through Him. Three or four devoted Galilaean women constantly accompanied Him and strove with one another for the pleasure (le plaisir) of listening to His teaching and attending to His comfort. Some of them were wealthy and used their means to enable the “amiable” (charmant) prophet to live without needing to practise His handicraft. The most devoted of all was Mary Magdalene, whose disordered mind had been healed by the influence of the pure and gracious beauty (par la beauté pure et douce) of the young Rabbi.

With the return to Galilee, the first act of the story begins. The rise of Christianity unfolds like a pastoral play. Bauer, in [pg 185] his “Philo, Strauss, and Renan” writes with sharp sarcasm: "Renan, who is both the author, stage manager, and director of the theater, signals the start. At his cue, the electric lights blaze to full brightness, the Bengal flares light up, the footlights are raised, and as the orchestra starts the overture with flutes and shawms, people enter and find their places among the bushes and along the shore of the Lake." And how trusting they were, this gentle and peaceful group of Galilean fishermen! And He, the young carpenter, brought the Kingdom of Heaven down to earth for a year, with the charm of the infinite tenderness that radiated from Him. A group of men and women, all filled with youthful integrity and simple innocence, became His followers and kept saying "You are the Savior." The women loved Him even more than He might have preferred, but motivated by His passion for His Father's glory, He gladly welcomed these “beautiful people” (beautiful creatures) and allowed them to serve Him, and God through Him. Three or four devoted Galilean women regularly accompanied Him, competing with each other for the joy (the pleasure) of listening to His teachings and attending to His needs. Some of them were wealthy and used their resources to allow the "adorable" (charming) prophet to live without having to work at His trade. The most devoted of all was Mary Magdalene, whose troubled mind was healed by the influence of the pure and gracious beauty (by pure and gentle beauty) of the young Rabbi.

Thus He rode, on His long-eyelashed gentle mule, from village to village, from town to town. The sweet theology of love (la délicieuse théologie de l'amour) won Him all hearts. His preaching was gentle and mild (suave et douce), full of nature and the fragrance of the country. Wherever He went the people kept festival. At marriages He was a welcome guest; to the feasts which He gave He invited women who were sinners, and publicans like the good Zacchaeus.

Thus He rode, on His gentle mule with long eyelashes, from village to village, from town to town. The sweet theology of love (the delicious theology of love) captured everyone’s heart. His preaching was gentle and kind (smooth and sweet), filled with the beauty of nature and the scent of the countryside. Wherever He went, the people celebrated. At weddings, He was a welcome guest; for the feasts He hosted, He invited women who were sinners and tax collectors like the good Zacchaeus.

“The Frenchman,” remarks Noack, “takes the mummied figure of the Galilaean Rabbi, which criticism has exhumed, endows it with life and energy, and brings Him upon the stage, first amid the lustre of the earthly happiness which it was His pleasure to bestow, and then in the moving aspect of one doomed to suffer.”

“The French guy,” says Noack, "brings the preserved image of the Galilean Rabbi, revealed by criticism, to life and energy, showcasing Him on stage, first in the warmth of the earthly joy He chose to give, and then in the touching depiction of someone meant to suffer."

When Jesus goes up to the Passover at the end of this first year, He comes into conflict with the Rabbis of the capital. The “winsome teacher, who offered forgiveness to all on the sole condition of loving Him,” found in the capital people upon whom His charm had no effect. When He returned to Galilee He had entirely abandoned His Jewish beliefs, and a revolutionary ardour glowed in His heart. The second act begins. “The action becomes more serious and gloomy, and the pupil of Strauss turns [pg 186] down the footlights of his stage.”108 The erstwhile “winsome moralist” has become a transcendental revolutionary. Up to this point He had thought to bring about the triumph of the Kingdom of God by natural means, by teaching and influencing men. The Jewish eschatology stood vaguely in the background. Now it becomes prominent. The tension set up between His purely ethical ideas and these eschatological expectations gives His words from this time forward a special force. The period of joyous simplicity is past.

When Jesus goes up to the Passover at the end of this first year, He runs into conflict with the Rabbis in the capital. The “a charming teacher who offered forgiveness to anyone as long as they loved Him,” found people in the capital who were not affected by His charm. When He returned to Galilee, He had completely abandoned His Jewish beliefs, and a revolutionary passion burned in His heart. The second act begins. "The mood shifts to one that is more serious and dark as Strauss's student steps down from the footlights of his stage."108 The former "charming moral philosopher" has transformed into a transcendental revolutionary. Until this point, He believed He could bring about the triumph of the Kingdom of God through natural means, by teaching and influencing people. The Jewish eschatology stood vaguely in the background. Now it becomes prominent. The tension between His purely ethical ideas and these eschatological expectations gives His words from this moment on a special impact. The time of joyful simplicity is over.

Even the character of the hero loses its simplicity. In the furtherance of His cause He becomes a wonder-worker. It is true that even before He had sometimes practised innocent arts such as Joan of Arc made use of later.109 He had, for instance, pretended to know the unspoken thoughts of one whom He desired to win, had reminded him, perhaps, of some experience of which he cherished the memory. He allowed the people to believe that He received knowledge of certain matters through a kind of revelation. Finally, it came to be whispered that He had spoken with Moses and Elias upon the mountains. But He now finds Himself compelled to adopt in earnest the rôle which He had formerly taken, as it were, in play. Against His will He is compelled to found His work upon miracle. He must face the alternative of either renouncing His mission or becoming a thaumaturge. He consented, therefore, to play an active part in many miracles. In this astute friends gave Him their aid. At Bethany something happened which could be regarded as a raising of the dead. Perhaps this miracle was arranged by Lazarus himself. When very ill he had allowed himself to be wrapped in the cerements of the dead and laid in the grave. His sisters sent for Jesus and brought Him to the tomb. He desired to look once more upon His friend, and when, overcome with grief, He cried his name aloud, Lazarus came forth from the grave. Why should the brother and sisters have hesitated to provide a miracle for the Master, in whose miracle-working power they, indeed, believed? Where, then, was Renan's allegiance to his “honoured master” Strauss, when he thus enrolled himself among the rationalists?

Even the hero's character loses its straightforwardness. In the pursuit of His cause, He becomes a miracle worker. It's true that even before, He had sometimes practiced innocent tricks similar to those Joan of Arc would later use. For example, He pretended to know the unspoken thoughts of someone He wanted to win over and reminded him, perhaps, of a cherished memory. He allowed people to think that He gained knowledge of certain matters through a sort of revelation. Eventually, it was rumored that He spoke with Moses and Elijah on the mountains. But now, He finds Himself forced to take on the role He once played as if it were a game. Against His will, He must establish His work on miracles. He faces the choice of either giving up His mission or becoming a miracle worker. So, He agreed to actively participate in many miracles. In this, clever friends supported Him. At Bethany, something occurred that could be considered a raising of the dead. Perhaps this miracle was arranged by Lazarus himself. When he was very sick, he allowed himself to be wrapped in burial cloths and laid in the tomb. His sisters sent for Jesus and brought Him to the grave. He wanted to see His friend one more time, and when, overcome with grief, He called out his name, Lazarus came out of the grave. Why would the brother and sisters hesitate to create a miracle for the Master, in whom they truly believed? Where, then, was Renan's loyalty to his “honored master” Strauss when he aligned himself with the rationalists?

On these lines Jesus played His part for eighteen months, from the Easter of 31 to the Feast of Tabernacles of 32. How great is the change from the gentle teacher of the Sermon on the Mount! His discourse takes on a certain hardness of tone. In the synagogue at Capernaum He drives many from Him, offended by the saying about eating and drinking His flesh and blood. The “extreme materialism of the expression,” which in Him had always been the natural counterpoise to the “extreme idealism of the [pg 187] thought,” becomes more and more pronounced. His “Kingdom of God” was indeed still essentially the kingdom of the poor, the kingdom of the soul, the great spiritual kingdom; but He now preached it as the kingdom of the apocalyptic writings. And yet in the very moment when He seems to be staking everything upon a supernatural fulfilment of His hopes, He provides with remarkable prescience the basis of a permanent Church. He appoints the Twelve Apostles and institutes the fellowship-meal. It is certain, Renan thinks, that the “Supper” was not first instituted on that last evening; even in the second Galilaean period He must have practised with His followers the mystic rite of the Breaking of Bread, which in some way symbolised His death.

On these lines, Jesus played His role for eighteen months, from Easter of 31 to the Feast of Tabernacles of 32. What a shift from the gentle teacher of the Sermon on the Mount! His messages had a harsher tone. In the synagogue at Capernaum, He drove many away, offended by His comments about eating and drinking His flesh and blood. The “extreme materialism of the expression,” which had always been a natural balance to the “extreme idealism of the thought,” becomes increasingly pronounced. His “Kingdom of God” was still fundamentally the kingdom of the poor, the kingdom of the soul, the great spiritual kingdom; however, He now preached it as described in the apocalyptic writings. Yet, at the very moment He appears to be putting everything on the line for a supernatural realization of His hopes, He remarkably lays down the foundation for a lasting Church. He appoints the Twelve Apostles and establishes the fellowship meal. Renan believes it’s clear that the “Supper” wasn’t first instituted on that last evening; even during the second Galilean phase, He must have practiced the mystic rite of the Breaking of Bread with His followers, which somehow symbolized His death.

By the end of this period He had cast off all earthly ambitions. Nothing of earth existed for Him any more. A strange longing for persecution and martyrdom had taken possession of Him. It was not, however, the resolve to offer an atonement for the sins of His people which familiarised Him with the thought of death; it was forced upon Him by the knowledge that He had entered upon a path in which it was impossible for Him to sustain His rôle for more than a few months, or perhaps even weeks. So He sets out for Jerusalem, outwardly a hero, inwardly half in despair because He has turned aside from His true path. The gentle, faithful, long-eyelashed mule bears Him, amid the acclamations of the multitude, through the gate of the capital.

By the end of this period, He had let go of all worldly ambitions. Nothing earthly mattered to Him anymore. A strange desire for persecution and martyrdom had taken hold of Him. However, it wasn't the commitment to make amends for the sins of His people that made Him contemplate death; it was the realization that He was on a path where it would be impossible to maintain His role for more than a few months, or maybe even weeks. So, He heads to Jerusalem, appearing outwardly like a hero, but inwardly feeling a bit of despair because He has strayed from His true path. The gentle, loyal, long-eyed mule carries Him, amid the cheers of the crowd, through the gate of the capital.

The third act begins: the stage is dark and becomes constantly darker, until at last, through the darkness of the scene, there is faintly visible only the figure of a woman—of her who in her deep grief beside the grave was by her vision to call to life again Him whom she loved. There was darkness, too, in the souls of the disciples, and in that of the Master. The bitter jealousy between Judas and John made one of them a traitor. As for Jesus, He had His hour of gloom to fight through in Gethsemane. For a moment His human nature awakened in Him; all that He thought He had slain and put behind Him for ever rose up and confronted Him as He knelt there upon the ground. “Did He remember the clear brooks of Galilee at which He might have slaked His thirst—the vine and the fig-tree beneath which He might have rested—the maidens who would perhaps have been willing to love Him? Did He regret His too exalted nature? Did He, a martyr to His own greatness, weep that He had not remained the simple carpenter of Nazareth? We do not know!”

The third act begins: the stage is dark and gets progressively darker, until finally, through the shadows, a woman is faintly visible—she who, in her deep sorrow beside the grave, was brought to summon back to life the one she loved. There was also darkness in the hearts of the disciples and in the Master. The bitter envy between Judas and John turned one of them into a traitor. As for Jesus, He had His moments of despair to confront in Gethsemane. For a brief time, His human nature flared up; everything He thought He had overcome and left behind came back to face Him as He knelt there on the ground. “Did He remember the clear streams of Galilee where He could have quenched His thirst—the vine and the fig tree where He might have found rest—the young women who might have loved Him? Did He regret His high calling? Did He, a martyr to His own greatness, wish He had remained the simple carpenter of Nazareth? We don’t know!”

He is dead. Renan, as though he stood in Père Lachaise, commissioned to pronounce the final allocution over a member of the Academy, apostrophises Him thus: “Rest now, amid Thy glory, noble pioneer. Thou conqueror of death, take the sceptre of Thy Kingdom, into which so many centuries of Thy [pg 188] worshippers shall follow Thee, by the highway which Thou hast opened up.”

He is dead. Renan, as if he were standing in Père Lachaise, tasked with delivering the final speech over a member of the Academy, addresses Him like this: "Rest now, in Your glory, noble pioneer. You, conqueror of death, take the scepter of Your Kingdom, into which so many centuries of Your [pg 188] worshippers will follow You, along the path that You have paved."

The bell rings; the curtain begins to fall; the swing-seats tilt. The epilogue is scarcely heard: “Jesus will never have a rival. His religion will again and again renew itself; His story will call forth endless tears: His sufferings will soften the hearts of the best; every successive century will proclaim that among the sons of men there hath not arisen a greater than Jesus.”

The bell rings; the curtain starts to come down; the swing-seats lean. The epilogue is barely audible: “Jesus will never have a competitor. His faith will constantly evolve; His story will inspire endless tears: His pain will resonate with the kindest hearts; each coming century will proclaim that no one in humanity has been greater than Jesus.”

The book passed through eight editions in three months. The writings of those who opposed it had an equal vogue. That of Freppel had reached its twelfth edition in 1864.110 Their name was legion. Whatever wore a soutane and could wield a pen charged against Renan, the bishops leading the van. The tone of these attacks was not always very elevated, nor their logic very profound. In most cases the writers were only concerned to defend the Deity of Christ,111 and the miracles, and are satisfied that they have done so when they have pointed out some of the glaring inconsistencies in Renan's work. Here and there, however, among these refutations we catch the tone of a loftier ethical spirit which has recognised the fundamental weakness of the work, the lack of any definite ethical principles in the writer's outlook upon life.112 There were some indeed who were not content with a refutation; they would gladly have seen active measures taken against Renan. One of his most embittered adversaries, Amadée Nicolas,113 reckons up in an appendix to his work the maximum penalties authorised by the existing enactments against free-thought, and would welcome the application of the law of the 25th of March 1822, according to which five years' imprisonment could be imposed for the crime of “insulting or making ridiculous a religion recognised by the state.”

The book went through eight editions in just three months. The writings of those who disagreed with it were equally popular. Freppel’s work had reached its twelfth edition by 1864.110 Their numbers were countless. Anyone in a cassock who could write took shots at Renan, with the bishops leading the charge. The tone of these attacks wasn’t always very sophisticated, nor was their reasoning particularly deep. Most of the writers were mainly concerned with defending the divinity of Christ,111 and the miracles, feeling satisfied when they pointed out some of the obvious inconsistencies in Renan's work. However, scattered among these rebuttals, we can find a more elevated ethical perspective that recognizes the fundamental flaw in his work: the absence of clear ethical principles in the writer's view of life.112 Some were not satisfied with just arguing against him; they would have preferred to see active measures taken against Renan. One of his most bitter opponents, Amadée Nicolas,113 lists in an appendix to his work the maximum penalties allowed by the current laws against free thought and would welcome the enforcement of the law from March 25, 1822, which could impose five years in prison for the crime of "insulting or mocking a religion that is recognized by the government."

Renan was defended by the Siècle, the Débats, at that time the leading French newspaper, and the Temps, in which Scherer published five articles upon the book. Even the Revue des deux mondes, which had formerly raised a warning voice against Strauss, allowed itself to go with the stream, and published in its August [pg 189] number of 1863 a critical analysis by Havet114 who hailed Renan's work as a great achievement, and criticised only the inconsistencies by which he had endeavoured to soften down the radical character of his undertaking. Later on the Revue changed its attitude and sided with Renan's opponents. In the Protestant camp there was an even keener sense of distaste than in the Catholic for the sentimental gloss which Renan had spread over his work to make it attractive to the multitude by its iridescent colours. In four remarkable letters Athanase Coquerel the younger took the author to task for this.115 From the standpoint of orthodox scholarship E. de Pressensé condemned him;116 and proceeded without loss of time to refute him in a large-scale Life of Jesus.117 He was answered by Albert Réville,118 who claims recognition for Renan's services to criticism.

Renan was defended by the Century, the Debates, which was the leading French newspaper at the time, and the Temps, where Scherer published five articles about the book. Even the Review of the Two Worlds, which had previously warned against Strauss, decided to go along with the popular view and published a critical analysis by Havet in its August [pg 189] issue of 1863. Havet praised Renan's work as a significant achievement while only criticizing the inconsistencies that showed attempts to soften the radical nature of his project. Later, the Review changed its stance and aligned with Renan's critics. Within the Protestant community, there was an even stronger objection than among Catholics to the sentimental embellishments that Renan added to his work to appeal to the masses with its vibrant colors. Athanase Coquerel the younger criticized the author in four notable letters.115 E. de Pressensé condemned him from an orthodox scholarly perspective;116 and promptly refuted him in a comprehensive Life of Jesus.117 He was responded to by Albert Réville,118 who acknowledged Renan's contributions to criticism.

In general, however, the rising French school of critical theology was disappointed in Renan. Their spokesman was Colani. “This is not the Christ of history, the Christ of the Synoptics,” he writes in 1864 in the Revue de théologie, “but the Christ of the Fourth Gospel, though without His metaphysical halo, and painted over with a brush which has been dipped in the melancholy blue of modern poetry, in the rose of the eighteenth-century idyll, and in the grey of a moral philosophy which seems to be derived from La Rochefoucauld.” “In expressing this opinion,” he adds, “I believe I am speaking in the name of those who belong to what is known as the new Protestant theology, or the Strassburg school. We opened M. Renan's book with sympathetic interest; we closed it with deep disappointment.”119

In general, however, the rising French school of critical theology was disappointed in Renan. Their spokesperson was Colani. "This isn’t the Christ from history, the Christ of the Synoptics," he writes in 1864 in the Theology Review, “but the Christ of the Fourth Gospel, although lacking His metaphysical halo, is portrayed with a brush dipped in the melancholy blue of contemporary poetry, the rose of the eighteenth-century ideal, and the grey of a moral philosophy that appears to originate from La Rochefoucauld.” "Sharing this opinion," he adds, "I believe I'm speaking for those in the new Protestant theology, or the Strassburg school. We started reading M. Renan's book with an open mind; we finished it feeling very disappointed."119

The Strassburg school had good cause to complain of Renan, for he had trampled their growing crops. They had just begun to arouse some interest, and slowly and surely to exercise an influence upon the whole spiritual life of France. Sainte-Beuve had called attention to the work of Reuss, Colani, Réville, and Scherer. [pg 190] Others of the school were Michel Nicolas of Montauban and Gustave d'Eichthal. Nefftzer, the editor of the Temps, who was at the same time a prophet of coming political events, defended their cause in the Parisian literary world. The Revue germanique of that period, the influence of which upon French literature can hardly be over-estimated, was their sworn ally. Then came Renan and threw public opinion into a ferment of excitement. Everything in the nature of criticism, and of progress in religious thought, was associated with his name, and was thereby discredited. By his untimely and over-easy popularisation of the ideas of the critical school he ruined their quiet work. The excitement roused by his book swept away all that had been done by those noble and lofty spirits, who now found themselves involved in a struggle with the outraged orthodoxy of Paris, and were hard put to it to defend themselves. Even down to the present day Renan's work forms the greatest hindrance to any serious advance in French religious thought.

The Strassburg school had good reason to be upset with Renan because he disrupted their progress. They were just starting to gain some attention and gradually having an impact on the entire spiritual life of France. Sainte-Beuve had highlighted the contributions of Reuss, Colani, Réville, and Scherer. [pg 190] Other members of the school included Michel Nicolas of Montauban and Gustave d'Eichthal. Nefftzer, the editor of the Temp workers, also a visionary for upcoming political events, advocated for them in the Paris literary scene. The German Review of that time, which had an immense influence on French literature, was their committed ally. Then Renan came along and stirred public opinion into a frenzy. Everything relating to criticism and advancements in religious thought became associated with his name, and as a result, it was discredited. His premature and overly simplistic popularization of critical school ideas undermined their steady progress. The excitement his book generated overshadowed all the work done by those noble and elevated thinkers, who suddenly found themselves battling the outraged orthodoxy of Paris and struggling to defend their positions. Even today, Renan's work remains the biggest obstacle to any genuine progress in French religious thought.

The excitement aroused upon the other side of the Rhine was scarcely less than in Paris. Within a year there appeared five different German translations, and many of the French criticisms of Renan were also translated.120 The German Catholic press was wildly excited;121 the Protestant press was more restrained, more inclined to give the author a fair hearing, and even ventured to express admiration of the historical merits of his performance. Beyschlag122 saw in Renan an advance upon Strauss, inasmuch as for him the life of Jesus as narrated in the Gospels, while not, indeed, in any sense supernatural, is nevertheless historical. For a certain school of theology, therefore, Renan was a deliverer from Strauss; they were especially grateful to him for his defence, sophistical though it was, of the Fourth Gospel. Weizsäcker expressed his admiration. Strauss, far from directing his “Life of Jesus for the German People,” with which he was then occupied, [pg 191] against the superficial and frivolous French treatment of the subject—as has sometimes been alleged—hailed Renan in his preface as a kindred spirit and ally, and “shook hands with him across the Rhine.” Luthardt,123 however, remained inexorable. “What is there lacking in Renan's work?” he asks. And he replies, “It lacks conscience.”

The excitement on the other side of the Rhine was almost as strong as in Paris. Within a year, five different German translations appeared, and many of the French critiques of Renan were also translated. The German Catholic press was extremely enthusiastic; the Protestant press was more reserved, more willing to give the author a fair hearing, and even dared to admire the historical value of his work. Beyschlag saw Renan as an improvement over Strauss because, for him, the life of Jesus as told in the Gospels, while not in any way supernatural, is nonetheless historical. For a certain group of theologians, Renan was their savior from Strauss; they were particularly thankful to him for his defense, although it was somewhat flawed, of the Fourth Gospel. Weizsäcker expressed his admiration. Strauss, far from steering his “Life of Jesus for the German People,” with which he was then busy, against the shallow and trivial French approach to the subject—as has sometimes been claimed—actually welcomed Renan in his preface as a kindred spirit and ally, and “shook hands with him across the Rhine.” Luthardt, however, remained unyielding. “What is lacking in Renan's work?” he asks. And he answers, “It lacks conscience.”

That is a just judgment. From this lack of conscience, Renan has not been scrupulous where he ought to have been so. There is a kind of insincerity in the book from beginning to end. Renan professes to depict the Christ of the Fourth Gospel, though he does not believe in the authenticity or the miracles of that Gospel. He professes to write a scientific work, and is always thinking of the great public and how to interest it. He has thus fused together two works of disparate character. The historian finds it hard to forgive him for not going more deeply into the problem of the development in the thought of Jesus, with which he was brought face to face by the emphasis which he laid on eschatology, and for offering in place of a solution the highly-coloured phrases of the novelist.

That is a fair judgment. Due to this lack of conscience, Renan hasn’t been as careful as he should have been. There’s a kind of insincerity in the book from start to finish. Renan claims to portray the Christ of the Fourth Gospel, even though he doesn’t believe in the authenticity or the miracles of that Gospel. He says he’s writing a scientific work, while constantly thinking about the general public and how to engage them. As a result, he has mixed together two very different kinds of works. The historian finds it difficult to forgive him for not diving deeper into the issue of Jesus's evolving thoughts, which he was forced to confront because of the emphasis he placed on eschatology, and for presenting instead the overly dramatic phrases of a novelist.

Nevertheless, this work will always retain a certain interest, both for Frenchmen and for Germans. The German is often so completely fascinated by it as to lose his power of criticism, because he finds in it German thought in a novel and piquant form. Conversely the Frenchman discovers in it, behind the familiar form, which is here handled in such a masterly fashion, ideas belonging to a world which is foreign to him, ideas which he can never completely assimilate, but which yet continually attract him. In this double character of the work lies its imperishable charm.

Nonetheless, this work will always hold a certain appeal for both French and German audiences. Germans often become so captivated by it that they lose their critical perspective, as they see German ideas presented in a fresh and engaging way. On the other hand, the French reader finds behind the familiar structure—skillfully crafted here—concepts from a world that feels foreign to them, ideas they can never fully grasp, yet are endlessly drawn to. The dual nature of this work is what gives it lasting charm.

[pg 192]

And its weakness? That it is written by one to whom the New Testament was to the last something foreign, who had not read it from his youth up in the mother-tongue, who was not accustomed to breathe freely in its simple and pure world, but must perfume it with sentimentality in order to feel himself at home in it.

And its weakness? That it is written by someone for whom the New Testament always felt a bit foreign, who hadn't read it in their native language since childhood, who wasn’t used to freely engaging with its straightforward and pure world, but had to add sentimentality to feel comfortable in it.

[pg 193]

XIV. The “Liberal” Jesus' Life

David Friedrich Strauss. Das Leben Jesu für das deutsche Volk bearbeitet. (A Life of Jesus for the German People.) Leipzig, 1864. 631 pp.

David Friedrich Strauss. A Life of Jesus for the German People. Leipzig, 1864. 631 pages.

Der Christus des Glaubens und der Jesus der Geschichte. Eine Kritik des Schleiermacher'schen Lebens Jesu. (The Christ of Faith and the Jesus of History, a Criticism of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus.) Berlin, 1865. 223 pp. Appendix, pp. 224-240.

The Christ of Faith and the Jesus of History: A Critique of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus. Berlin, 1865. 223 pages. Appendix, pages 224-240.

Der Schenkel'sche Handel in Baden. (The Schenkel Affair in Baden.) A corrected reprint from No. 441 of the National-Zeitung, of the 21st September 1864.

The Schenkel Affair in Baden. A revised reprint from No. 441 of the __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__. National Newspaper, dated September 21, 1864.

Die Halben und die Ganzen. (The Half-way-ers and the Whole-way-ers.) 1865.

The Half-way-ers and the Whole-way-ers. 1865.

Daniel Schenkel. Das Charakterbild Jesu. (The Portrait of Jesus.) Wiesbaden, 1864 (ed. 1 and 2). 405 pp. Fourth edition, with a preface opposing Strauss's Der alte und der neue Glaube (The Old Faith and the New), 1873.

Daniel Schenkel. The Character Portrait of Jesus. Wiesbaden, 1864 (1st and 2nd editions). 405 pages. Fourth edition, with a preface critiquing Strauss's The Old and the New Faith (The Old Faith and the New), 1873.

Karl Heinrich Weizsäcker. Untersuchungen über die evangelische Geschichte, ihre Quellen und den Gang ihrer Entwicklung. (Studies in the Gospel History, its Sources and the Progress of its Development.) Gotha, 1864. 580 pp.

Karl Heinrich Weizsäcker. Studies in Gospel History, Its Sources, and the Progress of Its Development. Gotha, 1864. 580 pages.

Heinrich Julius Holtzmann. Die synoptischen Evangelien. Ihr Ursprung und geschichtlicher Charakter. (The Synoptic Gospels. Their Origin and Historical Character.) Leipzig, 1863. 514 pp.

Heinrich Julius Holtzmann. The Synoptic Gospels: Their Origin and Historical Character. Leipzig, 1863. 514 pages.

Theodor Keim. Die Geschichte Jesu von Nazara. (The History of Jesus of Nazara.) 3 vols., Zurich; vol. i., 1867, 446 pp.; vol. ii., 1871, 616 pp.; vol. iii., 1872, 667 pp.

Theodor Keim. The History of Jesus of Nazareth. (Die Geschichte Jesu von Nazara.) 3 volumes, Zurich; volume 1, 1867, 446 pages; volume 2, 1871, 616 pages; volume 3, 1872, 667 pages.

Die Geschichte Jesu. Zurich, 1872. 398 pp.

The Story of Jesus. Zurich, 1872. 398 pages.

Karl Hase. Geschichte Jesu. Nach akademischen Vorlesungen. (The History of Jesus. Academic Lectures, revised.) Leipzig, 1876. 612 pp.

Karl Hase. The History of Jesus. Derived from Academic Lectures. (Revised Edition.) Leipzig, 1876. 612 pages.

Willibald Beyschlag. Das Leben Jesu. First Part: Preliminary Investigations, 1885, 450 pp. Second Part: Narrative, 1886, 495 pp.; 2nd ed., 1887-1888.

Willibald Beyschlag. The Life of Jesus. First Part: Introductory Studies, 1885, 450 pages. Second Part: Story, 1886, 495 pages; 2nd edition, 1887-1888.

Bernhard Weiss. Das Leben Jesu. 1st ed., 2 vols., 1882; 2nd ed., 1884. First vol., down to the Baptist's question, 556 pp. Second vol., 617 pp.

Bernhard Weiss. The Life of Jesus. 1st edition, 2 volumes, 1882; 2nd edition, 1884. First volume, up to the question from the Baptist, 556 pages. Second volume, 617 pages.

“My hope is,” writes Strauss in concluding the preface of his new Life of Jesus, “that I have written a book as thoroughly well adapted for Germans as Renan's is for Frenchmen.” He was mistaken; in spite of its title the book was not a book for the people. It had nothing new to offer, and what it did offer was not in a form calculated to become popular. It is true Strauss, like Renan, was an artist, but he did not write, like an imaginative novelist, with a constant eye to effect. His art was unpretentious, [pg 194] even austere, appealing to the few, not to the many. The people demand a complete and vivid picture. Renan had given them a figure which was theatrical no doubt, but full of life and movement, and they had been grateful to him for it. Strauss could not do that.

“I hope,” writes Strauss in concluding the preface of his new Life of Jesus, "that I have written a book that is just as well suited for Germans as Renan's is for French people." He was wrong; despite its title, the book wasn’t meant for the general public. It didn’t offer anything new, and what it did offer wasn’t presented in a way that would resonate with a wide audience. While it’s true that Strauss, like Renan, was an artist, he didn’t write with the flair of a creative novelist focused on impact. His style was unpretentious, [pg 194] even stark, appealing to a select few rather than the masses. The public wants a complete and lively portrayal. Renan gave them a depiction that, while theatrical, was full of life and movement, and they appreciated him for it. Strauss couldn’t deliver that.

Even the arrangement of the work is thoroughly unfortunate. In the first part, which bears the title “The Life of Jesus,” he attempts to combine into a harmonious portrait such of the historical data as have some claim to be considered historical; in the second part he traces the “Origin and Growth of the Mythical History of Jesus.” First, therefore, he tears down from the tree the ivy and the rich growth of creepers, laying bare the worn and corroded bark; then he fastens the faded growths to the stem again, and describes the nature, origin, and characteristics of each distinct species.

Even the layout of the work is quite unfortunate. In the first part, titled “Jesus' Life,” he tries to blend together the historical data that can reasonably be seen as historical; in the second part, he explores the "Origin and Development of the Mythical History of Jesus." First, he tears away the ivy and the dense growth of vines, exposing the worn and damaged bark; then he reattaches the faded growths to the trunk and describes the nature, origin, and characteristics of each distinct type.

How vastly different, how much more full of life, had been the work of 1835! There Strauss had not divided the creepers from the stem. The straining strength which upheld this wealth of creepers was but vaguely suspected. Behind the billowy mists of legend we caught from time to time a momentary glimpse of the gigantic figure of Jesus, as though lit up by a lightning-flash. It was no complete and harmonious picture, but it was full of suggestions, rich in thoughts thrown out carelessly, rich in contradictions even, out of which the imagination could create a portrait of Jesus. It is just this wealth of suggestion that is lacking in the second picture. Strauss is trying now to give a definite portrait. In the inevitable process of harmonising and modelling to scale he is obliged to reject the finest thoughts of the previous work because they will not fit in exactly; some of them are altered out of recognition, some are filed away.

How vastly different, how much more vibrant, was the work from 1835! There, Strauss didn’t separate the creepers from the stem. The powerful force that supported this abundance of creepers was only vaguely hinted at. Behind the swirling mists of legend, we occasionally caught a fleeting glimpse of the massive figure of Jesus, almost illuminated by a flash of lightning. It wasn’t a complete and harmonious image, but it brimmed with suggestions, rich in thoughts tossed out casually, even full of contradictions, from which the imagination could shape a portrait of Jesus. It's exactly this richness of suggestion that's missing in the second image. Strauss is now trying to create a clear portrait. In the unavoidable process of harmonizing and scaling down, he has to discard the finest ideas from the earlier work because they don’t fit perfectly; some of them are changed beyond recognition, and others are set aside.

There is wanting, too, that perfect freshness as of the spring which is only found when thoughts have but newly come into flower. The writing is no longer spontaneous; one feels that Strauss is setting forth thoughts which have ripened with his mind and grown old with it, and now along with their definiteness of form have taken on a certain stiffness. There are now no hinted possibilities, full of promise, to dance gaily through the movement of his dialectic; all is sober reason—a thought too sober. Renan had one advantage over Strauss in that he wrote when the material was fresh to him—one might almost say strange to him—and was capable of calling up in him the response of vivid feeling.

There’s a lack of that perfect freshness of spring that only comes when ideas are just starting to bloom. The writing no longer feels spontaneous; it’s clear that Strauss presents ideas that have matured in his mind and aged with him, which gives them a certain rigidity along with their clarity. There are no longer any hinted possibilities, bursting with potential, to enliven his arguments; everything is just sober reasoning—a thought that's too serious. Renan had an edge over Strauss because he wrote when the material still felt fresh, almost unfamiliar to him, which allowed him to evoke a lively emotional response.

For a popular book, too, it lacks that living interplay of reflection with narration without which the ordinary reader fails to get a grip of the history. The first Life of Jesus had been rich in this respect, since it had been steeped in the Hegelian theory regarding the realisation of the Idea. In the meantime Strauss [pg 195] had seen the Hegelian philosophy fall from its high estate, and himself had found no way of reconciling history and idea, so that his present Life of Jesus was a mere objective presentment of the history. It was, therefore, not adapted to make any impression upon the popular mind.

For a popular book, it also lacks that engaging interaction between reflection and narration that ordinary readers need to really understand the history. The first Life of Jesus was rich in this regard because it was deeply influenced by Hegel's theory about the realization of the Idea. Meanwhile, Strauss [pg 195] had watched Hegelian philosophy lose its prominence and had not found a way to reconcile history with idea, so his current Life of Jesus was simply a straightforward presentation of the history. Because of this, it didn’t resonate with the general public.

In reality it is merely an exposition, in more or less popular form, of the writer's estimate of what had been done in the study of the subject during the past thirty years, and shows what he had learnt and what he had failed to learn.

In reality, it's just an explanation, presented in a relatively accessible way, of the writer's view on what has been accomplished in the study of the topic over the past thirty years, and it reflects what he has learned and what he hasn't.

As regards the Synoptic question he had learnt nothing. In his opinion the criticism of the Gospels has “run to seed.” He treats with a pitying contempt both the earlier and the more recent defenders of the Marcan hypothesis. Weisse is a dilettante; Wilke had failed to make any impression on him; Holtzmann's work was as yet unknown to him. But in the following year he discharged the vials of his wrath upon the man who had both strengthened the foundations and put on the coping-stone of the new hypothesis. “Our lions of St. Mark, older and younger,” he says in the appendix to his criticism of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus, “may roar as loud as they like, so long as there are six solid reasons against the priority of Mark to set against every one of their flimsy arguments in its favour—and they themselves supply us with a store of counter-arguments in the shape of admissions of later editing and so forth. The whole theory appears to me a temporary aberration, like the 'music of the future' or the anti-vaccination movement; and I seriously believe that it is the same order of mind which, in different circumstances, falls a victim to the one delusion or the other.” But he must not be supposed, he says, to take the critical mole-hills thrown up by Holtzmann for veritable mountains.

As for the Synoptic question, he hadn’t learned anything new. He believed that the criticism of the Gospels had “run to seed.” He viewed both the early and recent supporters of the Marcan hypothesis with a mixture of pity and contempt. Weisse was just a hobbyist; Wilke hadn't made any impact on him; Holtzmann's work was still unfamiliar to him. However, the following year he unleashed his anger on the person who had both reinforced the foundations and added the finishing touch to the new hypothesis. “Our lions of St. Mark, older and younger,” he states in the appendix to his critique of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus, “may roar as loud as they want, as long as there are six solid reasons against the priority of Mark to counter every one of their weak arguments in its favor—and they themselves provide us with a host of counter-arguments in the form of admissions of later editing and so on. The whole theory seems to me a temporary deviation, like the 'music of the future' or the anti-vaccination movement; and I seriously believe that it's the same kind of mindset that, in different circumstances, can fall prey to one delusion or the other.” But he insists that he should not be thought to confuse the critical molehills created by Holtzmann for real mountains.

Against such opponents he does not scruple to seek aid from Schleiermacher, whose unbiased but decided opinion had ascribed a tertiary character to Mark. Even Gfrörer's view that Mark adapted his Gospel to the needs of the Church by leaving out everything which was open to objection in Matthew and Luke, is good enough to be brought to bear against the bat-eyed partisans of Mark. F. C. Baur is reproached for having given too much weight to the “tendency” theory in his criticism of the Gospels; and also for having taken suggestions of Strauss's and worked them out, supposing that he was offering something new when he was really only amplifying. In the end he had only given a criticism of the Gospels, not of the Gospel history.

Against such opponents, he doesn't hesitate to seek help from Schleiermacher, whose unbiased yet firm opinion considered Mark to be of lesser importance. Even Gfrörer's belief that Mark modified his Gospel to fit the Church's needs by excluding anything that could be criticized in Matthew and Luke is relevant enough to argue against the biased supporters of Mark. F. C. Baur is criticized for placing too much importance on the “tendency” theory in his analysis of the Gospels and for taking ideas from Strauss and expanding them, thinking he was presenting something new when he was really just elaborating on existing concepts. In the end, he provided only an analysis of the Gospels, not of the actual events of Gospel history.

But this irritation against his old teacher is immediately allayed when he comes to speak of the Fourth Gospel. Here the teacher has carried to a successful issue the campaign which the pupil had begun. Strauss feels compelled to “express his gratitude for the work done by the Tübingen school on the Johannine question.” [pg 196] He himself had only been able to deal with the negative side of the question—to show that the Fourth Gospel was not an historical source, but a theological invention; they had dealt with it positively, and had assigned the document to its proper place in the evolution of Christian thought. There is only one point with which he quarrels. Baur had made the Fourth Gospel too completely spiritual, “whereas the fact is,” says Strauss, “that it is the most material of all.” It is true, Strauss explains, that the Evangelist starts out to interpret miracle and eschatology symbolically; but he halts half-way and falls back upon the miraculous, enhancing the professed fact in proportion as he makes it spiritually more significant. Beside the spiritual return of Jesus in the Paraclete he places His return in a material body, bearing the marks of the wounds; beside the inward present judgment, a future outward judgment; and the fact that he sees the one in the other, finds the one present and visible in the other, is just what constitutes the mystical character of his Gospel. This mysticism attracts the modern world. “The Johannine Christ, who in His descriptions of Himself seems to be always out-doing Himself, is the counterpart of the modern believer, who in order to remain a believer must continually out-do himself; the Johannine miracles which are always being interpreted spiritually, and at the same time raised to a higher pitch of the miraculous, which are counted and documented in every possible way, and yet must not be considered the true ground of faith, are at once miracles and no miracles. We must believe them, and yet can believe without them; in short they exactly meet the taste of the present day, which delights to involve itself in contradictions and is too lethargic and wanting in courage for any clear insight or decided opinion on religious matters.”

But this irritation with his former teacher quickly fades when he discusses the Fourth Gospel. In this case, the teacher has successfully completed the work that the student had started. Strauss feels the need to "express his thanks for the work done by the Tübingen school on the Johannine question." [pg 196] He himself had only been able to address the negative aspect of the issue—showing that the Fourth Gospel was not a historical source, but a theological construct; they, however, approached it positively and positioned the document correctly within the development of Christian thought. There is only one point he disagrees with. Baur made the Fourth Gospel too entirely spiritual, "the reality is," says Strauss, "that it's the most important of all." It’s true, Strauss explains, that the Evangelist begins with a symbolic interpretation of miracle and eschatology; however, he stops halfway and reverts to the miraculous, amplifying the stated fact as he makes it spiritually more significant. Alongside the spiritual return of Jesus in the Paraclete, he includes His return in a physical body, with the marks of the wounds; alongside the inner present judgment, there is a future external judgment; and the way he perceives one in the other, seeing the one present and visible in the other, is precisely what gives his Gospel its mystical character. This mysticism appeals to the modern world. The Johannine Christ, who in His descriptions always seems to go beyond Himself, reflects the modern believer, who must constantly push beyond their limits to maintain their faith. The Johannine miracles, often interpreted spiritually while also being seen as higher forms of the miraculous, are counted and validated in every possible way. However, they should not be viewed as the true foundation of faith; they are both miracles and not miracles at the same time. We must believe in them, yet we can also have faith without them. In short, they align perfectly with the preferences of today’s society, which thrives on contradictions and lacks the energy and courage for clear understanding or firm positions on religious issues.

Strictly speaking, however, the Strauss of the second Life of Jesus has no right to criticise the Fourth Gospel for sublimating the history, for he himself gives what is nothing else than a spiritualisation of the Jesus of the Synoptics. And he does it in such an arbitrary fashion that one is compelled to ask how far he does it with a good conscience. A typical case is the exposition of Jesus' answer to the Baptist's message. “Is it possible,” Jesus means, “that you fail to find in Me the miracles which you expect from the Messiah? And yet I daily open the eyes of the spiritually blind and the ears of the spiritually deaf, make the lame walk erect and vigorous, and even give new life to those who are morally dead. Any one who understands how much greater these spiritual miracles are, will not be offended at the absence of bodily miracles; only such an one can receive, and is worthy of, the salvation which I am bringing to mankind.”

Strictly speaking, however, the Strauss from the second Life of Jesus has no right to criticize the Fourth Gospel for elevating history, because he himself presents nothing more than a spiritualized version of the Jesus from the Synoptics. He does this in such a random way that it makes you wonder how he can do it with a clear conscience. A prime example is his interpretation of Jesus' response to the Baptist's message. "Is it possible?" Jesus implies, "Do you not see in Me the miracles you expect from the Messiah? Yet I open the eyes of the spiritually blind and the ears of the spiritually deaf every day, help the lame walk energetically, and even give new life to those who are morally dead. Anyone who realizes how much more significant these spiritual miracles are won’t be bothered by the absence of physical miracles; only that person can receive and is worthy of the salvation I offer to humanity."

Here the fundamental weakness of his method is clearly shown. [pg 197] The vaunted apparatus for the evaporation of the mythical does not work quite satisfactorily. The ultimate product of this process was expected to be a Jesus who should be essential man; the actual product, however, is Jesus the historical man, a being whose looks and sayings are strange and unfamiliar. Strauss is too purely a critic, too little of the creative historian, to recognise this strange being. That Jesus really lived in a world of Jewish ideas and held Himself to be Messiah in the Jewish sense is for the writer of the Life of Jesus an impossibility. The deposit which resists the chemical process for the elimination of myth, he must therefore break up with the hammer.

Here the fundamental weakness of his method is clearly shown. [pg 197] The praised apparatus for getting rid of the mythical doesn’t work quite right. The expected outcome of this process was a Jesus who would be the essential man; however, the actual product is Jesus the historical figure, a person whose appearance and words are strange and unfamiliar. Strauss is too much of a critic and not enough of a creative historian to recognize this unusual figure. The idea that Jesus actually lived in a world of Jewish thought and saw Himself as the Messiah in a Jewish context is something the writer of the Life of Jesus finds impossible. Therefore, he must break apart the material that resists the process of removing the myth with a hammer.

How different from the Strauss of 1835! He had then recognised eschatology as the most important element in Jesus' world of thought, and in some incidental remarks had made striking applications of it. He had, for example, proposed to regard the Last Supper not as the institution of a feast for coming generations, but as a Paschal meal, at which Jesus declared that He would next partake of the Paschal bread and Paschal wine along with His disciples in the heavenly kingdom. In the second Life of Jesus this view is given up; Jesus did found a feast. “In order to give a living centre of unity to the society which it was His purpose to found, Jesus desired to institute this distribution of bread and wine as a feast to be constantly repeated.” One might be reading Renan. This change of attitude is typical of much else.

How different from the Strauss of 1835! Back then, he recognized eschatology as the most important aspect of Jesus' way of thinking and made some bold applications of it in his remarks. For instance, he suggested viewing the Last Supper not as a celebration meant for future generations, but as a Passover meal, where Jesus declared that he would next share the Passover bread and wine with his disciples in the heavenly kingdom. In the second Life of Jesus, this perspective changed; Jesus did establish a feast. "To create a living center of unity for the society he aimed to establish, Jesus wanted to set up this distribution of bread and wine as a feast to be regularly repeated." One might as well be reading Renan. This change in perspective is indicative of much else.

Strauss is not in the least disquieted by finding himself at one with Schleiermacher in these attempts to spiritualise. On the contrary, he appeals to him. He shares, he says, Schleiermacher's conviction “that the unique self-consciousness of Jesus did not develop as a consequence of His conviction that He was the Messiah; on the contrary, it was a consequence of His self-consciousness that He arrived at the view that the Messianic prophecies could point to no one but Himself.” The moment eschatology entered into the consciousness of Jesus it came in contact with a higher principle which over-mastered it and gradually dissolved it. “Had Jesus applied the Messianic idea to Himself before He had had a profound religious consciousness to which to relate it, doubtless it would have taken possession of Him so powerfully that He could never have escaped from its influence.” We must suppose the ideality, the concentration upon that which was inward, the determination to separate religion, on the one hand, from politics, and on the other, from ritual, the serene consciousness of being able to attain to peace with God and with Himself by purely spiritual means—all this we must suppose to have reached a certain ripeness, a certain security, in the mind of Jesus, before He permitted Himself to entertain the thought of His Messiahship, and this we may believe is the reason why He grasped [pg 198] it in so independent and individual a fashion. In this, therefore, Strauss has become the pupil of Weisse.

Strauss is not at all troubled by aligning himself with Schleiermacher in these efforts to spiritualize things. In fact, he refers to him. He agrees with Schleiermacher’s belief that “the unique self-consciousness of Jesus did not develop because He believed He was the Messiah; rather, it was due to His self-awareness that He came to see the Messianic prophecies could only point to Himself.” The moment eschatology entered Jesus' consciousness, it encountered a higher principle that dominated it and gradually unraveled it. “If Jesus had applied the Messianic idea to Himself before he had a deep religious consciousness to relate it to, it would have undoubtedly overwhelmed Him to the point where He could never escape its influence.” We must assume that the idealism, the focus on inner experiences, the decision to separate religion from politics and from ritual, and the calm realization of being able to find peace with God and Himself through purely spiritual means—all of this must have matured and secured itself in Jesus's mind before he allowed himself to consider the notion of His Messiahship. This, we believe, explains why he approached it in such an independent and unique way. In this regard, Strauss has become a student of Weisse.

Even in the Old Testament prophecies, he explains, we find two conceptions, a more ideal and a more practical. Jesus holds consistently to the first, He describes Himself as the Son of Man because this designation “contains the suggestion of humility and lowliness, of the human and natural.” At Jerusalem, Jesus, in giving His interpretation of Psalm cx., “made merry over the Davidic descent of the Messiah.” He desired “to be Messiah in the sense of a patient teacher exercising a quiet influence.” As the opposition of the people grew more intense, He took up some of the features of Isaiah liii. into His conception of the Messiah.

Even in the Old Testament prophecies, he explains, we find two ideas: a more ideal one and a more practical one. Jesus consistently embraces the first. He describes Himself as the Son of Man because this title "implies humility and being lowly, both in a human and natural sense." In Jerusalem, Jesus, while interpreting Psalm cx., “downplayed the Davidic lineage of the Messiah.” He wanted "to be the Messiah as a patient teacher who has a subtle impact." As the people's opposition grew stronger, He incorporated some aspects of Isaiah liii. into His understanding of the Messiah.

Of His resurrection, Jesus can only have spoken in a metaphorical sense. It is hardly credible that one who was pure man could have arrogated to himself the position of judge of the world. Strauss would like best to ascribe all the eschatology to the distorting medium of early Christianity, but he does not venture to carry this through with logical consistency. He takes it as certain, however, that Jesus, even though it sometimes seems as if He did not expect the Kingdom to be realised in the present, but in a future, world-era, and to be brought about by God in a supernatural fashion, nevertheless sets about the establishment of the Kingdom by purely spiritual influence.

Of His resurrection, Jesus must have spoken in a metaphorical way. It's hard to believe that someone who was just a man could claim the role of judge of the world. Strauss would prefer to attribute all the ideas about the end times to the twisted perspective of early Christianity, but he doesn’t fully commit to this idea with logical consistency. He does, however, take it as certain that Jesus, even if it sometimes seems like He didn’t expect the Kingdom to come into being in the present but rather in a future era, brought about by God in a supernatural way, still aimed to establish the Kingdom through purely spiritual influence.

With this end in view He leaves Galilee, when He judges the time to be ripe, in order to work on a larger scale. “In case of an unfavourable issue, He reckons on the influence which a martyr-death has never failed to exercise in giving momentum to a lofty idea.” How far He had advanced, when He entered on the fateful journey to Jerusalem, in shaping His plan, and especially in organising the company of adherents who had gathered about Him, it is impossible to determine with any exactness. He permitted the triumphal entry because He did not desire to decline the role of the Messiah in every aspect of it.

With this goal in mind, He leaves Galilee when He feels the time is right to expand His work. “If things don’t go well, He relies on the influence that a martyr's death has always had in advancing a noble cause.” It's hard to determine just how far He had progressed in crafting His plan, especially in organizing the group of followers who had gathered around Him, when He set out on the crucial journey to Jerusalem. He allowed the triumphal entry because He didn't want to shy away from embracing the full role of the Messiah.

Owing to this arbitrary spiritualisation of the Synoptic Jesus, Strauss's picture is in essence much more unhistorical than Renan's. The latter had not needed to deny that Jesus had done miracles, and he had been able to suggest an explanation of how Jesus came in the end to fall back upon the eschatological system of ideas. But at what a price! By portraying Jesus as at variance with Himself, a hero broken in spirit. This price is too high for Strauss. Arbitrary as his treatment of history is, he never loses the intuitive feeling that in Jesus' self-consciousness there is a unique absence of struggle; that He does not bear the scars which are found in those natures which win their way to freedom and purity through strife and conflict, that in Him there is no trace of the hardness, harshness, and gloom which cleave to such natures [pg 199] throughout life, but that He “is manifestly a beautiful nature from the first.” Thus, for all Strauss's awkward, arbitrary handling of the history he is greater than the rival124 who could manufacture history with such skill.

Due to this random spiritualization of the Synoptic Jesus, Strauss's portrayal is fundamentally much less historical than Renan's. The latter didn't have to deny that Jesus performed miracles and was able to propose an explanation for why Jesus ultimately resorted to an eschatological system of ideas. But it came at a cost! By depicting Jesus as being at odds with Himself, a hero broken in spirit. This cost is too steep for Strauss. Despite his arbitrary approach to history, he always maintains the intuitive sense that in Jesus' self-awareness, there is a unique lack of struggle; He doesn't bear the scars found in those who achieve freedom and purity through struggle and conflict. In him, there is no sign of the hardness, severity, and gloom that cling to such individuals throughout life, but rather He "is manifestly a beautiful nature from the first.” Therefore, despite Strauss's clumsy and arbitrary handling of history, he is greater than the competitor who could skillfully fabricate history. [pg 199]

Nevertheless, from the point of view of theological science, this work marks a standstill. That was the net result of the thirty years of critical study of the life of Jesus for the man who had inaugurated it so impressively. This was the only fruit which followed those blossoms so full of promise of the first Life of Jesus.

Nevertheless, from the perspective of theological study, this work represents a halt. That was the end result of thirty years of critical examination of Jesus' life for the man who had started it so noticeably. This was the only outcome that came from the hopeful beginnings of the first Life of Jesus.

It is significant that in the same year there appeared Schleiermacher's lectures on the Life of Jesus, which had not seen the light for forty years, because, as Strauss himself remarked in his criticism of the resurrected work, it had neither anodyne nor dressing for the wounds which his first Life of Jesus had made.125 The wounds, however, had cicatrised in the meantime. It is true Strauss is a just judge, and makes ample acknowledgment of the greatness of Schleiermacher's achievement.126 He blames Schleiermacher for setting up his “presuppositions in regard to Christ” as an historical canon, and considering it a proof that a statement is unhistorical if it does not square with those presuppositions. But does not the purely human, but to a certain extent unhistorical, man, who is to be the ultimate product of the process of eliminating myth, serve Strauss as his “theoretic Christ” who determines the presentment of his historical Jesus? Does he not share with Schleiermacher the erroneous, artificial, “double” construction of the consciousness of Jesus? And what about their views of Mark? What fundamental difference is there, when all is said, between Schleiermacher's de-rationalised Life of Jesus and Strauss's? Certainly this second Life of Jesus would not have frightened Schleiermacher's away into hiding for thirty years.

It’s important to note that in the same year, Schleiermacher's lectures on the Life of Jesus were published for the first time in forty years. This is significant because, as Strauss pointed out in his critique of the revived work, it didn’t offer any relief or remedy for the issues caused by his first Life of Jesus. The wounds, however, had healed in the meantime. Strauss is a fair judge and acknowledges the significance of Schleiermacher's work. He criticizes Schleiermacher for establishing his “presuppositions regarding Christ” as a historical standard and for treating it as evidence that a statement is unhistorical if it doesn’t align with those presuppositions. But doesn’t the purely human, yet somewhat unhistorical figure who is meant to be the final outcome of the myth-elimination process serve as Strauss's “theoretic Christ,” determining how he presents his historical Jesus? Doesn’t he also share with Schleiermacher the flawed, artificial “double” view of Jesus's consciousness? And what about their perspectives on Mark? What real difference is there, when all is considered, between Schleiermacher's de-rationalized Life of Jesus and Strauss's? Certainly, this second Life of Jesus wouldn’t have made Schleiermacher feel like hiding for thirty years.

So Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus might now safely venture [pg 200] forth into the light. There was no reason why it should feel itself a stranger at this period, and it had no need to be ashamed of itself. Its rationalistic birth-marks were concealed by its brilliant dialectic.127 And the only real advance in the meantime was the general recognition that the Life of Jesus was not to be interpreted on rationalistic, but on historical lines. All other, more definite, historical results had proved more or less illusory; there is no vitality in them. The works of Renan, Strauss, Schenkel, Weizsäcker, and Keim are in essence only different ways of carrying out a single ground-plan. To read them one after another is to be simply appalled at the stereotyped uniformity of the world of thought in which they move. You feel that you have read exactly the same thing in the others, almost in identical phrases. To obtain the works of Schenkel and Weizsäcker you only need to weaken down in Strauss the sharp discrimination between John and the Synoptists so far as to allow of the Fourth Gospel being used to some extent as an historical source “in the higher sense,” and to put the hypothesis of the priority of Mark in place of the Tübingen view adopted by Strauss. The latter is an external operation and does not essentially modify the view of the Life of Jesus, since by admitting the Johannine scheme the Marcan plan is again disturbed, and Strauss's arbitrary spiritualisation of the Synoptics comes to something not very different from the acceptance of that “in a higher sense historical Gospel” alongside of them. The whole discussion regarding the sources is only loosely connected with the process of arriving at the portrait of Jesus, since this portrait is fixed from the first, being determined by the mental atmosphere and religious horizon of the 'sixties. They all portray the Jesus of liberal theology; the only difference is that one is a little more conscientious in his colouring than another, and one perhaps has a little more taste than another, or is less concerned about the consequences.

So Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus can now confidently step into the spotlight. There’s no reason for it to feel out of place at this time, and it shouldn’t feel ashamed of itself. Its rationalistic origins are hidden by its impressive arguments. And the only real progress in the meantime has been the widespread agreement that the Life of Jesus should be understood historically, rather than rationalistically. All other, more specific historical results have turned out to be somewhat illusory; they lack vitality. The works of Renan, Strauss, Schenkel, Weizsäcker, and Keim are essentially just different interpretations of the same foundational idea. Reading them one after the other leaves you shocked by the repetitive uniformity of thought they share. You realize you’ve encountered nearly identical phrases in the others. To access the works of Schenkel and Weizsäcker, you just need to soften Strauss's sharp distinction between John and the Synoptics enough to accept the Fourth Gospel as a historical source “in the higher sense,” and replace the Tübingen theory adopted by Strauss with the idea that Mark has priority. This is an external adjustment and doesn’t fundamentally change the view of the Life of Jesus, since by accepting the Johannine framework, the Marcan outline is disrupted again, and Strauss's arbitrary spiritual interpretation of the Synoptics ends up being not much different from accepting that “in a higher sense historical Gospel” alongside them. The entire debate about the sources is only loosely related to shaping the portrait of Jesus, as this portrait is established from the beginning, shaped by the intellectual climate and religious outlook of the sixties. They all depict the Jesus of liberal theology; the only difference is that one might be a bit more careful in his shading than another, and one might show a bit more flair than another, or be less concerned about the implications.

The desire to escape in some way from the alternative between the Synoptists and John was native to the Marcan hypothesis. Weisse had endeavoured to effect this by distinguishing between the sources in the Fourth Gospel.128 Schenkel and Weizsäcker are [pg 201] more modest. They do not feel the need of any clear literary view of the Fourth Gospel, of any critical discrimination between original and secondary elements in it; they are content to use as historical whatever their instinct leads them to accept. “Apart from the fourth Gospel,” says Schenkel, “we should miss in the portrait of the Redeemer the unfathomable depths and the inaccessible heights.” “Jesus,” to quote his aphorism, “was not always thus in reality, but He was so in truth.” Since when have historians had the right to distinguish between reality and truth? That was one of the bad habits which the author of this characterisation of Jesus brought with him from his earlier dogmatic training.

The urge to escape the choice between the Synoptic Gospels and John was inherent to the Markan hypothesis. Weisse tried to do this by differentiating between the sources in the Fourth Gospel.128 Schenkel and Weizsäcker are [pg 201] more modest. They don’t feel the need for a clear literary perspective on the Fourth Gospel or any critical distinction between its original and secondary elements; they are satisfied to treat as historical whatever their intuition tells them to accept. "Besides the fourth Gospel," says Schenkel, "We should note that the portrait of the Redeemer lacks both the deep complexities and the unreachable heights." "Jesus," to quote his saying, "was not always like this in reality, but He was like this in truth." Since when do historians have the authority to separate reality from truth? That was one of the bad habits the author of this characterization of Jesus brought with him from his earlier dogmatic training.

Weizsäcker129 expresses himself with more circumspection. “We possess,” he says, “in the Fourth Gospel genuine apostolic reminiscences as much as in any part of the first three Gospels; but between the facts on which the reminiscences are based and their reproduction in literary form there lies the development of their possessor into a great mystic, and the influence of a philosophy which here for the first time united itself in this way with the Gospel; they need, therefore, to be critically examined; and the historical truth of this gospel, great as it is, must not be measured with a painful literality.”

Weizsäcker129 speaks more cautiously. “We have," he states, "In the Fourth Gospel, there are true apostolic memories, similar to those found in the first three Gospels. However, between the events that these memories reflect and how they are expressed in writing, there is a transformation of the person who holds them into a deep mystic, along with the influence of a philosophy that for the first time intertwines with the Gospel in this way. Therefore, they need to be critically evaluated, and the historical accuracy of this gospel, as important as it is, shouldn't be judged with strict literalness."

One wonders why both these writers appeal to Holtzmann, seeing that they practically abandon the Marcan plan which he had worked out at the end of his very thorough examination of this Gospel. They do not accept as sufficient the controversy regarding the ceremonial regulations in Mark vii. which, with the rejection at Nazareth, constitute, in Holtzmann's view, the turning-point of the Galilaean ministry, but find the cause of the change of attitude on the part of the people rather in the Johannine discourse about eating and drinking the flesh and blood of the Son of Man. The section Mark x.-xv., which has a certain unity, they interpret in the light of the Johannine tradition, finding in it traces of a previous ministry of Jesus in Jerusalem and interweaving with it the Johannine story of the Passion. According to Schenkel the last visit to Jerusalem must have been of considerable duration. When confronted with John, the admission may be wrung from the Synoptists that Jesus did not travel straight through Jericho to the capital, but worked first for a considerable time in Judaea. Strauss [pg 202] tartly observes that he cannot see what the author of the “characterisation” stood to gain by underwriting Holtzmann's Marcan hypothesis.130

One wonders why both these writers refer to Holtzmann, considering they nearly disregard the Marcan framework he developed at the end of his detailed analysis of this Gospel. They don’t find the debate about the ceremonial laws in Mark 7, along with the rejection at Nazareth, to be enough for understanding the turning point in the Galilean ministry, as Holtzmann suggested. Instead, they believe the shift in the people's attitude stems more from the Johannine discussion about consuming the flesh and blood of the Son of Man. They interpret the Mark 10-15 section, which has a certain cohesion, through the lens of Johannine tradition, seeing hints of a prior ministry of Jesus in Jerusalem and blending it with the Johannine Passion narrative. According to Schenkel, Jesus's last visit to Jerusalem must have lasted a significant amount of time. When compared to John, the Synoptists might have to admit that Jesus didn’t travel directly from Jericho to the capital, but spent a considerable time working in Judea first. Strauss [pg 202] pointedly remarks that he doesn't understand what the author of the "character development" hoped to gain by supporting Holtzmann's Marcan theory.130

Weizsäcker is still bolder in making interpolations from the Johannine tradition. He places the cleansing of the Temple, in contradiction to Mark, in the early period of Jesus' ministry, on the ground that “it bears the character of a first appearance, a bold deed with which to open His career.” He fails to observe, however, that if this act really took place at this point of time, the whole development of the life of Jesus which Holtzmann had so ingeniously traced in Mark, is at once thrown into confusion. In describing the last visit to Jerusalem, Weizsäcker is not content to insert the Marcan stones into the Johannine cement; he goes farther and expressly states that the great farewell discourses of Jesus to His disciples agree with the Synoptic discourses to the disciples spoken during the last days, however completely they of all others bear the peculiar stamp of the Johannine diction.

Weizsäcker is still bolder in making connections from the Johannine tradition. He places the cleansing of the Temple, contrary to Mark, at the start of Jesus' ministry, arguing that “it has the vibe of a first appearance, a bold act to kick off His career.” However, he doesn't notice that if this event really happened at this time, the entire development of Jesus' life that Holtzmann cleverly traced in Mark gets completely thrown off. In describing the last visit to Jerusalem, Weizsäcker doesn't just mix the Marcan elements into the Johannine narrative; he goes further and explicitly states that Jesus' significant farewell speeches to His disciples line up with the Synoptic speeches given to the disciples during the last days, despite the fact that they distinctly carry the unique style of Johannine language.

Thus in the second period of the Marcan hypothesis the same spectacle meets us as in the earlier. The hypothesis has a literary existence, indeed it is carried by Holtzmann to such a degree of demonstration that it can no longer be called a mere hypothesis, but it does not succeed in winning an assured position in the critical study of the Life of Jesus. It is common-land not yet taken into cultivation.

Thus, in the second stage of the Marcan hypothesis, we encounter the same scene as in the earlier one. The hypothesis has a literary presence; in fact, Holtzmann takes it to such a level of proof that it can no longer be regarded as just a hypothesis, but it still fails to gain a solid standing in the critical study of the Life of Jesus. It remains common ground that has yet to be cultivated.

That is due in no small measure to the fact that Holtzmann did not work out the hypothesis from the historical side, but rather on literary lines, recalling Wilke—as a kind of problem in Synoptic arithmetic—and in his preface expresses dissent from the Tübingen school, who desired to leave no alternative between John on the one side and the Synoptics on the other, whereas he approves the attempt to evade the dilemma in some way or other, and thinks he can find in the didactic narrative of the Fourth Gospel the traces of a development of Jesus similar to that portrayed in the Synoptics, and has therefore no fundamental objection to the use of John alongside of the Synoptics. In taking up this position, however, he does not desire to be understood as meaning that “it would be to the interests of science to throw Synoptic and Johannine passages together indiscriminately and thus construct a life of Jesus out of them.” “It would be much better first to reconstruct separately the Synoptic and Johannine pictures of Christ, composing each of its own distinctive material. It is only when this has been done that it is possible to make a fruitful comparison of the two.” Exactly the same position had been taken up sixty-seven years [pg 203] before by Herder. In Holtzmann's case, however, the principle was stated with so many qualifications that the adherents of his view read into it the permission to combine, in a picture treated “in the grand style,” Synoptic with Johannine passages.

That is largely because Holtzmann approached the hypothesis not from a historical perspective, but rather through a literary lens, echoing Wilke—as a kind of problem in Synoptic arithmetic—and in his preface, he expresses disagreement with the Tübingen school, which wanted to impose a strict choice between John and the Synoptics. He supports efforts to find a way out of that dilemma and believes that in the teaching narrative of the Fourth Gospel, there are signs of a development of Jesus akin to what is shown in the Synoptics. Therefore, he has no fundamental issue with using John alongside the Synoptics. However, by taking this stance, he does not mean to suggest that “it would be to the interests of science to throw Synoptic and Johannine passages together indiscriminately and thus construct a life of Jesus out of them.” “It would be much better first to reconstruct separately the Synoptic and Johannine pictures of Christ, composing each from its own unique material. Only after this can a meaningful comparison of the two be made.” The same position was taken sixty-seven years before by Herder. In Holtzmann's case, however, the principle was articulated with so many qualifications that his followers interpreted it as permission to combine, in a depiction treated “in the grand style,” Synoptic and Johannine passages.

In addition to this, the plan which Holtzmann finally evolved out of Mark was much too fine-drawn to bear the weight of the remainder of the Synoptic material. He distinguishes seven stages in the Galilaean ministry,131 of which the really decisive one is the sixth, in which Jesus leaves Galilee and goes northward, so that Schenkel and Weizsäcker are justified in distinguishing practically only two great Galilaean periods, the first of which—down to the controversy about ceremonial purity—they distinguish as the period of success, the second—down to the departure from Judaea—as the period of decline. What attracted these writers to the Marcan hypothesis was not so much the authentification which it gave to the detail of Mark, though they were willing enough to accept that, but the way in which this Gospel lent itself to the a priori view of the course of the life of Jesus which they unconsciously brought with them. They appealed to Holtzmann because he showed such wonderful skill in extracting from the Marcan narrative the view which commended itself to the spirit of the age as manifested in the 'sixties.

In addition to this, the plan that Holtzmann ultimately developed from Mark was way too detailed to support the rest of the Synoptic material. He identifies seven stages in the Galilean ministry, of which the truly critical one is the sixth, where Jesus leaves Galilee and heads north. This allows Schenkel and Weizsäcker to justify recognizing essentially only two major Galilean periods: the first—up to the debate about ceremonial purity—they call the period of success, and the second—up to the departure from Judea—they see as the period of decline. What drew these writers to the Marcan hypothesis wasn’t just the legitimacy it gave to Mark’s details, though they were certainly open to that, but how this Gospel fit their preconceived notions about the life of Jesus that they unknowingly brought along. They were attracted to Holtzmann because he demonstrated an impressive ability to extract from the Marcan narrative the perspective that resonated with the spirit of the 'sixties.

Holtzmann read into this Gospel that Jesus had endeavoured in Galilee to found the Kingdom of God in an ideal sense; that He concealed His consciousness of being the Messiah, which was constantly growing more assured, until His followers should have attained by inner enlightenment to a higher view of the Kingdom of God and of the Messiah; that almost at the end of His Galilaean ministry He declared Himself to them as the Messiah at Caesarea Philippi; that on the same occasion He at once began to picture to them a suffering Messiah, whose lineaments gradually became more and more distinct in His mind amid the growing opposition which He encountered, until finally, He communicated to His disciples His decision to put the Messianic cause to the test in the capital, and that they followed Him thither and saw how His fate fulfilled itself. It was this fundamental view which made the success of the hypothesis. Holtzmann, not less than his followers, believed that he had discovered it in the Gospel itself, although Strauss, the passionate opponent of the Marcan hypothesis, took essentially the same view of the development of Jesus' thought. But the way in which Holtzmann exhibited this characteristic view of the 'sixties as arising naturally out of the detail of Mark, was so perfect, so artistically charming, that this view appeared henceforward to be inseparably bound up with the [pg 204] Marcan tradition. Scarcely ever has a description of the life of Jesus exercised so irresistible an influence as that short outline—it embraces scarcely twenty pages—with which Holtzmann closes his examination of the Synoptic Gospels. This chapter became the creed and catechism of all who handled the subject during the following decades. The treatment of the life of Jesus had to follow the lines here laid down until the Marcan hypothesis was delivered from its bondage to that a priori view of the development of Jesus. Until then any one might appeal to the Marcan hypothesis, meaning thereby only that general view of the inward and outward course of development in the life of Jesus, and might treat the remainder of the Synoptic material how he chose, combining with it, at his pleasure, material drawn from John. The victory, therefore, belonged, not to the Marcan hypothesis pure and simple, but to the Marcan hypothesis as psychologically interpreted by a liberal theology.

Holtzmann interpreted this Gospel to mean that Jesus tried to establish the Kingdom of God in a spiritual way while keeping His growing awareness of being the Messiah hidden until His followers could gain a deeper understanding of the Kingdom of God and the Messiah through inner reflection. Near the end of His ministry in Galilee, He revealed His identity as the Messiah to them at Caesarea Philippi. On that occasion, He also started to express the idea of a suffering Messiah, whose features became clearer in His mind as opposition against Him grew. Eventually, He shared with His disciples His intention to test the Messianic mission in the capital, and they followed Him there to witness how His fate unfolded. This foundational view supported the success of the hypothesis. Holtzmann, like his followers, believed he had found this in the Gospel itself, even though Strauss, a strong critic of the Marcan hypothesis, held a similar perspective on the development of Jesus' thoughts. However, Holtzmann's presentation of this significant view from the 'sixties, emerging naturally from the details of Mark, was so compelling and artistically appealing that it became tightly linked to the [pg 204] Marcan tradition. Few descriptions of Jesus' life have had as powerful an impact as that brief overview—barely twenty pages long—with which Holtzmann concluded his study of the Synoptic Gospels. This chapter became the foundational belief and teaching tool for everyone engaging with the topic in the following decades. Approaches to Jesus' life had to align with the framework established here until the Marcan hypothesis was freed from its ties to that initial interpretation of Jesus' development. Until then, anyone could reference the Marcan hypothesis as a general view of the internal and external progression in Jesus' life and could use the rest of the Synoptic material as they wished, merging it with material from John as they saw fit. Therefore, the victory belonged not just to the Marcan hypothesis itself, but to the Marcan hypothesis as understood through a psychological lens by liberal theology.

The points of distinction between the Weissian and the new interpretation are as follows:—Weisse is sceptical as regards the detail; the new Marcan hypothesis ventures to base conclusions even upon incidental remarks in the text. According to Weisse there were not distinct periods of success and failure in the ministry of Jesus; the new Marcan hypothesis confidently affirms this distinction, and goes so far as to place the sojourn of Jesus in the parts beyond Galilee under the heading “Flights and Retirements.”132 The earlier Marcan hypothesis expressly denies that outward circumstances influenced the resolve of Jesus to die; according to the later, it was the opposition of the people, and the impossibility of carrying out His mission on other lines which forced Him to enter on the path of suffering.133 The Jesus of Weisse's view has [pg 205] completed His development at the time of His appearance; the Jesus of the new interpretation of Mark continues to develop in the course of His public ministry.

The differences between the Weissian and the new interpretation are as follows: Weisse is skeptical about the details; the new Marcan hypothesis even bases conclusions on incidental remarks in the text. According to Weisse, there weren't separate periods of success and failure in Jesus's ministry; the new Marcan hypothesis confidently claims this distinction and even categorizes Jesus's time spent in areas beyond Galilee as “Flights and Retirements.” The earlier Marcan hypothesis clearly denies that external factors influenced Jesus's decision to die; the later one argues that it was the people's opposition and the inability to carry out His mission differently that compelled Him to follow the path of suffering. The Jesus in Weisse's view has completed His development by the time of His appearance, while the Jesus in the new interpretation of Mark continues to evolve throughout His public ministry.

There is complete agreement, however, in the rejection of eschatology. For Holtzmann, Schenkel, and Weizsäcker, as for Weisse, Jesus desires “to found an inward kingdom of repentance.”134 It was Israel's duty, according to Schenkel, to believe in the presence of the Kingdom which Jesus proclaimed. John the Baptist was unable to believe in it, and it was for this reason that Jesus censured him—for it is in this sense that Schenkel understands the saying about the greatest among those born of women who is nevertheless the least in the Kingdom of Heaven. “So near the light and yet shutting his eyes to its beams—is there not some blame here, an undeniable lack of spiritual and moral receptivity?”

There is complete agreement, however, in rejecting eschatology. For Holtzmann, Schenkel, and Weizsäcker, as well as Weisse, Jesus wants to "create an internal realm of reflection and change."134 According to Schenkel, it was Israel's responsibility to believe in the presence of the Kingdom that Jesus announced. John the Baptist couldn't believe in it, and that’s why Jesus criticized him—for this is how Schenkel interprets the saying about the greatest among those born of women who is still the least in the Kingdom of Heaven. "So near to the light yet oblivious to its rays—shouldn't there be some blame here, an undeniable lack of spiritual and moral awareness?"

Jesus makes Messianic claims only in a spiritual sense. He does not grasp at super-human glory; it is His purpose to bear the sin of the whole people, and He undergoes baptism “as a humble member of the national community.”

Jesus makes Messianic claims only in a spiritual sense. He doesn’t seek superhuman glory; His purpose is to take on the sins of all people, and He undergoes baptism "as a modest member of the national community."

His whole teaching consists, when once He Himself has attained to clear consciousness of His vocation, in a constant struggle to root out from the hearts of His disciples their theocratic hopes and to effect a transformation of their traditional Messianic ideas. When, on Simon's hailing Him as the Messiah, He declares that flesh and blood has not revealed it to him, He means, according to Schenkel, “that Simon has at this moment overcome the false Messianic ideas, and has recognised in Him the ethical and spiritual deliverer of Israel.”

His entire teaching, once He has gained a clear understanding of His purpose, revolves around the ongoing effort to eliminate the theocratic hopes from the hearts of His disciples and to transform their traditional ideas about the Messiah. When Simon calls Him the Messiah and He responds that flesh and blood did not reveal this to him, He means, according to Schenkel, "Right now, Simon has moved past the false Messianic ideas and has acknowledged Him as the ethical and spiritual savior of Israel."

“That Jesus predicted a personal, bodily, Second Coming, in the brightness of His heavenly splendour and surrounded by the heavenly hosts, to establish an earthly kingdom, is not only not proved, it is absolutely impossible.” His purpose is to establish a community of which His disciples are to be the foundation, and by means of this community to bring about the coming of the Kingdom of God. He can, therefore, only have spoken of His return as an impersonal return in the Spirit. The later exponents of the Marcan view were no doubt generally inclined to regard the return as personal and corporeal. For Schenkel, however, it is historically certain that the real meaning of the eschatological [pg 206] discourses is more faithfully preserved in the Fourth Gospel than in the Synoptics.

“The concept that Jesus foretold a personal, physical Second Coming, shining in His heavenly glory and accompanied by heavenly beings to establish an earthly kingdom is not only unproven; it’s entirely impossible.” His goal is to create a community where His disciples serve as the foundation, and through this community, bring about the arrival of the Kingdom of God. Therefore, He likely spoke of His return as an impersonal return in the Spirit. Later followers of the Marcan perspective probably tended to see the return as personal and physical. For Schenkel, however, it is historically certain that the true meaning of the eschatological [pg 206] discourses is more accurately reflected in the Fourth Gospel than in the Synoptics.

In his anxiety to eliminate any enthusiastic elements from the representation of Jesus, he ends by drawing a bourgeois Messiah whom he might have extracted from the old-fashioned rationalistic work of the worthy Reinhard. He feels bound to save the credit of Jesus by showing that the entry into Jerusalem was not intended as a provocation to the government. “It is only by making this supposition,” he explains, “that we avoid casting a slur upon the character of Jesus. It was certainly a constant trait in His character that He never unnecessarily exposed Himself to danger, and never, except for the most pressing reasons, did He give any support to the suspicions which were arising against Him; He avoided provoking His opponents to drastic measures by any overt act directed against them.” Even the cleansing of the Temple was not an act of violence but merely an attempt at reform.

In his eagerness to remove any passionate aspects from the depiction of Jesus, he ultimately portrays a middle-class Messiah that he could have taken from the outdated rationalistic work of the respectable Reinhard. He feels compelled to protect Jesus's reputation by suggesting that the entry into Jerusalem wasn't meant to provoke the authorities. "Only by making this assumption," he explains, "that we avoid damaging the reputation of Jesus. One consistent trait of His character was that He never put Himself in danger without good reason, and except for very urgent matters, He did not validate the suspicions against Him; He refrained from provoking His opponents to extreme actions through any deliberate acts against them." Even the cleansing of the Temple was not an act of violence but just an effort at reform.

Schenkel is able to give these explanations because he knows the most secret thoughts of Jesus and is therefore no longer bound to the text. He knows, for example, that immediately after His baptism He attained to the knowledge “that the way of the Law was no longer the way of salvation for His people.” Jesus cannot therefore have uttered the saying about the permanence of the Law in Mark v. 18. In the controversies about the Sabbath “He proclaims freedom of worship.”

Schenkel can provide these explanations because he understands the deepest thoughts of Jesus and is no longer tied to the text. He knows, for example, that right after His baptism, He realized "that the path of the Law was no longer the path to salvation for His people." Therefore, Jesus couldn't have made the statement about the permanence of the Law in Mark v. 18. In the debates about the Sabbath, “He proclaims freedom of religion.”

As time went on, He began to take the heathen world into the scope of His purpose. “The hard saying addressed to the Canaanite woman represents rather the proud and exclusive spirit of Pharisaism than the spirit of Jesus.” It was a test of faith, the success of which had a decisive influence upon Jesus' attitude towards the heathen. Henceforth it is obvious that He is favourably disposed towards them. He travels through Samaria and establishes a community there. In Jerusalem He openly calls the heathen to Him. At certain feasts which they had arranged for that purpose, some of the leaders of the people set a trap for Him, and betrayed Him into liberal sayings in regard to the Gentiles which sealed His fate.

As time went on, He started to include the non-Jewish world in His plans. "The harsh words aimed at the Canaanite woman show more about the proud and exclusive attitude of the Pharisees than the spirit of Jesus." It was a test of faith, and its outcome significantly shaped Jesus' views on non-Jews. From that point on, it’s clear that He is more open to them. He travels through Samaria and establishes a community there. In Jerusalem, He openly welcomes non-Jews. During certain festivals set up for this purpose, some leaders tricked Him and forced Him into making statements about Gentiles that sealed His fate.

This was the course of development of the Master, who, according to Schenkel, “saw with a clear eye into the future history of the world,” and knew that the fall of Jerusalem must take place in order to close the theocratic era and give the Gentiles free access to the universal community of Christians which He was to found. “This period He described as the period of His coming, as in a sense His Second Advent upon earth.”

This was the development path of the Master, who, according to Schenkel, "had a clear vision of the future history of the world," and understood that the fall of Jerusalem had to happen to end the theocratic era and allow the Gentiles to have unrestricted access to the universal community of Christians that He was going to establish. "He called this time the period of His coming, similar to His Second Advent on earth."

The same general procedure is followed by Weizsäcker in his “Gospel History,” though his work is of a much higher quality [pg 207] than Schenkel's. His account of the sources is one of the clearest that has ever been written. In the description of the life of Jesus, however, the unhesitating combination of material from the Fourth Gospel with that of the Synoptics rather confuses the picture. And whereas Renan only offers the results of the completed process, Weizsäcker works out his, it might almost be said, under the eyes of the reader, which makes the arbitrary character of the proceeding only the more obvious. But in his attitude towards the sources Weizsäcker is wholly free from the irresponsible caprice in which Schenkel indulges. From time to time, too, he gives a hint of unsolved problems in the background. For example, in treating of the declaration of Jesus to His judges that He would come as the Son of Man upon the clouds of heaven, he remarks how surprising it is that Jesus could so often have used the designation Son of Man on earlier occasions without being accused of claiming the Messiahship. It is true that this is a mere scraping of the keel upon a sandbank, by which the steersman does not allow himself to be turned from his course, for Weizsäcker concludes that the name Son of Man, in spite of its use in Daniel, “had not become a generally current or really popular designation of the Messiah.” But even this faint suspicion of the difficulty is a welcome sign. Much emphasis, in fact, in practice rather too much emphasis, is laid on the principle that in the great discourses of Jesus the structure is not historical; they are only collections of sayings formed to meet the needs of the Christian community in later times. In this Weizsäcker is sometimes not less arbitrary than Schenkel, who represents the Lord's Prayer as given by Jesus to the disciples only in the last days at Jerusalem. It was an axiom of the school that Jesus could not have delivered discourses such as the Evangelists record.

The same general approach is used by Weizsäcker in his “Gospel History” although his work is of a much higher quality [pg 207] than Schenkel's. His discussion of the sources is one of the clearest that has ever been written. However, in describing Jesus's life, the seamless blending of material from the Fourth Gospel with that of the Synoptics tends to muddle the picture. While Renan only presents the outcomes of the finished process, Weizsäcker works through his reasoning, almost in plain sight of the reader, which makes the arbitrary nature of the method even more apparent. Yet, in his approach to the sources, Weizsäcker remains completely free from the careless whims that Schenkel indulges in. From time to time, he also hints at unresolved issues in the background. For instance, when discussing Jesus's statement to his judges that he would come as the Son of Man on the clouds of heaven, he notes how surprising it is that Jesus frequently used the title Son of Man earlier without being accused of claiming to be the Messiah. While this is essentially just skimming the surface without a deep dive, it does show that Weizsäcker concludes that the name Son of Man, despite its use in Daniel, "had not become a widely accepted or truly popular title for the Messiah." Still, this slight hint of difficulty is a positive sign. In fact, a lot of emphasis, perhaps too much, is placed on the idea that in Jesus’s major discourses, the structure is not historical; they are merely collections of sayings created to address the needs of the Christian community in later times. Here, Weizsäcker can sometimes be just as arbitrary as Schenkel, who portrays the Lord's Prayer as given by Jesus to the disciples only in the final days in Jerusalem. The prevailing assumption among scholars was that Jesus could not have delivered talks like those recorded by the Evangelists.

If Schenkel's picture of Jesus' character attracted much more attention than Weizsäcker's work, that is mainly due to the art of lively popular presentation by which it is distinguished. The writer knows well how to keep the reader's interest awake by the use of exciting headlines. Catchwords abound, and arrest the ear, for they are the catchwords about which the religious controversies of the time revolved. There is never far to look for the moral of the history, and the Jesus here portrayed can be imagined plunging into the midst of the debates in any ministerial conference. The moralising, it must be admitted, sometimes becomes the occasion of the feeblest ineptitudes. Jesus sent out His disciples two and two; this is for Schenkel a marvellous exhibition of wisdom. The Lord designed, thereby, to show that in His opinion “nothing is more inimical to the interests of the Kingdom of God than individualism, self-will, self-pleasing.” Schenkel entirely fails to recognise the superb irony of the saying that in this life all that a [pg 208] man gives up for the sake of the Kingdom of God is repaid a hundredfold in persecutions, in order that in the Coming Age he may receive eternal life as his reward. He interpreted it as meaning that the sufferer shall be compensated by love; his fellow-Christians will endeavour to make it up to him, and will offer him their own possessions so freely that, in consequence of this brotherly love, he will soon have, for the house which he has lost, a hundred houses, for the lost sisters, brothers, and so forth, a hundred sisters, a hundred brothers, a hundred fathers, a hundred mothers, a hundred farms. Schenkel forgets to add that, if this is to be the interpretation of the saying, the persecuted man must also receive through this compensating love, a hundred wives.135

If Schenkel's portrayal of Jesus' character drew a lot more attention than Weizsäcker's work, it's mainly because of the engaging way he presents his ideas. The author knows how to keep the reader interested with catchy headlines. He uses a lot of phrases that catch the ear, as they're the key terms around which the religious debates of the time revolved. The moral of the story is always easy to find, and the Jesus he describes could be imagined joining any ministerial conference debate. It must be noted that sometimes the moralizing leads to rather weak arguments. Jesus sent out His disciples two by two; for Schenkel, this is a brilliant example of wisdom. He believes that this shows that, in His view, "Nothing is more damaging to the interests of the Kingdom of God than individualism, self-will, and self-indulgence." Schenkel completely overlooks the irony in the saying that in this life, everything a [pg 208] man sacrifices for the Kingdom of God is repaid a hundredfold in persecutions, so that in the next life, he may receive eternal life as his reward. He interprets it as meaning that the one suffering will be compensated by love; his fellow Christians will try to repay him, offering their own possessions so freely that, thanks to this brotherly love, he'll end up with a hundred houses for the one he lost, a hundred sisters for the ones he lost, a hundred brothers, a hundred fathers, a hundred mothers, and a hundred farms. Schenkel fails to mention that, if this is the interpretation of the saying, the persecuted person must also receive, through this compensating love, a hundred wives.135

This want of insight into the largeness, the startling originality, the self-contradictoriness, and the terrible irony in the thought of Jesus, is not a peculiarity of Schenkel's; it is characteristic of all the liberal Lives of Jesus from Strauss's down to Oskar Holtzmann's.136 How could it be otherwise? They had to transpose a way of envisaging the world which belonged to a hero and a dreamer to the plane of thought of a rational bourgeois religion. But in Schenkel's representation, with its popular appeal, this banality is particularly obtrusive.

This lack of understanding about the vastness, the surprising originality, the self-contradictions, and the deep irony in Jesus's thought isn't just something unique to Schenkel; it's something all liberal interpretations of Jesus share, from Strauss to Oskar Holtzmann. How could it be any different? They had to shift the worldview of a visionary and a dreamer to fit into the more conventional thinking of a rational middle-class religion. However, in Schenkel's portrayal, which aims for broad appeal, this simplification stands out even more.

In the end, however, what made the success of the book was not its popular characteristics, whether good or bad, but the enmity which it drew down upon the author. The Basle Privat-Docent who, in his work of 1839, had congratulated the Zurichers on having rejected Strauss, now, as Professor and Director of the Seminary at Heidelberg, came very near being adjudged worthy of the martyr's crown himself. He had been at Heidelberg since 1851, after holding for a short time De Wette's chair at Basle. At his first coming a mildly reactionary theology might have claimed him as its own. He gave it a right to do so by the way in which he worked against the philosopher, Kuno Fischer, in the Higher Consistory. But in the struggles over the constitution of the Church he changed his position. As a defender of the rights of the laity he ranged himself on the more liberal side. After his great victory in the General Synod of 1861, in which the new constitution of the Church was established, he called a German Protestant assembly at Frankfort, in order to set on foot a general movement for Church reform. This assembly met in 1863, and led to the formation of the Protestant Association.

In the end, what really fueled the success of the book wasn’t its popular features, whether good or bad, but the hostility it stirred up against the author. The Basle Privat-Docent who, in his 1839 work, had praised the Zurichers for rejecting Strauss, now, as a Professor and Director of the Seminary at Heidelberg, came very close to being considered worthy of the martyr's crown himself. He had been in Heidelberg since 1851, after briefly occupying De Wette's chair at Basle. When he first arrived, a mild reactionary theology might have claimed him as one of its own. He earned that right by the way he opposed the philosopher Kuno Fischer in the Higher Consistory. However, during the struggles over the Church's constitution, he shifted his stance. As a defender of laypeople's rights, he aligned himself with the more liberal side. After his significant victory in the General Synod of 1861, which established the new constitution of the Church, he called for a German Protestant assembly in Frankfurt to initiate a broad movement for Church reform. This assembly took place in 1863 and resulted in the creation of the Protestant Association.

When the Charakterbild Jesu appeared, friend and foe were alike surprised at the thoroughness with which Schenkel advocated the more liberal views. “Schenkel's book,” complained Luthardt, [pg 209] in a lecture at Leipzig,137 “has aroused a painful interest. We had learnt to know him in many aspects; we were not prepared for such an apostasy from his own past. How long is it since he brought about the dismissal of Kuno Fischer from Heidelberg because he saw in the pantheism of this philosopher a danger to Church and State? It is still fresh in our memory that it was he who in the year 1852 drew up the report of the Theological Faculty of Heidelberg upon the ecclesiastical controversy raised by Pastor Dülon at Bremen, in which he denied Dülon's Christianity on the ground that he had assailed the doctrines of original sin, of justification by faith, of a living and personal God, of the eternal Divine Sonship of Christ, of the Kingdom of God, and of the credibility of the holy Scriptures.” And now this same Schenkel was misusing the Life of Jesus as a weapon in “party polemics”!

When the Profile of Jesus was released, both friends and critics were shocked by how strongly Schenkel supported the more liberal views. “Schenkel's book,” complained Luthardt, [pg 209] in a lecture at Leipzig,137 “has sparked a painful curiosity. We had known him in many ways; we weren't prepared for such a betrayal of his own past. How long has it been since he caused Kuno Fischer's dismissal from Heidelberg because he saw this philosopher's pantheism as a threat to Church and State? It’s still fresh in our minds that in 1852 he wrote the Theological Faculty of Heidelberg's report on the church controversy raised by Pastor Dülon in Bremen, where he denied Dülon's Christianity because Dülon challenged the doctrines of original sin, justification by faith, a living and personal God, the eternal Divine Sonship of Christ, the Kingdom of God, and the authenticity of the holy Scriptures.” And now this same Schenkel was using the Life of Jesus as a tool in "party debates"!

The agitation against him was engineered from Berlin, where his successful attack upon the illiberal constitution of the Church had not been forgiven. One hundred and seventeen Baden clerics signed a protest declaring the author unfitted to hold office as a theological teacher in the Baden Church. Throughout the whole of Germany the pastors agitated against him. It was especially demanded that he should be immediately removed from his post as Director of the Seminary. A counter-protest was issued by the Durlach Conference in the July of 1864, in which Bluntschli and Holtzmann vigorously defended him. The Ecclesiastical Council supported him, and the storm gradually died away, especially when Schenkel in two “Defences” skilfully softened down the impression made by his work, and endeavoured to quiet the public mind by pointing out that he had only attempted to set forth one side of the truth.138

The opposition against him was orchestrated from Berlin, where his successful challenge to the repressive constitution of the Church had not been forgiven. One hundred and seventeen clerics from Baden signed a protest stating that he was unfit to serve as a theological teacher in the Baden Church. Throughout Germany, pastors campaigned against him. There were strong calls for his immediate removal from his position as Director of the Seminary. In July 1864, a counter-protest was issued by the Durlach Conference, in which Bluntschli and Holtzmann strongly defended him. The Ecclesiastical Council backed him, and the uproar gradually subsided, particularly when Schenkel, in two “Defenses”, skillfully downplayed the impact of his work and sought to calm the public by pointing out that he had only tried to present one side of the truth.138

The position of the prospective martyr was not rendered any more easy by Strauss. In an appendix to his criticism of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus he settled accounts with his old antagonist.139 He recognises no scientific value whatever in the work. None of the ideas developed in it are new. One might [pg 210] fairly say, he thinks, “that the conclusions which have given offence had been carried down the Neckar from Tübingen to Heidelberg, and had there been salvaged by Herr Schenkel—in a somewhat sodden and deteriorated condition, it must be admitted—and incorporated into the edifice which he was constructing.” Further, Strauss censures the book for its want of frankness, its half-and-half character, which manifests itself especially in the way in which the author clings to orthodox phraseology. “Over and over again he gives criticism with one hand all that it can possibly ask, and then takes back with the other whatever the interests of faith seem to demand; with the constant result that what is taken back is far too much for criticism and not nearly enough for faith.” “In the future,” he concludes, “it will be said of the seven hundred Durlachers that they fought like paladins to prevent the enemy from capturing a standard which was really nothing but a patched dish-clout.”

The situation for the potential martyr was made even tougher by Strauss. In an appendix to his critique of Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus, he settled scores with his longtime opponent.139 He sees no scientific value in the work at all. None of the ideas presented are original. He suggests that the conclusions that caused the uproar had been brought down the Neckar from Tübingen to Heidelberg, where they had been salvaged by Herr Schenkel—in a pretty messy and deteriorated state, it must be said—and incorporated into the structure he was building. Furthermore, Strauss criticizes the book for its lack of honesty, its mixed nature, which shows especially in the way the author sticks to traditional terminology. “Again and again,” he states, “he gives criticism all it could possibly ask for with one hand, and then takes back with the other whatever the interests of faith seem to require; with the outcome that what is taken back is far too much for criticism and not nearly enough for faith.” “In the future,” he wraps up, “it will be said of the seven hundred Durlachers that they fought like heroes to keep the enemy from capturing a standard that was really just a tattered old rag.”

Schenkel died in 1885 after severe sufferings. As a critic he lacked independence, and was, therefore, always inclined to compromises; in controversy he was vehement. Though he did nothing remarkable in theology, German Protestantism owes him a vast debt for acting as its tribune in the 'sixties.

Schenkel died in 1885 after great suffering. As a critic, he lacked independence and was therefore always prone to compromises; in debates, he was intense. Although he didn't accomplish anything notable in theology, German Protestantism owes him a significant debt for being its spokesperson in the '60s.

That was the last time that any popular excitement was aroused in connexion with the critical study of the life of Jesus; and it was a mere storm in a tea-cup. Moreover, it was the man and not his work that aroused the excitement. Henceforth public opinion was almost entirely indifferent to anything which appeared in this department. The great fundamental question whether historical criticism was to be applied to the life of Jesus had been decided in connexion with Strauss's first work on the subject. If here and there indignation aroused by a Life of Jesus brought inconveniences to the author and profit to the publisher, that was connected in every case with purely external and incidental circumstances. Public opinion was not disquieted for a moment by Volkmar and Wrede, although they are much more extreme than Schenkel.

That was the last time any significant public interest was sparked regarding the serious study of Jesus's life; and it was just a minor fuss. Additionally, it was the person and not their work that created the stir. From then on, public opinion was mostly indifferent to anything that came up in this area. The essential question of whether historical criticism should be applied to Jesus's life was settled with Strauss's first book on the topic. While here and there, outrage generated by a Life of Jesus brought difficulties for the author and gains for the publisher, those instances were all tied to purely external and incidental factors. Public opinion wasn’t disturbed at all by Volkmar and Wrede, even though they are much more radical than Schenkel.

Most of the Lives of Jesus which followed had, it is true, nothing very exciting about them. They were mere variants of the type established during the 'sixties, variants of which the minute differences were only discernible by theologians, and which were otherwise exactly alike in arrangement and result. As a contribution to criticism, Keim's140 “History of Jesus of Nazara” [pg 211] was the most important Life of Jesus which appeared in a long period.

Most of the biographies of Jesus that came after weren’t particularly exciting. They were just variations of the style established in the '60s, with differences so subtle that only theologians could notice them, while being otherwise identical in structure and outcome. Keim's140“History of Jesus of Nazareth”[pg 211] was the most significant biography of Jesus that was published in a long time.

It is not of much consequence that he believes in the priority of Matthew, since his presentment of the history follows the general lines of the Marcan plan, which is preserved also in Matthew. He gives it as his opinion that the life of Jesus is to be reconstructed from the Synoptics, whether Matthew has the first place or Mark. He sketches the development of Jesus in bold lines. As early as his inaugural address at Zurich, delivered on the 17th of December 1860, which, short as it was, made a powerful impression upon Holtzmann as well as upon others, he had set up the thesis that the Synoptics “artlessly, almost against their will, show us unconsciously in incidental, unobtrusive traits the progressive development of Jesus as youth and man.”141 His later works are the development of this sketch.

It doesn’t really matter that he believes Matthew came first, since his portrayal of the history follows the basic structure of Mark, which is also found in Matthew. He expresses the view that we should piece together the life of Jesus from the Synoptic Gospels, regardless of whether Matthew or Mark is considered first. He outlines Jesus's development in broad strokes. Even in his inaugural speech at Zurich on December 17, 1860, which was brief but left a strong impression on Holtzmann and others, he proposed the idea that the Synoptics "Naively, almost reluctantly, show us in subtle, small details the gradual development of Jesus as a young person and as an adult."141 His later works expand on this outline.

His grandiose style gave the keynote for the artistic treatment of the portrait of Jesus in the 'sixties. His phrases and expressions became classical. Every one follows him in speaking of the “Galilaean spring-tide” in the ministry of Jesus.

His extravagant style set the tone for how Jesus was portrayed artistically in the '60s. His phrases and expressions became iconic. Everyone references the "Galilean spring tide" when discussing Jesus’s ministry.

On the Johannine question he takes up a clearly defined position, denying the possibility of using the Fourth Gospel side by side with the Synoptics as an historical source. He goes very far in finding special significance in the details of the Synoptists, especially when he is anxious to discover traces of want of success in the second period of Jesus' ministry, since the plan of his Life of Jesus depends on the sharp antithesis between the periods of success and failure. The whole of the second half of the Galilaean period consists for him in “flights and retirements.” “Beset by constantly renewed alarms and hindrances, Jesus left the scene of His earlier work, left His dwelling-place at Capernaum, and accompanied only by a few faithful followers, in the end only by the Twelve, sought in all directions for places of refuge for longer or shorter periods, in order to avoid and elude His enemies.” Keim frankly admits, indeed, that there is not a syllable in the Gospels to suggest that these journeys are the journeys of a fugitive. But instead of allowing that to shake his conviction, he abuses the narrators and suggests that they desired to conceal the truth. “These flights,” he says, “were no doubt inconvenient to the Evangelists. Matthew is here the frankest, but in order to restore the impression of Jesus' greatness he transfers to this [pg 212] period the greatest miracles. The later Evangelists are almost completely silent about these retirements, and leave us to suppose that Jesus made His journeys to Caesarea Philippi and the neighbourhood of Tyre and Sidon in the middle of winter from mere pleasure in travel, or for the extension of the Gospel, and that He made His last journey to Jerusalem without any external necessity, entirely in consequence of His free decision, even though the expectation of death which they ascribe to Him goes far to counteract the impression of complete freedom.” Why do they thus correct the history? “The motive was the same difficulty which draws from us also the question, ‘Is it possible that Jesus should flee?’ ” Keim answers “Yes.” Here the liberal psychology comes clearly to light. “Jesus fled,” he explains, “because He desired to preserve Himself for God and man, to secure the continuance of His ministry to Israel, to defeat as long as possible the dark designs of His enemies, to carry His cause to Jerusalem, and there, while acting, as it was His duty to do, with prudence and foresight in his relations with men, to recognise clearly, by the Divine silence or the Divine action, what the Divine purpose really was, which could not be recognised in a moment. He acts like a man who knows the duty both of examination and action, who knows His own worth and what is due to Him and His obligations towards God and man.”142

On the Johannine question, he takes a clear stance, rejecting the idea of using the Fourth Gospel alongside the Synoptics as a historical source. He goes to great lengths to find special significance in the details of the Synoptists, especially when he seeks to uncover signs of failure during the second period of Jesus' ministry, since the structure of his Life of Jesus hinges on the stark contrast between periods of success and failure. For him, the entire second half of the Galilean period consists of “flights and retirements.” "Always faced with new threats and challenges, Jesus left the region of His earlier work, departed from His home in Capernaum, and, accompanied only by a few devoted followers—eventually just the Twelve—sought refuge in different locations for short or long periods to avoid and escape His enemies." Keim openly acknowledges that there is no evidence in the Gospels to imply that these journeys are those of a fugitive. However, rather than allow that to weaken his belief, he criticizes the storytellers and suggests they wanted to hide the truth. “These flights,” he states, "Certainly, this presented challenges for the Evangelists. Matthew is the most straightforward in this regard, but to emphasize Jesus' greatness, he attributes the most significant miracles to this [pg 212] period. The later Evangelists mostly avoid discussing these retreats, leading us to believe that Jesus traveled to Caesarea Philippi and the areas around Tyre and Sidon during the winter merely for relaxation or to share the Gospel, and that His final journey to Jerusalem happened without any specific reason, purely by His own choice, even though His anticipated death, as they describe, largely challenges the idea of complete freedom." Why do they alter the history like this? “The motive was the same struggle that leads us to ask, ‘Could Jesus really have fled?’ Keim answers “Yep.” Here, the liberal psychology becomes evident. "Jesus ran away," he explains, "Because He wanted to preserve Himself for God and humanity, to ensure His ministry to Israel continued, to delay the dark plans of His enemies for as long as possible, to advance His mission in Jerusalem, and while fulfilling His duty, to proceed with caution and foresight in His interactions with others, and to clearly understand, through Divine silence or action, what the true Divine purpose was, which could not be seen right away. He acts like someone who knows the importance of both reflection and action, who understands His own worth and what is expected of Him, along with His responsibilities to God and humanity."142

In regard to the question of eschatology, however, Keim does justice to the texts.143 He admits that eschatology, “a Kingdom of God clothed with material splendours,” forms an integral part of the preaching of Jesus from the first; “that He never rejected it, and therefore never by a so-called advance transformed the sensuous Messianic idea into a purely spiritual one.” “Jesus does not uproot from the minds of the sons of Zebedee their belief in the thrones on His right hand and His left; He does not hesitate to make His entry into Jerusalem in the character of the Messiah; He acknowledges His Messiahship before the Council without making any careful reservations; upon the cross His title is The King of the Jews; He consoles Himself and His followers with the thought of His return as an earthly ruler, and leaves with His disciples, without making any attempt to check it, the belief, which long survived, in a future establishment or restoration of the Kingdom in an Israel delivered from bondage.” Keim remarks with much justice “that Strauss had been wrong in rejecting his own earlier and more correct formula,” which combined the eschatological [pg 213] and spiritual elements as operating side by side in the plan of Jesus.

In terms of the question of eschatology, Keim accurately reflects the texts. He acknowledges that eschatology, "a Kingdom of God adorned in material luxury,” is a vital part of Jesus' preaching from the start; "that He never turned it down, and therefore never changed the physical Messianic concept into just a spiritual one as part of a so-called evolution." “Jesus doesn’t take away the belief of the sons of Zebedee in the thrones at His right and left; He boldly enters Jerusalem as the Messiah; He openly acknowledges His role as the Messiah before the Council without any reservations; on the cross, His title is The King of the Jews; He reassures Himself and His followers with the idea of His return as an earthly ruler, and leaves His disciples with the belief, which lasted for a long time, in a future establishment or restoration of the Kingdom in an Israel freed from bondage, without attempting to correct it.” Keim justly points out "that Strauss was incorrect to disregard his previous and more accurate formula," which integrated the eschatological [pg 213] and spiritual elements as operating together in Jesus' plan.

Keim, however, himself in the end allows the spiritual elements practically to cancel the eschatological. He admits, it is true, that the expression Son of Man which Jesus uses designated the Messiah in the sense of Daniel's prophecy, but he thinks that these pictorial representations in Daniel did not repel Jesus because He interpreted them spiritually, and “intended to describe Himself as belonging to mankind even in His Messianic office.” To solve the difficulty Keim assumes a development. Jesus' consciousness of His vocation had been strengthened both by success and by disappointment. As time went on He preached the Kingdom not as a future Kingdom, as at first, but as one which was present in Him and with Him, and He declares His Messiahship more and more openly before the world. He thinks of the Kingdom as undergoing development, but not with an unlimited, infinite horizon as the moderns suppose; the horizon is bounded by the eschatology. “For however easy it may be to read modern ideas into the parables of the draught of fishes, the mustard seed and the leaven, which, taken by themselves, seem to suggest the duration contemplated by the modern view, it is nevertheless indubitable that Jesus, like Paul, by no means looks forward to so protracted an earthly development; on the contrary, nothing appears more clearly from the sources than that He thought of its term as rapidly approaching, and of His victory as nigh at hand; and looked to the last decisive events, even to the day of judgment, as about to occur during the lifetime of the existing generation, including Himself and His apostles.” “It was the overmastering pressure of circumstances which held Him prisoner within the limitations of this obsolete belief.” When His confidence in the development of His Kingdom came into collision with barriers which He could not pass, when His belief in the presence of the Kingdom of God grew dim, the purely eschatological ideas won the upper hand, “and if we may suppose that it was precisely this thought of the imminent decisive action of God, taking possession of His mind with renewed force at this point, which steeled His human courage, and roused Him to a passion of self-sacrifice with the hope of saving from the judgment whatever might still be saved, we may welcome His adoption of these narrower ideas as in accordance with the goodwill of God, which could only by this means maintain the failing strength of its human instrument and secure the spoils of the Divine warfare—the souls of men subdued and conquered by Him.”

Keim, however, ultimately lets the spiritual elements effectively override the eschatological aspects. He acknowledges that the term Son of Man, as used by Jesus, refers to the Messiah in line with Daniel's prophecy. Still, he believes that Jesus was not put off by the vivid imagery in Daniel because He interpreted them in a spiritual way and “meant to show that He is part of humanity even in His role as the Messiah.” To address the issue, Keim suggests a progression. Jesus’ understanding of His mission had been shaped by both triumphs and setbacks. Over time, He preached about the Kingdom not as a future reality, as He did initially, but as something that was present within Him and alongside Him, declaring His Messiahship more openly to the world. He viewed the Kingdom as developing, but not with the limitless, infinite perspective that modern thinkers assume; the view is constrained by eschatology. No matter how tempting it is to inject modern ideas into the parables of the catch of fish, the mustard seed, and the leaven— which on their own seem to imply the long duration suggested by today’s perspective— it is clear that Jesus, like Paul, did not anticipate such an extended earthly development. In fact, the sources indicate that He believed the end was coming soon and that His victory was imminent. He expected the final significant events, including the day of judgment, to happen within the lifetime of the current generation, encompassing Himself and His apostles. “It was the intense pressure of circumstances that kept Him trapped in this outdated belief.” When His confidence in the growth of His Kingdom came up against obstacles that He could not overcome, and when His belief in the presence of the Kingdom of God began to fade, the purely eschatological concepts gained dominance, "And if we can assume that it was this thought of God's imminent decisive action, becoming more intense in His mind at this moment, that strengthened His human courage and inspired Him with a passion for self-sacrifice in hopes of saving whatever could still be saved from judgment, we can accept His embracing of these more focused ideas as aligning with God's goodwill. This was the only way to sustain the dwindling strength of His human form and secure the outcomes of the Divine battle—the souls of men transformed and won over by Him."

The thought which had hovered before the mind of Renan, but which in his hands had become only the motive of a romance—une ficelle dé roman as the French express it—was realised by [pg 214] Keim. Nothing deeper or more beautiful has since been written about the development of Jesus.

The idea that had been in Renan's mind, which he turned into just a plot device for a novel—a plot thread of the novel as the French say—was brought to life by [pg 214] Keim. Since then, nothing deeper or more beautiful has been written about the life of Jesus.

Less critical in character is Hase's “History of Jesus,”144 which superseded in 1876 the various editions of the Handbook on the Life of Jesus which had first appeared in 1829.

Less critical in character is Hase's "History of Jesus,"144 which replaced the different editions of the Handbook on the Life of Jesus that first came out in 1829.

The question of the use of John's Gospel side by side with the Synoptics he leaves in suspense, and speaks his last word on the subject in the form of a parable. “If I may be allowed to use an avowedly parabolic form of speech, the relation of Jesus to the two streams of Gospel tradition may be illustrated as follows. Once there appeared upon earth a heavenly Being. According to His first three biographers He goes about more or less incognito, in the long garment of a Rabbi, a forceful popular figure, somewhat Judaic in speech, only occasionally, almost unmarked by His biographers, pointing with a smile beyond this brief interlude to His home. In the description left by His favourite disciple, He has thrown off the talar of the Rabbi, and stands before us in His native character, but in bitter and angry strife with those who took offence at His magnificent simplicity, and then later—it must be confessed, more attractively—in deep emotion at parting with those whom, during His pilgrimage on earth, He had made His friends, though they did not rightly understand His strange, unearthly speech.”

The question of using John's Gospel alongside the Synoptics is left open, and he shares his final thoughts on the topic in the form of a parable. “To put it in a more relatable way, we can think of Jesus' connection to the two streams of Gospel tradition like this. There was once a divine Being living among us. According to His first three biographers, He moved around somewhat unnoticed, wearing a Rabbi's long robe, becoming a dynamic figure people admired, speaking in a way that was somewhat Jewish, and only occasionally, almost without being noticed by His biographers, hinting with a smile about where He truly belonged. In the account written by His closest disciple, He sheds the Rabbi's robe and shows His true self, but in a fierce and angry clash with those who were upset by His remarkable simplicity. Later—it's important to acknowledge—in a more touchingly appealing manner, He becomes deeply emotional as He says goodbye to those who, during His time on earth, had become His friends, even though they didn’t fully understand His strange, otherworldly words.”

This is Hase's way, always to avoid a final decision. The fifty years of critical study of the subject which he had witnessed and taken part in had made him circumspect, sometimes almost sceptical. But his notes of interrogation do not represent a covert supernaturalism like those in the Life of Jesus of 1829. Hase had been penetrated by the influence of Strauss and had adopted from him the belief that the true life of Jesus lies beyond the reach of criticism. “It is not my business,” he says to his students in an introductory lecture, “to recoil in horror from this or that thought, or to express it with embarrassment as being dangerous; I would not forbid even the enthusiasm of doubt and destruction which makes Strauss so strong and Renan so seductive.”

This is Hase's way, always avoiding a final decision. The fifty years of critical study of the subject that he had witnessed and participated in made him careful, sometimes even a bit skeptical. However, his notes of questioning do not express a hidden supernaturalism like those in the Life of Jesus from 1829. Hase had been deeply influenced by Strauss and had adopted the belief that the true life of Jesus is beyond the reach of criticism. "That's not my problem," he tells his students in an introductory lecture, “to shrink back in horror from certain thoughts, or to talk about them awkwardly as if they’re risky; I wouldn’t hold back the excitement of questioning and dismantling that gives Strauss his strength and makes Renan so attractive.”

It is left uncertain whether Jesus' consciousness of His Messiahship reaches back to the days of His childhood, or whether it arose in the ethical development of His ripening manhood. The concealment of His Messianic claims is ascribed, [pg 215] as by Schenkel and others, to paedagogic motives; it was necessary that Jesus should first educate the people and the disciples up to a higher ethical view of His office. In the stress which he lays upon the eschatology Hase has points of affinity with Keim, for whom he had prepared the way in his Life of Jesus of 1829, in which he had been the first to assert a development in Jesus in the course of which He at first fully shared the Jewish eschatological views, but later advanced to a more spiritual conception. In his Life of Jesus of 1876 he is prepared to make the eschatology the dominant feature in the last period also, and does not hesitate to represent Jesus as dying in the enthusiastic expectation of returning upon the clouds of heaven. He feels himself driven to this by the eschatological ideas in the last discourses. “Jesus' clear and definite sayings,” he declares, “with the whole context of the circumstances in which they were spoken and understood, have been forcing me to this conclusion for years past.”

It's unclear whether Jesus was aware of His role as the Messiah from childhood or if it developed during His moral growth into adulthood. The reason He kept His Messianic claims hidden is attributed, as noted by Schenkel and others, to educational purposes; it was important for Jesus to first guide the people and His disciples to a more profound ethical understanding of His role. Hase shares some similarities with Keim in his focus on eschatology. Keim had laid the groundwork in his 1829 work, where he was the first to suggest that Jesus evolved over time, initially fully embracing Jewish eschatological beliefs, but later moving toward a more spiritual understanding. In his 1876 Life of Jesus, he continues to emphasize eschatology as a key aspect of Jesus' later life, confidently portraying Jesus as dying with the passionate hope of returning on the clouds of heaven. He feels compelled to this view based on the eschatological themes present in Jesus' final teachings. "Jesus' clear and definite sayings," he states, "along with the entire context of the circumstances in which they were spoken and understood, have led me to this conclusion for many years."

“That lofty Messianic dream must therefore continue to hold its place, since Jesus, influenced as much by the idea of the Messianic glories taken over from the beliefs of His people as by His own religious exaltation, could not think of the victory of His Kingdom except as closely connected with His own personal action. But that was only a misunderstanding due to the unconscious poesy of a high-ranging religious imagination, the ethical meaning of which could only be realised by a long historical development. Christ certainly came again as the greatest power on earth, and His power, along with His word, is constantly judging the world. He faced the sufferings which lay immediately before Him with His eyes fixed upon this great future.”

“That grand Messianic vision must remain relevant because Jesus, inspired both by the Messianic glory from His people’s beliefs and by His own deep religious passion, could only see the success of His Kingdom as closely linked to His own actions. However, this was just a misunderstanding stemming from the deep creativity of a rich religious imagination, whose moral significance could only unfold over a long historical journey. Christ undoubtedly came back as the strongest force on earth, and His power, along with His teachings, continually assesses the world. He faced the suffering to come with His eyes set on this hopeful future.”


The chief excellence of Beyschlag's Life of Jesus consists in its arrangement.145 He first, in the volume of preliminary investigations, discusses the problems, so that the narrative is disencumbered of all explanations, and by virtue of the author's admirable style becomes a pure work of art, which rivets the interest of the reader and almost causes the want of a consistent historical conception to be overlooked. The fact is, however, that in regard to the two decisive questions Beyschlag is deliberately inconsistent. Although he recognises that the Gospel [pg 216] of John has not the character of an essentially historical source, “being, rather, a brilliant subjective portrait,” “a didactic, quite as much as an historical work,” he produces his Life of Jesus by “combining and mortising together Synoptic and Johannine elements.” The same uncertainty prevails in regard to the recognition of the definitely eschatological character of Jesus' system of ideas. Beyschlag gives a very large place to eschatology, so that in order to combine the spiritual with the eschatological view his Jesus has to pass through three stages of development. In the first He preaches the Kingdom as something future, a supernatural event which was to be looked forward to, much as the Baptist preached it. Then the response which was called forth on all hands by His preaching led Him to believe that the Kingdom was in some sense already present, “that the Father, while He delays the outward manifestation of the Kingdom, is causing it to come even now in quiet and unnoticed ways by a humble gradual growth, and the great thought of His parables, which dominates the whole middle period of His public life, the resemblance of the Kingdom to mustard seed or leaven, comes to birth in His mind.” As His failure becomes more and more certain, “the centre of gravity of His thought is shifted to the world beyond the grave, and the picture of a glorious return to conquer and to judge the world rises before Him.”

The main strength of Beyschlag's Life of Jesus lies in its organization. He starts with a volume of preliminary investigations where he addresses the issues, allowing the narrative to be free of explanations. Because of the author's impressive writing style, it becomes a pure work of art that captivates the reader, almost making the lack of a consistent historical understanding fade away. However, it’s important to note that Beyschlag is intentionally inconsistent regarding two key questions. He acknowledges that the Gospel of John isn’t essentially a historical source, describing it instead as “a brilliant subjective portrait” and “a didactic, as much as a historical work.” Despite this, he creates his Life of Jesus by “combining and fitting together elements from the Synoptic and Johannine gospels.” The same ambiguity exists when it comes to recognizing the distinctly eschatological nature of Jesus' ideas. Beyschlag places great emphasis on eschatology, so to merge the spiritual with the eschatological perspective, his Jesus undergoes three stages of development. Initially, He preaches the Kingdom as a future event, a miraculous occurrence to be anticipated, similar to the way the Baptist preached it. Then, the reactions to His preaching lead Him to believe that the Kingdom is somehow already present, “that the Father, while delaying the outward manifestation of the Kingdom, is causing it to come even now in quiet and unnoticed ways through a humble gradual growth, and the significant idea of His parables, which dominates the entire middle period of His public life, the comparison of the Kingdom to a mustard seed or leaven, emerges in His mind.” As His failure becomes more evident, “the focus of His thoughts shifts to the afterlife, and the vision of a glorious return to conquer and judge the world appears before Him.”

The peculiar interweaving of Synoptic and Johannine ideas leads to the result that, between the two, Beyschlag in the end forms no clear conception of the eschatology, and makes Jesus think in a half-Johannine, half-Synoptic fashion. “It is a consequence of Jesus' profound conception of the Kingdom of God as something essentially growing that He regards its final perfection not as a state of rest, but rather as a living movement, as a process of becoming, and since He regards this process as a cosmic and supernatural process in which history finds its consummation, and yet as arising entirely out of the ethical and historical process, He combines elements from each into the same prophetic conception.” An eschatology of this kind is not matter for history.

The unique blending of Synoptic and Johannine ideas results in Beyschlag ultimately lacking a clear understanding of eschatology, causing Jesus to think in a mix of Johannine and Synoptic ways. “It comes from Jesus' profound understanding of the Kingdom of God as something that is constantly growing. He sees its ultimate perfection not as a static state, but as a vibrant movement, an ongoing process. Since He views this process as both a cosmic and supernatural event where history reaches its ultimate conclusion, while also acknowledging it as completely arising from the ethical and historical journey, He combines elements from both into a unified prophetic perspective.” An eschatology like this is not a matter for history.

In the acceptance of the “miracles” Beyschlag goes to the utmost limits allowed by criticism; in considering the possibility of one or another of the recorded raisings from the dead he even finds himself within the borders of rationalist territory.

In accepting the “miracles”, Beyschlag pushes the boundaries of criticism to the extreme; when he examines the possibility of some of the documented resurrections, he even finds himself in the realm of rationalist thinking.


Whether Bernhard Weiss's146 is to be numbered with the liberal [pg 217] Lives of Jesus is a question to which we may answer “Yes; but along with the faults of these it has some others in addition.” Weiss shares with the authors of the liberal “Lives” the assumption that Mark designed to set forth a definite “view of the course of development of the public ministry of Jesus,” and on the strength of that believes himself justified in giving a very far-reaching significance to the details offered by this Evangelist. The arbitrariness with which he carries out this theory is quite as unbounded as Schenkel's, and in his fondness for the “argument from silence” he even surpasses him. Although Mark never allows a single word to escape him about the motives of the northern journeys, Weiss is so clever at reading between the lines that the motives are “quite sufficiently” clear to him. The object of these journeys was, according to his explanation, “that the people might have an opportunity, undistracted by the immediate impression of His words and actions, to make up their minds in regard to the questions which they had put to Him so pressingly and inescapably in the last days of His public ministry; they must themselves draw their own conclusions alike from the declarations and from the conduct of Jesus. Only by Jesus' removing Himself for a time from their midst could they come to a clear decision as to their attitude to Jesus.” This modern psychologising, however, is closely combined with a dialectic which seeks to show that there is no irreconcilable opposition between the belief in the Son of [pg 218] God and Son of Man which the Church of Christ has always confessed, and a critical investigation of the question how far the details of His life have been accurately preserved by tradition, and how they are to be historically interpreted. That means that Weiss is going to cover up the difficulties and stumbling-blocks with the mantle of Christian charity which he has woven out of the most plausible of the traditional sophistries. As a dialectical performance on these lines his Life of Jesus rivals in importance any except Schleiermacher's. On points of detail there are many interesting historical observations. When all is said, one can only regret that so much knowledge and so much ability have been expended in the service of so hopeless a cause.

Whether Bernhard Weiss's 146 should be considered alongside the liberal [pg 217] Lives of Jesus is a question we can answer with "Yes; but along with their faults, it has some additional ones as well." Weiss shares the assumption with the authors of the liberal "Life" that Mark intended to present a specific “overview of the progression of Jesus' public ministry,” and based on that, he believes he has the right to attribute significant meaning to the details provided by this Evangelist. The way he applies this theory is just as arbitrary as Schenkel's, and in his reliance on the "argument from silence" he even goes beyond Schenkel. Although Mark never mentions the reasons behind the northern journeys, Weiss is so skilled at reading between the lines that he finds the motives to be “good enough” clear. According to his explanation, the purpose of these journeys was “so that the people could have a chance, without being distracted by His words and actions, to reflect on the questions they had persistently asked Him during the final days of His public ministry; they needed to come to their own conclusions based on both what Jesus said and how He acted. Only by Jesus stepping away from them for a while could they come to a clear decision about their view of Him.” This modern psychological approach, however, is closely tied to a dialectic that aims to demonstrate that there is no irreconcilable conflict between the belief in the Son of [pg 218] God and Son of Man, which the Christian Church has always professed, and a critical examination of how accurately the details of His life have been preserved by tradition, and how they should be historically interpreted. That means Weiss intends to obscure the difficulties and obstacles with the cloak of Christian charity, which he has woven from the most convincing traditional arguments. As a dialectical endeavor along these lines, his Life of Jesus is as significant as any work except Schleiermacher's. There are many interesting historical observations in terms of detail. Ultimately, one can only lament that so much knowledge and skill have been dedicated to such a futile cause.

What was the net result of these liberal Lives of Jesus? In the first place the clearing up of the relation between John and the Synoptics. That seems surprising, since the chief representatives of this school, Holtzmann, Schenkel, Weizsäcker, and Hase, took up a mediating position on this question, not to speak of Beyschlag and Weiss, for whom the possibility of reconciliation between the two lines of tradition is an accepted datum for ecclesiastical and apologetic reasons. But the very attempt to hold the position made clear its inherent untenability. The defence of the combination of the two traditions exhausted itself in the efforts of these its critical champions, just as the acceptance of the supernatural in history exhausted itself in the—to judge from the approval of the many—victorious struggle against Strauss. In the course of time Weizsäcker, like Holtzmann,147 advanced to the rejection of any possibility of reconciliation, and gave up the Fourth Gospel as an historical source. The second demand of Strauss's first Life of Jesus was now—at last—conceded by scientific criticism.

What was the overall impact of these liberal interpretations of Jesus' life? First, it clarified the relationship between John and the Synoptic Gospels. This is surprising, since the main figures of this school, like Holtzmann, Schenkel, Weizsäcker, and Hase, took a mediating stance on this issue. Beyschlag and Weiss also believed reconciliation between the two traditions was acceptable for church and apologetic reasons. However, the struggle to maintain this position highlighted its fundamental weaknesses. The defense of merging the two traditions became limited by the efforts of its critical advocates, much like the acceptance of the supernatural in history became constrained by the widely approved victory against Strauss. Over time, Weizsäcker, like Holtzmann, ultimately rejected any possibility of reconciliation and dismissed the Fourth Gospel as a historical source. The second point raised by Strauss's first Life of Jesus was finally accepted by scholarly criticism.

That does not mean, of course, that no further attempts at reconciliation appeared thenceforward. Was ever a street so closed by a cordon that one or two isolated individuals did not get through? And to dodge through needs, after all, no special [pg 219] intelligence, or special courage. Must we never speak of a victory so long as a single enemy remains alive? Individual attempts to combine John with the Synoptics which appeared after this decisive point are in some cases deserving of special attention, as for example, Wendt's148 acute study of the “Teaching of Jesus,” which has all the importance of a full treatment of the “Life.” But the very way in which Wendt grapples with his task shows that the main issue is already decided. All he can do is to fight a skilful and determined rearguard action. It is not the Fourth Gospel as it stands, but only a “ground-document” on which it is based, which he, in common with Weiss, Alexander Schweizer, and Renan, would have to be recognised “alongside of the Gospel of Mark and the Logia of Matthew as an historically trustworthy tradition regarding the teaching of Jesus,” and which may be used along with those two writings in forming a picture of the Life of Jesus. For Wendt there is no longer any question of an interweaving and working up together of the individual sections of John and the Synoptists. He takes up much the same standpoint as Holtzmann occupied in 1863, but he provides a much more comprehensive and well-tested basis for it.

That doesn’t mean, of course, that no further attempts at reconciliation came up after that. Has there ever been a street so blocked off that one or two people didn’t manage to get through? And getting through, after all, doesn’t require special [pg 219] intelligence or special courage. Should we never talk about a victory as long as there’s a single enemy left alive? Individual efforts to link John with the Synoptics that emerged after this critical point are, in some instances, worth noting, like Wendt's148 insightful study of the "Teachings of Jesus," which is just as significant as a full analysis of the "Life." But the way Wendt approaches his task shows that the main issue has already been settled. All he can do is engage in a clever and determined rearguard strategy. It’s not the Fourth Gospel itself, but rather a "ground document" upon which it’s based that he, along with Weiss, Alexander Schweizer, and Renan, would have to acknowledge “together with the Gospel of Mark and the Logia of Matthew as a reliable historical tradition about the teachings of Jesus,” which can be used along with those two texts to form a picture of the Life of Jesus. For Wendt, there’s no longer any question of intertwining and combining the individual sections of John and the Synoptics. He adopts a similar stance to that of Holtzmann in 1863, but offers a much more thorough and well-supported foundation for it.

In the end there is no such very great difference between Wendt and the writers who had advanced to the conviction of the irreconcilability of the two traditions. Wendt refuses to give up the Fourth Gospel altogether; they, on their part, won only a half victory because they did not as a matter of fact escape from the Johannine interpretation of the Synoptics. By means of their psychological interpretation of the first three Gospels they make for themselves an ideal Fourth Gospel, in the interests of which they reject the existing Fourth Gospel. They will hear nothing of the spiritualised Johannine Christ, and refuse to acknowledge even to themselves that they have only deposed Him in order to put in His place a spiritualised Synoptic Jesus Christ, that is, a man who claimed to be the Messiah, but in a spiritual sense. All the development which they discover in Jesus is in the last analysis only an evidence of the tension between the Synoptics, in their natural literal sense, and the “Fourth Gospel” which is extracted from them by an artificial interpretation.

In the end, there's not that much of a difference between Wendt and the writers who have come to believe that the two traditions can't be reconciled. Wendt doesn't completely dismiss the Fourth Gospel; on the other hand, those writers only achieved a partial victory because they didn’t really break free from the Johannine interpretation of the Synoptic Gospels. By using their psychological interpretation of the first three Gospels, they create an ideal Fourth Gospel, for which they dismiss the actual Fourth Gospel. They refuse to acknowledge the spiritualized Johannine Christ and won't even admit to themselves that they've only replaced Him with a spiritualized Synoptic Jesus Christ—a person who claimed to be the Messiah in a spiritual way. All the developments they see in Jesus ultimately show the tension between the Synoptics in their straightforward literal sense and the "Book of John" that they've extracted from them through a forced interpretation.

The fact is, the separation between the Synoptics and the Fourth Gospel is only the first step to a larger result which [pg 220] necessarily follows from it—the complete recognition of the fundamentally eschatological character of the teaching and influence of the Marcan and Matthaean Jesus. Inasmuch as they suppressed this consequence, Holtzmann, Schenkel, Hase, and Weizsäcker, even after their critical conversion, still lay under the spell of the Fourth Gospel, of a modern, ideal Fourth Gospel. It is only when the eschatological question is decided that the problem of the relation of John to the Synoptics is finally laid to rest. The liberal Lives of Jesus grasped their incompatibility only from a literary point of view, not in its full historical significance.

The reality is, the divide between the Synoptic Gospels and the Fourth Gospel is just the first step toward a bigger conclusion that necessarily follows—the complete acknowledgment of the fundamentally eschatological nature of the teachings and influence of the Jesus portrayed in Mark and Matthew. Since they did not acknowledge this conclusion, Holtzmann, Schenkel, Hase, and Weizsäcker, even after their critical awakening, remained under the influence of the Fourth Gospel, of a modern, idealized version of it. It’s only when the eschatological question is resolved that the issue of John’s relationship to the Synoptics can finally be settled. The liberal Lives of Jesus recognized their incompatibility only from a literary perspective, not in its full historical context.

There is another result in the acceptance of which the critical school had stopped half-way. If the Marcan plan be accepted, it follows that, setting aside the references to the Son of Man in Mark ii. 10 and 28, Jesus had never, previous to the incident at Caesarea Philippi, given Himself out to be the Messiah or been recognised as such. The perception of this fact marks one of the greatest advances in the study of the subject. This result, once accepted, ought necessarily to have suggested two questions: in the first place, why Jesus down to that moment had made a secret of His Messiahship even to His disciples; in the second place, whether at any time, and, if so, when and how, the people were made acquainted with His Messianic claims. As a fact, however, by the application of that ill-starred psychologising both questions were smothered; that is to say, a sham answer was given to them. It was regarded as self-evident that Jesus had concealed His Messiahship from His disciples for so long in order in the meantime to bring them, without their being aware of it, to a higher spiritual conception of the Messiah; it was regarded as equally self-evident that in the last weeks the Messianic claims of Jesus could no longer be hidden from the people, but that He did not openly avow them, but merely allowed them to be divined, in order to lead up the multitude to the recognition of the higher spiritual character of the office which He claimed for Himself. These ingenious psychologists never seemed to perceive that there is not a word of all this in Mark; but that they had read it all into some of the most contradictory and inexplicable facts in the Gospels, and had thus created a Messiah who both wished to be Messiah and did not wish it, and who in the end, so far as the people were concerned, both was and was not the Messiah. Thus these writers had only recognised the importance of the scene at Caesarea Philippi, they had not ventured to attack the general problem of Jesus' attitude in regard to the Messiahship, and had not reflected further on the mutually contradictory facts that Jesus purposed to be the Messiah and yet did not come forward publicly in that character.

There’s another outcome that the critical school only partially accepted. If we accept the Marcan plan, it suggests that, aside from references to the Son of Man in Mark 2:10 and 2:28, Jesus never claimed to be the Messiah or was recognized as such before the incident at Caesarea Philippi. Realizing this is a significant step forward in understanding the topic. Once this conclusion is reached, two questions should naturally arise: first, why did Jesus keep His Messiahship a secret from His disciples until that point? Second, at what point—if ever—and how did the public become aware of His claims to be the Messiah? Unfortunately, these questions were overlooked due to the misguided psychological analysis that provided superficial answers. It was assumed that Jesus had hidden His Messiahship from His disciples for so long to lead them, unbeknownst to them, to a deeper spiritual understanding of the Messiah. Similarly, it was taken for granted that in the final weeks, Jesus’ Messianic claims could no longer be hidden from the public, but He chose not to openly admit them, instead allowing them to be inferred, to guide the crowd toward recognizing the spiritual depth of the role He claimed. These clever psychologists seemed unaware that none of this is mentioned in Mark; they had interpreted some of the most conflicting and confusing events in the Gospels through this lens, creating a Messiah who both wanted to be the Messiah and did not, who, in terms of the public, was and was not the Messiah. Therefore, while these authors acknowledged the significance of the scene at Caesarea Philippi, they shied away from addressing the broader issue of Jesus’ stance on his Messiahship and did not consider the conflicting facts that Jesus intended to be the Messiah yet did not present Himself publicly as such.

Thus they had side-tracked the study of the subject, and based all their hopes of progress on an intensive exegesis of the detail of [pg 221] Mark. They thought they had nothing to do but to occupy a conquered territory, and never suspected that along the whole line they had only won a half victory, never having thought out to the end either the eschatological question or the fundamental historical question of the attitude of Jesus to the Messiahship.

Thus, they had sidetracked the study of the subject and based all their hopes for progress on a deep analysis of the details of [pg 221] Mark. They believed they only needed to occupy a territory they had conquered and never realized that along the entire line, they had only achieved a partial victory, never fully considering either the ultimate questions or the fundamental historical question of Jesus's view on being the Messiah.

They were not disquieted by the obstinate persistence of the discussion on the eschatological question. They thought it was merely a skirmish with a few unorganised guerrillas; in reality it was the advance-guard of the army with which Reimarus was threatening their flank, and which under the leadership of Johannes Weiss was to bring them to so dangerous a pass. And while they were endeavouring to avoid this turning movement they fell into the ambush which Bruno Bauer had laid in their rear: Wrede held up the Marcan hypothesis and demanded the pass-word for the theory of the Messianic consciousness and claims of Jesus to which it was acting as convoy.

They weren’t bothered by the stubborn continuation of the discussion about the end times. They thought it was just a minor conflict with a few disorganized rebels; in reality, it was the advance guard of the force that Reimarus was threatening them with, and which, under Johannes Weiss’s leadership, was going to put them in a very risky situation. While trying to dodge this strategy, they fell into the trap that Bruno Bauer had set behind them: Wrede raised the Marcan hypothesis and demanded the password for the theory of Jesus's Messianic consciousness and claims that it was supporting.

The eschatological and the literary school, finding themselves thus opposed to a common enemy, naturally formed an alliance. The object of their combined attack was not the Marcan outline of the life of Jesus, which, in fact, they both accept, but the modern “psychological” method of reading between the lines of the Marcan narrative. Under the cross fire of these allies that idea of development which had been the strongest entrenchment of the liberal critical Lives of Jesus, and which they had been desperately endeavouring to strengthen down to the very last, was finally blown to atoms.

The eschatological and literary schools, finding themselves up against a common enemy, naturally teamed up. Their joint attack wasn't aimed at the Marcan outline of Jesus's life, which they both accept, but rather at the modern "mental" approach of reading between the lines of the Marcan narrative. Under the crossfire of these allies, the idea of development, which had been the strongest defense of the liberal critical Lives of Jesus and which they had been desperately trying to reinforce until the very end, was ultimately destroyed.

But the striking thing about these liberal critical Lives of Jesus was that they unconsciously prepared the way for a deeper historical view which could not have been reached apart from them. A deeper understanding of a subject is only brought to pass when a theory is carried to its utmost limit and finally proves its own inadequacy.

But the impressive thing about these liberal critical Lives of Jesus was that they unintentionally opened the door for a deeper historical perspective that couldn’t have been reached without them. A deeper understanding of a subject only comes about when a theory is pushed to its limits and ultimately reveals its own shortcomings.

There is this in common between rationalism and the liberal critical method, that each had followed out a theory to its ultimate consequences. The liberal critical school had carried to its limit the explanation of the connexion of the actions of Jesus, and of the events of His life, by a “natural” psychology; and the conclusions to which they had been driven had prepared the way for the recognition that the natural psychology is not here the historical psychology, but that the latter must be deduced from certain historical data. Thus through the meritorious and magnificently sincere work of the liberal critical school the a priori “natural” psychology gave way to the eschatological. That is the net result, from the historical point of view, of the study of the life of Jesus in the post-Straussian period.

There is something in common between rationalism and the liberal critical method: both followed a theory to its ultimate consequences. The liberal critical school fully explored the connection between the actions of Jesus and the events of His life using a natural psychology. The conclusions they reached paved the way for recognizing that natural psychology isn't the same as historical psychology; the latter must be derived from specific historical data. Therefore, thanks to the commendable and genuinely honest efforts of the liberal critical school, the a priori "organic" psychology was replaced by the eschatological. This is the overall outcome, from a historical perspective, of studying the life of Jesus in the post-Straussian period.

[pg 222]

XV. The End Times Question

Timothée Colani. Jésus-Christ et les croyances messianiques de son temps. Strassburg, 1864. 255 pp.

Timothée Colani. Jesus Christ and the Messianic Beliefs of His Time. Strasbourg, 1864. 255 pages.

Gustav Volkmar. Jesus Nazarenus und die erste christliche Zeit, mit den beiden ersten Erzählern. (Jesus the Nazarene and the Beginnings of Christianity, with the two earliest narrators of His life.) Zurich, 1882. 403 pp.

Gustav Volkmar. Jesus the Nazarene and the Early Christian Era, highlighting the first two storytellers of His life. Zurich, 1882. 403 pages.

Wilhelm Weiffenbach. Der Wiederkunftsgedanke Jesu. (Jesus' Conception of His Second Coming.) 1873. 424 pp.

Wilhelm Weiffenbach. The Idea of Jesus' Second Coming. 1873. 424 pages.

W. Baldensperger. Das Selbstbewusstsein Jesu im Lichte der messianischen Hoffnungen seiner Zeit. (The Self-consciousness of Jesus in the Light of the Messianic Hopes of His time.) Strassburg, 1888. 2nd ed., 1892, 282 pp.; 3rd ed. pt. i. 240 pp.

W. Baldensperger. The Self-Awareness of Jesus in Relation to the Messianic Hopes of His Era. Strassburg, 1888. 2nd edition, 1892, 282 pages; 3rd edition part 1, 240 pages.

Johannes Weiss. Die Predigt Jesu vom Reiche Gottes. (The Preaching of Jesus concerning the Kingdom of God.) 1892. Göttingen. 67 pp. Second revised and enlarged edition, 1900, 210 pp.

Johannes Weiss. The Preaching of Jesus on the Kingdom of God. 1892. Göttingen. 67 pages. Second revised and expanded edition, 1900, 210 pages.

So long as it was merely a question of establishing the distinctive character of the thought of Jesus as compared with the ancient prophetic and Danielic conceptions, and so long as the only available storehouse of Rabbinic and Late-Jewish ideas was Lightfoot's Horae Hebraicae et Talmudicae in quatuor Evangelistas,149 it was still possible to cherish the belief that the preaching of Jesus could be conceived as something which was, in the last analysis, independent of all contemporary ideas. But after the studies of Hilgenfeld and Dillmann150 had made known the Jewish apocalyptic in its fundamental characteristics, and the Jewish pseudepigrapha were no longer looked on as “forgeries,” but as representative documents of the last stage of Jewish thought, the necessity of taking account of them in interpreting the thought of Jesus became more and more emphatic. Almost two decades [pg 223] were to pass, however, before the full significance of this material was realised.

As long as it was just a matter of defining the unique nature of Jesus's thoughts compared to ancient prophetic and Danielic ideas, and as long as the main source of Rabbinic and Late-Jewish concepts was Lightfoot's Hebrew and Talmudic Hours on the Four Gospels,149, it was still possible to believe that Jesus's preaching could be seen as something ultimately separate from all contemporary thoughts. However, after Hilgenfeld and Dillmann's studies revealed the fundamental characteristics of Jewish apocalyptic, and Jewish pseudepigrapha were no longer considered “forged items,” but rather as essential documents of the final stage of Jewish thought, the need to account for them when interpreting Jesus’s thoughts became increasingly clear. Nearly two decades [pg 223] would pass, though, before the full importance of this material was recognized.

It might almost have seemed as if it was to meet this attack by anticipation that Colani wrote in 1864 his work, Jésus-Christ et les croyances messianiques de son temps.

It might have looked like Colani wrote his work, Jesus Christ and the messianic beliefs of his time, in 1864 to preempt this attack.

Timothée Colani was born in 1824 at Lemé (Aisne), studied in Strassburg and became pastor there in 1851. In the year 1864 he was appointed Professor of Pastoral Theology in Strassburg in spite of some attempted opposition to the appointment on the part of the orthodox party in Paris, which was then growing in strength. The events of the year 1870 left him without a post. As he had no prospect of being called to a pastorate in France, he became a merchant. In consequence of some unfortunate business operations he lost all his property. In 1875 he obtained a post as librarian at the Sorbonne. He died in 1888.

Timothée Colani was born in 1824 in Lemé (Aisne), studied in Strasbourg, and became a pastor there in 1851. In 1864, he was appointed Professor of Pastoral Theology in Strasbourg despite some opposition from the orthodox faction in Paris, which was gaining strength at the time. The events of 1870 left him without a job. As he had no chance of being appointed to a pastorate in France, he became a merchant. Due to some unfortunate business decisions, he lost all his assets. In 1875, he secured a position as a librarian at the Sorbonne. He passed away in 1888.

How far was Jesus a Jew? That was the starting-point of Colani's study. According to him there was a complete lack of homogeneity in the Messianic hopes cherished by the Jewish people in the time of Jesus, since the prophetic conception, according to which the Kingdom of the Messiah belonged to the present world-order, and the apocalyptic, which transferred it to the future age, had not yet been brought into any kind of unity. The general expectation was focused rather upon the Forerunner than upon the Messiah. Jesus Himself in the first period of His public ministry, up to Mark viii., had never designated Himself as the Messiah, for the expression Son of Man carried no Messianic associations for the multitude. His fundamental thought was that of perfect communion with God; only little by little, as the success of the preaching of the Kingdom more and more impressed His mind, did His consciousness take on a Messianic colouring. In face of the undisciplined expectations of the people He constantly repeats in His parables of the growth of the Kingdom, the word “patience.” By revealing Himself as the Lord of this spiritual kingdom He makes an end of the oscillation between the sensuous and the spiritual in the current expectations of the future blessedness. He points to mankind as a whole, not merely to the chosen people, as the people of the Kingdom, and substitutes for the apocalyptic catastrophe an organic development. By His interpretation of Psalm cx., in Mark xii. 35-37, He makes known that the Messiah has nothing whatever to do with the Davidic kingship. It was only with difficulty that He came to resolve to accept the title of Messiah; He knew what a weight of national prejudices and national hopes hung upon it.

How Jewish was Jesus? That was the starting point of Colani's study. He believed there was a complete lack of uniformity in the Messianic hopes held by the Jewish people during Jesus' time. The prophetic view, which saw the Kingdom of the Messiah as part of the current world, and the apocalyptic view, which pushed it to the future, had not yet been unified in any way. The general expectation was more focused on the Forerunner than the Messiah. During the early part of His public ministry, up to Mark viii., Jesus never referred to Himself as the Messiah, because the term Son of Man didn’t carry any Messianic meaning for the crowd. His main focus was perfect communion with God; it was only gradually, as the success of His preaching about the Kingdom impacted Him more, that His awareness began to take on a Messianic tone. In response to the disorganized expectations of the people, He repeatedly uses the word "patience." By revealing Himself as the Lord of this spiritual kingdom, He ends the conflict between the physical and spiritual aspects of current hopes for future happiness. He points to humanity as a whole, rather than just the chosen people, as the recipients of the Kingdom, and replaces the apocalyptic disaster with natural growth. In His interpretation of Psalm cx. in Mark xii. 35-37, He shows that the Messiah is not connected to the Davidic kingship at all. He only reluctantly accepted the title of Messiah; he was aware of the heavy burden of national biases and expectations that came with it.

But He is “Messiah the Son of Man”; He created this expression in order thereby to make known His lowliness. In the moment in which He accepted the office He registered the resolve [pg 224] to suffer. His purpose is, to be the suffering, not the triumphant, Messiah. It is to the influence which His Passion exercises upon the souls of men that He looks for the firm establishment of His Kingdom.

But He is "Messiah, Son of Man"; He created this term to show His humility. The moment He accepted this role, He made the decision [pg 224] to suffer. His goal is to be the suffering, not the triumphant, Messiah. He relies on the impact of His Passion on people's souls for the solid establishment of His Kingdom.

This spiritual conception of the Kingdom cannot possibly be combined with the thought of a glorious Second Coming, for if Jesus had held this latter view He must necessarily have thought of the present life as only a kind of prologue to that second existence. Neither the Jewish, nor the Jewish-Christian eschatology as represented in the eschatological discourses in the Gospels, can, therefore, in Colani's opinion, belong to the preaching of Jesus. That He should sometimes have made use of the imagery associated with the Jewish expectations of the future is, of course, only natural. But the eschatology occupies far too important a place in the tradition of the preaching of Jesus to be explained as a mere symbolical mode of expression. It forms a substantial element of that preaching. A spiritualisation of it will not meet the case. Therefore, if the conviction has been arrived at on other grounds that Jesus' preaching did not follow the lines of Jewish eschatology, there is only one possible way of dealing with it, and that is by excising it from the text on critical grounds.

This spiritual understanding of the Kingdom can't be combined with the idea of a glorious Second Coming. If Jesus believed in that view, He would have seen this life as just a prelude to a second existence. According to Colani, neither Jewish nor Jewish-Christian eschatology, as depicted in the eschatological teachings in the Gospels, can be considered part of Jesus' preaching. It's natural that He sometimes used imagery linked to Jewish expectations about the future. However, eschatology plays too significant a role in the tradition of Jesus' teachings to be dismissed as just a symbolic way of expressing ideas. It is a key component of His message. Simply spiritualizing it won’t suffice. If it's been concluded from other evidence that Jesus' preaching didn’t align with Jewish eschatology, the only way to address this is by critically removing it from the text.

The only element in the preaching of Jesus which can, in Colani's opinion, be called in any sense “eschatological” was the conviction that there would be a wide extension of the Gospel even within the existing generation, that Gentiles should be admitted to the Kingdom, and that in consequence of the general want of receptivity towards the message of salvation, judgment should come upon the nations.

The only aspect of Jesus's preaching that Colani thinks can be considered “eschatological” is the belief that the Gospel will spread widely, even among people alive at that time, that non-Jews would be welcomed into the Kingdom, and that, due to the overall lack of acceptance of the message of salvation, judgment would come upon the nations.

These views of Colani furnish him with a basis upon which to decide on the genuineness or otherwise of the eschatological discourses. Among the sayings put into the mouth of Jesus which must be rejected as impossible are: the promise, in the discourse at the sending forth of the Twelve, of the imminent coming of the Son of Man, Matt. x. 23; the promise to the disciples that they should sit upon twelve thrones judging the tribes of Israel, Matt. xix. 28; the saying about His return in Matt. xxiii. 39; the final eschatological saying at the Last Supper, Matt. xxvi. 29, “the Papias-like Chiliasm of which is unworthy of Jesus”; and the prediction of His coming on the clouds of heaven with which He closes His Messianic confession before the Council. The apocalyptic discourses in Mark xiii., Matt. xxiv., and Luke xxi. are interpolated. A Jewish-Christian apocalypse of the first century, probably composed before the destruction of Jerusalem, has been interwoven with a short exhortation which Jesus gave on the occasion when He predicted the destruction of the temple.

These views of Colani provide him with a foundation to determine the authenticity of the eschatological teachings. Among the statements attributed to Jesus that must be dismissed as impossible are: the promise made during the sending out of the Twelve about the imminent arrival of the Son of Man, Matt. x. 23; the promise to the disciples that they would sit on twelve thrones judging the tribes of Israel, Matt. xix. 28; the statement regarding His return in Matt. xxiii. 39; the final eschatological statement at the Last Supper, Matt. xxvi. 29, "the Papias-like Chiliasm that is unworthy of Jesus"; and the prediction of His coming on the clouds of heaven, which concludes His Messianic confession before the Council. The apocalyptic teachings in Mark xiii., Matt. xxiv., and Luke xxi. have been added later. A Jewish-Christian apocalypse from the first century, likely written before the destruction of Jerusalem, has been woven together with a brief exhortation that Jesus gave when He predicted the destruction of the temple.

According to Colani, therefore, Jesus did not expect to come [pg 225] again from Heaven to complete His work. It was completed by His death, and the purpose of the coming of the Spirit was to make manifest its completion. Strauss and Renan had entered upon the path of explaining Jesus' preaching from the history of the time by the assumption of an intermixture in it of Jewish ideas, but it was now recognised “that this path is a cul-de-sac, and that criticism must turn round and get out of it as quickly as possible.”

According to Colani, Jesus didn't expect to come [pg 225] back from Heaven to finish His work. It was completed with His death, and the purpose of the Spirit's arrival was to show that it was done. Strauss and Renan had started to explain Jesus' teachings by looking at the history of the time, assuming it mixed with Jewish ideas, but it was now acknowledged "that this path leads nowhere, and that criticism needs to turn back and leave it as soon as possible."

The new feature of Colani's view was not so much the uncompromising rejection of eschatology as the clear recognition that its rejection was not a matter to be disposed of in a phrase or two, but necessitated a critical analysis of the text.

The new aspect of Colani's perspective wasn't just a straightforward dismissal of eschatology; it was the clear acknowledgment that rejecting it couldn't be summed up in a couple of phrases. Instead, it required a thorough analysis of the text.

The systematic investigation of the Synoptic apocalypse was a contribution to criticism of the utmost importance.

The thorough study of the Synoptic apocalypse was a highly significant contribution to criticism.


In the year 1882 Volkmar took up this attempt afresh, at least in its main features.151 His construction rests upon two main points of support; upon his view of the sources and his conception of the eschatology of the time of Jesus. In his view the sole source for the Life of Jesus is the Gospel of Mark, which was “probably written exactly in the year 73,” five years after the Johannine apocalypse.

In 1882, Volkmar renewed this effort, focusing primarily on two key aspects: his perspective on the sources and his understanding of the eschatology during Jesus' time. He argues that the only source for the Life of Jesus is the Gospel of Mark, which was “likely written in the year 73,” five years after the Johannine apocalypse.

The other two of the first three Gospels belong to the second century, and can only be used by way of supplement. Luke dates from the beginning of the first decade of the century; while Matthew is regarded by Volkmar, as by Wilke, as being a combination of Mark and Luke, and is relegated to the end of this first decade. The work is in his opinion a revision of the Gospel tradition “in the spirit of that primitive Christianity which, while constantly opposing the tendency of the apostle of the Gentiles to make light of the Law, was nevertheless so far universalistic that, starting from the old legal ground, it made the first steps towards a catholic unity.” Once Matthew has been set aside in this way, the literary elimination of the eschatology follows as a matter of course; the much smaller element of discourse in Mark can offer no serious resistance.

The other two of the first three Gospels come from the second century and can only be used as a supplement. Luke is from the beginning of the first decade of that century, while Matthew is seen by Volkmar, as well as by Wilke, as a mix of Mark and Luke, and is placed at the end of this first decade. In his view, the work is a revision of the Gospel tradition "in the spirit of that early Christianity which, while consistently challenging the apostle of the Gentiles' tendency to downplay the Law, was still universal enough that it began from the old legal foundation and took the first steps toward a unified faith." Once Matthew is set aside in this way, the removal of eschatology follows naturally; the much smaller amount of discourse in Mark doesn’t pose any serious challenge.

As regards the Messianic expectations of the time, they were, in Volkmar's opinion, such that Jesus could not possibly have come [pg 226] forward with Messianic claims. The Messianic Son of Man, whose aim was to found a super-earthly Kingdom, only arose in Judaism under the influence of Christian dogma. The contemporaries of Jesus knew only the political ideal of the Messianic King. And woe to any one who conjured up these hopes! The Baptist had done so by his too fervent preaching about repentance and the Kingdom, and had been promptly put out of the way by the Tetrarch. The version found even in Mark, which represents that it was on Herodias' account, and at her daughter's petition, that John was beheaded, is a later interpretation which, according to Volkmar, is evidently false on chronological grounds, since the Baptist was dead before Herod took Herodias as his wife. Had Jesus desired the Messiahship, He could only have claimed it in this political sense. The alternative is to suppose that He did not desire it.

Regarding the Messianic expectations of the time, Volkmar believes that Jesus could not have made any Messianic claims. The Messianic Son of Man, whose purpose was to establish a heavenly Kingdom, only emerged in Judaism under the influence of Christian teachings. The people living during Jesus' time were only aware of the political idea of the Messianic King. And woe to anyone who raised these hopes! The Baptist had done this with his intense preaching about repentance and the Kingdom and was quickly silenced by the Tetrarch. The account found even in Mark, which suggests that John was beheaded on the advice of Herodias and her daughter, is a later interpretation that, according to Volkmar, is clearly incorrect based on the timeline, since the Baptist was dead before Herod married Herodias. If Jesus had wanted to be the Messiah, he could only have claimed it in a political sense. The other possibility is that he didn't want it at all.

Volkmar's contribution to the subject consists in the formulating of this clean-cut alternative. Colani had indeed recognised the alternative, but had not taken up a consistent attitude in regard to it. Here, that way of escape from the difficulty is barred, which suggests that Jesus set Himself up as Messiah, but in another than the popular sense. What may be called Jesus' Messianic consciousness consisted solely “in knowing Himself to be first-born among many brethren, the Son of God after the Spirit, and consequently feeling Himself enabled and impelled to bring about that regeneration of His people which alone could make it worthy of deliverance.” It is in any case clearly evident from Paul, from the Apocalypse, and from Mark, “the three documentary witnesses emanating from the circle of the followers of Jesus during the first century, that it was only after His crucifixion that Jesus was hailed as the Christ; never during His earthly life.” The elimination of the eschatology thus leads also to the elimination of the Messiahship of Jesus.

Volkmar's contribution to the topic involves presenting this clear-cut alternative. Colani had indeed recognized the alternative, but he didn’t adopt a consistent stance towards it. Here, the idea that Jesus positioned Himself as the Messiah—though in a different sense than what was commonly understood—is ruled out. What we can refer to as Jesus' Messianic awareness was simply about “knowing Himself to be the first-born among many siblings, the Son of God in the Spirit, and therefore feeling capable and driven to bring about the regeneration of His people that was necessary for their deliverance.” It is evident from Paul, the Apocalypse, and Mark, “the three documentary witnesses from the circle of Jesus’ followers in the first century,” that it was only after His crucifixion that Jesus was recognized as the Christ; it never happened during His lifetime. Thus, removing the eschatology also results in the removal of Jesus' role as the Messiah.

If we are told in Mark viii. 29 that Simon Peter was the first among men to hail Jesus as the Messiah, it is to be noticed, Volkmar points out, that the Evangelist places this confession at a time when Jesus' work was over and the thought of His Passion first appears; and if we desire fully to understand the author's purpose we must fix our attention on the Lord's command not to make known His Messiahship until after His resurrection (Mark viii. 30, ix. 9 and 10), which is a hint that we are to date Jesus' Messiahship from His death. For Mark is no mere naïve chronicler, but a conscious artist interpreting the history; sometimes, indeed, a powerful epic writer in whose work the historical and the poetic are intermingled.

If we look at Mark 8:29, we see that Simon Peter was the first to recognize Jesus as the Messiah. It’s important to note, as Volkmar points out, that the Gospel writer mentions this confession at a time when Jesus’ mission was coming to an end and the idea of His suffering was just beginning to emerge. To fully grasp the author’s intent, we need to focus on Jesus’ instruction not to reveal His identity as the Messiah until after His resurrection (Mark 8:30, 9:9-10). This suggests that we should consider Jesus’ role as Messiah from the point of His death. Mark is not just an unthinking recorder of events; he’s a deliberate artist who interprets history, and at times, he is a powerful epic writer where the historical and the poetic blend together.

Thus the conclusion is that Mark, in agreement with Paul, represents Jesus as becoming the Messiah only as a consequence of His resurrection. He really appeared, and His first appearance [pg 227] was to Peter. When Peter on that night of terror fled from Jerusalem to take refuge in Galilee, Jesus, according to the mystic prediction of Mark xiv. 28 and xvi. 7, went before him. “He was constantly present to his spirit, until on the third day He manifested Himself before his eyes, in the heavenly appearance which was also vouchsafed to the last of the apostles 'as he was in the way'—and Peter, enraptured, gave expression to the clear conviction with which the whole life of Jesus had inspired him in the cry 'Thou art the Christ.'”

So, the conclusion is that Mark, in agreement with Paul, shows Jesus becoming the Messiah only as a result of His resurrection. He truly appeared, and His first appearance [pg 227] was to Peter. When Peter fled from Jerusalem to seek safety in Galilee on that terrifying night, Jesus, in line with the mystical predictions from Mark xiv. 28 and xvi. 7, went ahead of him. “He was always in tune with His spirit until, on the third day, He revealed Himself to Peter in a heavenly form that was also shown to the last of the apostles 'as he was on his way.' Overwhelmed, Peter expressed the profound conviction that the entire life of Jesus had instilled in him by proclaiming, 'You are the Christ.'”

The historical Jesus therefore founded a community of followers without advancing any claims to the Messiahship. He desired only to be a reformer, the spiritual deliverer of the people of God, to realise upon earth the Kingdom of God which they were all seeking in the beyond, and to extend the reign of God over all nations. “The Kingdom of God is doubtless to win its final and decisive victory by the almighty aid of God; our duty is to see to its beginnings”—that is, according to Volkmar, the lesson which Jesus teaches us in the parable of the Sower. The ethic of this Kingdom was not yet confused by any eschatological ideas. It was only when, as the years went on, the expectation of the Parousia rose to a high pitch of intensity that “marriage and the bringing up of children came to be regarded as superfluous, and were consequently thought of as signs of an absorption in earthly interests which was out of harmony with the near approach to the goal of these hopes.” Jesus had renewed the foundations on which “the family” was based and had made it, in turn, a corner stone of the Kingdom of God, even as He had consecrated the common meal by making it a love feast.

The historical Jesus established a community of followers without claiming to be the Messiah. He aimed to be a reformer, the spiritual deliverer of God's people, to bring about the Kingdom of God on earth that they were all longing for in the afterlife, and to expand God's reign over all nations. "The Kingdom of God will definitely reach its ultimate and decisive victory with God's all-powerful help; our role is to ensure its beginnings." This, according to Volkmar, is the lesson Jesus teaches us in the parable of the Sower. The ethics of this Kingdom weren't yet mixed up with any apocalyptic ideas. It was only later, as the years passed and the anticipation of the Parousia intensified, that "Marriage and raising children were considered unnecessary, and therefore seen as signs of being overly focused on worldly matters, which conflicted with the upcoming fulfillment of these aspirations." Jesus had revitalized the foundations of "the family" and had made it a cornerstone of the Kingdom of God, just as He had sanctified the shared meal by turning it into a love feast.

In most things Jesus was conservative. The ritual worship of the God of Israel remained for Him always a sacred thing. But in spite of that He withdrew more and more from the synagogue, the scene of His earliest preaching, and taught in the houses of His disciples. “He had learned to fulfil the law as implicit in one highest commandment and supreme principle, therefore 'in spirit and in truth'; but He never, as appears from all the evidence, declared it to be abolished.” “We may be equally certain, however, that Jesus, while He asserted the abiding validity of the Ten Commandments, never explicitly declared that of the Mosaic Law as a whole. The absence of any such saying from the tradition regarding Jesus made it possible for Paul to take his decisive step forward.”

In most respects, Jesus was a traditionalist. The ritual worship of the God of Israel always held significant meaning for Him. However, He began to distance Himself from the synagogue, where He initially preached, and started teaching in the homes of His disciples. “He had come to understand the law through one main commandment and supreme principle, which is 'in spirit and in truth'; however, He never, as shown by all accounts, claimed that it was abolished.” "We can also be sure that while Jesus confirmed the continued importance of the Ten Commandments, He never clearly stated that the entire Mosaic Law still applied. The absence of such a declaration in the stories about Jesus allowed Paul to make his important progress."

As regards the Gospel discourses about the Parousia, it is easy to recognise that, even in Mark, these “are one and all the work of the narrator, whose purpose is edification. He connects his work as closely as possible with the Apocalypse, which had appeared some five years earlier, in order to emphasise, in contrast to it, the [pg 228] higher truth.” Jesus' own hope, in all its clearness and complete originality, is recorded in the parables of the seed growing secretly and the grain of mustard seed, and in the saying about the immortality of His words. Nothing beyond this is in any way certain, however remarkable the saying in Mark ix. 1 may be, that the looked-for consummation is to take place during the lifetime of the existing generation.

Regarding the Gospel discussions about the Second Coming, it's clear that, even in Mark, these “are all the work of the narrator, whose goal is to build up faith. He connects his work as closely as possible with the Apocalypse, which had appeared about five years earlier, in order to highlight, in contrast to it, the higher truth.” Jesus' own hope, in all its clarity and originality, is captured in the parables of the seed growing secretly and the mustard seed, as well as in the statement about the immortality of His words. However, nothing beyond this is certain, no matter how striking the statement in Mark ix. 1 may be, that the anticipated fulfillment is meant to occur during the lifetime of the current generation.

“It is only the fact that Mark is preceded by 'the book of the Birth (and History) of Christ according to Matthew'—not only in the Scriptures, but also in men's minds, which were dominated by it as the ‘first Gospel’—which has caused it to be taken as self-evident that Jesus, knowing Himself from the first to be the Messiah, expected His Parousia solely from heaven, and therefore with, or in, the clouds of heaven.... But since He who was thought of as by birth the Son of God, is now thought of as the Son of Man, born an Israelite, and becoming the Son of God after the spirit only at His baptism, the hope that looks to the clouds of heaven cannot be, or at least ought not to be, any longer explained otherwise than as an enthusiastic dream.”

The reason Mark is introduced with 'the book of the Birth (and History) of Christ according to Matthew'—not just in the Scriptures, but also in people's minds, which were influenced by it as the ‘first Gospel’—has led to the idea that Jesus, knowing from the start that He was the Messiah, expected His return only from heaven, and therefore in the clouds of heaven.... However, since He who was initially seen as the Son of God by birth is now viewed as the Son of Man, who was born an Israelite and became the Son of God only in spirit at His baptism, the expectation of looking to the clouds of heaven can’t be seen in any way other than as an enthusiastic dream.

If, even at the beginning of the 'eighties, a so extreme theory on the other side could, without opposition, occupy all the points of vantage, it is evident that the theory which gave eschatology its due place was making but slow progress. It was not that any one had been disputing the ground with it, but that all its operations were characterised by a nervous timidity. And these hesitations are not to be laid to the account of those who did not perceive the approach of the decisive conflict, or refused to accept battle, like the followers of Reuss, for instance, who were satisfied with the hypothesis that thoughts about the Last Judgment had forced their way into the authentic discourses of Jesus about the destruction of the city;152 even those who like Weiffenbach are fully convinced that “the eschatological question, and in particular the question of the Second Coming, which in many quarters has up to the present been treated as a noli me tangere, must sooner or later become the battle-ground of the greatest and most decisive of theological controversies”—even those who shared this conviction stopped half-way on the road on which they had entered.

If, even at the beginning of the '80s, such an extreme theory could, without opposition, take hold of all the key positions, it’s clear that the theory acknowledging eschatology's rightful place was advancing very slowly. It wasn’t that anyone was openly challenging it, but rather that all its actions were marked by a nervous hesitance. These uncertainties can’t be blamed on those who didn’t see the decisive conflict approaching or who refused to engage, like the followers of Reuss, who were content with the idea that thoughts about the Last Judgment had squeezed into the authentic teachings of Jesus regarding the city's destruction; 152 even those like Weiffenbach, who are fully convinced that "The eschatological question, especially regarding the Second Coming, which in many contexts has been treated like a noli me tangere, will inevitably turn into the battleground for the biggest and most crucial theological debates."—even those who shared this belief faltered midway on the path they had started.


Weiffenbach's153 work, “Jesus' Conception of His Second Coming,” published in 1873, sums up the results of the previous discussions of the subject. He names as among those who ascribe the [pg 229] expectation of the Parousia, in the sensuous form in which it meets us in the documents, to a misunderstanding of the teaching of Jesus on the part of the disciples and the writers who were dependent upon them—Schleiermacher, Bleek, Holtzmann, Schenkel, Colani, Baur, Hase, and Meyer. Among those who maintained that the Parousia formed an integral part of Jesus' teaching, he cites Keim, Weizsäcker, Strauss, and Renan. He considers that the readiest way to advance the discussion will be by undertaking a critical review of the attempt to analyse the great Synoptic discourse about the future in which Colani had led the way.

Weiffenbach's153 work, "Jesus' View on His Second Coming," published in 1873, summarizes the outcomes of earlier discussions on the topic. He identifies several scholars who attribute the expectation of the Parousia, in the tangible form presented in the documents, to a misunderstanding of Jesus' teachings by the disciples and the writers who followed them—Schleiermacher, Bleek, Holtzmann, Schenkel, Colani, Baur, Hase, and Meyer. Among those who argued that the Parousia was a vital part of Jesus' teaching, he mentions Keim, Weizsäcker, Strauss, and Renan. He believes that the best way to move the discussion forward is by conducting a critical review of the efforts to analyze the significant Synoptic discourse about the future in which Colani had pioneered.

The question of the Parousia is like, Weiffenbach suggests, a vessel which has become firmly wedged between rocks. Any attempt to get it afloat again will be useless until a new channel is found for it. His detailed discussions are devoted to endeavouring to discover the relation between the declarations regarding the Second Coming and the predictions of the Passion. In the course of his analysis of the great prophetic discourse he rejects the suggestion made by Weisse in his Evangelienfrage of 1856, that the eschatological character of the discourse results from the way in which it is put together; that while the sayings in their present mosaic-like combination certainly have a reference to the last things, each of them individually in its original context might well bear a natural sense. In Colani's hypothesis of conflation the suggestion was to be rejected that it was not “Ur-Markus,” but the author of the Synoptic apocalypse who was responsible for the working in of the “Little Apocalypse.”154 It was an unsatisfactory feature of Weizsäcker's position155 that he insisted on regarding the “Little Apocalypse” as Jewish, not Jewish-Christian; Pfleiderer had distinguished sharply what belongs to the Evangelist from the “Little Apocalypse,” and had sought to prove that the purpose of the Evangelist in thus breaking up the latter and working it into a discourse of Jesus was to tone down the eschatological hopes expressed in the discourse, because they had remained unfulfilled even at the fall of Jerusalem, and to retard the rapid development of the apocalyptic process by inserting between its successive phases passages from a different discourse.156 Weiffenbach carries this series of tentative suggestions to its logical conclusion, advancing the view that the link of connexion between [pg 230] the Jewish-Christian Apocalypse and the Gospel material in which it is embedded is the thought of the Second Coming. This was the thought which gave the impulse from without towards the transmutation of Jewish into Jewish-Christian eschatology. Jesus must have given expression to the thought of His near return; and Jewish-Christianity subsequently painted it over with the colours of Jewish eschatology.

The question of the Parousia is like a vessel that has gotten stuck between rocks, as Weiffenbach suggests. Any attempt to set it afloat again will be useless until a new channel is found. His detailed discussions focus on discovering the relationship between the claims about the Second Coming and the predictions of the Passion. Throughout his analysis of the great prophetic discourse, he dismisses the suggestion made by Weisse in his Gospel question of 1856. Weisse argued that the eschatological nature of the discourse comes from how it's structured; while the sayings in their current mosaic-like form do refer to the end times, each one in its original context could have a straightforward meaning. Colani's hypothesis of conflation also rejects the idea that it was not “Original Markus,” but the author of the Synoptic apocalypse who integrated the “Small Apocalypse.”154 A troublesome aspect of Weizsäcker's position155 was his insistence on viewing the "Mini Apocalypse" as Jewish, rather than Jewish-Christian. Pfleiderer had clearly separated what belongs to the Evangelist from the “Little Apocalypse,” arguing that the Evangelist's purpose in breaking up the latter and incorporating it into a discourse of Jesus was to downplay the eschatological hopes expressed in the discourse, since they remained unfulfilled even at the fall of Jerusalem, and to slow the rapid development of the apocalyptic process by inserting excerpts from a different discourse between its successive phases.156 Weiffenbach takes this series of tentative suggestions to its logical conclusion by proposing that the connection between [pg 230] the Jewish-Christian Apocalypse and the Gospel material in which it is embedded is the concept of the Second Coming. This idea provided the external impetus for transforming Jewish into Jewish-Christian eschatology. Jesus must have expressed the idea of His imminent return; and Jewish-Christianity later embellished it with elements of Jewish eschatology.

In developing this theory, Weiffenbach thought that he had succeeded in solving the problem which had been first critically formulated by Keim, who is constantly emphasising the idea that the eschatological hopes of the disciples could not be explained merely from their Judaic pre-suppositions, but that some incentive to the formation of these hopes must be sought in the preaching of Jesus; otherwise primitive Christianity and the life of Jesus would stand side by side unconnected and unexplained, and in that case we must give up all hope “of distinguishing the sure word of the Lord from Israel's restless speculations about the future.”

In developing this theory, Weiffenbach believed he had successfully addressed the issue first critically outlined by Keim, who continually emphasized that the eschatological hopes of the disciples couldn't be solely explained by their Jewish background. Instead, some motivation for these hopes had to be found in Jesus' teachings; otherwise, primitive Christianity and Jesus' life would appear disconnected and incomprehensible. In that case, we would lose all hope "of recognizing the true word of the Lord from Israel's anxious thoughts about what’s to come."

When the Jewish-Christian Apocalypse has been eliminated, we arrive at a discourse, spoken on the Mount of Olives, in which Jesus exhorted His disciples to watchfulness, in view of the near, but nevertheless undefined, hour of the return of “the Master of the House.”

When the Jewish-Christian Apocalypse is gone, we come to a conversation that took place on the Mount of Olives, where Jesus urged His disciples to stay alert, considering the imminent, yet still unclear, time of the return of “the Head of the House.”

In this discourse, therefore, we have a standard by which criticism may test all the eschatological sayings and discourses. Weiffenbach has the merit of having gathered together all the eschatological material of the Synoptics and examined it in the light of a definite principle. In Colani the material was incomplete, and instead of a critical principle he offered only an arbitrary exegesis which permitted him, for example, to conceive the watchfulness on which the eschatological parables constantly insist as only a vivid expression for the sense of responsibility “which weighs upon the life of man.”

In this discussion, we have a standard that allows us to evaluate all the eschatological statements and discussions. Weiffenbach deserves credit for compiling all the eschatological content from the Synoptics and analyzing it through a clear principle. Colani's material was lacking, and instead of a critical approach, he provided only a subjective interpretation that allowed him, for instance, to view the emphasis on watchfulness in the eschatological parables merely as a vivid expression of the sense of responsibility "that burdens human life."

And yet the outcome of this attempt of Weiffenbach's, which begins with so much real promise, is in the end wholly unsatisfactory. The “authentic thought of the return” which he takes as his standard has for its sole content the expectation of a visible personal return in the near future “free from all more or less fantastic apocalyptic and Jewish-Christian speculations about the future.” That is to say, the whole of the eschatological discourses of Jesus are to be judged by the standard of a colourless, unreal figment of theology. Whatever cannot be squared with that is to be declared spurious and cut away! Accordingly the eschatological closing saying at the Last Supper is stigmatised as a “Chiliastic-Capernaitic”157 distortion of a “normal” promise of the Second Coming; the idea of the παλιγγενεσία, Matt. xix. 28, is said to be [pg 231] wholly foreign to Jesus' world of thought; it is impossible, too, that Jesus can have thought of Himself as the Judge of the world, for the Jewish and Jewish-Christian eschatology does not ascribe the conduct of the Last Judgment to the Messiah; that is first done by Gentile Christians, and especially by Paul. It was, therefore, the later eschatology which set the Son of Man on the throne of His glory and prepared “the twelve thrones of judgment for the disciples.” The historian ought only to admit such of the sayings about bearing rule in the Messianic Kingdom as can be interpreted in a spiritual, non-sensuous fashion.

And yet the outcome of Weiffenbach's attempt, which starts with such great promise, ultimately falls short. The “genuine thought of the return” he uses as his benchmark is solely focused on the expectation of a visible personal return in the near future "free from all kinds of more or less unrealistic apocalyptic and Jewish-Christian theories about the future." In other words, the entire eschatological teachings of Jesus are judged by the standard of a dull, unrealistic theological concept. Anything that doesn't fit with that is considered fake and discarded! As a result, the eschatological closing statement at the Last Supper is labeled a “Chiliastic-Capernaitic” distortion of a "standard" promise of the Second Coming. The idea of the παλιγγενεσία, Matt. xix. 28, is claimed to be [pg 231] completely foreign to Jesus' worldview. It is also said that Jesus couldn't have seen Himself as the Judge of the world because Jewish and Jewish-Christian eschatology does not assign the task of the Last Judgment to the Messiah; that role is first given to Gentile Christians, particularly Paul. Therefore, it was the later eschatology that placed the Son of Man on His glorious throne and prepared "the twelve thrones of judgment for the disciples." Historians should only accept those sayings about ruling in the Messianic Kingdom that can be interpreted in a spiritual, non-literal way.

In the end Weiffenbach's critical principle proves to be merely a bludgeon with which he goes seal-hunting and clubs the defenceless Synoptic sayings right and left. When his work is done you see before you a desert island strewn with quivering corpses. Nevertheless the slaughter was not aimless, or at least it was not without result.

In the end Weiffenbach's critical principle turns out to be just a heavy tool he uses for seal-hunting, striking the defenseless Synoptic sayings indiscriminately. When he's finished, you're left looking at a barren island covered in trembling bodies. However, the killing wasn't pointless, or at least it wasn't without consequence.

In the first place, it did really appear, as a by-product of the critical processes, that Jesus' discourses about the future had nothing to do with an historical prevision of the destruction of Jerusalem, whereas the supposition that they had, had hitherto been taken as self-evident, the prediction of the destruction of Jerusalem being regarded as the historic nucleus of Jesus' discourses regarding the future, to which the idea of the Last Judgment had subsequently attached itself.

In the first place, it really seemed that Jesus' talks about the future had nothing to do with a historical prediction of the destruction of Jerusalem, even though people had previously assumed that they did. The prediction of Jerusalem's destruction was seen as the key part of Jesus' discussions about the future, to which the concept of the Last Judgment was later connected.

Here, then, we have the introduction of the converse opinion, which was subsequently established as correct; namely, that Jesus foresaw, indeed, the Last Judgment, but not the historical destruction of Jerusalem.

Here, then, we have the introduction of the opposing view, which was later confirmed as accurate; specifically, that Jesus foresaw the Last Judgment but did not foresee the historical destruction of Jerusalem.

In the next place, in the course of his critical examination of the eschatological material, Weiffenbach stumbles upon the discourse at the sending forth of the Twelve in Matt. x., and finds himself face to face with the fact that the discourse which he was expected to regard as a discourse of instruction was really nothing of the kind, but a collection of eschatological sayings. As he had taken over along with the Marcan hypothesis the closely connected view of the composite character of the Synoptic discourses, he does not allow himself to be misled, but regards this inappropriate charge to the Twelve as nothing else than an impossible anticipation and a bold anachronism. He knows that he is at one in this with Holtzmann, Colani, Bleek, Scholten, Meyer, and Keim, who also made the discourse of instruction end at the point beyond which they find it impossible to explain it, and regard the predictions of persecution as only possible in the later period of the life of Jesus. “For these predictions,” to express Weiffenbach's view in the words of Keim, “are too much at variance with the essentially gracious and happy mood which suggested the sending [pg 232] forth of the disciples, and reflect instead the lurid gloom of the fierce conflicts of the later period and the sadness of the farewell discourses.”

Next, during his critical examination of the eschatological material, Weiffenbach encounters the discourse at the sending out of the Twelve in Matt. x. He realizes that what he thought was a discourse of instruction is actually just a collection of eschatological sayings. Having adopted the Marcan hypothesis and the related idea of the composite nature of the Synoptic discourses, he doesn't let himself be misled. Instead, he sees this inappropriate charge to the Twelve as nothing more than an impossible prediction and a bold anachronism. He aligns himself with Holtzmann, Colani, Bleek, Scholten, Meyer, and Keim, who also conclude that the discourse of instruction ends at a point that makes it impossible to explain beyond that, viewing the predictions of persecution as only relevant in the later period of Jesus' life. “For these forecasts,” to put Weiffenbach's view in Keim's words, "are too different from the fundamentally gracious and happy mood that inspired the sending [pg 232] of the disciples, and instead convey the harsh darkness of the intense conflicts of the later period and the sadness of the farewell speeches."

It was a good thing that Bruno Bauer did not hear this chorus. If he had, he would have asked Weiffenbach and his allies whether the poor fragment that remained after the critical dissection of the “charge to the Twelve” was “a discourse of instruction,” and if in view of these difficulties they could not realise why he had refused, thirty years before, to believe in the “discourse of instruction.” But Bruno Bauer heard nothing: and so their blissful unconsciousness lasted for nearly a generation longer.

It was a good thing that Bruno Bauer didn’t hear this chorus. If he had, he would have asked Weiffenbach and his allies whether the poor fragment that remained after the critical breakdown of the "task for the Twelve" was “a guide to learning,” and if, considering these challenges, they couldn’t understand why he had refused, thirty years earlier, to believe in the "teaching discourse." But Bruno Bauer heard nothing, and so their blissful ignorance continued for nearly another generation.

The expectation of His Second Coming, repeatedly expressed by Jesus towards the close of His life, is on this hypothesis authentic; it was painted over by the primitive Christian community with the colours of its own eschatology, in consequence of the delay of the Parousia; and in view of the mission to the Gentiles a more cautious conception of the nearness of the time commended itself; nay, when Jerusalem had fallen and the “signs of the end” which had been supposed to be discovered in the horrors of the years 68 and 69 had passed without result, the return of Jesus was relegated to a distant future by the aid of the doctrine that the Gospel must first be preached to all the heathen. Thus the Parousia, which according to the Jewish-Christian eschatology belonged to the present age, was transferred to the future. “With this combination and making coincident—they were not so at the first—of the Second Coming, the end of the world, and the final Judgment, the idea of the Second Coming reached the last and highest stage of its development.”

The expectation of His Second Coming, which Jesus repeatedly mentioned toward the end of His life, is genuine based on this assumption; it was reshaped by the early Christian community with the ideas of its own beliefs about the end times, because of the delay in the return. Considering the mission to the Gentiles, a more cautious view of how soon that time might come became preferable; indeed, when Jerusalem fell and the “signs of the end” that were thought to be seen in the horrors of 68 and 69 ended up being unfulfilled, the return of Jesus was pushed to a far-off future, supported by the belief that the Gospel had to be preached to all non-believers first. Therefore, the Parousia, which in Jewish-Christian end-time beliefs was associated with the present age, was moved to the future. “With this combination and making coincident—they were not so at the first—of the Second Coming, the end of the world, and the final Judgment, the idea of the Second Coming reached the last and highest stage of its development.”

Weiffenbach's view, as we have seen, empties Jesus' expectation of His return of almost all its content, and to that is due the fact that his investigation did not prove so useful as it might have done. His purpose is, following suggestions thrown out by Schleiermacher and Weisse, to prove the identity of the predictions of the Second Coming and of the Resurrection, and he takes as his starting-point the observation that the conduct of the disciples after the death of Jesus forbids us to suppose that the Resurrection had been predicted in clear and unambiguous sayings, and that, on the other hand, the announcement of the Second Coming coincides in point of time with the predictions of the Resurrection, and the predictions both of the Second Coming and of the Resurrection stand in organic connexion with the announcement of His approaching death. The two are therefore identical.

Weiffenbach's view, as we've seen, strips Jesus' expectation of His return of almost all its meaning, which is why his investigation wasn't as helpful as it could have been. His aim, following suggestions made by Schleiermacher and Weisse, is to demonstrate that the predictions of the Second Coming and the Resurrection are the same. He starts with the observation that the disciples' behavior after Jesus' death makes it hard to believe that the Resurrection was clearly and unambiguously predicted. At the same time, the announcement of the Second Coming occurs around the same time as the predictions of the Resurrection, and both predictions are closely linked to the announcement of His imminent death. Therefore, they are essentially the same.

It was only after the death of their Master that the disciples differentiated the thought of the Resurrection from that of the Second Coming. The Resurrection did not bring them that which the Second Coming had promised; but it produced the result that the eschatological hopes, which Jesus had with difficulty succeeded [pg 233] in damping, flamed up again in the hearts of His disciples. The spiritual presence of the Deliverer who had manifested Himself to them did not seem to them to be the fulfilment of the promise of the Second Coming; but the expectation of the latter, being brought into contact with the flame of eschatological hope with which their hearts were a-fire, was fused, and cast into a form quite different from that in which it had been derived from the words of Jesus.

It was only after their Master died that the disciples began to separate the idea of the Resurrection from that of the Second Coming. The Resurrection didn’t deliver what the Second Coming had promised; instead, it reignited the eschatological hopes that Jesus had struggled to quell in their hearts. The spiritual presence of the Deliverer who had revealed Himself to them didn’t feel like the fulfillment of the Second Coming promise. However, when their expectation of the Second Coming met the intense eschatological hope burning within them, it transformed into something entirely different from what Jesus had originally conveyed.

That is all finely observed. For the first time it had dawned upon historical criticism that the great question is that concerning the identity or difference of the Parousia and the Resurrection. But the man who had been the first to grasp that thought, and who had undertaken his whole study with the special purpose of working it out, was too much under the influence of the spiritualised eschatology of Schleiermacher and Weisse to be able to assign the right values in the solution of his equation. And, withal, he is too much inclined to play the apologist as a subsidiary rôle. He is not content merely to render the history intelligible; he is, by his own confession, urged on by the hope that perhaps a way may be found of causing that “error” of Jesus to disappear and proving it to be an illusion due to the want of a sufficiently close study of His discourses. But the historian simply must not be an apologist; he must leave that to those who come after him and he may do so with a quiet mind, for the apologists, as we learn from the history of the Lives of Jesus, can get the better of any historical result whatever. It is, therefore, quite unnecessary that the historian should allow himself to be led astray by following an apologetic will-o'-the-wisp.

That is all well noted. For the first time, it has become clear to historical criticism that the big question is about the identity or difference between the Parousia and the Resurrection. However, the person who first captured this idea, and who dedicated his entire study to exploring it, was too influenced by the spiritualized eschatology of Schleiermacher and Weisse to assign the correct values in solving his equation. Additionally, he tends to take on the role of an apologist as a secondary task. He is not satisfied with simply making history understandable; he openly admits that he is motivated by the hope that perhaps a way can be found to make that “error” of Jesus disappear and prove it to be an illusion caused by insufficiently close study of His teachings. But a historian must not be an apologist; that role should be left to those who come after him, and he can do so with peace of mind because, as we see from the history of the Lives of Jesus, apologists can manipulate any historical findings. Therefore, it is entirely unnecessary for the historian to let himself be misled by chasing after an apologetic mirage.

Technically regarded, the mistake on which Weiffenbach's investigation made shipwreck was the failure to bring the Jewish apocalyptic material into relation with the Synoptic data. If he had done this, it would have been impossible for him to extract an absolutely unreal and unhistorical conception of the Second Coming out of the discourses of Jesus.

Technically speaking, the error that led to Weiffenbach's investigation failing was the inability to connect the Jewish apocalyptic material with the Synoptic data. If he had done this, he wouldn't have been able to derive an entirely unrealistic and unhistorical idea of the Second Coming from Jesus's teachings.


The task which Weiffenbach had neglected remained undone—to the detriment of theology—until Baldensperger158 repaired the omission. His book, “The Self-consciousness of Jesus in the Light of the Messianic Hopes of His Time,”159 published in 1888, made its impression by reason of the fullness of its material. Whereas Colani and Volkmar had still been able to deny the existence of [pg 234] a fully formed Messianic expectation in the time of Jesus, the genesis of the expectation was now fully traced out, and it was shown that the world of thought which meets us in Daniel had won the victory, that the “Son of Man” Messiah of the Similitudes of Enoch was the last product of the Messianic hope prior to the time of Jesus; and that therefore the fully developed Danielic scheme with its unbridgeable chasm between the present and the future world furnished the outline within which all further and more detailed traits were inserted. The honour of having effectively pioneered the way for this discovery belongs to Schürer.160 Baldensperger adopts his ideas, but sets them forth in a much more direct way, because he, in contrast with Schürer, gives no system of Messianic expectation—and there never in reality was a system—but is content to picture its many-sided growth.

The task that Weiffenbach neglected remained incomplete—affecting theology—until Baldensperger fixed the oversight. His book, “The Self-Awareness of Jesus in Relation to the Messianic Expectations of His Time,”159 published in 1888, made an impact due to the depth of its content. While Colani and Volkmar had previously been able to deny the presence of [pg 234] a fully formed Messianic expectation during Jesus's time, Baldensperger traced the origins of that expectation thoroughly. He demonstrated that the thought world we encounter in Daniel had triumphed, and that the "Son of Man" Messiah from the Similitudes of Enoch was the most recent product of the Messianic hope before Jesus’s era. Thus, the fully developed Danielic framework, with its unbridgeable gap between the present and the future world, provided the basis on which all additional and more specific features were added. The credit for effectively laying the groundwork for this discovery goes to Schürer.160 Baldensperger builds on his ideas but presents them in a much more straightforward manner. In contrast to Schürer, he does not provide a system of Messianic expectation—since there was never really a system—but instead focuses on illustrating its diverse development.

He does not, it is true, escape some minor inconsistencies. For example, the idea of a “political Messiahship,” which is really set aside by his historical treatment, crops up here and there, as though the author had not entirely got rid of it himself. But the impression made by the book as a whole was overpowering.

He does have some minor inconsistencies, it's true. For instance, the notion of a "political messiahship," which he mostly sets aside in his historical analysis, pops up now and then, as if the author hasn't completely let it go himself. Still, the overall impression of the book is overwhelmingly strong.

Nevertheless this book does not exactly fulfil the promise of its title, any more than Weiffenbach's. The reader expects that now at last Jesus' sayings about Himself will be consistently explained in the light of the Jewish Messianic ideas, but that is not done. For Baldensperger, instead of tracing down and working out the conception of the Kingdom of God held by Jesus as a product of the Jewish eschatology, at least by way of trying whether that method would suffice, takes it over direct from modern historical theology. He assumes as self-evident that Jesus' conception of the Kingdom of God had a double character, that the eschatological and spiritual elements were equally represented in it and mutually conditioned one another, and that Jesus therefore began, in pursuance of this conception, to found a spiritual invisible Kingdom, although He expected its fulfilment to be effected by supernatural means. Consequently there must also have been a [pg 235] duality in His religious consciousness, in which these two conceptions had to be combined. Jesus' Messianic consciousness sprang, according to Baldensperger, “from a religious root”; that is to say, the Messianic consciousness was a special modification of a self-consciousness in which a pure, spiritual, unique relation to God was the fundamental element; and from this arises the possibility of a spiritual transformation of the Jewish-Messianic self-consciousness. In making these assumptions, Baldensperger does not ask himself whether it is not possible that for Jesus the purely Jewish consciousness of a transcendental Messiahship may itself have been religious, nay even spiritual, just as well as the Messiahship resting on a vague, indefinite, colourless sense of union with God which modern theologians arbitrarily attribute to Him.

Nevertheless, this book doesn’t fully deliver on the promise of its title, any more than Weiffenbach's does. The reader expects that finally, Jesus' statements about Himself will be consistently explained in the context of Jewish Messianic ideas, but that doesn’t happen. Instead of exploring and developing Jesus' understanding of the Kingdom of God as a product of Jewish eschatology, at least to see if that approach might work, Baldensperger takes it directly from modern historical theology. He assumes it’s obvious that Jesus’ view of the Kingdom of God had a dual nature, with both eschatological and spiritual elements being equally represented and influencing each other. Therefore, Jesus began, in line with this understanding, to establish a spiritual, invisible Kingdom, even though He expected it to be realized through supernatural means. As a result, there must have been a duality in His religious awareness, where these two concepts needed to be integrated. According to Baldensperger, Jesus’ Messianic awareness originated “from a religious root”; that is, the Messianic consciousness was a unique variation of a self-awareness in which a pure, spiritual, exclusive relationship with God was fundamental. From this arises the possibility for a spiritual transformation of the Jewish-Messianic self-awareness. In making these assumptions, Baldensperger doesn’t consider whether it’s possible that, for Jesus, the purely Jewish understanding of a transcendent Messiah could also be religious, or even spiritual, just as the Messiahship based on a vague, undefined, bland sense of unity with God that modern theologians arbitrarily attribute to Him.

Again, instead of arriving at the two conceptions, Kingdom of God and Messianic consciousness, purely empirically, by an unbiased comparison of the Synoptic passages with the Late-Jewish conceptions, Baldensperger, in this following Holtzmann, brings them into his theory in the dual form in which contemporary theology, now becoming faintly tinged with eschatology, offered them to him. Consequently, everything has to be adapted to this duality. Jesus, for example, in applying to Himself the title Son of Man, thinks not only of the transcendental significance which it has in the Jewish apocalyptic, but gives it at the same time an ethico-religious colouring.

Once again, instead of arriving at the two ideas, the Kingdom of God and Messianic consciousness, through an unbiased comparison of the Synoptic passages with Late-Jewish concepts, Baldensperger, following Holtzmann, incorporates them into his theory in the dual form that contemporary theology, now slightly influenced by eschatology, presented to him. As a result, everything has to fit into this duality. For instance, when Jesus refers to Himself as the Son of Man, He is not only thinking about the transcendental meaning it holds in Jewish apocalyptic literature but is also giving it an ethical and religious dimension.

Finally, the duality is explained by an application of the genetic method, in which the “course of the development of the self-consciousness of Jesus” is traced out. The historical psychology of the Marcan hypothesis here shows its power of adapting itself to eschatology. From the first, to follow the course of Baldensperger's exposition, the eschatological view influenced Jesus' expectation of the Kingdom and His Messianic consciousness. In the wilderness, after the dawn of His Messianic consciousness at His baptism, He had rejected the ideal of the Messianic king of David's line and put away all warlike thoughts. Then He began to found the Kingdom of God by preaching. For a time the spiritualised idea of the Kingdom was dominant in His mind, the Messianic eschatological idea falling rather into the background.

Finally, the duality is explained through an application of the genetic method, which traces the “course of the development of Jesus’ self-consciousness.” The historical psychology of the Marcan hypothesis shows its ability to adapt to eschatology. From the start, following Baldensperger's exposition, the eschatological view shaped Jesus’ expectation of the Kingdom and His Messianic awareness. In the wilderness, after His Messianic awareness was awakened at His baptism, He rejected the idea of the Messianic king from David's lineage and dismissed all warlike thoughts. Then He began to establish the Kingdom of God through preaching. For a while, the spiritualized idea of the Kingdom was dominant in His mind, while the Messianic eschatological idea receded somewhat into the background.

But His silence regarding His Messianic office was partly due to paedagogic reasons, “since He desired to lead His hearers to a more spiritual conception of the Kingdom and so to obviate a possible political movement on their part and the consequent intervention of the Roman government.” In addition to this He had also personal reasons for not revealing Himself which only disappeared in the moment when His death and Second Coming became part of His plan; previous to that He did not know how and when the Kingdom was to come. Prior to the confession at [pg 236] Caesarea Philippi, the disciples “had only a faint and vague suspicion of the Messianic dignity of their Master.”

But His silence about His role as Messiah was partly for teaching reasons, "since He wanted to lead His listeners to a deeper spiritual understanding of the Kingdom and to avoid any possible political actions from them, along with the subsequent intervention of the Roman government." Additionally, He had personal reasons for not revealing Himself, which only disappeared when His death and Second Coming became part of His plan; before that, He didn't know how and when the Kingdom would arrive. Before the confession at [pg 236] Caesarea Philippi, the disciples "had a faint and unclear suspicion of their Master’s Messianic significance."

This was “rather the preparatory stage of His Messianic work.” Objectively, it may be described “as the period of growing emphasis upon the spiritual characteristics of the Kingdom, and of resigned waiting and watching for its outward manifestation in glory; subjectively, from the point of view of the self-consciousness of Jesus, it may be characterised as the period of the struggle between His religious conviction of His Messiahship and the traditional rationalistic Messianic belief.”

This was "more like the preparation for His Messianic mission." Objectively, it can be described “As the focus on the spiritual aspects of the Kingdom grows, along with a patient waiting and watching for its outward display in glory, it can be described, from Jesus’s self-awareness perspective, as a time of conflict between His religious belief in His Messiahship and the traditional rational view of the Messianic belief.”

This first period opens out into a second in which He had attained to perfect clearness of vision and complete inner harmony. By the acceptance of the idea of suffering, Jesus' inner peace is enhanced to the highest degree conceivable. “By throwing Himself upon the thought of death He escaped the lingering uncertainty as to when and how God would fulfil His promise....” “The coming of the Kingdom was fixed down to the Second Coming of the Messiah. Now He ventured to regard Himself as the Son of Man who was to be the future Judge of the world, for the suffering and dying Son of Man was closely associated with the Son of Man surrounded by the host of heaven. Would the people accept Him as Messiah? He now, in Jerusalem, put the question to them in all its sharpness and burning actuality; and the people were moved to enthusiasm. But so soon as they saw that He whom they had hailed with such acclamation was neither able nor willing to fulfil their ambitious dreams, a reaction set in.”

This first period leads into a second where He achieved perfect clarity of vision and complete inner harmony. By accepting the concept of suffering, Jesus’ inner peace is elevated to the highest level imaginable. "By accepting the idea of death, He freed Himself from the ongoing uncertainty about when and how God would keep His promise...." The arrival of the Kingdom was connected to the Second Coming of the Messiah. Now He felt confident enough to see Himself as the Son of Man who would be the future Judge of the world, because the suffering and dying Son of Man was closely associated with the Son of Man surrounded by the heavenly host. Would the people accept Him as the Messiah? He now posed the question to them in Jerusalem with all its urgency and intensity, and the people responded with enthusiasm. But as soon as they realized that He, whom they had celebrated so loudly, was neither able nor willing to meet their grand expectations, a backlash started.

Thus, according to Baldensperger, there was an interaction between the historical and the psychological events. And that is right!—if only the machinery were not so complicated, and a “development” had not to be ground out of it at whatever cost. But this, and the whole manner of treatment in the second part, encumbered as it is with parenthetic qualifications, was rendered inevitable by the adoption of the two aforesaid not purely historical conceptions. Sometimes, too, one gets the impression that the author felt that he owed it to the school to which he belonged to advance no assertion without adding the limitations which scientifically secure it against attack. Thus on every page he digs himself into an entrenched position, with palisades of footnotes—in fact the book actually ends with a footnote. But the conception which underlay the whole was so full of vigour that in spite of the thoughts not being always completely worked out, it produced a powerful impression. Baldensperger had persuaded theology at least to admit the hypothesis—whether it took up a positive or negative position in regard to it—that Jesus possessed a fully-developed eschatology. He thus provided a new basis for discussion and gave an impulse to the study of the subject such as it had not received [pg 237] since the 'sixties, at least not in the same degree of energy. Perhaps the very limitations of the work, due as they were to its introduction of modern ideas, rendered it better adapted to the spirit of the age, and consequently more influential, than if it had been characterised by that rigorous maintenance of a single point of view which was abstractly requisite for the proper treatment of the subject. It was precisely the rejection of this rigorous consistency which enabled it to gain ground for the cause of eschatology.

According to Baldensperger, there was a connection between historical and psychological events. That's true!—if only the process weren't so complicated and if we didn't feel the need to extract a "development" from it at any cost. However, this, along with the way the second part is treated—filled with parenthetical qualifications—was made necessary by adopting the two previously mentioned not purely historical concepts. At times, it seems like the author believed he had to respect the academic community to back every statement with the limitations that would protect it from criticism. As a result, he settles into a defensive stance on every page, surrounded by footnotes—actually, the book concludes with a footnote. Still, the underlying idea was so dynamic that, despite some thoughts not being fully fleshed out, it left a strong impact. Baldensperger convinced theology to at least consider the hypothesis—regardless of whether it took a positive or negative stance—that Jesus had a fully-developed eschatology. He thus created a new foundation for discussion and sparked interest in the subject like it hadn't seen since the 'sixties, at least not with the same intensity. Perhaps the very limitations of the work, stemming from its introduction of modern ideas, made it more aligned with the spirit of the time, and thus more influential, than if it had strictly adhered to a single viewpoint, which would have been necessary for proper treatment of the subject. It was precisely the rejection of this rigid consistency that allowed it to advance the cause of eschatology.


But the consistent treatment from a single point of view was bound to come; and it came four years later. In passing from Weiffenbach and Baldensperger to Johannes Weiss161 the reader feels like an explorer who after weary wanderings through billowy seas of reed-grass at length reaches a wooded tract, and instead of swamp feels firm ground beneath his feet, instead of yielding rushes sees around him the steadfast trees. At last there is an end of “qualifying clause” theology, of the “and yet,” the “on the other hand,” the “notwithstanding”! The reader had to follow the others step by step, making his way over every footbridge and gang-plank which they laid down, following all the meanderings in which they indulged, and must never let go their hands if he wished to come safely through the labyrinth of spiritual and eschatological ideas which they supposed to be found in the thought of Jesus.

But the consistent treatment from a single perspective was bound to happen, and it did four years later. When transitioning from Weiffenbach and Baldensperger to Johannes Weiss161, the reader feels like an explorer who, after exhausting journeys through tall grass, finally reaches a forested area. Instead of marshland, there's solid ground beneath their feet; instead of swaying reeds, there are sturdy trees all around. At last, there's an end to “qualifying clause” theology, the “but still,”, the “on the flip side,”, and the "despite"! The reader had to follow the others step by step, navigating every footbridge and gangplank they laid down, following all the twists and turns they took, and had to hold onto their hands if they wanted to safely make it through the maze of spiritual and eschatological ideas that were believed to be present in Jesus's thought.

In Weiss there are none of these devious paths: “behold the land lies before thee.”

In Weiss, there are none of these tricky paths: "Look, the land is right in front of you."

His “Preaching of Jesus concerning the Kingdom of God,”162 published in 1892, has, on its own lines, an importance equal to that of Strauss's first Life of Jesus. He lays down the third great alternative which the study of the life of Jesus had to meet. The first was laid down by Strauss: either purely historical or purely supernatural. The second had been worked out by the Tübingen school and Holtzmann: either Synoptic or Johannine. Now came the third: either eschatological or non-eschatological!

His "Jesus' teachings about the Kingdom of God,"162 published in 1892, holds significant importance on its own, comparable to Strauss's first Life of Jesus. He establishes the third major alternative that the study of Jesus's life needed to address. The first was proposed by Strauss: either purely historical or purely supernatural. The second was developed by the Tübingen school and Holtzmann: either Synoptic or Johannine. Now comes the third: either eschatological or non-eschatological!

Progress always consists in taking one or other of two alternatives, in abandoning the attempt to combine them. The pioneers of progress have therefore always to reckon with the law of mental inertia which manifests itself in the majority—who always go on believing that it is possible to combine that which can no longer be combined, and in fact claim it as a special merit that they, in contrast with the “one-sided” writers, can do justice to the other side of the question. One must just let them be, till their time is over, [pg 238] and resign oneself not to see the end of it, since it is found by experience that the complete victory of one of two historical alternatives is a matter of two full theological generations.

Progress always involves choosing between two options and giving up on trying to combine them. The pioneers of progress must deal with the mental inertia that most people have—who continue to believe it's possible to merge things that can no longer be joined, often priding themselves on being able to appreciate both sides of the issue, unlike the "one-sided" writers. It's best to just let them be until their time passes, [pg 238] and accept that the resolution might not be witnessed, as experience shows that the complete victory of one of the two historical options usually takes about two full theological generations.

This remark is made in order to explain why the work of Johannes Weiss did not immediately make an end of the mediating views. Another reason perhaps was that, according to the usual canons of theological authorship, the book was much too short—only sixty-seven pages—and too simple to allow its full significance to be realised. And yet it is precisely this simplicity which makes it one of the most important works in historical theology. It seems to break a spell. It closes one epoch and begins another.

This comment is made to explain why Johannes Weiss's work didn't immediately put an end to the mediating views. Another reason might be that, according to the usual standards of theological writing, the book was just too short—only sixty-seven pages—and too straightforward for its full importance to be recognized. Yet, it's this simplicity that makes it one of the most significant works in historical theology. It seems to break a spell. It ends one era and starts another.

Weiffenbach had failed to solve the problem of the Second Coming, Baldensperger that of the Messianic consciousness of Jesus, because both of them allowed a false conception of the Kingdom of God to keep its place among the data. The general conception of the Kingdom was first rightly grasped by Johannes Weiss. All modern ideas, he insists, even in their subtlest forms, must be eliminated from it; when this is done, we arrive at a Kingdom of God which is wholly future; as is indeed implied by the petition in the Lord's prayer, “Thy Kingdom come.” Being still to come, it is at present purely supra-mundane. It is present only as a cloud may be said to be present which throws its shadow upon the earth; its nearness, that is to say, is recognised by the paralysis of the Kingdom of Satan. In the fact that Jesus casts out the demons, the Pharisees are bidden to recognise, according to Matt. xii. 25-28, that the Kingdom of God is already come upon them.

Weiffenbach had failed to solve the issue of the Second Coming, and Baldensperger struggled with understanding Jesus' Messianic consciousness, because both allowed a mistaken view of the Kingdom of God to persist among the information. The true understanding of the Kingdom was first clearly articulated by Johannes Weiss. He argues that all modern ideas, even in their most subtle forms, must be removed from the concept; once that is done, we arrive at a Kingdom of God that is entirely future-oriented, as suggested by the request in the Lord's Prayer, “Your Kingdom come.” Still to come, it exists right now only in a transcendent sense. It is only present in the same way a cloud might be said to be present when it casts a shadow on the earth; its proximity is acknowledged by the paralysis of the Kingdom of Satan. In the act of Jesus casting out demons, the Pharisees are urged to recognize, according to Matt. xii. 25-28, that the Kingdom of God has already arrived among them.

This is the only sense in which Jesus thinks of the Kingdom as present. He does not “establish it,” He only proclaims its coming. He exercises no “Messianic functions,” but waits, like others, for God to bring about the coming of the Kingdom by supernatural means. He does not even know the day and hour when this shall come to pass. The missionary journey of the disciples was not designed for the extension of the Kingdom of God, but only as a means of rapidly and widely making known its nearness. But it was not so near as Jesus thought. The impenitence and hardness of heart of a great part of the people, and the implacable enmity of His opponents, at length convinced Him that the establishment of the Kingdom of God could not yet take place, that such penitence as had been shown hitherto was not sufficient, and that a mighty obstacle, the guilt of the people, must first be put away. It becomes clear to Him that His own death must be the ransom-price. He dies, not for the community of His followers only, but for the nation; that is why He always speaks of His atoning death as “for many,” not “for you.” After His death He would come again in all the splendour and glory with which, since the days of [pg 239] Daniel, men's imaginations had surrounded the Messiah, and He was to come, moreover, within the lifetime of the generation to which He had proclaimed the nearness of the Kingdom of God.

This is the only way in which Jesus views the Kingdom as present. He does not "set it up," He merely announces its arrival. He doesn’t perform any "Messianic roles," but waits, like everyone else, for God to bring about the Kingdom through supernatural means. He doesn’t even know the exact day and hour when this will happen. The disciples' missionary journey wasn’t meant to expand the Kingdom of God but to quickly and broadly communicate its closeness. However, it was not as close as Jesus believed. The stubbornness and hard hearts of many people, along with the relentless hostility of His opponents, eventually led Him to realize that the establishment of the Kingdom of God couldn’t happen yet, that the repentance shown so far wasn’t enough, and that a significant barrier, the people's guilt, had to be dealt with first. He comes to understand that His own death must be the ransom. He dies not just for His followers but for the nation; that’s why He consistently refers to His atoning death as "for many people," not "for you." After His death, He would return in all the splendor and glory that people had imagined since the days of [pg 239] Daniel, and He was meant to come, furthermore, within the lifetime of the generation to whom He announced the Kingdom of God was near.

The setting up of the Kingdom was to be preceded by the Day of Judgment. In describing the Messianic glory Jesus makes use of the traditional picture, but He does so with modesty, restraint, and sobriety. Therein consists His greatness.

The establishment of the Kingdom was to come after the Day of Judgment. When describing the Messianic glory, Jesus uses the traditional imagery, but He does so with humility, restraint, and seriousness. That’s what makes Him great.

With political expectations this Kingdom has nothing whatever to do. “To hope for the Kingdom of God in the transcendental sense which Jesus attaches to it, and to raise a revolution, are two things as different as fire and water.” The transcendental character of the expectation consists precisely in this, that the State and all earthly institutions, conditions, and benefits, as belonging to the present age, shall either not exist at all in the coming Kingdom, or shall exist only in a sublimated form. Hence Jesus cannot preach to men a special ethic of the Kingdom of God, but only an ethic which in this world makes men free from the world and prepared to enter unimpeded into the Kingdom. That is why His ethic is of so completely negative a character; it is, in fact, not so much an ethic as a penitential discipline.

With political expectations, this Kingdom has nothing to do with. "Hoping for the Kingdom of God in the spiritual way that Jesus connects with it, and encouraging a revolution, are as different as fire and water." The transcendental nature of the expectation lies in the fact that the State and all earthly institutions, conditions, and benefits, which belong to the present age, will either not exist at all in the coming Kingdom or will only exist in an elevated form. Therefore, Jesus cannot teach people a specific ethic of the Kingdom of God; instead, He presents an ethic that frees people from this world and prepares them to enter the Kingdom without hindrance. That’s why His ethic is largely negative; it is more of a penitential discipline than an ethic.

The ministry of Jesus is therefore not in principle different from that of John the Baptist: there can be no question of a founding and development of the Kingdom within the hearts of men. What distinguishes the work of Jesus from that of the Baptist is only His consciousness of being the Messiah. He awoke to this consciousness at His baptism. But the Messiahship which He claims is not a present office; its exercise belongs to the future. On earth He is only a man, a prophet, as in the view implied in the speeches in the Acts of the Apostles. “Son of Man” is therefore, in the passages where it is authentic, a purely eschatological designation of the Messiah, though we cannot tell whether His hearers understood Him as speaking of Himself in His future rank and dignity, or whether they thought of the Son of Man as a being quite distinct from Himself, whose coming He was only proclaiming in advance.

The ministry of Jesus is fundamentally similar to that of John the Baptist: there’s no doubt about establishing and nurturing the Kingdom within people’s hearts. What sets Jesus apart from the Baptist is His awareness of being the Messiah. He became aware of this at His baptism. However, the Messiahship He claims is not something He exercises now; it belongs to the future. On earth, He is just a man, a prophet, as suggested in the speeches in the Acts of the Apostles. The term “Son of Man” is, in the passages where it is authentic, a strictly eschatological title for the Messiah, although we can’t know if His audience understood Him as referring to Himself in His future role and dignity, or if they viewed the Son of Man as a separate being whose arrival He was merely announcing ahead of time.

“The sole object of this argument is to prove that the Messianic self-consciousness of Jesus, as expressed in the title ‘Son of Man,’ shares in the transcendental apocalyptic character of Jesus' idea of the Kingdom of God, and cannot be separated from that idea.” The only partially correct evaluation of the factors in the problem of the Life of Jesus which Baldensperger had taken over from contemporary theology, and which had hitherto prevented historical science from obtaining a solution of that problem, had now been corrected from the history itself, and it was now only necessary to insert the corrected data into the calculation.

“The main goal of this discussion is to show that Jesus' understanding of his role as the ‘Son of Man,’ is connected to the transcendent and apocalyptic nature of his idea of the Kingdom of God, and that it cannot be separated from that idea.” The only partially accurate assessment of the factors in the Life of Jesus problem that Baldensperger adopted from contemporary theology, which had previously hindered historical science from solving that problem, has now been corrected based on historical evidence, and it is now only necessary to integrate the corrected data into the analysis.

Here is the point at which it is fitting to recall Reimarus. He [pg 240] was the first, and indeed, before Johannes Weiss, the only writer who recognised and pointed out that the preaching of Jesus was purely eschatological. It is true that his conception of the eschatology was primitive, and that he applied it not as a constructive, but as a destructive principle of criticism. But read his statement of the problem “with the signs changed,” and with the necessary deduction for the primitive character of the eschatology, and you have the view of Weiss.

Here is the point where it's appropriate to recall Reimarus. He [pg 240] was the first, and really, before Johannes Weiss, the only writer who recognized and pointed out that Jesus's preaching was entirely about the end times. It's true that his understanding of eschatology was basic, and that he used it not as a constructive but as a destructive critical principle. But if you read his statement of the problem “with the signs updated,” and take into account the primitive nature of his eschatology, you'll see the perspective of Weiss.

Ghillany, too, has a claim to be remembered. When Weiss asserts that the part played by Jesus was not the active rôle of establishing the Kingdom, but the passive rôle of waiting for the coming of the Kingdom; and that it was, in a sense, only by the acceptance of His sufferings that He emerged from that passivity; he is only asserting what Ghillany had maintained thirty years before with the same arguments and with the same decisiveness. But Weiss places the assertion on a scientifically unassailable basis.

Ghillany also deserves to be remembered. When Weiss argues that Jesus's role was not about actively establishing the Kingdom, but rather passively waiting for it to come; and that He only transcended that passivity by accepting His sufferings, he's simply reiterating what Ghillany claimed thirty years earlier with the same reasoning and conviction. However, Weiss backs up his claim with a scientifically solid foundation.

[pg 241]

XVI. The Fight Against Eschatology

Wilhelm Bousset. Jesu Predigt in ihrem Gegensatz zum Judentum. Ein religionsgeschichtlicher Vergleich. (The Antithesis between Jesus' Preaching and Judaism. A Religious-Historical Comparison.) Göttingen, 1892. 130 pp.

Wilhelm Bousset. Jesus' Teaching in Contrast to Judaism: A Religious-Historical Comparison. Göttingen, 1892. 130 pages.

Erich Haupt. Die eschatologischen Aussagen Jesu in den synoptischen Evangelien. (The Eschatological Sayings of Jesus in the Synoptic Gospels.) 1895. 167 pp.

Erich Haupt. The Eschatological Sayings of Jesus in the Synoptic Gospels. 1895. 167 pages.

Paul Wernle. Die Anfänge unserer Religion. Tübingen-Leipzig, 1901; 2nd ed., 1904, 410 pp.

Paul Wernle. The Origins of Our Religion. Tübingen-Leipzig, 1901; 2nd ed., 1904, 410 pp.

Emil Schürer. Das messianische Selbstbewusstsein Jesu-Christi. 1903. Akademische Festrede. (The Messianic Self-consciousness of Jesus Christ.) 24 pp.

Emil Schürer. The Messianic Self-Consciousness of Jesus Christ. 1903. Academic Celebration Speech. 24 pages.

Wilhelm Brandt. Die evangelische Geschichte und der Ursprung des Christentums auf Grund einer Kritik der Berichte über das Leiden und die Auferstehung Jesu. (The Gospel History and the Origin of Christianity. Based upon a Critical Study of the Narratives of the Sufferings and Resurrection of Jesus.) Leipzig, 1893. 591 pp.

Wilhelm Brandt. The Gospel History and the Origin of Christianity Based on a Critical Study of the Accounts of the Sufferings and Resurrection of Jesus. Leipzig, 1893. 591 pages.

Adolf Jülicher. Die Gleichnisreden Jesu. (The Parables of Jesus.) Vol. i., 1888, 291 pp.; vol. ii., 1899, 643 pp.

Adolf Jülicher. The Parables of Jesus. Volume I, 1888, 291 pages; Volume II, 1899, 643 pages.

In this period the important books are short. The sixty-seven pages of Johannes Weiss are answered by Bousset163 in a bare hundred and thirty. People began to see that the elaborate Lives of Jesus which had hitherto held the field, and enjoyed an immortality of revised editions, only masked the fact that the study of the subject was at a standstill; and that the tedious re-handling of problems which had been solved so far as they were capable of solution only served as an excuse for not grappling with those which still remained unsolved.

In this time, the key books are brief. The sixty-seven pages by Johannes Weiss are countered by Bousset163 in just a straightforward hundred and thirty. People started to realize that the complex Lives of Jesus, which had dominated the field and enjoyed an endless series of revisions, merely concealed the truth that the study of the topic was stagnant; and that the tedious revisiting of issues that had been resolved, as much as they could be, only served as a way to avoid tackling the problems that were still unresolved.

This conviction is expressed by Bousset at the beginning of his work. The criticism of the sources, he says, is finished, and its results may be regarded, so far as the Life of Jesus is concerned, as provisionally complete. The separation between John and the Synoptists has been secured. For the Synoptists, the two-document hypothesis has been established, according to which the sources are a primitive form of Mark, and a collection of “logia.” A certain interest might still attach to the attempt to arrive at the primitive kernel of Mark; but the attempt has a priori so little [pg 242] prospect of success that it was almost a waste of time to continue to work at it. It would be a much more important thing to get rid of the feeling of uncertainty and artificiality in the Lives of Jesus. What is now chiefly wanted, Bousset thinks, is “a firmly-drawn and life-like portrait which, with a few bold strokes, should bring out clearly the originality, the force, the personality of Jesus.”

This belief is expressed by Bousset at the start of his work. He states that the critique of the sources is complete, and its findings can be considered, regarding the Life of Jesus, as provisionally finished. The distinction between John and the Synoptic Gospels has been established. For the Synoptics, the two-document hypothesis has been confirmed, suggesting that the sources include a primitive version of Mark and a collection of “logia.” There may still be some interest in trying to uncover the original core of Mark; however, the chances of success are so slim a priori that continuing to pursue it seems almost pointless. It would be far more significant to eliminate the sense of uncertainty and artificiality in the Lives of Jesus. What Bousset believes is needed now is "a clearly defined and realistic portrait that, with a few bold strokes, should vividly reveal the uniqueness, strength, and personality of Jesus."

It is evident that the centre of the problem has now been reached. That is why the writing becomes so terse. The masses of thought can only be manœuvred here in a close formation such as Weiss gives them. The loose order of discursive exegetical discussions of separate passages is now no longer in place. The first step towards further progress was the simple one of marshalling the passages in such a way as to gain a single consistent impression from them.

It’s clear that we’ve reached the core of the problem. That’s why the writing is now so concise. The abundance of thoughts can only be handled in a tight arrangement like the one Weiss provides. The scattered discussions of individual passages are no longer appropriate. The first step toward moving forward was simply organizing the passages to create a cohesive overall impression.

In the first instance Bousset is as ready as Johannes Weiss to admit the importance for the mind of Jesus of the eschatological “then” and “now.” The realistic school, he thinks, are perfectly right in endeavouring to relate Jesus, without apologetic or theological inconsistencies, to the background of contemporary ideas. Later, in 1901, he was to make it a reproach against Harnack's “What is Christianity?” (Das Wesen des Christentums) that it did not give sufficient importance to the background of contemporary thought in its account of the preaching of Jesus.164

In the beginning, Bousset is just as willing as Johannes Weiss to acknowledge the significance for Jesus' mindset of the eschatological "then" and "now." He believes the realistic school is completely correct in trying to connect Jesus, without any apologetic or theological inconsistencies, to the context of contemporary ideas. Later, in 1901, he would criticize Harnack's "What is Christianity?" (Das Wesen des Christentums) for not giving enough importance to the context of contemporary thought in its portrayal of Jesus' preaching.164

He goes on to ask, however, whether the first enthusiasm over the discovery of this genuinely historical way of looking at things should not be followed by some “second thoughts” of a deeper character. Accepting the position laid down by Johannes Weiss, we must ask, he thinks, whether this purely historical criticism, by the exclusive emphasis which it has laid upon eschatology, has not allowed the “essential originality and power of the personality of Jesus to slip through its fingers,” and closed its grasp instead upon contemporary conceptions and imaginations which are often of a quite special character.

He goes on to ask, however, whether the initial excitement over discovering this genuinely historical way of thinking should be followed by some “second thoughts” of a deeper nature. Accepting the viewpoint outlined by Johannes Weiss, he believes we need to consider whether this purely historical criticism, with its focus on eschatology, has allowed the "the essential originality and strength of Jesus' personality to slip through its grasp," and instead tightened its grip on contemporary ideas and imaginations that are often quite unique.

The Late-Jewish eschatology was, according to Bousset, by no means a homogeneous system of thought. Realistic and transcendental elements stand side by side in it, unreconciled. The genuine popular belief of Late Judaism still clung quite naively to the earthly realistic hopes of former times, and had never been able to rise to the purely transcendental regions which are the characteristic habitat of apocalyptic. The rejection of the world is never carried out consistently; something of the Jewish national ideal always remains. And for this reason Late Judaism made no progress towards the overcoming of particularism.

The Late-Jewish eschatology, according to Bousset, was definitely not a uniform system of thought. Realistic and transcendental elements coexist within it, without resolution. The genuine popular belief of Late Judaism still held onto the earthly, realistic hopes of earlier times and had never managed to elevate itself to the purely transcendental areas that are typical of apocalyptic thought. The rejection of the world is never fully embraced; a portion of the Jewish national ideal always persists. For this reason, Late Judaism did not move forward in overcoming particularism.

Probably, Bousset holds, this Apocalyptic thought is not even genuinely Jewish; as he ably argued in another work, there [pg 243] was a considerable strain of Persian influence in it.165 The dualism, the transference to the transcendental region of the future hope, the conception of the world which appears in Jewish apocalyptic, are of Iranian rather than Jewish origin.

Bousset likely believes that this Apocalyptic idea isn’t even truly Jewish; as he convincingly argued in another work, there [pg 243] is a significant influence from Persian thought in it.165 The dualism, the shift to a transcendent future hope, and the worldview present in Jewish apocalyptic literature come from Iranian origins rather than Jewish ones.

Two thoughts are especially characteristic of Bousset's position; first, that this transcendentalising of the future implied a spiritualisation of it; secondly, that in post-exilic Judaism there was always an undercurrent of a purer and more spontaneous piety, the presence of which is especially to be traced in the Psalms.

Two ideas are particularly representative of Bousset's viewpoint: first, that this elevation of the future suggested a spiritual interpretation of it; second, that in post-exilic Judaism, there was always an underlying current of a more genuine and instinctual faith, which is especially evident in the Psalms.

Into a dead world, where a kind of incubus seems to stifle all naturalness and spontaneity, there comes a living Man. According to the formulae of His preaching and the designations which He applies to Himself, He seems at first sight to identify Himself with this world rather than to oppose it. But these conceptions and titles, especially the Kingdom of God and the Son of Man, must be provisionally left in the background, since they, as being conceptions taken over from the past, conceal rather than reveal what is most essential in His personality. The primary need is to discover, behind the phenomenal, the real character of the personality and preaching of Jesus. The starting-point must therefore be the simple fact that Jesus came as a living Man into a dead world. He is living, because in contrast with His contemporaries He has a living idea of God. His faith in the Fatherhood of God is Jesus' most essential act. It signifies a breach with the transcendental Jewish idea of God, and an unconscious inner negation of the Jewish eschatology. Jesus, therefore, walks through a world which denies His own eschatology like a man who has firm ground under his feet.

Into a lifeless world, where a kind of oppressive force seems to suffocate all naturalness and spontaneity, a living Man arrives. By the way He preaches and the names He uses for Himself, it initially appears that He aligns Himself with this world rather than opposing it. However, these concepts and titles, particularly the Kingdom of God and the Son of Man, should be set aside for now, as they come from the past and obscure rather than clarify the essence of His character. The main goal is to uncover the true nature of Jesus' personality and teachings behind the superficial appearances. Therefore, we must start with the straightforward fact that Jesus entered a lifeless world as a living Man. He is alive because, unlike those around Him, He possesses a vibrant understanding of God. His belief in the Fatherhood of God is the most fundamental aspect of Jesus. It represents a break from the traditional Jewish notion of God and an implicit rejection of Jewish eschatology. Consequently, Jesus moves through a world that rejects His eschatology like someone who stands firmly grounded.

That which on a superficial view appears to be eschatological preaching turns out to be essentially a renewal of the old prophetic preaching with its positive ethical emphasis. Jesus is a manifestation of that ancient spontaneous piety of which Bousset had shown the existence in Late Judaism.

What seems to be end-of-the-world preaching at first glance is actually a revival of the old prophetic preaching, focusing on positive ethics. Jesus embodies that ancient, instinctive piety that Bousset revealed in Late Judaism.

The most characteristic thing in the character of Jesus, according to Bousset, is His joy in life. It is true that if, in endeavouring to understand Him, we take primitive Christianity as our starting-point, we might conceive of this joy in life as the complement of the eschatological mood, as the extreme expression of indifference to the world, which can as well enjoy the world as flee it. But the purely eschatological attitude, though it reappears [pg 244] in early Christianity, does not give the right clue for the interpretation of the character of Jesus as a whole. His joy in the world was real, a genuine outcome of His new type of piety. It prevented the eudaemonistic eschatological idea of reward, which some think they find in Jesus' preaching, from ever really becoming an element in it.

The most defining trait of Jesus' character, according to Bousset, is His joy in life. It’s true that if we start with primitive Christianity to understand Him, we might view this joy as the counterpart to the eschatological mindset, reflecting an extreme indifference to the world, which could either enjoy it or escape from it. However, the purely eschatological stance, although it shows up again [pg 244] in early Christianity, doesn’t really offer the right perspective for interpreting Jesus' character as a whole. His joy in the world was authentic, a true result of His new approach to piety. It kept the idea of a eudaemonic eschatological reward, which some believe they find in Jesus' teachings, from ever truly becoming part of it.

Jesus is best understood by contrasting Him with the Baptist. John was a preacher of repentance whose eyes were fixed upon the future. Jesus did not allow the thought of the nearness of the end to rob Him of His simplicity and spontaneity, and was not crippled by the reflection that everything was transitory, preparatory, a mere means to an end. His preaching of repentance was not gloomy and forbidding; it was the proclamation of a new righteousness, of which the watchword was, “Ye shall be perfect as your Father in Heaven is perfect.” He desires to communicate this personal piety by personal influence. In contrast with the Baptist He never aims at influencing masses of men, but rather avoids it. His work was accomplished mainly among little groups and individuals. He left the task of carrying the Gospel far and wide as a legacy to the community of His followers. The mission of the Twelve, conceived as a mission for the rapid and widespread extension of the Gospel, is not to be used to explain Jesus' methods of teaching; the narrative of it rests on an “obscure and unintelligible tradition.”

Jesus is best understood by comparing Him to John the Baptist. John was a preacher of repentance whose focus was on the future. Jesus, however, didn’t let the thought of the end being near take away His simplicity and spontaneity. He wasn’t held back by the idea that everything was temporary, just a preparation, a means to an end. His message of repentance wasn’t gloomy or harsh; it announced a new form of righteousness, with the key idea being, "You should be as perfect as your Father in Heaven is perfect." He wanted to share this personal faith through personal connections. Unlike the Baptist, He didn’t try to influence large groups; in fact, He often avoided it. His work was mostly done among small groups and individuals. He left the responsibility of spreading the Gospel widely to His followers. The mission of the Twelve, which was intended for the quick and broad dissemination of the Gospel, shouldn’t be used to explain Jesus’ teaching methods; its story is based on an “obscure and confusing tradition.”

This genuine joy in life was not unnoticed by the contemporaries of Jesus who contrasted Him as “a gluttonous man and a wine-bibber,” with the Baptist. They were vaguely conscious that the whole life of Jesus was “sustained by the feeling of an absolute antithesis between Himself and His times.” He lived not in anxious expectation, but in cheerful gladness, because by the native strength of His piety He had brought present and future into one. Free from all extravagant Jewish delusions about the future, He was not paralysed by the conditions which must be fulfilled to make this future present. He has a peculiar conviction of its coming which gives Him courage to “marry” the present with the future. The present as contrasted with the beyond is for Him no mere shadow, but truth and reality; life is not for Him a mere illusion, but is charged with a real and valuable meaning. His own time is the Messianic time, as His answer to the Baptist's question shows. “And it is among the most certain things in the Gospel that Jesus in His earthly life acknowledged Himself as Messiah both to His disciples and to the High-Priest, and made His entry into Jerusalem as such.”

This genuine joy in life didn't go unnoticed by the people of Jesus' time, who contrasted Him as “a glutton and a drunk,” with John the Baptist. They were somewhat aware that Jesus' entire life was "supported by the sense of a deep conflict between Himself and His era." He lived not in anxious anticipation, but in joyful happiness, because through the inherent strength of His faith, He united the present and the future. Free from all exaggerated Jewish ideas about the future, He wasn’t immobilized by the conditions that needed to be met to make that future a reality. He had a unique belief in its arrival that gave Him the courage to “connect” the present with the future. For Him, the present, in contrast to what lies beyond, is not just a shadow but truth and reality; life is not merely an illusion, but is filled with real and valuable meaning. His own time is the Messianic time, as His response to the Baptist's question demonstrates. “It is one of the most certain points in the Gospel that Jesus recognized Himself as the Messiah during His life on earth, both to His disciples and to the High Priest, and that He made His entry into Jerusalem in that role.”

He can, therefore, fully recognise the worth of the present. It is not true that He taught that this world's goods were in themselves bad; what He said was only that they must not be put first. [pg 245] Indeed He gives a new value to life by teaching that man cannot be righteous in isolation, but only in the fellowship of love. And as, moreover, the righteousness which He preaches is one of the goods of the Kingdom of God, He cannot have thought of the Kingdom as wholly transcendental. The Reign of God begins for Him in the present era. His consciousness of being able to cast out demons in the spirit of God because Satan's kingdom on earth is at an end is only the supernaturalistic expression for something of which He also possesses an ethical consciousness, namely, that in the new social righteousness the Kingdom of God is already present.

He can, therefore, fully recognize the value of the present. It’s not true that He taught that the things of this world are inherently bad; what He said was that they shouldn’t come first. [pg 245] In fact, He gives a new meaning to life by teaching that a person cannot be righteous on their own, but only in a community filled with love. Furthermore, the righteousness He teaches is part of the goods of the Kingdom of God, so He couldn’t have seen the Kingdom as completely beyond our reach. For Him, the Kingdom of God starts in the present time. His awareness of being able to cast out demons through the spirit of God, because Satan’s reign on earth is over, is just a supernatural way of expressing something He also understands ethically: that in the new social righteousness, the Kingdom of God is already here.

This presence of the Kingdom was not, however, clearly explained by Jesus, but was set forth in paradoxes and parables, especially in the parables of Mark iv. When we find the Evangelist, in immediate connexion with these parables, asserting that the aim of the parables was to mystify and conceal, we may conclude that the basis of this theory is the fact that these parables concerning the presence of the Kingdom of God were not understood.

This presence of the Kingdom wasn’t clearly explained by Jesus; instead, it was presented in paradoxes and parables, especially in the parables of Mark 4. When we see the Evangelist, in direct relation to these parables, stating that the purpose of the parables was to confuse and hide meaning, we can infer that the foundation of this theory is the truth that these parables about the presence of the Kingdom of God were not understood.

In effecting this tacit transformation Jesus is acting in accordance with a tendency of the time. Apocalyptic is itself a spiritualisation of the ancient Israelitish hopes of the future, and Jesus only carries this process to its completion. He raises Late Judaism above the limitations in which it was involved, separates out the remnant of national, political, and sensuous ideas which still clung to the expectation of the future in spite of its having been spiritualised by apocalyptic, and breaks with the Jewish particularism, though without providing a theoretical basis for this step.

In making this subtle change, Jesus is responding to a trend of his time. Apocalyptic thought is essentially a spiritual take on the ancient Israelite hopes for the future, and Jesus simply brings this process to its final form. He elevates late Judaism beyond the confines it was trapped in, distinguishes the remnants of national, political, and tangible ideas that still clung to future expectations even though they had been spiritualized by apocalyptic thought, and moves away from Jewish exclusivity, although he doesn't offer a theoretical foundation for this shift.

Thus, in spite of, nay even because of, His opposition to it, Jesus was the fulfiller of Judaism. In Him were united the ancient and vigorous prophetic religion and the impulse which Judaism itself had begun to feel towards the spiritualisation of the future hope. The transcendental and the actual meet in a unity which is full of life and strength, creative not reflective, and therefore not needing to set aside the ancient traditional ideas by didactic explanations, but overcoming them almost unconsciously by the truth which lies in this paradoxical union. The historical formula embodied in Bousset's closing sentence runs thus: “The Gospel develops some of the deeper-lying motifs of the Old Testament, but it protests against the prevailing tendency of Judaism.”

Thus, despite, or rather because of, His opposition to it, Jesus was the true fulfillment of Judaism. In Him, the ancient and vibrant prophetic religion came together with the growing inclination within Judaism itself towards a more spiritual view of future hope. The transcendental and the actual converge in a unity that is full of life and strength, more creative than reflective, and therefore does not need to dismiss ancient traditional ideas with didactic explanations, but instead transcends them almost instinctively through the truth found in this paradoxical union. The historical formulation captured in Bousset's closing sentence states: “The Gospel explores some of the deeper themes of the Old Testament, but it pushes back against the dominant trends in Judaism.”

Such of the underlying assumptions of this construction as invite challenge lie open to inspection, and do not need to be painfully disentangled from a web of exegesis; that is one of the merits of the book. The chief points to be queried are as follows:—

Such underlying assumptions of this construction that invite challenge are open for inspection and don't need to be painfully disentangled from a web of interpretation; that's one of the strengths of the book. The main points to be questioned are as follows:—

Is it the case that the apocalypses mark the introduction of a process of spiritualisation applied to the ancient Israelitish hopes? [pg 246] A picture of the future is not spiritualised simply by being projected upon the clouds. This elevation to the transcendental region signifies, on the contrary, the transference to a place of safety of the eudaemonistic aspirations which have not been fulfilled in the present, and which are expected, by way of compensation, from the other world. The apocalyptic conception is so far from being a spiritualisation of the future expectations, that it represents on the contrary the last desperate effort of a strongly eudaemonistic popular religion to raise to heaven the earthly goods from which it cannot make up its mind to part.

Is it true that the apocalypses signal the beginning of a process of spiritualization applied to the ancient hopes of Israel? [pg 246] A vision of the future isn’t spiritualized just by being cast into the clouds. This shift to a higher realm actually represents the relocation of unfulfilled desires for happiness in this life, which are now expected, as compensation, from the afterlife. The apocalyptic view is far from being a spiritualization of future hopes; instead, it reflects the final, desperate attempt of a deeply eudaemonistic popular religion to lift up the earthly treasures it struggles to let go of.

Next we must ask: Is it really necessary to assume the existence of so wide reaching a Persian influence in Jewish eschatology? The Jewish dualism and the sublimation of its hope have become historical just because, owing to the fate of the nation, the religious life of the present and the fair future which was logically bound up with it became more and more widely separated, temporally and locally, until at last only its dualism and the sublimation of its hope enabled the nation to survive its disappointment.

Next we need to ask: Is it really necessary to believe in such a broad Persian influence on Jewish eschatology? Jewish dualism and the transformation of its hope have become historical because, due to the nation’s fate, the religious life of the present and the brighter future that was logically connected to it became increasingly disconnected, both in time and place, until finally, only its dualism and the transformation of its hope allowed the nation to cope with its disappointment.

Again, is it historically permissible to treat the leading ideas of the preaching of Jesus, which bear so clearly the marks of the contemporary mould of thought, as of secondary importance for the investigation, and to endeavour to trace Jesus' thoughts from within outwards and not from without inwards?

Again, is it historically acceptable to consider the key ideas in Jesus' preaching, which clearly reflect the contemporary way of thinking, as less important for our study, and to try to understand Jesus' thoughts from the inside out rather than from the outside in?

Further, is there really in Judaism no tendency towards the overcoming of particularism? Has not its eschatology, as shaped by the deutero-prophetic literature, a universalistic outlook? Did Jesus overcome particularism in principle otherwise than it is overcome in Jewish eschatology, that is to say, with reference to the future?

Further, is there really no inclination in Judaism to overcome particularism? Doesn’t its eschatology, shaped by the deutero-prophetic literature, have a universal perspective? Did Jesus address particularism in a way that is different from how it is addressed in Jewish eschatology, specifically regarding the future?

What is there to prove that Jesus' distinctive faith in the Fatherhood of God ever existed independently, and not as an alternative form of the historically-conditioned Messianic consciousness? In other words, what is there to show that the “religious attitude” of Jesus and His Messianic consciousness are anything else than identical, temporally and conceptually, so that the first must always be understood as conditioned by the second?

What evidence is there to show that Jesus' unique belief in the Fatherhood of God existed on its own, rather than as an alternative version of the historically influenced Messianic mindset? In other words, how can we demonstrate that Jesus' “spiritual mindset” and His Messianic awareness are anything other than the same, both in time and concept, such that the first must always be understood as influenced by the second?

Again, is the saying about the gluttonous man and wine-bibber a sufficient basis for the contrast between Jesus and the Baptist? Is not Jesus' preaching of repentance gloomy as well as the Baptist's? Where do we read that He, in contrast with the Baptist, avoided dealing with masses of men? Where did He give “the community of His disciples” marching orders to go far and wide in the sense required by Bousset's argument? Where is there a word to tell us that He thought of His work among individuals and little groups of men as the most important feature [pg 247] of His ministry? Are we not told the exact contrary, that He “taught” His disciples as little as He did the people? Is there any justification for characterising the missionary journey of the Twelve, just because it directly contradicts this view, as “an obscure and unintelligible tradition?”

Again, is the saying about the gluttonous man and drunkard enough to support the contrast between Jesus and the Baptist? Is Jesus' message of repentance any more cheerful than the Baptist's? Where do we find evidence that He, unlike the Baptist, avoided engaging with large crowds? When did He give "the community of His followers" orders to spread out and reach different places as Bousset suggests? Where is it stated that He considered His work with individuals and small groups as the most significant aspect [pg 247] of His ministry? Aren't we told the exact opposite—that He "teaching" His disciples just as little as He did the crowds? Is there any reason to label the missionary journey of the Twelve, simply because it directly contradicts this perspective, as “a weird and unclear tradition?”

Is it so certain that Jesus made a Messianic entry into Jerusalem, and that, accordingly, He declared Himself to the disciples and to the High Priest as Messiah in the present, and not in a purely future sense?

Is it really so certain that Jesus made a Messianic entry into Jerusalem, and that, as a result, He declared Himself to the disciples and the High Priest as the Messiah in the present, and not just in a future sense?

What are the sayings which justify us in making the attitude of opposition which He took up towards the Rabbinic legalism into a “sense of the absolute opposition between Himself and His people”? The very “absolute,” with its ring of Schleiermacher, is suspicious.

What are the statements that support our choice to interpret the stance of opposition He had towards Rabbinic legalism as a “sense of the complete opposition between Himself and His people”? The term "absolute" with its connection to Schleiermacher, raises some doubts.

All these, however, are subsidiary positions. The decisive point is: Can Bousset make good the assertion that Jesus' joy in life was a more or less unconscious inner protest against the purely eschatological world-renouncing religious attitude, the primal expression of that “absolute” antithesis to Judaism? Is it not the case that His attitude towards earthly goods was wholly conditioned by eschatology? That is to say, were not earthly goods emptied of any essential value in such a way that joy in the world and indifference to the world were simply the final expression of an ironic attitude which had been sublimated into pure serenity. That is the question upon the answer to which depends the decision whether Bousset's position is tenable or not.

All of these, however, are secondary points. The main question is: Can Bousset prove that Jesus' joy in life was more or less an unconscious inner protest against the purely eschatological and world-renouncing religious attitude, which is the fundamental opposition to Judaism? Isn't it true that His view on earthly possessions was entirely influenced by eschatology? In other words, weren't earthly goods stripped of any real value to the point where joy in the world and indifference to it became merely the ultimate expression of an ironic perspective that had transformed into pure serenity? That is the question that determines whether Bousset's position is viable or not.

It is not in fact tenable, for the opposite view has at its disposal inexhaustible reserves of world-renouncing, world-contemning sayings, and the few utterances which might possibly be interpreted as expressing a purely positive joy in the world, desert and go over to the enemy, because they textually and logically belong to the other set of sayings. Finally, the promise of earthly happiness as a reward, to which Bousset had denied a position in the teaching of Jesus, also falls upon his rear, and that in the very moment when he is seeking to prove from the saying, “Seek ye first the Kingdom of God and His righteousness, and all these things shall be added unto you,” that for Jesus this world's goods are not in themselves evil, but are only to be given a secondary place. Here the eudaemonism is written on the forehead of the saying, since the receiving of these things—we must remember, too, the “hundredfold” in another passage—is future, not present, and will only “come” at the same time as the Kingdom of God. All present goods, on the other hand, serve only to support life and render possible an undistracted attitude of waiting in pious hope for that future, and therefore are not thought of as gains, but purely as a gift of God, to be cheerfully and freely enjoyed as a foretaste [pg 248] of those blessings which the elect are to enjoy in the future Divine dispensation.

It's actually not sustainable because the opposing view has endless resources of world-denying and world-hating quotes. The few statements that could be seen as expressing a genuine joy in life defect and align with the other perspective because they fundamentally and logically belong to that collection of sayings. Ultimately, the promise of earthly happiness as a reward, which Bousset claimed wasn't part of Jesus' teachings, also turns against him at the very moment he tries to prove with the saying, "First, seek the Kingdom of God and His righteousness, and all these things will be given to you." that for Jesus, material goods are not inherently evil, but simply need to be placed in a secondary position. The idea of happiness is clearly evident here, as the gaining of these things—we should also consider the hundredfold mentioned elsewhere—is future-focused, not present, and will only "arrive" alongside the Kingdom of God. In contrast, all present benefits exist solely to support life and allow for an undistracted state of hopeful waiting for that future, and therefore are not seen as profits, but simply as a gift from God, meant to be enjoyed happily and freely as a preview [pg 248] of the blessings that the chosen will receive in the future Divine arrangement.

The loss of this position decides the further point that if there is any suggestion in the teaching of Jesus that the future Kingdom of God is in some sense present, it is not to be understood as implying an anti-eschatological acceptance of the world, but merely as a phenomenon indicative of the extreme tension of the eschatological consciousness, just in the same way as His joy in the world. Bousset has a kind of indirect recognition of this in his remark that the presence of the Kingdom of God is only asserted by Jesus as a kind of paradox. If the assertion of its presence indicated that acceptance of the world formed part of Jesus' system of thought, it would be at variance with His eschatology. But the paradoxical character of the assertion is due precisely to the fact that His acceptance of the world is but the last expression of the completeness with which He rejects it.

The loss of this position leads to the conclusion that if there’s any indication in Jesus' teaching that the future Kingdom of God is somehow present, it shouldn’t be taken to mean an acceptance of the world that goes against eschatology. Instead, it reflects the intense tension of eschatological awareness, just like His joy in the world. Bousset indirectly acknowledges this when he notes that Jesus speaks of the presence of the Kingdom of God as a kind of paradox. If the assertion that it’s present suggested that acceptance of the world was part of Jesus' way of thinking, it would conflict with His eschatology. But the paradoxical nature of this assertion is exactly because His acceptance of the world is just the ultimate expression of how completely He rejects it.

But what do critical cavils matter in the case of a book of which the force, the influence, the greatness, depends upon its spirit? It is great because it recognises—what is so rarely recognised in theological works—the point where the main issue really lies; in the question, namely, whether Jesus preached and worked as Messiah, or whether, as follows if a prominent place is given to eschatology, as Colani had long ago recognised, His career, historically regarded, was only the career of a prophet with an undercurrent of Messianic consciousness.

But what do critical objections matter when it comes to a book whose strength, impact, and significance depend on its essence? It stands out because it acknowledges—something that is so seldom recognized in theological works—the true heart of the matter, which is whether Jesus preached and acted as the Messiah, or whether, as Colani pointed out long ago, if a major focus is placed on eschatology, His life, when looked at historically, was simply that of a prophet with an underlying sense of Messianic awareness.

As a consequence of grasping the question in its full significance, Bousset rejects all the little devices by which previous writers had endeavoured to relate Jesus' ministry to His times, each one prescribing at what point He was to connect Himself with it, and of course proceeding in his book to represent Him as connecting Himself with it in precisely that way. Bousset recognises that the supreme importance of eschatology in the teaching of Jesus is not to be got rid of by whittling away a little point here and there, and rubbing it smooth with critical sandpaper until it is capable of reflecting a different thought, but only by fully admitting it, while at the same time counteracting it by asserting a mysterious element of world-acceptance in the thought of Jesus, and conceiving His whole teaching as a kind of alternating current between positive and negative poles.

As a result of understanding the question in its full significance, Bousset dismisses all the minor strategies that earlier writers used to relate Jesus’ ministry to His time, each one dictating how He was supposed to connect with it, and of course going on in their books to portray Him as connecting in exactly that way. Bousset understands that the critical importance of eschatology in Jesus’ teachings can't be ignored by chiseling away a small piece here and there and smoothing it out with critical sandpaper until it reflects a different idea. Instead, it can only be acknowledged fully while also balancing it by suggesting that there’s a mysterious element of world-acceptance in Jesus’ thinking, and viewing His entire teaching as a sort of alternating current between positive and negative aspects.

This is the last possible sincere attempt to limit the exclusive importance of eschatology in the preaching of Jesus, an attempt so gallant, so brilliant, that its failure is almost tragic; one could have wished success to the book, to which Carlyle might have stood sponsor. That it is inspired by the spirit of Carlyle, that it vindicates the original force of a great Personality against the attempt to dissolve it into a congeries of contemporary conceptions, [pg 249] therein lies at once its greatness and its weakness. Bousset vindicates Jesus, not for history, but for Protestantism, by making Him the heroic representative of a deeply religious acceptance of the goods of life amid an apocalyptic world. His study is not unhistorical, but supra-historical. The spirit of Jesus was in fact world-accepting in the sense that through the experience of centuries it advanced historically to the acceptance of the world, since nothing can appear phenomenally which is not in some sense ideally present from the first. But the teaching of the historical Jesus was purely and exclusively world-renouncing. If, therefore, the problem which Bousset has put on the blackboard for the eschatological school to solve is to be successfully solved, the solution is to be sought on other, more objectively historical, lines.

This is the last sincere attempt to downplay the exclusive importance of eschatology in Jesus's preaching, an effort so bold and remarkable that its failure is almost tragic; one could have wished for the book's success, which could have been endorsed by Carlyle. It embodies Carlyle's spirit by defending the original power of a great figure against the effort to reduce it to a collection of contemporary ideas. In that lies both its strength and its weakness. Bousset defends Jesus, not for history, but for Protestantism, by portraying Him as the heroic symbol of a deeply religious acceptance of life's blessings in an apocalyptic world. His study isn’t unhistorical, but rather above historical. The essence of Jesus was indeed world-accepting in the sense that, over centuries, it moved historically to embrace the world, since nothing can appear in reality that isn't ideally present in some way from the beginning. However, the message of the historical Jesus was purely and solely about renouncing the world. Therefore, if the problem that Bousset has presented for the eschatological school to resolve is to be successfully addressed, the solution must be sought along other, more objectively historical paths.

That the decision of the question whether Jesus' preaching of the Kingdom of God is wholly eschatological or only partly eschatological, is primarily to be sought in His ethical teaching, is recognised by all the critics of Baldensperger and Weiss. They differ only in the importance which they assign to eschatology. But no other writer has grasped the problem as clearly as Bousset.

That the decision about whether Jesus' preaching of the Kingdom of God is entirely about the end times or just partially about the end times should mainly be found in His ethical teaching is acknowledged by all the critics of Baldensperger and Weiss. They only differ in how much importance they give to eschatology. However, no other writer has understood the problem as clearly as Bousset.


The Parisian Ehrhardt emphasises eschatology very strongly in his work “The Fundamental Character of the Preaching of Jesus in Relation to the Messianic Hopes of His People and His own Messianic Consciousness.”166 Nevertheless he asserts the presence of a twofold ethic in Jesus' teaching: eschatology did not attempt to evacuate everything else of all value, but allowed the natural and ethical goods of this world to hold their place, as belonging to a world of thought which resisted its encroachments.

The Parisian Ehrhardt strongly emphasizes eschatology in his work “The Core Nature of Jesus’ Preaching in Connection to His People’s Messianic Hopes and His Own Messianic Awareness.”166 However, he argues that Jesus' teaching includes a dual ethic: eschatology didn't try to dismiss everything else of value, but rather allowed the natural and ethical goods of this world to have their place, as part of a way of thinking that stood against its influence.

A much more negative attitude is taken up by Albert Réville in his Jésus de Nazareth.167 According to him both Apocalyptic and Messianism are foreign bodies in the teaching of Jesus which have been forced into it by the pressure of contemporary thought. Jesus would never of His own motion have taken up the rôle of Messiah.

A much more negative attitude is taken up by Albert Réville in his Jesus of Nazareth.167 According to him, both Apocalyptic and Messianism are outside influences in Jesus's teachings that have been imposed by the pressures of contemporary thought. Jesus would never have chosen to take on the role of Messiah on His own.

Wendt, too, in the second edition of his Lehre Jesu, which appeared in 1903, held in the main to the fundamental idea of the first, the 1890, edition; namely, that Jesus in view of His purely religious relation to God could not do otherwise than transform, from within outwards, the traditional conceptions, even though [pg 250] they seem to be traceable in their actual contemporary form on the surface of His teaching. He had already, in 1893, in the Christliche Welt clearly expounded, and defended against Weiss, his view of the Kingdom of God as already present for the thought of Jesus.

Wendt, too, in the second edition of his Jesus' teachings, which came out in 1903, mainly stuck to the core idea of the first edition from 1890; that is, that Jesus, due to His purely religious relationship with God, could only transform traditional concepts from the inside out, even though [pg 250] these concepts might appear to be present in their actual modern form on the surface of His teachings. He had already, in 1893, in the Christian World clearly laid out and defended against Weiss his perspective on the Kingdom of God as already being present in Jesus' thinking.

The effect which Baldensperger and Weiss had upon Weiffenbach168 was to cause him to bring out in full strength the apologetic aspect which had been somewhat held in check in his work of 1873 by the thoroughness of his exegesis. The apocalyptic of this younger school, which was no longer willing to believe that in the mouth of Jesus the Parousia meant nothing more than an issuing from death clothed with power, is on all grounds to be rejected. It assumes, since this expectation was not fulfilled, an error on the part of Jesus. It is better to rest content with not being able to see quite clearly.

The influence that Baldensperger and Weiss had on Weiffenbach was to encourage him to fully express the apologetic angle that had been somewhat restrained in his 1873 work due to the depth of his analysis. The apocalyptic perspective of this younger group, which no longer believed that Jesus meant anything more than a powerful emergence from death when he spoke of the Parousia, should be completely rejected. It implies that, since this expectation wasn’t met, Jesus made a mistake. It’s better to be at peace with the fact that we can’t see everything clearly.

Protected by a similar armour, the successive editions of Bernhard Weiss's Life of Jesus went their way unmolested down to 1902.

Protected by a similar protection, the later editions of Bernhard Weiss's Life of Jesus continued on without disturbance until 1902.

Not with an apologetic purpose, but on the basis of an original religious view, Titius, in his work on the New Testament doctrine of blessedness, develops the teaching of Jesus concerning the Kingdom of God as a present good.169

Not with an apologetic purpose, but based on an original religious perspective, Titius, in his work on the New Testament doctrine of blessedness, explains Jesus' teaching about the Kingdom of God as a current benefit.169

In the same year, 1895, appeared E. Haupt's work on “The Eschatological Sayings of Jesus in the Synoptic Gospels.”170 In contradistinction to Bousset he takes as his starting-point the eschatological passages, examining each separately and modulating them back to the Johannine key. It is so delicately and ingeniously done that the reading of the book is an aesthetic pleasure which makes one in the end quite forget the apologetic motif in order to surrender oneself completely to the author's mystical system of religious thought.

In the same year, 1895, E. Haupt released his work on "The End Times Teachings of Jesus in the Synoptic Gospels."170 Unlike Bousset, he starts with the eschatological passages, examining each one individually and relating them back to the Johannine perspective. It's done so skillfully and beautifully that reading the book becomes a pleasure, allowing readers to ultimately forget the apologetic motive and fully embrace the author's mystical religious ideas.

It is, indeed, not the least service of the eschatological school that it compels modern theology, which is so much preoccupied with history, to reveal what is its own as its own. Eschatology makes it impossible to attribute modern ideas to Jesus and then by way of “New Testament Theology” take them back from Him as a loan, as even Ritschl not so long ago did with such naïveté. Johannes Weiss, in cutting himself loose, as an historian, from Ritschl, and recognising that “the real roots of Ritschl's ideas [pg 251] are to be found in Kant and the illuminist theology,”171 introduced the last decisive phase of the process of separation between historical and “modern” theology. Before the advent of eschatology, critical theology was, in the last resort, without a principle of discrimination, since it possessed no reagent capable of infallibly separating out modern ideas on the one hand and genuinely ancient New Testament ideas on the other. The application of the criterion has now begun. What will be the issue, the future alone can show.

It really is one of the significant contributions of the eschatological school that it forces modern theology, which is so focused on history, to clarify what belongs to it. Eschatology makes it impossible to credit modern ideas to Jesus and then, through “New Testament Theology,” reclaim them as if they were borrowed, as even Ritschl did not too long ago with such naïveté. Johannes Weiss, in breaking away as a historian from Ritschl and recognizing that “the real roots of Ritschl's ideas [pg 251] are to be found in Kant and the illuminist theology,” introduced the final critical phase of the separation between historical and “modern” theology. Before eschatology emerged, critical theology lacked a principle of differentiation, as it had no means to reliably distinguish between modern ideas and genuinely ancient New Testament ideas. The application of this criterion has now begun. What will come of it, only the future can tell.

But even now we can recognise that the separation was not only of advantage to historical theology; for modern theology, the manifestation of the modern spirit as it really is, was still more important. Only when it became conscious of its own inmost essence and of its right to exist, only when it freed itself from its illegitimate historical justification, which, leaping over the centuries, appealed directly to an historical exposition of the New Testament, only then could it unfold its full wealth of ideas, which had been hitherto root-bound by a false historicity. It was not by chance that in Bousset's reply a certain affirmation of life, something expressive of the genius of Protestantism, cries aloud as never before in any theological work of this generation, or that in Haupt's work German mysticism interweaves its mysterious harmonies with the Johannine motif. The contribution of Protestantism to the interpretation of the world had never been made so manifest in any work prior to Weiss's. The modern spirit is here breaking in wreaths of foam upon the sharp cliffs of the rock-bound eschatological world-view of Jesus. To put it more prosaically, modern theology is at last about to become sincere. But this is so far only a prophecy of the future.

But even now we can see that the separation was not just beneficial to historical theology; for modern theology, the expression of the modern spirit as it truly is, was even more crucial. It was only when it became aware of its own deepest nature and its right to exist, and when it liberated itself from its unjustified historical basis—which, bypassing the centuries, directly referred to a historical explanation of the New Testament—that it could fully express its wealth of ideas, which had previously been stunted by a misguided historicism. It is no coincidence that in Bousset's response, a certain affirmation of life, something that embodies the essence of Protestantism, is more evident than ever in any theological work of this generation, or that in Haupt's work, German mysticism weaves its mysterious harmonies with the Johannine . The contribution of Protestantism to interpreting the world had never been so clear in any work before Weiss's. The modern spirit is now crashing against the sharp cliffs of the rock-bound eschatological worldview of Jesus like waves of foam. To put it more simply, modern theology is finally becoming sincere. But so far, this is merely a glimpse of the future.

If we are to speak of the present it must be fully admitted that even historical science, when it desires to continue the history of Christianity beyond the life of Jesus, cannot help protesting against the one-sidedness of the eschatological world of thought of the “Founder.” It finds itself obliged to distinguish in the thought of Jesus “permanent elements and transitory elements” which, being interpreted, means eschatological and not essentially eschatological materials; otherwise it can get no farther. For if Jesus' world of thought was wholly and exclusively eschatological, there can only have arisen out of it, as Reimarus long ago maintained, an exclusively eschatological primitive Christianity. But how a community of that kind could give birth to the Greek non-eschatological theology no Church history and no history of dogma has so far shown. Instead of that they all—Harnack, with the most consummate historical ability—lay down from the very first, alongside [pg 252] of the main line intended for “contemporary views” traffic, a relief line for the accommodation of through trains of “non-temporally limited ideas”; and at the point where primitive Christian eschatology becomes of less importance they switch off the train to the relief line, after slipping the carriages which are not intended to go beyond that station.

If we talk about the present, we must acknowledge that even historical science, when it aims to extend the history of Christianity beyond Jesus’ life, cannot help but critique the one-sided eschatological thinking of the "Founder." It must differentiate between "permanent and temporary elements" in Jesus’ thoughts, which means distinguishing between eschatological and not essentially eschatological ideas; otherwise, it cannot progress further. If Jesus’ worldview was entirely eschatological, then, as Reimarus suggested long ago, this would solely lead to an eschatological form of primitive Christianity. However, no history of the Church or of doctrine has shown how a community like this could develop into Greek, non-eschatological theology. Instead, everyone—Harnack, with the greatest historical skill—establishes from the outset, alongside [pg 252] of the main line intended for “modern perspectives” traffic, a side track for accommodating through trains of "timeless ideas"; and at the point where primitive Christian eschatology becomes less significant, they redirect the train to the side track, detaching the carriages not meant to go beyond that stop.

This procedure has now been rendered impossible for them by Weiss, who leaves no place in the teaching of Jesus for anything but the single-line traffic of eschatology. If, during the last fifteen years, any one had attempted to carry out in a work on a large scale the plan of Strauss and Renan, linking up the history of the life of Jesus with the history of early Christianity, and New Testament theology with the early history of dogma, the immense difficulties which Weiss had raised without suspecting it, in the course of his sixty-seven pages, would have become clearly apparent. The problem of the Hellenisation of Christianity took on quite a new aspect when the trestle bridge of modern ideas connecting the eschatological early Christianity with Greek theology broke down under the weight of the newly-discovered material, and it became necessary to seek within the history itself an explanation of the way in which an exclusively eschatological system of ideas came to admit Greek influences, and—what is much more difficult to explain—how Hellenism, on its part, found any point of contact with an eschatological sect.

This process has now become impossible for them because of Weiss, who allows no room in the teachings of Jesus for anything other than a straightforward approach to eschatology. If, over the past fifteen years, anyone had tried to implement on a large scale the ideas of Strauss and Renan—connecting the life of Jesus with the early history of Christianity, and New Testament theology with the initial development of dogma—the significant challenges that Weiss raised, though he was unaware of it, throughout his sixty-seven pages, would have become clearly evident. The issue of how Christianity was influenced by Hellenism took on a new perspective when the modern ideas that connected eschatological early Christianity with Greek theology collapsed under the weight of newly discovered materials. It became essential to look within the history itself to explain how a purely eschatological system of thought began to incorporate Greek influences, and—what’s even harder to explain—how Hellenism found any common ground with an eschatological sect.

The new problem is as yet hardly recognised, much less grappled with. The few who since Weiss's time have sought to pass over from the life of Jesus to early Christianity, have acted like men who find themselves on an ice-floe which is slowly dividing into two pieces, and who leap from one to the other before the cleft grows too wide. Harnack, in his “What is Christianity?” almost entirely ignores the contemporary limitations of Jesus' teaching, and starts out with a Gospel which carries him down without difficulty to the year 1899. The anti-historical violence of this procedure is, if possible, still more pronounced in Wernle. The “Beginnings of our Religion”172 begins by putting the Jewish eschatology in a convenient posture for the coming operation by urging that the idea of the Messiah, since there was no appropriate place for it in connexion with the Kingdom of God or the new Earth, had become obsolete for the Jews themselves.

The new issue is still barely acknowledged, let alone dealt with. The few who, since Weiss's time, have tried to move from the life of Jesus to early Christianity have acted like people on an ice floe that's slowly splitting into two pieces, jumping from one side to the other before the gap gets too wide. Harnack, in his “What is Christianity?”, mostly overlooks the contemporary limitations of Jesus' teachings and begins with a Gospel that smoothly leads him down to 1899. The historical disregard in this approach is, if anything, even more evident in Wernle. The “Origins of our Religion”172 starts by positioning Jewish eschatology conveniently for the upcoming discussion, arguing that the idea of the Messiah became outdated for the Jews since there was no suitable connection to the Kingdom of God or the new Earth.

The inadequateness of the Messianic idea for the purposes of Jesus is therefore self-evident. “His whole life long”—as if we knew any more of it than the few months of His public ministry!—“He laboured to give a new and higher content to the Messianic title which He had adopted.” In the course of this endeavour He [pg 253] discarded “the Messiah of the Zealots”—by that is meant the political non-transcendent Messianic ideal. As if we had any knowledge of the existence of such an ideal in the time of Jesus! The statements of Josephus suggest, and the conduct of Pilate at the trial of Jesus confirms the conclusion, that in none of the risings did a claimant of the Messiahship come forward, and this should be proof enough that there did not exist at that time a political eschatology alongside of the transcendental, and indeed it could not on inner grounds subsist alongside of it. That was, after all, the thing which Weiss had shown most clearly!

The inadequacy of the Messianic idea for Jesus' purposes is therefore obvious. "His entire life"—as if we know more about it than just the few months of His public ministry!—“He aimed to provide a new and deeper significance to the Messianic title He had taken on.” During this effort, He [pg 253] rejected “the Zealots' Messiah”—referring to the political, non-transcendent Messianic ideal. As if we had any evidence of such an ideal existing in Jesus' time! The writings of Josephus suggest, and Pilate's actions during Jesus' trial confirm, that no one claiming to be the Messiah emerged during any of the uprisings, which should be enough proof that there was no political eschatology existing alongside the transcendental one, and indeed, it could not coexist with it for internal reasons. That was, after all, what Weiss demonstrated most clearly!

Jesus, therefore, had dismissed the Messiah of the Zealots; He had now to turn Himself into the “waiting” Messiah of the Rabbis. Yet He does not altogether accept this rôle, for He works actively as Messiah. His struggle with the Messianic conception could not but end in transforming it. This transformed conception is introduced by Jesus to the people at His entry into Jerusalem, since His choice of the ass to bear Him inscribed as a motto, so to speak, over the demonstration the prophecy of the Messiah who should be a bringer of peace. A few days later He gives the Scribes to understand by His enigmatic words with reference to Mark xii. 37, that His Messiahship has nothing to do with Davidic descent and all that that implied.

Jesus had dismissed the Zealots' idea of the Messiah and now found Himself becoming the "waiting" Messiah of the Rabbis. However, He didn’t fully accept this role, as He actively worked as the Messiah. His struggle with the conventional view of the Messiah inevitably led to a transformation of that idea. This new understanding was introduced to the people during His entry into Jerusalem, where His choice to ride an ass symbolized the prophesied Messiah as a bringer of peace. A few days later, He indicated to the Scribes through His puzzling words, referencing Mark 12:37, that His role as Messiah had nothing to do with being a descendant of David or what that typically entailed.

The Kingdom of God was not, of course, for Him, according to Wernle, a purely eschatological entity; He saw in many events evidence that it had already dawned. Wernle's only real concession to the eschatological school is the admission that the Kingdom always remained for Jesus a supernatural entity.

The Kingdom of God was not just, according to Wernle, a future event; He noticed many signs that it had already begun. Wernle's only real acceptance of the eschatological viewpoint is that the Kingdom always stayed a supernatural concept for Jesus.

The belief in the presence of the Kingdom was, it seems, only a phase in the development of Jesus. When confronted with growing opposition He abandoned this belief again, and the super-earthly future character of the Kingdom was all that remained. At the end of His career Jesus establishes a connexion between the Messianic conception, in its final transformation, and the Kingdom, which had retained its eschatological character; He goes to His death for the Messiahship in its new significance, but He goes on believing in His speedy return as the Son of Man. This expectation of His Parousia as Son of Man, which only emerges immediately before His exit from the world—when it can no longer embarrass the author in his account of the preaching of Jesus—is the only point in which Jesus does not overcome the inadequacy of the Messianic idea with which He had to deal. “At this point the fantastic conception of Late Judaism, the magically transformed world of the ancient popular belief, thrusts itself incongruously into Jesus' great and simple consciousness of His vocation.”

The belief in the presence of the Kingdom was, it seems, just a phase in Jesus' development. When he faced increasing opposition, he let go of this belief, and all that remained was the idea of the Kingdom as something beyond this world. Toward the end of his life, Jesus connects the Messianic idea, in its final form, with the Kingdom, which still held its end-time significance; he goes to his death for the Messiah role in its new meaning but continues to believe in his quick return as the Son of Man. This expectation of his return as the Son of Man, which only comes up right before he leaves the world—when it can no longer cause issues for the author in his account of Jesus' preaching—is the one area where Jesus does not fully resolve the limitations of the Messianic idea he had to contend with. “At this stage, the fantastical ideas of Late Judaism and the magically altered world of ancient popular belief awkwardly interrupt Jesus' deep and clear understanding of his mission.”

Thus Wernle takes with him only so much of Apocalyptic as he can safely carry over into early Christianity. Once he has got [pg 254] safely across, he drags the rest over after him. He shows that in and with the titles and expressions borrowed from apocalyptic thought, Messiah, Son of God, Son of Man, which were all at bottom so inappropriate to Jesus, early Christianity slipped in again “either the old ideas or new ones misunderstood.” In pointing this out he cannot refrain from the customary sigh of regret—these apocalyptic titles and expressions “were from the first a misfortune for the new religion.” One may well ask how Wernle has discovered in the preaching of Jesus anything that can be called, historically, a new religion, and what would have become of this new religion apart from its apocalyptic hopes and its apocalyptic dogma? We answer: without its intense eschatological hope the Gospel would have perished from the earth, crushed by the weight of historic catastrophes. But, as it was, by the mighty power of evoking faith which lay in it, eschatology made good in the darkest times Jesus' sayings about the imperishability of His words, and died as soon as these sayings had brought forth new life upon a new soil. Why then make such a complaint against it?

Thus, Wernle only brings over as much of the Apocalyptic as he can safely integrate into early Christianity. Once he has successfully moved [pg 254] over, he drags the rest along with him. He demonstrates that through the titles and phrases borrowed from apocalyptic thought—Messiah, Son of God, Son of Man—which were fundamentally unsuitable for Jesus, early Christianity again slipped in "either the old ideas or the new ones are misunderstood." While pointing this out, he can't help but express a familiar sense of regret—these apocalyptic titles and phrases “were a setback for the new religion from the beginning.” One might reasonably question how Wernle has identified anything in Jesus' preaching that can be historically considered a new religion, and what would have become of this new religion without its apocalyptic hopes and dogma. We respond: without its intense eschatological hope, the Gospel would have faded away, crushed by the weight of historical disasters. However, through the powerful ability to inspire faith that it possessed, eschatology validated Jesus' words about the endurance of His teachings during the darkest times, and it vanished as soon as those teachings produced new life in a fresh context. So why complain about it?

The tragedy does not consist in the modification of primitive Christianity by eschatology, but in the fate of eschatology itself, which has preserved for us all that is most precious in Jesus, but must itself wither, because He died upon the cross with a loud cry, despairing of bringing in the new heaven and the new earth—that is the real tragedy. And not a tragedy to be dismissed with a theologian's sigh, but a liberating and life-giving influence, like every great tragedy. For in its death-pangs eschatology bore to the Greek genius a wonder-child, the mystic, sensuous, Early-Christian doctrine of immortality, and consecrated Christianity as the religion of immortality to take the place of the slowly dying civilisation of the ancient world.

The tragedy doesn't come from the way primitive Christianity has been changed by eschatology, but from the fate of eschatology itself. Eschatology has kept for us all that is most valuable in Jesus, but it must ultimately fade away because He died on the cross with a loud cry, in despair of establishing the new heaven and new earth—that is the real tragedy. And it's not just a tragedy to be brushed off with a theologian's sigh, but a liberating and life-giving force, like every great tragedy. For in its final struggles, eschatology brought forth a wonder-child to the Greek mind, the mystical, sensory, Early-Christian idea of immortality, and it established Christianity as the religion of immortality to replace the slowly dying civilization of the ancient world.

But it is not only those who want to find a way from the preaching of Jesus to early Christianity who are conscious of the peculiar difficulties raised by the recognition of its purely Jewish eschatological character, but also those who wish to reconstruct the connexion backwards from Jesus to Judaism. For example, Wellhausen and Schürer repudiate the results arrived at by the eschatological school, which, on its part, bases itself upon their researches into Late Judaism. Wellhausen, in his “Israelitish and Jewish History,”173 gives a picture of Jesus which lifts Him out of the Jewish frame altogether. The Kingdom which He desires to found becomes a present spiritual entity. To the Jewish eschatology [pg 255] His preaching stands in a quite external relation, for what was in His mind was rather a fellowship of spiritual men engaged in seeking a higher righteousness. He did not really desire to be the Messiah, and in His inmost heart had renounced the hopes of His people. If He called Himself Messiah, it was in view of a higher Messianic ideal. For the people His acceptance of the Messiahship denoted the supersession of their own very differently coloured expectation. The transcendental events become immanent. In regard to the apocalyptic Judgment of the World, he retains only the sermon preserved by John about the inward and constant process of separation.

But it’s not just those trying to trace a path from Jesus' preaching to early Christianity who recognize the unique challenges posed by acknowledging its strictly Jewish eschatological nature; those looking to connect Jesus back to Judaism feel the same difficulties. For instance, Wellhausen and Schürer dismiss the findings of the eschatological school, which relies on their studies of Late Judaism. In Wellhausen's "Israeli and Jewish History,"173 he presents a view of Jesus that completely removes Him from the Jewish context. The Kingdom He aims to establish transforms into a present spiritual reality. His teachings relate very little to Jewish eschatology [pg 255], as what He envisioned was more of a community of spiritual individuals striving for a higher righteousness. He didn’t genuinely want to be the Messiah and had deep down given up on His people’s hopes. When He identified as the Messiah, it was in light of a loftier Messianic ideal. For the people, His acceptance of this title suggested a replacement of their own, very different expectations. The extraordinary events become ordinary. Regarding the apocalyptic Judgment of the World, He only keeps the sermon recorded by John about the ongoing and internal process of separation.

Although not to the same extent, Schürer also, in his view of the teaching of Jesus, is strongly influenced by the Fourth Gospel. In an inaugural discourse of 1903174 he declares that in his opinion there is a certain opposition between Judaism and the preaching of Jesus, since the latter contains something absolutely new. His Messiahship is only the temporally limited expression of a unique, generally ethical, consciousness of being a child of God, which has a certain analogy with the relation of all God's children to their Heavenly Father. The reason for His reserve in regard to His Messiahship was, according to Schürer, Jesus' fear of kindling “political enthusiasm”; from the same motive He repudiates in Mark xii. 37 all claim to be the Messiah of David's line. The ideas of the Messiah and the Kingdom of God at least underwent a transformation in His use of them. If in His earlier preaching He only announces the Kingdom as something future, in His later preaching He emphasises the thought that in its beginnings it is already present.

Although not to the same extent, Schürer is also significantly influenced by the Fourth Gospel in his perspective on the teachings of Jesus. In an inaugural address from 1903174, he states that he believes there is a certain opposition between Judaism and Jesus' message, as the latter includes something completely new. His role as the Messiah is merely a temporarily limited expression of a unique, generally ethical awareness of being a child of God, which has some similarity to the relationship of all God's children with their Heavenly Father. According to Schürer, Jesus’ hesitance about His Messiahship stemmed from His fear of inciting political passion; for the same reason, He rejects any claim to be the Messiah from David's lineage in Mark xii. 37. The concepts of the Messiah and the Kingdom of God at least underwent a transformation in His interpretation of them. While in His earlier preaching He only speaks of the Kingdom as a future reality, in His later preaching, He emphasizes that its beginnings are already present.

That it is precisely the representatives of the study of Late Judaism who lift Jesus out of the Late-Jewish world of thought, is not in itself a surprising phenomenon. It is only an expression of the fact that here something new and creative enters into an uncreative age, and of the clear consciousness that this Personality cannot be resolved into a complex of contemporary ideas. The problem of which they are conscious is the same as Bousset's. But the question cannot be avoided whether the violent separation of Jesus from Late Judaism is a real solution, or whether the very essence of Jesus' creative power does not consist, not in taking out one or other of the parts of the eschatological machinery, but in doing what no one had previously done, namely, in setting the whole machinery in motion by the application of an ethico-religious motive power. To perceive the unsatisfactoriness of the transformation hypothesis it is only necessary to think of all the [pg 256] conditions which would have to be realised in order to make it possible to trace, even in general outline, the evidence of such a transformation in the Gospel narrative.

That it's the scholars studying Late Judaism who separate Jesus from the Late-Jewish way of thinking isn’t surprising. It simply reflects the reality that something new and innovative is emerging in a stagnant era, and there's a clear awareness that this figure cannot be reduced to a mix of contemporary ideas. The issue they recognize is the same as Bousset's. However, the question remains whether the forceful division of Jesus from Late Judaism truly resolves anything, or if the very essence of Jesus' creative influence lies not in picking apart elements of the eschatological framework, but in doing what no one else had done before—activating the entire framework through a unique ethico-religious motivation. To see the shortcomings of this transformation theory, one just needs to consider all the [pg 256] conditions that would need to be satisfied to even vaguely outline such a transformation in the Gospel narrative.

All these solutions of the eschatological question start from the teaching of Jesus, and it was, indeed, from this point of view that Johannes Weiss had stated the problem. The final decision of the question is not, however, to be found here, but in the examination of the whole course of Jesus' life. On which of the two presuppositions, the assumption that His life was completely dominated by eschatology, or the assumption that He repudiated it, do we find it easiest to understand the connexion of events in the life of Jesus, His fate, and the emergence of the expectation of the Parousia in the community of His disciples?

All these solutions to the eschatological question start with the teachings of Jesus, and it was indeed from this perspective that Johannes Weiss framed the problem. However, the final answer to the question isn't found here, but rather in examining the entire course of Jesus' life. Which of the two assumptions—whether His life was entirely dominated by eschatology or whether He rejected it—helps us best understand the connection of events in Jesus' life, His fate, and the rise of the expectation of the Parousia in His disciples' community?

The works which in the examination of the connexion of events follow a critical procedure are few and far between. The average “Life of Jesus” shows in this respect an inconceivable stupidity. The first, after Bruno Bauer, to apply critical methods to this point was Volkmar; between Volkmar and Wrede the only writer who here showed himself critical, that is sceptical, was W. Brandt. His work on the “Gospel History”175 appeared in 1893, a year after Johannes Weiss's work and in the same year as Bousset's reply. In this book the question of the absolute, or only partial, dominance of eschatology is answered on the ground of the general course of Jesus' life.

The works that critically examine the connection of events are quite rare. The typical "Life of Jesus" demonstrates a surprising level of ignorance in this regard. Volkmar was the first to apply critical methods to this issue after Bruno Bauer; the only other writer who showed a critical, or skeptical, approach between Volkmar and Wrede was W. Brandt. His work on the "Gospel History"175 was published in 1893, a year after Johannes Weiss's publication and in the same year as Bousset's response. In this book, the question of whether eschatology is absolutely or only partially dominant is addressed based on the overall trajectory of Jesus' life.

Brandt goes to work with a truly Cartesian scepticism. He first examines all the possibilities that the reported event did not happen in the way in which it is reported before he is satisfied that it really did happen in that way. Before he can accept the statement that Jesus died with a loud outcry, he has to satisfy his critical conscience by the following consideration: “The statement regarding this cry, is, so far as I can see, to be best explained by supposing that it was really uttered.” The burial of Jesus owes its acceptance as history to the following reflection. “We hold Joseph of Arimathea to be an historical person; but the only reason which the narrative has for preserving his name is that he buried Jesus. Therefore the name guarantees the fact.”

Brandt approaches his work with a truly skeptical mindset. He first looks at all the possibilities that the reported event didn't happen the way it's said to have before he is convinced that it actually did occur that way. Before he can agree with the statement that Jesus died with a loud cry, he needs to satisfy his critical conscience with the following thought: "The statement about this cry is best understood by assuming it was actually made." The acceptance of Jesus' burial as a historical fact is based on this reflection: "We see Joseph of Arimathea as a historical figure, but the only reason his name appears in the story is that he buried Jesus. So, the name itself backs up the fact."

But the moment the slightest possibility presents itself that the event happened in a different way, Brandt declines to be held by any seductions of the text, and makes his own “probably” into an [pg 257] historical fact. For instance, he thinks it unlikely that Peter was the only one to smite with the sword; so the history is immediately rectified by the phrase “that sword-stroke was doubtless not the only one, other disciples also must have pressed to the front.” That Jesus was first condemned by the Sanhedrin at a night-sitting, and that Pilate in the morning confirmed the sentence, seems to him on various grounds impossible. It is therefore decided that we have here to do only with a combination devised by “a Christian from among the Gentiles.” In this way the “must have been's” and “may have been's” exercise a veritable reign of terror throughout the book.

But the moment there's even the slightest chance that the event occurred differently, Brandt refuses to be swayed by any allure of the text and turns his own “likely” into an [pg 257] historical fact. For example, he doubts that Peter was the only one who struck with the sword; so the history is quickly adjusted by the phrase "That sword strike was definitely not the only one; other disciples must have also pushed to the front." He finds it impossible for Jesus to have been condemned first by the Sanhedrin at a night meeting, and then for Pilate to confirm the sentence in the morning, for various reasons. Therefore, it’s concluded that we are dealing only with a combination created by "a Christian from the Gentiles." This way, the “must've been” and "might have been's" cast a real reign of terror throughout the book.

Yet that does not prevent the general contribution of the book to criticism from being a very remarkable one. Especially in regard to the trial of Jesus, it brings to light a whole series of previously unsuspected problems. Brandt is the first writer since Bauer who dares to assert that it is an historical absurdity to suppose that Pilate, when the people demanded from him the condemnation of Jesus, answered: “No, but I will release you another instead of Him.”

Yet that doesn’t stop the overall contribution of the book to criticism from being quite remarkable. Especially regarding the trial of Jesus, it uncovers a whole series of previously unrecognized issues. Brandt is the first writer since Bauer who dares to claim that it’s historically ridiculous to think that Pilate, when the crowd demanded the criticism of Jesus, responded: “No, but I will release another one for you instead of Him.”

As his starting-point he takes the complete contrast between the Johannine and Synoptic traditions, and the inherent impossibility of the former is proved in detail. The Synoptic tradition goes back to Mark alone. His Gospel is, as was also held by Bruno Bauer, and afterwards by Wrede, a sufficient basis for the whole tradition. But this Gospel is not a purely historical source, it is also, and in a very much larger degree, poetic invention. Of the real history of Jesus but little is preserved in the Gospels. Many of the so-called sayings of the Lord are certainly to be pronounced spurious, a few are probably to be recognised as genuine. But the theory of the “poetic invention” of the earliest Evangelist is not consistently carried out, because Brandt does not take as his criterion, as Wrede did later, a definite principle on which Mark is supposed to have constructed his Gospel, but decides each case separately. Consequently the most important feature of the work lies in the examination of detail.

He starts by highlighting the complete contrast between the Johannine and Synoptic traditions, proving the inherent impossibility of the former in detail. The Synoptic tradition traces back solely to Mark. His Gospel serves, as Bruno Bauer and later Wrede argued, as a sufficient foundation for the whole tradition. However, this Gospel is not just a purely historical source; it’s also, and to a much greater extent, a poetic creation. Very little of the actual history of Jesus is preserved in the Gospels. Many of the so-called sayings of the Lord are definitely spurious, while a few can probably be recognized as genuine. However, the theory of the “poetic creativity” by the earliest Evangelist is not consistently applied because Brandt does not use a specific criterion, as Wrede later did, to determine how Mark constructed his Gospel, instead evaluating each case individually. As a result, the most significant aspect of the work focuses on the examination of details.

Jesus died and was believed to have risen again: this is the only absolutely certain information that we have regarding His “Life.” And accordingly this is the crucial instance for testing the worth of the Gospel tradition. It is only on the basis of an elaborate criticism of the accounts of the suffering and resurrection of Jesus that Brandt undertakes to give a sketch of the life of Jesus as it really was.

Jesus died and was believed to have risen again: this is the only completely certain information we have about His "Life." Therefore, this is the key example for evaluating the value of the Gospel tradition. It's only through a thorough analysis of the accounts of Jesus's suffering and resurrection that Brandt attempts to provide an overview of Jesus's life as it truly was.

What was, then, so far as appears from His life, Jesus' attitude towards eschatology? It was, according to Brandt, a self-contradictory attitude. “He believed in the near approach of the Kingdom of God, and yet, as though its time were still far distant, [pg 258] He undertakes the training of disciples. He was a teacher and yet is said to have held Himself to be the Messiah.” The duality lies not so much in the teaching itself; it is rather a cleavage between His conviction and consciousness on the one hand, and His public attitude on the other.

What was, then, as it seems from His life, Jesus' attitude towards eschatology? According to Brandt, it was a self-contradictory stance. "He believed that the Kingdom of God was coming soon, but as if its arrival were still distant, [pg 258] he began training disciples. He was a teacher and yet was known to see Himself as the Messiah." The contradiction lies not so much in the teaching itself; rather, it reflects a disconnect between His personal beliefs and awareness on one side, and His public demeanor on the other.

To this observation we have to add a second, namely, that Jesus cannot possibly during the last few days at Jerusalem have come forward as Messiah. Critics, with the exception, of course, of Bruno Bauer, had only cursorily touched on this question. The course of events in the last few days in Jerusalem does not at all suggest a Messianic claim on the part of Jesus, indeed it directly contradicts it. Only imagine what would have happened if Jesus had come before the people with such claims, or even if such thoughts had been so much as attributed to Him! On the other side, of course, we have the report of the Messianic entry, in which Jesus not only accepted the homage offered to Him as Messiah, but went out of His way to invite it; and the people must therefore from that point onwards have regarded him as Messiah. In consequence of this contradiction in the narrative, all Lives of Jesus slur over the passage, and seem to represent that the people sometimes suspected Jesus' Messiahship, sometimes did not suspect it, or they adopt some other similar expedient. Brandt, however, rigorously drew the logical inference. Since Jesus did not stand and preach in the temple as Messiah, He cannot have entered Jerusalem as Messiah. Therefore “the well-known Messianic entry is not historical.” That is also implied by the manner of His arrest. If Jesus had come forward as a Messianic claimant, He would not simply have been arrested by the civil police; Pilate would have had to suppress a revolt by military force.

To this observation, we need to add another: Jesus definitely could not have presented Himself as the Messiah in the last few days in Jerusalem. Critics, except for Bruno Bauer, have only briefly touched on this issue. The events leading up to those last days in Jerusalem do not suggest that Jesus claimed to be the Messiah; in fact, they contradict it outright. Just think about what would have happened if Jesus had come forward with those claims, or even if people had just attributed such thoughts to Him! On the other hand, we have the report of the Messianic entry, where Jesus not only accepted the homage offered to Him as the Messiah but actively invited it; as a result, the people must have seen Him as the Messiah from that moment on. Because of this contradiction in the story, all Lives of Jesus gloss over this section and seem to suggest that people occasionally suspected Jesus’ Messiahship and sometimes didn’t, or they come up with some other similar workaround. Brandt, however, made the logical conclusion. Since Jesus did not stand and preach in the temple as the Messiah, He cannot have entered Jerusalem as the Messiah. Therefore “The famous Messianic entry is not historical.” This is also suggested by how He was arrested. If Jesus had claimed to be the Messiah, He wouldn’t have simply been arrested by the civil police; Pilate would have had to put down a rebellion with military force.

This admission implies the surrender of one of the most cherished prejudices of the anti-eschatological school, namely, that Jesus raised the thoughts of the people to a higher conception of His Messiahship, and consequently to a spiritual view of the Kingdom of God, or at least tried so to raise them. But we cannot assume this to have been His intention, since He does not allow the multitude to suspect His Messiahship. Thus the conception of a “transformation” becomes untenable as a means of reconciling eschatological and non-eschatological elements. And as a matter of fact—that is the stroke of critical genius in the book—Brandt lets the two go forward side by side without any attempt at reconciliation; for the reconciliation which would be possible if one had only to deal with the teaching of Jesus becomes impossible when one has to take in His life as well. For Brandt the life of Jesus is the life of a Galilaean teacher who, in consequence of the eschatology with which the period was so fully charged, was for a time and to a certain extent set at variance with [pg 259] Himself and who met His fate for that reason. This conception is at bottom identical with Renan's. But the stroke of genius in leaving the gap between eschatological and non-eschatological elements unbridged sets this work, as regards its critical foundation and historical presentment, high above the smooth romance of the latter.

This admission means giving up one of the most deeply held beliefs of the anti-eschatological camp: that Jesus elevated people's thoughts to a higher understanding of His role as the Messiah, prompting them to see the Kingdom of God in a more spiritual way—or at least that He tried to do this. However, we can't assume that this was His intention because He doesn’t let the crowd suspect His Messiahship. Therefore, the idea of a “transformation” doesn’t hold up as a way to reconcile eschatological and non-eschatological elements. In fact, the brilliance of Brandt’s work lies in allowing these two aspects to exist side by side without trying to reconcile them. The reconciliation that might be possible if we only looked at Jesus’ teachings becomes impossible when we consider His life as a whole. For Brandt, Jesus lived as a Galilean teacher who, due to the heavy eschatological atmosphere of His time, found Himself at odds with His mission and ultimately faced the consequences. This view is fundamentally similar to Renan's, but the genius in intentionally leaving the divide between eschatological and non-eschatological elements unbridged elevates this work, both in its critical foundation and historical representation, far above the smooth narrative of the latter.

The course of Jesus' life, according to Brandt, was therefore as follows: Jesus was a teacher; not only so, but He took disciples in order to train them to be teachers. “This is in itself sufficient to show there was a period in His life in which His work was not determined by the thought of the immediate nearness of the decisive moment. He sought men, therefore, who might become His fellow-workers. He began to train disciples who, if He did not Himself live to see the Day of the Lord, would be able after His death to carry on the work of educating the people along the lines which He had laid down.” “Then there occurred in Judaea an event of which the rumour spread like wildfire throughout Palestine. A prophet arose—a thing which had not happened for centuries—a man who came forward as an envoy of God; and this prophet proclaimed the immediate coming of the reign of God: ‘Repent that ye may escape the wrath of God.’ ” The Baptist's great sermon on repentance falls, according to Brandt, in the last period of the life of Jesus. We must assume, he thinks, that before John came forward in this dramatic fashion he had been a teacher, and at that period of his life had numbered Jesus among his pupils. Nevertheless his life previous to his public appearance must have been a rather obscure one. When he suddenly launched out into this eschatological preaching of repentance “he seemed like an Elijah who had long ago been rapt away from the earth and now appeared once more.”

The course of Jesus' life, according to Brandt, went like this: Jesus was a teacher; not only that, but He took on disciples to train them to be teachers as well. "This is enough to show that there was a time in His life when His work wasn't motivated by the idea of an impending crucial moment. He sought out individuals who could be His collaborators. He started training disciples who, in case He didn't survive to witness the Day of the Lord, would be capable of carrying on the task of educating the people based on the principles He had set." “Then, something happened in Judea that spread like wildfire throughout Palestine. A prophet appeared— a rare event after centuries— a man who arose as a messenger of God; and this prophet declared the soon-to-come reign of God: ‘Repent so you can escape God's wrath.’ ” Brandt suggests that the Baptist's significant sermon on repentance took place during the last part of Jesus' life. He believes that before John made this dramatic appearance, he had been a teacher and that at that time in his life, he had counted Jesus among his students. Still, his life before his public ministry must have been rather unremarkable. When he suddenly began preaching eschatological repentance, “he seemed like Elijah, who had long been taken from the earth and had now reappeared.”

From this point onwards Jesus had to concentrate His activity, for the time was short. If He desired to effect anything and so far as possible to make the people, before the coming of the end, obedient to the will of God, He must make Jerusalem the starting-point of His work. “Only from this central position, and only with the help of an authority which had at its disposal the whole synagogal system, could He effect within a short time much, perhaps all, of what was needful. So He determined on journeying to Jerusalem with this end in view, and with the fixed resolve there to carry into effect the will of God.”

From this point on, Jesus had to focus His efforts because time was limited. If He wanted to accomplish anything and, as much as possible, get the people to align with God's will before the end came, He needed to make Jerusalem the starting point of His mission. "Only from this central location, and with the support of an authority that controlled the entire synagogue system, could He accomplish a lot, maybe everything needed, in a short time. So, He decided to go to Jerusalem with this goal in mind, committed to fulfilling God's will there."

The journey to Jerusalem was not therefore a pilgrimage of death. “So long as we are obliged to take the Gospels as a true reflection of the history of Jesus we must recognise with Weizsäcker that Jesus did not go to Jerusalem in order to be put to death there, nor did He go to keep the Feast. Both suppositions are excluded by the vigour of his action in Jerusalem, and the bright colours of hope with which the picture of that period was painted [pg 260] in the recollection of those who had witnessed it.” We cannot therefore regard the predictions of the Passion as historical, or “at most we might perhaps suppose that Jesus in the consciousness of His innocence may have said to His disciples: 'If I should die, may God for the sake of My blood be merciful to you and to the people.'”

The journey to Jerusalem was not a pilgrimage of death. "As long as we have to accept the Gospels as an accurate reflection of Jesus' history, we must agree with Weizsäcker that Jesus didn't go to Jerusalem to be killed, nor did He go to celebrate the Feast. Both ideas are ruled out by the intensity of His actions in Jerusalem and the hopeful feelings remembered by those who witnessed that time [pg 260]." Therefore, we can't see the predictions of the Passion as historical, or “At most, we might imagine that Jesus, knowing He was innocent, could have said to His disciples: ‘If I die, may God, for the sake of My blood, be merciful to you and the people.’”

He went to Jerusalem, then, to fulfil the will of God. “It was God's will that the preaching by which alone the people could be inwardly renewed and made into a real people of God should be recognised and organised by the national and religious authorities. To effect this through the existing authorities, or to realise it in some other way, such was the task which Jesus felt Himself called on to perform.” With his eyes upon this goal, behind which lay the near approach of the Kingdom of God, He set His face towards Jerusalem.

He went to Jerusalem to fulfill God's will. “It was God's intention that preaching, the sole means for the people to be spiritually renewed and transformed into a genuine people of God, should be recognized and organized by national and religious leaders. Accomplishing this through the current authorities, or finding another way to achieve it—this was the mission Jesus felt called to undertake.” With this goal in mind, on the horizon of the imminent arrival of the Kingdom of God, He set His sights on Jerusalem.

“But nothing could be more natural than that out of the belief that He was engaged in a work which God had willed, there should arise an ever stronger belief in His personal vocation.” It was thus that the Messianic consciousness entered into Jesus' thoughts. His conviction of His vocation had nothing to do with a political Messiahship, it was only gradually from the development of events that He was able to draw the inference that He was destined to the Messianic sovereignty, “it may have become more and more clear to Him, but it did not become a matter of absolute certainty.” It was only amid opposition, in deep dejection, in consequence of a powerful inner reaction against circumstances, that He came to recognise Himself with full conviction as the anointed of God.

"But nothing could be more natural than for the belief that He was doing work that God intended to lead to a growing belief in His personal calling." This is how the Messianic awareness took root in Jesus' mind. His belief in His mission had nothing to do with being a political Messiah; it was only through the unfolding of events that He started to realize He was meant for Messianic leadership, "It might have become clearer to Him, but it didn't become a matter of absolute certainty." It was only in the face of opposition, in deep sadness, and as a result of a strong inner response to his circumstances that He fully recognized Himself as God's anointed.

When it began to be bruited about that He was the Messiah, the rulers had Him arrested and handed Him over to the Procurator. Judas the traitor “had only been a short time among His followers, and only in those unquiet days at Jerusalem when the Master had scarcely any opportunity for private intercourse with him and for learning really to know him. He had not been with Jesus during the Galilaean days, and Jesus was consequently nothing more to him than the future ruler of the Kingdom of God.”

When people started talking about Him being the Messiah, the rulers had Him arrested and handed Him over to the Procurator. Judas the traitor “had only been with His followers for a brief period and only during those chaotic days in Jerusalem when the Master had little opportunity for private talks with him to truly understand him. He had not been with Jesus during the Galilean period, so to him, Jesus was just the future leader of the Kingdom of God.”

After His death the disciples “could not, unless something occurred to restore their faith, continue to believe in His Messiahship.” Jesus had taken away with Him in His death the hopes which they had set upon Him, especially as He had not foretold His death, much less His resurrection. “At first, therefore, it would be all in favour of His memory if the disciples remembered that He Himself had never openly and definitely declared Himself to be the Messiah.” They returned to Galilee. “Simon Peter, and perhaps the son of Zebedee, who afterwards ranked along with him as a pillar of the Church, resolved to continue that preparation for their work which [pg 261] had been interrupted by their journey to Jerusalem. It seemed to them that if they were once more on Galilaean soil the days which they had spent in the inhospitable Jerusalem would cease to oppress their spirits with the leaden weight of sorrowful recollection.... One might almost say that they had to make up their minds to give up Jesus the author of the attempt to take Jerusalem by storm; but for Jesus the gracious gentle Galilaean teacher they kept a warm place in their hearts.” So love watched over the dead until hope was rekindled by the Old Testament promises and came to reawaken Him. “The first who, in an enthusiastic vision, saw this wish fulfilled was Simon Peter.” This “resurrection” has nothing to do with the empty grave, which, like the whole narrative of the Jerusalem appearances, only came into the tradition later. The first appearances took place in Galilee. It was there that the Church was founded.

After His death, the disciples "could not continue to believe in His Messiahship unless something happened to restore their faith." Jesus took away with Him the hopes they had placed in Him, especially since He hadn't predicted His death, let alone His resurrection. "At first, it would really help His memory if the disciples remembered that He never openly and definitely claimed to be the Messiah." They went back to Galilee. Simon Peter, along with possibly the son of Zebedee, who later became a key figure in the Church, decided to keep preparing for their work that had been interrupted by their trip to Jerusalem. They felt that being back on Galilean soil would lift the heavy sadness from their hearts that came from the difficult time they had in Jerusalem. It was as if they needed to come to terms with letting go of Jesus, the one who had started the effort to take Jerusalem by force; but they held a special place in their hearts for Jesus, the kind and gentle teacher from Galilee. So love watched over the dead until hope was rekindled by the Old Testament promises, bringing Him back to life. “The first person who, in an excited vision, saw this wish come true was Simon Peter.” This “revival” has nothing to do with the empty grave, which, like the entire narrative of the appearances in Jerusalem, only entered the tradition later. The first appearances occurred in Galilee. It was there that the Church was founded.

This attempt to grasp the connexion of events in the life of Jesus from a purely historical point of view is one of the most important that have ever been made in this department of study. If it had been put in a purely constructive form, this criticism would have made an impression unequalled by any other Life of Jesus since Renan's. But in that case it would have lost that free play of ideas which the critical recognition of the unbridged gap admits. The eschatological question is not, it is true, decided by this investigation. It shows the impossibility of the previous attempts to establish a present Messiahship of Jesus, but it shows, too, that the questions, which are really historical questions, concerning the public attitude of Jesus, are far from being solved by asserting the exclusively eschatological character of His preaching, but that new difficulties are always presenting themselves.

This effort to understand the connections between events in the life of Jesus from a purely historical perspective is one of the most significant ever made in this field of study. If it had been presented in a strictly constructive way, this critique would have made an impression unmatched by any other Life of Jesus since Renan's. However, in that case, it would have lost the openness of ideas that the critical acknowledgment of the significant gap allows. The eschatological question is not resolved by this investigation. It demonstrates the failure of previous attempts to establish Jesus as a present Messiah, but it also shows that the genuinely historical questions regarding the public perception of Jesus are far from resolved by claiming that His preaching is solely eschatological; rather, new challenges continue to emerge.

It was perhaps not so much through these general ethico-religious historical discussions as in consequence of certain exegetical problems which unexpectedly came to light that theologians became conscious that the old conception of the teaching of Jesus was not tenable, or was only tenable by violent means. On the assumption of the modified eschatological character of His teaching, Jesus is still a teacher; that is to say, He speaks in order to be understood, in order to explain, and has no secrets. But if His teaching is throughout eschatological, then He is a prophet, who points in mysterious speech to a coming age, whose words conceal secrets and offer enigmas, and are not intended to be understood always and by everybody. Attention was now turned to a number of passages in which the question arises whether Jesus had any secrets to keep or not.

It wasn't just through these general ethical and religious historical discussions, but also because of certain interpretive issues that came up unexpectedly, that theologians realized the old view of Jesus' teachings was unsustainable or could only be held onto with great effort. Assuming the modified eschatological nature of His teachings, Jesus remains a teacher; in other words, He speaks to be understood, to explain, and has no hidden messages. However, if His teachings are entirely eschatological, then He is a prophet who speaks in mysterious ways about an upcoming era, with words that hide secrets and offer riddles, not meant to be understood by everyone all the time. Attention then shifted to several passages that raise the question of whether Jesus had any secrets to keep or not.

This question presents itself in connexion with the very earliest of the parables. In Mark iv. 11, 12 it is distinctly stated that the parables spoken in the immediate context embody the mystery of the [pg 262] Kingdom of God in an obscure and unintelligible form, in order that those for whom it is not intended may hear without understanding. But this is not borne out by the character of the parables themselves, since we at least find in them the thought of the constant and victorious development of the Kingdom from small beginnings to its perfect development. After the passage had had to suffer many things from constantly renewed attempts to weaken down or explain away the statement, Jülicher, in his work upon the Parables,176 released it from these tortures, left Jesus the parables in their natural meaning, and put down this unintelligible saying about the purpose of the parabolic form of discourse to the account of the Evangelist. He would rather, to use his own expression, remove a little stone from the masonry of tradition than a diamond from the imperishable crown of honour which belongs to Jesus. Yes, but, for all that, it is an arbitrary assumption which damages the Marcan hypothesis more than will be readily admitted. What was the reason, or what was the mistake which led the earliest Evangelist to form so repellent a theory regarding the purpose of the parables? Is the progressive exaggeration of the contrast between veiled and open speech, to which Jülicher often appeals, sufficient to account for it? How can the Evangelist have invented such a theory, when he immediately proceeds to invalidate it by the rationalising, rather commonplace explanation of the parable of the Sower?

This question arises in connection with the very earliest of the parables. In Mark 4:11-12, it’s clearly stated that the parables spoken in this context represent the mystery of the Kingdom of God in a vague and unclear way, so those who aren't meant to understand will hear without grasping the meaning. However, this doesn’t align with the nature of the parables themselves, since we can at least see in them the idea of the ongoing and victorious growth of the Kingdom from small beginnings to its full development. After this passage faced many challenges from repeated efforts to dilute or reinterpret the statement, Jülicher, in his work on the Parables, freed it from these constraints, allowing Jesus’ parables to retain their natural meaning, and he attributed the confusing claim about the purpose of parabolic discourse to the Evangelist. He preferred, as he put it, to remove a small stone from the structure of tradition rather than a diamond from the enduring crown of honor that rightfully belongs to Jesus. Yet, it remains an arbitrary assumption that undermines the Marcan hypothesis more than is readily acknowledged. What ultimately caused the earliest Evangelist to develop such an off-putting theory about the purpose of the parables? Is the increasing exaggeration of the contrast between veiled and open speech, which Jülicher often references, enough to explain it? How could the Evangelist have created such a theory when he immediately goes on to disprove it with a rational and rather ordinary explanation of the parable of the Sower?

Bernhard Weiss, not being so much under the influence of modern theology as to feel bound to recognise the paedagogic purpose in Jesus, gives the text its due, and admits that Jesus intended to use the parabolic form of discourse as a means of separating receptive from unreceptive hearers. He does not say, however, what kind of secret, intelligible only to the predestined, was concealed in these parables which seem clear as daylight.

Bernhard Weiss, not being too influenced by modern theology to feel obligated to recognize the teaching purpose in Jesus, gives the text its proper credit and acknowledges that Jesus aimed to use parables to differentiate between open and closed-minded listeners. However, he doesn’t explain what kind of secret, understandable only to the chosen ones, was hidden in these parables that seem as clear as day.

That was before Johannes Weiss had stated the eschatological question. Bousset, in his criticism of the eschatological theory,177 is obliged to fall back upon Jülicher's method in order to justify the rationalising modern way of explaining these parables as pointing to a Kingdom of God actually present. It is true Jülicher's explanation of the way in which the theory arose does not satisfy him; he prefers to assume that the basis of this false theory of Mark's is to be found in the fact that the parables concerning the presence of the Kingdom remained unintelligible to the contemporaries of Jesus. But we may fairly ask that he should point out the connecting link between that failure to understand and [pg 263] the invention of a saying like this, which implies so very much more!

That was before Johannes Weiss brought up the eschatological question. Bousset, in his criticism of the eschatological theory, 177 has to rely on Jülicher's approach to justify the modern, rational way of interpreting these parables as signifying a present Kingdom of God. It's true that Jülicher's explanation for how this theory developed doesn’t satisfy him; he prefers to believe that the roots of Mark's incorrect theory lie in the fact that the parables about the presence of the Kingdom were unclear to those who lived during Jesus' time. However, we can reasonably ask him to show the connection between that misunderstanding and [pg 263] the creation of a saying like this, which implies so much more!

If there are no better grounds than that for calling in question Mark's theory of the parables, then the parables of Mark iv., the only ones from which it is possible to extract the admission of a present Kingdom of God, remain what they were before, namely, mysteries.

If there aren't any better reasons than that to challenge Mark's theory of the parables, then the parables in Mark iv., the only ones that suggest the existence of a present Kingdom of God, still remain what they were before: mysteries.

The second volume of Jülicher's “Parables”178 found the eschatological question already in possession of the field. And, as a matter of fact, Jülicher does abandon “the heretofore current method of modernising the parables,” which finds in one after another of them only its own favourite conception of the slow and gradual development of the Kingdom of God. The Kingdom of Heaven is for Jülicher a completely supernatural idea; it is to be realised without human help and independently of the attitude of men, by the sole power of God. The parables of the mustard seed and the leaven are not intended to teach the disciples the necessity and wisdom of a development occupying a considerable time, but are designed to make clear and vivid to them the idea that the period of perfecting and fulfilment will follow with super-earthly necessity upon that of imperfection.

The second volume of Jülicher's "Stories with a moral"178 encountered the eschatological question already dominating the discussion. And, in fact, Jülicher does move away from "the method previously accepted for modernizing the parables," which interprets each parable solely through its own favored concept of the slow and gradual development of the Kingdom of God. For Jülicher, the Kingdom of Heaven is a completely supernatural concept; it will be realized without human involvement and independently of people's attitudes, solely through God's power. The parables of the mustard seed and the leaven are not meant to teach the disciples the necessity and wisdom of a lengthy development, but rather to illustrate clearly and vividly the idea that a period of perfection and fulfillment will inevitably follow the period of imperfection.

But in general the new problem plays no very special part in Jülicher's exposition. He takes up, it might almost be said, in relation to the parables, too independent a position as a religious thinker to care to understand them against the background of a wholly different world-view, and does not hesitate to exclude from the authentic discourses of Jesus whatever does not suit him. This is the fate, for instance, of the parable of the wicked husbandmen in Mark xii. He finds in it traits which read like vaticinia ex eventu, and sees therefore in the whole thing only a prophetically expressed “view of the history as it presented itself to an average man who had been present at the crucifixion of Jesus and nevertheless believed in Him as the Son of God.”

But overall, the new issue doesn't really play a significant role in Jülicher's analysis. He adopts a position that's rather independent as a religious thinker in relation to the parables, showing little interest in understanding them through the lens of a completely different worldview, and he doesn't hesitate to dismiss any parts of Jesus' authentic teachings that don't align with his perspective. For example, the parable of the wicked tenants in Mark 12 ends up being one of those that he rejects. He finds elements in it that seem like prophecy after the fact, and so he interprets the whole story as merely a prophetically articulated “perspective on history as seen by an everyday person who was there during the crucifixion of Jesus and still believed in Him as the Son of God.”

But this absolute method of explanation, independent of any traditional order of time or events, makes it impossible for the author to draw from the parables any general system of teaching. He makes no distinction between the Galilaean mystical parables and the polemical, menacing Jerusalem parables. For instance, he supposes the parable of the Sower, which according to Mark was the very first of Jesus' parabolic discourses, to have been spoken as the result of a melancholy review of a preceding period [pg 264] of work, and as expressing the conviction, stamped upon His mind by the facts, “that it was in accordance with higher laws that the word of God should have to reckon with defeats as well as victories.” Accordingly he adopts in the main the explanation which the Evangelist gives in Mark iv. 13-20. The parable of the seed growing secretly is turned to account in favour of the “present” Kingdom of God.

But this absolute method of explanation, which ignores any traditional order of time or events, makes it impossible for the author to derive a general teaching system from the parables. He does not differentiate between the mystical parables from Galilee and the aggressive, threatening parables from Jerusalem. For example, he assumes that the parable of the Sower, which according to Mark was the very first of Jesus' parabolic teachings, was spoken after a sad reflection on a previous period of work, and expressed the belief, shaped in His mind by reality, "that it was in line with greater principles that the word of God needed to face both defeats and victories." Thus, he largely adopts the explanation provided by the Evangelist in Mark iv. 13-20. The parable of the seed growing secretly is interpreted in support of the “gift” Kingdom of God.

Jülicher has an incomparable power of striking fire out of every one of the parables, but the flame is of a different colour from that which it showed when Jesus pronounced the parables before the enchanted multitude. The problem posed by Johannes Weiss in connexion with the teaching of Jesus is treated by Jülicher only so far as it has a direct interest for the creative independence of his own religious thought.

Jülicher has an unmatched ability to draw insights from every parable, but the meaning is different from what it was when Jesus told these stories to the captivated crowd. Jülicher addresses the issue raised by Johannes Weiss regarding Jesus' teaching only to the extent that it is relevant to the unique development of his own religious beliefs.

Alongside of the parabolic discourses of Mark iv. we have now to place, as a newly discovered problem, the discourse at the sending out of the Twelve in Matt. x. Up to the time of Johannes Weiss it had been possible to rest content with transplanting the gloomy sayings regarding persecutions to the last period of Jesus' life; but now there was the further difficulty to be met that while so hasty a proclamation of the Kingdom of God is quite reconcilable with an exclusively eschatological character of the preaching of the Kingdom, the moment this is at all minimised it becomes unintelligible, not to mention the fact that in this case nothing can be made of the saying about the immediate coming of the Son of Man in Matt. x. 23. As though he felt the stern eye of old Reimarus upon him, Bousset hastens in a footnote to throw overboard the whole report of the mission of the Twelve as an “obscure and unintelligible tradition.” Not content with that, he adds: “Perhaps the whole narrative is merely an expansion of some direction about missionising given by Jesus to the disciples in view of a later time.” Before, it was only the discourse which was unhistorical; now it is the whole account of the mission—at least if we may assume that here, as is usual with theologians of all times, the author's real opinion is expressed in the footnote, and his most cherished opinion of all introduced with “perhaps.” But how much historical material will remain to modern theologians in the Gospels if they are forced to abandon it wholesale from their objection to pure eschatology? If all the pronouncements of this kind to which the representatives of the Marcan hypothesis have committed themselves were collected together, they would make a book which would be much more damaging even than that book of Wrede's which dropped a bomb into their midst.

Alongside the parabolic teachings in Mark 4, we now have to consider, as a newly discovered issue, the speech given at the sending out of the Twelve in Matthew 10. Until Johannes Weiss's time, it was possible to be satisfied with attributing the grim comments about persecution to the last part of Jesus' life; however, now there is the additional challenge that while such a rapid announcement of the Kingdom of God can easily fit into an entirely eschatological view of the Kingdom's preaching, the moment this is reduced in any way, it becomes incomprehensible. Not to mention the fact that, in this scenario, the statement about the immediate return of the Son of Man in Matthew 10:23 is rendered meaningless. As if feeling the critical gaze of old Reimarus upon him, Bousset hurriedly dismisses the entire account of the mission of the Twelve in a footnote as an “confusing and unknown tradition.” Not satisfied with that, he adds: "Maybe the entire story is just an elaboration of some guidance about the mission that Jesus gave to the disciples for a future time." Previously, only the discourse was deemed unhistorical; now it’s the entire mission account—at least if we assume that here, as is common with theologians throughout history, the author's true opinion is revealed in the footnote, and his most cherished view is introduced with "maybe." But how much historical content will remain for modern theologians in the Gospels if they are compelled to discard it entirely based on their objections to pure eschatology? If all such statements by supporters of the Marcan hypothesis were compiled, they would create a book that would be far more damaging than that one by Wrede which caused a stir in their ranks.

A third problem is offered by the saying in Matt. xi. 12, about “the violent” who, since the time of John the Baptist, “take the Kingdom of Heaven by force,” which raises fresh difficulties for the [pg 265] exegetical art. It is true that if art sufficed, we should not have long to wait for the solution in this case. We should be asked to content ourselves with one or other of the artificial solutions with which exegetes have been accustomed from of old to find a way round this difficulty. Usually the saying is claimed as supporting the “presence” of the Kingdom. This is the line taken by Wendt, Wernle, and Arnold Meyer.179 According to the last named it means: “From the days of John the Baptist it has been possible to get possession of the Kingdom of God; yea, the righteous are every day earning it for their own.” But no explanation has heretofore succeeded in making it in any degree intelligible how Jesus could date the presence of the Kingdom from the Baptist, whom in the same breath He places outside of the Kingdom, or why, in order to express so simple an idea, He uses such entirely unnatural and inappropriate expressions as “rape” and “wrest to themselves.”

A third problem arises from the saying in Matt. xi. 12 about "the violent ones" who, since the time of John the Baptist, "seize the Kingdom of Heaven with determination," which creates new challenges for the [pg 265] study of the text. It’s true that if interpretation were enough, we wouldn't have to wait long for an answer in this case. We would be asked to settle for one of the traditional interpretations that scholars have used for years to get around this issue. Typically, this saying is viewed as evidence for the “presence” of the Kingdom. This is the perspective held by Wendt, Wernle, and Arnold Meyer.179 According to the latter, it means: “Since the time of John the Baptist, people have been able to take hold of the Kingdom of God; in fact, the righteous are claiming it for themselves every day.” However, no explanation has successfully clarified how Jesus could claim the Kingdom's presence began with the Baptist, whom He simultaneously places outside of the Kingdom, or why He would use such strange and unsuitable terms as sexual assault and “wrest for themselves.”

The full difficulties of the passage are first exhibited by Johannes Weiss.180 He restores it to its natural sense, according to which it means that since that time the Kingdom suffers, or is subjected to, violence, and in order to be able to understand it literally he has to take it in a condemnatory sense. Following Alexander Schweizer,181 he sums up his interpretation in the following sentence: Jesus describes, and in the form of the description shows His condemnation of, a violent Zealotistic Messianic movement which has been in progress since the days of the Baptist.182 But this explanation again makes Jesus express a very simple meaning in a very obscure phrase. And what indication is there that the sense is condemnatory? Where do we hear anything more about a Zealotic Messianic movement, of which the Baptist formed the starting-point? His preaching certainly offered no incentive to such a movement, and Jesus' attitude towards the Baptist is elsewhere, even in Jerusalem, entirely one of approval. Moreover, a condemnatory saying of this kind would not have been closed with the distinctive formula: “He that hath ears to hear let him hear” (Matt. xi. 15), which elsewhere, cf. Mark iv. 9, indicates a mystery.

The full difficulties of the passage are first shown by Johannes Weiss. He brings it back to its original meaning, which suggests that since that time the Kingdom has been subjected to violence, and to understand it literally, he has to interpret it in a condemnatory way. Following Alexander Schweizer, he summarizes his interpretation in this sentence: Jesus describes, and through this description expresses His condemnation of a violent Zealotistic Messianic movement that has been ongoing since the days of the Baptist. But this explanation makes Jesus convey a very straightforward message in an unclear way. What evidence is there that the meaning is condemnatory? Where do we hear anything more about a Zealotic Messianic movement that started with the Baptist? His preaching certainly didn’t encourage such a movement, and Jesus' attitude towards the Baptist is, in other passages, even in Jerusalem, one of full approval. Additionally, a condemnatory statement like this wouldn't end with the notable phrase: "Anyone who has ears to hear should listen." (Matt. xi. 15), which elsewhere, see Mark iv. 9, indicates a mystery.

We must, therefore, accept the conclusion that we really do not understand the saying, that we “have not ears to hear it,” that we do not know sufficiently well the essential character of the Kingdom of God, to understand why Jesus describes the coming of the [pg 266] Kingdom as a doing-violence-to-it, which has been in progress since the days of the Baptist, especially as the hearers themselves do not seem to have cared, or been able, to understand what was the connexion of the coming with the violence; nor do we know why He expects them to understand how the Baptist is identical with Elias.

We must, therefore, accept the conclusion that we really do not understand the saying that we "do not have ears to hear it," and that we do not know the true nature of the Kingdom of God well enough to grasp why Jesus describes its arrival as something that has been met with violence since the days of the Baptist. This is especially puzzling since the audience themselves don’t seem to have cared or been able to figure out the connection between the coming and the violence; we also don’t know why He expects them to understand how the Baptist is the same as Elias.

But the problem which became most prominent of all the new problems raised by eschatology, was the question concerning the Son of Man. It had become a dogma of theology that Jesus used the term Son of Man to veil His Messiahship; that is to say, every theologian found in this term whatever meaning he attached to the Messiahship of Jesus, the human, humble, ethical, unpolitical, unapocalyptic, or whatever other character was held to be appropriate to the orthodox “transformed” Messiahship. The Danielic Son of Man entered into the conception only so far as it could do so without endangering the other characteristics. Confronted with the Similitudes of Enoch, theologians fell back upon the expedient of assuming them to be spurious, or at least worked-over in a Christian sense in the Son of Man passages, just as the older history of dogma got rid of the Ignatian letters, of which it could make nothing, by denying their genuineness. But once the Jewish eschatology was seriously applied to the explanation of the Son of Man conception, all was changed. A new dilemma presented itself; either Jesus used the expression, and used it in a purely Jewish apocalyptic sense, or He did not use it at all.

But the main issue that emerged from the new challenges brought up by eschatology was the question about the Son of Man. It became a standard belief in theology that Jesus used the term Son of Man to hide His role as the Messiah. This meant that every theologian interpreted this term according to their understanding of Jesus's Messiahship, whether they saw it as human, humble, ethical, non-political, non-apocalyptic, or any other characteristic deemed fitting for the orthodox "changed" Messiah. The Danielic Son of Man only fit into this idea as long as it didn’t undermine the other traits. When faced with the Similitudes of Enoch, theologians resorted to declaring them as inauthentic, or at least revised in a Christian context within the Son of Man references, similar to how earlier theological history dismissed the Ignatian letters, which they couldn’t interpret, by questioning their authenticity. However, once Jewish eschatology was seriously applied to understanding the concept of the Son of Man, everything changed. A new dilemma arose: either Jesus used the term in a strictly Jewish apocalyptic way, or He didn’t use it at all.

Although Baldensperger did not state the dilemma in its full trenchancy, Hilgenfeld thought it necessary to defend Jesus against the suspicion of having borrowed His system of thought and His self-designation from Jewish Apocalypses.183 Orello Cone, too, will not admit that the expression Son of Man has only apocalyptic suggestion in the mouth of Jesus, but will have it interpreted according to Mark ii. 10 and 28, where His pure humanity is the idea which is emphasised.184 Oort holds, more logically, that Jesus did not use it, but that the disciples took the expression from “the Gospel” and put it into the mouth of Jesus.185

Although Baldensperger didn't fully articulate the dilemma, Hilgenfeld felt it was important to defend Jesus against the idea that He borrowed His way of thinking and His title from Jewish Apocalypses.183 Orello Cone, too, does not believe that the term Son of Man only has apocalyptic connotations when spoken by Jesus; he interprets it in light of Mark ii. 10 and 28, where His humanity is the key point.184 Oort argues more logically that Jesus didn't actually use this term; rather, the disciples took it from "the Gospel" and attributed it to Jesus.185

Johannes Weiss formulated the problem clearly, and proposed that, with the exception of the two passages where Son of Man means man in general, only those should be recognised in which the significance attached to the term in Daniel and the Apocalypses is demanded by the context. By so doing he set theology a problem calculated to keep it occupied for many years. Not many indeed at first recognised the problem. Charles, however, meets it [pg 267] in a bold fashion, proposing to regard the Son of Man, in Jesus' usage of the title, as a conception in which the Messiah of the Book of Enoch and the Servant of the Lord in Isaiah are united into one.186 Most writers, however, did not free themselves from inconsistencies. They wanted at one and the same time to make the apocalyptic element dominant in the expression, and to hold that Jesus could not have taken the conception over unaltered, but must have transformed it in some way. These inconsistencies necessarily result from the assumption of Weiss's opponents that Jesus intended to designate Himself as Messiah in the actual present. For since the expression Son of Man has in itself only an apocalyptic sense referring to the future, they had to invent another sense applicable to the present, which Jesus might have inserted into it. In all these learned discussions of the title Son of Man this operation is assumed to have been performed.

Johannes Weiss clearly defined the issue and argued that, aside from the two instances where "Son of Man" refers to humanity in general, only those contexts where its meaning connects to the significance in Daniel and the Apocalypses should be acknowledged. In doing so, he posed a challenge for theology that would keep scholars busy for many years. Initially, not many recognized the challenge. However, Charles boldly tackled it, suggesting that Jesus' use of the title "Son of Man" represents a concept where the Messiah from the Book of Enoch and the Servant of the Lord from Isaiah are merged into one. Most writers, though, struggled with inconsistencies. They simultaneously wanted to emphasize the apocalyptic aspect of the term while believing that Jesus could not have adopted the concept unaltered but must have transformed it in some way. These inconsistencies emerged from Weiss's opponents assuming that Jesus aimed to identify Himself as the Messiah in the present. Since "Son of Man" inherently carries an apocalyptic meaning referring to the future, they had to create an alternative interpretation relevant to the present that Jesus could have used. This assumption underlies all the scholarly discussions about the title "Son of Man."

According to Bousset, Jesus created, and embodied in this term, a new form of the Messianic ideal which united the super-earthly with the human and lowly. In any case, he thinks, the term has a meaning applicable in this present world. Jesus uses it at once to conceal and to suggest His Messianic dignity. How conscious Bousset, nevertheless, is of the difficulty is evident from the fact that in discussing the meaning of the title he remarks that the Messianic significance must have been of subordinate importance in the estimation of Jesus, and cannot have formed the basis of His actions, otherwise He would have laid more stress upon it in His preaching. As if the term Son of Man had not meant for His contemporaries all He needed to say!

According to Bousset, Jesus created and embodied a new version of the Messianic ideal that connected the divine with the human and humble. He believes this term has relevance in today's world. Jesus uses it both to hide and to hint at His Messianic status. Bousset is clearly aware of the challenges, as he points out that when discussing the meaning of the title, the Messianic significance likely held less importance for Jesus than it would seem, and couldn’t have driven His actions; otherwise, He would have emphasized it more in His teachings. As if the term Son of Man didn't convey everything He needed to express to His contemporaries!

Bousset's essay on Jewish Apocalyptic,187 published in 1903, seeks the solution in a rather different direction, by postponing, namely, to the very last possible moment the adoption of this self-designation. “In all probability Jesus in a few isolated sayings towards the close of His life hit upon this title Son of Man as a means of expressing, in the face of the thought of defeat and death, which forced itself upon Him, His confidence in the abiding victory of His person and His cause.” If this is so, the emphasis must be principally on the triumphant apocalyptic aspects of the title.

Bousset's essay on Jewish Apocalyptic, 187 published in 1903, offers a different perspective by delaying the use of this self-designation until the very last moment. "Towards the end of His life, it's likely that Jesus used the title Son of Man in a few isolated statements to express, despite the impending thoughts of defeat and death he was facing, His confidence in the lasting success of His identity and mission." If this is the case, the focus should be primarily on the victorious apocalyptic elements of the title.

Even this belated adoption of the title Son of Man is more [pg 268] than Brandt is willing to admit, and he holds it to be improbable that Jesus used the expression at all. It would be more natural, he thinks, to suppose that the Evangelist Mark introduced this self-designation, as he introduced so much else, into the Gospel on the ground of the figurative apocalyptic discourses in the Gospel.

Even this late adoption of the title Son of Man is more [pg 268] than Brandt is willing to admit, and he believes it's unlikely that Jesus used the term at all. He thinks it would make more sense to assume that the Evangelist Mark added this self-designation, along with many other elements, into the Gospel based on the figurative apocalyptic discussions in the text.

Just when ingenuity appeared to have exhausted itself in attempts to solve the most difficult of the problems raised by the eschatological school, the historical discussion suddenly seemed about to be rendered objectless. Philology entered a caveat. In 1896 appeared Lietzmann's essay upon “The Son of Man,” which consisted of an investigation of the linguistic basis of the enigmatic self-designation.

Just when creativity seemed to have run out in trying to tackle the toughest issues raised by the eschatological school, the historical discussion unexpectedly looked like it would lose its focus. Philology issued a warning. In 1896, Lietzmann published an essay titled “The Son of Man,” which explored the language behind this mysterious self-designation.

[pg 269]

XVII. Questions About The Aramaic Language, Rabbinic Parallels, And Buddhist Influence

Arnold Meyer. Jesu Muttersprache. (The Mother Tongue of Jesus.) Leipzig, 1896. 166 pp.

Arnold Meyer. The Native Language of Jesus. Leipzig, 1896. 166 pages.

Hans Lietzmann. Der Menschensohn. Ein Beitrag zur neutestamentlichen Theologie. (The Son of Man. A Contribution to New Testament Theology.) Freiburg, 1896. 95 pp.

Hans Lietzmann. The Son of Man: A Contribution to New Testament Theology. Freiburg, 1896. 95 pages.

J. Wellhausen. Israelitische und jüdische Geschichte. (History of Israel and the Jews.) 3rd ed., 1897; 4th ed., 1901. 394 pp.

J. Wellhausen. History of Israel and the Jews. 3rd edition, 1897; 4th edition, 1901. 394 pages.

Gustaf Dalman. Grammatik des jüdisch-palästinensischen Aramäisch. (Grammar of Jewish-Palestinian Aramaic.) Leipzig, 1894. Die Worte Jesu. Mit Berücksichtigung des nachkanonischen jüdischen Schrifttums und der aramäischen Sprache. (The Sayings of Jesus considered in connexion with the post-canonical Jewish writings and the Aramaic Language.) I. Introduction and certain leading conceptions: with an appendix on Messianic texts. Leipzig, 1898. 309 pp.

Gustaf Dalman. Grammar of Jewish-Palestinian Aramaic. Leipzig, 1894. The Sayings of Jesus: Analyzing the post-canonical Jewish writings and the Aramaic Language. I. Introduction and key concepts, along with an appendix on Messianic texts. Leipzig, 1898. 309 pp.

A. Wünsche. Neue Beiträge zur Erläuterung der Evangelien aus Talmud und Midrasch. (New Contributions to the Explanation of the Gospels, from Talmud and Midrash.) Göttingen, 1878. 566 pp.

A. Wishes. New Insights into the Interpretation of the Gospels from Talmud and Midrash. Göttingen, 1878. 566 pages.

Ferdinand Weber. System der altsynagogalen palästinensischen Theologie. (System of Theology of the Ancient Palestinian Synagogue.) Leipzig, 1880. 399 pp. 2nd ed., 1897.

Ferdinand Weber. System of Theology of the Ancient Palestinian Synagogue. Leipzig, 1880. 399 pages. 2nd edition, 1897.

Rudolf Seydel. Das Evangelium Jesu in seinen Verhältnissen zur Buddha-Sage und Buddha-Lehre. (The Gospel of Jesus in its relations to the Buddha-Legend and the Teaching of Buddha.) Leipzig, 1882. 337 pp. Die Buddha-Legende und das Leben Jesu nach den Evangelien. Erneute Prüfung ihres gegenseitigen Verhältnisses. (The Buddha-Legend and the Life of Jesus in the Gospels. A New Examination of their Mutual Relations.) 2nd ed., 1897. 129 pp.

Rudolf Seydel. The Gospel of Jesus and its Connections to the Buddha Legend and the Teachings of Buddha. Leipzig, 1882. 337 pages. The Buddha Legend and the Life of Jesus According to the Gospels. A New Perspective on their Relationship. 2nd edition, 1897. 129 pages.

Only since the appearance of Dalman's Grammar of Jewish Palestinian Aramaic in 1894 have we really known what was the dialect in which the Beatitudes of the Sermon on the Mount were spoken. This work closes a discussion which had been proceeding for centuries on a line parallel to that of theology proper, and which, according to the clear description of Arnold Meyer, ran its course somewhat as follows.188

Only since the publication of Dalman's Grammar of Jewish Palestinian Aramaic in 1894 have we truly understood the dialect in which the Beatitudes of the Sermon on the Mount were spoken. This work wraps up a discussion that had been ongoing for centuries alongside theological discussions, and which, as Arnold Meyer clearly described, unfolded in the following way.188

[pg 270]

The question regarding the language spoken by Jesus had been vigorously discussed in the sixteenth century. Up till that time no one had known what to make of the tradition recorded by Eusebius that the speech of the apostles had been “Syrian” since the distinction between Syrian, Hebrew, and “Chaldee” was not understood and all three designations were used indiscriminately. Light was first thrown upon the question by Joseph Justus Scaliger († 1609). In the year 1555, Joh. Alb. Widmanstadt, Chancellor of Ferdinand I., had published the Syriac translation of the Bible in fulfilment of the wishes of an old scholar of Bologna, Theseus Ambrosius, who had left him the manuscript as a sacred legacy. He himself and his contemporaries believed that in this they had the Gospel in the mother-tongue of Jesus, until Scaliger, in one of his letters, gave a clear sketch of the Syrian dialects, distinguished Syriac from Chaldee, and further drew a distinction between the Babylonian Chaldee and Jewish Chaldee of the Targums, and in the language of the Targums itself distinguished an earlier from a later stratum. The apostles spoke, according to Scaliger, a Galilaean dialect of Chaldaic, or according to the more correct nomenclature introduced later, following a suggestion of Scaliger's, a dialect of Aramaic, and, in addition to that, the Syriac of Antioch. Next, Hugo Grotius put in a strong plea for a distinction between Jewish and Antiochian Syriac. Into the confusion caused at that time by the use of the term “Hebrew” some order was introduced by the Leyden Calvinistic professor Claude Saumaise, who, writing in French, emphasised the point that the New Testament, and the Early Fathers, when they speak of Hebrew, mean Syriac, since Hebrew had become completely unknown to the Jews of that period. Brian Walton, the editor of the London polyglot, which was completed in 1657, supposed that the dialect of Onkelos and Jonathan was the language of Jesus, being under the impression that both these Targums were written in the time of Jesus.

The question about the language spoken by Jesus was intensely debated in the sixteenth century. Until then, no one really knew how to interpret Eusebius's tradition that the apostles spoke "Syrian," as the differences between Syrian, Hebrew, and "Chaldee" weren’t clear, and all three terms were often used interchangeably. Joseph Justus Scaliger shed some light on this issue († 1609). In 1555, Joh. Alb. Widmanstadt, Chancellor of Ferdinand I., published the Syriac translation of the Bible at the request of an old scholar from Bologna, Theseus Ambrosius, who had left him the manuscript as a sacred legacy. He and his contemporaries believed this was the Gospel in Jesus's native language until Scaliger, in one of his letters, provided a clear outline of the Syrian dialects, differentiating Syriac from Chaldee, and further distinguishing between Babylonian Chaldee and Jewish Chaldee found in the Targums, recognizing an earlier and a later layer in the language of the Targums itself. According to Scaliger, the apostles spoke a Galilean dialect of Chaldaic, or more accurately, as later terminology suggested based on Scaliger's recommendations, a dialect of Aramaic, along with the Syriac of Antioch. Following this, Hugo Grotius strongly advocated for a distinction between Jewish and Antiochian Syriac. Amid the confusion caused at the time by the use of the term "Hebrew," Leyden Calvinistic professor Claude Saumaise brought some clarity by stating in French that when the New Testament and the Early Fathers referred to Hebrew, they meant Syriac, since Hebrew had become completely unfamiliar to Jews of that era. Brian Walton, the editor of the London polyglot completed in 1657, believed that the dialect of Onkelos and Jonathan was the language of Jesus, mistakenly thinking both Targums were written during Jesus's time.

The growing knowledge of the distinction between Hebrew and Aramaic did not prevent the Vienna Jesuit Inchofer († 1648) from maintaining that Jesus spoke—Latin! The Lord cannot have used any other language upon earth, since this is the language of the saints in heaven. On the Protestant side, Vossius, opposing Richard Simon, endeavoured to establish the thesis that Greek was the language of Jesus, being partly inspired by the apologetic purpose of preventing the authenticity of the discourses and sayings of Jesus from being weakened by supposing them to have been translated from Aramaic into Greek, but also rightly recognising the importance which the Greek language must have assumed at that time in northern Palestine, through which there passed such important trade routes.

The increasing understanding of the differences between Hebrew and Aramaic didn't stop the Jesuit Inchofer from claiming that Jesus spoke—Latin! He argued that the Lord must have used no other language on earth because it is the language of the saints in heaven. On the Protestant side, Vossius, in opposition to Richard Simon, tried to assert that Greek was the language of Jesus. His argument was partly motivated by the desire to maintain the authenticity of Jesus' teachings and sayings, preventing them from being diluted by the idea that they were translated from Aramaic into Greek. He also correctly recognized the significant role the Greek language likely played in northern Palestine at that time, given the important trade routes that passed through the region.

This view was brought up again by the Neapolitan legal scholar, [pg 271] Dominicus Diodati, in his book De Christo Graece loquente, 1767, who added some interesting material concerning the importance of the Greek language at the period and in the native district of Jesus. But five years later, in 1772, this view was thoroughly refuted by Giambernardo de Rossi,189 who argued convincingly that among a people so separate and so conservative as the Jews the native language cannot possibly have been wholly driven out. The apostles wrote Greek for the sake of foreign readers. In the year 1792, Johann Adrian Bolten, “first collegiate pastor at the principal church in Altona” († 1807), made the first attempt to re-translate the sayings of Jesus into the original tongue.190

This idea was brought up again by the Neapolitan legal scholar, [pg 271] Dominicus Diodati, in his book Christ speaking in Greek, 1767, who included some interesting information about the importance of the Greek language during the time and in the region where Jesus grew up. But five years later, in 1772, this viewpoint was thoroughly challenged by Giambernardo de Rossi,189 who convincingly argued that among a community as isolated and traditional as the Jews, the native language couldn't possibly have been completely eliminated. The apostles wrote in Greek for the benefit of non-Jewish readers. In 1792, Johann Adrian Bolten, "first college pastor at the main church in Altona" († 1807), made the first attempt to retranslate the sayings of Jesus into the original language.190

The certainly original Greek of the Epistles and the Johannine literature was a strong argument against the attempt to recognise no language save Aramaic as known to Jesus and His disciples. Paulus the rationalist, therefore, sought a middle path, and explained that while the Aramaic dialect was indeed the native language of Jesus, Greek had become so generally current among the population of Galilee, and still more of Jerusalem, that the founders of Christianity could use this language when they found it needful to do so. His Catholic contemporary, Hug, came to a similar conclusion.

The original Greek of the Epistles and the Johannine literature strongly argued against the idea that Jesus and His disciples only knew Aramaic. Paulus the rationalist, therefore, tried to find a middle ground, explaining that while Aramaic was indeed Jesus's native language, Greek had become widely spoken among the people of Galilee and even more so in Jerusalem, allowing the founders of Christianity to use it when necessary. His Catholic contemporary, Hug, reached a similar conclusion.

In the course of the nineteenth century Aramaic—known down to the time of Michaelis as “Chaldee”191—was more thoroughly studied. The various branches of this language and the history of its progress became more or less clearly recognisable. Kautzsch's grammar of Biblical Aramaic192 (1884) and Dalman's193 work embody the result of these studies. “The Aramaic language,” explains Meyer, “is a branch of the North Semitic, the linguistic stock to which also belong the Assyrio-Babylonian language in the East, and the Canaanitish languages, including Hebrew, in the West, while the South Semitic languages—the Arabic and Aethiopic—form a group by themselves.” The users of these languages, the [pg 272] Aramaeans, were seated in historic times between the Babylonians and Canaanites, the area of their distribution extending from the foot of Lebanon and Hermon in a north-easterly direction as far as Mesopotamia, where “Aram of the two rivers” forms their easternmost province. Their immigration into these regions forms the third epoch of the Semitic migrations, which probably lasted from 1600 b.c. down to 600.

During the nineteenth century, Aramaic—previously referred to as “Chaldean”191—was studied in greater depth. The different branches of this language and its historical development became more recognizable. Kautzsch's grammar of Biblical Aramaic192 (1884) and Dalman's193 work reflect the outcomes of these studies. “Aramaic language,” explains Meyer, “is part of the North Semitic family, which also includes the Assyrio-Babylonian language in the East and the Canaanitish languages, like Hebrew, in the West, while the South Semitic languages—Arabic and Ethiopic—make up their own group.” The speakers of these languages, the [pg 272] Aramaeans, were historically positioned between the Babylonians and Canaanites, with their territory stretching from the base of Lebanon and Hermon northeastward to Mesopotamia, where “Aram of the Tigris and Euphrates” serves as their easternmost province. Their migration into these areas marks the third phase of the Semitic migrations, which likely took place from 1600 b.c. to 600.

The Aramaic states had no great stability. The most important of them was the kingdom of Damascus, which at a certain period was so dangerous an enemy to northern Israel. In the end, however, the Aramaean dynasties were crushed, like the two Israelitish kingdoms, between the upper and nether millstones of Babylon and Egypt. In the time of the successors of Alexander, there arose in these regions the Syrian kingdom; which in turn gave place to the Roman power.

The Aramaic states lacked stability. The kingdom of Damascus was the most significant, posing a major threat to northern Israel at one point. Ultimately, however, the Aramaean dynasties were destroyed, just like the two Israelite kingdoms, caught between the powers of Babylon and Egypt. During the time of Alexander's successors, the Syrian kingdom emerged in these areas, which was eventually replaced by Roman dominance.

But linguistically the Aramaeans conquered the whole of Western Asia. In the course of the first millennium b.c. Aramaic became the language of commerce and diplomacy, as Babylonian had been during the second. It was only the rise of Greek as a universal language which put a term to these conquests of the Aramaic.

But linguistically, the Aramaeans took over all of Western Asia. During the first millennium b.c., Aramaic became the language of business and diplomacy, just like Babylonian had been in the second millennium. It wasn't until the rise of Greek as a universal language that the spread of Aramaic came to an end.

In the year 701 b.c. Aramaic had not yet penetrated to Judaea. When the rabshakeh (officer) sent by Sennacherib addressed the envoys of Hezekiah in Hebrew, they begged him to speak Aramaic in order that the men upon the wall might not understand.194 For the post-exilic period the Aramaic edicts in the Book of Ezra and inscriptions on Persian coins show that throughout wide districts of the new empire Aramaic had made good its position as the language of common intercourse. Its domain extended from the Euxine southwards as far as Egypt, and even into Egypt itself. Samaria and the Hauran adopted it. Only the Greek towns and Phoenicia resisted.

In the year 701 b.c., Aramaic had not yet reached Judaea. When the rabshakeh (officer) sent by Sennacherib spoke to Hezekiah's envoys in Hebrew, they pleaded with him to speak Aramaic so that the men on the wall wouldn't understand. 194 During the post-exilic period, the Aramaic edicts in the Book of Ezra and inscriptions on Persian coins demonstrate that across large areas of the new empire, Aramaic had established itself as the language of everyday communication. Its influence stretched from the Euxine Sea southward to Egypt, and even into Egypt itself. Samaria and the Hauran adopted it, while only the Greek cities and Phoenicia resisted.

The influence of Aramaic upon Jewish literature begins to be noticeable about the year 600. Jeremiah and Ezekiel, writing in a foreign land in an Aramaic environment, are the first witnesses to its supremacy. In the northern part of the country, owing to the immigration of foreign colonists after the destruction of the northern kingdom, it had already gained a hold upon the common people. In the Book of Daniel, written in the year 167 b.c., the Hebrew and Aramaic languages alternate. Perhaps, indeed, we ought to assume an Aramaic ground-document as the basis of this work.

The influence of Aramaic on Jewish literature starts to become evident around the year 600. Jeremiah and Ezekiel, writing in a foreign land within an Aramaic context, are the first to show its dominance. In the northern region, due to the arrival of foreign colonists after the fall of the northern kingdom, it had already taken root among the common people. In the Book of Daniel, written in 167 b.c., Hebrew and Aramaic are used interchangeably. We might even consider an Aramaic source document as the foundation for this work.

At what time Aramaic became the common popular speech in the post-exilic community we cannot exactly discover. Under Nehemiah “Judaean,” that is to say, Hebrew, was still spoken in Jerusalem; in the time of the Maccabees Aramaic seems to have [pg 273] wholly driven out the ancient national language. Evidence for this is to be found in the occurrence of Aramaic passages in the Talmud, from which it is evident that the Rabbis used this language in the religious instruction of the people. The provision that the text, after being read in Hebrew, should be interpreted to the people, may quite well reach back into the time of Jesus. The first evidence for the practice is in the Mishna, about a.d. 150.

At what point Aramaic became the common spoken language in the post-exilic community is unclear. During Nehemiah’s time, Hebrew was still spoken in Jerusalem; by the Maccabees' era, it seems Aramaic had completely replaced the ancient national language. Evidence for this can be found in the Aramaic passages in the Talmud, which show that the Rabbis used this language for teaching the people. The guideline that the text, after being read in Hebrew, should be explained to the people may well date back to the time of Jesus. The earliest evidence of this practice appears in the Mishna, around A.D. 150.

In the time of Jesus three languages met in Galilee—Hebrew, Aramaic, and Greek. In what relation they stood to each other we do not know, since Josephus, the only writer who could have told us, fails us in this point, as he so often does elsewhere. He informs us that when acting as an envoy of Titus he spoke to the people of Jerusalem in the ancestral language, and the word he uses is ἑβραΐζων. But the very thing we should like to know—whether, namely, this language was Aramaic or Hebrew, he does not tell us. We are left in the same uncertainty by the passage in Acts (xxii. 2) which says that Paul spoke to the people Ἑβραΐδι διαλέκτῳ, thereby gaining their attention, for there is no indication whether the language was Aramaic or Hebrew. For the writers of that period “Hebrew” simply means Jewish.

In the time of Jesus, three languages were spoken in Galilee—Hebrew, Aramaic, and Greek. We don’t know how they related to one another because Josephus, the only writer who could clarify this, doesn’t provide that information, as he often does elsewhere. He tells us that when he represented Titus, he spoke to the people of Jerusalem in their ancestral language, using the term ἑβραΐζων. However, he doesn’t clarify whether this language was Aramaic or Hebrew, which is exactly what we want to know. We face the same uncertainty with the passage in Acts (xxii. 2) that states Paul spoke to the people Ἑβραΐδι διαλέκτῳ, which got their attention, but it doesn’t specify if the language was Aramaic or Hebrew. For writers of that time, “Hebrew” simply referred to Jewish.

We cannot, therefore, be sure in what relation the ancient Hebrew sacred language and the Aramaic of ordinary intercourse stood to one another as regards religious writings and religious instruction. Did the ordinary man merely learn by heart a few verses, prayers, and psalms? Or was Hebrew, as the language of the cultus, also current in wider circles?

We can't be sure how the ancient Hebrew sacred language and the everyday Aramaic were related when it comes to religious texts and teachings. Did the average person just memorize a few verses, prayers, and psalms? Or was Hebrew, as the language of worship, also used more broadly?

Dalman gives a number of examples of works written in Hebrew in the century which witnessed the birth of Christ: “A Hebrew original,” he says, “must be assumed in the case of the main part of the Aethiopic book of Enoch, the Assumption of Moses, the Apocalypse of Baruch, Fourth Ezra, the Book of Jubilees, and for the Jewish ground-document of the Testament of the Twelve Patriarchs, of which M. Gaster has discovered a Hebrew manuscript.” The first Book of Maccabees, too, seems to him to go back to a Hebrew original. Nevertheless, he holds it to be impossible that synagogue discourses intended for the people can have been delivered in Hebrew, or that Jesus taught otherwise than in Aramaic.

Dalman provides several examples of works written in Hebrew during the century when Christ was born: “A Hebrew original,” he states, "It must be assumed in the case of the main part of the Aethiopic Book of Enoch, the Assumption of Moses, the Apocalypse of Baruch, Fourth Ezra, the Book of Jubilees, and for the Jewish foundational document of the Testament of the Twelve Patriarchs, for which M. Gaster has discovered a Hebrew manuscript." He also believes that the first Book of Maccabees likely has a Hebrew original. However, he thinks it is impossible for synagogue sermons meant for the public to have been delivered in Hebrew or for Jesus to have taught in any language other than Aramaic.

Franz Delitzsch's view, on the other hand, is that Jesus and the disciples taught in Hebrew; and that is the opinion of Resch also. Adolf Neubauer,195 Reader in Rabbinical Hebrew at Oxford, attempted a compromise. It was certainly the case, he thought, [pg 274] that in the time of Jesus Aramaic was spoken throughout Palestine; but whereas in Galilee this language had an exclusive dominance, and the knowledge of Hebrew was confined to texts learned by heart, in Jerusalem Hebrew had renewed itself by the adoption of Aramaic elements, and a kind of Neo-Hebraic language had arisen. This solution at least testifies to the difficulty of the question. The fact is that from the language of the New Testament it is often difficult to make out whether the underlying words are Hebrew or Aramaic. Thus, for instance, Dalman remarks—with reference to the question whether the statement of Papias refers to a Hebrew or an Aramaic “primitive Matthew”—that it is difficult “to produce proof of an Aramaic as distinct from a Hebrew source, because it is often the case in Biblical Hebrew, and still more often in the idiom of the Mishna, that the same expressions and forms of phrase are possible as in Aramaic.” Delitzsch's196 “retranslation” of the New Testament into Hebrew is therefore historically justified.

Franz Delitzsch believed that Jesus and the disciples taught in Hebrew; Resch shares this view. Adolf Neubauer, a Reader in Rabbinical Hebrew at Oxford, tried to find a middle ground. He thought that during Jesus' time, Aramaic was commonly spoken across Palestine. However, while Galilee had a strong dominance of this language with Hebrew being mainly known through memorized texts, in Jerusalem, Hebrew had revitalized itself through the incorporation of Aramaic elements, leading to a kind of Neo-Hebraic language. This perspective highlights the complexity of the issue. In fact, the language of the New Testament often makes it hard to determine whether the original words were Hebrew or Aramaic. For example, Dalman notes—regarding whether Papias's statement refers to a Hebrew or an Aramaic "primitive Matthew"—that it is tough "to provide proof of an Aramaic versus a Hebrew source because, in Biblical Hebrew, and even more in the Mishnaic idiom, the same expressions and phrases can often be found in Aramaic." Therefore, Delitzsch's "retranslation" of the New Testament into Hebrew is historically well-founded.

But the question about the language of Jesus must not be confused with the problem of the original language of the primitive form of Matthew's Gospel. In reference to the latter, Dalman thinks that the tradition of the Early Church regarding an earlier Aramaic form of the Gospel must be considered as lacking confirmation. “It is only in the case of Jesus' own words that an Aramaic original form is undeniable, and it is only for these that Early Church tradition asserted the existence of a Semitic documentary source. It is, therefore, the right and duty of Biblical scholarship to investigate the form which the sayings of Jesus must have taken in the original and the sense which in this form they must have conveyed to Jewish hearers.”

But the question about the language of Jesus shouldn't be mixed up with the issue of the original language of the earliest version of Matthew's Gospel. Regarding the latter, Dalman believes that the Early Church's tradition about an earlier Aramaic version of the Gospel must be seen as lacking evidence. "The only instance where an original Aramaic version of Jesus' words is undeniable is in his own sayings, and it’s only for these that Early Church tradition claimed there was a Semitic documentary source. Therefore, it is both the responsibility and obligation of Biblical scholars to explore the form that Jesus' sayings would have taken in their original context and the meaning they would have conveyed to Jewish audiences."

That Jesus spoke Aramaic, Meyer has shown by collecting all the Aramaic expressions which occur in His preaching.197 He considers the “Abba” in Gethsemane decisive, for this means that Jesus prayed in Aramaic in His hour of bitterest need. Again the cry from the cross was, according to Mark xv. 34, also Aramaic: Ἑλωΐ, ἑλωΐ, λαμὰ σαβαχθανεὶ. The Old Testament was therefore most familiar to Him in an Aramaic translation, otherwise this form of the Psalm passage would not have come to His lips at the moment of death.

That Jesus spoke Aramaic has been demonstrated by Meyer, who gathered all the Aramaic phrases found in His teachings. He believes the “ABBA” in Gethsemane is crucial, as it indicates that Jesus prayed in Aramaic during His most trying moment. Additionally, the cry from the cross, according to Mark xv. 34, was also in Aramaic: Ἑλωΐ, ἑλωΐ, λαμὰ σαβαχθανεὶ. Thus, the Old Testament was likely most familiar to Him in an Aramaic translation; otherwise, He wouldn’t have spoken that version of the Psalm at the moment of His death.

It is a quite independent question whether Jesus could speak, [pg 275] or at least understand, Greek. According to Josephus the knowledge of Greek in Palestine at that time, even among educated Jews, can only have been of a quite elementary character. He himself had to learn it laboriously in order to be able to write in it. His “Jewish War” was first written in Aramaic for his fellow-countrymen; the Greek edition was, by his own avowal, not intended for them. In another passage, it is true, he seems to imply a knowledge of, and interest in, foreign languages even among people in humble life.198

It’s an entirely separate question whether Jesus could speak, [pg 275] or at least understand, Greek. According to Josephus, the understanding of Greek in Palestine at that time, even among educated Jews, was likely quite basic. He had to learn it with great effort to be able to write in it. His "Jewish War" was initially written in Aramaic for his fellow countrymen; the Greek version, he admitted, was not meant for them. In another part, he does seem to suggest that even people in lower classes had some knowledge of and interest in foreign languages.198

An analogy, which is in many respects very close, to the linguistic conditions in Palestine was offered by Alsace under French rule in the 'sixties of the nineteenth century. Here, too, three languages met in the same district. The High-German of Luther's translation of the Bible was the language of the Church, the Alemannic dialect was the usual speech of the people, while French was the language of culture and of government administration. This remarkable analogy would be rather in favour—if analogy can be admitted to have any weight in the question—of Delitzsch and Resch, since the Biblical High-German, although never spoken in social intercourse, strongly influenced the Alemannic dialect—although this was, on the other hand, quite uninfluenced by Modern High-German—but did not allow it to penetrate into Church or school, there maintaining for itself an undivided sway. French made some progress, but only in certain circles, and remained entirely excluded from the religious sphere. The Alsatians of the poorer classes who could at that time have repeated the Lord's Prayer or the Beatitudes in French would not have been difficult to count. The Lutheran translation still holds its own to some extent against the French translation with the older generation of the Alsatian community in Paris, which has in other respects become completely French—so strong is the influence of a former ecclesiastical language even among those who have left their native home. There is one factor, however, which is not represented in the analogy; the influence of the Greek-speaking Jews of the Diaspora, who gathered to the Feasts at Jerusalem, upon the extension of the Greek language in the mother-country.

An analogy that closely mirrors the linguistic situation in Palestine was found in Alsace during French rule in the 1860s. Here, too, three languages coexisted in the same area. The High German of Luther's Bible translation was used in the Church, the Alemannic dialect was the everyday language of the people, and French served as the language of culture and government. This interesting analogy could support Delitzsch and Resch, since Biblical High German, though never used in daily conversation, had a strong influence on the Alemannic dialect—despite that dialect being unaffected by Modern High German. However, Biblical High German didn't infiltrate the Church or schools, where it maintained complete control. French made some inroads but was limited to certain groups and was completely excluded from the religious realm. At that time, it would have been easy to count the poorer Alsatians who could recite the Lord's Prayer or the Beatitudes in French. The Lutheran translation still holds some significance for the older generation of the Alsatian community in Paris, who have otherwise fully embraced French—illustrating how a former ecclesiastical language can influence those who have left their homeland. One aspect, though, isn't captured by this analogy: the impact of the Greek-speaking Jews of the Diaspora, who gathered for the Feasts in Jerusalem, on the growth of the Greek language in their homeland.

Jesus, then, spoke Galilaean Aramaic, which is known to us as a separate dialect from writings of the fourth to the seventh century. For the Judaean dialect we have more and earlier evidence. We have literary monuments in it from the first to the third century. “It is very probable,” Dalman thinks, “that the popular dialect of Northern Palestine, after the final fall of the Judaean centre of the Aramaic-Jewish culture, which followed on the Bar-Cochba rising, spread over almost the whole of Palestine.”

Jesus spoke Galilean Aramaic, which we recognize as a distinct dialect from writings dating from the fourth to the seventh century. We have more and earlier evidence for the Judean dialect. There are literary records from the first to the third century. "There's a good chance," Dalman believes, “the common dialect of Northern Palestine, after the total breakdown of the Judean center of Aramaic-Jewish culture that came after the Bar-Cochba uprising, spread throughout almost all of Palestine.”

The retranslations into Aramaic are therefore justified. After [pg 276] J. A. Bolten's attempt had remained for nearly a hundred years the only one of its kind, the experiment has been renewed in our own time by J. T. Marshall, E. Nestle, J. Wellhausen, Arnold Meyer, and Gustaf Dalman; in the case of Marshall and Nestle with the subsidiary purpose of endeavouring to prove the existence of an Aramaic documentary source. These retranslations first attracted their due meed of attention from theologians in connexion with the Son-of-Man question. Rarely, if ever, have theologians experienced such a surprise as was sprung upon them by Hans Lietzmann's essay in 1896.199 Jesus had never, so ran the thesis of the Bonn candidate in theology, applied to Himself the title Son of Man, because in the Aramaic the title did not exist, and on linguistic grounds could not have existed. In the language which He used, בן אנש was merely a periphrasis for “a man.” That Jesus meant Himself when He spoke of the Son of Man, none of His hearers could have suspected.

The retranslations into Aramaic are therefore justified. After [pg 276] J. A. Bolten's attempt had been the only one of its kind for nearly a hundred years, this experiment has been renewed in our time by J. T. Marshall, E. Nestle, J. Wellhausen, Arnold Meyer, and Gustaf Dalman; in the cases of Marshall and Nestle, there was also the additional aim of trying to prove the existence of an Aramaic documentary source. These retranslations first gained the attention they deserved from theologians in relation to the Son-of-Man question. Rarely, if ever, have theologians been as surprised as they were by Hans Lietzmann's essay in 1896. According to the thesis presented by the Bonn theology candidate, Jesus never referred to Himself as the Son of Man because, in Aramaic, the title didn’t exist and linguistically could not have existed. In the language He used, בן אנש was merely a way of saying “a man.” None of His listeners could have suspected that Jesus was referring to Himself when He mentioned the Son of Man.

Lietzmann had not been without predecessors.200 Gilbert Génébrard, who died Archbishop of Aix as long ago as 1597, had emphasised the point that the term Son of Man should not be interpreted with reference solely to Christ, but to the race of mankind. Hugo Grotius maintained the same position even more emphatically. With a quite modern one-sidedness, Paulus the rationalist maintained in his commentaries and in his Life of Jesus that according to Ezek. ii. 1 “Barnash” meant man in general. Jesus, he thought, whenever He used the expression the Son of Man, pointed to Himself and thus gave it the sense of “this man.” In taking this line he gives up the general reference to mankind as a whole for which Mark ii. 28 is generally cited as the classical passage. The suggestion that the term Son of Man in its apocalyptic signification was first attributed to Jesus at a later time and that the passages where it occurs in this sense are therefore suspicious, was first put forward by Fr. Aug. Fritzsche. He hoped in this way to get rid of Matt. x. 23. De Lagarde, like Paulus, emphatically asserted that Son of Man only meant man. But instead of the clumsy explanation of the rationalist he gave another and a more pleasing one, namely, that Jesus by choosing this title designed to ennoble mankind. Wellhausen, in his “History of Israel and of the Jews” (1894), remarked on it as strange that Jesus should have called Himself “the Man.” B. D. Eerdmans, taking the apocalyptic significance of the term as his starting-point, attempted to carry out consistently the theory of the later interpolation of this title into the sayings of Jesus.201

Lietzmann had predecessors. Gilbert Génébrard, who died as Archbishop of Aix in 1597, stressed that the term "Son of Man" shouldn't be interpreted solely in reference to Christ, but to humanity as a whole. Hugo Grotius held the same view even more strongly. In a rather one-sided modern approach, Paulus the rationalist claimed in his commentaries and in his Life of Jesus that, according to Ezek. ii. 1, "Barnash" meant man in general. He believed that whenever Jesus used the term "Son of Man," He was referring to Himself, giving it the meaning of "this man." By taking this stance, he abandoned the general reference to all humanity that Mark ii. 28 is often cited for. The idea that the term "Son of Man" in its apocalyptic meaning was first attributed to Jesus later, and that the passages where it appears in this sense should be viewed with skepticism, was first proposed by Fr. Aug. Fritzsche. He hoped to eliminate Matt. x. 23 this way. De Lagarde, like Paulus, insisted that "Son of Man" simply meant man. However, rather than the awkward explanation of the rationalist, he offered a more appealing one: that by choosing this title, Jesus intended to elevate humanity. Wellhausen, in his "History of Israel and of the Jews" (1894), found it odd that Jesus referred to Himself as "the Man." B. D. Eerdmans, starting from the apocalyptic significance of the term, tried to consistently apply the theory that this title was added to Jesus' sayings later.

[pg 277]

Thus Lietzmann had predecessors; but they were not so in any real sense. They had either started out from the Marcan passage where the Son of Man is described as the Lord of the Sabbath, and endeavoured arbitrarily to interpret all the Son-of-Man passages in the same sense; or they assumed without sufficient grounds that the title Son of Man was a later interpolation. The new idea consisted in combining the two attempts, and declaring the passages about the Son of Man to be linguistically and historically impossible, seeing that, on linguistic grounds, “son of man” means “man.”

Thus Lietzmann had predecessors, but they weren't truly so. They either started from the Marcan passage where the Son of Man is referred to as the Lord of the Sabbath and tried to interpret all the Son-of-Man passages in the same way arbitrarily, or they assumed without adequate justification that the title Son of Man was a later addition. The new idea was to merge these two approaches and claim that the passages about the Son of Man are linguistically and historically impossible, reasoning that, linguistically, “Son of Man” means “dude.”

Arnold Meyer and Wellhausen expressed themselves in the same sense as Lietzmann. The passages where Jesus uses the expression in an unmistakably Messianic sense are, according to them, to be put down to the account of Early Christian theology. The only passages which in their opinion are historically tenable are the two or three in which the expression denotes man in general, or is equivalent to the simple “I.” These latter were felt to be a difficulty by the Church when it came to think in Greek, since this way of speaking of oneself was strange to them; consequently the expression appeared to them deliberately enigmatic and only capable of being interpreted in the sense which it bears in Daniel. The Son-of-Man conception, argued Lietzmann, when he again approached the question two years later, had arisen in a Hellenistic environment,202 on the basis of Dan. vii. 13; N. Schmidt,203 too, saw in the apocalyptic Bar-Nasha passages which follow the revelation of the Messiahship at Caesarea Philippi an interpolation from the later apocalyptic theology. On the other hand, P. Schmiedel still wished to make it a Messianic designation, and to take it as being historical in this sense even in passages in which the term man “gave a possible sense.”204 H. Gunkel thought that it was possible to translate Bar-Nasha simply by “man,” and nevertheless hold to the historicity of the expression as a self-designation of Jesus. Jesus, he suggests, had borrowed this enigmatic term, which goes back to Dan. vii. 13, from the mystical apocalyptic literature, meaning thereby to indicate that He was the Man of God in contrast to the Man of Sin.205

Arnold Meyer and Wellhausen had views similar to Lietzmann. They believed that the instances where Jesus uses the term in a clearly Messianic way should be attributed to Early Christian theology. They considered the only historically valid passages to be the two or three where the term refers to humans in general, or is simply equivalent to "I." The Church found these later passages challenging as they tended to think in Greek, which made this way of referring to oneself unusual for them. Consequently, the term seemed deliberately obscure and could only be interpreted as it is in Daniel. Lietzmann argued, when he revisited the topic two years later, that the Son-of-Man concept emerged in a Hellenistic context based on Daniel 7:13. N. Schmidt also viewed the apocalyptic Bar-Nasha references that follow the announcement of the Messiahship at Caesarea Philippi as additions from later apocalyptic theology. Conversely, P. Schmiedel still wanted to consider it a Messianic title, deeming it historical even in passages where the term "man" allowed for alternative interpretations. H. Gunkel believed it was possible to translate Bar-Nasha simply as "man," while still maintaining that the expression was a historical self-reference of Jesus. He suggested that Jesus had adopted this enigmatic term, rooted in Daniel 7:13, from mystical apocalyptic literature to signify that He was the Man of God, in contrast to the Man of Sin.

Holtzmann felt a kind of relief in handing over to the philologists the obstinate problem which since the time of Baldensperger and [pg 278] Weiss had caused so much trouble to theologians, and wanted to postpone the historical discussion until the Aramaic experts had settled the linguistic question. That happened sooner than was expected. In 1898 Dalman declared in his epoch-making work (Die Worte Jesu) that he could not admit the linguistic objections to the use of the expression Son of Man by Jesus. “Biblical Aramaic,” he says, “does not differ in this respect from Hebrew. The simple אנש and not בן אנש is the term for man.”... It was only later that the Jewish-Galilaean dialect, like the Palestinian-Christian dialect, used בן אנש for man, though in both idioms the simple אנש occurs in the sense of “some one.” “In view of the whole facts of the case,” he continues, “what has to be said is that Jewish-Palestinian Aramaic of the earlier period used אנש for ‘man,’ and occasionally to designate a plurality of men makes use of the expression בני אנשא. The singular בן אנש was not current, and was only used in imitation of the Hebrew text of the Bible, where בן אדם belongs to the poetic diction, and is, moreover, not of very frequent occurrence.” “It is,” he says elsewhere, “by no means a sign of a sound historical method, instead of working patiently at the solution of the problem, to hasten like Oort and Lietzmann to the conclusion that the absence of the expression in the New Testament Epistles is a proof that Jesus did not use it either, but that there was somewhere or other a Hellenistic community in the Early Church which had a predilection for this name, and often made Jesus speak of Himself in the Gospel narrative in the third person, in order to find an opportunity of bringing it in.”

Holtzmann felt relieved to leave the stubborn issue that had troubled theologians since Baldensperger and Weiss to the philologists, wanting to delay the historical discussion until the Aramaic experts resolved the linguistic question. That happened sooner than expected. In 1898, Dalman announced in his groundbreaking work (*Die Worte Jesu*) that he could not accept the linguistic arguments against Jesus using the term Son of Man. “Biblical Aramaic,” he says, “does not differ in this respect from Hebrew. The simple אנש and not בן אנש is the term for man.”... It was only later that the Jewish-Galilean dialect, like the Palestinian-Christian dialect, began using בן אנש for man, although both idioms used the simple אנש in the sense of “someone.” “Considering all the facts of the case,” he continues, “what should be said is that Jewish-Palestinian Aramaic of the earlier period used אנש for ‘man,’ and occasionally to indicate a plurality of men, the expression בני אנשא is used. The singular בן אנש was not common and was only used in imitation of the Hebrew text of the Bible, where בן אדם belongs to poetic language and is also not very frequently encountered.” “It is,” he says elsewhere, “by no means a sign of a sound historical method, instead of patiently working on the solution of the problem, to rush like Oort and Lietzmann to the conclusion that the absence of the expression in the New Testament Epistles proves that Jesus didn’t use it either, but that there was a Hellenistic community in the Early Church that had a liking for this title and often had Jesus refer to Himself in the third person in the Gospel narrative to find a way to include it.”

So the oxen turned back with the ark into the land of the Philistines. It was a case of returning to the starting-point and deciding on historical grounds in what sense Jesus had used the expression.206 But the possibilities were reduced by the way in which Lietzmann had posed the problem, since the interpretations according to which Jesus had used it in a veiled ethical Messianic sense, to indicate the ethical and spiritual transformation of all the eschatological conceptions, were now manifestly incapable of offering any convincing argument against the radical denial of the use of the expression. Baldensperger rightly remarked in a review of the whole discussion that the question which was ultimately at stake in [pg 279] the combat over the title Son of Man was the question whether Jesus was the Messiah or no, and that Dalman, by his proof of its linguistic possibility, had saved the Messiahship of Jesus.207

So the oxen turned back with the ark into the land of the Philistines. It was like going back to square one and figuring out, historically, what Jesus meant by the phrase. But the options were limited by how Lietzmann framed the issue, as the interpretations suggesting that Jesus used it in a subtle ethical Messianic way to signify the moral and spiritual transformation of all eschatological ideas clearly failed to provide any convincing argument against the outright rejection of the phrase. Baldensperger rightly pointed out in a review of the entire discussion that the fundamental question in the debate over the title "Son of Man" was whether Jesus was the Messiah or not, and that Dalman, by demonstrating its linguistic possibility, had defended Jesus’ Messiahship.

But what kind of Messiahship? Is it any other kind than the future Messiahship of the apocalyptic Son of Man which Johannes Weiss had asserted? Did Jesus mean anything different by the Son of Man from that which was meant by the apocalyptic writers? To put it otherwise: behind the Son-of-Man problem there lies the general question whether Jesus can have described Himself as a present Messiah; for the fundamental difficulty is that He, a man upon earth, should give Himself out to be the Son of Man, and at the same time apparently give to that title a quite different sense from that which it previously possessed.

But what kind of Messiah are we talking about? Is it any different from the future Messiah that the apocalyptic Son of Man asserted by Johannes Weiss? Did Jesus interpret the term Son of Man in a way that differs from how the apocalyptic writers understood it? To rephrase it: underlying the issue of the Son of Man is the broader question of whether Jesus could have claimed to be a present Messiah. The main challenge is that He, as a human on earth, would refer to Himself as the Son of Man, while seemingly giving that title a completely different meaning than it had before.

The champion of the linguistic possibility of this self-designation made the last serious attempt to render the transformation of the conception historically conceivable. He argues that Jesus cannot have used it as a mere meaningless expression, a periphrasis for the simple I.208 On the other hand, the term cannot have been understood by the disciples as an exalted title, or at least only in the sense that the title indicative of exaltation is paradoxically connected with the title indicative of humility. “We shall be justified in saying, that, for the Synoptic Evangelists, ‘Man's Son’ was no title of honour for the Messiah, but—as it must necessarily appear to a Hellenist—a veiling of His Messiahship under a name which emphasises the humanity of its bearer.” For them it was not the references to the sufferings of “Man's Son” that were paradoxical, but the references to His exaltation: that “Man's Son” should be put to death is not wonderful; what is wonderful is His “coming again upon the clouds of heaven.”

The advocate for the linguistic possibility of this self-designation made the last serious effort to make the transformation of the concept historically understandable. He argues that Jesus couldn't have used it as just a meaningless expression, a roundabout way of saying "I." On the other hand, the term couldn't have been seen by the disciples as an elevated title, or at least only in the way that a title indicating exaltation is paradoxically connected to a title indicating humility. "We can confidently say that for the Synoptic Evangelists, ‘Man's Son’ was not a title of respect for the Messiah, but— as it would likely seem to a Hellenist— a way to hide His Messiahship behind a name that highlights the humanity of the person it refers to." For them, it wasn't the references to the sufferings of "Son of Man" that were paradoxical, but the references to His exaltation: that “Son of Man” should be put to death is not surprising; what is surprising is His "coming again on the clouds of heaven."

If Jesus called Himself the Son of Man, the only conclusion which could be drawn by those that heard Him was, “that for some reason or other He desired to describe Himself as a Man par excellence.” There is no reason to think of the Heavenly Son of Man of the Similitudes of Enoch and Fourth Ezra; that conception could hardly be present to the minds of His auditors.

If Jesus referred to Himself as the Son of Man, the only conclusion that could be drawn by those who heard Him was, “that for some reason He wanted to show Himself as the ultimate Man par excellence.” There’s no reason to consider the Heavenly Son of Man from the Similitudes of Enoch and Fourth Ezra; that idea probably wasn’t on the minds of His listeners.

[pg 280]

“How was one who was now walking upon earth, to come from heaven? He would have needed first to be translated thither. One who had died or been rapt away from earth might be brought back to earth again in this way, or a being who had never before been upon earth, might be conceived as descending thither.”

"How can someone who is currently walking on earth originate from heaven? They would have to be taken there first. A person who died or was taken away from earth could come back this way, or a being who has never been on earth before could be envisioned as coming down here."

But if, on the one hand, the title Son of Man was not to be understood apart from the reference to the passage in Daniel, while on the other Jesus so designated Himself as a man actually present upon earth, “what was really implied was that He was the man in whom Daniel's vision of ‘one like unto a Son of Man’ was being fulfilled.” He could not certainly expect from His hearers a complete understanding of the self-designation. “We are doubtless justified in saying that in using it, He intentionally offered them an enigma which challenged further reflection upon His Person.”

But if, on one hand, the title Son of Man shouldn’t be understood without referencing the passage in Daniel, while on the other, Jesus identified Himself as a man actually present on Earth, "what was really implied was that He was the man in whom Daniel's vision of ‘one like unto a Son of Man’ was being fulfilled." He couldn’t really expect His listeners to fully understand this self-designation. “We can confidently say that by using it, He purposefully gave them a puzzle that prompted them to think more deeply about who He is.”

According to Peter's confession the name was intelligible to the disciples as coming from Dan. vii. 13, and obviously indicating Him who was destined to the sovereignty of the world. Jesus calls Himself the Son of Man, “not as meaning the lowly one, but as a scion of the human race with its human weakness, whom nevertheless God will make Lord of the world; and it is very probable that Jesus found the Son of Man of Dan. vii. in Ps. viii. 5 ff. also.” Sayings regarding humiliation and suffering could be attached to the title just as well as references to exaltation. For since the “Child of Man” has placed Himself upon the throne of God, He is in reality no longer a mere man, but ruler over heaven and earth, “the Lord.”

According to Peter's confession, the name was recognized by the disciples as coming from Dan. vii. 13, clearly pointing to the one who was destined to rule the world. Jesus refers to Himself as the Son of Man, "not suggesting someone inferior, but as a representative of humanity with its flaws, whom God will still appoint as the Lord of the world; and it's quite possible that Jesus saw the Son of Man in Dan. vii. reflected in Ps. viii. 5 ff. as well." Teachings about humiliation and suffering can be associated with this title just as much as those about exaltation. Since the "Child of Humanity" has taken His place on the throne of God, He is truly no longer just a man, but the ruler over heaven and earth, "God."

This attempt of Dalman's has the same significance in regard to the question of the Messiahship as Bousset's had for the ethical question. Just as in Bousset's view the Kingdom of God was, in a paradoxical way, after all proclaimed as present, so here the self-designation “Son of Man” is retained by a paradox as conveying the sense of a present Messiahship. But the documents do not give any support to this assumption; on the contrary they contradict it at every point. According to Dalman it was not the predictions of the passion of the Son of Man which sounded paradoxical to the disciples, but the predictions of His exaltation. But we are distinctly told that when He spoke of His passion they did not understand the saying. The predictions of His exaltation, however, they understood so well that without troubling themselves further about the predictions of the sufferings, they began to dispute who should be greatest in the Kingdom of Heaven, and who should have his throne closest to the Son of Man. And if it is once admitted that Jesus took the designation from Daniel, what ground is there for asserting that the [pg 281] purely eschatological transcendental significance which the term had taken on in the Similitudes of Enoch and retains in Fourth Ezra had no existence for Jesus? Thus, by a long round-about, criticism has come back to Johannes Weiss.209 His eschatological solution of the Son-of-Man question—the elements of which are to be found in Strauss's first Life of Jesus—is the only possible one. Dalman expresses the same idea in the form of a question. “How could one who was actually walking the earth come down from heaven? He would have needed first to be translated thither. One who had died or been rapt away from earth might possibly be brought back to earth in this way.” Having reached this point we have only to observe further that Jesus, from the “confession of Peter” onwards, always speaks of the Son of Man in connexion with death and resurrection. That is to say, that once the disciples know in what relation He stands to the Son of Man, He uses this title to suggest the manner of His return: as the sequel to His death and resurrection He will return to the world again as a superhuman Personality. Thus the purely transcendental use of the term suggested by Dalman as a possibility turns out to be the historical reality.

Dalman's attempt is just as significant for the question of the Messiah as Bousset's was for the ethical question. Just like Bousset claimed that the Kingdom of God was paradoxically proclaimed as present, here the self-designation "Son of Man" is used in a way that suggests a present Messiah. However, the documents do not support this assumption; in fact, they contradict it at every point. According to Dalman, it wasn’t the predictions about the suffering of the Son of Man that seemed paradoxical to the disciples, but the predictions about His exaltation. Yet, we are clearly told that when He spoke of His suffering, they did not understand what He meant. They understood the predictions of His exaltation so well that instead of worrying about the suffering, they started arguing about who would be the greatest in the Kingdom of Heaven and who would sit closest to the Son of Man. And if we accept that Jesus took this title from Daniel, what reason do we have to claim that the [pg 281] term’s purely eschatological significance, as seen in the Similitudes of Enoch and maintained in Fourth Ezra, didn’t exist for Jesus? Thus, through a long process, criticism has returned to Johannes Weiss. His eschatological solution to the Son-of-Man question—the ideas of which can be found in Strauss's first Life of Jesus—is the only possible one. Dalman poses the same idea as a question. "How could someone who was actually walking on Earth come down from heaven? They would have needed to be taken up there first. A person who died or was taken from Earth might possibly return this way." At this point, we just need to note that from the "Peter's confession" onward, Jesus always talks about the Son of Man in connection with death and resurrection. This means that once the disciples understand His relationship to the Son of Man, He uses this title to hint at how He will return: after His death and resurrection, He will come back to the world as a superhuman figure. Therefore, the purely transcendental use of the term proposed by Dalman as a possibility turns out to be a historical reality.

Broadly speaking, therefore, the Son-of-Man problem is both historically solvable and has been solved. The authentic passages are those in which the expression is used in that apocalyptic sense which goes back to Daniel. But we have to distinguish two different uses of the term according to the degree of knowledge assumed in the hearers. If the secret of Jesus is unknown to them, then in that case they understand simply that Jesus is speaking of the “Son of Man” and His coming without having any suspicion that He and the Son of Man have any connexion. It would be thus, for instance, when in sending out the disciples in Matt. x. 23, He announced the imminence of the appearing of the Son of Man; or when He pictured the judgment which the Son of Man would hold (Matt. xxv. 31-46), if we may imagine [pg 282] it to have been spoken to the people at Jerusalem. Or, on the other hand, the secret is known to the hearers. In that case they understand that the term Son of Man points to the position to which He Himself is to be exalted when the present era passes into the age to come. It was thus, no doubt, in the case of the disciples at Caesarea Philippi, and of the High Priest to whom Jesus, after answering his demand with the simple “Yea” (Mark xiv. 62), goes on immediately to speak of the exaltation of the Son of Man to the right hand of God, and of His coming upon the clouds of heaven.

Generally speaking, the Son-of-Man issue can be historically understood and has been resolved. The authentic passages are those that use the term in the apocalyptic sense rooted in Daniel. However, we need to differentiate between two different uses of the term depending on what the audience knows. If Jesus's secret is unknown to them, they simply comprehend that He is talking about the “Son of Man” and His coming without any idea that He and the Son of Man are connected. This is what happens, for example, when He sends out the disciples in Matt. x. 23, announcing the imminent appearance of the Son of Man, or when He describes the judgment that the Son of Man will hold (Matt. xxv. 31-46), if we imagine it being said to the people in Jerusalem. On the other hand, if the audience knows the secret, they understand that the term Son of Man refers to the status He will attain when the current age transitions into the next one. This was likely the case for the disciples at Caesarea Philippi and for the High Priest, to whom Jesus, after simply answering “Yea” (Mark xiv. 62), immediately speaks about the exaltation of the Son of Man to the right hand of God and His coming on the clouds of heaven.

Jesus did not, therefore, veil His Messiahship by using the expression Son of Man, much less did He transform it, but He used the expression to refer, in the only possible way, to His Messianic office as destined to be realised at His “coming,” and did so in such a manner that only the initiated understood that He was speaking of His own coming, while others understood Him as referring to the coming of a Son of Man who was other than Himself.

Jesus didn’t hide His role as the Messiah by calling Himself the Son of Man; instead, He used the term to refer to His Messianic mission that was meant to be fulfilled at His "arriving," and He did it in a way that only those in the know realized He was talking about His own arrival, while others thought He was referring to a different Son of Man.

The passages where the title has not this apocalyptic reference, or where, previous to the incident at Caesarea Philippi, Jesus in speaking to the disciples equates the Son of Man with His own “ego,” are to be explained as of literary origin. This set of secondary occurrences of the title has nothing to do with “Early Church theology”; it is merely a question of phenomena of translation and tradition. In the saying about the Sabbath in Mark ii. 28, and perhaps also in the saying about the right to forgive sins in Mark ii. 10, Son of Man doubtless stood in the original in the general sense of “man,” but was later, certainly by our Evangelists, understood as referring to Jesus as the Son of Man. In other passages tradition, following the analogy of those passages in which the title is authentic, put in place of the simple I—expressed in the Aramaic by “the man”—the self-designation “Son of Man,” as we can clearly show by comparing Matt. xvi. 13, “Who do men say that the Son of Man is?” with Mark viii. 27, “Who do men say that I am?”

The sections where the title doesn’t have an apocalyptic meaning, or where, before the incident at Caesarea Philippi, Jesus tells the disciples that the Son of Man refers to His own “self,” should be understood as having a literary origin. This group of secondary uses of the title is unrelated to "Early church theology"; it is simply a matter of translation and tradition. In the statement about the Sabbath in Mark ii. 28, and possibly also in the statement about the right to forgive sins in Mark ii. 10, the term Son of Man likely meant “man” in the original context but was later interpreted by our Evangelists to refer specifically to Jesus as the Son of Man. In other passages, tradition, following the pattern of those where the title is authentic, replaced the simple I—expressed in Aramaic as “the guy”—with the self-designation "Son of Man," which we can clearly demonstrate by comparing Matt. xvi. 13, "Who do people say the Son of Man is?" with Mark viii. 27, "Who do people say I am?"

Three passages call for special discussion. In the statement that a man may be forgiven for blasphemy against the Son of Man, but not for blasphemy against the Holy Spirit, in Matt. xii. 32, the “Son of Man” may be authentic. But of course it would not, even in that case, give any hint that “Son of Man designates the Messiah in His humiliation” as Dalman wished to infer from the passage, but would mean that Jesus was speaking of the Son of Man, here as elsewhere, in the third person without reference to Himself, and was thinking of a contemptuous denial of the Parousia such as might have been uttered by a Sadducee. But if we take into account the parallel in Mark iii. 28 and 29, where blasphemy against the Holy Ghost is spoken of without any mention of [pg 283] blasphemy against the Son of Man, it seems more natural to take the mention of the Son of Man as a secondary interpolation, derived from the same line of tradition, perhaps from the same hand, as the “Son of Man” in the question to the disciples at Caesarea Philippi.

Three passages call for special discussion. In the statement that a man can be forgiven for blasphemy against the Son of Man, but not for blasphemy against the Holy Spirit, in Matt. xii. 32, the "Son of Man" may be authentic. However, even in that case, it wouldn't indicate that “Son of Man refers to the Messiah in His humility.” as Dalman suggested, but would imply that Jesus was referring to the Son of Man, here as elsewhere, in the third person without referring to Himself, and was considering a dismissive denial of the Parousia that could have been expressed by a Sadducee. But when we consider the parallel in Mark iii. 28 and 29, where blasphemy against the Holy Spirit is discussed without mentioning [pg 283] blasphemy against the Son of Man, it seems more logical to view the mention of the Son of Man as a later addition, stemming from the same line of tradition, perhaps from the same source, as the "Son of Man" in the question to the disciples at Caesarea Philippi.

The two other sayings, the one about the Son of Man “who hath not where to lay His head,” Matt. viii. 20, and that about the Son of Man who must submit to the reproach of being a glutton and a wine-bibber, Matt. xi. 19, belong together. If we assume it to be possible, in conformity with the saying about the purpose of the parables in Mark iv. 11 and 12, that Jesus sometimes spoke words which He did not intend to be understood, we may—if we are unwilling to accept the supposition of a later periphrasis for the ego, which would certainly be the most natural explanation—recognise in these sayings two obscure declarations regarding the Son of Man. They would then be supposed to have meant in the original form, which is no longer clearly recognisable, that the Son of Man would in some way justify the conduct of Jesus of Nazareth. But the way in which this idea is expressed was not such as to make it easy for His hearers to identify Him with the Son of Man. Moreover, it was for them a conception impossible to realise, since Jesus was a natural, and the Son of Man a supernatural, being; and the eschatological scheme of things had not provided for a man who at the end of the existing era should hint to others that at the great transformation of all things He would be manifested as the Son of Man. This case presented itself only in the course of history, and it created a preparatory stage of eschatology which does not answer to any traditional scheme.

The two other sayings, one about the Son of Man who “has nowhere to lay His head” (Matt. viii. 20), and the other about the Son of Man who has to endure being labeled a glutton and a wine drinker (Matt. xi. 19), go together. If we consider the possibility, in line with the saying about the purpose of parables in Mark iv. 11 and 12, that Jesus sometimes spoke in ways that were not meant to be understood, we may—if we don’t want to accept the idea that later writers paraphrased the 'I' phrase, which would be the most straightforward explanation—see these sayings as two unclear statements about the Son of Man. They would then be thought to have originally meant, in a form that is no longer clearly recognizable, that the Son of Man would somehow justify the actions of Jesus of Nazareth. However, the way this idea is expressed was not easy for His listeners to connect with the Son of Man. Moreover, for them, it was an impossible concept to grasp since Jesus was a natural being, while the Son of Man was a supernatural figure; and the eschatological framework hadn’t anticipated a man at the end of the current era implying that during the great transformation of all things, He would be revealed as the Son of Man. This scenario only became apparent over time, and it established a preparatory stage of eschatology that doesn't fit any traditional framework.

That act of the self-consciousness of Jesus by which He recognised Himself in His earthly existence as the future Messiah is the act in which eschatology supremely affirms itself. At the same time, since it brings, spiritually, that which is to come, into the unaltered present, into the existing era, it is the end of eschatology. For it is its “spiritualisation,” a spiritualisation of which the ultimate consequence was to be that all its “supersensuous” elements were to be realised only spiritually in the present earthly conditions, and all that is affirmed as supersensuous in the transcendental sense was to be regarded as only the ruined remains of an eschatological world-view. The Messianic secret of Jesus is the basis of Christianity, since it involves the de-nationalising and the spiritualisation of Jewish eschatology.

That moment when Jesus became aware of Himself in His earthly life as the future Messiah is the point where eschatology truly asserts itself. At the same time, because it brings the future into the unchanged present and into the current era, it marks the end of eschatology. This represents its "spiritualization," a transformation where ultimately, all its “super sensory” aspects were to be understood only in spiritual terms within present earthly conditions, and everything affirmed as supersensuous in the transcendental sense was to be seen merely as the shattered remnants of an eschatological worldview. The Messianic secret of Jesus forms the foundation of Christianity, as it entails the de-nationalising and spiritualisation of Jewish eschatology.

Yet more. It is the primal fact, the starting-point, of a process which manifests itself, indeed, in Christianity, but cannot fully work itself out even here, of a movement in the direction of inwardness which brings all religious magnitudes into the one indivisible spiritual present, and which Christian dogmatic has not [pg 284] ventured to carry to its completion. The Messianic consciousness of the uniquely great Man of Nazareth sets up a struggle between the present and the beyond, and introduces that resolute absorption of the beyond by the present, which in looking back we recognise as the history of Christianity, and of which we are conscious in ourselves as the essence of religious progress and experience—a process of which the end is not yet in sight.

Yet more. It is the fundamental fact, the starting point, of a process that shows itself in Christianity but can't fully develop even here. It’s a movement towards inwardness that brings all religious aspects into one united spiritual present, which Christian doctrine has not ventured to complete. The Messianic awareness of the uniquely great man from Nazareth creates a tension between the present and the beyond and introduces the determined integration of the beyond into the present. In hindsight, we recognize this as the history of Christianity, which we experience as the essence of religious progress and experience—a journey whose conclusion is still not in sight.

In this sense Jesus did “accept the world” and did stand in conflict with Judaism. Protestantism was a step—a step on which hung weighty consequences—in the progress of that “acceptance of the world” which was constantly developing itself from within. By a mighty revolution which was in harmony with the spirit of that great primal act of the consciousness of Jesus, though in opposition to some of the most certain of His sayings, ethics became world-accepting. But it will be a mightier revolution still when the last remaining ruins of the supersensuous other-worldly system of thought are swept away in order to clear the site for a new spiritual, purely real and present world. All the inconsistent compromises and constructions of modern theology are merely an attempt to stave off the final expulsion of eschatology from religion, an inevitable but a hopeless attempt. That proleptic Messianic consciousness of Jesus, which was in reality the only possible actualisation of the Messianic idea, carries these consequences with it inexorably and unfailingly. At that last cry upon the cross the whole eschatological supersensuous world fell in upon itself in ruins, and there remained as a spiritual reality only that present spiritual world, bound as it is to sense, which Jesus by His all-powerful word had called into being within the world which He contemned. That last cry, with its despairing abandonment of the eschatological future, is His real acceptance of the world. The “Son of Man” was buried in the ruins of the falling eschatological world; there remained alive only Jesus “the Man.” Thus these two Aramaic synonyms include in themselves, as in a symbol of reality, all that was to come.

In this way, Jesus did "embrace the world" and stood in conflict with Judaism. Protestantism was a significant step—one that had serious consequences—in the ongoing process of that “accepting the world” which was continuously evolving. Through a major shift that aligned with the essence of Jesus's awareness, ethics became open to the world, despite opposing some of His most certain teachings. However, an even greater transformation will occur when the last remnants of the other-worldly way of thinking are removed to make space for a new spiritual and purely real present world. All the inconsistent compromises and theories of modern theology are simply attempts to delay the ultimate removal of eschatology from religion, an effort that is both unavoidable and futile. That forward-looking Messianic awareness of Jesus, which was truly the only way to realize the Messianic idea, brings with it these outcomes unavoidably and consistently. At that final cry from the cross, the entire eschatological other-worldly realm collapsed in ruins, leaving behind only the spiritual reality of the present world, tethered to sensory experience, which Jesus had called into existence with His powerful words within the world He criticized. That last cry, expressing a despairing surrender of the eschatological future, represents His true acceptance of the world. The “Son of Man” was buried in the ruins of the crumbling eschatological world; only Jesus "the Man." Thus, these two Aramaic synonyms encapsulate, as symbols of reality, all that was yet to come.

If theology has found it so hard a task to arrive at an historical comprehension of the secret of this self-designation, this is due to the fact that the question is not a purely historical one. In this word there lies the transformation of a whole system of thought, the inexorable consequence of the elimination of eschatology from religion. It was only in this future form, not as actual, that Jesus spoke of His Messiahship. Modern theology keeps on endeavouring to discover in the title of Son of Man, which is bound up with the future, a humanised present Messiahship. It does so in the conviction that the recognition of a purely future reference in the Messianic consciousness of Jesus would lead in the last result to a modification of the historic basis of our faith, which has itself become [pg 285] historical, and therefore true and self-justifying. The recognition of the claims of eschatology signifies for our dogmatic a burning of the boats by which it felt itself able to return at any moment from the time of Jesus direct to the present.

If theology has found it so challenging to achieve a historical understanding of the meaning behind this self-designation, it’s because the question isn’t purely historical. In this term lies the transformation of an entire system of thought, a necessary result of removing eschatology from religion. Jesus spoke of His Messiahship only in a future context, not as something that was actual. Modern theology keeps trying to find a humanized, present-day Messiahship in the title Son of Man, which is tied to the future. It does this believing that recognizing a strictly future perspective in Jesus’ Messianic awareness would ultimately alter the historical foundation of our faith, which has itself become [pg 285] historical, and thus true and justifiable. Acknowledging the claims of eschatology means for our doctrine a total commitment, leaving no option to go back from the time of Jesus directly to the present.

One point that is worthy of notice in this connexion is the trustworthiness of the tradition. The Evangelists, writing in Greek, and the Greek-speaking Early Church, can hardly have retained an understanding of the purely eschatological character of that self-designation of Jesus. It had become for them merely an indirect method of self-designation. And nevertheless the Evangelists, especially Mark, record the sayings of Jesus in such a way that the original significance and application of the designation in His mouth is still clearly recognisable, and we are able to determine with certainty the isolated cases in which this self-designation in His discourses is of a secondary origin.

One point that's worth noting in this context is the reliability of the tradition. The Evangelists, writing in Greek, and the Greek-speaking Early Church, probably didn't maintain a full understanding of the purely eschatological nature of Jesus's self-designation. It had become for them just an indirect way of referring to Himself. However, the Evangelists, especially Mark, recorded Jesus's sayings in such a way that the original meaning and intent of the designation in His words are still clearly recognizable. We can identify with certainty the specific instances in which this self-designation in His discussions is of a later origin.

Thus the use of the term Son of Man—which, if we admitted the sweeping proposal of Lietzmann and Wellhausen to cancel it everywhere as an interpolation of Greek Early Church theology, would throw doubt on the whole of the Gospel tradition—becomes a proof of the certainty and trustworthiness of that tradition. We may, in fact, say that the progressive recognition of the eschatological character of the teaching and action of Jesus carries with it a progressive justification of the Gospel tradition. A series of passages and discourses which had been endangered because from the modern theological point of view which had been made the criterion of the tradition they appeared to be without meaning, are now secured. The stone which the critics rejected has become the corner-stone of the tradition.

Thus, the use of the term Son of Man—which, if we accepted the broad suggestion of Lietzmann and Wellhausen to dismiss it everywhere as an interpolation of Early Church Greek theology, would cast doubt on the entire Gospel tradition—becomes evidence of the reliability and trustworthiness of that tradition. In fact, we can say that the increasing recognition of the eschatological nature of Jesus' teachings and actions leads to a stronger justification of the Gospel tradition. A series of passages and discourses that were at risk because, from a modern theological perspective that had been used as the standard for the tradition, they seemed meaningless, are now validated. The stone that the critics rejected has become the cornerstone of the tradition.


If Aramaic scholarship appears in regard to the Son-of-Man question among the opponents of the thorough-going eschatological view, it takes no other position in connexion with the retranslations and in the application of illustrative parallels from the Rabbinic literature.

If Aramaic scholarship shows up in discussions about the Son-of-Man issue among those who oppose the complete eschatological perspective, it doesn’t adopt any different stance when it comes to retranslations and using parallels from Rabbinic literature for illustration.

In looking at the earlier works in this department, one is struck with the smallness of the result in proportion to the labour expended. The names that call for mention here are those of John Lightfoot, Christian Schöttgen, Joh. Gerh. Meuschen, J. Jak. Wettstein, F. Nork, Franz Delitzsch, Carl Siegfried, and A. Wünsche.210 But even a work like F. Weber's System der altsynagogalen [pg 286]palästinensischen Theologie,211 which does not confine itself to single sayings and thoughts, but aims at exhibiting the Rabbinic system of thought as a whole, throws, in the main, but little light on the thoughts of Jesus. The Rabbinic parables supply, according to Jülicher, but little of value for the explanation of the parables of Jesus.212 In this method of discourse, Jesus is so pre-eminently original, that any other productions of the Jewish parabolic literature are like stunted undergrowth beside a great tree; though that has not prevented His originality from being challenged in this very department, both in earlier times and at the present. As early as 1648, Robert Sheringham, of Cambridge,213 suggested that the parables in Matt. xx. 1 ff., xxv. 1 ff., and Luke xvi., were derived from Talmudic sources, an opinion against which J. B. Carpzov, the younger, raised a protest; in 1839, F. Nork asserted, in his work on “Rabbinic Sources and Parallels for the New Testament Writings,” that the best thoughts in the discourses of Jesus are to be attributed to His Jewish teachers; in 1880 the Dutch Rabbi, T. Tal, maintained the thesis that the parables of the New Testament are all borrowed from the Talmud.214 Theories of this kind cannot be refuted, because they lack the foundation necessary to any theory which is to be capable of being rationally discussed—that of plain common sense.215

In looking at the earlier works in this field, it’s surprising how little was achieved compared to the effort put in. The key figures worth mentioning here include John Lightfoot, Christian Schöttgen, Joh. Gerh. Meuschen, J. Jak. Wettstein, F. Nork, Franz Delitzsch, Carl Siegfried, and A. Wünsche.210 However, even a work like F. Weber's System of ancient synagogue [pg 286]Palestinian theology,211 which doesn’t just focus on individual sayings and ideas, but seeks to present the Rabbinic system of thought as a whole, sheds very little light on Jesus’ ideas. According to Jülicher, the Rabbinic parables offer little value for explaining Jesus' parables.212 In this method of discourse, Jesus is so uniquely original that other works in Jewish parabolic literature seem like small plants next to a giant tree; yet, this hasn’t stopped His originality from being questioned both in the past and today. In 1648, Robert Sheringham from Cambridge213 suggested that the parables in Matt. xx. 1 ff., xxv. 1 ff., and Luke xvi., originated from Talmudic sources, a viewpoint that J. B. Carpzov, the younger, protested against; in 1839, F. Nork claimed in his work on “Rabbinic Sources and Parallels for the New Testament Texts,” that the best ideas in Jesus' teachings should be attributed to His Jewish teachers; in 1880, the Dutch Rabbi, T. Tal, argued that all New Testament parables are borrowed from the Talmud.214 Such theories can’t be disproven because they lack the basic foundation necessary for any theory to be of rational discussion—common sense.215

We possess, however, really scientific attempts to define more closely the thoughts of Jesus by the aid of the Rabbinic language and Rabbinic ideas in the works of Arnold Meyer and Dalman. It cannot indeed be said that the obscure sayings which form the problem of present-day exegesis are in all cases made clearer by them, much as we may admire the comprehensive knowledge of [pg 287] these scholars. Sometimes, indeed, they become more obscure than before. According to Meyer, for instance, the question of Jesus whether His disciples can drink of His cup, and be baptized with His baptism means, if put back into Aramaic, “Can you drink as bitter a drink as I; can you eat as sharply salted meat as I?”216 Nor does Dalman's Aramaic retranslation help us much with the saying about the violent who take the Kingdom of Heaven by force. According to him, it is not spoken of the faithful, but of the rulers of this world, and refers to the epoch of the Divine rule which has been introduced by the imprisonment of the Baptist. No one can violently possess himself of the Divine reign, and Jesus can therefore only mean that violence is done to it in the person of its subjects.

We do have genuine scientific efforts to better understand Jesus' thoughts using Rabbinic language and ideas, as seen in the works of Arnold Meyer and Dalman. However, it's fair to say that the unclear sayings that challenge modern interpretation aren’t always clarified by their analyses, no matter how much we respect the extensive knowledge of these scholars. Sometimes, their explanations can make things even more confusing. For example, according to Meyer, when Jesus asks if His disciples can drink from His cup and be baptized with His baptism, it translates back into Aramaic as, "Can you drink a drink as bitter as mine? Can you eat meat as heavily salted as I do?"216 Similarly, Dalman's Aramaic retranslation doesn't offer much clarity on the saying about the violent taking the Kingdom of Heaven by force. He suggests it doesn’t refer to the faithful, but rather to the rulers of this world, relating to the era of Divine rule that began with John the Baptist's imprisonment. Ultimately, no one can forcibly claim the Divine reign, so Jesus must mean that violence is done to it through its subjects.

On this it must be remarked, that if the saying really means this, it is about as appropriate to its setting as a rock in the sky. Jesus is not speaking of the imprisonment of the Baptist. By the days of John the Baptist He means the time of his public ministry.

On this, it should be noted that if the saying really means this, it is as out of place as a rock in the sky. Jesus isn't talking about the imprisonment of John the Baptist. By the days of John the Baptist, He means the period of his public ministry.

It is equally open to question whether in putting that crucial question regarding the Messiah in Mark xii. 37 He really intended to show, as Dalman thinks, “that physical descent from David was not of decisive importance—it did not belong to the essence of the Messiahship.”

It’s also worth asking whether, when he asked that key question about the Messiah in Mark 12:37, he actually meant to demonstrate, as Dalman suggests, "being a physical descendant of David wasn’t essential—it wasn’t part of what it means to be the Messiah."

But a point in regard to which Dalman's remarks are of great value for the reconstruction of the life of Jesus is the entry into Jerusalem. Dalman thinks that the simple “Hosanna, blessed be he that cometh in the name of the Lord” (Mark xi. 9) was what the people really shouted in acclamation, and that the additional words in Mark and Matthew are simply an interpretative expansion. This acclamation did not itself contain any Messianic reference. This explains “why the entry into Jerusalem was not made a count in the charge urged against Him before Pilate.” The events of “Palm Sunday” only received their distinctively Messianic colour later. It was not the Messiah, but the prophet and wonder-worker of Galilee whom the people hailed with rejoicing and accompanied with invocations of blessing.217

But a key point regarding Dalman's insights that is incredibly valuable for understanding the life of Jesus is His entry into Jerusalem. Dalman believes that the simple "Hosanna, blessed is he who comes in the name of the Lord." (Mark xi. 9) was what the people truly shouted in celebration, and that the additional phrases in Mark and Matthew are merely an interpretive addition. This celebration did not inherently contain any Messianic implication. This clarifies "why the entry into Jerusalem was not included in the accusations against Him before Pilate." The events of "Palm Sunday" only gained their distinctly Messianic significance later on. It was not the Messiah, but rather the prophet and miracle worker from Galilee whom the people welcomed with joy and accompanied with blessings.217

Generally speaking, the value of Dalman's work lies less in the solutions which it offers than in the problems which it raises. By its very thorough discussions it challenges historical theology to test its most cherished assumptions regarding the teaching of Jesus, and make sure whether they are really so certain and self-evident. Thus, in opposition to Schürer, he denies that the thought of the [pg 288] pre-existence in heaven of all the good things belonging to the Kingdom of God was at all generally current in the Late-Jewish world of ideas, and thinks that the occasional references218 to a pre-existing Jerusalem, which shall finally be brought down to the earth, do not suffice to establish the theory. Similarly, he thinks it doubtful whether Jesus used the terms “this world (age),” “the world (age) to come” in the eschatological sense which is generally attached to them, and doubts, on linguistic grounds, whether they can have been used at all. Even the use of עלם or עולם for “world” cannot be proved. In the pre-Christian period there is much reason to doubt its occurrence, though in later Jewish literature it is frequent. The expression ἐν τῇ παλιγγενεσίᾳ in Matt. xix. 28, is specifically Greek and cannot be reproduced in either Hebrew or Aramaic. It is very strange that the use which Jesus makes of Amen is unknown in the whole of Jewish literature. According to the proper idiom of the language “אמן is never used to emphasise one's own speech, but always with reference to the speech, prayer, benediction, oath, or curse of another.” Jesus, therefore, if He used the expression in this sense, must have given it a new meaning as a formula of asseveration, in place of the oath which He forbade.

Generally speaking, the value of Dalman's work lies less in the solutions it offers and more in the problems it raises. Through its in-depth discussions, it challenges historical theology to examine its most cherished assumptions about the teachings of Jesus and verify whether they are truly as certain and obvious as believed. Thus, contrary to Schürer, he argues that the idea of the pre-existence in heaven of all the good things belonging to the Kingdom of God was not widely accepted in the Late-Jewish intellectual world, and believes that the occasional references to a pre-existing Jerusalem that will eventually be brought down to earth are not enough to support that theory. Similarly, he finds it questionable whether Jesus used the terms “this world (age)” and “the world (age) to come” in the eschatological sense they are commonly understood to have, and on linguistic grounds, he doubts that they were even used at all. Even the use of עלם or עולם for “world” cannot be verified. In the pre-Christian period, there is much reason to doubt its occurrence, although it appears frequently in later Jewish literature. The phrase ἐν τῇ παλιγγενεσίᾳ in Matt. xix. 28 is specifically Greek and cannot be translated into either Hebrew or Aramaic. It is quite strange that the way Jesus uses “Amen” is not found in any Jewish literature. According to the language's proper idiom, “אמן” is never used to emphasize one's own speech, but always in reference to someone else's speech, prayer, benediction, oath, or curse. Therefore, if Jesus used the term in this way, he must have given it a new meaning as a formula of affirmation, replacing the oath he prohibited.

All these acute observations are marked by the general tendency which was observable in the interpretation of the term Son of Man, that is, by the endeavour so to weaken down the eschatological conceptions of the Kingdom and the Messiah, that the hypothesis of a making-present and spiritualising of these conceptions in the teaching of Jesus might appear inherently and linguistically possible and natural. The polemic against the pre-existent realities of the Kingdom of God is intended to show that for Jesus the Reign of God is a present benefit, which can be sought after, given, possessed, and taken. Even before the time of Jesus, according to Dalman, a tendency had shown itself to lay less emphasis, in connexion with the hope of the future, upon the national Jewish element. Jesus forced this element still farther into the background, and gave a more decided prominence to the purely religious element. “For Him the reign of God was the Divine power, which from this time onward was steadily to carry forward the renewal of the world, and also the renewed world, into which men shall one day enter, which even now offers itself, and therefore can be grasped and received as a present good.” The supernatural coming of the Kingdom is only the final stage of the coming which is now being inwardly spiritually brought about by the preaching of Jesus. Though He may perhaps have spoken of “this” world and the “world to come,” these expressions had in His use of them no very special importance. It is for Him less a question of an antithesis between “then” and [pg 289] “now,” than of establishing a connexion between them by which the transition from one to the other is to be effected.

All these sharp observations show a general trend in how the term "Son of Man" is interpreted, which involves downplaying the end-times ideas of the Kingdom and the Messiah. This approach makes the idea of these concepts being made present and spiritualized in Jesus' teaching seem both possible and natural. The argument against the existing realities of the Kingdom of God aims to demonstrate that for Jesus, the Reign of God is a present gift that can be sought, given, possessed, and experienced. Even before Jesus' time, according to Dalman, there was a shift away from stressing the national Jewish element in connection with future hope. Jesus pushed this element further into the background and highlighted the purely religious aspect. “For Him, the reign of God was the Divine power that from this moment on would consistently drive the renewal of the world, along with the renewed world that people will one day enter. It even presents itself now and can therefore be grasped and received as a current good.” The supernatural arrival of the Kingdom is merely the final stage of the bringing about that is currently happening spiritually through Jesus' preaching. While He might have referenced this world and the “next world,” these terms didn't hold any particular significance in His usage. For Him, it is less about an opposition between "then" and [pg 289] “now,” and more about establishing a connection that facilitates the transition from one to the other.

It is the same in regard to Jesus' consciousness of His Messiahship. “In Jesus' view,” says Dalman, “the period before the commencement of the Reign of God was organically connected with the actual period of His Reign.” He was the Messiah because He knew Himself to stand in a unique ethico-religious relation to God. His Messiahship was not something wholly incomprehensible to those about Him. If redemption was regarded as being close at hand, the Messiah must be assumed to be in some sense already present. Therefore Jesus is both directly and indirectly spoken of as Messiah.

It’s the same when it comes to Jesus’ awareness of His role as the Messiah. “In Jesus' perspective,” Dalman states, "The time before the start of the Reign of God was naturally connected to the actual time of His Reign." He identified as the Messiah because he recognized his unique ethical and spiritual relationship with God. His role as the Messiah wasn’t completely foreign to those around him. If redemption was seen as imminent, then the Messiah must be considered to be, in some way, already present. Therefore, Jesus is referred to both directly and indirectly as the Messiah.

Thus the most important work in the department of Aramaic scholarship shows clearly the anti-eschatological tendency which characterised it from the beginning. The work of Lietzmann, Meyer, Wellhausen, and Dalman, forms a distinct episode in the general resistance to eschatology. That Aramaic scholarship should have taken up a hostile attitude towards the eschatological system of thought of Jesus lies in the nature of things. The thoughts which it takes as its standard of comparison were only reduced to writing long after the period of Jesus, and, moreover, in a lifeless and distorted form, at a time when the apocalyptic temper no longer existed as the living counterpoise to the legal righteousness, and this legal righteousness had allowed only so much of Apocalyptic to survive as could be brought into direct connexion with it. In fact, the distance between Jesus' world of thought and this form of Judaism is as great as that which separates it from modern ideas. Thus in Dalman modernising tendencies and Aramaic scholarship were able to combine in conducting a criticism of the eschatology in the teaching of Jesus in which the modern man thought the thoughts and the expert in Aramaic formulated and supported them, yet without being able in the end to make any impression upon the well-rounded whole formed by Jesus' eschatological preaching of the Kingdom.

Thus, the most important work in the field of Aramaic scholarship clearly shows the anti-eschatological trend that has characterized it from the beginning. The contributions of Lietzmann, Meyer, Wellhausen, and Dalman represent a distinct episode in the broader resistance to eschatology. It's inherent that Aramaic scholarship would adopt a negative stance toward the eschatological beliefs of Jesus. The ideas used as benchmarks were only written down long after Jesus' time, and they were also presented in a lifeless and distorted way, at a time when the apocalyptic mindset was no longer a vibrant alternative to legal righteousness, which had only allowed a fragment of Apocalyptic thought to persist that could be directly linked to it. In fact, the gap between Jesus' way of thinking and this form of Judaism is as wide as that which separates it from contemporary ideas. Therefore, in Dalman, modernizing tendencies and Aramaic scholarship could merge to critique the eschatology found in Jesus' teachings, where modern thinkers conceptualized ideas, and Aramaic experts articulated and supported them, yet in the end, they failed to make any real impact on the cohesive whole represented by Jesus' eschatological message about the Kingdom.

Whether Aramaic scholarship will contribute to the investigation of the life and teaching of Jesus along other lines and in a direct and positive fashion, only the future can show. But certainly if theologians will give heed to the question-marks so acutely placed by Dalman, and recognise it as one of their first duties to test carefully whether a thought or a connexion of thought is linguistically or inherently Greek, and only Greek, in character, they will derive a notable advantage from what has already been done in the department of Aramaic study.

Whether Aramaic scholarship will aid in exploring the life and teachings of Jesus in new and direct ways remains to be seen. However, if theologians pay attention to the important questions raised by Dalman and see it as their responsibility to carefully examine whether a thought or connection of thoughts is strictly linguistic or inherently Greek, they will benefit significantly from the work that has already been done in Aramaic studies.


But if the service rendered by Aramaic studies has been hitherto mainly indirect, no success whatever has attended, or seems likely [pg 290] to attend, the attempt to apply Buddhist ideas to the explanation of the thoughts of Jesus. It could only indeed appear to have some prospect of success if we could make up our minds to follow the example of the author of one of the most recent of fictitious lives of Christ in putting Jesus to school to the Buddhist priests; in which case the six years which Monsieur Nicolas Notowitsch allots to this purpose, would certainly be none too much for the completion of the course.219 If imagination boggles at this, there remains no possibility of showing that Buddhist ideas exercised any direct influence upon Jesus. That Buddhism may have had some kind of influence upon Late Judaism and thus indirectly upon Jesus is not inherently impossible, if we are prepared to recognise Buddhistic influence on the Babylonian and Persian civilisations. But it is unproved, unprovable, and unthinkable, that Jesus derived the suggestion of the new and creative ideas which emerge in His teaching from Buddhism. The most that can be done in this direction is to point to certain analogies. For the parables of Jesus, Buddhist parallels were suggested by Renan and Havet.220

But if the contribution of Aramaic studies has mostly been indirect so far, there has been no success at all, nor does it seem likely to happen, in trying to apply Buddhist ideas to explain the thoughts of Jesus. It would only seem to have a chance of success if we decided to follow the approach of the author of one of the most recent fictional accounts of Christ by sending Jesus to study under Buddhist monks; in that case, the six years that Monsieur Nicolas Notowitsch allocates for this would definitely not be too long to complete the course. If that thought is hard to accept, there's no way to prove that Buddhist ideas directly influenced Jesus. It’s not impossible that Buddhism had some impact on Late Judaism and, therefore, indirectly on Jesus, especially if we acknowledge the influence of Buddhism on Babylonian and Persian cultures. However, it's unproven, unprovable, and quite far-fetched to claim that Jesus got his innovative ideas from Buddhism. The most we can do in this regard is point out some similarities. For the parables of Jesus, Renan and Havet suggested Buddhist parallels.

How little these analogies mean in the eyes of a cautious observer is evident from the attitude which Max Müller took up towards the question. “That there are startling coincidences between Buddhism and Christianity,” he remarks in one passage,221 “cannot be denied; and it must likewise be admitted that Buddhism existed at least four hundred years before Christianity. I go even further and say that I should be extremely grateful if anybody would point out to me the historical channels through which Buddhism had influenced early Christianity. I have been looking for such channels all my life, but hitherto I have found none. What I have found is that for some of the most startling coincidences there are historical antecedents on both sides; and if we once know these antecedents the coincidences become far less startling.”

How little these analogies mean to a careful observer is clear from Max Müller's perspective on the question. "That there are unexpected similarities between Buddhism and Christianity," he notes in one part, 221 "It can't be denied, and we must also recognize that Buddhism existed at least four hundred years before Christianity. I'd even go as far as to say that I would appreciate it if anyone could show me the historical links through which Buddhism influenced early Christianity. I've been looking for these connections my entire life, but I haven't found any yet. What I have found is that for some of the most noticeable similarities, there are historical precedents on both sides; and once we understand these precedents, the similarities appear much less surprising."

A year before Max Müller formulated his impression in these terms, Rudolf Seydel222 had endeavoured to explain the analogies [pg 291] which had been noticed by supposing Christianity to have been influenced by Buddhism. He distinguishes three distinct classes of analogies:

A year before Max Müller shared his views, Rudolf Seydel222 tried to explain the similarities [pg 291] that had been observed by suggesting that Christianity was influenced by Buddhism. He identifies three separate categories of similarities:

1. Those of which the points of resemblance can without difficulty be explained as due to the influence of similar sources and motives in the two cases.

1. The similarities can easily be explained by the influence of similar sources and motives in both cases.

2. Those which show a so special and unexpected agreement that it appears artificial to explain it from the action of similar causes, and the dependence of one upon the other commends itself as the most natural explanation.

2. Those that show such a unique and surprising connection that it seems unnatural to explain it through similar causes, and the reliance of one on the other stands out as the most fitting explanation.

3. Those in which there exists a reason for the occurrence of the idea only within the sphere of one of the two religions, or in which at least it can very much more easily be conceived as originating within the one than within the other, so that the inexplicability of the phenomenon within the one domain gives ground for seeking its source within the other.

3. Those situations where there's a reason for the idea to occur only within one of the two religions, or where it can be much more easily understood as coming from one rather than the other, meaning that the inability to explain the phenomenon in one area leads to looking for its source in the other.

This last class demands a literary explanation of the analogy. Seydel therefore postulates, alongside of primitive forms of Matthew and Luke, a third source, “a poetic-apocalyptic Gospel of very early date which fitted its Christian material into the frame of a Buddhist type of Gospel, transforming, purifying, and ennobling the material taken from the foreign but related literature by a kind of rebirth inspired by the Christian Spirit.” Matthew and Luke, especially Luke, follow this poetic Gospel up to the point where historic sources become more abundant, and the primitive form of Mark begins to dominate their narrative. But even in later parts the influence of this poetical source, which as an independent document was subsequently lost, continued to make itself felt.

This final class requires a literary explanation of the analogy. Seydel therefore suggests, along with the original versions of Matthew and Luke, a third source, "a poetic-apocalyptic Gospel from a very early time that combined its Christian content into a Buddhist-style Gospel, transforming, purifying, and enhancing the information drawn from related but different texts through a sort of rebirth inspired by the Christian Spirit." Matthew and Luke, especially Luke, follow this poetic Gospel until more historical sources become available, and the original form of Mark starts to dominate their narrative. However, even in the later sections, the influence of this poetic source, which was eventually lost as an independent document, continued to be felt.

The strongest point of support for this hypothesis, if a mere conjecture can be described as such, is found by Seydel in the introductory narratives in Luke. Now it is not inherently impossible that Buddhist legends, which in one form or another were widely current in the East, may have contributed more or less to the formation of the mythical preliminary history. Who knows the laws of the formation of legend? Who can follow the course of the wind which carries the seed over land and sea? But in general it may be said that Seydel actually refutes the hypothesis which he is defending. If the material which he brings forward is all that there is to suggest a relation between Buddhism and Christianity, we are justified in waiting until new discoveries are made in that quarter before asserting the necessity of a Buddhist primitive Gospel. That will not prevent a succession of theosophic Lives of Jesus from finding their account in Seydel's classical work. Seydel indeed delivered himself into their hands, because he did not [pg 292] entirely avoid the rash assumption of theosophic “historical science” that Jewish eschatology can be equated with Buddhistic.

The strongest support for this hypothesis, if we can call a mere guess that, is found by Seydel in the introductory stories in Luke. It's not impossible that Buddhist legends, which were widely known in the East in one form or another, may have somewhat contributed to the creation of the mythical backstory. Who truly understands the rules of how legends form? Who can track the wind that carries seeds across land and sea? However, it can generally be said that Seydel actually undermines the hypothesis he is defending. If the evidence he presents is all there is to suggest a connection between Buddhism and Christianity, we are justified in waiting for new discoveries before claiming the necessity of a Buddhist original Gospel. That won’t stop a series of theosophical Lives of Jesus from finding support in Seydel's classic work. Seydel indeed left himself open to their interpretations because he didn’t entirely avoid the risky assumption of theosophic “historical science” that Jewish eschatology can be compared to Buddhism.

Eduard von Hartmann, in the second edition of his work, “The Christianity of the New Testament,”223 roundly asserts that there can be no question of any relation of Jesus to Buddha, nor of any indebtedness either in His teaching or in the later moulding of the story of His life, but only of a parallel formation of myth.

Eduard von Hartmann, in the second edition of his work, "The Christianity of the New Testament,"223 clearly states that there is no evidence of any connection between Jesus and Buddha, nor any influence in His teachings or in the later shaping of His life story, but rather a parallel development of myth.

[pg 293]

18. The Role of the Individual at the End of the Nineteenth Century

Oskar Holtzmann. Das Leben Jesu. Tübingen, 1901. 417 pp.

Oskar Holtzmann. The Life of Jesus. Tübingen, 1901. 417 pages.

Das Messianitätsbewusstsein Jesu und seine neueste Bestreitung. Vortrag. (The Messianic Consciousness of Jesus and the most recent denial of it. A Lecture.) 1902. 26 pp. (Against Wrede.)

The Messianic Awareness of Jesus and the Latest Rejection of It. A Lecture. 1902. 26 pages. (In Opposition to Wrede.)

War Jesus Ekstatiker? (Was Jesus an ecstatic?) Tübingen, 1903. 139 pp.

Was Jesus an Ecstatic? Tübingen, 1903. 139 pages.

Paul Wilhelm Schmidt. Die Geschichte Jesu. (The History of Jesus.) Freiburg. 1899. 175 pp. (4th impression.)

Paul Wilhelm Schmidt. The History of Jesus. Freiburg. 1899. 175 pages. (4th edition.)

Die Geschichte Jesu. Erläutert. Mit drei Karten von Prof. K. Furrer (Zürich). (The History of Jesus. Preliminary Discussions. With three maps by Prof. K. Furrer of Zurich.) Tübingen, 1904. 414 pp.

The Story of Jesus. Explained. Featuring three maps by Prof. K. Furrer (Zurich). Tübingen, 1904. 414 pages.

Otto Schmiedel. Die Hauptprobleme der Leben-Jesu-Forschung. (The main Problems in the Study of the Life of Jesus.) Tübingen, 1902. 71 pp. 2nd ed., 1906.

Otto Schmiedel. The Main Issues in the Study of the Life of Jesus. Tübingen, 1902. 71 pages. 2nd edition, 1906.

Hermann Freiherr von Soden. Die wichtigsten Fragen im Leben Jesu. (The most important Questions about the Life of Jesus.) Vacation Lectures. Berlin, 1904. 111 pp.

Hermann Freiherr von Soden. The Key Questions About Jesus' Life. Vacation Lectures. Berlin, 1904. 111 pages.

Gustav Frenssen. Hilligenlei. Berlin, 1905, pp. 462-593: Die Handschrift.(The Manuscript—in which a Life of Jesus, written by one of the characters of the story, is given in full.)

Gustav Frenssen. Hilligenlei. Berlin, 1905, pp. 462-593: “The Manuscript.”Below is a short piece of text (5 words or fewer). Modernize it into contemporary English if there's enough context, but do not add or omit any information. If context is insufficient, return it unchanged. Do not add commentary, and do not modify any placeholders. If you see placeholders of the form __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_x__, you must keep them exactly as-is so they can be replaced with links. (“The Manuscript”—which contains a full account of Jesus' life, written by one of the characters in the story.)

Otto Pfleiderer. Das Urchristentum, seine Schriften und Lehren in geschichtlichem Zusammenhang beschrieben. (Primitive Christianity. Its Documents and Doctrines in their Historical Context.) 2nd ed. Berlin, 1902. Vol. i., 696 pp.

Otto Pfleiderer. Primitive Christianity: Its Documents and Doctrines in Their Historical Context. 2nd ed. Berlin, 1902. Vol. 1, 696 pages.

Die Entstehung des Urchristentums. (How Primitive Christianity arose.) Munich, 1905. 255 pp.

The origins of early Christianity. (How Primitive Christianity Developed.) Munich, 1905. 255 pages.

Albert Kalthoff. Das Christus-Problem. Grundlinien zu einer Sozialtheologie. (The Christ-problem. The Ground-plan of a Social Theology.) Leipzig, 1902. 87 pp.

Albert Kalthoff. The Christ Problem: A Framework for Social Theology. Leipzig, 1902. 87 pages.

Die Entstehung des Christentums. Neue Beiträge zum Christus-Problem. (How Christianity arose. New contributions to the Christ-problem.) Leipzig, 1904. 155 pp.

The Origin of Christianity: New Insights into the Christ Issue. Leipzig, 1904. 155 pages.

Eduard von Hartmann. Das Christentum des Neuen Testaments. (The Christianity of the New Testament.) 2nd revised edition of Letters on the Christian Religion. Sachsa-in-the-Harz, 1905. 311 pp.

Eduard von Hartmann. The Christianity of the New Testament. 2nd revised edition of __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ “Letters on Christianity.” Sachsa-in-the-Harz, 1905. 311 pp.

De Jonge. Jeschua. Der klassische jüdische Mann. Zerstörung des kirchlichen, Enthüllung des jüdischen Jesus-Bildes. Berlin, 1904. 112 pp. (Jeshua. The Classical Jewish Man. In which the Jewish picture of Jesus is unveiled, and the ecclesiastical picture destroyed.)

De Jonge. Jeschua. The Classical Jewish Man. The destruction of the church's image and the revealing of the Jewish portrayal of Jesus. Berlin, 1904. 112 pages. (Jeshua. The Classical Jewish Man. This book reveals the Jewish image of Jesus and dismantles the church's depiction.)

[pg 294]

Wolfgang Kirchbach. Was lehrte Jesus? Zwei Urevangelien. (What was the teaching of Jesus? Two Primitive Gospels.) Berlin, 1897. 248 pp. 2nd revised and greatly enlarged edition, 1902, 339 pp.

Wolfgang Kirchbach. What did Jesus teach? Two Original Gospels. Berlin, 1897. 248 pages. 2nd revised and greatly expanded edition, 1902, 339 pages.

Albert Dulk. Der Irrgang des Lebens Jesu. In geschichtlicher Auffassung dargestellt. (The Error of the Life of Jesus. An Historical View.) 1st part, 1884, 395 pp.; 2nd part, 1885, 302 pp.

Albert Dulk. The Mistakes in the Life of Jesus. Offered from a Historical Viewpoint. Part 1, 1884, 395 pages; Part 2, 1885, 302 pages.

Paul de Régla. Jesus von Nazareth. German by A. Just. Leipzig, 1894. 435 pp.

Paul de Régla. Jesus of Nazareth. Translated by A. Just. Leipzig, 1894. 435 pages.

Ernest Bosc. La Vie ésotérique de Jésus de Nazareth et les origines orientales du christianisme. (The secret Life of Jesus of Nazareth, and the Oriental Origins of Christianity.) Paris, 1902.

Ernest Bosc. The Hidden Life of Jesus of Nazareth and the Eastern Roots of Christianity. Paris, 1902.

The ideal Life of Jesus of the close of the nineteenth century is the Life which Heinrich Julius Holtzmann did not write—but which can be pieced together from his commentary on the Synoptic Gospels and his New Testament Theology.224 It is ideal because, for one thing, it is unwritten, and arises only in the idea of the reader by the aid of his own imagination, and, for another, because it is traced only in the most general outline. What Holtzmann gives us is a sketch of the public ministry, a critical examination of details, and a full account of the teaching of Jesus. He provides, therefore, the plan and the prepared building material, so that any one can carry out the construction in his own way and on his own responsibility. The cement and the mortar are not provided by Holtzmann; every one must decide for himself how he will combine the teaching and the life, and arrange the details within each.

The ideal Life of Jesus at the end of the nineteenth century is the Life that Heinrich Julius Holtzmann didn’t write—but can be put together from his commentary on the Synoptic Gospels and his New Testament Theology.224 It’s ideal because, for one thing, it remains unwritten and exists only in the imagination of the reader, and for another, it is only outlined in the broadest terms. What Holtzmann provides is a sketch of the public ministry, a critical look at the details, and a comprehensive overview of Jesus’ teachings. He offers the blueprint and the building materials, so anyone can create their own version based on their own interpretation and responsibility. Holtzmann doesn’t provide the concrete and the mortar; everyone must figure out how to blend the teachings and the life, and how to organize the details within each.

We may recall the fact that Weisse, too, the other founder of the Marcan hypothesis, avoided writing a Life of Jesus, because the difficulty of fitting the details into the ground-plan appeared to him so great, not to say insuperable. It is just this modesty which constitutes his greatness and Holtzmann's. Thus the Marcan hypothesis ends, as it had begun, with a certain historical scepticism.225

We should remember that Weisse, another originator of the Marcan hypothesis, also chose not to write a Life of Jesus because he found it incredibly challenging—if not impossible—to fit all the details into a coherent framework. This humility is what defines his greatness, as well as Holtzmann's. So, the Marcan hypothesis concludes, just as it started, with a kind of historical skepticism.225

[pg 295]

The subordinates, it is true, do not allow themselves to be disturbed by the change of attitude at head-quarters. They keep busily at work. That is their right, and therein consists their significance. By keeping on trying to take the positions, and constantly failing, they furnish a practical proof that the plan of operations worked out by the general staff is not capable of being carried out, and show why it is so, and what kind of new tactics will have to be evolved.

The subordinates, they don’t let the change in attitude at headquarters bother them. They stay focused and keep working hard. That’s their right, and that’s what makes them important. By continuously trying to take the positions and repeatedly failing, they provide clear evidence that the strategy developed by the general staff isn’t feasible, and they illustrate why that is and what new tactics will need to be developed.

The credit of having written a life of Christ which is strictly scientific, in its own way very remarkable, and yet foredoomed to failure, belongs to Oskar Holtzmann.226 He has complete confidence in the Marcan plan, and makes it his task to fit all the sayings of Jesus into this framework, to show “what can belong to each period of the preaching of Jesus, and what cannot.” His method is to give free play to the magnetic power of the most important passages in the Marcan text, making other sayings of similar import detach themselves from their present connexion and come and group themselves round the main passages.

The credit for writing a life of Christ that is scientifically thorough, quite impressive in its own way, yet likely destined to fail, goes to Oskar Holtzmann. He fully trusts the Marcan framework and takes it upon himself to fit all of Jesus' sayings into this structure, aiming to demonstrate "what can be associated with each period of Jesus' preaching, and what cannot." His approach is to allow the most significant passages in the Marcan text to shine, causing other sayings of similar importance to detach from their current context and gather around the main passages.

[pg 296]

For example, the controversy with the scribes at Jerusalem regarding the charge of doing miracles by the help of Satan (Mark iii. 22-30) belongs, according to Holtzmann, as regards content and chronology, to the same period as the controversy, in Mark vii., about the ordinances of men which results in Jesus being “obliged to take to flight”; the woes pronounced upon Chorazin, Bethsaida, and Capernaum, which now follow on the eulogy upon the Baptist (Matt. xi. 21-23), and are accordingly represented as having been spoken at the time of the sending forth of the Twelve, are drawn by the same kind of magnetic force into the neighbourhood of Mark vii., and “express very clearly the attitude of Jesus at the time of His withdrawal from the scene of His earlier ministry.” The saying in Matt. vii. 6 about not giving that which is holy to the dogs or casting pearls before swine, does not belong to the Sermon on the Mount, but to the time when Jesus, after Caesarea Philippi, forbids the disciples to reveal the secret of His Messiahship to the multitude; Jesus' action in cursing the fig-tree so that it should henceforth bring no fruit to its owner, who was perhaps a poor man, is to be brought into relation with the words spoken on the evening before, with reference to the lavish expenditure involved in His anointing, “The poor ye have always with you,” the point being that Jesus now, “in the clear consciousness of His approaching death, feels His own worth,” and dismisses “the contingency of even the poor having to lose something for His sake” with the words “it does not matter.”227

For instance, the argument with the scribes in Jerusalem about the claim that he performed miracles with the help of Satan (Mark 3:22-30) is, according to Holtzmann, relevant in terms of content and timing to the earlier dispute in Mark 7 about human traditions that leads to Jesus being "forced to escape"; the condemnations aimed at Chorazin, Bethsaida, and Capernaum, which come after the praise of the Baptist (Matt. 11:21-23), are thus portrayed as having been said when the Twelve were sent out, and are pulled by a similar magnetic force into the context of Mark 7, expressing "clearly reflects Jesus' attitude when He stepped away from His earlier ministry." The statement in Matt. 7:6 about not giving what is holy to dogs or casting pearls before pigs does not belong to the Sermon on the Mount but to the time after Jesus, following his visit to Caesarea Philippi, tells his disciples not to share the secret of his messiahship with the crowds; Jesus' action of cursing the fig tree so it would no longer bear fruit for its owner, who might have been a poor man, should be connected to the remarks made the evening before regarding the extravagant cost of his anointing, “You will always have the poor with you,” meaning that now, “fully aware of His upcoming death, recognizes His own value,” and dismisses “the chance of even the poor sacrificing something for His sake” with the words "it doesn't matter."227

All these transpositions and new connexions mean, it is clear, a great deal of internal and external violence to the text.

All these transpositions and new connections clearly mean a lot of internal and external pressure on the text.

A further service rendered by this very thorough work of Oskar Holtzmann's, is that of showing how much reading between the lines is necessary in order to construct a Life of Jesus on the basis of the Marcan hypothesis in its modern interpretation. It is thus, for instance, that the author must have acquired the knowledge that the controversy about the ordinances of purification in Mark vii. forced the people “to choose between the old and the new religion”—in which case it is no wonder that many “turned back from following Jesus.”

A further service provided by this comprehensive work of Oskar Holtzmann is demonstrating how much reading between the lines is needed to build a Life of Jesus based on the modern interpretation of the Marcan hypothesis. For example, the author must have understood that the debate over the purification laws in Mark 7 made the people "decide between the old and the new religion"—which explains why many “turned back from following Jesus.”

Where are we told that there was any question of an old and a new “religion”? The disciples certainly did not think of things in this way, as is shown by their conduct at the time of His death [pg 297] and the discourses of Peter in Acts. Where do we read that the people turned away from Jesus? In Mark vii. 17 and 24 all that is said is, that Jesus left the people, and in Mark vii. 33 the same multitude is still assembled when Jesus returns from the “banishment” into which Holtzmann relegates Him.

Where are we told that there was any question of an old and a new "faith"? The disciples definitely didn't see it this way, as shown by their actions during His death [pg 297] and Peter's speeches in Acts. Where do we read that the people turned away from Jesus? In Mark 7:17 and 24, it just says that Jesus left the crowd, and in Mark 7:33, the same crowd is still gathered when Jesus returns from the exile that Holtzmann claims He went to.

Oskar Holtzmann declares that we cannot tell what was the size of the following which accompanied Jesus in His journey northwards, and is inclined to assume that others besides the Twelve shared His exile. The Evangelists, however, say clearly that it was only the μαθηταί, that is, the Twelve, who were with Him. The value which this special knowledge, independent of the text, has for the author, becomes evident a little farther on. After Peter's confession Jesus calls the “multitude” to Him (Mark viii. 34) and speaks to them of His sufferings and of taking up the cross and following Him. This “multitude” Holtzmann wants to make “the whole company of Jesus' followers,” “to which belonged, not only the Twelve whom Jesus had formerly sent out to preach, but many others also.” The knowledge drawn from outside the text is therefore required to solve a difficulty in the text.

Oskar Holtzmann states that we can't determine the size of those who accompanied Jesus on His journey north and suggests that others besides the Twelve were part of His exile. However, the Evangelists clearly indicate that only the μαθηταί, meaning the Twelve, were with Him. The significance of this special knowledge, which is independent of the text, becomes clear a bit later. After Peter's confession, Jesus calls the "crowd" to Him (Mark viii. 34) and speaks to them about His sufferings and the need to take up the cross and follow Him. Holtzmann wants to interpret this “variety” as "the entire group of Jesus' followers," “which included not just the Twelve that Jesus had sent out to preach before, but many others too.” Therefore, knowledge drawn from outside the text is needed to resolve a difficulty within the text.

But how did His companions in exile, the remnant of the previous multitude, themselves become a multitude, the same multitude as before? Would it not be better to admit that we do not know how, in a Gentile country, a multitude could suddenly rise out of the ground as it were, continue with Him until Mark ix. 30, and then disappear into the earth as suddenly as they came, leaving Him to pursue His journey towards Galilee and Jerusalem alone?

But how did His companions in exile, the few left from the previous crowd, become a crowd again, the same crowd as before? Wouldn't it be better to admit that we don't know how, in a non-Jewish country, a crowd could suddenly appear out of nowhere, stick with Him until Mark ix. 30, and then vanish just as suddenly, leaving Him to continue His journey toward Galilee and Jerusalem alone?

Another thing which Oskar Holtzmann knows is that it required a good deal of courage for Peter to hail Jesus as Messiah, since the “exile wandering about with his small following in a Gentile country” answered “so badly to the general picture which people had formed of the coming of the Messiah.” He knows too, that in the moment of Peter's confession, “Christianity was complete” in the sense that “a community separate from Judaism and centring about a new ideal, then arose.” This “community” frequently appears from this point onwards. There is nothing about it in the narratives, which know only the Twelve and the people.

Another thing Oskar Holtzmann understands is that it took a lot of courage for Peter to call Jesus the Messiah, since the "an exile moving around with his small group in a non-Jewish country" did "did not align with the common expectations people had about the arrival of the Messiah." He also knows that at the moment of Peter's confession, “Christianity is complete” in the sense that "A community emerged that was distinct from Judaism and focused on a new ideal." This “community” often appears from this point on. There is nothing about it in the narratives, which only recognize the Twelve and the people.

Oskar Holtzmann's knowledge even extends to dialogues which are not reported in the Gospels. After the incident at Caesarea Philippi, the minds of the disciples were, according to him, preoccupied by two questions. “How did Jesus know that He was the Messiah?” and “What will be the future fate of this Messiah?” The Lord answered both questions. He spoke to them of His baptism, and “doubtless in close connexion with that” He told them the story of His temptation, during which He had laid down the lines which He was determined to follow as Messiah.

Oskar Holtzmann's knowledge even includes conversations that aren't recorded in the Gospels. After the event at Caesarea Philippi, he suggests the disciples were focused on two questions: "How did Jesus know He was the Messiah?" and "What will happen to this Messiah in the future?" The Lord addressed both questions. He talked to them about His baptism and “definitely related to that” He shared the story of His temptation, during which He established the path He intended to take as the Messiah.

[pg 298]

Of the transfiguration, Oskar Holtzmann can state with confidence, “that it merely represents the inner experience of the disciples at the moment of Peter's confession.” How is it then that Mark expressly dates that scene, placing it (ix. 2) six days after the discourse of Jesus about taking up the cross and following Him? The fact is that the time-indications of the text are treated as non-existent whenever the Marcan hypothesis requires an order determined by inner connexion. The statement of Luke that the transfiguration took place eight days after, is dismissed in the remark “the motive of this indication of time is doubtless to be found in the use of the Gospel narratives for reading in public worship; the idea was that the section about the transfiguration should be read on the Sunday following that on which the confession of Peter formed the lesson.” Where did Oskar Holtzmann suddenly discover this information about the order of the “Sunday lessons” at the time when Luke's Gospel was written?

Of the transfiguration, Oskar Holtzmann confidently states, "that it simply reflects the inner feelings of the disciples at the time of Peter's confession." So how is it that Mark specifically dates that scene, placing it (ix. 2) six days after Jesus' talk about taking up the cross and following Him? The truth is that the time references in the text are ignored whenever the Marcan hypothesis requires a sequence based on internal connections. Luke’s statement that the transfiguration happened eight days later is brushed aside with the comment "The reason for this timing is clearly related to the use of the Gospel stories in public worship. The idea was that the part about the transfiguration should be read on the Sunday after the one where Peter's confession was the lesson." Where did Oskar Holtzmann suddenly find this information about the order of the “Sunday classes” at the time when Luke's Gospel was written?

It was doubtless from the same private source of information that the author derived his knowledge regarding the gradual development of the thought of the Passion in the consciousness of Jesus. “After the confession of Peter at Caesarea Philippi,” he explains, “Jesus' death became for Him only the necessary point of transition to the glory beyond. In the discourse of Jesus to which the request of Salome gave occasion, the death of Jesus already appears as the means of saving many from death, because His death makes possible the coming of the Kingdom of God. At the institution of the Supper, Jesus regards His imminent death as the meritorious deed by which the blessings of the New Covenant, the forgiveness of sins and victory over sin, are permanently secured to His ‘community.’ We see Jesus constantly becoming more and more at home with the idea of His death and constantly giving it a deeper interpretation.”

It’s clear that the author got his information from the same private source regarding how the idea of the Passion gradually developed in Jesus' mind. "After Peter confessed at Caesarea Philippi," he explains, Jesus started to see His death as just a necessary step toward the glory that awaited Him. In the conversation sparked by Salome’s request, Jesus’ death is already seen as a way to save many from death because His death clears the path for the Kingdom of God to arrive. At the Last Supper, Jesus views His upcoming death as the essential act that guarantees the blessings of the New Covenant—specifically, the forgiveness of sins and victory over sin—will be permanently assured to His ‘community.’ We see Jesus growing more comfortable with the idea of His death and continually deepening its significance.

Any one who is less skilled in reading the thoughts of Jesus, and more simple and natural in his reading of the text of Mark, cannot fail to observe that Jesus speaks in Mark x. 45 of His death as an expiation, not as a means of saving others from death, and that at the Lord's Supper there was no reference to His “community,” but only to the inexplicable “many,” which is also the word in Mark x. 45. We ought to admit freely that we do not know what the thoughts of Jesus about His death were at the time of the first prediction of the Passion after Peter's confession; and to be on our guard against the “original sin” of theology, that of exalting the argument from silence, when it happens to be useful, to the rank of positive realities.

Anyone who is less skilled at understanding Jesus's thoughts and more straightforward in reading the text of Mark can't help but notice that Jesus refers to His death in Mark 10:45 as an act of atonement, not as a way to save others from death. Additionally, during the Last Supper, there was no mention of His “community,” only the mysterious "lots," which is the same term used in Mark 10:45. We should openly acknowledge that we don't know what Jesus truly thought about His death when He first predicted His Passion after Peter's confession, and we need to be cautious of the “original sin” of theology, which is the tendency to elevate silence into definite truths when it serves a particular agenda.

Is there not a certain irony in the fact that the application of “natural” psychology to the explanation of the thoughts of Jesus compels the assumption of supra-historical private information [pg 299] such as this? Bahrdt and Venturini hardly read more subjective interpretations into the text than many modern Lives of Jesus; and the hypothesis of the secret society, which after all did recognise and do justice to the inexplicability from an external standpoint of the relation of events and of the conduct of Jesus, was in many respects more historical than the psychological links of connexion which our modernising historians discover without having any foundation for them in the text.

Isn't it a bit ironic that using "natural" psychology to explain Jesus's thoughts requires us to assume some kind of private, otherworldly insight? Bahrdt and Venturini don't add any more subjective interpretations to the text than many contemporary biographies of Jesus; and the idea of a secret society, which acknowledged and respected the mysterious nature of the events and Jesus's actions, was, in many ways, more grounded in history than the psychological connections that our modern historians find, even though those connections aren't really supported by the text. “organic” [pg 299]

In the end this supplementary knowledge destroys the historicity of the simplest sections. Oskar Holtzmann ventures to conjecture that the healing of the blind man at Jericho “is to be understood as a symbolical representation of the conversion of Zacchaeus,” which, of course, is found only in Luke. Here then the defender of the Marcan hypothesis rejects the incident by which the Evangelist explains the enthusiasm of the entry into Jerusalem, not to mention that Luke tells us nothing whatever about a conversion of Zacchaeus, but only that Jesus was invited to his house and graciously accepted the invitation.

In the end, this extra knowledge undermines the historical value of even the simplest parts. Oskar Holtzmann suggests that the healing of the blind man at Jericho "should be seen as a symbolic representation of Zacchaeus's transformation," which, of course, only appears in Luke. Here, the supporter of the Marcan hypothesis dismisses the event that the Evangelist uses to clarify the excitement of the entry into Jerusalem, not to mention that Luke doesn't say anything about Zacchaeus' conversion; he only tells us that Jesus was invited to his house and graciously accepted the invitation.

It would be something if this almost Alexandrian symbolical exegesis contributed in some way to the removal of difficulties and to the solution of the main question, that, namely, of the present or future Messiah, the present or future Kingdom. Oskar Holtzmann lays great stress upon the eschatological character of the preaching of Jesus regarding the Kingdom, and assumes that, at least at the beginning, it would not have been natural for His hearers to understand that Jesus, the herald of the Messiah, was Himself the Messiah. Nevertheless, he is of opinion that, in a certain sense, the presence of Jesus implied the presence of the Kingdom, that Peter and the rest of the disciples, advancing beyond the ideas of the multitude, recognised Him as Messiah, that this recognition ought to have been possible for the people also, and, in that case, would have been “the strongest incentive to abandon evil ways,” and “that Jesus at the time of His entry into Jerusalem seems to have felt that in Isa. lxii. 11228 there was a direct command not to withhold the knowledge of His Messiahship from the inhabitants of Jerusalem.”

It would be significant if this almost Alexandrian symbolic interpretation helped to resolve issues and addressed the key question of the current or future Messiah, the current or future Kingdom. Oskar Holtzmann emphasizes the eschatological nature of Jesus' preaching about the Kingdom and suggests that, at least initially, it wouldn’t have been natural for His listeners to realize that Jesus, the messenger of the Messiah, was Himself the Messiah. However, he believes that, in a way, Jesus’ presence signified the presence of the Kingdom, and that Peter and the other disciples, moving beyond the crowd's concepts, recognized Him as the Messiah. This recognition should have been possible for the people as well, and if so, would have been "the greatest motivation to give up bad habits," and "At the time Jesus entered Jerusalem, it seems He felt that Isaiah 62:11 __A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__ contained a direct command to not withhold the knowledge of His role as the Messiah from the people of Jerusalem."

But if Jesus made a Messianic entry He must thereafter have given Himself out as Messiah, and the whole controversy would necessarily have turned upon this claim. This, however, was not the case. According to Holtzmann, all that the hearers could make out of that crucial question for the Messiahship in Mark xii. 35-37 was only “that Jesus clearly showed from the Scriptures that the Messiah was not in reality the son of David.”229

But if Jesus made a Messianic entry, He must have subsequently claimed to be the Messiah, and the entire debate would have revolved around this assertion. However, that wasn’t the case. According to Holtzmann, all the listeners could gather from that key question regarding the Messiahship in Mark 12:35-37 was only "Jesus clearly showed through the Scriptures that the Messiah was not actually the son of David."229

[pg 300]

But how was it that the Messianic enthusiasm on the part of the people did not lead to a Messianic controversy, in spite of the fact that Jesus “from the first came forward in Jerusalem as Messiah”? This difficulty O. Holtzmann seems to be trying to provide against when he remarks in a footnote: “We have no evidence that Jesus, even during the last sojourn in Jerusalem, was recognised as Messiah except by those who belonged to the inner circle of disciples. The repetition by the children of the acclamations of the disciples (Matt. xxi. 15 and 16) can hardly be considered of much importance in this connexion.” According to this, Jesus entered Jerusalem as Messiah, but except for the disciples and a few children no one recognised His entry as having a Messianic significance! But Mark states that many spread their garments upon the way, and others plucked down branches from the trees and strewed them in the way, and that those that went before and those that followed after, cried “Hosanna!” The Marcan narrative must therefore be kept out of sight for the moment in order that the Life of Jesus as conceived by the modern Marcan hypothesis may not be endangered.

But how is it that the excitement about the Messiah from the people didn't lead to a debate about the Messiah, even though Jesus “from the beginning came forward in Jerusalem as the Messiah”? This issue seems to be what O. Holtzmann is addressing when he notes in a footnote: "We have no evidence that Jesus, even during his final time in Jerusalem, was recognized as the Messiah except by those in his close circle of disciples. The repeated cheers from the children, as noted in Matt. xxi. 15 and 16, can hardly be seen as significant in this context." According to this, Jesus entered Jerusalem as the Messiah, but aside from the disciples and a few children, no one recognized His entry as significant! Yet Mark states that many spread their garments on the road, and others cut branches from the trees and laid them on the road, while those who went ahead and those following shouted "Hosanna!" Therefore, the Marcan account must be set aside for now so that the Life of Jesus as understood by the modern Marcan hypothesis can remain intact.

We should not, however, regard the evidence of supernatural knowledge and the self-contradictions of this Life of Jesus as a matter for censure, but rather as a proof of the merits of O. Holtzmann's work.230 He has written the last large-scale Life of Jesus, the only one which the Marcan hypothesis has produced, and aims at providing a scientific basis for the assumptions which the general lines of that hypothesis compel him to make; and in [pg 301] this process it becomes clearly apparent that the connexion of events can only be carried through at the decisive passages by violent treatment, or even by rejection of the Marcan text in the interests of the Marcan hypothesis.

We shouldn't, however, see the evidence of supernatural knowledge and the contradictions in this Life of Jesus as something to criticize, but rather as evidence of the value of O. Holtzmann's work.230 He has written the most comprehensive Life of Jesus, the only one that the Marcan hypothesis has led to, and aims to provide a scientific foundation for the assumptions that the main points of that hypothesis require him to make; and in [pg 301] this process, it becomes clear that the connection of events can only be established at key points through forced interpretations or even by disregarding the Marcan text in favor of the Marcan hypothesis.

These merits do not belong in the same measure to the other modern Lives of Jesus, which follow more or less the same lines. They are short sketches, in some cases based on lectures, and their brevity makes them perhaps more lively and convincing than Holtzmann's work; but they take for granted just what he felt it necessary to prove. P. W. Schmidt's231 Geschichte Jesu (1899), which as a work of literary art has few rivals among theological works of recent years, confines itself to pure narrative. The volume of prolegomena which appeared in 1904, and is intended to exhibit the foundations of the narrative, treats of the sources, of the Kingdom of God, of the Son of Man, and of the Law. It makes the most of the weakening of the eschatological standpoint which is manifested in the second edition of Johannes Weiss's “Preaching of Jesus,” but it does not give sufficient prominence to the difficulties of reconstructing the public ministry of Jesus.

These benefits don’t really apply to the other modern biographies of Jesus, which generally follow similar patterns. They are brief sketches, often based on lectures, and their short length makes them possibly more engaging and persuasive than Holtzmann’s work; however, they assume what he felt he needed to demonstrate. P. W. Schmidt's231The Story of Jesus (1899), which stands out as a work of literary art among recent theological writings, focuses solely on storytelling. The volume of introductory material that came out in 1904, which aims to lay the groundwork for the narrative, discusses the sources, the Kingdom of God, the Son of Man, and the Law. It emphasizes the weakening of the eschatological perspective shown in the second edition of Johannes Weiss's “Teaching of Jesus,” but it doesn’t adequately highlight the challenges of reconstructing Jesus’s public ministry.

Neither Otto Schmiedel's “The Principal Problems of the Study of the Life of Jesus,” nor von Soden's “Vacation Lectures” on “The Principal Questions in the Life of Jesus” fulfils the promise of its title.232 They both aim rather at solving new problems proposed by themselves than at restating the old ones and adding new. They hope to meet the views of Johannes Weiss by strongly emphasising the eschatology, and think they can escape the critical scepticism of writers like Volkmar and Brand by assuming an “Ur-Markus.” Their view is, therefore, that with a few modifications dictated by the eschatological and sceptical school, the traditional conception of the Life of Jesus is still tenable, whereas it is just the a priori presuppositions of this conception, hitherto held to be self-evident, which constitute the main problems.

Neither Otto Schmiedel's “The Key Issues in Studying the Life of Jesus,” nor von Soden's "Vacation Talks" on “The Main Questions in the Life of Jesus” lives up to its title.232 They both focus more on addressing new issues they’ve proposed themselves rather than revisiting and expanding on the old ones. They aim to engage with Johannes Weiss's ideas by strongly highlighting eschatology, believing they can sidestep the critical skepticism of authors like Volkmar and Brand by positing an “Ur-Markus.” Their perspective, therefore, is that with a few adjustments influenced by the eschatological and skeptical schools, the traditional understanding of the Life of Jesus remains valid, whereas it's the a priori assumptions of this understanding that are actually the main problems.

[pg 302]

“It is self-evident,” says von Soden in one passage, “in view of the inner connexion in which the Kingdom of God and the Messiah stood in the thoughts of the people ... that in all classes the question must have been discussed, so that Jesus could not permanently have avoided their question, ‘What of the Messiah? Art thou not He?’ ” Where, in the Synoptics, is there a word to show that this is “self-evident”? When the disciples in Mark viii. tell Jesus “whom men held Him to be,” none of them suggests that any one had been tempted to regard Him as the Messiah. And that was shortly before Jesus set out for Jerusalem.

"Clearly," von Soden says in one part, “Considering the deep link between the Kingdom of God and the Messiah as the people understood it... everyone must have talked about the question, so Jesus couldn’t have dodged their inquiry, ‘What about the Messiah? Are you Him?’ Where, in the Synoptics, is there any mention that this is clear? When the disciples in Mark viii. tell Jesus “who people thought He was,” none of them implies that anyone had considered Him to be the Messiah. And that was just before Jesus headed to Jerusalem.

From the day when the envoys of the Scribes from Jerusalem first appeared in the north, the easily influenced Galilaean multitude began, according to von Soden, “to waver.” How does he know that the Galilaeans were easily influenced? How does he know they “wavered”? The Gospels tell us neither one nor the other. The demand for a sign was, to quote von Soden again, a demand for a proof of His Messiahship. “Yet another indication,” adds the author, “that later Christianity, in putting so high a value on the miracles of Jesus as a proof of His Messiahship, departed widely from the thoughts of Jesus.”

From the day the envoys of the Scribes from Jerusalem first showed up in the north, the easily swayed Galilean crowd began, according to von Soden, “to hesitate.” How does he know that the Galileans were easily swayed? How does he know they "hesitated"? The Gospels tell us neither one nor the other. The request for a sign was, to quote von Soden again, a request for proof of His Messiahship. “Another sign,” adds the author, "Later Christianity, by emphasizing the miracles of Jesus as proof of His role as the Messiah, moved away from Jesus' original beliefs."

Before levelling reproaches of this kind against later Christianity, it would be well to point to some passage of Mark or Matthew in which there is mention of a demand for a sign as a proof of His Messiahship.

Before criticizing later Christianity for this kind of thing, it would be wise to point to a passage in Mark or Matthew where there's a request for a sign as proof of His Messiahship.

When the appearance of Jesus in the south—we are still following von Soden—aroused the Messianic expectations of the people, as they had formerly been aroused in His native country, “they once more failed to understand the correction of them which Jesus had made by the manner of His entry and His conduct in Jerusalem.” They are unable to understand this “transvaluation of values,” and as often as the impression made by His personality suggested the thought that He was the Messiah, they became doubtful again. Wherein consisted the correction of the Messianic expectation given at the triumphal entry? Was it that He rode upon an ass? Would it not be better if modern historical theology, instead of always making the people “grow doubtful,” were to grow a little doubtful of itself, and begin to look for the evidence of that “transvaluation of values” which, according to them, the contemporaries of Jesus were not able to follow?

When Jesus showed up in the south—following von Soden again—it sparked the Messianic hopes of the people, just as it had in His hometown. "They once again failed to understand the correction that Jesus had provided through the way He entered and acted in Jerusalem." They couldn’t grasp this "value reassessment," and every time His presence suggested to them that He might be the Messiah, they started to doubt again. What was the correction of their Messianic expectations during the triumphal entry? Was it that He rode a donkey? Shouldn’t modern historical theology, instead of always making the people "start to doubt," start doubting itself a little and look for the evidence of that "value revaluation" that, according to them, the people of Jesus' time couldn’t comprehend?

Von Soden also possesses special information about the “peculiar history of the origin” of the Messianic consciousness of Jesus. He knows that it was subsidiary to a primary general religious consciousness of Sonship. The rise of this Messianic consciousness implies, in its turn, the “transformation of the conception of the Kingdom of God, and explains how in the mind of Jesus this conception was both present and future.” The greatness [pg 303] of Jesus is, he thinks, to be found in the fact that for Him this Kingdom of God was only a “limiting conception”—the ultimate goal of a gradual process of approximation. “To the question whether it was to be realised here or in the beyond Jesus would have answered, as He answered a similar question, ‘That, no man knoweth; no, not the Son.’ ”

Von Soden also has unique insights into the “uncommon origin story” of Jesus' Messianic awareness. He understands that this awareness was secondary to a broader religious understanding of Sonship. The emergence of this Messianic consciousness indicates, in turn, the "the transformation of the concept of the Kingdom of God, and clarifies how this idea was understood by Jesus as both present and future." He believes that the greatness [pg 303] of Jesus lies in the fact that for Him, the Kingdom of God was merely a "restrictive idea"—the ultimate aim of a gradual process of getting closer. “To the question of whether it would happen here or in the afterlife, Jesus would have answered, as He did to a similar question, ‘That, no one knows; not even the Son.’

As if He had not answered that question in the petition “Thy Kingdom come”—supposing that such a question could ever have occurred to a contemporary—in the sense that the Kingdom was to pass from the beyond into the present!

As if He hadn't answered that question in the request "Your Kingdom come"—assuming that anyone at the time would even think to ask it—in the way that the Kingdom would come from the beyond into the here and now!

This modern historical theology will not allow Jesus to have formed a “theory” to explain His thoughts about His passion. “For Him the certainty was amply sufficient; ‘My death will effect what My life has not been able to accomplish.’ ”

This modern historical theology does not permit Jesus to have developed a theory to clarify His views on His passion. “For Him, the certainty was more than enough; ‘My death will accomplish what My life has not been able to achieve.’ ”

Is there then no theory implied in the saying about the “ransom for many,” and in that about “My blood which is shed for many for the forgiveness of sins,” although Jesus does not explain it? How does von Soden know what was “amply sufficient” for Jesus or what was not?

Is there really no theory implied in the phrase about the “ransom for many,” and in the one about "My blood, which is poured out for many for the forgiveness of sins," even though Jesus doesn't clarify it? How does von Soden know what was “plenty sufficient” for Jesus or what wasn't?

Otto Schmiedel goes so far as to deny that Jesus gave distinct expression to an expectation of suffering; the most He can have done—and this is only a “perhaps”—is to have hinted at it in His discourses.

Otto Schmiedel goes so far as to deny that Jesus clearly expressed an expectation of suffering; the most He could have done—and this is only a “maybe”—is to have alluded to it in His teachings.

In strong contrast with this confidence in committing themselves to historical conjectures stands the scepticism with which von Soden and Schmiedel approach the Gospels. “It is at once evident,” says Schmiedel, “that the great groups of discourses in Matthew, such as the Sermon on the Mount, the Seven Parables of the Kingdom, and so forth, were not arranged in this order in the source (the Logia), still less by Jesus Himself. The order is, doubtless, due to the Evangelist. But what is the answer to the question, ‘On what grounds is this “at once” clear?’ ”233

In sharp contrast to this confidence in committing to historical guesses is the skepticism that von Soden and Schmiedel have towards the Gospels. “It’s clear right away,” says Schmiedel, "the main groups of teachings in Matthew, like the Sermon on the Mount, the Seven Parables of the Kingdom, and others, weren't organized this way in the source (the Logia), let alone by Jesus Himself. The order was definitely set by the Evangelist. But what’s the answer to the question, ‘On what basis is this “immediately” clear?’?"233

Von Soden's pronouncement is even more radical. “In the composition of the discourses,” he says, “no regard is paid in Matthew, any more than in John, to the supposed audience, or to the point of time in the life of Jesus to which they are attributed.” As early as the Sermon on the Mount we find references to persecutions, and warnings against false prophets. Similarly, in the charge to the Twelve, there are also warnings, which undoubtedly [pg 304] belong to a later time. Intimate sayings, evidently intended for the inner circle of disciples, have the widest publicity given to them.

Von Soden's pronouncement is even more radical. "In creating the discussions," he says, "Matthew, like John, doesn't consider the supposed audience or the specific time in Jesus' life that these are attributed to." As early as the Sermon on the Mount, we encounter references to persecutions and warnings about false prophets. Similarly, in the charge to the Twelve, there are warnings that undoubtedly [pg 304] belong to a later time. Intimate sayings, clearly meant for the inner circle of disciples, are given the widest publicity.

But why should whatever is incomprehensible to us be unhistorical? Would it not be better simply to admit that we do not understand certain connexions of ideas and turns of expression in the discourses of Jesus?

But why should anything we don't understand be seen as unhistorical? Wouldn't it be better to just admit that there are certain connections of ideas and ways of expressing things in Jesus's teachings that we don't get?

But instead even of making an analytical examination of the apparent connexions, and stating them as problems, the discourses of Jesus and the sections of the Gospels are tricked out with ingenious headings which have nothing to do with them. Thus, for instance, von Soden heads the Beatitudes (Matt. v. 3-12), “What Jesus brings to men,” the following verses (Matt. v. 13-16), “What He makes of men.” P. W. Schmidt, in his “History of Jesus,” shows himself a past master in this art. “The rights of the wife” is the title of the dialogue about divorce, as if the question at stake had been for Jesus the equality of the sexes, and not simply and solely the sanctity of marriage. “Sunshine for the children” is his heading for the scene where Jesus takes the children in His arms—as if the purpose of Jesus had been to protest against severity in the upbringing of children. Again, he brings together the stories of the man who must first bury his father, of the rich young man, of the dispute about precedence, of Zacchaeus, and others which have equally little connexion under the heading “Discipline for Jesus' followers.” These often brilliant creations of artificial connexions of thought give a curious attractiveness to the works of Schmidt and von Soden. The latter's survey of the Gospels is a really delightful performance. But this kind of thing is not consistent with pure objective history.

But instead of doing an analytical examination of the apparent connections and stating them as problems, the discourses of Jesus and the sections of the Gospels are dressed up with clever headings that have nothing to do with the content. For example, von Soden titles the Beatitudes (Matt. v. 3-12), “What Jesus offers to people,” and the following verses (Matt. v. 13-16), “How He shapes people.” P. W. Schmidt, in his “History of Jesus,” is especially skilled in this approach. He titles the dialogue about divorce "Women's rights," as if the issue for Jesus was gender equality rather than the sanctity of marriage. He calls the scene where Jesus embraces children “Sunshine for the kids,” suggesting that Jesus aimed to protest against strict parenting. He also combines stories like the man who wanted to bury his father, the rich young man, a discussion about precedence, Zacchaeus, and others with little connection under the title "Discipline for Jesus’ followers." These often brilliant, artificial connections of thought add a curious appeal to the works of Schmidt and von Soden. The latter's overview of the Gospels is genuinely enjoyable. However, this kind of presentation doesn’t align with pure objective history.

Disposing in this lofty fashion of the connexion of events, Schmiedel and von Soden do not find it difficult to distinguish between Mark and “Ur-Markus”; that is, to retain just so much of the Gospel as will fit in to their construction. Schmiedel feels sure that Mark was a skilful writer, and that the redactor was “a Christian of Pauline sympathies.” According to “Ur-Markus,” to which Mark iv. 33 belongs, the Lord speaks in parables in order that the people may understand Him the better; “it was only by the redactor that the Pauline theory about hardening their hearts (Rom. ix.-xi.) was interpolated, in Mark iv. 10 ff., and the meaning of Mark iv. 33 was thus obscured.”

Disposing of the connections between events in this elevated manner, Schmiedel and von Soden find it easy to differentiate between Mark and "Original Markus"; that is, to keep only as much of the Gospel as fits their interpretation. Schmiedel is convinced that Mark was a skilled writer and that the editor was “a Christian with Pauline beliefs.” According to "Original Markus," which includes Mark iv. 33, the Lord speaks in parables so that the people can better understand Him; "The Pauline theory about hardening their hearts (Rom. ix.-xi.) was added to Mark iv. 10 ff. only through the editor, which made the meaning of Mark iv. 33 less clear."

It is high time that instead of merely asserting Pauline influences in Mark some proof of the assertion should be given. What kind of appearance would Mark have presented if it had really passed through the hands of a Pauline Christian?

It’s about time that instead of just claiming that there are Pauline influences in Mark, some actual evidence of that claim should be provided. What kind of form would Mark have taken if it truly had been edited by a Pauline Christian?

Von Soden's analysis is no less confident. The three outstanding miracles, the stilling of the storm, the casting out of the legion of devils, the overcoming of death (Mark iv. 35-v. 43), the [pg 305] romantically told story of the death of the Baptist (Mark vi. 17-29), the story of the feeding of the multitudes in the desert, of Jesus' walking on the water, and of the transfiguration upon an high mountain, and the healing of the lunatic boy—all these are dashed in with a broad brush, and offer many analogies to Old Testament stories, and some suggestions of Pauline conceptions, and reflections of experiences of individual believers and of the Christian community. “All these passages were, doubtless, first written down by the compiler of our Gospel.”

Von Soden's analysis is just as assured. The three major miracles—the calming of the storm, the expulsion of the legion of demons, and conquering death (Mark iv. 35-v. 43), the dramatically told account of the Baptist's death (Mark vi. 17-29), the story of feeding the multitudes in the desert, Jesus walking on water, the transfiguration on a high mountain, and the healing of the boy with seizures—are all painted broadly and provide many parallels to Old Testament tales, some hints of Pauline ideas, and reflections of the experiences of individual believers and the Christian community. "All these passages were definitely first recorded by the person who put together our Gospel."

But how can Schmiedel and von Soden fail to see that they are heading straight for Bruno Bauer's position? They assert that there is no distinction of principle between the way in which the Johannine and the Synoptic discourses are composed: the recognition of this was Bruno Bauer's starting-point. They propose to find experiences of the Christian community and Pauline teaching reflected in the Gospel of Mark; Bruno Bauer asserted the same. The only difference is that he was consistent, and extended his criticism to those portions of the Gospel which do not present the stumbling-block of the supernatural. Why should these not also contain the theology and the experiences of the community transformed into history? Is it only because they remain within the limits of the natural?

But how can Schmiedel and von Soden not see that they are heading straight for Bruno Bauer's viewpoint? They claim there’s no fundamental difference between how the Johannine and the Synoptic discourses are structured: recognizing this was Bruno Bauer's starting point. They aim to find reflections of the Christian community's experiences and Pauline teachings in the Gospel of Mark; Bruno Bauer made the same assertion. The only difference is that he was consistent and expanded his criticism to include parts of the Gospel that don't present the challenge of the supernatural. Why shouldn't these portions also reflect the theology and experiences of the community turned into history? Is it just because they stay within the realm of the natural?

The real difficulty consists in the fact that all the passages which von Soden ascribes to the redactor stand, in spite of their mythical colouring, in a closely-knit historical connexion; in fact, the historical connexion is nowhere so close. How can any one cut out the feeding of the multitudes and the transfiguration as narratives of secondary origin without destroying the whole of the historical fabric of the Gospel of Mark? Or was it the redactor who created the plan of the Gospel of Mark, as von Soden seems to imply?234

The real difficulty lies in the fact that all the parts von Soden attributes to the redactor are, despite their mythical elements, tightly connected to the historical narrative; in fact, the historical connection is nowhere stronger. How can anyone remove the feeding of the multitudes and the transfiguration as stories of secondary origin without ruining the entire historical structure of the Gospel of Mark? Or did the redactor actually create the overall plan of the Gospel of Mark, as von Soden seems to suggest?234

[pg 306]

But in that case how can a modern Life of Jesus be founded on the Marcan plan? How much of Mark is, in the end, historical? Why should not Peter's confession at Caesarea Philippi have been derived from the theology of the primitive Church, just as well as the transfiguration? The only difference is that the incident at Caesarea Philippi is more within the limits of the possible, whereas the scene upon the mountain has a supernatural colouring. But is the incident at Philippi so entirely natural? Whence does Peter know that Jesus is the Messiah?

But in that case, how can a modern Life of Jesus be based on the Markan outline? How much of Mark is actually historical? Why couldn't Peter's confession at Caesarea Philippi come from the beliefs of the early Church, just like the transfiguration? The only difference is that the event at Caesarea Philippi seems more plausible, while the scene on the mountain has a supernatural aspect. But is the event at Philippi completely ordinary? How does Peter know that Jesus is the Messiah?

This semi-scepticism is therefore quite unjustifiable, since in Mark natural and supernatural both stand in an equally good and close historical connexion. Either, then, one must be completely sceptical like Bruno Bauer, and challenge without exception all the facts and connexions of events asserted by Mark; or, if one means to found an historical Life of Jesus upon Mark, one must take the Gospel as a whole because of the plan which runs right through it, accepting it as historical and then endeavouring to explain why certain narratives, like the feeding of the multitude and the transfiguration, are bathed in a supernatural light, and what is the historical basis which underlies them. A division between the natural and supernatural in Mark is purely arbitrary, because the supernatural is an essential part of the history. The mere fact that he has not adopted the mythical material of the childhood stories and the post-resurrection scenes ought to have been accepted as evidence that the supernatural material which he does embody belongs to a category of its own and cannot be simply rejected as due to the invention of the primitive Christian community. It must belong in some way to the original tradition.

This semi-skepticism is completely unjustifiable because in Mark, the natural and supernatural are both closely connected in a historical context. So, one must either be entirely skeptical like Bruno Bauer and challenge every fact and connection of events presented by Mark, or if one intends to create a historical account of Jesus based on Mark, one must view the Gospel as a whole due to the overarching narrative, accepting it as historical and then trying to explain why certain stories, like the feeding of the multitude and the transfiguration, are described in a supernatural way, and what the historical foundation for them is. Dividing the natural and supernatural in Mark is completely arbitrary since the supernatural is a crucial part of the history. The simple fact that he hasn't included the mythical elements of the childhood stories and the post-resurrection accounts should indicate that the supernatural elements he does include belong to a unique category and cannot be dismissed as merely the invention of the early Christian community. They must in some way be rooted in the original tradition.

Oskar Holtzmann realises that to a certain extent. According to him Mark is a writer “who embodied the materials which he received from the tradition more faithfully than discriminatingly.” “That which was related as a symbol of inner events, he takes as history—in the case, for example, of the temptation, the walking on the sea, the transfiguration of Jesus.” “Again in other cases he has made a remarkable occurrence into a supernatural miracle, [pg 307] as in the case of the feeding of the multitude, where Jesus' courageous love and ready organising skill overcame a momentary difficulty, whereas the Evangelist represents it as an amazing miracle of Divine omnipotence.”

Oskar Holtzmann realizes that to some extent. He believes Mark is a writer "who represented the materials he received from tradition more honestly than with criticism." "He sees what was portrayed as a symbol of internal events as history—like the temptation, walking on water, and the transfiguration of Jesus." “In other instances, he has transformed a major event into a supernatural miracle, [pg 307] such as with the feeding of the multitude, where Jesus' brave love and fast organizational skills addressed a temporary problem, while the Evangelist depicts it as an extraordinary miracle of Divine power.”

Oskar Holtzmann is thus more cautious than von Soden. He is inclined to see in the material which he wishes to exclude from the history, not so much inventions of the Church as mistaken shaping of history by Mark, and in this way he gets back to genuine old-fashioned rationalism. In the feeding of the multitude Jesus showed “the confidence of a courageous housewife who knows how to provide skilfully for a great crowd of children from small resources.” Perhaps in a future work Oskar Holtzmann will be less reserved, not for the sake of theology, but of national well-being, and will inform his contemporaries what kind of domestic economy it was which made it possible for the Lord to satisfy with five loaves and two fishes several thousand hungry men.

Oskar Holtzmann is more cautious than von Soden. He tends to view the material he wants to exclude from history not as inventions of the Church, but as misinterpretations of history by Mark, thus returning to a more traditional rationalism. In the feeding of the multitude, Jesus demonstrated "the confidence of a brave housewife who knows how to skillfully care for a big group of kids with limited resources." Perhaps in a future work, Oskar Holtzmann will be less reserved, not for the sake of theology, but for the well-being of the nation, and will enlighten his contemporaries about the kind of domestic economy that allowed the Lord to feed several thousand hungry men with just five loaves and two fishes.

Modern historical theology, therefore, with its three-quarters scepticism, is left at last with only a torn and tattered Gospel of Mark in its hands. One would naturally suppose that these preliminary operations upon the source would lead to the production of a Life of Jesus of a similarly fragmentary character. Nothing of the kind. The outline is still the same as in Schenkel's day, and the confidence with which the construction is carried out is not less complete. Only the catch-words with which the narrative is enlivened have been changed, being now taken in part from Nietzsche. The liberal Jesus has given place to the Germanic Jesus. This is a figure which has as little to do with the Marcan hypothesis as the “liberal” Jesus had which preceded it; otherwise it could not so easily have survived the downfall of the Gospel of Mark as an historical source. It is evident, therefore, that this professedly historical Jesus is not a purely historical figure, but one which has been artificially transplanted into history. As formerly in Renan the romantic spirit created the personality of Jesus in its own image, so at the present day the Germanic spirit is making a Jesus after its own likeness. What is admitted as historic is just what the Spirit of the time can take out of the records in order to assimilate it to itself and bring out of it a living form.

Modern historical theology, therefore, with its three-quarters skepticism, is left with only a torn and tattered Gospel of Mark in its hands. One would naturally think that these initial efforts on the source would result in a Life of Jesus that is similarly fragmented. Yet, nothing of the sort happens. The outline remains the same as in Schenkel's time, and the confidence with which the construction is executed is just as strong. Only the phrases that make the narrative lively have changed, now partially drawn from Nietzsche. The liberal Jesus has been replaced by the Germanic Jesus. This new figure has as little in common with the Marcan hypothesis as the “liberal” Jesus that came before it; otherwise, it could not have so easily survived the decline of the Gospel of Mark as a historical source. It’s clear, then, that this so-called historical Jesus is not a purely historical figure but one that has been artificially inserted into history. Just as Renan’s romantic spirit fashioned the personality of Jesus in its own image, today the Germanic spirit is creating a Jesus in its own likeness. What is accepted as historical is merely what the Spirit of the time can extract from the records to make it fit and bring forth a living form.

Frenssen betrays the secret of his teachers when in Hilligenlei he confidently superscribes the narrative drawn from the “latest critical investigations” with the title “The Life of the Saviour portrayed according to German research as the basis for a spiritual re-birth of the German nation.”235

Frenssen reveals the secret of his instructors when in Hilligenlei he confidently titles the narrative based on the “latest critical research” as “The life of the Savior depicted based on German research as the basis for a spiritual revival of the German nation.”235

[pg 308]

As a matter of fact the Life of Jesus of the “Manuscript”236 is unsatisfactory both scientifically and artistically, just because it aims at being at once scientific and artistic. If only Frenssen, with his strongly life-accepting instinct, which gives to his thinking, at least in his earliest writings where he reveals himself without artificiality, such a wonderful simplicity and force, had dared to read his Jesus boldly from the original records, without following modern historical theology in all its meanderings! He would have been able to force his way through the underwood well enough if only he had been content to break the branches that got in his way, instead of always waiting until some one went in front to disentwine them for him. The dependence to which he surrenders himself is really distressing. In reading almost every paragraph one can tell whether Kai Jans was looking, as he wrote it, into Oskar Holtzmann or P. W. Schmidt or von Soden. Frenssen resigns the dramatic scene of the healing of the blind man at Jericho. Why? Because at this point he was listening to Holtzmann, who proposes to regard the healing of the blind man as only a symbolical representation of the “conversion of Zacchaeus.” Frenssen's masters have robbed him of all creative spontaneity. He does not permit himself to discover motifs for himself, but confines himself to working over and treating in cruder colours those which he finds in his teachers.

In fact, the Life of Jesus in the “Draft”236 is lacking both scientifically and artistically because it tries to be both at the same time. If only Frenssen, with his strong instinct for embracing life, which gives his early writings a wonderful simplicity and strength as he reveals himself honestly, had the courage to interpret his Jesus directly from the original records, without getting lost in the twists of modern historical theology! He could have navigated through the complexities easily if he had just been willing to clear the branches blocking his path, instead of always waiting for someone else to clear them for him. His dependency is truly troubling. In almost every paragraph, you can tell whether Kai Jans was influenced by Oskar Holtzmann, P. W. Schmidt, or von Soden as he wrote. Frenssen avoids the dramatic scene of the healing of the blind man at Jericho. Why? Because at this moment, he was listening to Holtzmann, who suggests viewing the healing as merely a symbol of the "Zacchaeus's conversion." Frenssen's influences have stripped him of all creative spontaneity. He doesn’t allow himself to discover motifs on his own but limits himself to reworking and interpreting in a rougher style those he finds in his teachers.

And since he cannot veil his assumptions in the cautious, carefully modulated language of the theologians, the faults of the modern treatment of the life of Jesus appear in him exaggerated an hundredfold. The violent dislocation of narratives from their connexion, and the forcing upon them of a modern interpretation, becomes a mania with the writer and a torture to the reader. The range of knowledge not drawn from the text is infinitely increased. Kai Jans sees Jesus after the temptation cowering beneath the brow of the hill “a poor lonely man, torn by fearful doubts, a man in the deepest distress.” He knows too that there was often great danger that Jesus would “betray the 'Father in heaven' and go back to His village to take up His handicraft again, but now as a man with a torn and distracted soul and a conscience tortured by the gnawings of remorse.”

And since he can't hide his assumptions in the careful, measured language of theologians, the flaws in the modern approach to the life of Jesus seem to him magnified a hundredfold. The disruptive shifting of narratives from their context and the imposition of a modern interpretation become an obsession for the writer and a punishment for the reader. The scope of knowledge not based on the text expands infinitely. Kai Jans depicts Jesus after the temptation as cowering beneath the brow of the hill, "A poor, lonely man, troubled by his fears and doubts, a man in the deepest distress." He is also aware of the frequent danger that Jesus might “betray the 'Father in heaven' and return to His village to resume His craft, but now as a man with a fractured and conflicted soul and a conscience tormented by the pangs of regret.”

The pupil is not content, as his teachers had been, merely to make the people sometimes believe in Jesus and sometimes doubt [pg 309] Him; he makes the enthusiastic earthly Messianic belief of the people “tug and tear” at Jesus Himself. Sometimes one is tempted to ask whether the author in his zeal “to use conscientiously the results of the whole range of scientific criticism” has not forgotten the main thing, the study of the Gospels themselves.

The student isn’t satisfied, like his teachers were, with just getting people to believe in Jesus sometimes and doubt Him at other times; he makes the excited, earthly Messianic belief of the people "tug and tear" at Jesus Himself. Sometimes it makes you wonder if the author, in his eagerness “to carefully use the results of all forms of scientific critique”, has forgotten the most important thing: studying the Gospels themselves.

And is all this science supposed to be new?237 Is this picture of Jesus really the outcome of the latest criticism? Has it not been in existence since the beginning of the 'forties, since Weisse's criticism of the Gospel history? Is it not in principle the same as Renan's, only that Germanic lapses of taste here take the place of Gallic, and “German art for German people,”238 here quite out of place, has done its best to remove from the picture every trace of fidelity?

And is all this science supposed to be new?237 Is this picture of Jesus really the result of the latest criticism? Hasn't it been around since the early '40s, since Weisse's critique of the Gospel history? Isn't it basically the same as Renan's, only with German stylistic shortcomings replacing the French ones, and “German art for Germans,”238 which feels completely out of place here, has done its best to strip the image of any sign of accuracy?

Kai Jans' “Manuscript” represents the limit of the process of diminishing the personality of Jesus. Weisse left Him still some greatness, something unexplained, and did not venture to apply to everything the petty standards of inquisitive modern psychology. In the 'sixties psychology became more confident and Jesus smaller; at the close of the century the confidence of psychology is at its greatest and the figure of Jesus at its smallest—so small, that Frenssen ventures to let His life be projected and written by one who is in the midst of a love affair!

Kai Jans' "Draft" shows the extent to which the personal identity of Jesus has been diminished. Weisse still allowed Him some level of greatness and mystery, avoiding the application of trivial standards from modern psychology to everything. In the 1960s, psychology grew bolder and Jesus' significance shrank; by the end of the century, psychology's confidence reached its peak while Jesus' figure became negligible—so much so that Frenssen dares to have His life interpreted and narrated by someone in the midst of a romance!

This human life of Jesus is to be “heart-stirring” from beginning to end, and “in no respect to go beyond human standards”! And this Jesus who “racks His brains and shapes His plans” is to contribute to bring about a re-birth of the German people. How could He? He is Himself only a phantom created by the Germanic mind in pursuit of a religious will-o'-the-wisp.

This human life of Jesus is meant to be “heartfelt” from start to finish and "never to go beyond human standards"! And this Jesus who “worries about His thoughts and makes His plans” is meant to help bring about a rebirth of the German people. How could He? He is merely a figment of the Germanic imagination chasing after a religious illusion.

It is possible, however, to do injustice to Frenssen's presentation, and to the whole of the confident, unconsciously modernising criticism of which he here acts as the mouthpiece. These writers have the great merit of having brought certain cultured circles nearer to Jesus and made them more sympathetic towards Him. Their fault lies in their confidence, which has blinded them to what Jesus is and is not, what He can and cannot do, so that in the end they fail to understand “the signs of the times” either as historians or as men of the present.

It's possible, though, to overlook the significance of Frenssen's presentation and the confident, subtly modernizing criticism he represents. These authors have done a great job of bringing certain educated circles closer to Jesus and helping them become more sympathetic towards Him. Their mistake is in their overconfidence, which has blinded them to who Jesus is and isn't, and what He can and cannot do, so ultimately they miss understanding "the signs of the times" both as historians and as people of today.

[pg 310]

If the Jesus who owes His birth to the Marcan hypothesis and modern psychology were capable of regenerating the world He would have done it long ago, for He is nearly sixty years old and his latest portraits are much less life-like than those drawn by Weisse, Schenkel, and Renan, or by Keim, the most brilliant painter of them all.

If the Jesus who comes from the Marcan hypothesis and modern psychology could transform the world, He would have done it by now, since He is almost sixty years old, and His latest images are far less realistic than those created by Weisse, Schenkel, Renan, or Keim, who is the most talented artist among them.

For the last ten years modern historical theology has more and more adapted itself to the needs of the man in the street. More and more, even in the best class of works, it makes use of attractive head-lines as a means of presenting its results in a lively form to the masses. Intoxicated with its own ingenuity in inventing these, it becomes more and more confident in its cause, and has come to believe that the world's salvation depends in no small measure upon the spreading of its own “assured results” broad-cast among the people. It is time that it should begin to doubt itself, to doubt its “historical” Jesus, to doubt the confidence with which it has looked to its own construction for the moral and religious regeneration of our time. Its Jesus is not alive, however Germanic they may make Him.

For the last ten years, modern historical theology has increasingly tailored itself to the needs of everyday people. Even in the top-tier works, it uses catchy headlines to present its findings in an engaging way for the masses. Feeling smug about its creativity in coming up with these, it grows more and more confident in its mission and has come to believe that the salvation of the world relies significantly on sharing its own "guaranteed results" widely among the public. It's time for it to start questioning itself, to question its “historical” Jesus, and to doubt the faith it has placed in its own interpretations for the moral and religious renewal of our time. Its Jesus isn't alive, no matter how much they may try to portray Him as such.

It was no accident that the chief priest of “German art for German people” found himself at one with the modern theologians and offered them his alliance. Since the 'sixties the critical study of the Life of Jesus in Germany has been unconsciously under the influence of an imposing modern-religious nationalism in art. It has been deflected by it as by an underground magnetic current. It was in vain that a few purely historical investigators uplifted their voices in protest. The process had to work itself out. For historical criticism had become, in the hands of most of those who practised it, a secret struggle to reconcile the Germanic religious spirit with the Spirit of Jesus of Nazareth.239 It was concerned for the religious interests of the present. Therefore its error had a kind of greatness, it was in fact the greatest thing about it; and the severity with which the pure historian treats it is in proportion to his respect for its spirit. For this German critical study of the Life of Jesus is an essential part of German religion. As of old Jacob wrestled with the angel, so German theology wrestles with Jesus of Nazareth and will not let Him go until He bless it—that is, until He will consent to serve it and will suffer Himself to be drawn by the Germanic spirit into the midst of our time and our civilisation. But when the day breaks, the wrestler must let Him go. He will not cross the ford with us. Jesus of Nazareth will not suffer Himself to be modernised. As an historic figure He refuses to be detached from His own time. He has no answer [pg 311] for the question, “Tell us Thy name in our speech and for our day!” But He does bless those who have wrestled with Him, so that, though they cannot take Him with them, yet, like men who have seen God face to face and received strength in their souls, they go on their way with renewed courage, ready to do battle with the world and its powers.

It was no coincidence that the chief priest of "German art for Germans" found himself aligning with modern theologians and offered them his support. Since the '60s, the critical examination of the Life of Jesus in Germany has been subtly influenced by a powerful modern-religious nationalism in art. It has been swayed by it like a hidden magnetic pull. A few strictly historical researchers raised their voices in protest, but it was in vain. The process had to unfold naturally. Historical criticism had turned, for most of those practicing it, into a secret struggle to align the Germanic religious spirit with the Spirit of Jesus of Nazareth. It was focused on the religious needs of the present. Consequently, its error had a certain grandness; in fact, that was its greatest aspect. The harshness with which pure historians approach it corresponds to their respect for its essence. This German critical study of the Life of Jesus is a vital part of German religion. Just as Jacob once wrestled with the angel, German theology grapples with Jesus of Nazareth and will not let Him go until He blesses it—that is, until He agrees to serve it and allows Himself to be brought by the Germanic spirit into our time and civilization. But when dawn breaks, the wrestler must release Him. He will not cross the river with us. Jesus of Nazareth refuses to be modernized. As a historical figure, He will not be separated from His own era. He has no response [pg 311] to the question, "Share your name in our language and for our time!" However, He does bless those who have struggled with Him, so that, although they cannot take Him with them, like people who have encountered God face to face and gained strength in their souls, they continue on their path with renewed courage, prepared to confront the world and its forces.

But the historic Jesus and the Germanic spirit cannot be brought together except by an act of historic violence which in the end injures both religion and history. A time will come when our theology, with its pride in its historical character, will get rid of its rationalistic bias. This bias leads it to project back into history what belongs to our own time, the eager struggle of the modern religious spirit with the Spirit of Jesus, and seek in history justification and authority for its beginning. The consequence is that it creates the historical Jesus in its own image, so that it is not the modern spirit influenced by the Spirit of Jesus, but the Jesus of Nazareth constructed by modern historical theology, that is set to work upon our race.

But the historical Jesus and the Germanic spirit can't really be combined without a violent act of history that ultimately harms both religion and history. A time will come when our theology, which takes pride in its historical roots, will shed its rationalistic bias. This bias makes it project our contemporary struggles between modern spirituality and the Spirit of Jesus back into history, looking for validation and authority for its origins. As a result, it creates the historical Jesus in its own likeness, so that it’s not the modern spirit shaped by the Spirit of Jesus, but rather the Jesus of Nazareth crafted by modern historical theology that influences our society.

Therefore both the theology and its picture of Jesus are poor and weak. Its Jesus, because He has been measured by the petty standard of the modern man, at variance with himself, not to say of the modern candidate in theology who has made shipwreck; the theologians themselves, because instead of seeking, for themselves and others, how they may best bring the Spirit of Jesus in living power into our world, they keep continually forging new portraits of the historical Jesus, and think they have accomplished something great when they have drawn an Oh! of astonishment from the multitude, such as the crowds of a great city emit on catching sight of a new advertisement in coloured lights.

So both the theology and its image of Jesus are lacking and weak. This image of Jesus has been judged by the shallow standards of modern individuals, which is inconsistent with who He truly is, not to mention the modern theologians who have lost their way; the theologians themselves, instead of exploring how to genuinely bring the Spirit of Jesus into our world with real power for themselves and others, keep trying to create new portrayals of the historical Jesus. They believe they've achieved something significant when they evoke a gasp of surprise from the masses, similar to the reaction of a big city's crowds when they see a flashy new advertisement.

Anyone who, admiring the force and authority of genuine rationalism, has got rid of the naïve self-satisfaction of modern theology, which is in essence only the degenerate offspring of rationalism with a tincture of history, rejoices in the feebleness and smallness of its professedly historical Jesus, rejoices in all those who are beginning to doubt the truth of this portrait, rejoices in the over-severity with which it is attacked, rejoices to take a share in its destruction.

Anyone who, appreciating the strength and authority of true rationalism, has moved past the naive self-satisfaction of modern theology—essentially just the weakened product of rationalism mixed with a bit of history—celebrates the weaknesses and insignificance of its so-called historical Jesus. They find joy in those starting to question the accuracy of this depiction, in the harsh criticism it receives, and in participating in its downfall.

Those who have begun to doubt are many, but most of them only make known their doubts by their silence. There is one, however, who has spoken out, and one of the greatest—Otto Pfleiderer.240

Those who have started to doubt are numerous, but most of them only show their uncertainty through their silence. However, there is one person who has spoken up, and he is one of the greatest—Otto Pfleiderer.240

In the first edition of his Urchristentum, published in 1887, he still shared the current conceptions and constructions, except that he held the credibility of Mark to be more affected than was [pg 312] usually supposed by hypothetical Pauline influences. In the second edition241 his positive knowledge has been ground down in the struggle with the sceptics—it is Brandt who has especially affected him—and with the partisans of eschatology. This is the first advance-guard action of modern theology coming into touch with the troops of Reimarus and Bruno Bauer.

In the first edition of his Early Christianity, published in 1887, he still shared the current ideas and theories, except he believed that Mark's reliability was more influenced by hypothetical Pauline factors than was usually thought. In the second edition241 his solid knowledge has been challenged in the battle against skeptics—it is especially Brandt who has impacted him—and with supporters of eschatology. This marks the first advance of modern theology engaging with the ideas of Reimarus and Bruno Bauer.

Pfleiderer accepts the purely eschatological conception of the Kingdom of God and holds also that the ethics of Jesus were wholly conditioned by eschatology. But in regard to the question of the Messiahship of Jesus he takes his stand with the sceptics. He rejects the hypothesis of a Messiah who, as being a “spiritual Messiah,” conceals His claim, but on the other hand, he cannot accept the eschatological Son-of-Man Messiahship having reference to the future, which the eschatological school finds in the utterances of Jesus, since it implies prophecies of His suffering, death, and resurrection which criticism cannot admit. “Instead of finding the explanation of how the Messianic title arose in the reflections of Jesus about the death which lay before Him,” he is inclined to find it “rather in the reflection of the Christian community upon the catastrophic death and exaltation of its Lord after this had actually taken place.”

Pfleiderer accepts the purely eschatological view of the Kingdom of God and believes that Jesus' ethics were entirely shaped by eschatology. However, regarding the question of whether Jesus is the Messiah, he aligns himself with the skeptics. He dismisses the idea of a "spiritual Messiah" who hides His claim, but he also cannot endorse the eschatological Son-of-Man Messiahship related to the future, which the eschatological school finds in Jesus' statements. This is because it suggests prophecies of His suffering, death, and resurrection, which criticism cannot support. "Instead of finding the explanation of how the Messianic title arose in the reflections of Jesus about the death that lay ahead," he tends to see it "more as the reflection of the Christian community on the catastrophic death and exaltation of its Lord after it actually happened."

Even the Marcan narrative is not history. The scepticism in regard to the main source, with which writers like Oskar Holtzmann, Schmiedel, and von Soden conduct a kind of intellectual flirtation, is here erected into a principle. “It must be recognised,” says Pfleiderer, “that in respect of the recasting of the history under theological influences, the whole of our Gospels stand in principle on the same footing. The distinction between Mark, the other two Synoptists, and John is only relative—a distinction of degree corresponding to different stages of theological reflection and the development of the ecclesiastical consciousness.” If only Bruno Bauer could have lived to see this triumph of his opinions!

Even the Marcan narrative isn't history. The skepticism regarding the main source, which writers like Oskar Holtzmann, Schmiedel, and von Soden have a kind of intellectual flirtation with, is here established as a principle. "It should be acknowledged," states Pfleiderer, "Concerning the reshaping of history influenced by theology, all our Gospels are essentially equal. The distinction between Mark, the other two Synoptic Gospels, and John is only relative—a difference in degree that shows various stages of theological thought and the development of church awareness." If only Bruno Bauer could have lived to witness this victory of his ideas!

Pfleiderer, however, is conscious that scepticism, too, has its difficulties. He wishes, indeed, to reject the confession of Jesus before the Sanhedrin “because its historicity is not well established (none of the disciples were present to hear it, and the apocalyptic prophecy which is added, Mark xiv. 62, is certainly derived from the ideas of the primitive Church)”; on the other hand, he is inclined to admit as possibilities—though marking them with a note of interrogation—that Jesus may have accepted the homage of the Passover pilgrims, and that the controversy with the Scribes [pg 313] about the Son of David had some kind of reference to Jesus Himself.

Pfleiderer, however, is aware that skepticism also has its challenges. He actually wants to dismiss the confession of Jesus before the Sanhedrin "because its historical accuracy isn't well established (none of the disciples were there to hear it, and the apocalyptic prophecy that follows, Mark xiv. 62, definitely comes from the beliefs of the early Church)"; on the other hand, he is open to the possibility—though he qualifies it with a question mark—that Jesus may have accepted the praise of the Passover pilgrims, and that the debate with the Scribes [pg 313] about the Son of David had some sort of relevance to Jesus Himself.

On the other hand, he takes it for granted that Jesus did not prophesy His death, on the ground that the arrest, trial, and betrayal must have lain outside all possibility of calculation even for Him. All these, he thinks, came upon Jesus quite unexpectedly. The only thing that He might have apprehended was “an attack by hired assassins,” and it is to this that He refers in the saying about the two swords in Luke xxii. 36 and 38, seeing that two swords would have sufficed as a protection against such an attack as that, though hardly for anything further. When, however, he remarks in this connexion that “this has been constantly overlooked” in the romances dealing with the Life of Jesus, he does injustice to Bahrdt and Venturini, since according to them the chief concern of the secret society in the later period of the life of Jesus was to protect Jesus from the assassination with which He was menaced, and to secure His formal arrest and trial by the Sanhedrin. Their view of the historical situation is therefore identical with Pfleiderer's, viz. that assassination was possible, but that administrative action was unexpected and is inexplicable.

On the other hand, he assumes that Jesus did not predict His death, believing that the arrest, trial, and betrayal were completely unpredictable events, even for Him. He thinks all of this caught Jesus by surprise. The only thing Jesus might have considered was "an attack by contract killers," which is what He refers to when talking about the two swords in Luke xxii. 36 and 38, since two swords would have been enough for defense against such an attack, but not for anything more. However, when he notes that “this has been frequently overlooked” in the stories about the Life of Jesus, he is dismissing Bahrdt and Venturini, who argued that the main goal of the secret society during Jesus' later life was to protect Him from the assassination threat and to ensure His formal arrest and trial by the Sanhedrin. Their perspective on the historical situation aligns with Pfleiderer's, stating that while assassination was a possibility, administrative actions were unexpected and hard to explain.

But how is this Jesus to be connected with primitive Christianity? How did the primitive Church's belief in the Messiahship of Jesus arise? To that question Pfleiderer can give no other answer than that of Volkmar and Brandt, that is to say, none. He laboriously brings together wood, straw, and stubble, but where he gets the fire from to kindle the whole into the ardent faith of primitive Christianity he is unable to make clear.

But how is this Jesus connected to early Christianity? How did the early Church's belief in Jesus as the Messiah come about? In response to that question, Pfleiderer offers no better answer than Volkmar and Brandt, which is to say, none at all. He painstakingly gathers bits and pieces, but he can't clarify where the flame comes from to ignite all of it into the passionate faith of early Christianity.


According to Albert Kalthoff,242 the fire lighted itself—Christianity arose—by spontaneous combustion, when the inflammable material, religious and social, which had collected together in the Roman Empire, came in contact with the Jewish Messianic expectations. Jesus of Nazareth never existed; and even supposing He had been one of the numerous Jewish Messiahs who were put to death by crucifixion, He certainly did not found Christianity. The story of Jesus which lies before us in the Gospels is in reality only the story of the way in which the picture of Christ arose, that is to say, the story of the growth of the Christian community. There is therefore no problem of the Life of Jesus, but only a problem of the Christ.

According to Albert Kalthoff, the fire sparked itself—Christianity emerged—through spontaneous combustion, when the flammable material, both religious and social, that had accumulated in the Roman Empire came into contact with Jewish Messianic hopes. Jesus of Nazareth didn’t actually exist; and even if He had been one of the many Jewish Messiahs who were crucified, He definitely did not start Christianity. The narrative of Jesus we see in the Gospels is really just the account of how the image of Christ came to be, meaning it’s the story of how the Christian community developed. Thus, there is no issue concerning the Life of Jesus, only an issue regarding the Christ.

[pg 314]

Kalthoff has not indeed always been so negative. When in the year 1880 he gave a series of lectures on the Life of Jesus he felt himself justified “in taking as his basis without further argument the generally accepted results of modern theology.” Afterwards he became so completely doubtful about the Christ after the flesh whom he had at that time depicted before his hearers that he wished to exclude Him even from the register of theological literature, and omitted to enter these lectures in the list of his writings, although they had appeared in print.243

Kalthoff hasn’t always been so critical. When he delivered a series of lectures on the Life of Jesus in 1880, he felt justified “by using the widely accepted findings of modern theology as his foundation without any further discussion.” Later, he became so doubtful about the Christ after the flesh that he had portrayed to his audience at that time that he wanted to remove Him entirely from theological literature, and he didn’t include those lectures in his list of works, even though they had been published.243

His quarrel with the historical Jesus of modern theology was that he could find no connecting link between the Life of Jesus constructed by the latter and primitive Christianity. Modern theology, he remarks in one passage, with great justice, finds itself obliged to assume, at the point where the history of the Church begins, “an immediate declension from, and falsification of, a pure original principle,” and that in so doing “it is deserting the recognised methods of historical science.” If then we cannot trace the path from its beginning onwards, we had better try to work backwards, endeavouring first to define in the theology of the primitive Church the values which we shall look to find again in the Life of Jesus.

His disagreement with the modern theological view of the historical Jesus was that he couldn’t find any connection between the Life of Jesus created by that perspective and early Christianity. Modern theology, he points out in one part, rightly has to assume, where the history of the Church starts, "a quick departure from, and distortion of, a pure original principle," and that in doing so "it's rejecting the established methods of historical science." So, if we can't trace the journey from the beginning onward, it might be better to work backward, first trying to define in the theology of the early Church the values we hope to find again in the Life of Jesus.

In that he is right. Modern historical theology will not have refuted him until it has explained how Christianity arose out of the life of Jesus without calling in that theory of an initial “Fall” of which Harnack, Wernle, and all the rest make use. Until this modern theology has made it in some measure intelligible how, under the influence of the Jewish Messiah-sect, in the twinkling of an eye, in every direction at once, Graeco-Roman popular Christianity arose; until at least it has described the popular Christianity of the first three generations, it must concede to all hypotheses which fairly face this problem and endeavour to solve it their formal right of existence.

In this, he is right. Modern historical theology won’t have refuted him until it explains how Christianity emerged from the life of Jesus without relying on that theory of an initial "Autumn" that Harnack, Wernle, and others depend on. Until this contemporary theology makes it somewhat understandable how, influenced by the Jewish Messiah-sect, Graeco-Roman popular Christianity suddenly arose in all directions, or at least describes the popular Christianity of the first three generations, it must acknowledge the validity of all hypotheses that genuinely confront this issue and try to solve it.

The criticism which Kalthoff directs against the “positive” accounts of the Life of Jesus is, in part, very much to the point. “Jesus,” he says in one place, “has been made the receptacle into which every theologian pours his own ideas.” He rightly remarks that if we follow “the Christ” backwards from the Epistles and Gospels of the New Testament right to the apocalyptic vision of Daniel, we always find in Him superhuman traits alongside of the human. “Never and nowhere,” he insists, “is He that which critical theology has endeavoured to make out of Him, a purely natural man, an indivisible historical unit.” “The title of 'Christ' had been raised by the Messianic apocalyptic writings so completely into the sphere of the heroic that it had become impossible to [pg 315] apply it to a mere historical man.” Bruno Bauer had urged the same considerations upon the theology of his time, declaring it to be unthinkable that a man could have arisen among the Jews and declared “I am the Messiah.”

The criticism Kalthoff makes about the “positive” accounts of the Life of Jesus is, in part, very relevant. “Jesus,” he says at one point, “has become the container into which every theologian pours their own ideas.” He correctly points out that if we trace “the Christ” back from the Epistles and Gospels of the New Testament to the apocalyptic vision of Daniel, we always find in Him superhuman qualities alongside the human ones. “Never and nowhere,” he insists, “is He what critical theology has tried to make Him out to be, a purely natural man, an indivisible historical unit.” “The title of 'Christ' had been elevated by the Messianic apocalyptic writings so much into the realm of the heroic that it became impossible to apply it to just an ordinary historical man.” Bruno Bauer argued similar points to the theology of his time, stating that it was unthinkable for a man to have emerged among the Jews and claimed, “I am the Messiah.”

But the unfortunate thing is that Kalthoff has not worked through Bruno Bauer's criticism, and does not appear to assume it as a basis, but remains standing half-way instead of thinking the questions through to the end as that keen critic did. According to Kalthoff it would appear that, year in year out, there was a constant succession of Messianic disturbances among the Jews and of crucified claimants of the Messiahship. “There had been many a 'Christ,'” he says in one place, “before there was any question of a Jesus in connexion with this title.”

But the unfortunate thing is that Kalthoff hasn't fully addressed Bruno Bauer's criticism and doesn't seem to use it as a foundation. Instead, he stops halfway rather than thinking through the questions to their conclusion, like that sharp critic did. According to Kalthoff, it seems that year after year, there was a constant stream of Messianic movements among the Jews, along with many individuals claiming to be the Messiah. “There have been many 'Christs,'” he states in one instance, "before there was any mention of a Jesus related to this title."

How does Kalthoff know that? If he had fairly considered and felt the force of Bruno Bauer's arguments, he would never have ventured on this assertion; he would have learned that it is not only historically unproved, but intrinsically impossible.

How does Kalthoff know that? If he had honestly considered and understood the strength of Bruno Bauer's arguments, he would never have made this claim; he would have realized that it is not only historically unproven, but also fundamentally impossible.

But Kalthoff was in far too great a hurry to present to his readers a description of the growth of Christianity, and therewith of the picture of the Christ, to absorb thoroughly the criticism of his great predecessor. He soon leads his reader away from the high road of criticism into a morass of speculation, in order to arrive by a short cut at Graeco-Roman primitive Christianity. But the trouble is that while the guide walks lightly and safely, the ordinary man, weighed down by the pressure of historical considerations, sinks to rise no more.

But Kalthoff was in way too much of a rush to give his readers a detailed account of how Christianity grew, and along with that, the image of Christ, to really take in the critiques of his major predecessor. He quickly steers his readers away from the solid path of criticism into a swamp of speculation, hoping to reach Graeco-Roman primitive Christianity more quickly. The problem is that while the guide moves easily and confidently, the average person, burdened by historical facts, gets stuck and can't recover.

The conjectural argument which Kalthoff follows out is in itself acute, and forms a suitable pendant to Bauer's reconstruction of the course of events. Bauer proposed to derive Christianity from the Graeco-Roman philosophy; Kalthoff, recognising that the origin of popular Christianity constitutes the main question, takes as his starting-point the social movements of the time.

The hypothetical argument that Kalthoff develops is sharp and serves as a fitting complement to Bauer's reconstruction of the sequence of events. Bauer aimed to trace Christianity back to Graeco-Roman philosophy; Kalthoff, acknowledging that the origin of popular Christianity is the key issue, begins with the social movements of the era.

In the Roman Empire, so runs his argument, among the oppressed masses of the slaves and the populace, eruptive forces were concentrated under high tension. A communistic movement arose, to which the influence of the Jewish element in the proletariat gave a Messianic-Apocalyptic colouring. The Jewish synagogue influenced Roman social conditions so that “the crude social ferment at work in the Roman Empire amalgamated itself with the religious and philosophical forces of the time to form the new Christian social movement.” Early Christian writers had learned in the synagogue to construct “personifications.” The whole Late-Jewish literature rests upon this principle. Thus “the Christ” became the ideal hero of the Christian community, “from the socio-religious standpoint the figure of Christ is the [pg 316] sublimated religious expression for the sum of the social and ethical forces which were at work at a certain period.” The Lord's Supper was the memorial feast of this ideal hero.

In the Roman Empire, his argument goes, the oppressed masses of slaves and the general populace were under intense pressure, creating explosive forces. A communistic movement emerged, infused with a Messianic-Apocalyptic flavor due to the influence of the Jewish element within the working class. The Jewish synagogue shaped Roman social conditions so that "The rough social changes happening in the Roman Empire, along with the religious and philosophical influences of the era, led to the emergence of the new Christian social movement." Early Christian writers learned in the synagogue how to create “personifications.” This principle underlies all of Late-Jewish literature. Thus “Christ” became the ideal hero of the Christian community, "From a socio-religious perspective, the figure of Christ represents the elevated religious expression for the entirety of the social and ethical forces at play during a specific time." The Lord's Supper was the commemorative feast honoring this ideal hero.

“As the Christ to whose Parousia the community looks forward this Hero-god of the community bears within Himself the capacity for expansion into the God of the universe, into the Christ of the Church, who is identical in essential nature with God the Father. Thus the belief in the Christ brought the Messianic hope of the future into the minds of the masses, who had already a certain organisation, and by directing their thoughts towards the future it won all those who were sick of the past and despairing about the present.”

"As the Messiah that the community looks forward to, this Hero-god represents the potential to grow into both the God of the universe and the Messiah of the Church, who is essentially the same as God the Father. Thus, faith in Christ instilled a Messianic hope for the future in the minds of the people, who already had some kind of organization. By concentrating their thoughts on what is ahead, it drew in all those who felt discouraged by the past and hopeless about the present."

The death and resurrection of Jesus represent experiences of the community. “For a Jew crucified under Pontius Pilate there was certainly no resurrection. All that is possible is a vague hypothesis of a vision lacking all historical reality, or an escape into the vaguenesses of theological phraseology. But for the Christian community the resurrection was something real, a matter of fact. For the community as such was not annihilated in that persecution: it drew from it, rather, new strength and life.”

The death and resurrection of Jesus symbolize experiences of the community. “For a Jew who was crucified under Pontius Pilate, there was certainly no resurrection. The only possibility could be a vague notion of a vision without any historical truth, or a retreat into unclear theological language. However, for the Christian community, the resurrection was something tangible, a factual event. The community as a whole didn’t get wiped out during that persecution; instead, it drew new strength and vitality from it.”

But what about the foundations of this imposing structure?

But what about the foundations of this impressive building?

For what he has to tell us about the condition of the Roman Empire and the social organisation of the proletariat in the time of Trajan—for it was then that the Church first came out into the light—we may leave the responsibility with Kalthoff. But we must inquire more closely how he brings the Jewish apocalyptic into contact with the Roman proletariat.

For what he has to tell us about the state of the Roman Empire and the social organization of the working class during Trajan's time—when the Church first emerged into the open—we can trust Kalthoff to take responsibility. However, we need to look more closely at how he connects Jewish apocalyptic ideas with the Roman working class.

Communism, he says, was common to both. It was the bond which united the apocalyptic “other-worldliness” with reality. The only difficulty is that Kalthoff omits to produce any proof out of the Jewish apocalypses that communism was “the fundamental economic idea of the apocalyptic writers.” He operates from the first with a special preparation of apocalyptic thought, of a socialistic or Hellenistic character. Messianism is supposed to have taken its rise from the Deuteronomic reform as “a social theory which strives to realise itself in practice.” The apocalyptic of Daniel arose, according to him, under Platonic influence. “The figure of the Messiah thus became a human figure; it lost its specifically Jewish traits.” He is the heavenly proto-typal ideal man. Along with this thought, and similarly derived from Plato, the conception of immortality makes its appearance in apocalyptic.244 This Platonic apocalyptic never had any existence, or at least, [pg 317] to speak with the utmost possible caution, its existence must not be asserted in the absence of all proof.

Communism, he says, was a common thread between them. It was the connection that linked the apocalyptic "otherworldliness" with reality. The only problem is that Kalthoff fails to provide any evidence from the Jewish apocalypses that communism was "the basic economic concept of the apocalyptic authors." He starts out with a specific interpretation of apocalyptic thought that has a socialistic or Hellenistic angle. Messianism is believed to have originated from the Deuteronomic reform as "a social theory that aims to put itself into practice." According to him, the apocalyptic writings of Daniel emerged under Platonist influence. "The concept of the Messiah became a human figure; it lost its distinctively Jewish characteristics." He embodies the ideal heavenly prototype of humanity. Alongside this idea, which is similarly based on Plato, the notion of immortality appears in apocalyptic thinking. 244 This Platonic apocalyptic never actually existed, or at least, [pg 317] to be completely cautious, its existence cannot be claimed without any proof.

But, supposing it were admitted that Jewish apocalyptic had some affinity for the Hellenic world, that it was Platonic and communistic, how are we to explain the fact that the Gospels, which describe the genesis of Christ and Christianity, imply a Galilaean and not a Roman environment?

But, assuming that Jewish apocalyptic had some connections to the Hellenic world, that it was influenced by Platonic and communist ideas, how do we explain the fact that the Gospels, which describe the origin of Christ and Christianity, suggest a Galilean rather than a Roman setting?

As a matter of fact, Kalthoff says, they do imply a Roman environment. The scene of the Gospel history is laid in Palestine, but it is drawn in Rome. The agrarian conditions implied in the narratives and parables are Roman. A vineyard with a wine-press of its own could only be found, according to Kalthoff, on the large Roman estates. So, too, the legal conditions. The right of the creditor to sell the debtor, with his wife and children, is a feature of Roman, not of Jewish law.

Actually, Kalthoff points out that they do suggest a Roman setting. The events of the Gospel story take place in Palestine, but they’re portrayed in a Roman context. The farming conditions mentioned in the stories and parables are Roman. A vineyard with its own wine press could only exist, according to Kalthoff, on the large Roman estates. Similarly, the legal situations reflect Roman law. The creditor’s right to sell the debtor, along with his wife and children, is a characteristic of Roman law, not Jewish law.

Peter everywhere symbolises the Church at Rome. The confession of Peter had to be transferred to Caesarea Philippi because this town, “as the seat of the Roman administration,” symbolised for Palestine the political presence of Rome.

Peter everywhere symbolizes the Church in Rome. The confession of Peter had to be moved to Caesarea Philippi because this town, “as the center of the Roman government,” represented for Palestine the political presence of Rome.

The woman with the issue was perhaps Poppaea Sabina, the wife of Nero, “who in view of her strong leaning towards Judaism might well be described in the symbolical style of the apocalyptic writings as the woman who touched the hem of Jesus' garment.”

The woman in question was likely Poppaea Sabina, Nero's wife, "She had a strong inclination towards Judaism and could be described in the symbolic language of apocalyptic texts as the woman who touched the hem of Jesus' garment."

The story of the unfaithful steward alludes to Pope Callixtus, who, when the slave of a Christian in high position, was condemned to the mines for the crime of embezzlement; that of the woman who was a sinner refers to Marcia, the powerful mistress of Commodus, at whose intercession Callixtus was released, to be advanced soon afterwards to the bishopric of Rome. “These two narratives, therefore,” Kalthoff suggests, “which very clearly allude to events well known at that time, and doubtless much discussed in the Christian community, were admitted into the Gospel to express the views of the Church regarding the life-story of a Roman bishop which had run its course under the eyes of the community, and thereby to give to the events themselves the Church's sanction and interpretation.”

The story of the unfaithful steward references Pope Callixtus, who, while being a slave to a powerful Christian, was sentenced to the mines for embezzlement. The account of the sinful woman refers to Marcia, the influential mistress of Commodus, who helped Callixtus get released, leading to his promotion to bishop of Rome shortly after. "These two stories, therefore," Kalthoff suggests, "which clearly refer to events that were well-known and probably widely discussed in the Christian community at that time, were included in the Gospel to reflect the Church's view on the life of a Roman bishop that occurred under the community's observation, thereby giving the events the Church's endorsement and interpretation."

Kalthoff does not, unfortunately, mention whether this is a case of simple, ingenuous, or of conscious, didactic, Early Christian imagination.

Kalthoff doesn’t, unfortunately, say whether this is an example of simple, naive, or of intentional, instructive, Early Christian imagination.

That kind of criticism is a casting out of Satan by the aid of Beelzebub. If he was going to invent on this scale, Kalthoff need not have found any difficulty in accepting the figure of Jesus evolved by modern theology. One feels annoyed with him because, while his thesis is ingenious, and, as against “modern theology” has a considerable measure of justification, he has worked it out in so uninteresting a fashion. He has no one but himself to blame [pg 318] for the fact that instead of leading to the right explanation, it only introduced a wearisome and unproductive controversy.245

That kind of criticism is like trying to kick out the devil with the help of the devil himself. If he was going to make up stories on this scale, Kalthoff wouldn’t have had any trouble accepting the version of Jesus developed by modern theology. You feel frustrated with him because, while his argument is clever and has some valid points against contemporary theology, he presented it in such a dull way. He has no one to blame but himself [pg 318] for the fact that instead of leading to the correct understanding, it only sparked a tedious and unproductive debate.245

In the end there remains scarcely a shade of distinction between Kalthoff and his opponents. They want to bring their “historical Jesus” into the midst of our time. He wants to do the same with his “Christ.” “A secularised Christ,” he says, “as the type of the self-determined man who amid strife and suffering carries through victoriously, and fully realises, His own personality in order to give the infinite fullness of love which He bears within Himself as a blessing to mankind—a Christ such as that can awaken to new life the antique Christ-type of the Church. He is no longer the Christ of the scholar, of the abstract theological thinker with his scholastic rules and methods. He is the people's Christ, the Christ of the ordinary man, the figure in which all those powers of the human soul which are most natural and simple—and therefore most exalted and divine—find an expression at once sensible and spiritual.” But that is precisely the description of the Jesus of modern historical theology; why, then, make this long roundabout through scepticism? The Christ of Kalthoff is nothing else than the Jesus of those whom he combats in such a lofty fashion; the only difference is that he draws his figure of Christ in red ink on blotting-paper, and because it is red in colour and smudgy in outline, wants to make out that it is something new.

In the end, there's barely any difference between Kalthoff and his opponents. They want to bring their “historical Jesus” into our time, and he wants to do the same with his “Christ.” “A secularized Christ,” he says, “as the embodiment of the self-determined person who, despite struggles and suffering, triumphs and fully realizes His own identity to share the immense love He holds within Himself as a blessing to humanity—a Christ like that can revive the ancient Christ of the Church. He’s no longer the Christ of scholars or abstract theological thinkers with their academic rules and methods. He’s the people’s Christ, the Christ of ordinary individuals, embodying all those powers of the human soul that are most natural and simple—and thus most exalted and divine—finding expression that is both sensible and spiritual.” But that’s exactly the description of the Jesus in modern historical theology; so why go through this long detour of skepticism? Kalthoff’s Christ is nothing other than the Jesus of those he criticizes so loftily; the only difference is that he sketches his figure of Christ in red ink on blotting paper, and because it’s red and smudgy, he wants to claim it's something new.


It is on ethical grounds that Eduard von Hartmann246 refuses to accept the Jesus of modern theology. He finds fault with it because in its anxiety to retain a personality which would be of value to religion it does not sufficiently distinguish between the authentic and the “historical” Jesus. When criticism has removed the paintings-over and retouchings to which this authentic portrait of Jesus has been subjected, it reaches, according to him, an unrecognisable painting below, in which it is impossible to discover any clear likeness, least of all one of any religious use and value.

It is on ethical grounds that Eduard von Hartmann246 refuses to accept the Jesus of modern theology. He criticizes it because, in its effort to maintain a personality that would be valuable to religion, it doesn't adequately differentiate between the true and the "historical" Jesus. When criticism strips away the embellishments and alterations that have been applied to the genuine portrait of Jesus, it reveals an unrecognizable image underneath, making it impossible to find any clear resemblance, especially one that holds religious significance or value.

Were it not for the tenacity and the simple fidelity of the epic tradition, nothing whatever would have remained of the historic Jesus. What has remained is merely of historical and psychological interest.

If it weren't for the persistence and the straightforward loyalty of the epic tradition, nothing at all would have survived about the historical Jesus. What we do have left is only of historical and psychological interest.

At His first appearance the historic Jesus was, according to [pg 319] Eduard von Hartmann, almost “an impersonal being,” since He regarded Himself so exclusively as the vehicle of His message that His personality hardly came into the question. As time went on, however, He developed a taste for glory and for wonderful deeds, and fell at last into a condition of “abnormal exaltation of personality.” In the end He declares Himself to His disciples and before the council as Messiah. “When He felt His death drawing nigh He struck the balance of His life, found His mission a failure, His person and His cause abandoned by God, and died with the unanswered question on His lips, ‘My God, why hast thou forsaken me?’ ”

At His first appearance, the historical Jesus was, according to [pg 319] Eduard von Hartmann, almost "a detached entity," because He saw Himself so strictly as the messenger of His message that His personality hardly mattered. However, over time, He developed a desire for glory and for performing amazing acts, ultimately reaching a state of “unusual personality enhancement.” In the end, He revealed Himself to His disciples and the council as the Messiah. “When He felt His death nearing, He reflected on His life, realized His mission had failed, felt deserted by God concerning both Himself and His purpose, and died with the unanswered question on His lips, ‘My God, why hast thou forsaken me?’ ”

It is significant that Eduard von Hartmann has not fallen into the mistake of Schopenhauer and many other philosophers, of identifying the pessimism of Jesus with the Indian speculative pessimism of Buddha. The pessimism of Jesus, he says, is not metaphysical, it is “a pessimism of indignation,” born of the intolerable social and political conditions of the time. Von Hartmann also clearly recognises the significance of eschatology, but he does not define its character quite correctly, since he bases his impressions solely on the Talmud, hardly making any use of the Old Testament, of Enoch, the Psalms of Solomon, Baruch, or Fourth Ezra. He has an irritating way of still using the name “Jehovah.”

It’s important to note that Eduard von Hartmann hasn’t made the mistake that Schopenhauer and many other philosophers have, of confusing Jesus' pessimism with the Indian philosophical pessimism of Buddha. He argues that Jesus’ pessimism is not metaphysical; it’s "indignant pessimism," arising from the unbearable social and political conditions of the time. Von Hartmann also clearly acknowledges the importance of eschatology, though he doesn’t quite define it correctly because he bases his views solely on the Talmud and hardly references the Old Testament, Enoch, the Psalms of Solomon, Baruch, or Fourth Ezra. It’s a bit annoying that he continues to use the name "God."

Like Reimarus—von Hartmann's positions are simply modernised Reimarus—he is anxious to show that Christian theology has lost the right “to treat the ideal Kingdom of God as belonging to itself.” Jesus and His teaching, so far as they have been preserved, belong to Judaism. His ethic is for us strange and full of stumbling-blocks. He despises work, property, and the duties of family life. His gospel is fundamentally plebeian, and completely excludes the idea of any aristocracy except in so far as it consents to plebeianise itself, and this is true not only as regards the aristocracy of rank, property, and fortune, but also the aristocracy of intellect. Von Hartmann cannot resist the temptation to accuse Jesus of “Semitic harshness,” finding the evidence of this chiefly in Mark iv. 12, where Jesus declares that the purpose of His parables was to obscure His teaching and cause the hearts of the people to be hardened.

Like Reimarus, von Hartmann’s views are simply a modern take on Reimarus—he is eager to show that Christian theology has lost the right “to consider the perfect Kingdom of God as its own.” Jesus and His teachings, as far as they have been preserved, are rooted in Judaism. His ethics seem strange to us and are full of difficulties. He looks down on work, property, and the responsibilities of family life. His gospel is fundamentally for the common person and completely rejects the concept of any aristocracy, except in cases where it chooses to embrace common values, and this applies not only to the aristocracy of rank, property, and wealth but also to the aristocracy of intellect. Von Hartmann cannot resist the urge to accuse Jesus of "Semitic toughness," mainly finding this evidence in Mark iv. 12, where Jesus states that the purpose of His parables was to obscure His teaching and harden the hearts of the people.

His judgment upon Jesus is: “He had no genius, but a certain talent which, in the complete absence of any sound education, produced in general only moderate results, and was not sufficient to preserve Him from numerous weaknesses and serious errors; at heart a fanatic and a transcendental enthusiast, who in spite of an inborn kindliness of disposition hates and despises the world and everything it contains, and holds any interest in it to be injurious to the sole true, transcendental interest; an amiable and modest youth who, through a remarkable concatenation of circumstances [pg 320] arrived at the idea, which was at that time epidemic,247 that He was Himself the expected Messiah, and in consequence of this met His fate.”

His judgment on Jesus is: "He wasn’t a genius, but he had a certain talent that, without any proper education, usually led to average results, and it wasn’t enough to save him from many flaws and serious mistakes. Deep down, he was a fanatic and an idealistic dreamer who, despite being naturally kind, despised and looked down on the world and everything in it, believing that any interest in the world was harmful to the only true, idealistic interest. He was a likable and humble young man who, through a series of remarkable circumstances [pg 320] came to the idea that was prevalent at the time: that he was the expected Messiah, and as a result, faced his fate."

It is to be regretted that a mind like Eduard von Hartmann's should not have got beyond the externals of the history, and made an effort to grasp the simple and impressive greatness of the figure of Jesus in its eschatological setting; and that he should imagine he has disposed of the strangeness which he finds in Jesus when he has made it as small as possible. And yet in another respect there is something satisfactory about his book. It is the open struggle of the Germanic spirit with Jesus. In this battle the victory will rest with true greatness. Others wanted to make peace before the struggle, or thought that theologians could fight the battle alone, and spare their contemporaries the doubts about the historical Jesus through which it was necessary to pass in order to reach the eternal Jesus—and to this end they kept preaching reconciliation while fighting the battle. They could only preach it on a basis of postulates, and postulates make poor preaching! Thus, Jülicher, for example, in his latest sketches of the Life of Jesus248 distinguishes between “Jewish and supra-Jewish” in Jesus, and holds that Jesus transferred the ideal of the Kingdom of God “to the solid ground of the present, bringing it into the course of historical events,” and further “associated with the Kingdom of God” the idea of development which was utterly opposed to all Jewish ideas about the Kingdom. Jülicher also desires to raise “the strongest protest against the poor little definition of His preaching which makes it consist in nothing further than an announcement of the nearness of the Kingdom, and an exhortation to the repentance necessary as a condition for attaining the Kingdom.”

It’s unfortunate that a mind like Eduard von Hartmann's hasn’t moved beyond the surface of history and made an effort to understand the simple yet profound greatness of Jesus in its eschatological context; and that he thinks he has dealt with the strangeness he sees in Jesus by minimizing it. Still, there’s something rewarding about his book. It represents the open conflict of the German spirit with Jesus. In this battle, the true greatness will prevail. Others wanted to negotiate peace before the struggle, or believed that theologians could handle the fight alone, sparing their contemporaries the questions about the historical Jesus that were necessary to confront in order to reach the eternal Jesus—and for this reason, they kept preaching reconciliation while engaging in the struggle. They could only offer it based on assumptions, and assumptions make for weak preaching! For instance, Jülicher, in his latest sketches of the Life of Jesus 248 differentiates between “Jewish and non-Jewish” aspects in Jesus, asserting that Jesus grounded the ideal of the Kingdom of God “in today’s realities, incorporating it into the sequence of historical events,” and further "connected the Kingdom of God" to the idea of development that was entirely contrary to all Jewish understandings of the Kingdom. Jülicher also aims to raise "the most powerful objection to the limited interpretation of His preaching that simplifies it to merely announcing the coming Kingdom and urging the repentance required to enter it."

But when has a protest against the pure truth of history ever been of any avail? Why proclaim peace where there is no peace, and attempt to put back the clock of time? Is it not enough that Schleiermacher and Ritschl succeeded again and again in making theology send on earth peace instead of a sword, and does not the [pg 321] weakness of Christian thought as compared with the general culture of our time result from the fact that it did not face the battle when it ought to have faced it, but persisted in appealing to a court of arbitration on which all the sciences were represented, but which it had successfully bribed in advance?

But when has protesting against the simple truth of history ever made a difference? Why announce peace where there isn’t any and try to turn back the hands of time? Isn’t it enough that Schleiermacher and Ritschl repeatedly managed to bring peace to the world through theology instead of conflict? Doesn’t the [pg 321] weakness of Christian thought in comparison to our culture today come from the fact that it didn’t confront the struggle when it should have but kept asking a jury—made up of all the sciences, which it had already managed to sway in its favor?


Now there comes to join the philosophers a jurist. Herr Doctor jur. De Jonge lends his aid to Eduard von Hartmann in “destroying the ecclesiastical,” and “unveiling the Jewish picture of Jesus.”249

Now a jurist joins the philosophers. Dr. De Jonge helps Eduard von Hartmann in “destroying the church,” and "revealing the Jewish perspective on Jesus."249

De Jonge is a Jew by birth, baptized in 1889, who on the 22nd of November 1902 again separated himself from the Christian communion and was desirous of being received back “with certain evangelical reservations” into the Jewish community. In spite of his faithful observance of the Law, this was refused. Now he is waiting “until in the Synagogue of the twentieth century a freedom of conscience is accorded to him equal to that which in the first century was enjoyed by John, the beloved disciple of Jeschua of Nazareth.” In the meantime he beguiles the period of waiting by describing Jesus and His earliest followers in the character of pattern Jews, and sets them to work in the interest of his “Jewish views with evangelical reservations.”

De Jonge is a Jew by birth, baptized in 1889, who on November 22, 1902, separated from the Christian church again and wanted to be welcomed back “with certain evangelical reservations” into the Jewish community. Despite his faithful observance of the Law, this was denied. Now he is waiting “until in the Synagogue of the twentieth century a freedom of conscience is granted to him equal to that enjoyed in the first century by John, the beloved disciple of Jeschua of Nazareth.” In the meantime, he occupies his waiting period by portraying Jesus and His earliest followers as exemplary Jews, encouraging them to support his “Jewish views with evangelical reservations.”

It is the colourless, characterless Jesus of the Superintendents and Konsistorialrats which especially arouses his enmity. With this figure he contrasts his own Jesus, the man of holy anger, the man of holy calm, the man of holy melancholy, the master of dialectic, the imperious ruler, the man of high gifts and practical ability, the man of inexorable consistency and reforming vigour.

It’s the bland, unremarkable Jesus of the Superintendents and Konsistorialrats that really fuels his resentment. He compares this figure to his own Jesus, the man of righteous anger, the man of serene composure, the man of profound melancholy, the master of debate, the commanding leader, the gifted and practical person, the one of relentless consistency and reforming energy.

Jesus was, according to De Jonge, a pupil of Hillel. He demanded voluntary poverty only in special cases, not as a general principle. In the case of the rich young man, He knew “that the property which he had inherited was derived in this particular case from impure sources which must be cut off at once and for ever.”

Jesus was, according to De Jonge, a student of Hillel. He only called for voluntary poverty in specific situations, not as a general rule. When it came to the rich young man, He understood "that the property he inherited came from questionable sources that needed to be cut off right away and for good."

But how does De Jonge know that Jesus knew this?

But how does De Jonge know that Jesus was aware of this?

A writer who is attacking the common theological picture of Jesus, and who displays in the process, as De Jonge does, not only [pg 322] wit and address, but historical intuition, ought not to fall into the error of the theology with which he is at feud; he ought to use sober history as his weapon against the supplementary knowledge which his opponents seem to find between the lines, instead of meeting it with an esoteric historical knowledge of his own.

A writer who challenges the typical view of Jesus should not, as De Jonge does, only show cleverness and charm but also a solid grasp of history. They shouldn't make the same mistakes as the theology they're criticizing. Instead of countering their opponents' hidden interpretations with their own obscure historical insights, they should rely on clear and straightforward history as their tool.

De Jonge knows that Jesus possessed property inherited from His father: “One proof may serve where many might be given—the hasty flight into Egypt with his whole family to escape from Herod, and the long sojourn in that country.”

De Jonge knows that Jesus had property passed down from His father: "One example can be enough when many could be provided—the swift escape to Egypt with His whole family to escape Herod, and the extended time spent in that country."

De Jonge knows—he is here, however, following the Gospel of John, to which he everywhere gives the preference—that Jesus was between forty and fifty years old at the time of His first coming forward publicly. The statement in Luke iii. 23, that He was ὡσεί thirty years old, can only mislead those who do not remember that Luke was a portrait painter and only meant that “Jeschua, in consequence of His glorious beauty and His ever-youthful appearance, looked ten years younger than He really was.”

De Jonge knows—he is here, however, following the Gospel of John, which he always prefers—that Jesus was between forty and fifty years old when He first came forward publicly. The statement in Luke 3:23, that He was about thirty years old, can only confuse those who forget that Luke was a portrait painter and meant that “Jeschua, because of His glorious beauty and eternally youthful look, appeared ten years younger than He actually was.”


De Jonge knows also that Jesus, at the time when He first emerged from obscurity, was a widower and had a little son—the “lad” of John vi. 9, who had the five barley loaves and two fishes, was in fact His son. This and many other things the author finds in “the glorious John.” According to De Jonge too we ought to think of Jesus as the aristocratic Jew, more accustomed to a dress coat than to a workman's blouse, something of an expert, as appears from some of the parables, in matters of the table, and conning the menu with interest when He dined with “privy-finance-councillor” Zacchaeus.

De Jonge also knows that Jesus, when He first came into the spotlight, was a widower and had a young son—the “guy” mentioned in John vi. 9, who had the five barley loaves and two fish, was actually His son. This and many other things the author finds in “the awesome John.” According to De Jonge, we should think of Jesus as an upper-class Jew, more familiar with a dress coat than a worker's shirt, somewhat of an expert, as shown in some of the parables, regarding dining, and scanning the menu with interest when He ate with “finance advisor” Zacchaeus.

But this is to modernise more distressingly than even the theologians!

But this is to modernize in a way that's even more disturbing than what the theologians do!

De Jonge's one-sided preference for the Fourth Gospel is shared by Kirchbach's book, “What did Jesus teach?”250 but here everything, instead of being judaised, is spiritualised. Kirchbach does not seem to have been acquainted with Noack's “History of Jesus,” otherwise he would hardly have ventured to repeat the same experiment without the latter's touch of genius and with much less skill and knowledge.

De Jonge's one-sided preference for the Fourth Gospel is echoed in Kirchbach's book, "What did Jesus say?"250 but here, instead of being made more Jewish, everything is made more spiritual. Kirchbach doesn’t seem to have been familiar with Noack's "History of Jesus" or he likely wouldn’t have tried the same approach without Noack's touch of genius and with far less skill and knowledge.

The teaching of Jesus is interpreted on the lines of the Kantian philosophy. The saying, “No man hath seen God at any time,” is to be understood as if it were derived from the same system of thought as the “Critique of Pure Reason.” Jesus always used the [pg 323] words “death” and “life” in a purely metaphorical sense. Eternal life is for Him not a life in another world, but in the present. He speaks of Himself as the Son of God, not as the Jewish Messiah. Son of Man is only the ethical explanation of Son of God. The only reason why a Son-of-Man problem has arisen, is because Matthew translated the ancient term Son of Man in the original collection of Logia “with extreme literality.”

The teachings of Jesus are interpreted through the lens of Kantian philosophy. The statement, "No one has seen God at any time," should be understood as if it came from the same framework as the "Critique of Pure Reason." Jesus consistently used the [pg 323] words "death" and “life” in a purely metaphorical way. For Him, eternal life isn’t a life in another world, but rather a life in the present. He refers to Himself as the Son of God, not as the Jewish Messiah. The title Son of Man is merely an ethical interpretation of Son of God. The only reason the Son-of-Man issue has come up is that Matthew translated the ancient term Son of Man in the original collection of Logia “with extreme literalness.”

The great discourse of Matt. xxiii. with its warnings and threatenings is, according to Kirchbach, merely “a patriotic oration in which Jesus gives expression in moving words to His opposition to the Pharisees and His inborn love of His native land.”

The significant talk in Matt. xxiii., filled with warnings and threats, is, as Kirchbach puts it, just "a passionate speech where Jesus shares in heartfelt words His opposition to the Pharisees and His deep love for His homeland."

The teaching of Jesus is not ascetic, it closely resembles the real teaching of Epicurus, “that is, the rejection of all false metaphysics, and the resulting condition of blessedness, of makaria.” The only purpose of the demand addressed to the rich young man was to try him. “If the youth, instead of slinking away dejectedly because he was called upon to sell all his goods, had replied, confident in the possession of a rich fund of courage, energy, ability, and knowledge, ‘Right gladly. It will not go to my heart to part with my little bit of property; if I'm not to have it, why then I can do without it,’ the Rabbi would probably in that case not have taken him at his word, but would have said, ‘Young man, I like you. You have a good chance before you, you may do something in the Kingdom of God, and in any case for My sake you may attach yourself to Me by way of trial. We can talk about your stocks and bonds later.’ ”

The teaching of Jesus isn’t about strict self-denial; it actually resembles the true teaching of Epicurus, “which is the rejection of all false metaphysics and the resulting state of blessedness, of *makaria*.” The only reason for the request made to the rich young man was to test him. “If the young man, instead of walking away sadly because he was asked to sell all his possessions, had responded confidently, saying, ‘Sure, I’d be happy to. It won’t upset me to give up my little bit of property; if I can’t keep it, then I can do without it,’ the Rabbi probably wouldn’t have taken him at his word. He would have said, ‘Young man, I like you. You have a good future ahead of you; you could contribute something to the Kingdom of God. And for My sake, you can choose to follow Me as a test. We can discuss your assets later.’”

Finally, Kirchbach succeeds, though only, it must be admitted, by the aid of some rather awkward phraseology, in spiritualising John vi. “It is not the body,” he explains, “of the long departed thinker, who apparently attached no importance whatever to the question of personal survival, that we, who understand Him in the right Greek sense, ‘eat’; in the sense which He intended, we eat and drink, and absorb into ourselves, His teaching, His spirit, His sublime conception of life, by constantly recalling them in connexion with the symbol of bread and flesh, the symbol of blood, the symbol of water.”251

Finally, Kirchbach succeeds, though it must be admitted that he does so with some rather awkward wording, in giving a spiritual interpretation to John vi. “It’s not the body,” he explains, "of the long-gone thinker, who apparently saw no significance in the question of personal survival, that we, who truly understand Him in the original Greek sense, ‘eat’; in the way He intended, we eat and drink, and take in His teachings, His spirit, His deep understanding of life, by constantly recalling them in relation to the symbols of bread and flesh, the symbol of blood, and the symbol of water."251

Worthless as Kirchbach's Life of Jesus is from an historical point of view, it is quite comprehensible as a phase in the struggle between the modern view of the world and Jesus. The aim of the [pg 324] work is to retain His significance for a metaphysical and non-ascetic time; and since it is not possible to do this in the case of the historical Jesus, the author denies His existence in favour of an apocryphal Jesus.

Worthless as Kirchbach's Life of Jesus is from a historical perspective, it makes sense as part of the conflict between modern worldviews and Jesus. The goal of the [pg 324] work is to maintain His importance for a metaphysical and non-ascetic era; and since it's not feasible to achieve this regarding the historical Jesus, the author denies His existence in favor of an apocryphal Jesus.

It is, in fact, the characteristic feature of the Life-of-Jesus literature on the threshold of the new century even in the productions of professedly historical and scientific theology, to subordinate the historical interest to the interest of the general world-view. And those who “wrest the Kingdom of Heaven” are beginning to wrest Jesus Himself along with it. Men who have no qualifications for the task, whose ignorance is nothing less than criminal, who loftily anathematise scientific theology instead of making themselves in some measure acquainted with the researches which it has carried out, feel impelled to write a Life of Jesus, in order to set forth their general religious view in a portrait of Jesus which has not the faintest claim to be historical, and the most far-fetched of these find favour, and are eagerly absorbed by the multitude.

It is, in fact, the main feature of the Life-of-Jesus literature at the start of the new century, even in works claiming to be historical and scientific, to prioritize the general worldview over historical accuracy. And those who “take the Kingdom of Heaven” are starting to do the same with Jesus Himself. People without the necessary qualifications, whose ignorance is nothing short of shocking, who arrogantly criticize scientific theology instead of familiarizing themselves with the research that has been done, feel compelled to write a Life of Jesus, in order to express their overall religious view through a portrayal of Jesus that has no genuine historical basis, and the most far-fetched of these are popular and eagerly embraced by the masses.

It would be something to be thankful for if all these Lives of Jesus were based on as definite an idea and as acute historical observation as we find in Albert Dulk's “The Error of the Life of Jesus.”252 In Dulk the story of the fate of Jesus is also the story of the fate of religion. The Galilaean teacher, whose true character was marked by deep religious inwardness, was doomed to destruction from the moment when He set Himself upon the dizzy heights of the divine sonship and the eschatological expectation. He died in despair, having vainly expected, down to the very last, a “telegram from heaven.” Religion as a whole can only avoid the same fate by renouncing all transcendental elements.

It would be something to be grateful for if all these Lives of Jesus were based on as clear an idea and as sharp historical observation as we see in Albert Dulk's "The Mistake in the Life of Jesus."252 In Dulk's view, the story of Jesus's fate mirrors the story of religion’s fate. The Galilean teacher, whose true nature was defined by profound spiritual depth, was destined for ruin from the moment He embraced the lofty idea of divine sonship and the expectation of the end times. He died in despair, having hopelessly anticipated, until the very end, a “message from heaven.” Religion as a whole can only escape the same fate by giving up all transcendent aspects.


The vast numbers of imaginative Lives of Jesus shrink into remarkably small compass on a close examination. When one knows two or three of them, one knows them all. They have scarcely altered since Venturini's time, except that some of the cures performed by Jesus are handled in the modern Lives from the point of view of the recent investigations in hypnotism and suggestion.253

The numerous creative interpretations of Jesus' life condense into a surprisingly small range when examined closely. Once you've read a couple of them, you've pretty much seen them all. They haven't changed much since Venturini's era, except that some of the healings attributed to Jesus are now explored through the lens of recent studies in hypnotism and suggestion.253

[pg 325]

According to Paul de Régla254 Jesus was born out of wedlock. Joseph, however, gave shelter and protection to the mother. De Régla dwells on the beauty of the child. “His eyes were not exceptionally large, but were well-opened, and were shaded by long, silky, dark-brown eyelashes, and rather deep-set. They were of a blue-grey colour, which changed with changing emotions, taking on various shades, especially blue and brownish-grey.”

According to Paul de Régla, Jesus was born outside of marriage. However, Joseph provided shelter and protection to his mother. De Régla highlights the beauty of the child. "His eyes weren't overly big, but they were wide open and framed by long, smooth dark-brown eyelashes, appearing somewhat deep-set. They were a blue-grey color that shifted with his emotions, displaying different shades, especially blue and brownish-grey."

He and His disciples were Essenes, as was also the Baptist. That implies that He was no longer a Jew in the strict sense. His preaching dealt with the rights of man, and put forward socialistic and communistic demands: His religion in the pure consciousness of communion with God. With eschatology He had nothing whatever to do, it was first interpolated into His teaching by Matthew.

He and His disciples were Essenes, as was the Baptist. This suggests that He was no longer a Jew in the strict sense. His preaching focused on human rights and promoted socialist and communist ideas. His religion was rooted in a pure sense of connection with God. He had nothing to do with eschatology; that was first added to His teachings by Matthew.

The miracles are all to be explained by suggestion and hypnotism. At the marriage at Cana, Jesus noticed that the guests were taking too much, and therefore secretly bade the servants pour out water instead of wine while He Himself said, “Drink, this is better wine.” In this way He succeeded in suggesting to a part of the company that they were really drinking wine. The feeding of the multitude is explained by striking out a couple of noughts from the numbers; the raising of Lazarus by supposing it a case of premature burial. Jesus Himself when taken down from the cross was not dead, and the Essenes succeeded in reanimating Him. His work is inspired with hatred against Catholicism, but with a real reverence for Jesus.

The miracles can all be explained by suggestion and hypnosis. At the wedding in Cana, Jesus noticed that the guests were drinking too much, so He discreetly told the servants to pour out water instead of wine while He said, “Drink, this wine is better.” In this way, He managed to suggest to some of the guests that they were really drinking wine. The feeding of the multitude can be explained by just removing a couple of zeros from the numbers; the raising of Lazarus can be understood as a case of being buried too soon. When Jesus was taken down from the cross, He wasn't actually dead, and the Essenes were able to bring Him back to life. His work is driven by a dislike for Catholicism, but there is a genuine respect for Jesus.

Another mere variant of the plan of Venturini is the fictitious Life of Jesus of Pierre Nahor.255 The sentimental descriptions of nature and the long dialogues characteristic of the Lives of Jesus of a hundred years ago are here again in full force. After John had already begun to preach in the neighbourhood of the Dead Sea, Jesus, in company with a distinguished Brahmin who possessed property at Nazareth and had an influential following in Jerusalem, made a journey to Egypt and was there indoctrinated into all kinds of Egyptian, Essene, and Indian philosophy, thus giving the author, [pg 326] or rather the authoress, an opportunity to develop her ideas on the philosophy of religion in didactic dialogues. When He soon afterwards begins to work in Galilee the young teacher is much aided by the fact that, at the instance of His fellow-traveller, He had acquired from Egyptian mendicants a practical acquaintance with the secrets of hypnotism. By His skill He healed Mary of Magdala, a distinguished courtesan of Tiberias. They had met before at Alexandria. After being cured she left Tiberias and went to live in a small house, inherited from her mother, at Magdala.

Another version of Venturini's plan is the fictional Life of Jesus by Pierre Nahor.255 The emotional descriptions of nature and the lengthy dialogues typical of the Lives of Jesus a century ago are once again prominent. After John had already begun preaching near the Dead Sea, Jesus, along with a notable Brahmin who owned land in Nazareth and had a strong following in Jerusalem, traveled to Egypt. There, He was introduced to various Egyptian, Essene, and Indian philosophies, giving the author, [pg 326] or rather the authoress, a chance to explore her thoughts on the philosophy of religion through didactic dialogues. When He soon starts His work in Galilee, the young teacher benefits greatly from the fact that, at the suggestion of His traveling companion, He had learned practical techniques in hypnotism from Egyptian beggars. With this skill, He healed Mary of Magdala, a well-known courtesan from Tiberias. They had previously met in Alexandria. After her recovery, she left Tiberias and moved into a small house, inherited from her mother, in Magdala.

Jesus Himself never went to Tiberias, but the social world of that place took an interest in Him, and often had itself rowed to the beach when He was preaching. Rich and pious ladies used to inquire of Him where He thought of preaching to the people on a given day, and sent baskets of bread and dried fish to the spot which He indicated, that the multitude might not suffer hunger. This is the explanation of the stories about the feeding of the multitudes; the people had no idea whence Jesus suddenly obtained the supplies which He caused His disciples to distribute.

Jesus Himself never went to Tiberias, but the social scene there was interested in Him and often had boats rowed to the shore when He was preaching. Wealthy and devout women would ask Him where He planned to preach on a certain day and would send baskets of bread and dried fish to the location He indicated so the crowds wouldn’t go hungry. This explains the stories about feeding the multitudes; the people had no idea where Jesus suddenly got the supplies that He had His disciples hand out.

When he became aware that the priests had resolved upon His death, He made His friend Joseph of Arimathea, a leading man among the Essenes, promise that he would take Him down from the cross as soon as possible and lay Him in the grave without other witnesses. Only Nicodemus was to be present. On the cross He put Himself into a cataleptic trance; He was taken down from the cross seemingly dead, and came to Himself again in the grave. After appearing several times to His disciples he set out for Nazareth and dragged His way painfully thither. With a last effort He reaches the house of His mysterious old Indian teacher. At the door He falls helpless, just as the morning dawns. The old slave-woman recognises Him and carries Him into the house, where He dies. “The serene solemn night withdrew and day broke in blinding splendour behind Tiberias.”

When he realized that the priests had decided on His death, He made His friend Joseph of Arimathea, who was an important figure among the Essenes, promise to take Him down from the cross as soon as he could and lay Him in the grave with no other witnesses. Only Nicodemus was to be there. On the cross, He entered a cataleptic trance; He was taken down from the cross looking dead, and He came to consciousness again in the grave. After appearing several times to His disciples, He headed for Nazareth and struggled his way there painfully. With one last effort, He reached the home of His mysterious old Indian teacher. At the door, He collapses helplessly, just as dawn breaks. The old slave-woman recognizes Him and carries Him

Nikolas Notowitsch256 finds in Luke i. 80 (“And the child grew [pg 327] ... and was in the deserts until the day of his shewing unto Israel”) a “gap in the life of Jesus,” in spite of the fact that this passage refers to the Baptist, and proposes to fill it by putting Jesus to school with the Brahmins and Buddhists from His thirteenth to His twenty-ninth year. As evidence for this he refers to statements about Buddhist worship of a certain Issa which he professes to have found in the monasteries of Little Thibet. The whole thing is, as was shown by the experts, a barefaced swindle and an impudent invention.

Nikolas Notowitsch256 finds in Luke i. 80 (“And the child grew [pg 327] ... and lived in the deserts until the day he was revealed to Israel.”) a “gap in the life of Jesus,” even though this passage actually refers to the Baptist, and suggests to fill it by claiming that Jesus attended school with the Brahmins and Buddhists from the age of thirteen to twenty-nine. To back this up, he points to claims about Buddhist worship of a certain Issa, which he asserts to have discovered in the monasteries of Little Thibet. Experts have thoroughly shown that the entire thing is a blatant scam and an outrageous fabrication.


To the fictitious Lives of Jesus belong also in the main the theosophical “Lives,” which equally play fast and loose with the history, though here with a view to proving that Jesus had absorbed the Egyptian and Indian theosophy, and had been indoctrinated with “occult science.” The theosophists, however, have the advantage of escaping the dilemma between reanimation after a trance and resurrection, since they are convinced that it was possible for Jesus to reassume His body after He had really died. But in the touching up and embellishment of the Gospel narratives they out-do even the romancers.

To the fictional Lives of Jesus, the theosophical “Lives” also mainly belong, which also twist history, but here to argue that Jesus had absorbed Egyptian and Indian theosophy and had been taught “occult science.” However, the theosophists have the advantage of avoiding the conflict between coming back to life after a trance and resurrection since they believe it was possible for Jesus to take back His body after He actually died. But in enhancing and embellishing the Gospel stories, they outdo even the storytellers.

Ernest Bosc,257 writing as a theosophist, makes it the chief aim of his work to describe the oriental origin of Christianity, and ventures to assert that Jesus was not a Semite, but an Aryan. The Fourth Gospel is, of course, the basis of his representation. He does not hesitate, however, to appeal also to the anonymous “Revelations” published in 1849, which are a mere plagiarism from Venturini.

Ernest Bosc, 257 writing as a theosophist, makes it his main goal to explain the eastern roots of Christianity and boldly claims that Jesus was not a Semite but an Aryan. The Fourth Gospel serves as the foundation for his argument. However, he also doesn’t hesitate to reference the anonymous "Revelations" published in 1849, which are simply a copy of Venturini's work.

A work which is written with some ability and with much out-of-the-way learning is “Did Jesus live 100 b.c.?”258 The author compares the Christian tradition with the Jewish, and finds in the latter a reminiscence of a Jesus who lived in the time of Alexander Jannaeus (104-76 b.c.). This person was transferred by the earliest Evangelist to the later period, the attempt being facilitated by the fact that during the procuratorship of Pilate a false prophet had attracted some attention. The author, however, only professes to offer it as a hypothesis, and apologises in advance for the offence which it is likely to cause.

A work that's written with some skill and a lot of unusual knowledge is “Did Jesus live 100 B.C.?”258 The author compares Christian tradition with Jewish tradition and finds in the latter a hint of a Jesus who lived during the time of Alexander Jannaeus (104-76 b.c.). This figure was moved by the earliest Evangelist to a later time, with the idea being helped along by the fact that during Pilate's rule a false prophet had gained some attention. The author, however, only claims to present this as a hypothesis and apologizes in advance for any offense it may cause.

[pg 328]

XIX. Complete Skepticism and Complete Eschatology

W. Wrede. Das Messiasgeheimnis in den Evangelien. Zugleich ein Beitrag zum Verständnis des Markusevangeliums. (The Messianic Secret in the Gospels. Forming a contribution also to the understanding of the Gospel of Mark.) Göttingen, 1901. 286 pp.

W. Wrede. The Messianic Secret in the Gospels. A contribution to understanding the Gospel of Mark as well. Göttingen, 1901. 286 pages.

Albert Schweitzer. Das Messianitäts- und Leidensgeheimnis. Eine Skizze des Lebens Jesu. (The Secret of the Messiahship and the Passion. A Sketch of the Life of Jesus.) Tübingen and Leipzig, 1901. 109 pp.

Albert Schweitzer. The Secret of the Messiahship and the Passion: A Sketch of the Life of Jesus. Tübingen and Leipzig, 1901. 109 pages.

The coincidence between the work of Wrede259 and the “Sketch of the Life of Jesus” is not more surprising in regard to the time of their appearance than in regard to the character of their contents. They appeared upon the self-same day, their titles are almost identical, and their agreement in the criticism of the modern historical conception of the life of Jesus extends sometimes to the very phraseology. And yet they are written from quite different standpoints, one from the point of view of literary criticism, the other from that of the historical recognition of eschatology. It seems to be the fate of the Marcan hypothesis that at the decisive periods its problems should always be attacked simultaneously and independently from the literary and the historical sides, and the results declared in two different forms which corroborate each other. So it was in the case of Weisse and Wilke; so it is again now, when, retaining the assumption of the priority of Mark, the historicity of the hitherto accepted view of the life of Jesus, based upon the Marcan narrative, is called in question.

The coincidence between Wrede's work and the "Outline of the Life of Jesus" is just as striking in terms of their timing as it is in the nature of their content. They were released on the same day, their titles are nearly the same, and they even share similar criticisms of modern historical views on Jesus's life. Yet, they approach the topic from completely different perspectives—one looks at it through literary criticism, while the other focuses on the historical context of eschatology. It seems that the Marcan hypothesis often faces its major issues being tackled simultaneously and independently from both literary and historical angles, with results that confirm each other in distinct ways. This was the case with Weisse and Wilke, and it’s happening again now, as the assumption of Mark's priority is maintained while questioning the historicity of the previously accepted view of Jesus's life based on the Marcan narrative.

[pg 329]

The meaning of that is that the literary and the eschatological view, which have hitherto been marching parallel, on either flank, to the advance of modern theology, have now united their forces, brought theology to a halt, surrounded it, and compelled it to give battle.

The meaning of that is that the literary and the eschatological perspectives, which have previously been running alongside each other in the progress of modern theology, have now joined forces, halted theology's advance, surrounded it, and forced it into battle.

That in the last three or four years so much has been written in which this enveloping movement has been ignored does not alter the real position of modern historical theology in the least. The fact is deserving of notice that during this period the study of the subject has not made a step in advance, but has kept moving to and fro upon the old lines with wearisome iteration, and has thrown itself with excessive zeal into the work of popularisation, simply because it was incapable of advancing.

That in the last three or four years so much has been written while ignoring this overarching movement doesn’t change the actual state of modern historical theology at all. It's worth noting that during this time, the study of the subject hasn’t progressed at all, but has instead been stuck going back and forth on the same old paths, with frustrating repetition, and has thrown itself into the work of making it more accessible, simply because it couldn’t move forward.

And even if it professes gratitude to Wrede for the very interesting historical point which he has brought into the discussion, and is also willing to admit that thoroughgoing eschatology has advanced the solution of many problems, these are mere demonstrations which are quite inadequate to raise the blockade of modern theology by the allied forces. Supposing that only a half—nay, only a third—of the critical arguments which are common to Wrede and the “Sketch of the Life of Jesus” are sound, then the modern historical view of the history is wholly ruined.

And even if it expresses gratitude to Wrede for the interesting historical point he brought to the discussion, and is also willing to acknowledge that thorough eschatology has helped solve many problems, these are just gestures that are not enough to lift the blockade of modern theology by the allied forces. If only half—no, even just a third—of the critical arguments shared by Wrede and the "Overview of the Life of Jesus" are valid, then the modern historical perspective on history is completely compromised.

The reader of Wrede's book cannot help feeling that here no quarter is given; and any one who goes carefully through the present writer's “Sketch” must come to see that between the modern historical and the eschatological Life of Jesus no compromise is possible.

The reader of Wrede's book can't help but feel that no leniency is offered here; and anyone who carefully examines the current author's "Sketch" will come to realize that between the modern historical view and the eschatological Life of Jesus, there's no room for compromise.

Thoroughgoing scepticism and thoroughgoing eschatology may, in their union, either destroy, or be destroyed by modern historical theology; but they cannot combine with it and enable it to advance, any more than they can be advanced by it.

Thoroughgoing skepticism and thoroughgoing eschatology might, when combined, either undermine or be undermined by modern historical theology; but they can't work together to help it progress, just as they can't be helped to progress by it.

We are confronted with a decisive issue. As with Strauss's “Life of Jesus,” so with the surprising agreement in the critical basis of these two schools—we are not here considering the respective solutions which they offer—there has entered into the domain of the theology of the day a force with which it cannot possibly ally itself. Its whole territory is threatened. It must either reconquer it step by step or else surrender it. It has no longer the right to advance a single assertion until it has taken up a definite position in regard to the fundamental questions raised by the new criticism.

We are faced with a crucial issue. Just like Strauss's "Life of Jesus," the surprising similarities in the critical foundations of these two schools reveal that we are not looking at the different solutions they propose—there's a force in today's theology that it can't possibly align with. The entire area is under threat. It must either gradually reclaim it or give it up entirely. It no longer has the right to make any claims until it has clearly addressed the fundamental questions posed by the new criticism.

Modern historical theology is no doubt still far from recognising this. It is warned that the dyke is letting in water and sends a couple of masons to repair the leak; as if the leak did not mean that the whole masonry is undermined, and must be rebuilt from the foundation.

Modern historical theology still hasn’t fully acknowledged this. It’s like being warned that the dam is leaking and then sending a few workers to patch it up; as if that leak doesn’t indicate that the entire structure is compromised and needs to be rebuilt from the ground up.

[pg 330]

To vary the metaphor, theology comes home to find the broker's marks on all the furniture and goes on as before quite comfortably, ignoring the fact it will lose everything if it does not pay its debts.

To change the metaphor, theology comes home to discover the broker's marks on all the furniture and continues on as usual, comfortably ignoring the fact that it will lose everything if it doesn't pay its debts.

The critical objections which Wrede and the “Sketch” agree in bringing against the modern treatment of the subject are as follows.

The key criticisms that Wrede and the "Draft" both raise against the modern approach to the topic are as follows.

In order to find in Mark the Life of Jesus of which it is in search, modern theology is obliged to read between the lines a whole host of things, and those often the most important, and then to foist them upon the text by means of psychological conjecture. It is determined to find evidence in Mark of a development of Jesus, a development of the disciples, and a development of the outer circumstances; and professes in so doing to be only reproducing the views and indications of the Evangelist. In reality, however, there is not a word of all this in the Evangelist, and when his interpreters are asked what are the hints and indications on which they base their assertions they have nothing to offer save argumenta e silentio.

To find in Mark the life of Jesus they seek, modern theology has to read between the lines and interpret a lot of things, often the most crucial ones, and then impose them on the text using psychological speculation. It aims to find evidence in Mark for Jesus' development, the disciples' growth, and the changing circumstances; and claims that it is simply reflecting the views and indications of the Evangelist. In reality, however, there’s not a single word of this in the Evangelist, and when interpreters are asked what hints and indications they rely on for their claims, they have nothing to offer except arguments from silence.

Mark knows nothing of any development in Jesus; he knows nothing of any paedagogic considerations which are supposed to have determined the conduct of Jesus towards the disciples and the people; he knows nothing of any conflict in the mind of Jesus between a spiritual and a popular, political Messianic ideal; he does not know, either, that in this respect there was any difference between the view of Jesus and that of the people; he knows nothing of the idea that the use of the ass at the triumphal entry symbolised a non-political Messiahship; he knows nothing of the idea that the question about the Messiah's being the Son of David had something to do with this alternative between political and non-political; he does not know, either, that Jesus explained the secret of the passion to the disciples, nor that they had any understanding of it; he only knows that from first to last they were in all respects equally wanting in understanding; he does not know that the first period was a period of success and the second a period of failure; he represents the Pharisees and Herodians as (from iii. 6 onwards) resolved upon the death of Jesus, while the people, down to the very last day when He preached in the temple, are enthusiastically loyal to Him.

Mark knows nothing about any developments in Jesus’ life; he knows nothing about any educational factors that were supposed to influence Jesus' behavior toward his disciples and the people; he doesn’t realize there was any internal conflict for Jesus between a spiritual view and a more popular, political view of being the Messiah; he doesn’t understand that there was any difference between how Jesus viewed things and how the people did; he doesn’t grasp that using a donkey during the triumphal entry symbolized a non-political Messiah; he doesn’t recognize that the question of whether the Messiah should be the Son of David was related to this choice between political and non-political; he doesn’t know that Jesus revealed the meaning of the passion to the disciples, nor does he know if they understood it; he only knows that overall, they lacked understanding from beginning to end; he doesn’t realize that the first period was a time of success and the second a time of failure; he portrays the Pharisees and Herodians as (from iii. 6 onward) determined to have Jesus killed, while the people remained passionately loyal to Him right up to the last day He preached in the temple.

All these things of which the Evangelist says nothing—and they are the foundations of the modern view—should first be proved, if proved they can be; they ought not to be simply read into the text as something self-evident. For it is just those things which appear so self-evident to the prevailing critical temper which are in reality the least evident of all.

All these things that the Evangelist doesn’t mention—and they form the basis of the modern perspective—should be established, if they can be, rather than just assumed to be obvious from the text. It's those aspects that seem so obvious to the current critical mindset that are actually the least clear of all.

Another hitherto self-evident point—the “historical kernel” which it has been customary to extract from the narratives—must [pg 331] be given up, until it is proved, if it is capable of proof, that we can and ought to distinguish between the kernel and the husk. We may take all that is reported as either historical or unhistorical, but, in respect of the definite predictions of the passion, death, and resurrection, we ought to give up taking the reference to the passion as historical and letting the rest go; we may accept the idea of the atoning death, or we may reject it, but we ought not to ascribe to Jesus a feeble, anaemic version of this idea, while setting down to the account of the Pauline theology the interpretation of the passion which we actually find in Mark.

Another previously obvious point—the “historical core” that has typically been extracted from the narratives—must [pg 331] be reconsidered until it can be demonstrated, if it can be proven, that we can and should differentiate between the kernel and the husk. We may accept everything that is reported as either historical or unhistorical, but regarding the specific predictions of the passion, death, and resurrection, we should stop considering the reference to the passion as historical while disregarding the rest; we might accept the concept of the atoning death, or we might reject it, but we shouldn't attribute to Jesus a weak, simplified version of this idea while crediting Pauline theology with the interpretation of the passion that we actually find in Mark.

Whatever the results obtained by the aid of the historical kernel, the method pursued is the same; “it is detached from its context and transformed into something different.” “It finally comes to this,” says Wrede, “that each critic retains whatever portion of the traditional sayings can be fitted into his construction of the facts and his conception of historical possibility and rejects the rest.” The psychological explanation of motive, and the psychological connexion of the events and actions which such critics have proposed to find in Mark, simply do not exist. That being so, nothing is to be made out of his account by the application of a priori psychology. A vast quantity of treasures of scholarship and erudition, of art and artifice, which the Marcan hypothesis has gathered into its storehouse in the two generations of its existence to aid it in constructing its life of Jesus has become worthless, and can be of no further service to true historical research. Theology has been simplified. What would become of it if that did not happen every hundred years or so? And the simplification was badly needed, for no one since Strauss had cleared away its impedimenta.

No matter what results come from the historical kernel, the method used remains the same; "It's removed from its context and transformed into something different." "It really comes down to this," says Wrede, “Each critic retains the parts of traditional sayings that align with their version of the facts and their perspective on historical possibilities, discarding the rest.” The psychological explanation of motives and the psychological connections of the events and actions that these critics have tried to find in Mark simply do not exist. Therefore, no value can be derived from his account by using a priori psychology. A huge amount of scholarly resources and knowledge, along with art and trickery that the Marcan hypothesis has accumulated over the past two generations to help construct its narrative of Jesus, has become worthless and can't assist true historical research anymore. Theology has been simplified. What would happen if that didn't occur every hundred years or so? And the simplification was necessary, as no one since Strauss had cleared away its obstacles.

Thoroughgoing scepticism and thoroughgoing eschatology, between them, are compelling theology to read the Marcan text again with simplicity of mind. The simplicity consists in dispensing with the connecting links which it has been accustomed to discover between the sections of the narrative (pericopes), in looking at each one separately, and recognising that it is difficult to pass from one to the other.

Thorough skepticism and thorough eschatology together create a strong reason to read the Marcan text again with a clear mind. This clarity means getting rid of the connections we usually find between the sections of the narrative (passages), examining each one individually, and acknowledging that it's hard to transition from one to the next.

The material with which it has hitherto been usual to solder the sections together into a life of Jesus will not stand the temperature test. Exposed to the cold air of critical scepticism it cracks; when the furnace of eschatology is heated to a certain point the solderings melt. In both cases the sections all fall apart.

The material that has been commonly used to piece together a life of Jesus won't hold up under scrutiny. When faced with the chill of critical skepticism, it breaks; when the heat of eschatology reaches a certain level, the bonds come undone. In both instances, the sections completely fall apart.

Formerly it was possible to book through-tickets at the supplementary-psychological-knowledge office which enabled those travelling in the interests of Life-of-Jesus construction to use express trains, thus avoiding the inconvenience of having to stop at every little station, change, and run the risk of missing their [pg 332] connexion. This ticket office is now closed. There is a station at the end of each section of the narrative, and the connexions are not guaranteed.

Previously, you could purchase through-tickets at the supplementary psychological knowledge office, which allowed those traveling for the purpose of Life-of-Jesus construction to take express trains, avoiding the hassle of stopping at every small station, changing trains, and the risk of missing their [pg 332] connection. This ticket office is now closed. There is a station at the end of each part of the narrative, and connections are not guaranteed.

The fact is, it is not simply that there is no very obvious psychological connexion between the sections; in almost every case there is a positive break in the connexion. And there is a great deal in the Marcan narrative which is inexplicable and even self-contradictory.

The truth is, it’s not just that there isn’t a clear psychological connection between the sections; in nearly every case, there’s a definite break in the connection. There’s also a lot in the Marcan narrative that is puzzling and even contradictory.

In their statement of the problems raised by this want of connexion Wrede and the “Sketch” are in the most exact agreement. That these difficulties are not artificially constructed has been shown by our survey of the history of the attempts to write the Life of Jesus, in the course of which these problems emerge one after another, after Bruno Bauer had by anticipation grasped them all in their complexity.

In their statement about the issues caused by this lack of connection, Wrede and the "Draft" completely agree. Our examination of the history of efforts to write the Life of Jesus has demonstrated that these difficulties are real and not artificially created, as these problems come up one after the other, all of which Bruno Bauer had already understood in their complexity.

How do the demoniacs know that Jesus is the Son of God? Why does the blind man at Jericho address Him as the Son of David, when no one else knows His Messianic dignity? How was it that these occurrences did not give a new direction to the thoughts of the people in regard to Jesus? How did the Messianic entry come about? How was it possible without provoking the interference of the Roman garrison of occupation? Why is it as completely ignored in the subsequent controversies as if had never taken place? Why was it not brought up at the trial of Jesus? “The Messianic acclamation at the entry into Jerusalem,” says Wrede, “is in Mark quite an isolated incident. It has no sequel, neither is there any preparation for it beforehand.”

How do the demoniacs know that Jesus is the Son of God? Why does the blind man at Jericho call Him the Son of David when no one else recognizes His Messianic status? Why didn't these events change how people thought about Jesus? How did the Messianic entry happen? How was it possible without provoking the Roman occupation forces? Why is it completely ignored in later debates as if it never happened? Why wasn't it mentioned during Jesus' trial? "The Messianic shout of praise when entering Jerusalem," says Wrede, "Mark portrays this as a pretty isolated event. There’s no follow-up, and there’s no setup for it before it happens."

Why does Jesus in Mark iv. 10-12 speak of the parabolic form of discourse as designed to conceal the mystery of the Kingdom of God, whereas the explanation which He proceeds to give to the disciples has nothing mysterious about it? What is the mystery of the Kingdom of God? Why does Jesus forbid His miracles to be made known even in cases where there is no apparent purpose for the prohibition? Why is His Messiahship a secret and yet no secret, since it is known, not only to the disciples, but to the demoniacs, the blind man at Jericho, the multitude at Jerusalem—which must, as Bruno Bauer expresses it, “have fallen from heaven”—and to the High Priest?

Why does Jesus in Mark 4:10-12 refer to the parabolic way of speaking as meant to hide the mystery of the Kingdom of God, while the explanation He gives to the disciples is straightforward? What is the mystery of the Kingdom of God? Why does Jesus prevent His miracles from being shared even when there seems to be no clear reason for this restriction? Why is His role as the Messiah both a secret and not a secret, since it is known not only to the disciples but also to the demon-possessed, the blind man in Jericho, the crowd in Jerusalem—which must, as Bruno Bauer puts it, "have fallen from the sky"—and to the High Priest?

Why does Jesus first reveal His Messiahship to the disciples at Caesarea Philippi, not at the moment when He sends them forth to preach? How does Peter know without having been told by Jesus that the Messiahship belongs to his Master? Why must it remain a secret until the “resurrection”? Why does Jesus indicate His Messiahship only by the title Son of Man? And why is it that this title is so far from prominent in primitive Christian theology?

Why does Jesus first reveal that He is the Messiah to the disciples at Caesarea Philippi, instead of when He sends them out to preach? How does Peter know, without being told by Jesus, that the title of Messiah belongs to his Master? Why does it have to remain a secret until the "revival"? Why does Jesus only refer to His Messiahship with the title Son of Man? And why is this title not more prominent in early Christian theology?

[pg 333]

What is the meaning of the statement that Jesus at Jerusalem discovered a difficulty in the fact that the Messiah was described as at once David's son and David's Lord? How are we to explain the fact that Jesus had to open the eyes of the people to the greatness of the Baptist's office, subsequently to the mission of the Twelve, and to enlighten the disciples themselves in regard to it during the descent from the mount of transfiguration? Why should this be described in Matt. xi. 14 and 15 as a mystery difficult to grasp (“If ye can receive it” ... “He that hath ears to hear, let him hear”)? What is the meaning of the saying that he that is least in the Kingdom of Heaven is greater than the Baptist? Does the Baptist, then, not enter into the Kingdom of Heaven? How is the Kingdom of Heaven subjected to violence since the days of the Baptist? Who are the violent? What is the Baptist intended to understand from the answer of Jesus?

What does it mean when Jesus, in Jerusalem, pointed out the challenge of the fact that the Messiah is referred to as both David's son and David's Lord? How can we explain that Jesus had to open people's eyes to the significance of John the Baptist's role, after sending out the Twelve, and also enlighten the disciples about it during the descent from the Mount of Transfiguration? Why is this described in Matt. xi. 14 and 15 as a hard-to-understand mystery (“If you can accept it” ... “Let anyone with ears listen”)? What does it mean when it's said that the least in the Kingdom of Heaven is greater than the Baptist? Does this imply that the Baptist does not enter the Kingdom of Heaven? How has the Kingdom of Heaven been subjected to violence since the days of the Baptist? Who are the violent? What is the message that Jesus wants John the Baptist to understand from His answer?

What importance was attached to the miracles by Jesus Himself? What office must they have caused the people to attribute to Him? Why is the discourse at the sending out of the Twelve filled with predictions of persecutions which experience had given no reason to anticipate, and which did not, as a matter of fact, occur? What is the meaning of the saying in Matt. x. 23 about the imminent coming of the Son of Man, seeing that the disciples after all returned to Jesus without its being fulfilled? Why does Jesus leave the people just when His work among them is most successful, and journey northwards? Why had He, immediately after the sending forth of the Twelve, manifested a desire to withdraw Himself from the multitude who were longing for salvation?

What significance did Jesus Himself attach to the miracles? What role must they have led people to assign to Him? Why does the speech during the sending out of the Twelve contain predictions of persecutions that experience didn’t suggest would happen, and which, in fact, didn’t occur? What does the saying in Matt. x. 23 about the imminent coming of the Son of Man mean, considering that the disciples ultimately returned to Jesus without it being fulfilled? Why does Jesus leave the people when His work among them is most successful and head north? Why did He, right after sending out the Twelve, express a desire to withdraw from the crowd that was eager for salvation?

How does the multitude mentioned in Mark viii. 34 suddenly appear at Caesarea Philippi? Why is its presence no longer implied in Mark ix. 30? How could Jesus possibly have travelled unrecognised through Galilee, and how could He have avoided being thronged in Capernaum although He stayed at “the house”?

How does the crowd mentioned in Mark 8:34 suddenly show up at Caesarea Philippi? Why isn’t its presence mentioned in Mark 9:30? How could Jesus travel through Galilee without being recognized, and how did He manage to not be overwhelmed in Capernaum even though He stayed at “the home”?

How came He so suddenly to speak to His disciples of His suffering and dying and rising again, without, moreover, explaining to them either the natural or the moral “wherefore”? “There is no trace of any attempt on the part of Jesus,” says Wrede, “to break this strange thought gradually to His disciples ... the prediction is always flung down before the disciples without preparation, it is, in fact, a characteristic feature of these sayings that all attempt to aid the understanding of the disciples is lacking.”

How did He suddenly start talking to His disciples about His suffering, death, and resurrection, without explaining to them the natural or moral reasons behind it? “There is no sign that Jesus,” Wrede says, “tried to gradually introduce this strange idea to His disciples ... the prediction is always thrown at the disciples without any preparation; in fact, a defining characteristic of these statements is that there’s no attempt to help the disciples understand.”

Did Jesus journey to Jerusalem with the purpose of working there, or of dying there? How comes it that in Mark x. 39, He holds out to the sons of Zebedee the prospect of drinking His [pg 334] cup and being baptized with His baptism? And how can He, after speaking so decidedly of the necessity of His death, think it possible in Gethsemane that the cup might yet pass from Him? Who are the undefined “many,” for whom, according to Mark x. 45 and xiv. 24, His death shall serve as a ransom?260

Did Jesus go to Jerusalem to do work there or to die there? Why does He, in Mark 10:39, offer the sons of Zebedee the chance to drink from His cup and be baptized with His baptism? And how can He, after clearly stating the necessity of His death, believe in Gethsemane that the cup might still be taken away from Him? Who are the unspecified “many” that, according to Mark 10:45 and 14:24, His death will redeem?

How came it that Jesus alone was arrested? Why were no witnesses called at His trial to testify that He had given Himself out to be the Messiah? How is it that on the morning after His arrest the temper of the multitude seems to be completely changed, so that no one stirs a finger to help Him?

How is it that Jesus was the only one arrested? Why weren't there any witnesses brought in during His trial to say that He claimed to be the Messiah? How come, on the morning after His arrest, the mood of the crowd seems to have completely shifted, so that no one lifts a finger to help Him?

In what form does Jesus conceive the resurrection, which He promises to His disciples, to be combined with the coming on the clouds of heaven, to which He points His judge? In what relation do these predictions stand to the prospect held out at the time of the sending forth of the Twelve, but not realized, of the immediate appearance of the Son of Man?

In what way does Jesus envision the resurrection, which He promises His disciples, to be linked with His arrival on the clouds of heaven, to which He refers when judging? How do these predictions relate to the expectation presented when the Twelve were sent out, but which didn’t happen, of the Son of Man’s immediate return?

What is the meaning of the further prediction on the way to Gethsemane (Mark xiv. 28) that after His resurrection He will go before the disciples into Galilee? How is the other version of this saying (Mark xvi. 7) to be explained, according to which it means, as spoken by the angel, that the disciples are to journey to Galilee to have their first meeting with the risen Jesus there, whereas, on the lips of Jesus, it betokened that, just as now as a sufferer He was going before them from Galilee to Jerusalem, so, after His resurrection, He would go before them from Jerusalem to Galilee? And what was to happen there?

What does the prediction about the journey to Gethsemane (Mark xiv. 28) mean, where it says that after His resurrection, He will lead the disciples to Galilee? How do we understand the other version of this message (Mark xvi. 7), which the angel says means that the disciples should go to Galilee for their first meeting with the risen Jesus? In contrast, when spoken by Jesus, it indicates that just as He is currently leading them from Galilee to Jerusalem as a sufferer, after His resurrection, He will lead them from Jerusalem back to Galilee. And what is supposed to happen there?

These problems were covered up by the naturalistic psychology as by a light snow-drift. The snow has melted, and they now stand out from the narratives like black points of rock. It is no longer allowable to avoid these questions, or to solve them, each by itself, by softening them down and giving them an interpretation by which the reported facts acquire a quite different significance from that which they bear for the Evangelist. Either the Marcan text as it stands is historical, and therefore to be retained, or it is not, and then it should be given up. What is really unhistorical is any softening down of the wording, and the meaning which it naturally bears.

These issues were hidden by naturalistic psychology, like a light layer of snow. Now that the snow has melted, they stand out in the narratives like dark rocks. We can no longer avoid these questions or address them separately by downplaying them and interpreting them in a way that gives the reported facts a completely different meaning than what they actually hold for the Evangelist. Either the Marcan text as it is should be considered historical and therefore kept, or it should be rejected if it isn’t. What is truly unhistorical is any attempt to soften the wording and the meaning it naturally carries.

The sceptical and eschatological schools, however, go still farther in company. If the connexion in Mark is really no connexion, it is important to try to discover whether any principle can be discovered in this want of connexion. Can any order be brought into the chaos? To this the answer is in the affirmative.

The skeptical and eschatological schools, however, go even further together. If the connection in Mark is truly not a connection, it's important to explore whether there’s any principle behind this lack of connection. Can we make sense of the chaos? The answer to that is yes.

The complete want of connexion, with all its self-contradictions, is ultimately due to the fact that two representations of the life of [pg 335] Jesus, or, to speak more accurately, of His public ministry, are here crushed into one; a natural and a deliberately supernatural representation. A dogmatic element has intruded itself into the description of this Life—something which has no concern with the events which form the outward course of that Life. This dogmatic element is the Messianic secret of Jesus and all the secrets and concealments which go along with it.

The complete lack of connection, with all its contradictions, ultimately stems from the fact that two portrayals of Jesus’ life, or more precisely, His public ministry, are forced together into one; a natural representation and a deliberately supernatural one. A dogmatic aspect has inserted itself into the narrative of this Life—something that has nothing to do with the events that outline that Life. This dogmatic aspect is the Messianic secret of Jesus along with all the secrets and concealments that come with it.

Hence the irrational and self-contradictory features of the presentation of Jesus, out of which a rational psychology can make only something which is unhistorical and does violence to the text, since it must necessarily get rid of the constant want of connexion and self-contradiction which belongs to the essence of the narrative, and portray a Jesus who was the Messiah, not one who at once was and was not Messiah, as the Evangelist depicts Him. When rational psychology conceives Him as one who was Messiah, but not in the sense expected by the people, that is a concession to the self-contradictions of the Marcan representation; which, however, does justice neither to the text nor to the history which it records, since the Gospel does not contain the faintest hint that the contradiction was of this nature.

Therefore, the irrational and self-contradictory aspects of how Jesus is presented lead to interpretations that are unhistorical and distort the text. This is because such interpretations must ignore the ongoing lack of connection and contradictions that are fundamental to the narrative. They end up portraying Jesus as the Messiah, rather than as the figure who is both a Messiah and not a Messiah, as the Evangelist describes Him. When rational psychology views Him as a Messiah but not in the way the people expected, it only acknowledges the contradictions within Mark's depiction. However, this does not accurately reflect the text or the history it records, since the Gospel provides no indication that the contradiction is of this kind.

Up to this point—up to the complete reconstruction of the system which runs through the disconnectedness, and the tracing back of the dogmatic element to the Messianic secret—there extends a close agreement between thoroughgoing scepticism and thoroughgoing eschatology. The critical arguments are identical, the construction is analogous and based on the same principle. The defenders of the modern psychological view cannot, therefore, play off one school against the other, as one of them proposed to do, but must deal with them both at once. They differ only when they explain whence the system that runs through the disconnectedness comes. Here the ways divide, as Bauer saw long ago. The inconsistency between the public life of Jesus and His Messianic claim lies either in the nature of the Jewish Messianic conception, or in the representation of the Evangelist. There is, on the one hand, the eschatological solution, which at one stroke raises the Marcan account as it stands, with all its disconnectedness and inconsistencies, into genuine history; and there is, on the other hand, the literary solution, which regards the incongruous dogmatic element as interpolated by the earliest Evangelist into the tradition and therefore strikes out the Messianic claim altogether from the historical Life of Jesus. Tertium non datur.

Up to this point—up until the complete reconstruction of the system that runs through the disconnectedness and tracing the dogmatic element back to the Messianic secret—there is a strong agreement between radical skepticism and radical eschatology. The critical arguments are the same, and the structure is similar, based on the same principle. Therefore, supporters of the modern psychological perspective cannot pit one school against the other, as one proposed, but must engage with them both simultaneously. They only differ in how they explain where the system that runs through the disconnectedness comes from. This is where the paths diverge, as Bauer pointed out long ago. The inconsistency between Jesus' public life and His Messianic claim stems either from the nature of the Jewish Messianic concept or from the Evangelist's portrayal. On one hand, there's the eschatological solution, which elevates the Marcan account as it is, with all its disconnections and contradictions, into actual history; and on the other hand, there's the literary solution, which sees the incongruous dogmatic element as added by the earliest Evangelist into the tradition and thus completely removes the Messianic claim from the historical life of Jesus. No third option.

But in some respects it really hardly matters which of the two “solutions” one adopts. They are both merely wooden towers erected upon the solid main building of the consentient critical induction which offers the enigmas detailed above to modern historical theology. It is interesting in this connexion that Wrede's [pg 336] scepticism is just as constructive as the eschatological outline of the Life of Jesus in the “Sketch.”

But in some ways, it really doesn’t matter which of the two "solutions" you choose. They are both just makeshift structures built on the solid foundation of the shared critical insights that present the puzzles mentioned earlier to modern historical theology. It's interesting in this context that Wrede's [pg 336] skepticism is just as constructive as the eschatological framework in the Life of Jesus in the "Draw."

Bruno Bauer chose the literary solution because he thought that we had no evidence for an eschatological expectation existing in the time of Christ. Wrede, though he follows Johannes Weiss in assuming the existence of a Jewish eschatological Messianic expectation, finds in the Gospel only the Christian conception of the Messiah. “If Jesus,” he thinks, “really knew Himself to be the Messiah and designated Himself as such, the genuine tradition is so closely interwoven with later accretions that it is not easy to recognise it.” In any case, Jesus cannot, according to Wrede, have spoken of His Messianic Coming in the way which the Synoptists report. The Messiahship of Jesus, as we find it in the Gospels, is a product of Early Christian theology correcting history according to its own conceptions.

Bruno Bauer chose the literary approach because he believed there was no evidence of an eschatological expectation during the time of Christ. Wrede, while following Johannes Weiss in believing there was a Jewish eschatological Messianic expectation, finds that the Gospel only reflects the Christian view of the Messiah. “If Jesus,” he argues, "He truly saw Himself as the Messiah and called Himself that way; the genuine tradition is so mixed with later additions that it's difficult to pinpoint it." In any case, according to Wrede, Jesus could not have spoken of His Messianic Coming in the way the Synoptists describe. The concept of Jesus' Messiahship, as we see it in the Gospels, is a result of early Christian theology reshaping history according to its own ideas.

It is therefore necessary to distinguish in Mark between the reported events which constitute the outward course of the history of Jesus, and the dogmatic idea which claims to lay down the lines of its inward course. The principle of division is found in the contradictions.

It is therefore necessary to distinguish in Mark between the events that are reported which make up the external history of Jesus, and the doctrinal idea that aims to outline its internal development. The basis for this division is found in the contradictions.

The recorded events form, according to Wrede, the following picture. Jesus came forward as a teacher,261 first and principally in Galilee. He was surrounded by a company of disciples, went about with them, and gave them instruction. To some of them He accorded a special confidence. A larger multitude sometimes attached itself to Him, in addition to the disciples. He is fond of discoursing in parables. Besides the teaching there are the miracles. These make a stir, and He is thronged by the multitudes. He gives special attention to the cases of demoniacs. He is in such close touch with the people that He does not hesitate to associate even with publicans and sinners. Towards the Law He takes up an attitude of some freedom. He encounters the opposition of the Pharisees and the Jewish authorities. They set traps for Him and endeavour to bring about His fall. Finally they succeed, when He ventures to show Himself not only on Judaean soil, but in Jerusalem. He remains passive and is condemned to death. The Roman administration supports the Jewish authorities.

The recorded events create, according to Wrede, the following picture. Jesus stepped forward as a teacher, primarily in Galilee. He was surrounded by a group of disciples, traveled with them, and taught them. He granted a special trust to some of them. Sometimes, a larger crowd also gathered around Him, in addition to the disciples. He often shared teachings in parables. Along with the teaching, there were miracles. These created a buzz, and crowds flocked to Him. He paid special attention to cases of those possessed by demons. He connected so closely with the people that He didn’t hesitate to associate with tax collectors and sinners. He took a somewhat relaxed approach to the Law. He faced opposition from the Pharisees and the Jewish authorities, who set traps for Him and tried to bring about His downfall. They eventually succeeded when He chose to appear not just in Judea, but in Jerusalem. He remained passive and was sentenced to death. The Roman authorities backed the Jewish leaders.

“The texture of the Marcan narrative as we know it,” continues Wrede, “is not complete until to the warp of these general historical notions there is added a strong weft of ideas of a dogmatic character,” the substance of which is that “Jesus, the bearer of a special office to which He was appointed by God,” becomes “a higher, superhuman being.” If this is the case, however, then the motives of His conduct are not derived from human characteristics, human aims and necessities. “The one [pg 337] motive which runs throughout is rather a Divine decree which lies beyond human understanding. This He seeks to fulfil alike in His actions and His sufferings. The teaching of Jesus is accordingly supernatural.” On this assumption the want of understanding of the disciples to whom He communicates, without commentary, unconnected portions of this supernatural knowledge becomes natural and explicable. The people are, moreover, essentially “non-receptive of revelation.”

"The texture of the Marcan story as we understand it," Wrede continues, “is not complete until, along with these general historical concepts, a strong thread of dogmatic ideas is added,” which suggest that "Jesus, selected for a special purpose by God," becomes “an elevated, superhuman being.” If this is true, then His actions are not motivated by human traits, goals, or needs. The main motive that runs throughout is more of a Divine decree that goes beyond human understanding. He aims to fulfill this in both His actions and His sufferings. So, the teachings of Jesus are essentially supernatural. Based on this premise, the disciples' lack of understanding as He shares unconnected pieces of this supernatural knowledge without explanation makes sense. Additionally, people are fundamentally "resistant to revelation."

“It is these motifs and not those which are inherently historical which give movement and direction to the Marcan narrative. It is they that give the general colour. On them naturally depends the main interest, it is to them that the thought of the writer is really directed. The consequence is that the general picture offered by the Gospel is not an historical representation of the Life of Jesus. Only some faded remnants of such an impression have been taken over into a supra-historical religious view. In this sense the Gospel of Mark belongs to the history of dogma.”

“It’s these motifs rather than the strictly historical ones that give movement and direction to the Marcan narrative. They establish the overall mood. The main focus lies on them, and the writer's thoughts are mainly directed towards them. Consequently, the overall picture offered by the Gospel doesn't accurately reflect Jesus's life. Only a few faint traces of that impression have been included in a broader religious context. In this way, the Gospel of Mark is part of the history of doctrine.”

The two conceptions of the Life of Jesus, the natural and the supernatural, are brought, not without inconsistencies, into a kind of harmony by means of the idea of intentional secrecy. The Messiahship of Jesus is concealed in His life as in a closed dark lantern, which, however, is not quite closed—otherwise one could not see that it was there—and allows a few bright beams to escape.

The two views of Jesus' life, the natural and the supernatural, are brought together, though not without contradictions, through the idea of intentional secrecy. Jesus' role as the Messiah is hidden in His life like a closed dark lantern, which isn’t completely shut—otherwise, we wouldn't know it exists—and it lets a few bright rays shine through.

The idea of a secret which must remain a secret until the resurrection of Jesus could only arise at a time when nothing was known of a Messianic claim of Jesus during His life upon earth: that is to say, at a time when the Messiahship of Jesus was thought of as beginning with the resurrection. But that is a weighty piece of indirect historical evidence that Jesus did not really profess to be the Messiah at all.

The concept of a secret that must stay hidden until the resurrection of Jesus could only come about at a time when no one was aware of any claims to Messiahship by Jesus during His life on earth. In other words, it emerged at a time when Jesus's role as the Messiah was believed to start only with the resurrection. This serves as significant indirect historical evidence that Jesus didn't actually claim to be the Messiah at all.

The positive fact which is to be inferred from this is that the appearances of the risen Jesus produced a sudden revolution in His disciples' conception of Him. “The resurrection” is for Wrede the real Messianic event in the Life of Jesus.

The important takeaway from this is that the appearances of the risen Jesus caused a dramatic shift in how His disciples viewed Him. "The resurrection" is, for Wrede, the true Messianic event in the life of Jesus.

Who is responsible, then, for introducing this singular feature, so destructive of the real historical connexion, into the life of Jesus, which was in reality that of a teacher? It is quite impossible, Wrede argues, that the idea of the Messianic secret is the invention of Mark. “A thing like that is not done by a single individual. It must, therefore, have been a view which was current in certain circles, and was held by a considerable number, though not necessarily perhaps by a very great number of persons. To say this is not to deny that Mark had a share and perhaps a considerable share in the creation of the view which he sets forth ... the motifs themselves are doubtless not, in part at least, [pg 338] peculiar to the Evangelist, but the concrete embodiment of them is certainly his own work; and to this extent we may speak of a special Marcan point of view which manifests itself here and there. Where the line is to be drawn between what is traditional and what is individual cannot always be determined even by a careful examination directed to this end. We must leave it commingled, as we find it.”

Who is responsible for introducing this unique aspect, which disrupts the true historical connection, into the life of Jesus, who was essentially a teacher? Wrede argues that it’s impossible for the concept of the Messianic secret to be solely Mark's creation. "Something like this doesn’t come from just one person. It must have been an idea that was common in certain circles and accepted by a decent number of people, though not necessarily by a large crowd. Saying this doesn’t mean Mark didn’t have a role, maybe even a big one, in shaping the view he shares... the motifs themselves are likely, at least in part, [pg 338] not exclusive to the Evangelist, but the specific way he presents them is definitely his own work; and in that sense, we can discuss a unique Marcan perspective that shows up here and there. Figuring out where to draw the line between what is traditional and what is personal isn’t always clear, even with careful analysis aimed at that goal. We need to accept it as a mix, just as we find it."

The Marcan narrative has therefore arisen from the impulse to give a Messianic form to the earthly life of Jesus. This impulse was, however, restrained by the impression and tradition of the non-Messianic character of the life of Jesus, which were still strong and vivid, and it was therefore not able wholly to recast the material, but could only bore its way into it and force it apart, as the roots of the bramble disintegrate a rock. In the Gospel literature which arose on the basis of Mark the Messianic secret becomes gradually of more subordinate importance and the life of Jesus more Messianic in character, until in the Fourth Gospel He openly comes before the people with Messianic claims.

The Marcan narrative came about from the desire to present Jesus' earthly life in a Messianic way. However, this desire was held back by the strong impressions and traditions of Jesus' non-Messianic life, which were still vivid and influential. As a result, it couldn't completely transform the material but instead had to push its way through and break it apart, similar to how the roots of a bramble can break down a rock. In the Gospel literature that developed from Mark, the Messianic secret gradually becomes less important, while Jesus' life takes on a more Messianic character, until in the Fourth Gospel, He openly presents Himself to the people with Messianic claims.

In estimating the value of this construction we must not attach too much importance to its a priori assumptions and difficulties. In this respect Wrede's position is much more precarious than that of his precursor Bruno Bauer. According to the latter the interpolation of the Messianic secret is the personal, absolutely original act of the Evangelist. Wrede thinks of it as a collective act, representing the new conception as moulded by the tradition before it was fixed by the Evangelist. That is very much more difficult to carry through. Tradition alters its materials in a different way from that in which we find them altered in Mark. Tradition transforms from without. Mark's way of drawing secret threads of a different material through the texture of the tradition, without otherwise altering it, is purely literary, and could only be the work of an individual person.

In evaluating the value of this construction, we shouldn't place too much importance on its initial assumptions and challenges. In this regard, Wrede's stance is much more vulnerable than that of his predecessor, Bruno Bauer. According to Bauer, the addition of the Messianic secret is the personal, entirely original act of the Evangelist. Wrede views it as a collective effort, reflecting a new understanding shaped by the tradition before it was established by the Evangelist. That's a lot more complex to execute. Tradition changes its materials differently than how we see them altered in Mark. Tradition transforms from the outside. Mark's method of weaving secret threads of a different material into the fabric of the tradition, without otherwise altering it, is purely literary and could only be the work of an individual.

A creative tradition would have carried out the theory of the Messianic secret in the life of Jesus much more boldly and logically, that is to say, at once more arbitrarily and more consistently.

A creative tradition would have implemented the idea of the Messianic secret in Jesus' life much more boldly and logically, meaning more freely and more consistently.

The only alternative is to distinguish two stages of tradition in early Christianity, a naive, freely-working, earlier stage, and a more artificial later stage confined to a smaller circle of a more literary character. Wrede does, as a matter of fact, propose to find in Mark traces of a simpler and bolder transformation which, leaving aside the Messianic secret, makes Jesus an openly-professed Messiah, and is therefore of a distinct origin from the conception of the secret Christ. To this tradition may belong, he thinks, the entry into Jerusalem and the confession before the High Priest, since these narratives “naively” imply an openly avowed Messiahship.

The only option is to differentiate between two stages of tradition in early Christianity: a simple, natural earlier stage and a more artificial later stage that is limited to a smaller, more literary group. Wrede actually suggests finding in Mark signs of a simpler and bolder transformation that, disregarding the Messianic secret, presents Jesus as an openly declared Messiah, which is therefore distinctly different from the idea of the secret Christ. He believes that this tradition may include the entry into Jerusalem and the confession before the High Priest, since these stories "innocently" suggest an openly declared Messiahship.

[pg 339]

The word “naively” is out of place here; a really naive tradition which intended to represent the entry of Jesus as Messianic would have done so in quite a different way from Mark, and would not have stultified itself so curiously as we find done even in Matthew, where the Galilaean Passover pilgrims, after the “Messianic entry,” answer the question of the people of Jerusalem as to who it was whom they were acclaiming, with the words “This is the Prophet Jesus from Nazareth of Galilee” (Matt. xxi. 11).

The word "innocently" doesn't fit here; a truly naive tradition that aimed to depict Jesus's entry as Messianic would have done it very differently than Mark does, and wouldn’t have contradicted itself as we see even in Matthew. There, the Galilean Passover pilgrims, after the "Messianic arrival," respond to the people of Jerusalem’s question about who they are cheering with, saying "This is the Prophet Jesus from Nazareth in Galilee." (Matt. xxi. 11).

The tradition, too, which makes Jesus acknowledge His Messiahship before His judges is not “naive” in Wrede's sense, for, if it were, it would not represent the High Priest's knowledge of Jesus' Messiahship as something so extraordinary and peculiar to himself that he can cite witnesses only for the saying about the Temple, not with reference to Jesus' Messianic claim, and bases his condemnation only on the fact that Jesus in answer to his question acknowledges Himself as Messiah—and Jesus does so, it should be remarked, as in other passages, with an appeal to a future justification of His claim. The confession before the council is therefore anything but a “naive representation of an openly avowed Messiahship.”

The tradition that has Jesus affirming His role as Messiah in front of His judges isn't "naive" in Wrede's sense. If it were, it wouldn't show the High Priest's understanding of Jesus' Messiahship as something so unique and specific to him that he can only provide witnesses for the statement about the Temple, and not for Jesus' claim to be the Messiah. He bases his condemnation solely on the fact that Jesus acknowledges Himself as the Messiah in response to his question—and it's worth noting that Jesus does this, as in other instances, by pointing to a future validation of His claim. Therefore, the confession before the council is far from a "naive representation of an openly declared Messiahship."

The Messianic statements in these two passages present precisely the same remarkable character as in all the other cases to which Wrede draws attention. We have not here to do with a different tradition, with a clear Messianic light streaming in through the window-pane, but, just as elsewhere, with the rays of a dark lantern. The real point is that Wrede cannot bring these two passages within the lines of the theory of secrecy, and practically admits this by assuming the existence of a second and rather divergent line of tradition. What concerns us is to note that this theory does not suffice to explain the two facts in question, the knowledge of Jesus' Messiahship shown by the Galilaean Passover pilgrims at the time of the entry into Jerusalem, and the knowledge of the High Priest at His trial.

The Messianic statements in these two passages show the same remarkable character as in all the other cases that Wrede points out. We're not dealing with a different tradition here, with a clear Messianic light shining through the window, but, like elsewhere, with the beams of a dark lantern. The main issue is that Wrede can't fit these two passages into the theory of secrecy and essentially admits this by suggesting the existence of a second and somewhat different line of tradition. What matters for us is to note that this theory does not adequately explain the two facts in question: the knowledge of Jesus' Messiahship displayed by the Galilean Passover pilgrims during His entry into Jerusalem, and the knowledge of the High Priest during His trial.

We can only touch on the question whether any one who wished to date back in some way or other the Messiahship into the life of Jesus could not have done it much more simply by making Jesus give His closest followers some hints regarding it. Why does the re-moulder of the history, instead of doing that, have recourse to a supernatural knowledge on the part of the demoniacs and the disciples? For Wrede rightly remarks, as Bruno Bauer and the “Sketch” also do, that the incident of Caesarea Philippi, as represented by Mark, involves a miracle, since Jesus does not, as is generally supposed, reveal His Messiahship to Peter; it is Peter who reveals it to Jesus (Mark viii. 29). This fact, however, makes nonsense of the whole theory about the disciples' want of understanding. It will not therefore fit into the concealment theory, [pg 340] and Wrede, as a matter of fact, feels obliged to give up that theory as regards this incident. “This scene,” he remarks, “can hardly have been created by Mark himself.” It also, therefore, belongs to another tradition.

We can only touch on the question of whether anyone who wanted to connect the Messiahship to the life of Jesus could have done it much more easily by having Jesus give His closest followers some hints about it. Why does the re-shaper of history, instead of doing that, rely on supernatural knowledge from demoniacs and the disciples? Wrede correctly points out, as Bruno Bauer and the “Draw” also do, that the incident at Caesarea Philippi, as described by Mark, involves a miracle, since Jesus does not, as is commonly thought, reveal His Messiahship to Peter; it's actually Peter who reveals it to Jesus (Mark viii. 29). This fact, however, undermines the entire theory about the disciples' lack of understanding. Therefore, it doesn’t fit into the concealment theory, [pg 340] and Wrede, in fact, feels compelled to abandon that theory regarding this incident. “This moment,” he notes, "must have hardly been created by Mark himself." It also belongs to a different tradition.

Here, then, is a third Messianic fact which cannot be brought within the lines of Wrede's “literary” theory of the Messianic secret. And these three facts are precisely the most important of all: Peter's confession, the Entry into Jerusalem, and the High Priest's knowledge of Jesus' Messiahship! In each case Wrede finds himself obliged to refer these to tradition instead of to the literary conception of Mark.262 This tradition undermines his literary hypothesis, for the conception of a tradition always involves the possibility of genuine historical elements.

Here’s a third fact about the Messiah that doesn’t fit into Wrede’s “literary” theory of the Messianic secret. These three facts are the most significant of all: Peter's confession, the Entry into Jerusalem, and the High Priest's recognition of Jesus as the Messiah! In each case, Wrede has to attribute them to tradition rather than to Mark's literary approach. This tradition challenges his literary hypothesis because the idea of tradition always includes the chance of real historical elements.

How greatly this inescapable intrusion of tradition weakens the theory of the literary interpolation of the Messiahship into the history, becomes evident when we consider the story of the passion. The representation that Jesus was publicly put to death as Messiah because He had publicly acknowledged Himself to be so, must, like the High Priest's knowledge of His claim, be referred to the other tradition which has nothing to do with the Messianic secret, but boldly antedates the Messiahship without employing any finesse of that kind. But that strongly tends to confirm the historicity of this tradition, and throws the burden of proof upon those who deny it. It is wholly independent of the hypothesis of secrecy, and in fact directly opposed to it. If, on the other hand, in spite of all the difficulties, the representation that Jesus was condemned to death on account of His Messianic claims is dragged by main force into the theory of secrecy, the question arises: What interest had the persons who set up the literary theory of secrecy, in representing Jesus as having been openly put to death as Messiah and in consequence of His Messianic claims? And the answer is: “None whatever: quite the contrary.” For in doing so the theory of secrecy stultifies itself. As though one were to develop a photographic plate with painful care and, just when one had finished, fling open the shutters, so, on this hypothesis, the natural Messianic light suddenly shines into the room which ought to be lighted only by the rays of the dark lantern.

How much the unavoidable influence of tradition undermines the theory that the Messiahship was inserted into history becomes clear when we look at the story of the passion. The idea that Jesus was publicly executed as the Messiah because He openly claimed to be one must, similar to the High Priest's awareness of His claim, be linked to another tradition that has nothing to do with the Messianic secret and instead straightforwardly acknowledges His Messiahship without any tricks. However, this strongly supports the authenticity of this tradition and shifts the burden of proof to those who dispute it. It stands completely separate from the secrecy hypothesis and is, in fact, directly against it. If, despite the challenges, the idea that Jesus was sentenced to death for His Messianic claims is forcefully brought into the secrecy theory, then we must ask: What motivation did those who proposed the secrecy theory have in portraying Jesus as having been openly executed as the Messiah due to His claims? The answer is: “None at all: quite the opposite.” By doing this, the secrecy theory contradicts itself. It’s like carefully developing a photographic plate only to open the shutters right when it’s done; under this theory, the natural light of the Messiah suddenly floods the room, which should only be lit by the dim glow of the dark lantern.

Here, therefore, the theory of secrecy abandoned the method which it had hitherto followed in regard to the traditional material. For if Jesus was not condemned and crucified at Jerusalem as [pg 341] Messiah, a tradition must have existed which preserved the truth about the last conflicts, and the motives of the condemnation. This is supposed to have been here completely set aside by the theory of the secret Messiahship, which, instead of drawing its delicate threads through the older tradition, has simply substituted its own representation of events. But in that case why not do away with the remainder of the public ministry? Why not at least get rid of the public appearance at Jerusalem? How can the crudeness of method shown in the case of the passion be harmonised with the skilful conservatism towards the non-Messianic tradition which it is obvious that the “Marcan circle” has scrupulously observed elsewhere?

Here, then, the theory of secrecy abandoned the method it had previously used regarding traditional material. If Jesus wasn’t condemned and crucified in Jerusalem as the Messiah, then there must have been a tradition that preserved the truth about the final conflicts and the reasons for his condemnation. This is thought to have been completely disregarded by the theory of secret Messiahship, which, instead of weaving through the older tradition, has simply replaced it with its own portrayal of events. But if that's the case, why eliminate the rest of the public ministry? Why not at least remove the public appearance in Jerusalem? How can the roughness of the method seen in the passion be reconciled with the careful approach to the non-Messianic tradition that the “Marcan circle” has clearly followed in other places?

If according to the original tradition, of which Wrede admits the existence, Jesus went to Jerusalem not to die, but to work there, the dogmatic view, according to which He went to Jerusalem to die, must have struck out the whole account of His sojourn in Jerusalem and His death, in order to put something else in its place. What we now read in the Gospels concerning those last days in Jerusalem cannot be derived from the original tradition, for one who came to work, and, according to Wrede, “to work with decisive effect,” would not have cast all His preaching into the form of obscure parables of judgment and minatory discourses. That is a style of speech which could be adopted only by one who was determined to force his adversaries to put him to death. Therefore the narrative of the last days of Jesus must be, from beginning to end, a creation of the dogmatic idea. And, as a matter of fact, Wrede, here in agreement with Weisse, “sees grounds for asserting that the sojourn at Jerusalem is presented to us in the Gospels in a very much abridged and weakened version.” That is a euphemistic expression, for if it was really the dogmatic idea which was responsible for representing Jesus as being condemned as Messiah, it is not a mere case of “abridging and weakening down,” but of displacing the tradition in favour of a new one.

If, according to the original tradition that Wrede acknowledges, Jesus went to Jerusalem not to die but to work, then the dogmatic belief that He went there to die must have erased the entire account of His time in Jerusalem and His death, to replace it with something else. What we currently read in the Gospels about those final days in Jerusalem cannot come from the original tradition, because someone who came to work and, as Wrede puts it, “to work with impact,” wouldn’t have expressed all His teachings through obscure parables of judgment and threatening sermons. That way of speaking could only be taken on by someone intent on provoking their opponents to execute him. Therefore, the story of Jesus' last days must be, from start to finish, a creation of the dogmatic perspective. In fact, Wrede, in agreement with Weisse, "sees reason to claim that the stay in Jerusalem is shown to us in the Gospels in a significantly shortened and weakened form." That’s a euphemism because if the dogmatic idea truly led to representing Jesus as being condemned as the Messiah, it’s not just a case of "shortening and weakening," but of replacing the tradition in favor of a new one.

But if Jesus was not condemned as Messiah, on what grounds was He condemned? And, again, what interest had those whose concern was to make the Messiahship a secret of His earthly life, in making Him die as Messiah, contrary to the received tradition? And what interest could the tradition have had in falsifying history in that way? Even admitting that the prediction of the passion to the disciples is of a dogmatic character, and is to be regarded as a creation of primitive Christian theology, the historic fact that He died would have been a sufficient fulfilment of those sayings. That He was publicly condemned and crucified as Messiah has nothing to do with the fulfilment of those predictions, and goes far beyond it.

But if Jesus wasn’t condemned as the Messiah, what were the reasons for His condemnation? And again, what motivation did those who wanted to keep His role as the Messiah a secret during His life have for making Him die as the Messiah, which was against the established tradition? What would the tradition gain by distorting history in that way? Even if we accept that the predictions of His suffering to the disciples are more about doctrine and stem from early Christian theology, the fact that He died would still fulfill those predictions. The fact that He was publicly condemned and crucified as the Messiah isn’t related to the fulfillment of those predictions; it goes much further than that.

To take a more general point: what interest had primitive [pg 342] theology in dating back the Messiahship of Jesus to the time of His earthly ministry? None whatever. Paul shows us with what complete indifference the earthly life of Jesus was regarded by primitive Christianity. The discourses in Acts show an equal indifference, since in them also Jesus first becomes the Messiah by virtue of His exaltation. To date the Messiahship earlier was not an undertaking which offered any advantage to primitive theology, in fact it would only have raised difficulties for it, since it involved the hypothesis of a dual Messiahship, one of earthly humiliation and one of future glory. The fact is, if one reads through the early literature one becomes aware that so long as theology had an eschatological orientation and was dominated by the expectation of the Parousia the question of how Jesus of Nazareth “had been” the Messiah not only did not exist, but was impossible. Primitive theology is simply a theology of the future, with no interest in history! It was only with the decline of eschatological interest and the change in the orientation of Christianity which was connected therewith that an interest in the life of Jesus and the “historical Messiahship” arose.

To take a broader view: what interest did early theology have in establishing the Messiahship of Jesus during His time on Earth? None at all. Paul demonstrates how little attention early Christianity paid to Jesus' earthly life. The speeches in Acts reflect this same indifference, as in them Jesus only becomes the Messiah through His exaltation. Dating the Messiahship earlier had no benefit for early theology; in fact, it would have created complications, as it suggested a dual Messiahship—one of earthly humiliation and another of future glory. The reality is that if you read through early writings, you'll notice that as long as theology focused on eschatology and was shaped by the expectation of the Parousia, the question of how Jesus of Nazareth “had been” the Messiah not only didn't exist, but was also unthinkable. Early theology is simply a theology of the future, uninterested in history! It was only when the focus on eschatology declined and the direction of Christianity shifted that interest in Jesus' life and the “historical Messiahship” began to develop.

That is to say, the Gnostics, who were the first to assert the Messiahship of the historical Jesus, and who were obliged to assert it precisely because they denied the eschatological conceptions, forced this view upon the theology of the Early Church, and compelled it to create in the Logos Christology an un-Gnostic mould in which to cast the speculative conception of the historical Messiahship of Jesus; and that is what we find in the Fourth Gospel. Prior to the anti-Gnostic controversies we find in the early Christian literature no conscious dating back of the Messiahship of Jesus to His earthly life, and no theological interest at work upon the dogmatic recasting of His history.263 It is therefore difficult to suppose that the Messianic secret in Mark, that is to say, in the very earliest tradition, was derived from primitive theology. The assertion of the Messiahship of Jesus was wholly independent of the latter. The instinct which led Bruno Bauer to explain the Messianic secret as the literary invention of Mark himself was therefore quite correct. Once suppose that tradition and primitive theology have anything to do with the matter, and the theory of the interpolation of the Messiahship into the history becomes almost impossible to carry through. But Wrede's greatness consists precisely in the fact that he was compelled by his acute perception of the significance of the critical data to set aside the purely literary version of the hypothesis and make Mark, so to speak, the instrument of the [pg 343] literary realisation of the ideas of a definite intellectual circle within the sphere of primitive theology.

That is to say, the Gnostics were the first to claim that the historical Jesus was the Messiah, and they had to make this claim because they rejected traditional end-times beliefs. This view influenced the theology of the Early Church, pushing it to develop a non-Gnostic framework in Logos Christology to articulate the speculative idea of Jesus as the historical Messiah. That's what we see in the Fourth Gospel. Before the debates against Gnosticism, early Christian writings did not consciously connect Jesus' Messiahship to His earthly life, and there was no theological effort to reshape His story. It’s thus hard to believe that the Messianic secret in Mark, meaning in the oldest tradition, originated from early theology. The claim of Jesus as the Messiah was completely independent of that. Bruno Bauer's instinct to interpret the Messianic secret as a literary invention by Mark himself was therefore quite accurate. If we assume that tradition and primitive theology played a role in this, the idea of inserting the Messiahship into the narrative becomes almost unfeasible. However, Wrede’s significance lies in his sharp insight into the importance of critical evidence, compelling him to move beyond the purely literary interpretation of the hypothesis and make Mark an instrument of the literary realization of the ideas from a specific intellectual circle within the realm of primitive theology.[pg 343]

The positive difficulty which confronts the sceptical theory is to explain how the Messianic beliefs of the first generation arose, if Jesus, throughout His life, was for all, even for the disciples, merely a “teacher,” and gave even His intimates no hint of the dignity which He claimed for Himself. It is difficult to eliminate the Messiahship from the “Life of Jesus,” especially from the narrative of the passion; it is more difficult still, as Keim saw long ago, to bring it back again after its elimination from the “Life” into the theology of the primitive Church. In Wrede's acute and logical thinking this difficulty seems to leap to light.

The challenge facing the skeptical theory is to explain how the Messianic beliefs of the first generation emerged if Jesus, throughout His life, was only seen as a "teacher" even by His closest disciples, and never indicated to them the divine status He claimed for Himself. It’s hard to separate the Messiahship from the "Jesus' Life," particularly from the account of the passion; it’s even harder, as Keim recognized long ago, to reintegrate it back into the theology of the early Church after it's been removed from the “Life.” In Wrede's sharp and logical reasoning, this challenge becomes clear.

Since the Messianic secret in Mark is always connected with the resurrection, the date at which the Messianic belief of the disciples arose must be the resurrection of Jesus. “But the idea of dating the Messiahship from the resurrection is certainly not a thought of Jesus, but of the primitive Church. It presupposes the Church's experience of the appearance of the risen Jesus.”

Since the Messianic secret in Mark is always linked to the resurrection, the moment when the disciples' belief in the Messiah emerged must be at the resurrection of Jesus. "However, the idea of proving the Messiahship through the resurrection is definitely not a concept of Jesus, but that of the early Church. It is based on the Church's experience of witnessing the risen Jesus."

The psychologist will say that the “resurrection experiences,” however they may be conceived, are only intelligible as based upon the expectation of the resurrection, and this again as based on references of Jesus to the resurrection. But leaving psychology aside, let us accept the resurrection experiences of the disciples as a pure psychological miracle. Even so, how can the appearances of the risen Jesus have suggested to the disciples the idea that Jesus, the crucified teacher, was the Messiah? Apart from any expectations, how can this conclusion have resulted for them from the mere “fact of the resurrection”? The fact of the appearance did not by any means imply it. In certain circles, indeed, according to Mark vi. 14-16, in the very highest quarters, the resurrection of the Baptist was believed in; but that did not make John the Baptist the Messiah. The inexplicable thing is that, according to Wrede, the disciples began at once to assert confidently and unanimously that He was the Messiah and would before long appear in glory.

The psychologist would argue that the “resurrection experiences,” no matter how they are interpreted, can only be understood as stemming from the expectation of the resurrection, which in turn is based on Jesus’ references to it. However, putting psychology aside, let’s consider the resurrection experiences of the disciples as purely a psychological miracle. Even so, how could the sightings of the risen Jesus have led the disciples to believe that Jesus, the crucified teacher, was the Messiah? Without any prior expectations, how could they have drawn that conclusion solely from the “reality of the resurrection”? The appearance alone didn’t imply that at all. In some circles, like those mentioned in Mark vi. 14-16, the resurrection of John the Baptist was believed, but that didn’t mean John the Baptist was the Messiah. What’s puzzling is that, according to Wrede, the disciples immediately began to assert with confidence and unity that He was the Messiah and would soon return in glory.

But how did the appearance of the risen Jesus suddenly become for them a proof of His Messiahship and the basis of their eschatology? That Wrede fails to explain, and so makes this “event” an “historical” miracle which in reality is harder to believe than the supernatural event.

But how did the appearance of the risen Jesus suddenly become proof for them of His Messiahship and the foundation of their beliefs about the end times? Wrede doesn’t explain this, making this "event" an "historic" miracle that is actually harder to believe than the supernatural event itself.

Any one who holds “historical” miracles to be just as impossible as any other kind, even when they occur in a critical and sceptical work, will be forced to the conclusion that the Messianic eschatological significance attached to the “resurrection experience” by the disciples implies some kind of Messianic eschatological references on the part of the historical Jesus which gave to the [pg 344] “resurrection” its Messianic eschatological significance. Here Wrede himself, though without admitting it, postulates some Messianic hints on the part of Jesus, since he conceives the judgment of the disciples upon the resurrection to have been not analytical, but synthetic, inasmuch as they add something to it, and that, indeed, the main thing, which was not implied in the conception of the event as such.

Anyone who considers "historical" miracles to be just as impossible as any other type, even when they appear in a critical and skeptical work, will have to conclude that the Messianic eschatological meaning attached to the "resurrection experience" by the disciples suggests some kind of Messianic eschatological references from the historical Jesus, which gave the "resurrection" its Messianic eschatological significance. Here, Wrede himself, although not admitting it, implies some Messianic hints from Jesus, since he believes that the disciples’ judgment of the resurrection was not analytical but synthetic, as they added something to it, which was indeed the main point that wasn’t incorporated in the understanding of the event itself.

Here again the merit of Wrede's contribution to criticism consists in the fact that he takes the position as it is and does not try to improve it artificially. Bruno Bauer and others supposed that the belief in the Messiahship of Jesus had slowly solidified out of a kind of gaseous state, or had been forced into primitive theology by the literary invention of Mark. Wrede, however, feels himself obliged to base it upon an historical fact, and, moreover, the same historical fact which is pointed to by the sayings in the Synoptics and the Pauline theology. But in so doing he creates an almost insurmountable difficulty for his hypothesis.

Here again, Wrede's contribution to criticism stands out because he accepts the situation as it is without trying to artificially enhance it. Bruno Bauer and others believed that the belief in Jesus' Messiahship gradually solidified from a kind of formless idea, or had been pushed into primitive theology by Mark's literary creation. However, Wrede feels he must ground it in a historical fact, and moreover, the same historical fact referenced by the sayings in the Synoptics and Pauline theology. But in doing so, he creates an almost insurmountable challenge for his hypothesis.

We can only briefly refer to the question what form the accounts of the resurrection must have taken if the historic fact which underlay them was the first surprised apprehension and recognition of the Messiahship of Jesus on the part of the disciples. The Messianic teaching would necessarily in that case have been somehow or other put into the mouth of the risen Jesus. It is, however, completely absent, because it was already contained in the teaching of Jesus during His earthly life. The theory of Messianic secrecy must therefore have re-moulded not merely the story of the passion, but also that of the resurrection, removing the revelation of the Messiahship to the disciples from the latter in order to insert it into the public ministry!

We can only briefly touch on the question of what form the accounts of the resurrection would have taken if the historical fact behind them was the initial surprise and recognition of Jesus as the Messiah by the disciples. In that case, the teachings about the Messiah would have had to be somehow attributed to the risen Jesus. However, this is completely absent because it was already part of Jesus' teachings during His time on earth. Therefore, the idea of Messianic secrecy must have reshaped not just the story of the passion, but also that of the resurrection, removing the revelation of His Messiahship to the disciples and placing it into His public ministry instead!

Wrede, moreover, will only take account of the Marcan text as it stands, not of the historical possibility that the “futuristic Messiahship” which meets us in the mysterious utterances of Jesus goes back in some form to a sound tradition. Further he does not take the eschatological character of the teaching of Jesus into his calculations, but works on the false assumption that he can analyse the Marcan text in and by itself and so discover the principle on which it is composed. He carries out experiments on the law of crystallisation of the narrative material in this Gospel, but instead of doing so in the natural and historical atmosphere he does it in an atmosphere artificially neutralised, which contains no trace of contemporary conceptions.264 Consequently the conclusion [pg 345] based on the sum of his observations has in it something arbitrary. Everything which conflicts with the rational construction of the course of the history is referred directly to the theory of the concealment of the Messianic secret. But in the carrying out of that theory a number of self-contradictions, without which it could not subsist, must be recognised and noted.

Wrede, furthermore, will only consider the Markan text as it is, not the historical possibility that the “futuristic messiah” found in the mysterious sayings of Jesus might be rooted in some form of a sound tradition. Additionally, he doesn't take into account the eschatological nature of Jesus's teachings, instead operating under the mistaken belief that he can analyze the Markan text in isolation and therefore uncover the principle underlying its composition. He conducts experiments on the crystallization of the narrative material in this Gospel, but instead of doing so within the natural and historical context, he works in an artificially neutralized environment that lacks any trace of contemporary ideas.264 Consequently, the conclusion [pg 345] derived from his observations has an arbitrary quality. Everything that contradicts the rational construction of the historical narrative is directly attributed to the theory of the concealment of the Messianic secret. However, while applying that theory, several self-contradictions must be acknowledged and noted, without which it could not hold up.

Thus, for example, all the prohibitions,265 whatever they may refer to, even including the command not to make known His miracles, are referred to the same category as the injunction not to reveal the Messianic secret. But what justification is there for that? It presupposes that according to Mark the miracles could be taken as proofs of the Messiahship, an idea of which there is no hint whatever in Mark. “The miracles,” Wrede argues, “are certainly used by the earliest Christians as evidence of the nature and significance of Christ.... I need hardly point to the fact that Mark, not less than Matthew, Luke, and John, must have held the opinion that the miracles of Jesus encountered a widespread and ardent Messianic expectation.”

Thus, for example, all the prohibitions, 265 no matter what they refer to, even including the instruction not to reveal His miracles, fall into the same category as the command not to disclose the Messianic secret. But what’s the justification for that? It assumes that in Mark's view, the miracles could be taken as evidence of the Messiahship, a notion that isn't suggested anywhere in Mark. “The miracles,” Wrede argues, “are definitely used by the earliest Christians as evidence of the nature and importance of Christ. I hardly need to point out that Mark, just like Matthew, Luke, and John, must have believed that Jesus' miracles fulfilled a widespread and intense Messianic expectation.”

In John this Messianic significance of the miracles is certainly assumed; but then the really eschatological view of things has here fallen into the background. It seems indeed as if genuine eschatology excluded the Messianic interpretation of the miracles. In Matthew the miracles of Jesus have nothing whatever to do with the proof of the Messiahship, but, as is evident from the saying about Chorazin and Bethsaida, Matt. xi. 20-24, are only an exhibition of mercy intended to awaken repentance, or, according to Matt. xii. 28, an indication of the nearness of the Kingdom of God. They have as little to do with the Messianic office as in the Acts of the Apostles.266 In Mark, from first to last, there is [pg 346] not a single syllable to suggest that the miracles have a Messianic significance. Even admitting the possibility that the “miracles of Jesus encountered an ardent Messianic expectation,” that does not necessarily imply a Messianic significance in them. To justify that conclusion requires the pre-supposition that the Messiah was expected to be some kind of an earthly man who should do miracles. This is presupposed by Wrede, by Bruno Bauer, and by modern theology in general, but it has not been proved, and it is at variance with eschatology, which pictured the Messiah to itself as a heavenly being in a world which was already being transformed into something supra-mundane.

In John, the Messianic significance of the miracles is definitely assumed; however, the really eschatological perspective seems to have taken a backseat here. It appears that true eschatology dismisses the Messianic interpretation of the miracles. In Matthew, the miracles of Jesus are not about proving his Messiahship, but, as evident from the comments on Chorazin and Bethsaida, Matt. xi. 20-24, they serve only to show mercy aimed at sparking repentance, or, according to Matt. xii. 28, to indicate the nearness of the Kingdom of God. They are just as unrelated to the Messianic role as in the Acts of the Apostles.266 In Mark, from start to finish, there isn't a single word to suggest that the miracles hold any Messianic significance. Even if we accept the possibility that the "the miracles of Jesus faced a significant expectation of the Messiah," that doesn’t necessarily mean they have a Messianic significance. To support that conclusion would require assuming that the Messiah was expected to be some sort of earthly person who performed miracles. This assumption is held by Wrede, Bruno Bauer, and modern theology in general, but it hasn't been proven, and it goes against the eschatology that envisioned the Messiah as a heavenly being in a world already transforming into something beyond the ordinary.

The assumption that the clue to the explanation of the command not to make known the miracles is to be found in the necessity of guarding the secret of the Messiahship is, therefore, not justified. The miracles are connected with the Kingdom and the nearness of the Kingdom, not with the Messiah. But Wrede is obliged to refer everything to the Messianic secret, because he leaves the preaching of the Kingdom out of account.

The idea that the reason for the command not to reveal the miracles lies in the need to protect the secret of the Messiah is not supported. The miracles are related to the Kingdom and its proximity, not the Messiah. However, Wrede feels he must connect everything to the Messianic secret because he overlooks the preaching of the Kingdom.

The same process is repeated in the discussion of the veiling of the mystery of the Kingdom of God in the parables of Mark iv. The mystery of the Kingdom is for Wrede the secret of Jesus' Messiahship. “We have learned in the meantime,” he says, “that one main element in this mystery is that Jesus is the Messiah, the Son of God. If Jesus, according to Mark, conceals his Messiahship, we are justified in interpreting the μυστήριον τῆς βασιλείας τοῦ θεοῦ in the light of this fact.”

The same process happens in the discussion about the hidden nature of the Kingdom of God in the parables of Mark iv. For Wrede, the mystery of the Kingdom is the secret of Jesus' role as the Messiah. "In the meantime, we've learned," he states, “A key part of this mystery is that Jesus is the Messiah, the Son of God. If, according to Mark, Jesus conceals his role as Messiah, we can rightly understand the μυστήριον τῆς βασιλείας τοῦ θεοῦ in light of this fact.”

That is one of the weakest points in Wrede's whole theory. Where is there any hint of this in these parables? And why should the secret of the Kingdom of God contain within it as one of its principal features the secret of the Messiahship of Jesus?

That is one of the weakest points in Wrede's entire theory. Where is there any indication of this in these parables? And why should the secret of the Kingdom of God include, as one of its main aspects, the secret of Jesus' role as the Messiah?

“Mark's account of Jesus' parabolic teaching,” he concludes, “is completely unhistorical,” because it is directly opposed to the essential nature of the parables. The ultimate reason, according to Wrede, why this whole view of the parables arose, was simply “because the general opinion was already in existence that Jesus had revealed Himself to the disciples, but concealed Himself from the multitude.”

"Mark's account of Jesus' parables," he concludes, “is totally unhistorical,” because it goes against the core essence of the parables. The main reason, according to Wrede, why this entire perspective on the parables came about was simply "because the common belief was already that Jesus had shown Himself to the disciples but kept Himself hidden from the crowd."

Instead of simply admitting that we are unable to discover what the mystery of the Kingdom in Mark iv. is, any more than we can understand why it must be veiled, and numbering it among the unsolved problems of Jesus' preaching of the Kingdom, Wrede forces this chapter inside the lines of his theory of the veiled Messiahship.

Instead of just acknowledging that we can't figure out the mystery of the Kingdom in Mark iv. any more than we understand why it has to be hidden, and counting it among the unanswered questions of Jesus' teaching about the Kingdom, Wrede pushes this chapter into his theory of the concealed Messiahship.

The desire of Jesus to be alone, too, and remain unrecognised (Mark vii. 24 and ix. 30 ff.) is supposed to have some kind of connexion with the veiling of the Messiahship. He even brings [pg 347] the multitude, which in Mark x. 47 ff. rebukes the blind beggar at Jericho who cried out to Jesus, into the service of his theory ... on the ground that the beggar had addressed Him as Son of David. But all the narrative says is that they told him to hold his peace—to cease making an outcry—not that they did so because of his addressing Jesus as “Son of David.”

The desire of Jesus to be alone and to remain unrecognized (Mark 7:24 and 9:30 ff.) is thought to be connected to the concealment of His Messiahship. He even brings the crowd, which in Mark 10:47 ff. scolds the blind beggar in Jericho for calling out to Jesus, into support of his theory... suggesting that the beggar was rebuked because he referred to Him as Son of David. However, the narrative only states that they told him to be quiet—to stop shouting—not that they did so because he addressed Jesus as “Son of David.”

In an equally arbitrary fashion the surprising introduction of the “multitude” in Mark viii. 34, after the incident of Caesarea Philippi, is dragged into the theory of secrecy.267 Wrede does not feel the possibility or impossibility of the sudden appearance of the multitude in this locality as an historical problem, any more than he grasps the sudden withdrawal of Jesus from His public ministry as primarily an historical question. Mark is for him a writer who is to be judged from a pathological point of view, a writer who, dominated by the fixed idea of introducing everywhere the Messianic secret of Jesus, is always creating mysterious and unintelligible situations, even when these do not directly serve the interests of his theory, and who in some of his descriptions, writes in a rather “fairy-tale” style. When all is said, his treatment of the history scarcely differs from that of the fourth Evangelist.

In a similarly arbitrary way, the unexpected mention of the "crowd" in Mark viii. 34, right after the event at Caesarea Philippi, is dragged into the secrecy theory. Wrede doesn’t consider the sudden appearance of the multitude in this location as a historical issue, just as he doesn’t see Jesus's abrupt departure from His public ministry as primarily a historical question. To him, Mark is an author who should be evaluated from a pathological standpoint, someone who, obsessed with presenting the Messianic secret of Jesus everywhere, continually creates mysterious and confusing situations, even when these don't directly support his theory, and in some of his accounts, writes in a somewhat "fairy tale" style. Ultimately, his approach to history hardly differs from that of the fourth Evangelist.

The absence of historical prepossessions which Wrede skilfully assumes in his examination of the connexion in Mark is not really complete. He is bound to refer everything inexplicable to the principle of the concealment of the Messiahship, which is the only principle that he recognises in the dogmatic stratum of the narrative, and is consequently obliged to deny the historicity of such passages, whereas in reality the veiling of the Messiahship is only involved in a few places and is there indicated in clear and simple words. He is unwilling to recognise that there is a second, wider circle of mystery which has to do, not with Jesus' Messiahship, but with His preaching of the Kingdom, with the mystery of the Kingdom of God in the wider sense, and that within this second circle there lie a number of historical problems, above all the mission of the Twelve and the inexplicable abandonment of public activity on the part of Jesus which followed soon afterwards. His mistake consists in endeavouring by violent methods to subsume the more general, the mystery of the Kingdom of God, under the more special, the mystery of the Messiahship, instead of inserting the latter as the smaller circle, within the wider, the secret of the Kingdom of God.

The lack of historical biases that Wrede skillfully adopts in his analysis of the connections in Mark isn't entirely thorough. He has to attribute everything that’s unclear to the idea of concealing the Messiahship, which is the only principle he acknowledges in the underlying doctrinal layer of the narrative. As a result, he has to reject the historical accuracy of certain passages. However, in reality, the concealment of the Messiahship is only relevant in a few instances, and those are stated clearly and simply. He doesn't want to acknowledge that there's a broader layer of mystery that pertains not to Jesus' Messiahship but to His preaching about the Kingdom, specifically the mystery of the Kingdom of God in a broader sense. Within this second layer, there are several historical issues, particularly the mission of the Twelve and the inexplicable cessation of Jesus' public activities that followed shortly after. His error lies in trying to force the more general mystery of the Kingdom of God into the narrower scope of the Messiahship, instead of placing the latter as a smaller subset within the broader concept of the secret of the Kingdom of God.

As he does not deal with the teaching of Jesus, he has no occasion to take account of the secret of the Kingdom of God. That is the more remarkable because corresponding to one fundamental idea of the Messianic secret there is a parallel, [pg 348] more general dogmatic conception in Jesus' preaching of the Kingdom. For if Jesus in Matt. x. gives the disciples nothing to take with them on their mission but predictions of suffering; if at the very beginning of His ministry He closes the Beatitudes with a blessing upon the persecuted; if in Mark viii. 34 ff. He warns the people that they will have to choose between life and life, between death and death; if, in short, from the first, He loses no opportunity of preaching about suffering and following Him in His sufferings; that is just as much a matter of dogma as His own sufferings and predictions of sufferings. For in both cases the necessity of suffering, the necessity of facing death, is not “a necessity of the historical situation,” not a necessity which arises out of the circumstances; it is an assertion put forth without empirical basis, a prophecy of storm while the sky is blue, since neither Jesus nor the people to whom He spoke were undergoing any persecution; and when His fate overtook Him not even the disciples were involved in it. It is distinctly remarkable that, except for a few meagre references, the enigmatic character of Jesus' constant predictions of suffering has not been discussed in the Life-of-Jesus literature.268

As he doesn't talk about the teachings of Jesus, he doesn't have to consider the secret of the Kingdom of God. This is even more striking because, relating to one key idea of the Messianic secret, there is a broader theological concept in Jesus' message about the Kingdom. If Jesus in Matthew 10 only tells the disciples to expect suffering on their mission; if at the start of His ministry He finishes the Beatitudes with a blessing for the persecuted; if in Mark 8:34 and following, He warns people that they will have to choose between life and life, between death and death; if, to put it simply, from the beginning, He never misses a chance to talk about suffering and following Him in suffering; that is just as much part of doctrine as His own suffering and predictions of suffering. In both instances, the need for suffering, the need to confront death, is not “a necessity of the historical situation,” nor is it a necessity created by the circumstances; it is a claim made without any empirical backing, a prediction of a storm while the sky is clear, since neither Jesus nor the people He spoke to were experiencing any persecution; and when His fate caught up with Him, not even the disciples were part of it. It’s particularly notable that, aside from a few scant references, the mysterious nature of Jesus' continuous predictions of suffering has not been addressed in the Life-of-Jesus literature.268

What has now to be done, therefore, is, in contradistinction to Wrede, to make a critical examination of the dogmatic element in the life of Jesus on the assumption that the atmosphere of the time was saturated with eschatology, that is, to keep in even closer touch with the facts than Wrede does, and moreover, to proceed, not from the particular to the general, but from the general to the particular, carefully considering whether the dogmatic element is not precisely the historical element. For, after all, why should not Jesus think in terms of doctrine, and make history in action, just as well as a poor Evangelist can do it on paper, under the pressure of the theological interests of the primitive community.

What needs to be done now, in contrast to Wrede, is to critically examine the dogmatic aspect of Jesus's life, assuming that the atmosphere of the time was filled with eschatology. This means staying even closer to the facts than Wrede does, and approaching the analysis from the general to the specific rather than from the specific to the general. We must carefully consider whether the dogmatic aspect might actually be the historical aspect. After all, why wouldn’t Jesus think in terms of doctrine and create history through his actions, just as a struggling Evangelist does on paper, influenced by the theological concerns of the early community?

Once again, however, we must repeat that the critical analysis and the assertion of a system running through the disorder are the same in the eschatological as in the sceptical hypothesis, only that in the eschatological analysis a number of problems come more clearly to light. The two constructions are related like the bones and cartilage of the body. The general structure is the same, only that in the case of the one a solid substance, lime, is distributed even in the minutest portions, giving it firmness and solidity, while in the other case this is lacking. This reinforcing substance is the eschatological world-view.

Once again, we need to emphasize that the critical analysis and the claim of a system that underlies the chaos are the same in both the eschatological and the skeptical perspective, except that in the eschatological analysis, several issues become clearer. The two frameworks are similar to the bones and cartilage of a body. The overall structure is the same; however, in one case, a solid substance, like lime, is distributed even in the smallest parts, providing it with firmness and solidity, while in the other case, that is absent. This reinforcing substance is the eschatological worldview.

How is it to be explained that Wrede, in spite of the eschatological school, in spite of Johannes Weiss, could, in critically [pg 349] investigating the connecting principle of the life of Jesus, simply leave eschatology out of account? The blame rests with the eschatological school itself, for it applied the eschatological explanation only to the preaching of Jesus, and not even to the whole of this, but only to the Messianic secret, instead of using it also to throw light upon the whole public work of Jesus, the connexion and want of connexion between the events. It represented Jesus as thinking and speaking eschatologically in some of the most important passages of His teaching, but for the rest gave as uneschatological a presentation of His life as modern historical theology had done. The teaching of Jesus and the history of Jesus were set in different keys. Instead of destroying the modern-historical scheme of the life of Jesus, or subjecting it to a rigorous examination, and thereby undertaking the performance of a highly valuable service to criticism, the eschatological theory confined itself within the limits of New Testament Theology, and left it to Wrede to reveal one after another by a laborious purely critical method the difficulties which from its point of view it might have grasped historically at a single glance. It inevitably follows that Wrede is unjust to Johannes Weiss and Johannes Weiss towards Wrede.269

How can we explain that Wrede, despite the eschatological school and Johannes Weiss, could critically examine the underlying principle of Jesus' life while completely ignoring eschatology? The fault lies with the eschatological school itself, as it only applied the eschatological explanation to Jesus' preaching, and not even to that in its entirety, but only to the Messianic secret. It should have also used it to shed light on Jesus' overall public work, including the connections and disconnections between events. It depicted Jesus as thinking and speaking eschatologically in some of His key teachings, yet for the rest, it provided a view of His life that was as uneschatological as modern historical theology. The teachings of Jesus and the history of Jesus were set in different contexts. Rather than dismantling the modern-historical model of Jesus' life or rigorously examining it, which would have served criticism well, the eschatological theory stayed restricted within the bounds of New Testament Theology. This allowed Wrede to slowly uncover one difficulty after another using a strictly critical approach, difficulties that the eschatological view might have grasped historically in an instant. It follows that Wrede is unfair to Johannes Weiss, and Johannes Weiss is unfair to Wrede.

It is quite inexplicable that the eschatological school, with its clear perception of the eschatological element in the preaching of the Kingdom of God, did not also hit upon the thought of the “dogmatic” element in the history of Jesus. Eschatology is simply “dogmatic history”—history as moulded by theological beliefs—which breaks in upon the natural course of history and abrogates. it. Is it not even a priori the only conceivable view that the conduct of one who looked forward to His Messianic “Parousia” in the near future should be determined, not by the natural course of events, but by that expectation? The chaotic confusion of the narratives ought to have suggested the thought that the events had been thrown into this confusion by the volcanic force of an incalculable personality, not by some kind of carelessness or freak of the tradition.

It’s surprising that the eschatological school, which clearly recognized the eschatological aspect of the preaching of the Kingdom of God, didn’t also consider the “dogmatic” aspect in the history of Jesus. Eschatology is really just “dogmatic history”—history shaped by theological beliefs—that disrupts the natural flow of history and overrides it. Isn’t it obvious that someone who anticipated His Messianic “Parousia” in the near future would act based on that expectation rather than the normal course of events? The chaotic mix of the narratives should have made it clear that the events were thrown into disarray by the powerful influence of an unpredictable personality, not due to carelessness or some quirk of tradition.

[pg 350]

A very little consideration suffices to show that there is something quite incomprehensible in the public ministry of Jesus taken as a whole. According to Mark it lasted less than a year, for since he speaks of only one Passover-journey we may conclude that no other Passover fell within the period of Jesus' activity as a teacher. If it is proposed to assume that He allowed a Passover to go by without going up to Jerusalem, His adversaries, who took Him to task about hand-washings and about rubbing the ears of corn on the Sabbath, would certainly have made a most serious matter of this, and we should have to suppose that the Evangelist for some reason or other thought fit to suppress the fact. That is to say, the burden of proof lies upon those who assert a longer duration for the ministry of Jesus.

A little thought makes it clear that there's something quite confusing about the public ministry of Jesus as a whole. According to Mark, it lasted less than a year, since he mentions only one Passover journey. This suggests no other Passover occurred during Jesus' time as a teacher. If we assume He skipped a Passover without heading to Jerusalem, His critics, who called Him out for things like hand-washing and picking corn on the Sabbath, would have definitely made a big deal out of it. We would then have to think that the Evangelist had a reason to hide this fact. In other words, the burden of proof is on those who claim that Jesus' ministry lasted longer.

Until they have succeeded in proving it, we may assume something like the following course of events. Jesus, in going up to a Passover, came in contact with the movement initiated by John the Baptist in Judaea, and, after the lapse of a little time—if we bring into the reckoning the forty days' sojourn in the wilderness mentioned in Mark i. 13, a few weeks later—appeared in Galilee proclaiming the near approach of the Kingdom of God. According to Mark He had known Himself since His baptism to be the Messiah, but from the historical point of view that does not matter, since history is concerned with the first announcement of the Messiahship, not with inward psychological processes.270

Until they have proven it, we can assume something like this happened. Jesus, while heading to a Passover, encountered the movement started by John the Baptist in Judea, and after a little while—if we factor in the forty days he spent in the wilderness mentioned in Mark 1:13, a few weeks later—he appeared in Galilee declaring that the Kingdom of God was near. According to Mark, he had known himself to be the Messiah since his baptism, but from a historical perspective, that doesn't matter, since history focuses on the first announcement of the Messiahship, not on internal psychological processes.270

This work of preaching the Kingdom was continued until the sending forth of the Twelve; that is to say, at the most for a few weeks. Perhaps in the saying “the harvest is great but the labourers are few,” with which Jesus closes His work prior to sending forth the disciples, there lies an allusion to the actual state of the natural fields. The flocking of the people to Him after the Mission of the Twelve, when a great multitude thronged about Him for several days during His journey along the northern shore of the lake, can be more naturally explained if the harvest had just been brought in.

This effort of spreading the message of the Kingdom continued until the sending out of the Twelve, which lasted just a few weeks at most. When Jesus stated, "The harvest is plentiful, but the workers are few." just before sending out the disciples, it might refer to the actual condition of the fields. The way crowds gathered around Him following the Mission of the Twelve, with many people surrounding Him for several days during His journey along the northern shore of the lake, makes more sense if the harvest had just been gathered in.

However that may be, it is certain that Jesus, in the midst of His initial success, left Galilee, journeyed northwards, and only resumed His work as a teacher in Judaea on the way to Jerusalem! Of His “public ministry,” therefore, a large section falls out, being cancelled by a period of inexplicable concealment; it dwindles to [pg 351] a few weeks of preaching here and there in Galilee and the few days of His sojourn in Jerusalem.271

However that may be, it's clear that Jesus, during His early success, left Galilee, traveled north, and only continued His teaching in Judaea on the way to Jerusalem! A significant part of His "public service," is therefore missing, marked by a time of unexplained absence; it reduces to just [pg 351] a few weeks of preaching here and there in Galilee and the few days He spent in Jerusalem.271

But in that case the public life of Jesus becomes practically unintelligible. The explanation that His cause in Galilee was lost, and that He was obliged to flee, has not the slightest foundation in the text.272 That was recognised even by Keim, the inventor of the successful and unsuccessful periods in the life of Jesus, as is shown by his suggestion that the Evangelists had intentionally removed the traces of failure from the decisive period which led up to the northern journey. The controversy over the washing of hands in Mark vii. 1-23, to which appeal is always made, is really a defeat for the Pharisees. The theory of the “desertion of the Galilaeans,” which appears with more or less artistic variations in all modern Lives of Jesus, owes its existence not to any other confirmatory fact, but simply to the circumstance that Mark makes the simple statement: “And Jesus departed and went into the region of Tyre” (vii. 24) without offering any explanation of this decision.

But in that case, the public life of Jesus becomes almost impossible to understand. The idea that his cause in Galilee was lost and that he had to escape has no support in the text.272 Even Keim, who introduced the concepts of successful and unsuccessful periods in Jesus's life, recognized this, as indicated by his suggestion that the Evangelists intentionally omitted any signs of failure from the crucial period leading up to the journey to the north. The debate over handwashing in Mark 7:1-23, frequently cited, is actually a setback for the Pharisees. The theory of the "desertion of the Galileans," which appears in various forms in all modern Lives of Jesus, exists not because of any corroborating evidence, but simply because Mark makes the straightforward statement: "And Jesus left and went to the area of Tyre." (7:24) without giving any explanation for this choice.

The only conclusion which the text warrants is that Mark mentioned no reason because he knew of none. The decision of Jesus did not rest upon the recorded facts, since it ignores these, but upon considerations lying outside the history. His life at this period was dominated by a “dogmatic idea” which rendered Him indifferent to all else ... even to the happy and successful work as a teacher which was opening before Him. How could Jesus the “teacher” abandon at that moment a people so anxious to learn and so eager for salvation? His action suggests a doubt whether He really felt Himself to be a “teacher.” If all the controversial discourses and sayings and answers to questions, which were so to speak wrung from Him, were subtracted from the sum of His utterances, how much of the didactic preaching of Jesus would be left over?

The only conclusion that the text supports is that Mark didn’t mention a reason because he didn't know of one. Jesus's decision didn’t rely on the recorded facts, as it disregards them, but was based on considerations that go beyond the history. During this time, his life was ruled by a “rigid belief” that made him indifferent to everything else... even to the joyful and successful work as a teacher that was unfolding before him. How could Jesus, the “teacher” abandon at that moment a people so eager to learn and desperate for salvation? His actions raise doubt about whether he truly saw himself as a "teacher." If we removed all the controversial discussions, sayings, and answers to questions that were practically forced out of him, how much of Jesus's actual teaching would be left?

But even the supposed didactic preaching is not really that of a “teacher,” since the purpose of His parables was, according to Mark iv. 10-12, not to reveal, but to conceal, and of the Kingdom of God He spoke only in parables (Mark iv. 34).

But even the so-called teaching isn’t truly that of a “educator,” since the purpose of His parables was, according to Mark iv. 10-12, not to reveal, but to conceal, and He spoke about the Kingdom of God only in parables (Mark iv. 34).

Perhaps, however, we are not justified in extending the theory [pg 352] of concealment, simply because it is mentioned in connexion with the first parable, to all the parables which He ever spoke, for it is never mentioned again. It could hardly indeed be applied to the parables with a moral, like that, for instance, of the pearl of great price. It is equally inapplicable to the parables of coming judgment uttered at Jerusalem, in which He explicitly exhorts the people to be prepared and watchful in view of the coming of judgment and of the Kingdom. But here too it is deserving of notice that Jesus, whenever He desires to make known anything further concerning the Kingdom of God than just its near approach, seems to be confined, as it were by a higher law, to the parabolic form of discourse. It is as though, for reasons which we cannot grasp, His teaching lay under certain limitations. It appears as a kind of accessory aspect of His vocation. Thus it was possible for Him to give up His work as a teacher even at the moment when it promised the greatest success.

Maybe, though, we shouldn't assume that the theory of concealment [pg 352] applies to all the parables just because it's mentioned alongside the first one, since it’s never referenced again. It definitely doesn’t seem relevant to the parables with moral lessons, like the one about the pearl of great price. It’s also not suitable for the parables about upcoming judgment spoken in Jerusalem, where He clearly urges the people to be prepared and watchful for the coming judgment and the Kingdom. Moreover, it’s interesting to note that whenever Jesus wants to share more about the Kingdom of God beyond its imminent arrival, he seems to be restricted, as if by some higher principle, to speaking in parables. It feels like, for reasons we can’t fully understand, His teaching was subject to specific limitations. This appears to be a secondary aspect of His mission. Thus, He could step back from His role as a teacher even at the moment when it was poised for the greatest success.

Accordingly the fact of His always speaking in parables and of His taking this inexplicable resolution both point back to a mysterious pre-supposition which greatly reduces the importance of Jesus' work as a teacher.

Accordingly, the fact that He always spoke in parables and made this inexplicable decision both point back to a mysterious assumption that greatly diminishes the significance of Jesus' role as a teacher.

One reason for this limitation is distinctly stated in Mark iv. 10-12, viz. predestination! Jesus knows that the truth which He offers is exclusively for those who have been definitely chosen, that the general and public announcement of His message could only thwart the plans of God, since the chosen are already winning their salvation from God. Only the phrase, “Repent for the Kingdom of God is at hand” and its variants belong to the public preaching. And this, therefore, is the only message which He commits to His disciples when sending them forth. What this repentance, supplementary to the law, the special ethic of the interval before the coming of the Kingdom (Interimsethik) is, in its positive acceptation, He explains in the Sermon on the Mount. But all that goes beyond that simple phrase must be publicly presented only in parables, in order that those only, who are shown to possess predestination by having the initial knowledge which enables them to understand the parables, may receive a more advanced knowledge, which is imparted to them in a measure corresponding to their original degree of knowledge: “Unto him that hath shall be given, and from him that hath not shall be taken away even that which he hath” (Mark iv. 24-25).

One reason for this limitation is clearly stated in Mark 4:10-12, which is predestination! Jesus knows that the truth He offers is only for those who have been specifically chosen, and that publicly announcing His message could hinder God's plans since the chosen are already gaining their salvation from God. Only the phrase, "Change your ways because the Kingdom of God is near." and its variations are meant for public preaching. Because of this, it’s the only message He gives to His disciples when sending them out. He explains what this repentance means, which supplements the law and serves as the special ethic during the time before the coming of the Kingdom (Interim ethics), in the Sermon on the Mount. However, everything that goes beyond that simple phrase must be presented publicly only in parables, so that only those who are shown to have predestination by possessing the initial understanding needed to grasp the parables may receive deeper knowledge, which is given to them in proportion to their original understanding: "To those who have, more will be given, and from those who don't have, even what they do have will be taken away." (Mark 4:24-25).

The predestinarian view goes along with the eschatology. It is pushed to its utmost consequences in the closing incident of the parable of the marriage of the King's son (Matt. xxii. 1-14) where the man who, in response to a publicly issued invitation, sits down at the table of the King, but is recognised from his appearance as not called, is thrown out into perdition. “Many are called but few are chosen.” [pg 353] The ethical idea of salvation and the predestinarian limitation of acceptance to the elect are constantly in conflict in the mind of Jesus. In one case, however, He finds relief in the thought of predestination. When the rich young man turned away, not having strength to give up his possessions for the sake of following Jesus as he had been commanded to do, Jesus and His disciples were forced to draw the conclusion that he, like other rich men, was lost, and could not enter into the Kingdom of God. But immediately afterwards Jesus makes the suggestion, “With men it is impossible, but not with God, for with God all things are possible” (Mark x. 17-27). That is, He will not give up the hope that the young man, in spite of appearances, which are against him, will be found to have belonged to the Kingdom of God, solely in virtue of the secret all-powerful will of God. Of a “conversion” of the young man there is no question.

The predestinarian view aligns with eschatology. It reaches its extreme implications in the final part of the parable of the marriage of the King's son (Matt. xxii. 1-14), where a man, responding to a publicly announced invitation, sits down at the King's table but is recognized by his appearance as uninvited and is thrown out into despair. "Many are called, but few are chosen." [pg 353] The ethical concept of salvation and the idea of predestination for the elect often clash in Jesus's mind. However, He finds some comfort in the thought of predestination when the rich young man walks away, unable to give up his possessions to follow Jesus as instructed. Jesus and His disciples conclude that he, like other wealthy individuals, is lost and cannot enter the Kingdom of God. But immediately after, Jesus suggests, “With humans, it’s impossible, but not with God; for with God, anything is possible.” (Mark x. 17-27). In other words, He holds on to the hope that the young man, despite the odds stacked against him, might still belong to the Kingdom of God, purely due to God’s secret, all-powerful will. There is no talk of a "conversion" of the young man.

In the Beatitudes, on the other hand, the argument is reversed; the predestination is inferred from its outward manifestation. It may seem to us inconceivable, but they are really predestinarian in form. Blessed are the poor in spirit! Blessed are the meek! Blessed are the peacemakers!—that does not mean that by virtue of their being poor in spirit, meek, peace-loving, they deserve the Kingdom. Jesus does not intend the saying as an injunction or exhortation, but as a simple statement of fact: in their being poor in spirit, in their meekness, in their love of peace, it is made manifest that they are predestined to the Kingdom. By the possession of these qualities they are marked as belonging to it. In the case of others (Matt. v. 10-12) the predestination to the Kingdom is made manifest by the persecutions which befall them in this world. These are the light of the world, which already shines among men for the glory of God (Matt. v. 14-15).

In the Beatitudes, the argument flips; predestination is inferred from its outward signs. It may seem hard to believe, but they actually have a predestined form. Blessed are the poor in spirit! Blessed are the meek! Blessed are the peacemakers!—this doesn't mean that just because they are poor in spirit, meek, or peace-loving, they deserve the Kingdom. Jesus isn't giving a command or encouragement; he's simply stating a fact: through their poverty of spirit, meekness, and love for peace, it’s shown that they are destined for the Kingdom. By having these qualities, they are marked as belonging to it. For others (Matt. v. 10-12), their predestination to the Kingdom is shown by the persecutions they face in this world. These are the light of the world, which already shines among people for the glory of God (Matt. v. 14-15).

The kingdom cannot be “earned”; what happens is that men are called to it, and show themselves to be called to it. On careful examination it appears that the idea of reward in the sayings of Jesus is not really an idea of reward, because it is relieved against a background of predestination. For the present it is sufficient to note the fact that the eschatologico-predestinarian view brings a mysterious element of dogma not merely into the teaching, but also into the public ministry of Jesus.

The kingdom can’t be "earned"; instead, people are called to it and reveal their calling. Upon closer look, it seems that the concept of reward in Jesus' teachings isn't truly about rewards, as it exists within the context of predestination. For now, it's enough to acknowledge that the eschatological-predestinarian perspective adds an element of mystery to both Jesus' teachings and His public ministry.

To take another point, what is the mystery of the Kingdom of God? It must consist of something more than merely its near approach, and something of extreme importance; otherwise Jesus would be here indulging in mere mystery-mongering. The saying about the candle which He puts upon the stand, in order that what was hidden may be revealed to those who have ears to hear, implies that He is making a tremendous revelation to those who understand the parables about the growth of the seed. The mystery must [pg 354] therefore contain the explanation why the Kingdom must now come, and how men are to know how near it is. For the general fact that it is very near had already been openly proclaimed both by the Baptist and by Jesus. The mystery, therefore, must consist of something more than that.

To take another perspective, what is the mystery of the Kingdom of God? It must be about more than just its imminent arrival, and something of great significance; otherwise, Jesus would just be engaging in pointless speculation. The saying about the candle that He puts on the stand so that what was hidden can be revealed to those who are willing to listen suggests that He is making a significant revelation to those who understand the parables about the seed's growth. The mystery must [pg 354] therefore include the explanation of why the Kingdom needs to come now, and how people will know how close it is. The simple fact that it is very close had already been openly stated by both the Baptist and Jesus. So, the mystery must involve something more than that.

In these parables it is not the idea of development, but of the apparent absence of causation which occupies the foremost place. The description aims at suggesting the question, how, and by what power, incomparably great and glorious results can be infallibly produced by an insignificant fact without human aid. A man sowed seed. Much of it was lost, but the little that fell into good ground brought forth a harvest—thirty, sixty, an hundredfold—which left no trace of the loss in the sowing. How did that come about?

In these parables, the main focus is not on the idea of growth, but on the seeming lack of a cause-and-effect relationship. The description raises the question of how, and by what power, incredibly great and glorious results can be produced effortlessly from something insignificant, without any human effort. A man sowed seeds. A lot of it was lost, but the little that landed on good soil yielded a harvest—thirty, sixty, even a hundred times as much—which erased all evidence of the loss during sowing. How did that happen?

A man sows seed and does not trouble any further about it—cannot indeed do anything to help it, but he knows that after a definite time the glorious harvest which arises out of the seed will stand before him. By what power is that effected?

A man plants seeds and doesn't worry about it anymore—there's nothing he can do to help it, but he knows that after a certain time, the amazing harvest that comes from the seeds will be right in front of him. How does that happen?

An extremely minute grain of mustard seed is planted in the earth and there necessarily arises out of it a great bush, which cannot certainly have been contained in the grain of seed. How was that?

A tiny grain of mustard seed is planted in the ground, and from it grows a large bush that definitely couldn't have been contained in the seed. How did that happen?

What the parables emphasise is, therefore, so to speak, the in itself negative, inadequate, character of the initial fact, upon which, as by a miracle, there follows in the appointed time, through the power of God, some great thing. They lay stress not upon the natural, but upon the miraculous character of such occurrences.

What the parables emphasize is, so to speak, the inherently negative and inadequate nature of the initial fact, which, like a miracle, is followed in due time by something great through the power of God. They focus not on the natural but on the miraculous nature of such events.

But what is the initial fact of the parables? It is the sowing.

But what is the initial fact of the parables? It is the sowing.

It is not said that by the man who sows the seed Jesus means Himself. The man has no importance. In the parable of the mustard seed he is not even mentioned. All that is asserted is that the initial fact is already present, as certainly present as the time of the sowing is past at the moment when Jesus speaks. That being so, the Kingdom of God must follow as certainly as harvest follows seed-sowing. As a man believes in the harvest, without being able to explain it, simply because the seed has been sown; so with the same absolute confidence he may believe in the Kingdom of God.

It doesn't say that the man who sows the seed represents Jesus. The man doesn’t matter. In the parable of the mustard seed, he isn’t even mentioned. What’s clear is that the initial fact is already there, as certainly present as the time for sowing has passed when Jesus speaks. With that in mind, the Kingdom of God must come just as surely as the harvest comes after sowing seeds. Just like a person believes in the harvest, even if they can’t explain it, simply because the seeds were sown; in the same way, they can confidently believe in the Kingdom of God.

And the initial fact which is symbolised? Jesus can only mean a fact which was actually in existence—the movement of repentance evoked by the Baptist and now intensified by His own preaching. That necessarily involves the bringing in of the Kingdom by the power of God; as man's sowing necessitates the giving of the harvest by the same Infinite Power. Any one who knows this sees with different eyes the corn growing in the fields [pg 355] and the harvest ripening, for he sees the one fact in the other, and awaits along with the earthly harvest the heavenly, the revelation of the Kingdom of God.

And what is the initial fact being represented? Jesus can only refer to something that actually existed—the wave of repentance stirred up by the Baptist and now heightened by His own teachings. This inevitably includes the establishment of the Kingdom through the power of God; just as a person's planting requires the same Infinite Power to provide the harvest. Anyone who understands this sees the corn growing in the fields [pg 355] and the harvest maturing with a different perspective, as they recognize that one fact leads to the other, and they anticipate, alongside the earthly harvest, the heavenly one—the unveiling of the Kingdom of God.

If we look into the thought more closely we see that the coming of the Kingdom of God is not only symbolically or analogically, but also really and temporally connected with the harvest. The harvest ripening upon earth is the last! With it comes also the Kingdom of God which brings in the new age. When the reapers are sent into the fields, the Lord in Heaven will cause His harvest to be reaped by the holy angels.

If we examine this idea more closely, we can see that the arrival of the Kingdom of God is not just symbolic or metaphorical, but also genuinely and temporally linked to the harvest. The harvest maturing on earth is the final one! Along with it comes the Kingdom of God, ushering in a new era. When the reapers are dispatched into the fields, the Lord in Heaven will have His harvest gathered by the holy angels.

If the three parables of Mark iv. contain the mystery of the Kingdom of God, and are therefore capable of being summed up in a single formula, this can be nothing else than the joyful exhortation: “Ye who have eyes to see, read, in the harvest which is ripening upon earth, what is being prepared in heaven!” The eager eschatological hope was to regard the natural process as the last of its kind, and to see in it a special significance in view of the event of which it was to give the signal.

If the three parables in Mark 4 contain the mystery of the Kingdom of God, and can therefore be summarized with a single statement, it can only be this joyful encouragement: "You with the ability to see, pay attention to the harvest that's maturing on earth, and notice what’s being prepared in heaven!" The enthusiastic hope for the end times was to view the natural process as the final one of its kind, and to see special meaning in it in light of the event it was signaling.

The analogical and temporal parallelism becomes complete if we assume that the movement initiated by the Baptist began in the spring, and notice that Jesus, according to Matt. ix. 37 and 38, before sending out the disciples to make a speedy proclamation of the nearness of the Kingdom of God, uttered the remarkable saying about the rich harvest. It seems like a final expression of the thought contained in the parables about the seed and its promise, and finds its most natural explanation in the supposition that the harvest was actually at hand.

The comparison and timing parallelism becomes complete if we assume that the movement started by the Baptist began in the spring. We also see that Jesus, according to Matt. ix. 37 and 38, before sending out the disciples to quickly announce the closeness of the Kingdom of God, made the notable remark about the plentiful harvest. This seems to be a final expression of the idea found in the parables about the seed and its promise, and it makes the most sense to assume that the harvest was indeed approaching.

Whatever may be thought of this attempt to divine historically the secret of the Kingdom of God, there is one thing that cannot be got away from, viz. that the initial fact to which Jesus points, under the figure of the sowing, is somehow or other connected with the eschatological preaching of repentance, which had been begun by the Baptist.

Whatever people might think about this effort to historically uncover the secret of the Kingdom of God, one thing is clear: the fundamental truth that Jesus highlights through the metaphor of sowing is somehow linked to the eschatological message of repentance that was initiated by the Baptist.

That may be the more confidently asserted because Jesus in another mysterious saying describes the days of the Baptist as a time which makes preparation for the coming of the Kingdom of God. “From the days of John the Baptist,” He says in Matt. xi. 12, “even until now, the Kingdom of Heaven is subjected to violence, and the violent wrest it to themselves.” The saying has nothing to do with the entering of individuals into the Kingdom; it simply asserts, that since the coming of the Baptist a certain number of persons are engaged in forcing on and compelling the coming of the Kingdom. Jesus' expectation of the Kingdom is an expectation based upon a fact which exercises an active influence upon the Kingdom of God. It was not He, and not the Baptist who “were working at the coming of the Kingdom”; it is the host [pg 356] of penitents which is wringing it from God, so that it may now come at any moment.

That might be stated more confidently because Jesus, in another mysterious saying, describes the days of the Baptist as a time that prepares for the arrival of the Kingdom of God. "From the time of John the Baptist," He says in Matt. xi. 12, "Even now, the Kingdom of Heaven is being attacked, and the aggressive force their way in." This saying doesn't pertain to individuals entering the Kingdom; it simply states that since the Baptist's arrival, a certain number of people are actively trying to bring about and hasten the coming of the Kingdom. Jesus' expectation of the Kingdom is based on a reality that actively influences the Kingdom of God. It wasn’t Him, nor the Baptist, who "were working toward the arrival of the Kingdom"; it is the multitude [pg 356] of penitents who are pressing for it from God, so that it could arrive at any moment.

The eschatological insight of Johannes Weiss made an end of the modern view that Jesus founded the Kingdom. It did away with all activity, as exercised upon the Kingdom of God, and made the part of Jesus purely a waiting one. Now the activity comes back into the preaching of the Kingdom, but this time eschatologically conditioned. The secret of the Kingdom of God which Jesus unveils in the parables about confident expectation in Mark iv., and declares in so many words in the eulogy on the Baptist (Matt. xi.), amounts to this, that in the movement to which the Baptist gave the first impulse, and which still continued, there was an initial fact which was drawing after it the coming of the Kingdom, in a fashion which was miraculous, unintelligible, but unfailingly certain, since the sufficient cause for it lay in the power and purpose of God.

The eschatological insight of Johannes Weiss ended the modern belief that Jesus established the Kingdom. It removed all actions related to the Kingdom of God and made Jesus's role solely about waiting. Now, activity is returning to the preaching of the Kingdom, but this time it's seen through an eschatological lens. The secret of the Kingdom of God, which Jesus reveals in the parables about confident expectation in Mark 4, and explicitly states in his praise of the Baptist (Matt. 11), is that within the movement sparked by the Baptist, which continued on, there was an initial event that was drawing the Kingdom’s arrival in a way that was miraculous, incomprehensible, yet unfailingly certain, because the sufficient cause for it was rooted in the power and purpose of God.

It should be observed that Jesus in these parables, as well as in the related saying at the sending forth of the Twelve, uses the formula, “He that hath ears to hear, let him hear” (Mark iv. 23 and Matt. xi. 15), thereby signifying that in this utterance there lies concealed a supernatural knowledge concerning the plans of God, which only those who have ears to hear—that is, the foreordained—can detect. For others these sayings are unintelligible.

It should be noted that Jesus, in these parables and in the related statement made when sending out the Twelve, uses the phrase, "Anyone who can hear, let them listen." (Mark iv. 23 and Matt. xi. 15). This indicates that there is hidden knowledge about God's plans in this statement, which only those with the ability to hear—meaning those chosen for this understanding—can perceive. For others, these statements are confusing.

If this genuinely “historical” interpretation of the mystery of the Kingdom of God is correct, Jesus must have expected the coming of the Kingdom at harvest time. And that is just what He did expect. It is for that reason that He sends out His disciples to make known in Israel, as speedily as may be, what is about to happen. That in this He is actuated by a dogmatic idea, becomes clear when we notice that, according to Mark, the mission of the Twelve followed immediately on the rejection at Nazareth. The unreceptiveness of the Nazarenes had made no impression upon Him; He was only astonished at their unbelief (Mark vi. 6). This passage is often interpreted to mean that He was astonished to find His miracle-working power fail Him. There is no hint of that in the text. What He is astonished at is, that in His native town there were so few believers, that is, elect, knowing as He does that the Kingdom of God may appear at any moment. But that fact makes no difference whatever to the nearness of the coming of the Kingdom.

If this truly "historical" interpretation of the mystery of the Kingdom of God is accurate, Jesus must have expected the Kingdom to come at harvest time. And that’s exactly what He did expect. That’s why He sends out His disciples to quickly announce what’s about to happen in Israel. It becomes clear that He is driven by a firm belief when we see that, according to Mark, the mission of the Twelve immediately followed the rejection in Nazareth. The lack of acceptance from the Nazarenes didn’t affect Him; He was only surprised by their unbelief (Mark vi. 6). Many often interpret this passage as saying He was shocked because His ability to perform miracles failed Him. However, there’s no indication of that in the text. What surprises Him is the lack of believers in His hometown—so few who are chosen—knowing, as He does, that the Kingdom of God could appear at any moment. But that fact does not change how close the coming of the Kingdom is.

The Evangelist, therefore, places the rejection at Nazareth and the mission of the Twelve side by side, simply because he found them in this temporal connexion in the tradition. If he had been working by “association of ideas,” he would not have arrived at this order. The want of connexion, the impossibility of applying any natural explanation, is just what is historical, because the course of [pg 357] the history was determined, not by outward events, but by the decisions of Jesus, and these were determined by dogmatic, eschatological considerations.

The Evangelist, therefore, puts the rejection at Nazareth and the mission of the Twelve next to each other because he found them connected in the tradition. If he had been following a "stream of consciousness" approach, he wouldn't have put them in this order. The lack of connection and the inability to apply any natural explanation is what makes it historical, as the course of [pg 357] history was shaped not by external events, but by Jesus's decisions, which were influenced by theological and future-oriented considerations.

To how great an extent this was the case in regard to the mission of the Twelve is clearly seen from the “charge” which Jesus gave them. He tells them in plain words (Matt. x. 23), that He does not expect to see them back in the present age. The Parousia of the Son of Man, which is logically and temporally identical with the dawn of the Kingdom, will take place before they shall have completed a hasty journey through the cities of Israel to announce it. That the words mean this and nothing else, that they ought not to be in any way weakened down, should be sufficiently evident. This is the form in which Jesus reveals to them the secret of the Kingdom of God. A few days later, He utters the saying about the violent who, since the days of John the Baptist, are forcing on the coming of the Kingdom.

To what extent this was true for the mission of the Twelve is clearly shown by the "charge" that Jesus gave them. He tells them plainly (Matt. x. 23) that He does not expect to see them back in this age. The return of the Son of Man, which is both logically and temporally the same as the beginning of the Kingdom, will happen before they finish a quick journey through the cities of Israel to announce it. It’s clear that these words mean exactly this and nothing else; they shouldn’t be weakened in any way. This is how Jesus discloses to them the secret of the Kingdom of God. A few days later, He makes the statement about the violent who, since the days of John the Baptist, have been forcing the coming of the Kingdom.

It is equally clear, and here the dogmatic considerations which guided the resolutions of Jesus become still more prominent, that this prediction was not fulfilled. The disciples returned to Him; and the appearing of the Son of Man had not taken place. The actual history disavowed the dogmatic history on which the action of Jesus had been based. An event of supernatural history which must take place, and must take place at that particular point of time, failed to come about. That was for Jesus, who lived wholly in the dogmatic history, the first “historical” occurrence, the central event which closed the former period of His activity and gave the coming period a new character. To this extent modern theology is justified when it distinguishes two periods in the Life of Jesus; an earlier, in which He is surrounded by the people, a later in which He is “deserted” by them, and travels about with the Twelve only. It is a sound observation that the two periods are sharply distinguished by the attitude of Jesus. To explain this difference of attitude, which they thought themselves bound to account for on natural historical grounds, theologians of the modern historical school invented the theory of growing opposition and waning support. Weisse, no doubt, had expressed himself in direct opposition to this theory.273 Keim, who gave it its place in theology, was aware that in setting it up he was going against the plain sense of the texts. Later writers lost this consciousness, just as in the first and third Gospel the significance of the Messianic secret in [pg 358] Mark gradually faded away; they imagined that they could find the basis of fact for the theory in the texts, and did not realise that they only believed in the desertion of the multitude and the “flights and retirements” of Jesus because they could not otherwise explain historically the alteration in His conduct, His withdrawal from public work, and His resolve to die.

It is also clear, and here the dogmatic ideas guiding Jesus' decisions become even more apparent, that this prediction did not come true. The disciples came back to Him, and the appearance of the Son of Man hadn’t happened. Actual history contradicted the dogmatic history that Jesus' actions were based on. A supernatural event that was supposed to happen, and was supposed to happen at a specific time, did not occur. For Jesus, who was completely immersed in the dogmatic history, this was the first historical event, the key moment that marked the end of the earlier phase of His mission and gave the next phase a new direction. In this sense, modern theology is justified in distinguishing two periods in Jesus' life: an earlier time when He was surrounded by the people, and a later time when He was abandoned by them, traveling only with the Twelve. It is a valid observation that the two periods are clearly defined by Jesus' attitude. To explain this change in attitude, which they felt they needed to account for using natural historical explanations, theologians from the modern historical school came up with the theory of increasing opposition and diminishing support. Weisse, without a doubt, expressed himself in direct opposition to this theory. Keim, who established it within theology, recognized that he was contradicting the plain meaning of the texts. Later writers lost this awareness, just as the significance of the Messianic secret in [pg 358] Mark gradually diminished; they believed they could find factual support for the theory in the texts and did not realize that they only accepted the idea of the crowd abandoning Jesus and His "flights and getaways" because they could not otherwise explain the change in His behavior, His withdrawal from public ministry, and His decision to die.

The thoroughgoing eschatological school makes better work of it. They recognise in the non-occurrence of the Parousia promised in Matt. x. 23, the “historic fact,” in the estimation of Jesus, which in some way determined the alteration in His plans, and His attitude towards the multitude.

The comprehensive eschatological school does a better job with this. They see the absence of the Parousia promised in Matt. x. 23 as the "historical fact," in Jesus' view, which somehow influenced the changes in His plans and His attitude toward the crowd.

The whole history of “Christianity” down to the present day, that is to say, the real inner history of it, is based on the delay of the Parousia, the non-occurrence of the Parousia, the abandonment of eschatology, the progress and completion of the “de-eschatologising” of religion which has been connected therewith. It should be noted that the non-fulfilment of Matt. x. 23 is the first postponement of the Parousia. We have therefore here the first significant date in the “history of Christianity”; it gives to the work of Jesus a new direction, otherwise inexplicable.

The entire history of “Christianity” up to today, specifically the real inner history of it, revolves around the delay of the Parousia, its non-appearance, the abandonment of eschatology, and the gradual move away from the "de-eschatologizing" of religion that has come with it. It's important to point out that the non-fulfillment of Matt. x. 23 marks the first postponement of the Parousia. This represents the first significant moment in the “Christianity history”; it gives Jesus' work a new direction that would otherwise be hard to explain.

Here we recognise also why the Marcan hypothesis, in constructing its view of the Life of Jesus, found itself obliged to have recourse more and more to the help of modern psychology, and thus necessarily became more and more unhistorical. The fact which alone makes possible an understanding of the whole, is lacking in this Gospel. Without Matt. x. and xi. everything remains enigmatic. For this reason Bruno Bauer and Wrede are in their own way the only consistent representatives of the Marcan hypothesis from the point of view of historical criticism, when they arrive at the result that the Marcan account is inherently unintelligible. Keim, with his strong sense of historical reality, rightly felt that the plan of the Life of Jesus should not be constructed exclusively on the basis of Mark.

Here we recognize also why the Marcan hypothesis, in shaping its view of the Life of Jesus, increasingly had to rely on modern psychology, and thus inevitably became less historical. The key fact necessary for understanding the whole is missing in this Gospel. Without Matt. x. and xi. everything remains puzzling. For this reason, Bruno Bauer and Wrede are, in their own way, the only consistent advocates of the Marcan hypothesis from a historical criticism perspective, arriving at the conclusion that the Marcan account is fundamentally unintelligible. Keim, with his strong sense of historical reality, rightly believed that the narrative of the Life of Jesus should not be based solely on Mark.

The recognition that Mark alone gives an inadequate basis, is more important than any “Ur-Markus” theories, for which it is impossible to discover a literary foundation, or find an historical use. A simple induction from the “facts” takes us beyond Mark. In the discourse-material of Matthew, which the modern-historical school thought they could sift in here and there, wherever there seemed to be room for it, there lie hidden certain facts—facts which never happened but are all the more important for that.

The realization that Mark alone provides an insufficient foundation is more significant than any “Ur-Markus” theories, as there is no way to identify a literary source or find a historical application for them. A straightforward deduction from the "facts" leads us beyond Mark. Within the discourse material of Matthew, which the modern historical school believed they could sift in and out wherever it seemed appropriate, certain facts are hidden—facts that never occurred but are all the more critical for that reason.

Why Mark describes the events and discourses in the neighbourhood of the mission of the Twelve with such careful authentication is a literary question which the historical study of the life of Jesus may leave open; the more so since, even as a literary question, it is insoluble.

Why Mark describes the events and discussions around the mission of the Twelve with such careful validation is a literary question that the historical study of Jesus's life might not answer; especially since, even as a literary question, it is unresolvable.

[pg 359]

The prediction of the Parousia of the Son of Man is not the only one which remained unfulfilled. There is the prediction of sufferings which is connected with it. To put it more accurately, the prediction of the appearing of the Son of Man in Matt. x. 23 runs up into a prediction of sufferings, which, working up to a climax, forms the remainder of the discourse at the sending forth of the disciples. This prediction of sufferings has as little to do with objective history as the prediction of the Parousia. Consequently, none of the Lives of Jesus, which follow the lines of a natural psychology, from Weisse down to Oskar Holtzmann, can make anything of it.274 They either strike it out, or transfer it to the last “gloomy epoch” of the life of Jesus, regard it as an unintelligible anticipation, or put it down to the account of “primitive theology,” which serves as a scrap-heap for everything for which they cannot find a place in the “historical life of Jesus.”

The prediction of the return of the Son of Man isn’t the only one that hasn’t come true. There’s also a prediction about suffering that’s linked to it. To be more precise, the prediction of the Son of Man’s appearance in Matt. x. 23 leads into a prediction of suffering that builds up to a climax, forming the rest of the speech when the disciples are sent out. This prediction of suffering has just as little connection to actual history as the prediction of the return. As a result, none of the Lives of Jesus, which follow a more psychological approach, from Weisse to Oskar Holtzmann, can make sense of it. They either ignore it, or move it to the final “dark times” of Jesus’ life, treating it as an unintelligible prediction, or classify it as "basic theology," which acts as a catch-all for anything they can’t fit into the "life of Jesus in history."

In the texts it is quite evident that Jesus is not speaking of sufferings after His death, but of sufferings which will befall them as soon as they have gone forth from Him. The death of Jesus is not here pre-supposed, but only the Parousia of the Son of Man, and it is implied that this will occur just after these sufferings and bring them to a close. If the theology of the primitive Church had remoulded the tradition, as is always being asserted, it would have made Jesus give His followers directions for their conduct after His death. That we do not find anything of this kind is the best proof that there can be no question of a remoulding of the Life of Jesus by primitive theology. How easy it would have been for the Early Church to scatter here and there through the discourses of Jesus directions which were only to be applied after His death! But the simple fact is that it did not do so.

In the texts, it's clear that Jesus isn't talking about suffering after His death, but about suffering that will come as soon as His followers leave Him. His death isn't assumed here; rather, it's just the return of the Son of Man that is implied to happen right after these sufferings and to put an end to them. If the early Church had changed the tradition, as is often claimed, it would have made Jesus provide guidelines for His followers' actions after He died. The absence of anything like that is strong evidence that there's no basis for saying primitive theology changed the Life of Jesus. It would have been easy for the Early Church to insert directions throughout Jesus' teachings meant to be followed after His death, but the fact is that it simply didn't happen.

The sufferings of which the prospect is held out at the sending forth are doubly, trebly, nay four times over, unhistorical. In the first place—and this is the only point which modern historical theology has noticed—because there is not a shadow of a suggestion in the outward circumstances of anything which could form a natural occasion for such predictions of, and exhortations relating to, sufferings. In the second place—and this has been overlooked by modern theology because it had already declared them to be unhistorical in its own characteristic fashion, viz. by striking them out—because they were not fulfilled. In the third place—and this has not entered into the mind of modern theology at all—because these sayings were spoken in the closest connexion [pg 360] with the promise of the Parousia and are placed in the closest connexion with that event. In the fourth place, because the description of that which is to befall the disciples is quite without any basis in experience. A time of general dissension will begin, in which brothers will rise up against brothers, and fathers against sons and children against their parents to cause them to be put to death (Matt. x. 21). And the disciples “shall be hated of all men for His name's sake.” Let them strive to hold out to the “end,” that is, to the coming of the Son of Man, in order that they may be saved (Matt. x. 22).

The sufferings that are mentioned at the beginning are completely unhistorical—doubly, triply, even four times over. Firstly—and this is the only aspect that modern historical theology has acknowledged—there’s not even a hint in the outward circumstances that could justify such predictions or encouragements related to suffering. Secondly—and this has been ignored by modern theology since it has already labeled them as unhistorical by simply omitting them—because these predictions were not fulfilled. Thirdly—and this hasn’t crossed the minds of modern theologians at all—because these statements were made in direct connection with the promise of the Second Coming and are closely related to that event. Fourthly, because the description of what will happen to the disciples is entirely without any basis in actual experience. A time of widespread conflict will start, where siblings will turn against each other, and parents against their children, leading to death (Matt. x. 21). And the disciples “shall be hated by everyone because of His name.” They are encouraged to hold out until the “end,” meaning the arrival of the Son of Man, so that they may be saved (Matt. x. 22).

But why should they suddenly be hated and persecuted for the name of Jesus, seeing that this name played no part whatever in their preaching? That is simply inconceivable. The relation of Jesus to the Son of Man, the fact, that is to say, that it is He who is to be manifested as Son of Man, must therefore in some way or other become known in the interval; not, however, through the disciples, but by some other means of revelation. A kind of supernatural illumination will suddenly make known all that Jesus has been keeping secret regarding the Kingdom of God and His position in the Kingdom. This illumination will arise as suddenly and without preparation as the spirit of strife.

But why should they suddenly be hated and persecuted for the name of Jesus, especially since this name had nothing to do with their preaching? That just doesn't make sense. The connection between Jesus and the Son of Man, meaning that He is the one who will be revealed as the Son of Man, must somehow become known during this time; not, however, through the disciples, but by some other means of revelation. A kind of supernatural insight will suddenly reveal everything Jesus has been keeping secret about the Kingdom of God and His role in it. This insight will come just as suddenly and unexpectedly as the spirit of conflict.

And as a matter of fact Jesus predicts to the disciples in the same discourse that to their own surprise a supernatural wisdom will suddenly speak from their lips, so that it will be not they but the Spirit of God who will answer the great ones of the earth. As the Spirit is for Jesus and early Christian theology something concrete which is to descend upon the elect among mankind only in consequence of a definite event—the outpouring of the Spirit which, according to the prophecy of Joel, should precede the day of judgment—Jesus must have anticipated that this would occur during the absence of the disciples, in the midst of the time of strife and confusion.

And actually, Jesus tells the disciples in the same talk that, to their surprise, a supernatural wisdom will suddenly come out of their mouths, so it won't be them speaking but the Spirit of God answering the powerful people of the world. For Jesus and early Christian theology, the Spirit is something real that will come down on the chosen ones among humanity only as a result of a specific event—the outpouring of the Spirit that, according to Joel's prophecy, should happen before the day of judgment. Jesus must have expected that this would take place while the disciples were away, during a time of conflict and chaos.

To put it differently; the whole of the discourse at the sending forth of the Twelve, taken in the clear sense of the words, is a prediction of the events of the “time of the end,” events which are immediately at hand, in which the supernatural eschatological course of history will break through into the natural course. The expectation of sufferings is therefore doctrinal and unhistorical, as is, precisely in the same way, the expectation of the pouring forth of the Spirit uttered at the same time. The Parousia of the Son of Man is to be preceded according to the Messianic dogma by a time of strife and confusion—as it were, the birth-throes of the Messiah—and the outpouring of the Spirit. It should be noticed that according to Joel iii. and iv. the outpouring of the Spirit, along with the miraculous signs, forms the prelude to the judgment; and also, that in the same context, Joel iii. 13, the judgment [pg 361] is described as the harvest-day of God.275 Here we have a remarkable parallel to the saying about the harvest in Matt. ix. 38, which forms the introduction to the discourse at the sending forth of the disciples.

To say it differently, the entire discussion about sending out the Twelve is essentially a prediction of the events of the "end times," which are just around the corner—events where the supernatural unfolding of history will break into our natural experience. The expectation of suffering is both doctrinal and not historically grounded, similar to the expectation of the Spirit being poured out at the same time. According to Messianic belief, the return of the Son of Man will be preceded by a period of conflict and turmoil—like the birth pains of the Messiah—along with the outpouring of the Spirit. It's important to note that according to Joel chapters 3 and 4, the outpouring of the Spirit, together with miraculous signs, is the lead-up to judgment. Additionally, within that same context in Joel 3:13, the judgment is described as God's harvest day. Here we find a striking parallel to the saying about the harvest in Matt. 9:38, which serves as the introduction to the discourse on sending out the disciples.

There is only one point in which the predicted course of eschatological events is incomplete: the appearance of Elias is not mentioned.

There is only one point where the predicted course of end-of-the-world events is incomplete: the appearance of Elijah is not mentioned.

Jesus could not prophesy to the disciples the Parousia of the Son of Man without pointing them, at the same time, to the pre-eschatological events which must first occur. He must open to them a part of the secret of the Kingdom of God, viz. the nearness of the harvest, that they might not be taken by surprise and caused to doubt by these events.

Jesus couldn't tell the disciples about the coming of the Son of Man without also highlighting the events that would happen before the end times. He needed to reveal to them part of the mystery of the Kingdom of God, specifically the imminent harvest, so they wouldn't be caught off guard or start to doubt because of these events.

Thus this discourse is historical as a whole and down to the smallest detail precisely because, according to the view of modern theology, it must be judged unhistorical. It is, in fact, full of eschatological dogma. Jesus had no need to instruct the disciples as to what they were to teach; for they had only to utter a cry. But concerning the events which should supervene, it was necessary that He should give them information. Therefore the discourse does not consist of instruction, but of predictions of sufferings and of the Parousia.

So this discourse is historical overall and in every detail precisely because, according to modern theology, it is often seen as unhistorical. In reality, it is packed with eschatological beliefs. Jesus didn’t need to tell the disciples what to teach; they only had to call out. But when it came to the events that would happen later, He needed to inform them. Therefore, the discourse isn’t about instruction but rather about predictions of suffering and the Parousia.

That being so, we may judge with what right the modern psychological theology dismisses the great Matthaean discourses off-hand as mere “composite structures.” Just let any one try to show how the Evangelist when he was racking his brains over the task of making a “discourse at the sending forth of the disciples,” [pg 362] half by the method of piecing it together out of traditional sayings and “primitive theology,” and half by inventing it, lighted on the curious idea of making Jesus speak entirely of inopportune and unpractical matters; and of then going on to provide the evidence that they never happened.

That being said, we can assess how justified modern psychological theology is in dismissing the great Matthaean discourses as just "composite structures." Just let anyone try to explain how the Evangelist, while struggling to create a "discussion at the sending out of the disciples," [pg 362] put together this idea of having Jesus talk solely about irrelevant and impractical issues; and then proceeded to offer proof that these things never actually occurred.

The foretelling of the sufferings that belong to the eschatological distress is part and parcel of the preaching of the approach of the Kingdom of God, it embodies the secret of the Kingdom. It is for that reason that the thought of suffering appears at the end of the Beatitudes and in the closing petition of the Lord's Prayer. For the πειρασμός which is there in view is not an individual psychological temptation, but the general eschatological time of tribulation, from which God is besought to exempt those who pray so earnestly for the coming of the Kingdom, and not to expose them to that tribulation by way of putting them to the test.

The prediction of the suffering associated with the end times is an essential part of preaching about the arrival of the Kingdom of God; it reveals the essence of the Kingdom. This is why the idea of suffering appears at the end of the Beatitudes and in the final request of the Lord's Prayer. The πειρασμός mentioned here isn't just a personal psychological temptation; it's the broader end times period of hardship. Those who pray intensely for the Kingdom's arrival ask God to spare them from this suffering and not to subject them to that test.

There followed neither the sufferings, nor the outpouring of the Spirit, nor the Parousia of the Son of Man. The disciples returned safe and sound and full of a proud satisfaction; for one promise had been realised—the power which had been given them over the demons.

There followed neither the suffering, nor the outpouring of the Spirit, nor the return of the Son of Man. The disciples came back safe and sound, filled with a sense of proud satisfaction; for one promise had been fulfilled—the power that had been given to them over the demons.

But from the moment when they rejoined Him, all His thoughts and efforts were devoted to getting rid of the people in order to be alone with them (Mark vi. 30-33). Previously, during their absence, He had, almost in open speech, taught the multitude concerning the Baptist, concerning that which was to precede the coming of the Kingdom, and concerning the judgment which should come upon the impenitent, even upon whole towns of them (Matt. xi. 20-24), because, in spite of the miracles which they had witnessed, they had not recognised the day of grace and diligently used it for repentance. At the same time He had rejoiced before them over all those whom God had enlightened that they might see what was going forward; and had called them to His side (Matt. xi. 25-30).

But from the moment they rejoined Him, all His thoughts and efforts were focused on getting rid of the crowd so He could be alone with them (Mark vi. 30-33). Before this, while they were away, He had openly taught the people about the Baptist, what needed to happen before the Kingdom came, and the judgment that would fall on those who refused to repent, even entire towns (Matt. xi. 20-24). Despite witnessing the miracles, they hadn't recognized the time of grace and hadn't used it to repent. At the same time, He had celebrated with them over those whom God had opened their eyes to see what was happening and had called them to come to Him (Matt. xi. 25-30).

And now suddenly, the moment the disciples return, His one thought is to get away from the people. They, however, follow Him and overtake Him on the shores of the lake. He puts the Jordan between Himself and them by crossing to Bethsaida. They also come to Bethsaida. He returns to Capernaum. They do the same. Since in Galilee it is impossible for Him to be alone, and He absolutely must be alone, He “slips away” to the north. Once more modern theology was right: He really does flee; not, however, from hostile Scribes, but from the people, who dog His footsteps in order to await in His company the appearing of the Kingdom of God and of the Son of Man—to await it in vain.276

And then suddenly, the moment the disciples come back, His only thought is to escape from the crowd. They, however, follow Him and catch up with Him on the shores of the lake. He puts the Jordan River between Himself and them by crossing over to Bethsaida. They also go to Bethsaida. He returns to Capernaum. They do the same. Since it’s impossible for Him to be alone in Galilee, and He absolutely needs to be alone, He "drifts away" to the north. Once again, modern theology got it right: He really does flee; not from hostile scribes, but from the people, who trail behind Him to wait for the arrival of the Kingdom of God and the Son of Man—to wait for it in vain.276

[pg 363]

In Strauss's first Life of Jesus the question is thrown out whether, in view of Matt. x. 23, Jesus did not think of His Parousia as a transformation which should take place during His lifetime. Ghillany bases his work on this possibility as on an established historical fact. Dalman takes this hypothesis to be the necessary correlative of the interpretation of the self-designation Son of Man on the basis of Daniel and the Apocalypses.

In Strauss's first Life of Jesus, the question is raised whether, considering Matt. x. 23, Jesus saw His Parousia as a transformation that would occur during His lifetime. Ghillany builds his work on this possibility as if it were an established historical fact. Dalman regards this hypothesis as a necessary counterpart to the interpretation of the self-designation Son of Man based on Daniel and the Apocalypses.

If Jesus, he argues, designated Himself in this futuristic sense as the Son of Man who comes from Heaven, He must have assumed that He would first be transported thither. “A man who had died or been rapt away from the earth might perhaps be brought into the world again in this way, or one who had never been on earth might so descend thither.” But as this conception of transformation and removal seems to Dalman untenable in the case of Jesus, he treats it as a reductio ad absurdum of the eschatological interpretation of the title.

If Jesus, he argues, saw Himself in this forward-looking way as the Son of Man who comes from Heaven, He must have assumed that He would first be taken there. “A man who had died or been removed from the world could possibly return this way, or someone who had never existed on earth might come down this way.” But since this idea of transformation and removal seems unreasonable to Dalman in the case of Jesus, he views it as a reduction to absurdity of the eschatological interpretation of the title.

But why? If Jesus as a man walking in a natural body upon earth, predicts to His disciples the Parousia of the Son of Man in the immediate future, with the secret conviction that He Himself was to be revealed as the Son of Man, He must have made precisely this assumption that He would first be supernaturally removed and transformed. He thought of Himself as any one must who believes in the immediate coming of the last things, as living in two different conditions: the present, and the future condition into which He is to be transferred at the coming of the new supernatural world. We learn later that the disciples on the way up to Jerusalem were entirely possessed by the thought of what they should be when this transformation took place. They contend as to who shall have the highest position (Mark ix. 33); James and John wish Jesus to promise them in advance the thrones on His right hand and on His left (Mark x. 35-37).

But why? If Jesus, as a man walking on earth in a physical body, predicts to His disciples the return of the Son of Man in the near future, with the underlying belief that He Himself would be revealed as the Son of Man, He must have assumed that He would first be supernaturally taken away and transformed. He thought of Himself like anyone who believes that the end times are coming soon, living in two different states: the present and the future state He would enter when the new supernatural world arrives. We later learn that as the disciples made their way to Jerusalem, they were completely focused on what they would become when this transformation happened. They debated who would hold the highest position (Mark ix. 33); James and John asked Jesus to promise them in advance the thrones at His right and left (Mark x. 35-37).

He, moreover, does not rebuke them for indulging such thoughts, but only tells them how much, in the present age, of service, humiliation, and suffering is necessary to constitute a claim to such places in the future age, and that it does not in the last resort belong to Him to allot the places on His left and on His right, but that they shall be given to those for whom they are prepared; therefore, perhaps not to any of the disciples (Mark x. 40). At this point, therefore, the knowledge and will of Jesus are thwarted and limited by the predestinarianism which is bound up with eschatology.

He doesn't criticize them for having such thoughts; instead, he explains how much service, humiliation, and suffering are needed in this life to deserve those positions in the next. He points out that it's not ultimately up to him to assign the places on his left and right; those spots will be given to the people they are meant for, which may not include any of the disciples (Mark x. 40). At this moment, Jesus' knowledge and will are constrained by the predestination linked to eschatology.

[pg 364]

It is quite mistaken, however, to speak as modern theology does, of the “service” here required as belonging to the “new ethic of the Kingdom of God.” There is for Jesus no ethic of the Kingdom of God, for in the Kingdom of God all natural relationships, even, for example, the distinction of sex (Mark xii. 25 and 26), are abolished. Temptation and sin no longer exist. All is “reign,” a “reign” which has gradations—Jesus speaks of the “least in the Kingdom of God”—according as it has been determined in each individual case from all eternity, and according as each by his self-humiliation and refusal to rule in the present age has proved his fitness for bearing rule in the future Kingdom.

It is quite mistaken, however, to speak as modern theology does, of the "service" here required as belonging to the “new ethics of the Kingdom of God.” For Jesus, there is no ethic of the Kingdom of God, because in the Kingdom of God all natural relationships, even, for example, the distinction of sex (Mark xii. 25 and 26), are abolished. Temptation and sin no longer exist. Everything is "rule," a rule that has different levels—Jesus speaks of the “least in the Kingdom of God”—depending on what has been determined for each individual case from all eternity, and based on how each person, by their humility and refusal to seek power in this current age, has shown their readiness to rule in the future Kingdom.

For the loftier stations, however, it is necessary to have proved oneself in persecution and suffering. Accordingly, Jesus asks the sons of Zebedee whether, since they claim these thrones on His right hand and on His left, they feel themselves strong enough to drink of His cup and be baptized with His baptism (Mark x. 38). To serve, to humble oneself, to incur persecution and death, belong to “the ethic of the interim” just as much as does penitence. They are indeed only a higher form of penitence.

For the higher positions, however, it's essential to have proven yourself through hardship and suffering. So, Jesus asks the sons of Zebedee if, since they want the thrones at His right and left, they feel strong enough to share in His suffering and be baptized with His baptism (Mark x. 38). Serving, humbling oneself, facing persecution and death are all part of “the ethic of the interim”, just like repentance. In fact, they are just a more advanced form of repentance.

A vivid eschatological expectation is therefore impossible to conceive apart from the idea of a metamorphosis. The resurrection is only a special case of this metamorphosis, the form in which the new condition of things is realised in the case of those who are already dead. The resurrection, the metamorphosis, and the Parousia of the Son of Man take place simultaneously, and are one and the same act.277 It is therefore quite indifferent whether a man loses his life shortly before the Parousia in order to “find his life,” if that is what is ordained for him; that signifies only that he will undergo the eschatological metamorphosis with the dead instead of with the living.

A clear expectation of the end times is impossible to imagine without the concept of transformation. The resurrection is just a specific instance of this transformation, the way in which the new state of affairs is realized for those who have already died. The resurrection, the transformation, and the return of the Son of Man happen at the same time and are all part of the same event.277 Therefore, it doesn’t really matter if a person loses their life right before the return; if that's what's meant to happen for them, it simply means they will experience the end times transformation alongside the dead instead of with the living.

The Pauline eschatology recognises both conceptions side by side, in such a way, however, that the resurrection is subordinated to the metamorphosis. “Behold, I shew you a mystery,” he says in 1 Cor. xv. 51 ff.; “we shall not all sleep, but we shall all be changed. In a moment, in the twinkling of an eye, at the last trump: for the trumpet shall sound, and the dead shall be raised incorruptible, and we shall be changed.”

The Pauline eschatology acknowledges both ideas simultaneously, but in a way that places the resurrection as secondary to the transformation. "Hey, I'm about to share a secret with you," he says in 1 Cor. xv. 51 ff.; “Not everyone will die, but we will all be changed. In an instant, in the blink of an eye, at the last trumpet: for the trumpet will sound, and the dead will be raised unchangeable, and we will be transformed.”

The apostle himself desires to be one of those who live to experience the metamorphosis and to be clothed with the heavenly mode of existence (2 Cor. v. 1 ff.). The metamorphosis, however, and the resurrection are, for those who are “in Christ,” connected [pg 365] with a being caught up into the clouds of heaven (1 Thess. iv. 15 ff.). Therefore Paul also makes one and the same event of the metamorphosis, resurrection, and translation.

The apostle himself wants to be one of those who get to experience the transformation and be dressed in a heavenly way of living (2 Cor. v. 1 ff.). However, for those who are "through Christ," the transformation and resurrection are connected [pg 365] with being taken up into the clouds of heaven (1 Thess. iv. 15 ff.). So, Paul treats the transformation, resurrection, and ascension as one single event.

In seeking clues to the eschatology of Jesus, scholars have passed over the eschatology which lies closest to it, that of Paul. But why? Is it not identical with that of Jesus, at least in so far that both are “Jewish eschatology”? Did not Reimarus long ago declare that the eschatology of the primitive Christian community was identical with the Jewish, and only went beyond it in claiming a definite knowledge on a single point which was unessential to the nature and course of the expected events, in knowing, that is, who the Son of Man should be? That Christians drew no distinction between their own eschatology and the Jewish is evident from the whole character of the earlier apocalyptic literature, and not least from the Apocalypse of John! After all, what alteration did the belief that Jesus was the Son of Man who was to be revealed make in the general scheme of the course of apocalyptic events?

In looking for clues about Jesus' eschatology, scholars have overlooked the eschatology that is closest to it: that of Paul. But why? Isn't it the same as Jesus', at least in that both are Jewish afterlife beliefs? Didn't Reimarus declare long ago that the eschatology of the early Christian community was identical to the Jewish one and only went further by claiming definite knowledge on a specific point that wasn't essential to the nature and progression of the expected events—specifically, who the Son of Man would be? It's clear that Christians saw no difference between their eschatology and the Jewish one from the overall character of earlier apocalyptic literature, especially the Apocalypse of John! After all, what change did the belief that Jesus was the Son of Man to be revealed bring to the general outline of apocalyptic events?

From the Rabbinic literature little help is to be derived towards the understanding of the world of thought in which Jesus lived, and His view of His own Person. The latest researches may be said to have made that clear. A few moral maxims, a few halting parables—that is all that can be produced in the way of parallels. Even the conception which is there suggested of the hidden coming and work of the Messiah is of little importance. We find the same ideas in the mouth of Trypho in Justin's dialogue, and that makes their Jewish character doubtful. That Jesus of Nazareth knew Himself to be the Son of Man who was to be revealed is for us the great fact of His self-consciousness, which is not to be further explained, whether there had been any kind of preparation for it in contemporary theology or not.

From the Rabbinic literature, we don't get much insight into the mindset of Jesus or how he viewed himself. Recent studies have made that clear. We can find a few moral sayings and a couple of awkward parables, but that's about it for parallels. Even the idea of the Messiah's hidden coming and work isn't that significant. Similar concepts appear in the dialogue between Trypho and Justin, which complicates their Jewish origin. The important takeaway is that Jesus of Nazareth recognized himself as the Son of Man who was meant to be revealed. This is a key aspect of his self-awareness that doesn't need any further explanation, regardless of whether there was any prior theological groundwork for it.

The self-consciousness of Jesus cannot in fact be illustrated or explained; all that can be explained is the eschatological view, in which the Man who possessed that self-consciousness saw reflected in advance the coming events, both those of a more general character, and those which especially related to Himself.278

The self-awareness of Jesus can't really be illustrated or explained; all we can explain is the eschatological perspective, where the man who had that self-awareness anticipated the coming events, both those of a broader nature and those that specifically concerned Him.278

The eschatology of Jesus can therefore only be interpreted by the aid of the curiously intermittent Jewish apocalyptic literature of the period between Daniel and the Bar-Cochba rising. What else, indeed, are the Synoptic Gospels, the Pauline letters, the Christian apocalypses than products of Jewish apocalyptic, belonging, [pg 366] moreover, to its greatest and most flourishing period? Historically regarded, the Baptist, Jesus, and Paul are simply the culminating manifestations of Jewish apocalyptic thought. The usual representation is the exact converse of the truth. Writers describe Jewish eschatology in order to illustrate the ideas of Jesus. But what is this “Jewish eschatology” after all? It is an eschatology with a great gap in it, because the culminating period, with the documents which relate to it, has been left out. The true historian will describe the eschatology of the Baptist, of Jesus, and of Paul in order to explain Jewish eschatology. It is nothing less than a misfortune for the science of New Testament Theology that no real attempt has hitherto been made to write the history of Jewish eschatology as it really was; that is, with the inclusion of the Baptist, of Jesus, and of Paul.279

The eschatology of Jesus can only be understood with the help of the sporadic Jewish apocalyptic literature from the time between Daniel and the Bar-Cochba uprising. What, in fact, are the Synoptic Gospels, the Pauline letters, and the Christian apocalypses if not products of Jewish apocalyptic thought, and they belong to its greatest and most vibrant era? Viewed historically, the Baptist, Jesus, and Paul represent the peak expressions of Jewish apocalyptic ideas. The common portrayal is the exact opposite of reality. Authors often explain Jewish eschatology to highlight the ideas of Jesus. But what is this “Jewish eschatology” really? It has a significant gap because the pivotal period and the documents related to it have been omitted. A true historian will outline the eschatology of the Baptist, Jesus, and Paul to clarify Jewish eschatology. It is nothing short of a misfortune for the field of New Testament Theology that no genuine effort has been made to write the history of Jewish eschatology as it truly was; that is, incorporating the Baptist, Jesus, and Paul.279

All this has had to be said in order to justify the apparently self-evident assertion that Mark, Matthew, and Paul are the best sources for the Jewish eschatology of the time of Jesus. They represent a phase, which even in detail is self-explanatory, of that Jewish apocalyptic hope which manifested itself from time to time. We are, therefore, justified in first reconstructing the Jewish apocalyptic of the time independently out of these documents, that is to say, in bringing the details of the discourses of Jesus into an eschatological system, and then on the basis of this system endeavouring to explain the apparently disconnected events in the history of His public life.

All of this needs to be mentioned to explain the seemingly obvious statement that Mark, Matthew, and Paul are the best sources for understanding Jewish eschatology during the time of Jesus. They reflect a phase, which is clearly understandable in detail, of the Jewish apocalyptic hope that emerged from time to time. Therefore, we can rightly start by independently reconstructing the Jewish apocalyptic of that time using these documents, meaning we will organize the details of Jesus’ teachings into an eschatological framework, and then, based on this framework, try to make sense of the seemingly unrelated events in His public life.

The lines of connection which run backwards towards the Psalms of Solomon, Enoch, and Daniel, and forwards towards the apocalypses of Baruch and Enoch, are extremely important for the understanding of certain general conceptions. On the other hand, it is impossible to over-emphasise the uniqueness of the point of view from which the eschatology of the time of the Baptist, of Jesus, and of Paul presents itself to us.

The connections that link back to the Psalms of Solomon, Enoch, and Daniel, and forward to the apocalypses of Baruch and Enoch, are really important for understanding some general ideas. At the same time, we can't stress enough how unique the perspective is from which the eschatology of the time of John the Baptist, Jesus, and Paul is presented to us.

In the first place, men feel themselves so close to the coming events that they only see what lies nearest to them, the imaginative development of detail entirely ceases. In the second place, it appears to us as though seen, so to speak, from within, passed through the medium of powerful minds like those of the Baptist and Jesus. That is why it is so great and simple. On the other hand, a certain complication arises from the fact that it now intersects actual history. All these are original features of it, which are not found in the Jewish apocalyptic writings of the preceding and following periods, and that is why these documents [pg 367] give us so little help in regard to the characteristic detail of the eschatology of Jesus and His contemporaries.

In the first place, people feel so close to the upcoming events that they only see what’s right in front of them, and their ability to imagine the development of details completely stops. Secondly, it seems like it’s viewed from within, filtered through the powerful minds of figures like John the Baptist and Jesus. That’s why it feels so profound and straightforward. On the other hand, a certain complexity arises from the fact that it now intersects with actual history. All these are unique features that aren’t found in the Jewish apocalyptic writings from before and after this period, which is why these documents [pg 367] offer us so little insight into the distinctive details of Jesus' eschatology and that of his contemporaries.

A further point to be noticed is that the eschatology of the time of Jesus shows the influence of the eschatology of the ancient prophets in a way which is not paralleled either before or after. Compare the Synoptic eschatology with that of the Psalms of Solomon. In place of the legal righteousness, which, since the return from the exile, had formed the link of connexion between the present and the future, we find the prophetic ethic, the demand for a general repentance, even in the case of the Baptist. In the Apocalypses of Baruch and Ezra we see, especially in the theological character of the latter, the persistent traces of this ethical deepening of apocalyptic.

A notable point to consider is that the eschatology during the time of Jesus reflects the influence of the ancient prophets in a way that is unique compared to both the past and the future. If you compare the eschatology in the Synoptic Gospels with that in the Psalms of Solomon, you'll see a shift. Instead of focusing on the legal righteousness that had connected the present and the future since the return from exile, there’s an emphasis on prophetic ethics and a call for widespread repentance, even in the case of John the Baptist. In the Apocalypses of Baruch and Ezra, particularly in the theological emphasis of the latter, we notice the lasting impact of this ethical evolution in apocalyptic thought.

But even in individual conceptions the apocalyptic of the Baptist, and of the period which he introduces, reaches back to the eschatology of the prophetic writings. The pouring forth of the spirit, and the figure of Elias, who comes again to earth, play a great rôle in it. The difficulty is, indeed, consciously felt of combining the two eschatologies, and bringing the prophetic within the Danielic. How, it is asked, can the Son of David be at the same time the Danielic Son-of-Man Messiah, at once David's son and David's Lord?

But even in individual views, the apocalyptic vision of the Baptist and the era he introduces connects back to the eschatology found in prophetic writings. The outpouring of the spirit and the figure of Elijah, who returns to earth, are both significant in this context. There is a noticeable challenge in merging these two eschatologies and integrating the prophetic with the Danielic. The question arises: how can the Son of David simultaneously be the Danielic Son-of-Man Messiah, both David's son and David's Lord?

It is inadequate to speak of a synthesis of the two eschatologies. What has happened is nothing less than the remoulding, the elevation, of the Daniel-Enoch apocalyptic by the spirit and conceptions belonging to the ancient prophetic hope.

It’s not enough to say there’s a synthesis of the two eschatologies. What has occurred is nothing short of a transformation, an enhancement, of the Daniel-Enoch apocalyptic by the ideas and spirit associated with the ancient prophetic hope.

A great simplification and deepening of eschatology begins to show itself even in the Psalms of Solomon. The conception of righteousness which the writer applies is, in spite of its legal aspect, of an ethical, prophetic character. It is an eschatology associated with great historical events, the eschatology of a Pharisaism which is fighting for a cause, and has therefore a certain inward greatness.280 Between the Psalms of Solomon and the appearance of the Baptist there lies the decadence of Pharisaism. At this point there suddenly appears an eschatological movement detached from Pharisaism, which was declining into an external legalism, a movement resting on a basis of its own, and thoroughly penetrated with the spirit of the ancient prophets.

A significant simplification and deepening of eschatology starts to reveal itself even in the Psalms of Solomon. The idea of righteousness that the writer uses, despite its legal aspects, carries an ethical, prophetic character. This eschatology is linked to major historical events, representing a Pharisaic movement fighting for a cause, which lends it a sense of inner significance. Between the Psalms of Solomon and the emergence of the Baptist lies the decline of Pharisaism. At this point, a new eschatological movement emerges, separate from the declining Pharisaism that had become focused on external legalism. This movement is based on its own foundation and is deeply influenced by the spirit of the ancient prophets.

The ultimate differentia of this eschatology is that it was not, like the other apocalyptic movements, called into existence by [pg 368] historical events. The Apocalypse of Daniel was called forth by the religious oppression of Antiochus;281 the Psalms of Solomon by the civil strife at Jerusalem and the first appearance of the Roman power under Pompey;282 Fourth Ezra and Baruch by the destruction of Jerusalem.283 The apocalyptic movement in the time of Jesus is not connected with any historical event. It cannot be said, as Bruno Bauer rightly perceived, that we know anything about the Messianic expectations of the Jewish people at that time.284 On the contrary, the indifference shown by the Roman administration towards the movement proves that the Romans knew nothing of a condition of great and general Messianic excitement among the Jewish people. The conduct of the Pharisaic party also, and the indifference of the great mass of the people, show that there can have been no question at that time of a national movement. What is really remarkable about this wave of apocalyptic enthusiasm is the fact that it was called forth not by external events, but solely by the appearance of two great personalities, and subsides with their disappearance, without leaving among the people generally any trace, except a feeling of hatred towards the new sect.

The main point of this eschatology is that it wasn't started, like other apocalyptic movements, due to historical events. The Apocalypse of Daniel arose from the religious oppression by Antiochus; the Psalms of Solomon were inspired by the civil unrest in Jerusalem and the rise of Roman power under Pompey; Fourth Ezra and Baruch were prompted by the destruction of Jerusalem. The apocalyptic movement during Jesus' time isn't linked to any historical event. It can't be said, as Bruno Bauer correctly noted, that we know anything about the Jewish people's Messianic expectations at that time. In fact, the lack of interest from the Roman administration towards the movement shows that the Romans were unaware of any widespread Messianic fervor among the Jewish people. The actions of the Pharisaic party and the indifference of the majority also indicate that there wasn't a national movement at that time. What's truly striking about this wave of apocalyptic enthusiasm is that it was triggered not by external events, but solely by the emergence of two prominent figures, and it faded away with their departure, leaving little impact on the general populace except for a sense of animosity towards the new sect.

The Baptist and Jesus are not, therefore, borne upon the current of a general eschatological movement. The period offers no events calculated to give an impulse to eschatological enthusiasm. They themselves set the times in motion by acting, by creating eschatological facts. It is this mighty creative force which constitutes the difficulty in grasping historically the eschatology of Jesus and the Baptist. Instead of literary artifice speaking out of a distant imaginary past, there now enter into the field of eschatology men, living, acting men. It was the only time when that ever happened in Jewish eschatology.

The Baptist and Jesus aren't just caught up in a general movement toward the end times. This period lacks events that would spark excitement about the end of the world. They initiate change by taking action and creating significant moments related to the end times. This powerful creative force makes it challenging to understand the historical context of Jesus and the Baptist's eschatology. Instead of literary devices reflecting a distant imagined past, real, living people are engaging with eschatology. This was the only time this ever occurred in Jewish eschatology.

There is silence all around. The Baptist appears, and cries: “Repent, for the Kingdom of Heaven is at hand.” Soon after that comes Jesus, and in the knowledge that He is the coming [pg 369] Son of Man lays hold of the wheel of the world to set it moving on that last revolution which is to bring all ordinary history to a close. It refuses to turn, and He throws Himself upon it. Then it does turn; and crushes Him. Instead of bringing in the eschatological conditions, He has destroyed them. The wheel rolls onward, and the mangled body of the one immeasurably great Man, who was strong enough to think of Himself as the spiritual ruler of mankind and to bend history to His purpose, is hanging upon it still. That is His victory and His reign.

There is silence all around. The Baptist shows up and shouts: "Turn away from your wrongdoings, because the Kingdom of Heaven is close." Soon after that, Jesus arrives, fully aware that He is the coming [pg 369] Son of Man, ready to grab hold of the wheel of the world to set it spinning on its final turn that will end all regular history. It won’t turn, so He throws Himself against it. Then it starts to turn and crushes Him. Instead of establishing the end-time conditions, He has destroyed them. The wheel keeps rolling, and the broken body of the one tremendously great Man, who was strong enough to see Himself as the spiritual leader of humanity and to shape history to His will, is still hanging on it. That is His victory and His reign.

These considerations regarding the distinctive character of the Synoptic eschatology were necessary in order to explain the significance of the sending forth of the disciples and the discourse which Jesus uttered upon that occasion. Jesus' purpose is to set in motion the eschatological development of history, to let loose the final woes, the confusion and strife, from which shall issue the Parousia, and so to introduce the supra-mundane phase of the eschatological drama. That is His task, for which He has authority here below. That is why He says in the same discourse, “Think not that I am come to send peace on the earth; I am not come to send peace, but a sword” (Matt. x. 34).

These considerations about the unique nature of Synoptic eschatology were necessary to explain the importance of sending out the disciples and the message Jesus delivered at that time. Jesus' goal is to kickstart the eschatological unfolding of history, to unleash the final troubles, the chaos and conflict, from which the Parousia will emerge, thereby introducing the transcendent phase of the eschatological narrative. This is His mission, for which He has authority here on earth. That's why He states in the same message, "Don't think that I've come to bring peace to the earth; I haven't come to bring peace, but a sword." (Matt. x. 34).

It was with a view to this initial movement that He chose His disciples. They are not His helpers in the work of teaching; we never see them in that capacity, and He did not prepare them to carry on that work after His death. The very fact that He chooses just twelve shows that it is a dogmatic idea which He has in mind. He chooses them as those who are destined to hurl the firebrand into the world, and are afterwards, as those who have been the comrades of the unrecognised Messiah, before He came to His Kingdom, to be His associates in ruling and judging it.285

It was with this initial movement in mind that He chose His disciples. They are not His helpers in teaching; we never see them in that role, and He didn’t prepare them to continue that work after His death. The fact that He chooses exactly twelve indicates that He has a specific dogmatic idea in mind. He selects them as those who are meant to ignite change in the world, and later, as those who have been companions of the unrecognized Messiah before He came into His Kingdom, they will be His partners in ruling and judging it.285

But what was to be the fate of the future Son of Man during the Messianic woes of the last times? It appears as if it was appointed for Him to share the persecution and the suffering. He [pg 370] says that those who shall be saved must take their cross and follow Him (Matt. x. 38), that His followers must be willing to lose their lives for His sake, and that only those who in this time of terror confess their allegiance to Him, shall be confessed by Him before His heavenly Father (Matt. x. 32). Similarly, in the last of the Beatitudes, He had pronounced those blessed who were despised and persecuted for His sake (Matt. v. 11, 12). As the future bearer of the supreme rule He must go through the deepest humiliation. There is danger that His followers may doubt Him. Therefore, the last words of His message to the Baptist, just at the time when He had sent forth the Twelve, is, “Blessed is he whosoever shall not be offended in me” (Matt. xi. 6).

But what would be the fate of the future Son of Man during the Messianic troubles of the end times? It seems He was destined to endure persecution and suffering. He [pg 370] says that those who will be saved must take up their cross and follow Him (Matt. x. 38), that His followers must be ready to give up their lives for Him, and that only those who confess their loyalty to Him during this time of fear will be acknowledged by Him before His heavenly Father (Matt. x. 32). Likewise, in the last of the Beatitudes, He declared those blessed who were scorned and persecuted for His sake (Matt. v. 11, 12). As the future holder of supreme authority, He must endure the greatest humiliation. There is a risk that His followers may doubt Him. Therefore, His final words to the Baptist, just when He had sent out the Twelve, are, "Blessed is the one who isn't offended by me." (Matt. xi. 6).

If He makes a point of familiarising others with the thought that in the time of tribulation they may even lose their lives, He must have recognised that this possibility was still more strongly present in His own case. It is possible that in the enigmatic saying about the disciples fasting “when the bridegroom is taken away from them” (Mark ii. 20), there is a hint of what Jesus expected. In that case suffering, death, and resurrection must have been closely united in the Messianic consciousness from the first. So much, however, is certain, viz. that the thought of suffering formed part, at the time of the sending forth the disciples, of the mystery of the Kingdom of God and of the Messiahship of Jesus, and that in the form that Jesus and all the elect were to be brought low in the πειρασμός at the time of the death-struggle against the evil world-power which would arise against them; brought down, it might be, even to death. It mattered as little in His own case as in that of others whether at the time of the Parousia He should be one of those who should be metamorphosed, or one who had died and risen again. The question arises, however, how this self-consciousness of Jesus could remain concealed. It is true the miracles had nothing to do with the Messiahship, since no one expected the Messiah to come as an earthly miracle-worker in the present age. On the contrary, it would have been the greatest of miracles if any one had recognised the Messiah in an earthly miracle-worker. How far the cries of the demoniacs who addressed Him as Messiah were intelligible by the people must remain an open question. What is clear is that His Messiahship did not become known in this way even to His disciples.

If He emphasizes the need to prepare others for the idea that they might even lose their lives during tough times, He must have realized that this possibility was even more significant for Himself. It’s possible that in His mysterious statement about the disciples fasting "when the groom is taken away from them" (Mark ii. 20), there’s a hint of what Jesus anticipated. In that sense, suffering, death, and resurrection must have been closely linked in the Messianic mindset from the beginning. What is certain, though, is that the thought of suffering was part of the mystery of the Kingdom of God and the Messiahship of Jesus at the time when the disciples were sent out. This involved the idea that Jesus and all the chosen ones would be humbled during the πειρασμός in the struggle against the evil worldly power that would rise against them, possibly even to the point of death. It mattered just as little for Him as it did for others whether, at the time of the Parousia, He would be transformed or one who had died and risen again. However, the question arises as to how this self-awareness of Jesus could remain hidden. It’s true that miracles were unrelated to His Messiahship since no one expected the Messiah to appear as an earthly miracle worker in this age. In fact, it would have been the greatest miracle if anyone had recognized the Messiah in an earthly miracle worker. How much the cries of the demoniacs who called Him the Messiah made sense to the people remains uncertain. What is clear is that His Messiahship was not recognized this way, even by His own disciples.

And yet in all His speech and action the Messianic consciousness shines forth. One might, indeed, speak of the acts of His Messianic consciousness. The Beatitudes, nay, the whole of the Sermon on the Mount, with the authoritative “I” for ever breaking through, bear witness to the high dignity which He ascribed to Himself. Did not this “I” set the people thinking?

And yet in everything He said and did, His Messianic awareness stood out. One could even talk about the actions of His Messianic awareness. The Beatitudes, and indeed the entire Sermon on the Mount, with the dominant “I” consistently emerging, testify to the immense dignity He attributed to Himself. Didn't this “I” make people think?

[pg 371]

What must they have thought when, at the close of this discourse, He spoke of people who, at the Day of Judgment, would call upon Him as Lord, and appeal to the works that they had done in His name, and who yet were destined to be rejected because He would not recognise them (Matt. vii. 21-23)?

What must they have thought when, at the end of this talk, He mentioned people who, on the Day of Judgment, would call out to Him as Lord and point to the deeds they had done in His name, yet were still destined to be turned away because He would not acknowledge them (Matt. vii. 21-23)?

What must they have thought of Him when He pronounced those blessed who were persecuted and despised for His sake (Matt. v. 11, 12)? By what authority did this man forgive sins (Mark ii. 5 ff.)?

What must they have thought of Him when He called those who were persecuted and looked down on for His sake blessed (Matt. v. 11, 12)? By what authority did this man forgive sins (Mark ii. 5 ff.)?

In the discourse at the sending forth of the disciples the “I” is still more prominent. He demands of men that in the trials to come they shall confess Him, that they shall love Him more than father or mother, bear their cross after Him, and follow Him to the death, since it is only for such that He can entreat His Heavenly Father (Matt. x. 32 ff.). Admitting that the expression “Heavenly Father” contained no riddle for the listening disciples, since He had taught them to pray “Our Father which art in Heaven,” we have still to ask who was He whose yea or nay should prevail with God to determine the fate of men at the Judgment?

In the discussion about sending out the disciples, the “I” is even more significant. He asks people to confess Him in the coming trials, to love Him more than their own parents, to take up their cross and follow Him even to death, because only for those people can He appeal to His Heavenly Father (Matt. x. 32 ff.). While the term “Heavenly Father” was clear to the listening disciples, since He had taught them to pray “Our Father which art in Heaven,” we still need to consider who He was whose yes or no would influence God to decide the fate of people at Judgment?

And yet they found it hard, nay impossible, to think of Him as Messiah. They guessed Him to be a prophet; some thought of Elias, some of John the Baptist risen from the dead, as appears clearly from the answer of the disciples at Caesarea Philippi.286 The Messiah was a supernatural personality who was to appear in the last times, and who was not expected upon earth before that.

And yet they found it difficult, even impossible, to see Him as the Messiah. They thought of Him as a prophet; some considered Him to be Elijah, others thought He might be John the Baptist come back to life, as is clearly shown by the disciples’ response at Caesarea Philippi.286 The Messiah was a supernatural figure who was meant to come in the last days, and who wasn’t expected to be on earth before that.

At this point a difficulty presents itself. How could Jesus be Elias for the people? Did they not hold John the Baptist to be Elias? Not in the least! Jesus was the first and the only person who attributed this office to him. And, moreover, He declares it to the people as something mysterious, difficult to understand—“If ye can receive it, this is Elias, which was for to come. He that hath ears to hear, let him hear” (Matt. xi. 14, 15). In making this revelation He is communicating to them a piece of supernatural knowledge, opening up a part of the mystery of the Kingdom of God. Therefore He uses the same formula of emphasis as when making known in parables the mystery of the Kingdom of God (Mark iv.).

At this point, a difficulty arises. How could Jesus be Elijah for the people? Didn't they believe John the Baptist was Elijah? Not at all! Jesus was the first and only one who assigned this role to him. Furthermore, He tells the people that this is something mysterious and hard to understand—"If you're willing to accept it, this is Elijah who was meant to come. Whoever has ears to hear, let them hear." (Matt. xi. 14, 15). By making this revelation, He is sharing with them a piece of supernatural knowledge, revealing part of the mystery of the Kingdom of God. That’s why He uses the same emphasis as when He explains the mystery of the Kingdom of God in parables (Mark iv.).

The disciples were not with Him at this time, and therefore did not learn what was the rôle of John the Baptist. When a little later, in descending from the mount of transfiguration He [pg 372] predicted to the three who formed the inner circle of His followers the resurrection of the Son of Man, they came to Him with difficulties about the rising from the dead—how could this be possible when, according to the Pharisees and Scribes, Elias must first come?—whereupon Jesus explains to them that the preacher of repentance whom Herod had put to death had been Elias (Mark ix. 11-13).

The disciples weren't with Him at that moment, so they didn't understand the role of John the Baptist. Later, as He was coming down from the mountain of transfiguration, He predicted to the three who were part of His inner circle the resurrection of the Son of Man. They approached Him with questions about rising from the dead—how could that happen when, according to the Pharisees and Scribes, Elijah had to come first? Jesus then explained to them that the preacher of repentance whom Herod had killed was Elijah (Mark ix. 11-13).

Why did not the people take the Baptist to be Elias? In the first place no doubt because he did not describe himself as such. In the next place because he did no miracle! He was only a natural man without any evidence of supernatural power, only a prophet. In the third place, and that was the decisive point, he had himself pointed forward to the coming of Elias. He who was to come, he whom he preached, was not the Messiah, but Elias.

Why didn’t the people think the Baptist was Elijah? First of all, it's probably because he didn’t call himself that. Secondly, because he performed no miracles! He was just an ordinary man with no signs of supernatural power, merely a prophet. Thirdly, and this was the most important reason, he himself indicated that Elijah was coming. The one who was to come, the one he preached about, was not the Messiah, but Elijah.

He describes him, not as a supernatural personality, not as a judge, not as one who will be manifested at the unveiling of the heavenly world, but as one who in his work shall resemble himself, only much greater—one who, like himself, baptizes, though with the Holy Spirit. Had it ever been represented as the work of the Messiah to baptize?

He describes him, not as a supernatural figure, not as a judge, not as someone who will appear at the unveiling of the heavenly world, but as someone whose work will resemble his own, only on a much larger scale—someone who, like him, baptizes, but with the Holy Spirit. Has it ever been suggested that the Messiah's role is to baptize?

Before the Last Judgment, so it was inferred from Joel, the great outpouring of the Spirit was to take place; before the Last Judgment, so taught Malachi, Elias was to come. Until these events had occurred the manifestation of the Son of Man was not to be looked for. Men's thoughts were fixed, therefore, not on the Messiah, but upon Elias and the outpouring of the Spirit.287 The Baptist in his preaching combines both ideas, and predicts the coming of the Great One who shall “baptize with the Holy Spirit,” i.e. who brings about the outpouring of the Spirit. His own preaching was only designed to secure that at His coming that Great One should find a community sanctified and prepared to receive the Spirit.

Before the Last Judgment, as Joel inferred, there would be a great outpouring of the Spirit; before the Last Judgment, as Malachi taught, Elias would come. Until these events happened, people weren't expecting the manifestation of the Son of Man. Their focus was, therefore, not on the Messiah, but on Elias and the outpouring of the Spirit. The Baptist, in his preaching, combines both ideas and predicts the arrival of the Great One who will "baptize with the Holy Spirit," i.e. who will bring about the outpouring of the Spirit. His preaching was meant to ensure that when the Great One arrived, he would find a community sanctified and ready to receive the Spirit.

When he heard in the prison of one who did great wonders and signs, he desired to learn with certainty whether this was “he who was to come.” If this question is taken as referring to the Messiahship the whole narrative loses its meaning, and it upsets the theory of the Messianic secret, since in this case at least one person had become aware, independently, of the office which belonged to Jesus, not to mention all the ineptitudes involved in making the Baptist here speak in doubt and confusion. Moreover, on this false interpretation of the question the point of Jesus' discourse is lost, for in this case it is not clear why He says to the people afterwards, “If ye can receive it, John himself is Elias.” This revelation presupposes that Jesus and the people, who had [pg 373] heard the question which had been addressed to Him, also gave it its only natural meaning, referring it to Jesus as the bearer of the office of Elias.

When he heard in the prison about someone who performed great wonders and signs, he wanted to find out for sure if this was "the one who was supposed to arrive." If this question is seen as relating to the Messiahship, the entire narrative loses its significance and contradicts the theory of the Messianic secret, because in this case at least one person had independently realized the role that belonged to Jesus. Not to mention the confusion that arises from making the Baptist express doubt and uncertainty. Furthermore, this incorrect interpretation of the question obscures the purpose of Jesus' message, as it’s unclear why He later tells the people, "If you can accept it, John is really Elias." This revelation assumes that Jesus and the people, who had [pg 373] heard the question directed at Him, understood it in its only logical way, connecting it to Jesus as the one who holds the office of Elias.

That even the first Evangelist gives the episode a Messianic setting by introducing it with the words “When John heard in the prison of the works of the Christ” does not alter the facts of the body of the narrative. The sequel directly contradicts the introduction. And this interpretation fully explains the evasive answer of Jesus, in which exegesis has always recognised a certain reserve without ever being able to make it intelligible why Jesus did not simply send him the message, “Yes, I am he”—whereto, however, according to modern theology, He would have needed to add, “but another kind of Messiah from him whom you expect.”

That even the first Evangelist sets the scene with a Messianic tone by starting with the words "When John heard in prison about the things Jesus was doing" doesn’t change the facts presented in the main part of the narrative. The follow-up directly contradicts the introduction. This interpretation fully explains Jesus's evasive response, which scholars have always noted contains a certain reserve but have never been able to clarify why Jesus didn’t just send the message, "Yes, that's me."—to which, however, according to modern theology, He would have needed to add, “but a different kind of Messiah than the one you’re expecting.”

The fact was, the Baptist had put Him in an extremely difficult position. He could not answer that He was Elias if He held Himself to be the Messiah; on the other hand He could not, and would not, disclose to him, and still less to the messengers and the listening multitude, the secret of His Messiahship. Therefore He sends this obscure message, which only contains a confirmation of the facts which John had already heard and closes with a warning, come what may, not to be offended in Him. Of this the Baptist was to make what he could.

The reality was that the Baptist had put Him in a really tough spot. He couldn't say He was Elijah if He considered Himself to be the Messiah; on the other hand, He also wouldn't reveal to him, and certainly not to the messengers and the crowd, the secret of His Messiahship. So, He sends this vague message, which only confirms what John had already heard and ends with a warning that, no matter what, he shouldn’t be offended by Him. The Baptist would have to figure it out from there.

It mattered, in fact, little how John understood the message. The time was much more advanced than he supposed; the hammer of the world's clock had risen to strike the last hour. All that he needed to know was that he had no cause to doubt.

It actually didn't matter much how John interpreted the message. Time was further along than he thought; the world's clock was about to strike the final hour. All he needed to understand was that he had no reason to doubt.

In revealing to the people the true office of the Baptist, Jesus unveiled to them almost the whole mystery of the Kingdom of God, and nearly disclosed the secret of His Messiahship. For if Elias was already present, was not the coming of the Kingdom close at hand? And if John was Elias, who was Jesus?... There could only be one answer: the Messiah. But this seemed impossible, because Messiah was expected as a supernatural personality. The eulogy on the Baptist is, historically regarded, identical in content with the prediction of the Parousia in the discourse at the sending forth of the disciples. For after the coming of Elias there must follow immediately the judgment and the other events belonging to the last time. Now we can understand why in the enumeration of the events of the last time in the discourse to the Twelve the coming of Elias is not mentioned.

In showing the people the true role of the Baptist, Jesus revealed almost all the mystery of the Kingdom of God and nearly disclosed the secret of His Messiahship. If Elijah was already present, didn’t that mean the Kingdom was just around the corner? And if John was Elijah, who was Jesus?... There could only be one answer: the Messiah. But this seemed impossible because people expected the Messiah to be a supernatural figure. Historically, the praise for the Baptist is essentially the same as the prophecy about the Second Coming in the speech when the disciples were sent out. Once Elijah comes, judgment and other events tied to the end times should follow right after. Now we see why the coming of Elijah isn’t mentioned in the list of end times events in the discourse to the Twelve.

We see here, too, how, in the thought of Jesus, Messianic doctrine forces its way into history and simply abolishes the historic aspect of the events. The Baptist had not held himself to be Elias, the people had not thought of attributing this office to him; the description of Elias did not fit him at all, since he had [pg 374] done none of those things which Elias was to do: and yet Jesus makes him Elias, simply because He expected His own manifestation as Son of Man, and before that it was necessary that Elias must first have come. And even when John was dead Jesus still told the disciples that in him Elias had come, although the death of Elias was not contemplated in the eschatological doctrine, and was in fact unthinkable, But Jesus must somehow drag or force the eschatological events into the framework of the actual occurrences.

We can also see here how, in Jesus' thinking, Messianic beliefs push their way into history and completely erase the historical side of events. The Baptist didn’t see himself as Elijah, and the people didn’t think of him that way either; the description of Elijah didn’t match him at all, as he hadn’t done any of the things Elijah was supposed to do. Yet, Jesus identifies him as Elijah simply because He anticipated His own appearance as the Son of Man, and before that could happen, it was necessary for Elijah to have come first. Even after John died, Jesus still told His disciples that Elijah had indeed come in him, even though the death of Elijah wasn’t part of the eschatological belief and was actually unthinkable. But Jesus needed to somehow fit the eschatological events into the reality of what actually happened.

Thus the conception of the “dogmatic element” in the narrative widens in an unsuspected fashion. And even what before seemed natural becomes on a closer examination doctrinal. The Baptist is made into Elias solely by the force of Jesus' Messianic consciousness.

Thus the idea of the "rigid belief" in the story expands in an unexpected way. Even what previously seemed natural becomes, upon closer inspection, doctrinal. The Baptist is turned into Elias solely by the influence of Jesus' Messianic awareness.

A short time afterwards, immediately upon the return of the disciples, He spoke and acted before their eyes in a way which presupposed the Messianic secret. The people had been dogging his steps; at a lonely spot on the shores of the lake they surrounded Him, and He “taught them about many things” (Mark vi. 30-34). The day was drawing to a close, but they held closely to Him without troubling about food. In the evening, before sending them away, He fed them.

A short time afterwards, right after the disciples returned, He spoke and acted in front of them in a way that assumed they understood the Messianic secret. The people had been following Him closely; at a secluded spot by the lake, they surrounded Him, and He “taught them about a lot” (Mark vi. 30-34). The day was ending, but they stayed close to Him without worrying about food. In the evening, before sending them away, He fed them.

Weisse, long ago, had constantly emphasised the fact that the feeding of the multitude was one of the greatest historical problems, because this narrative, like that of the transfiguration, is very firmly riveted to its historical setting and, therefore, imperatively demands explanation. How is the historical element in it to be got at? Certainly not by seeking to explain the apparently miraculous in it on natural lines, by representing that at the bidding of Jesus people brought out the baskets of provisions which they had been concealing, and, thus importing into the tradition a natural fact which, so far from being hinted at in the narrative, is actually excluded by it.

Weisse, a long time ago, emphasized that the feeding of the multitude was one of the biggest historical issues, because this story, like the one about the transfiguration, is tightly connected to its historical context and therefore requires a clear explanation. How can we understand the historical aspect of it? Definitely not by trying to explain the seemingly miraculous events in natural terms, by suggesting that at Jesus's command, people revealed the baskets of food they had been hiding, and thus introducing a natural fact into the tradition that is not only not hinted at in the story but is actually ruled out by it.

Our solution is that the whole is historical, except the closing remark that they were all filled. Jesus distributed the provisions which He and His disciples had with them among the multitude so that each received a very little, after He had first offered thanks. The significance lies in the giving of thanks and in the fact that they had received from Him consecrated food. Because He is the future Messiah, this meal becomes without their knowledge the Messianic feast. With the morsel of bread which He gives His disciples to distribute to the people He consecrates them as partakers in the coming Messianic feast, and gives them the guarantee that they, who had shared His table in the time of His obscurity, would also share it in the time of His glory. In the prayer He gave thanks not only for the food, but also for the coming Kingdom and all its blessings. It is the counterpart of [pg 375] the Lord's prayer, where He so strangely inserts the petition for daily bread between the petitions for the coming of the Kingdom and for deliverance from the πειρασμός.

Our perspective is that everything is historical, except for the final note that they were all filled. Jesus shared the supplies He and His disciples had with the crowd so that each person received just a little, after He had first given thanks. The importance lies in the act of giving thanks and the fact that they received from Him sanctified food. Since He is the future Messiah, this meal unknowingly turns into the Messianic feast. With the piece of bread He shares with His disciples to distribute to the people, He designates them as participants in the upcoming Messianic feast, assuring them that those who shared His table during His humble days would also share it in His glorious time. In the prayer, He gave thanks not only for the food but also for the forthcoming Kingdom and all its blessings. This corresponds to the Lord's Prayer, where He intriguingly places the request for daily bread between the requests for the coming of the Kingdom and for deliverance from temptation.

The feeding of the multitude was more than a love-feast, a fellowship-meal. It was from the point of view of Jesus a sacrament of salvation.

The feeding of the multitude wasn't just a love feast or a shared meal. For Jesus, it was a sacred act of salvation.

We never realise sufficiently that in a period when the judgment and the glory were expected as close at hand, one thought arising out of this expectation must have acquired special prominence—how, namely, in the present time a man could obtain a guarantee of coming scatheless through the judgment, of being saved and received into the Kingdom, of being signed and sealed for deliverance amid the coming trial, as the Chosen People in Egypt had a sign revealed to them from God by means of which they might be manifest as those who were to be spared. But once we do realise this, we can understand why the thought of signing and sealing runs through the whole of the apocalyptic literature. It is found as early as the ninth chapter of Ezekiel. There, God is making preparation for judgment. The day of visitation of the city is at hand. But first the Lord calls unto “the man clothed with linen who had the writer's ink-horn by his side” and said unto him, “Go through the midst of the city, through the midst of Jerusalem, and set a mark upon the foreheads of the men that sigh and that cry for all the abominations that be done in the midst thereof.” Only after that does He give command to those who are charged with the judgment to begin, adding, “But come not near any man upon whom is the mark” (Ezek. ix. 4 and 6).

We often don't realize that in a time when judgment and glory were expected to be right around the corner, one thought stemming from this expectation must have stood out—how, in that moment, a person could secure assurance of coming through the judgment unharmed, of being saved and welcomed into the Kingdom, of being marked and sealed for deliverance during the upcoming trial, just as the Chosen People in Egypt were given a sign from God to show they would be spared. Once we grasp this, we can understand why the theme of signing and sealing is prevalent throughout apocalyptic literature. It appears as early as the ninth chapter of Ezekiel. There, God is preparing for judgment. The day of reckoning for the city is approaching. But first, the Lord calls to “the man clothed with linen who had the writer's ink-horn by his side” and says to him, “Go through the midst of the city, through the midst of Jerusalem, and set a mark upon the foreheads of the men that sigh and cry for all the abominations that are done there.” Only after that does He instruct those responsible for the judgment to begin, adding, “But come not near any man upon whom is the mark” (Ezek. ix. 4 and 6).

In the fifteenth of the Psalms of Solomon,288 the last eschatological writing before the movement initiated by the Baptist, it is expressly said in the description of the judgment that “the saints of God bear a sign upon them which saves them.”

In the fifteenth of the Psalms of Solomon,288 the last prophetic writing before the movement started by the Baptist, it clearly states in the description of judgment that “The saints of God have a mark on them that protects them.”

In the Pauline theology very striking prominence is given to the thought of being sealed unto salvation. The apostle is conscious of bearing about with him in his body “the marks of Jesus” (Gal. vi. 17), the “dying” of Jesus (2 Cor. iv. 10). This sign is received in baptism, since it is a baptism “into the death of Christ”; in this act the recipient is in a certain sense really buried with Him, and thenceforth walks among men as one who belongs, even here below, to risen humanity (Rom. vi. 1 ff.). Baptism is the seal, the earnest of the spirit, the pledge of that which is to come (2 Cor i. 22; Eph. i. 13, 14, iv. 30).

In Pauline theology, the idea of being sealed for salvation is very prominent. The apostle is aware that he carries with him in his body “the wounds of Jesus” (Gal. vi. 17), the “dying” of Jesus (2 Cor. iv. 10). This sign is received in baptism, as it is a baptism “into Christ's death”; in this act, the person is in a way truly buried with Him and from that point on lives among people as someone who, even here on earth, belongs to resurrected humanity (Rom. vi. 1 ff.). Baptism is the seal, the down payment of the Spirit, the promise of what is to come (2 Cor i. 22; Eph. i. 13, 14, iv. 30).

This conception of baptism as a “salvation” in view of that which was to come goes down through the whole of ancient theology. Its preaching might really be summed up in the words, “Keep your baptism holy and without blemish.”

This idea of baptism as a “salvation” in anticipation of what’s ahead has been a consistent theme in ancient theology. Its message can basically be summarized in the phrase, "Keep your baptism pure and unblemished."

[pg 376]

In the Shepherd of Hermas even the spirits of the men of the past must receive “the seal, which is the water” in order that they may “bear the name of God upon them.” That is why the tower is built over the water, and the stones which are brought up out of the deep are rolled through the water (Vis. iii. and Sim. ix. 16).

In the Shepherd of Hermas, even the spirits of people from the past must receive "the seal, which represents the water" so that they can "carry the name of God on them." That’s why the tower is built over the water, and the stones that are brought up from the depths are rolled through the water (Vis. iii. and Sim. ix. 16).

In the Apocalypse of John the thought of the sealing stands prominently in the foreground. The locusts receive power to hurt those only who have not the seal of God on their foreheads (Rev. ix. 4, 5). The beast (Rev. xiii. 16 ff.) compels men to bear his mark; only those who will not accept it are to reign with Christ (Rev. xx. 4). The chosen hundred and forty-four thousand bear the name of God and the name of the Lamb upon their foreheads (Rev. xiv. 1).

In the Apocalypse of John, the idea of sealing is a key theme. The locusts are given power to harm only those who do not have the seal of God on their foreheads (Rev. ix. 4, 5). The beast (Rev. xiii. 16 ff.) forces people to take his mark; only those who refuse it are destined to reign with Christ (Rev. xx. 4). The chosen hundred and forty-four thousand have the name of God and the name of the Lamb written on their foreheads (Rev. xiv. 1).

“Assurance of salvation” in a time of eschatological expectation demanded some kind of security for the future of which the earnest could be possessed in the present. And with this the predestinarian thought of election was in complete accord. If we find the thought of being sealed unto salvation previously in the Psalms of Solomon, and subsequently in the same signification in Paul, in the Apocalypse of John, and down to the Shepherd of Hermas, it may be assumed in advance that it will be found in some form or other in the so strongly eschatological teaching of Jesus and the Baptist.

“Guaranteed salvation” during a time of waiting for the end times required some sort of security for the future that could be experienced in the present. This idea aligned perfectly with the belief in predestination and election. If we see the concept of being marked for salvation in the Psalms of Solomon, later used in the same sense by Paul, in the Book of Revelation, and up to the Shepherd of Hermas, we can reasonably expect to find it reflected in some way in the strongly eschatological teachings of Jesus and John the Baptist.

It may be said, indeed, to dominate completely the eschatological preaching of the Baptist, for this preaching does not confine itself to the declaration of the nearness of the Kingdom, and the demand for repentance, but leads up to an act to which it gives a special reference in relation to the forgiveness of sins and the outpouring of the spirit. It is a mistake to regard baptism with water as a “symbolic act” in the modern sense, and make the Baptist decry his own wares by saying, “I baptize only with water, but the other can baptize with the Holy Spirit.” He is not contrasting the two baptisms, but connecting them—he who is baptized by him has the certainty that he will share in the outpouring of the Spirit which shall precede the judgment, and at the judgment shall receive forgiveness of sins, as one who is signed with the mark of repentance. The object of being baptized by him is to secure baptism with the Spirit later. The forgiveness of sins associated with baptism is proleptic; it is to be realised at the judgment. The Baptist himself did not forgive sin.289 If he had done so, how could [pg 377] such offence have been taken when Jesus claimed for Himself the right to forgive sins in the present (Mark ii. 10).

It can be said that the eschatological preaching of the Baptist completely dominates the message, as this preaching doesn’t just announce the nearness of the Kingdom and the need for repentance, but also points to an act that specifically relates to the forgiveness of sins and the outpouring of the Spirit. It's a mistake to think of water baptism as a “symbolic gesture” in the modern sense and to have the Baptist downplay his own purpose by saying, “I baptize with just water, but the other can baptize with the Holy Spirit.” He’s not contrasting the two baptisms; he’s actually linking them—those who are baptized by him can be certain that they will participate in the outpouring of the Spirit that will happen before the judgment, and at that judgment, they will receive forgiveness of sins as those marked by repentance. The goal of being baptized by him is to ensure baptism with the Spirit later. The forgiveness of sins connected to baptism is anticipatory; it will be realized at the judgment. The Baptist himself did not forgive sins.289 If he had, how could there have been such offense taken when Jesus claimed the authority to forgive sins in the present (Mark ii. 10)?

The baptism of John was therefore an eschatological sacrament pointing forward to the pouring forth of the spirit and to the judgment, a provision for “salvation.” Hence the wrath of the Baptist when he saw Pharisees and Sadducees crowding to his baptism: “Ye generation of vipers, who hath warned you to flee from the wrath to come? Bring forth now fruits meet for repentance” (Matt. iii. 7, 8). By the reception of baptism, that is, they are saved from the judgment.

The baptism of John was an eschatological sacrament that looked ahead to the outpouring of the spirit and to judgment, serving as a means for “salvation.” This explains the Baptist's anger when he saw Pharisees and Sadducees coming to his baptism: "You bunch of snakes, who told you to escape from the upcoming punishment? Show that you have changed by the way you live." (Matt. iii. 7, 8). Through baptism, they are saved from judgment.

As a cleansing unto salvation it is a divine institution, a revealed means of grace. That is why the question of Jesus, whether the baptism of John was from heaven or from men, placed the Scribes at Jerusalem in so awkward a dilemma (Mark xi. 30).

As a cleansing for salvation, it is a divine institution and a revealed means of grace. That’s why Jesus' question about whether John's baptism was from heaven or from people put the Scribes in Jerusalem in such an awkward position (Mark xi. 30).

The authority of Jesus, however, goes farther than that of the Baptist. As the Messiah who is to come He can give even here below to those who gather about Him a right to partake in the Messianic feast, by this distribution of food to them; only, they do not know what is happening to them and He cannot solve the riddle for them. The supper at the Lake of Gennesareth was a veiled eschatological sacrament. Neither the disciples nor the multitude understood what was happening, since they did not know who He was who thus made them His guests.290 This meal must [pg 378] have been transformed by tradition into a miracle, a result which may have been in part due to the references to the wonders of the Messianic feast which were doubtless contained in the prayers, not to speak of the eschatological enthusiasm which then prevailed universally. Did not the disciples believe that on the same evening, when they had been commanded to take Jesus into their ship at the mouth of the Jordan, to which point He had walked along the shore—did they not believe that they saw Him come walking towards them upon the waves of the sea? The impulse to the introduction of the miraculous into the narrative came from the unintelligible element with which the men who surrounded Jesus were at this time confronted.291

The authority of Jesus, however, goes beyond that of John the Baptist. As the Messiah who is to come, He can give those who gather around Him a right to participate in the Messianic feast, symbolized by His sharing of food with them; yet, they don’t realize what is happening, and He can't explain the mystery to them. The meal at the Lake of Gennesareth was a hidden eschatological sacrament. Neither the disciples nor the crowd understood what was going on since they didn’t know who He was who had made them His guests. This meal must [pg 378] have been transformed by tradition into a miracle, partly due to the references to the wonders of the Messianic feast that were likely included in the prayers, not to mention the widespread eschatological excitement of that time. Didn't the disciples believe that on the same evening they were told to take Jesus into their boat at the mouth of the Jordan, where He had walked along the shore—didn't they think they saw Him walking towards them on the waves? The urge to introduce the miraculous into the story stemmed from the confusing elements faced by the people surrounding Jesus at that moment.

The Last Supper at Jerusalem had the same sacramental significance as that at the lake. Towards the end of the meal Jesus, after giving thanks, distributes the bread and wine. This had as little to do with the satisfaction of hunger as the distribution to the Galilaean believers. The act of Jesus is an end in itself, and the significance of the celebration consists in the fact that it is He Himself who makes the distribution. In Jerusalem, however, they understood what was meant, and He explained it to them explicitly by telling them that He would drink no more of the fruit of the vine until He drank it new in the Kingdom of God. The mysterious images which He used at the time of the distribution concerning the atoning significance of His death do not touch the essence of the celebration, they are only discourses accompanying it.

The Last Supper in Jerusalem held the same sacred meaning as the one by the lake. Near the end of the meal, Jesus, after giving thanks, shares the bread and wine. This had little to do with satisfying hunger, just like the sharing with the Galilean followers. Jesus's action stands alone, and the importance of the celebration lies in the fact that He Himself is the one serving. In Jerusalem, they understood the deeper meaning, and He made it clear by saying that He would not drink from the fruit of the vine again until He drank it fresh in the Kingdom of God. The symbolic images He used during the distribution regarding the redemptive meaning of His death do not change the essence of the celebration; they are merely discussions that accompany it.

On this interpretation, therefore, we may think of Baptism and the Lord's Supper as from the first eschatological sacraments in the eschatological movement which later detached itself from Judaism under the name of Christianity. That explains why we find them both in Paul and in the earliest theology as sacramental acts, not as symbolic ceremonies, and find them dominating the whole Christian doctrine. Apart from the assumption of the eschatological sacraments, we can only make the history of dogma begin with a “fall” from the earlier purer theology into the sacramental magical, without being able to adduce a single syllable in support of the idea that after the death of Jesus Baptism and the Lord's Supper existed even for an hour as symbolical actions—Paul, indeed, makes this supposition wholly impossible.

On this interpretation, we can see Baptism and the Lord's Supper as the first eschatological sacraments in the eschatological movement that later separated from Judaism and became known as Christianity. This explains why we find both of them in Paul’s writings and in early theology as sacramental acts, not just symbolic ceremonies, and why they are central to the entire Christian doctrine. Without the assumption of these eschatological sacraments, we could only say that the history of dogma begins with a "autumn" from the earlier, purer theology into a sacramental magic, without any evidence to support the idea that after Jesus' death, Baptism and the Lord's Supper functioned for even a moment as symbolic actions—Paul, in fact, makes that assumption completely impossible.

In any case the adoption of the baptism of John in Christian practice cannot be explained except on the assumption that it was [pg 379] the sacrament of the eschatological community, a revealed means of securing “salvation” which was not altered in the slightest by the Messiahship of Jesus. How else could we explain the fact that baptism, without any commandment of Jesus, and without Jesus' ever having baptized, was taken over, as a matter of course, into Christianity, and was given a special reference to the receiving of the Spirit?

In any case, the adoption of John’s baptism in Christian practice can't be understood unless we assume that it was the sacrament of the eschatological community, a revealed way of securing “salvation” that wasn’t changed at all by Jesus’ role as Messiah. How else can we explain the fact that baptism, without any instruction from Jesus and despite Jesus never having baptized anyone, became a standard part of Christianity and was specifically linked to receiving the Spirit?

It is no use proposing to explain it as having been instituted as a symbolical repetition of the baptism of Jesus, thought of as “an anointing to the Messiahship.” There is not a single passage in ancient theology to support such a theory. And we may point also to the fact that Paul never refers to the baptism of Jesus in explaining the character of Christian baptism, never, in fact, makes any distinct reference to it. And how could baptism, if it had been a symbolical repetition of the baptism of Jesus, ever have acquired this magic-sacramental sense of “salvation”?

It's pointless to suggest that it was established as a symbolic repeat of Jesus' baptism, seen as “an anointing to the Messiahship.” There's not a single reference in ancient theology to back up that idea. We should also note that Paul never mentions Jesus' baptism when talking about the nature of Christian baptism; in fact, he doesn't refer to it at all. And how could baptism, if it had been just a symbolic repeat of Jesus' baptism, have gained this powerful sacramental meaning of “salvation”?

Nothing shows more clearly than the dual character of ancient baptism, which makes it the guarantee both of the reception of the Spirit and of deliverance from the judgment, that it is nothing else than the eschatological baptism of John with a single difference. Baptism with water and baptism with the Spirit are now connected not only logically, but also in point of time, seeing that since the day of Pentecost the period of the outpouring of the Spirit is present. The two portions of the eschatological sacrament which in the Baptist's preaching were distinguished in point of time—because he did not expect the outpouring of the Spirit until some future period—are now brought together, since one eschatological condition—the baptism with the Spirit—is now present. The “Christianising” of baptism consisted in this and in nothing else; though Paul carried it a stage farther when he formed the conception of baptism as a mystic partaking in the death and resurrection of Jesus.

Nothing illustrates the dual nature of ancient baptism more clearly than its role as the guarantee of receiving the Spirit and escaping judgment; it’s essentially the same as John’s eschatological baptism, with just one difference. Water baptism and Spirit baptism are now connected not only logically but also in timing, since the outpouring of the Spirit has been present since Pentecost. The two aspects of the eschatological sacrament that John separated by time—because he didn’t expect the Spirit’s outpouring until a later time—are now combined, as one eschatological condition—the baptism with the Spirit—is now here. The "Christianizing" of baptism was about this and nothing more; though Paul took it a step further by conceptualizing baptism as a mystical participation in the death and resurrection of Jesus.

Thus the thoroughgoing eschatological interpretation of the Life of Jesus puts into the hands of those who are reconstructing the history of dogma in the earliest times an explanation of the conception of the sacraments, of which they had been able hitherto only to note the presence as an x of which the origin was undiscoverable, and for which they possessed no equation by which it could be evaluated. If Christianity as the religion of historically revealed mysteries was able to lay hold upon Hellenism and overcome it, the reason of this was that it was already in its purely eschatological beginnings a religion of sacraments, a religion of eschatological sacraments, since Jesus had recognised a Divine institution in the baptism of John, and had Himself performed a sacramental action in the distribution of food at the Lake of Gennesareth and at the Last Supper.

Thus, the comprehensive eschatological interpretation of the Life of Jesus provides those reconstructing the history of doctrine in the early days with an understanding of the concept of the sacraments. Previously, they could only acknowledge their existence as an x whose origin was elusive, and for which they had no means to evaluate. If Christianity, as the religion of historically revealed mysteries, could seize upon Hellenism and overcome it, the reason lies in its foundational eschatological nature as a religion of sacraments. This eschatological sacramental aspect is evident since Jesus recognized a Divine institution in John’s baptism and performed a sacramental act in the sharing of food at the Lake of Gennesareth and at the Last Supper.

[pg 380]

This being so, the feeding of the multitude also belongs to the dogmatic element in the history. But no one had previously recognised it as what it really was, an indirect disclosure of the Messianic secret, just as no one had understood the full significance of Jesus' description of the Baptist as Elias.

This being the case, the feeding of the multitude is also part of the dogmatic element in history. However, no one had previously recognized it for what it truly was, an indirect revelation of the Messianic secret, just as no one had grasped the full significance of Jesus' description of the Baptist as Elias.

But how does Peter at Caesarea Philippi know the secret of his Master? What he there declares is not a conviction which had gradually dawned on him, and slowly grown through various stages of probability and certainty.

But how does Peter at Caesarea Philippi know the secret of his Master? What he declares there is not a belief that gradually became clear to him, growing slowly through different levels of likelihood and certainty.

The real character of this incident has been interpreted with remarkable penetration by Wrede. The incident itself, he says, is to be understood in quite as supernatural a fashion in Mark as in Matthew. But on the other hand one does not receive the impression that the writer intends to represent the confession as a merit or a discovery of Peter. “For according to the text of Mark, Jesus shows no trace of joy or surprise at this confession. His only answer consists of the command to say nothing about His Messiahship.” Keim, whom Wrede quotes, had received a similar impression from the Marcan account, and had supposed that Jesus had actually found the confession of Peter inopportune.

The true nature of this incident has been analyzed with incredible insight by Wrede. He argues that the incident should be understood in a way that is just as supernatural in Mark as it is in Matthew. However, it doesn't seem like the writer aims to portray Peter's confession as a merit or a revelation. "In the Gospel of Mark, Jesus does not display any joy or surprise at this confession. His only response is to instruct them not to talk about His identity as the Messiah." Keim, who Wrede references, had a similar reaction to the Markan account and believed that Jesus actually found Peter's confession untimely.

How is all this to be explained—the supernatural knowledge of Peter and the rather curt fashion in which Jesus receives his declaration?

How can we explain all this—the supernatural knowledge of Peter and the somewhat abrupt way Jesus responds to his declaration?

It might be worth while to put the story of the transfiguration side by side with the incident at Caesarea Philippi, since there the Divine Sonship of Jesus is “a second time” revealed to the “three,” Peter, James, and John, and the revelation is made supernaturally by a voice from heaven. It is rather striking that Mark does not seem to be conscious that he is reporting something which the disciples knew already. At the beginning of the actual transfiguration Peter still addresses Jesus simply as Rabbi (Mark ix. 5). And what does it mean when Jesus, during the descent from the mountain, forbids them to speak to any man concerning that which they have seen until after the resurrection of the Son of Man? That would exclude even the other disciples who knew only the secret of His Messiahship. But why should they not be told of the Divine confirmation of that which Peter had declared at Caesarea Philippi and Jesus had “admitted”?

It might be worthwhile to compare the story of the transfiguration with the event at Caesarea Philippi, because there the Divine Sonship of Jesus is “again” revealed to the "three" Peter, James, and John, and this revelation comes supernaturally through a voice from heaven. It's quite striking that Mark doesn’t seem aware that he is sharing something the disciples already knew. At the start of the actual transfiguration, Peter still refers to Jesus simply as Rabbi (Mark ix. 5). And what does it mean when Jesus, while coming down the mountain, instructs them not to tell anyone about what they’ve seen until after the resurrection of the Son of Man? This would even keep the other disciples, who only knew about His Messiahship, in the dark. But why shouldn’t they be informed of the Divine confirmation of what Peter had declared at Caesarea Philippi and what Jesus had "confessed"?

What has the transfiguration to do with the resurrection of the dead? And why are the thoughts of the disciples suddenly busied, not with what they have seen, not with the fact that the Son of Man shall rise from the dead, but simply with the possibility of the rising from the dead, the difficulty being that Elias was not yet present? Those who see in the transfiguration a projection backwards of the Pauline theology into the Gospel history do not realise what are the principal points and difficulties of the [pg 381] narrative. The problem lies in the conversation during the descent. Against the Messiahship of Jesus, against His rising from the dead, they have only one objection to suggest: Elias had not yet come.

What does the transfiguration have to do with the resurrection of the dead? And why are the disciples suddenly focused, not on what they saw, not on the fact that the Son of Man will rise from the dead, but simply on the idea of rising from the dead, with the issue being that Elias had not yet arrived? Those who view the transfiguration as a retroactive projection of Pauline theology into the Gospel story don't recognize the main points and challenges of the [pg 381] narrative. The issue arises from the conversation during the descent. In opposition to Jesus' Messiahship and His resurrection, they have only one argument to make: Elias had not come yet.

We see here, in the first place, the importance of the revelation which Jesus had made to the people in declaring to them the secret that the Baptist is Elias. From the standpoint of the eschatological expectation no one could recognise Elias in the Baptist, unless he knew of the Messiahship of Jesus. And no one could believe in the Messiahship and “resurrection” of Jesus, that is, in His Parousia, without presupposing that Elias had in some way or other already come. This was therefore the primary difficulty of the disciples, the stumbling-block which Jesus must remove for them by making the same revelation concerning the Baptist to them as to the people. It is also once more abundantly clear that expectation was directed at that time primarily to the coming of Elias.292 But since the whole eschatological movement arose out of the Baptist's preaching, the natural conclusion is that by “him who was to come after” and baptize with the Holy Spirit John meant, not the Messiah, but Elias.

We see here, first of all, the importance of the revelation Jesus shared with the people by revealing that the Baptist is Elijah. From the perspective of eschatological expectation, no one could recognize Elijah in the Baptist unless they knew about Jesus’ role as the Messiah. And no one could believe in Jesus’ Messiahship and "revival", that is, in His Second Coming, without assuming that Elijah had already come in some way. This was, therefore, the main challenge for the disciples, the stumbling block that Jesus had to clear up for them by revealing to them the same truth about the Baptist as He did to the people. It is also clear once again that the expectation at that time was primarily focused on the coming of Elijah.292 But since the entire eschatological movement emerged from the Baptist's preaching, the logical conclusion is that by “the one who was to follow” and baptize with the Holy Spirit, John meant not the Messiah, but Elijah.

But if the non-appearance of Elias was the primary difficulty of the disciples in connexion with the Messiahship of Jesus and all that it implied, why does it only strike the “three,” and moreover, all three of them together, now, and not at Caesarea Philippi?293 How could Peter there have declared it and here be still labouring with the rest over the difficulty which stood in the way of his own declaration? To make the narrative coherent, the transfiguration, as being a revelation of the Messiahship, ought to precede the incident at Caesarea Philippi. Now let us look at the connexion in which it actually occurs. It falls in that inexplicable section Mark viii. 34-ix. 30 in which the multitude suddenly appears in the company of Jesus who is sojourning in a Gentile district, only to disappear again, equally enigmatically, afterwards, when He sets out for Galilee, instead of accompanying Him back to their own country.

But if Elias not showing up was the main issue for the disciples regarding Jesus's role as the Messiah and everything that comes with it, why does it only seem to impact the "3," and all of them together now, rather than at Caesarea Philippi? How could Peter have declared it there and still be struggling here with the others over the obstacle that hindered his own declaration? To make the story consistent, the transfiguration, as a revelation of the Messiahship, should have come before the event at Caesarea Philippi. Now, let’s examine the context in which it actually happens. It takes place in that puzzling section Mark viii. 34-ix. 30, where the crowd suddenly appears with Jesus while He is in a Gentile area, only to mysteriously vanish again later when He heads back to Galilee, rather than returning to their own country with Him.

In this section everything points to the situation during the days at Bethsaida after the return of the disciples from their mission. Jesus is surrounded by the people, while what He desires is to be alone with His immediate followers. The disciples make use of the healing powers which He had bestowed upon them when sending them forth, and have the experience of finding that they are not in all cases adequate (Mark ix. 14-29). The [pg 382] mountain to which He takes the “three” is not a mountain in the north, or as some have suggested, an imaginary mountain of the Evangelist, but the same to which Jesus went up to pray and to be alone on the evening of the feeding of the multitude (Mark vi. 46 and ix. 2). The house to which He goes after His return from the transfiguration is therefore to be placed at Bethsaida.

In this section, everything highlights the situation during the days at Bethsaida after the disciples came back from their mission. Jesus is surrounded by the crowd, while what He really wants is to be alone with His close followers. The disciples are using the healing powers that He had given them when He sent them out, and they discover that, in some cases, they aren't quite enough (Mark ix. 14-29). The [pg 382] mountain where He takes the "3" is not a mountain in the north, nor is it, as some have suggested, an imaginary mountain created by the Evangelist, but the same one that Jesus went up to pray and be alone on the evening of the feeding of the multitude (Mark vi. 46 and ix. 2). Therefore, the house He goes to after returning from the transfiguration should be located at Bethsaida.

Another thing which points to a sojourn at Bethsaida after the feeding of the multitude is the story of the healing of the blind man at Bethsaida (Mark viii. 22-26).

Another thing that indicates a stay in Bethsaida after the feeding of the multitude is the story of the healing of the blind man at Bethsaida (Mark viii. 22-26).

The circumstances, therefore, which we have to presuppose are that Jesus is surrounded and thronged by the people at Bethsaida. In order to be alone He once more puts the Jordan between Himself and the multitude, and goes with the “three” to the mountain where He had prayed after the feeding of the five thousand. This is the only way in which we can understand how the people failed to follow Him, and He was able really to carry out His plan.

The situation we need to assume is that Jesus is crowded and surrounded by people in Bethsaida. To find some solitude, He once again puts the Jordan River between Himself and the crowd, and goes with the "3" to the mountain where He had prayed after feeding the five thousand. This is the only way we can understand why the people didn’t follow Him, allowing Him to truly execute His plan.

But how could this story be torn out of its natural context and its scene removed to Caesarea Philippi, where it is both on external and internal grounds impossible? What we need to notice is the Marcan account of the events which followed the sending forth of the disciples. We have two stories of the feeding of the multitude with a crossing of the lake after each (Mark vi. 31-56, Mark viii. 1-22), two stories of Jesus going away towards the north with the same motive, that of being alone and unrecognised. The first time, after the controversy about the washing of hands, His course is directed towards Tyre (Mark vii. 24-30), the second time, after the demand for a sign, he goes into the district of Caesarea Philippi (Mark viii. 27). The scene of the controversy about the washing of hands is some locality in the plain of Gennesareth (Mark vi. 53 ff); Dalmanutha is named as the place where the sign was demanded (Mark viii. 10 ff.).

But how could this story be taken out of its natural context and moved to Caesarea Philippi, where it's impossible both externally and internally? We need to pay attention to the Markan account of the events that followed the sending out of the disciples. There are two stories of feeding the multitude, each followed by a crossing of the lake (Mark vi. 31-56, Mark viii. 1-22), and two stories of Jesus heading north for the same reason: to be alone and unrecognized. The first time, after the debate about handwashing, He heads towards Tyre (Mark vii. 24-30); the second time, after the request for a sign, He goes into the area of Caesarea Philippi (Mark viii. 27). The scene of the debate about handwashing takes place in a location in the plain of Gennesareth (Mark vi. 53 ff); Dalmanutha is identified as the place where the sign was requested (Mark viii. 10 ff.).

The most natural conclusion is to identify the two cases of feeding the multitude, and the two journeys northwards. In that case we should have in the section Mark vi. 31-ix. 30, two sets of narratives worked into one another, both recounting how Jesus, after the disciples came back to Him, went with them from Capernaum to the northern shore of the lake, was there surprised by the multitude, and after the meal which He gave them, crossed the Jordan by boat to Bethsaida, stayed there for a while, and then returned again by ship to the country of Gennesareth, and was there again overtaken and surrounded by the people; then after some controversial encounters with the Scribes, who at the report of His miracles had come down from Jerusalem (Mark vii. 1), left Galilee and again went northwards.294

The most natural conclusion is to connect the two accounts of feeding the multitude and the two journeys north. In that case, in the section Mark vi. 31-ix. 30, we would have two sets of stories woven together, both telling how Jesus, after the disciples returned to Him, went with them from Capernaum to the northern shore of the lake, was then met by the crowd, and after the meal He provided, crossed the Jordan by boat to Bethsaida. He stayed there for a while and then returned by ship to the region of Gennesareth, where He was again surrounded by the people. After some controversial exchanges with the scribes who had come down from Jerusalem after hearing about His miracles (Mark vii. 1), He left Galilee and headed north again.294

[pg 383]

The seams at the joining of the narratives can be recognised in Mark vii. 31, where Jesus is suddenly transferred from the north to Decapolis, and in the saying in Mark viii. 14 ff., which makes explicit reference to the two miracles of feeding the multitude. Whether the Evangelist himself worked these two sets of narratives together, or whether he found them already united, cannot be determined, and is not of any direct historical interest. The disorder is in any case so complete that we cannot fully reconstruct each of the separate sets of narratives.

The connections between the stories can be seen in Mark vii. 31, where Jesus is abruptly moved from the north to Decapolis, and in Mark viii. 14 ff., which explicitly refers to the two miracles of feeding the crowd. It’s unclear whether the Evangelist combined these two groups of stories himself or if he found them already connected, and this isn’t particularly relevant to historical analysis. The disarray is so significant that we can’t completely piece together each individual set of narratives.

The external reasons why the narratives of Mark viii. 34-ix. 30, of which the scene is on the northern shore of the lake, are placed in this way after the incident of Caesarea Philippi are not difficult to grasp. The section contains an impressive discourse to the people on following Jesus in His sufferings, crucifixion, and death (Mark viii. 34-ix. 1). For this reason the whole series of scenes is attached to the revelation of the secret of the suffering of the Son of Man; and the redactor did not stop to think how the people could suddenly appear, and as suddenly disappear again. The statement, too, “He called the people with the disciples” (Mark viii. 34), helped to mislead him into inserting the section at this point, although this very remark points to the circumstances of the time just after the return of the disciples, when Jesus was sometimes alone with the disciples, and sometimes calls the eager multitude about Him.

The external reasons why the stories in Mark viii. 34-ix. 30, which take place on the northern shore of the lake, are arranged this way after the event at Caesarea Philippi are not hard to understand. This section includes a powerful message to the people about following Jesus through His sufferings, crucifixion, and death (Mark viii. 34-ix. 1). Because of this, the entire series of scenes is linked to the revelation of the secret about the suffering of the Son of Man; and the editor didn't pause to consider how the crowd could suddenly appear and then disappear again. The statement, too, "He gathered the people along with the disciples." (Mark viii. 34), misled him into placing this section here, even though this very remark refers to the time just after the disciples returned, when Jesus was sometimes alone with them and at other times called the eager crowd around Him.

The whole scene belongs, therefore, to the days which He spent at Bethsaida, and originally followed immediately upon the crossing of the lake, after the feeding of the multitude. It was after Jesus had been six days surrounded by the people, not six days after the revelation at Caesarea Philippi, that the “transfiguration” took place (Mark ix. 2). On this assumption, all the difficulties of the incident at Caesarea Philippi are cleared up in a moment; there is no longer anything strange in the fact that Peter declares to Jesus who He really is, while Jesus appears neither surprised nor especially rejoiced at the insight of His disciple. The transfiguration had, in fact, been the revelation of the secret of the Messiahship to the three who constituted the inner circle of the disciples.295 And Jesus had not Himself revealed it to them; what had happened was, that [pg 384] in a state of rapture common to them all, in which they had seen the Master in a glorious transfiguration, they had seen Him talking with Moses and Elias and had heard a voice from heaven saying, “This is my beloved Son, hear ye Him.”

The entire scene takes place during the days that Jesus spent in Bethsaida, right after crossing the lake following the feeding of the crowd. It was after Jesus had been with the people for six days—not six days after the revelation at Caesarea Philippi—that the “transformation” occurred (Mark ix. 2). With this understanding, all the confusion about the events at Caesarea Philippi is instantly resolved; there's nothing unusual about Peter recognizing who Jesus really is, while Jesus doesn’t seem surprised or especially pleased by His disciple's insight. The transfiguration was, in fact, the revelation of the secret of His Messiahship to the three disciples who were in His inner circle. And Jesus hadn’t revealed this to them; instead, in a shared state of wonder, they saw the Master in a glorious transformation, talking with Moses and Elijah, and they heard a voice from heaven saying, "This is my beloved Son; listen to Him."

We must always make a fresh effort to realise to ourselves, that Jesus and His immediate followers were, at that time, in an enthusiastic state of intense eschatological expectation. We must picture them among the people, who were filled with penitence for their sins, and with faith in the Kingdom, hourly expecting the coming of the Kingdom, and the revelation of Jesus as the Son of Man, seeing in the eager multitude itself a sign that their reckoning of the time was correct; thus the psychological conditions were present for a common ecstatic experience such as is described in the account of the transfiguration.

We need to continually remind ourselves that Jesus and His close followers were, at that time, filled with a passionate sense of anticipation about the end times. We should envision them among the people, who were repentant for their sins and had faith in the Kingdom, eagerly expecting its arrival and the revelation of Jesus as the Son of Man. They believed that the enthusiastic crowd itself was proof that their timing was right; thus, the psychological conditions were set for a shared ecstatic experience like the one described in the account of the transfiguration.

In this ecstasy the “three” heard the voice from heaven saying who He was. Therefore, the Matthaean report, according to which Jesus praises Simon “because flesh and blood have not revealed it to him, but the Father who is in heaven,” is not really at variance with the briefer Marcan account, since it rightly indicates the source of Peter's knowledge.

In this ecstasy, the "3" heard the voice from heaven revealing who He was. Therefore, the Gospel of Matthew's account, where Jesus praises Simon “because no human has revealed it to him, but the Father in heaven has.” doesn’t actually contradict the shorter version in Mark, as it correctly points to the source of Peter's understanding.

Nevertheless Jesus was astonished. For Peter here disregarded the command given during the descent from the mount of transfiguration. He had “betrayed” to the Twelve Jesus' consciousness of His Messiahship. One receives the impression that Jesus did not put the question to the disciples in order to reveal Himself to them as Messiah, and that by the impulsive speech of Peter, upon whose silence He had counted because of His command, and to whom He had not specially addressed the question, He was forced to take a different line of action in regard to the Twelve from what He had intended. It is probable that He had never had the intention of revealing the secret of His Messiahship to the disciples. Otherwise He would not have kept it from them at the time of their mission, when He did not expect them to return before the Parousia. Even at the transfiguration the “three” do not learn it from His lips, but in a state of ecstasy, an ecstasy which He shared with them. At Caesarea Philippi it is not He, but Peter, who reveals His Messiahship. We may say, therefore, that Jesus did not voluntarily give up His Messianic secret; it was wrung from Him by the pressure of events.

Nevertheless, Jesus was astonished. Peter disregarded the command given during the descent from the mount of transfiguration. He had “betrayed” to the Twelve Jesus' awareness of His Messiahship. It seems that Jesus didn’t ask the question to the disciples to reveal Himself to them as the Messiah, and because of Peter’s impulsive response—someone whose silence He had relied on due to His command, and to whom He hadn’t specifically addressed the question—Jesus was compelled to change His approach with the Twelve from what He had originally intended. It’s likely that He never intended to disclose the secret of His Messiahship to the disciples. If He had, He wouldn’t have kept it from them during their mission, especially since He didn’t expect them to return before the Parousia. Even during the transfiguration, the "three" did not hear it from His lips, but experienced it in a state of ecstasy, which He shared with them. At Caesarea Philippi, it is not Jesus, but Peter, who reveals His Messiahship. Therefore, we can conclude that Jesus did not willingly give up His Messianic secret; it was forced out of Him by the pressure of events.

However that may be, from Caesarea Philippi onwards it was known to the other disciples through Peter; what Jesus Himself revealed to them, was the secret of his sufferings.

However that may be, from Caesarea Philippi onwards, it was known to the other disciples through Peter; what Jesus Himself revealed to them was the secret of his sufferings.

Pfleiderer and Wrede were quite right in pointing to the clear and definite predictions of the suffering, death, and resurrection as the historically inexplicable element in our reports, since the necessity of Jesus' death, by which modern theology endeavours [pg 385] to make His resolve and His predictions intelligible, is not a necessity which arises out of the historical course of events. There was not present any natural ground for such a resolve on the part of Jesus. Had He returned to Galilee, He would immediately have had the multitudes flocking after Him again.

Pfleiderer and Wrede were absolutely correct in highlighting the clear and unmistakable predictions of suffering, death, and resurrection as the historically unexplainable aspect of our accounts. This is because the necessity of Jesus' death, which modern theology tries to explain as part of His decisions and predictions, does not stem from the actual historical events. There was no natural reason for Jesus to make such a decision. If He had gone back to Galilee, the crowds would have immediately come after Him again.

In order to make the historical possibility of the resolve to suffer and the prediction of the sufferings in some measure intelligible, modern theology has to ignore the prediction of the resurrection which is bound up with them, for this is “dogmatic.” That is, however, not permissible. We must, as Wrede insists, take the words as they are, and must not even indulge in ingenious explanations of the “three days.” Therefore, the resolve to suffer and to die are dogmatic; therefore, according to him, they are unhistorical, and only to be explained by a literary hypothesis.

To understand the historical context of the decision to endure suffering and the prophecy of those sufferings, modern theology tends to overlook the prediction of the resurrection that is associated with them, since this is "dogmatic." However, this isn't acceptable. We must, as Wrede argues, take the words at face value and not get caught up in clever interpretations of the “3 days.” Therefore, the decision to suffer and to die is dogmatic; accordingly, Wrede believes they are unhistorical and can only be explained through a literary hypothesis.

But the thoroughgoing eschatological school says they are dogmatic, and therefore historical; because they find their explanation in eschatological conceptions.

But the thoroughgoing eschatological school argues that they are dogmatic and, therefore, historical; because they find their explanation in eschatological ideas.

Wrede held that the Messianic conception implied in the Marcan narrative is not the Jewish Messianic conception, just because of the thought of suffering and death which it involves. No stress must be laid on the fact that in Fourth Ezra vii. 29 the Christ dies and rises again, because His death takes place at the end of the Messianic Kingdom.296 The Jewish Messiah is essentially a glorious being who shall appear in the last time. True, but the case in which the Messiah should be present, prior to the Parousia, should cause the final tribulations to come upon the earth, and should Himself undergo them, does not arise in the Jewish eschatology as described from without. It first arises with the self-consciousness of Jesus. Therefore, the Jewish conception of the Messiah has no information to give us upon this point.

Wrede believed that the Messianic idea mentioned in the Markan narrative is different from the Jewish Messianic concept, primarily because it involves suffering and death. It's not important to emphasize that in Fourth Ezra 7:29, the Christ dies and then rises again, since His death occurs at the end of the Messianic Kingdom. The Jewish Messiah is fundamentally a glorious figure who will appear at the end of times. While it's true, the scenario where the Messiah is present before the Parousia, brings on the final tribulations on earth, and experiences them Himself, doesn't appear in Jewish eschatology as seen from an outside perspective. This notion only arises with Jesus's self-awareness. Therefore, the Jewish understanding of the Messiah doesn’t provide any insights on this matter.

In order to understand Jesus' resolve to suffer, we must first recognise that the mystery of this suffering is involved in the mystery of the Kingdom of God, since the Kingdom cannot come until the πειρασμός has taken place. This certainty of suffering is quite independent of the historic circumstances, as the beatitude on the persecuted in the sermon on the mount, and the predictions in the discourse at the sending forth of the Twelve, clearly show. Jesus' prediction of His own sufferings at Caesarea Philippi is precisely as unintelligible, precisely as dogmatic, and therefore precisely as historical as the prediction to the disciples at the time of their mission. The “must be” of the sufferings is the same—the coming of the Kingdom, and of the Parousia, which are dependent upon the πειρασμός having first taken place.

To understand Jesus' determination to suffer, we first need to recognize that the mystery of this suffering is tied to the mystery of the Kingdom of God, since the Kingdom cannot arrive until the πειρασμός has happened. This certainty of suffering stands apart from historical circumstances, as seen in the beatitude for the persecuted in the Sermon on the Mount and the predictions in the discourse when the Twelve were sent out. Jesus' prediction of His own sufferings at Caesarea Philippi is just as puzzling, just as dogmatic, and therefore just as historical as the prediction He made to the disciples at the time of their mission. The "has to be" of the sufferings is the same—the coming of the Kingdom and of the Parousia, which depend on the πειρασμός occurring first.

[pg 386]

In the first period Jesus' thoughts concerning His own sufferings were included in the more general thought of the sufferings which formed part of the mystery of the Kingdom of God. The exhortations to hold steadfastly to Him in the time of trial, and not to lose faith in Him, certainly tended to suggest that He thought of Himself as the central point amid these conflicts and confusions, and reckoned on the possibility of His own death as much as on that of others. Upon this point nothing more definite can be said, since the mystery of Jesus' own sufferings does not detach itself from the mystery of the sufferings connected with the Kingdom of God until after the Messianic secret is made known at Caesarea Philippi. What is certain is that, for Him, suffering was always associated with the Messianic secret, since He placed His Parousia at the end of the pre-Messianic tribulations in which He was to have His part.

In the first period, Jesus' thoughts about His own suffering were part of a broader understanding of the sufferings that were tied to the mystery of the Kingdom of God. The encouragements to stay loyal to Him during tough times and not lose faith implied that He saw Himself as the focal point in these struggles and was aware of the possibility of His own death, just like the deaths of others. Nothing more can be said about this point since Jesus' own suffering doesn't separate from the suffering associated with the Kingdom of God until the Messianic secret is revealed at Caesarea Philippi. What is clear is that, for Him, suffering was always linked to the Messianic secret, as He positioned His return at the end of the pre-Messianic trials in which He was to participate.

The suffering, death, and resurrection of which the secret was revealed at Caesarea Philippi are not therefore in themselves new or surprising.297 The novelty lies in the form in which they are conceived. The tribulation, so far as Jesus is concerned, is now connected with an historic event: He will go to Jerusalem, there to suffer death at the hands of the authorities.

The suffering, death, and resurrection that were revealed at Caesarea Philippi aren’t, on their own, new or surprising. The newness comes from how they are understood. The struggles that Jesus faces are now tied to a specific event in history: He will go to Jerusalem, where He will suffer and die at the hands of the authorities.

For the future, however, He no longer speaks of the general tribulation which He is to bring upon the earth, nor of the sufferings which await His followers, nor of the sufferings in which they must rally round Him. In the predictions of the passion there is no word of that; at Jerusalem there is no word of that. This thought disappears once for all.

For the future, though, He no longer talks about the general suffering He will bring upon the earth, or the hardships His followers will face, or the struggles they need to support Him through. In the predictions of the suffering, there is no mention of that; in Jerusalem, there is no mention of that. This idea is gone for good.

In the secret of His passion which Jesus reveals to the disciples at Caesarea Philippi the pre-Messianic tribulation is for others set aside, abolished, concentrated upon Himself alone, and that in the [pg 387] form that they are fulfilled in His own passion and death at Jerusalem. That was the new conviction that had dawned upon Him. He must suffer for others ... that the Kingdom might come.

In the secret of His passion, which Jesus shares with the disciples at Caesarea Philippi, the suffering before the Messiah is set aside for others, abolished, and focused solely on Himself. This is shown in the [pg 387] way that it all culminates in His own suffering and death in Jerusalem. This was the new understanding that had come to Him. He must suffer for others... so that the Kingdom might arrive.

This change was due to the non-fulfilment of the promises made in the discourse at the sending forth of the Twelve. He had thought then to let loose the final tribulation and so compel the coming of the Kingdom. And the cataclysm had not occurred. He had expected it also after the return of the disciples. In Bethsaida, in speaking to the multitude which He had consecrated by the foretaste of the Messianic feast, as also to the disciples at the time of their mission, He had turned their thoughts to things to come and had adjured them to be prepared to suffer with Him, to give up their lives, not to be ashamed of Him in His humiliation, since otherwise the Son of Man would be ashamed of them when He came in glory (Mark viii. 34-ix. 1).298

This change was due to the failure to keep the promises made during the speech at the sending out of the Twelve. He had then planned to unleash the final tribulation to bring about the Kingdom. And the catastrophe had not happened. He had also anticipated it after the disciples returned. In Bethsaida, while speaking to the crowd he had gathered with a taste of the Messianic feast, as well as to the disciples during their mission, he directed their thoughts to future events and urged them to be ready to suffer with him, to give up their lives, and not to be ashamed of him in his humiliation, because otherwise the Son of Man would be ashamed of them when he came in glory (Mark viii. 34-ix. 1).298

In leaving Galilee He abandoned the hope that the final tribulation would begin of itself. If it delays, that means that there is still something to be done, and yet another of the violent must lay violent hands upon the Kingdom of God. The movement of repentance had not been sufficient. When, in accordance with His commission, by sending forth the disciples with their message, he hurled the fire-brand which should kindle the fiery trials of the Last Time, the flame went out. He had not succeeded in sending the sword on earth and stirring up the conflict. And until the time of trial had come, the coming of the Kingdom and His own manifestation as Son of Man were impossible.

In leaving Galilee, he gave up the hope that the final tribulation would start on its own. If it's delayed, it means there's still something to be done, and another violent person must take action against the Kingdom of God. The movement of repentance wasn't enough. When, as part of his mission, he sent out the disciples with their message to ignite the fiery trials of the Last Time, the flame extinguished. He hadn't managed to bring the sword to earth or spark the conflict. Until the trial begins, the arrival of the Kingdom and his own revelation as the Son of Man couldn't happen.

That meant—not that the Kingdom was not near at hand—but that God had appointed otherwise in regard to the time of trial. He had heard the Lord's Prayer in which Jesus and His followers prayed for the coming of the Kingdom—and at the same time, for deliverance from the πειρασμός. The time of trial was not come; therefore God in His mercy and omnipotence had eliminated it from the series of eschatological events, and appointed to Him whose commission had been to bring it about, instead to accomplish it in His own person. As He who was to rule over the members of the Kingdom in the future age, He was appointed to serve them in the present, to give His life for them, the many (Mark x. 45 and xiv. 24), and to make in His own blood the atonement which they would have had to render in the tribulation.

That meant—not that the Kingdom was not close by—but that God had planned differently regarding the time of trial. He had heard the Lord's Prayer in which Jesus and His followers prayed for the arrival of the Kingdom—and at the same time, for deliverance from temptation. The time of trial had not yet come; therefore, God in His mercy and power had removed it from the series of end times events, and instead appointed the one whose mission was to bring it about, to fulfill it Himself. As the one who would rule over the members of the Kingdom in the future, He was chosen to serve them in the present, to give His life for them, the many (Mark x. 45 and xiv. 24), and to make atonement in His own blood for what they would have had to endure in the tribulation.

The Kingdom could not come until the debt which weighed upon the world was discharged. Until then, not only the now living believers, but the chosen of all generations since the beginning [pg 388] of the world wait for their manifestation in glory—Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob and all the countless unknown who should come from the East and from the West to sit at tables with them at the Messianic feast (Matt. viii. 11). The enigmatic πολλοί for whom Jesus dies are those predestined to the Kingdom, since His death must at last compel the Coming of the Kingdom.299

The Kingdom can’t come until the debt that hangs over the world is paid off. Until then, not only the believers alive today but also the chosen ones from every generation since the beginning of the world [pg 388] are waiting to be revealed in glory—Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, along with all the countless unknown individuals who will come from the East and the West to join them at the Messianic feast (Matt. viii. 11). The mysterious πολλοί for whom Jesus died are those destined for the Kingdom, as His death must ultimately bring about the Coming of the Kingdom.299

This thought Jesus found in the prophecies of Isaiah, which spoke of the suffering Servant of the Lord. The mysterious description of Him who in His humiliation was despised and misunderstood, who, nevertheless bears the guilt of others and afterwards is made manifest in what He has done for them, points, He feels, to Himself.

This idea Jesus found in the prophecies of Isaiah, which talked about the suffering Servant of the Lord. The enigmatic portrayal of Someone who, despite being humiliated, was despised and misunderstood, yet still carries the guilt of others and ultimately reveals Himself through what He has done for them, He believes refers to Him.

And since He found it there set down that He must suffer unrecognised, and that those for whom He suffered should doubt Him, His suffering should, nay must, remain a mystery. In that case those who doubted Him would not bring condemnation upon themselves. He no longer needs to adjure them for their own sakes to be faithful to Him and to stand by Him even amid reproach and humiliation; He can calmly predict to His disciples that they shall all be offended in Him and shall flee (Mark xiv. 26, 27); He can tell Peter, who boasts that he will die with Him, that before the dawn he shall deny Him thrice (Mark xiv. 29-31); all that is so set down in the Scripture. They must doubt Him. But now they shall not lose their blessedness, for He bears all sins and transgressions. That, too, is buried in the atonement which He offers.

And because He found it written that He would suffer without being recognized, and that those for whom He suffered would doubt Him, His suffering should, in fact, remain a mystery. In this way, those who doubted Him wouldn’t be condemning themselves. He no longer needs to urge them to be loyal and stand by Him, even in the face of shame and humiliation; He can calmly tell His disciples that they will all be offended by Him and will flee (Mark xiv. 26, 27); He can tell Peter, who insists he will die with Him, that before dawn he will deny Him three times (Mark xiv. 29-31); all of this is written in Scripture. They must doubt Him. But now they won’t lose their blessedness, because He carries all sins and transgressions. That, too, is included in the atonement He offers.

[pg 389]

Therefore, also, there is no need for them to understand His secret. He spoke of it to them without any explanation. It is sufficient that they should know why He goes up to Jerusalem. They, on their part, are thinking only of the coming transformation of all things, as their conversation shows. The prospect which He has opened up to them is clear enough; the only thing that they do not understand is why He must first die at Jerusalem. The first time that Peter ventured to speak to Him about it, He had turned on him with cruel harshness, had almost cursed him (Mark viii. 32, 33); from that time forward they no longer dared to ask Him anything about it. The new thought of His own passion has its basis therefore in the authority with which Jesus was armed to bring about the beginning of the final tribulation. Ethically regarded, His taking the suffering upon Himself is an act of mercy and compassion towards those who would otherwise have had to bear these tribulations, and perhaps would not have stood the test. Historically regarded, the thought of His sufferings involves the same lofty treatment both of history and eschatology as was manifested in the identification of the Baptist with Elias. For now He identifies His condemnation and execution, which are to take place on natural lines, with the predicted pre-Messianic tribulations. This imperious forcing of eschatology into history is also its destruction; its assertion and abandonment at the same time.

Therefore, there’s no need for them to understand His secret. He shared it with them without any explanation. It's enough for them to know why He’s going up to Jerusalem. They are only focused on the upcoming transformation of everything, as their conversation reveals. The future He has shown them is clear enough; the only thing they don’t get is why He must first die in Jerusalem. The first time Peter dared to talk to Him about it, He reacted harshly, almost cursing him (Mark viii. 32, 33); after that, they didn't dare to ask Him anything related to it. The idea of His own suffering is based on the authority with which Jesus was empowered to initiate the final tribulation. Ethically speaking, Him taking on the suffering is an act of mercy and compassion for those who would otherwise have to endure these tribulations, and they might not have been able to handle it. Historically, the thought of His sufferings involves the same high-level treatment of history and eschatology that was shown in identifying the Baptist with Elijah. Now He links His condemnation and execution, which will happen in a natural way, with the foretold pre-Messianic tribulations. This forceful merging of eschatology into history also leads to its destruction; it is both asserted and abandoned at the same time.

Towards Passover, therefore, Jesus sets out for Jerusalem, solely in order to die there.300 “It is,” says Wrede, “beyond question the opinion of Mark that Jesus went to Jerusalem because He had decided to die; that is obvious even from the details of the story.” It is therefore a mistake to speak of Jesus as “teaching” in Jerusalem. He has no intention of doing so. As a prophet He foretells in veiled parabolic form the offence which must come (Mark xii. 1-12), exhorts men to watch for the Parousia, pictures the nature of the judgment which the Son of Man shall hold, and, for the rest, thinks only how He can so provoke the Pharisees and the rulers that they will be compelled to get rid of Him. That is why He violently cleanses the Temple, and attacks the Pharisees, in the presence of the people, with passionate invective.

Towards Passover, Jesus heads to Jerusalem solely to die there.300 "It is," says Wrede, "There's no doubt about Mark's belief that Jesus went to Jerusalem because He had chosen to die; that's clear even from the details of the story." Therefore, it’s incorrect to refer to Jesus as “teaching” in Jerusalem. He has no intention of doing that. As a prophet, He foreshadows, in a veiled and parabolic way, the offense that must come (Mark xii. 1-12), urges people to be alert for the Parousia, describes the nature of the judgment that the Son of Man will carry out, and mostly considers how He can provoke the Pharisees and the leaders into eliminating Him. That’s why He forcefully cleanses the Temple and vehemently confronts the Pharisees in front of the crowd.

From the revelation at Caesarea Philippi onward, all that belongs to the history of Jesus, in the strict sense, are the events which lead up to His death; or, to put it more accurately, the events in which He Himself is the sole actor. The other things which happen, the questions which are laid before Him for decision, the episodic incidents which occur in those days, have nothing to [pg 390] do with the real “Life of Jesus,” since they contribute nothing to the decisive issue, but merely form the anecdotic fringes of the real outward and inward event, the deliberate bringing down of death upon Himself.

From the revelation at Caesarea Philippi onward, everything that is part of Jesus's history, in the strictest sense, includes the events leading up to His death; or, to put it more accurately, the events where He is the only one taking action. The other things that happen, the questions presented to Him for answers, and the random incidents that occur during those days, have nothing to do with the true “Life of Jesus,” since they don’t contribute to the crucial outcome, but rather serve as the anecdotal details surrounding the real, intentional act of bringing death upon Himself.

It is in truth surprising that He succeeded in transforming into history this resolve which had its roots in dogma, and really dying alone. Is it not almost unintelligible that His disciples were not involved in His fate? Not even the disciple who smote with the sword was arrested along with Him (Mark xiv. 47); Peter, recognised in the courtyard of the High Priest's house as one who had been with Jesus the Nazarene, is allowed to go free.

It’s truly surprising that He managed to change this determination, which was rooted in dogma, into a part of history, even while facing death alone. Isn’t it hard to understand why His followers weren’t involved in what happened to Him? Not even the disciple who drew a sword was arrested along with Him (Mark xiv. 47); Peter, who was identified in the courtyard of the High Priest’s house as someone who had been with Jesus the Nazarene, is allowed to go free.

For a moment indeed, Jesus believes that the “three” are destined to share His fate, not from any outward necessity, but because they had professed themselves able to suffer the last extremities with Him. The sons of Zebedee, when He asked them whether, in order to sit at His right hand and His left, they are prepared to drink His cup and be baptized with His baptism, had declared that they were, and thereupon He had predicted that they should do so (Mark x. 38, 39). Peter again had that very night, in spite of the warning of Jesus, sworn that he would go even unto death with Him (Mark xiv. 30, 31). Hence He is conscious of a higher possibility that these three are to go through the trial with Him. He takes them with Him to Gethsemane and bids them remain near Him and watch with Him. And since they do not perceive the danger of the hour, He adjures them to watch and pray. They are to pray that they may not have to pass through the trial (ἵνα μὴ ἔλθητε εἰς πειρασμόν) since, though the spirit is willing, the flesh is weak. Amid His own sore distress He is anxious about them and their capacity to share His trial as they had declared their willingness to do.301

For a moment, Jesus truly believes that the three are meant to share His fate, not because they have to, but because they have claimed they can endure the worst alongside Him. When He asked the sons of Zebedee if they were prepared to drink from His cup and be baptized with His baptism to sit at His right and left, they assured Him they were ready, and He then foretold that they would (Mark x. 38, 39). That very night, despite Jesus’ warning, Peter swore that he would follow Him even to death (Mark xiv. 30, 31). Therefore, Jesus feels a deeper possibility that these three will face the trial with Him. He takes them to Gethsemane and asks them to stay close and keep watch with Him. Since they don’t recognize the danger of the moment, He urges them to watch and pray. They should pray to avoid facing the trial (ἵνα μὴ ἔλθητε εἰς πειρασμόν) because, although the spirit is willing, the flesh is weak. Despite His own profound distress, He is concerned about their ability to endure the trial as they had promised. 301

Here also it is once more made clear that for Jesus the necessity of His death is grounded in dogma, not in external historical facts. Above the dogmatic eschatological necessity, however, there stands the omnipotence of God, which is bound by no limitations. As Jesus in the Lord's Prayer had taught His followers to pray for deliverance from the πειρασμός, and as in His fears for the three He bids them pray for the same thing, so now He Himself prays for deliverance, even in this last moment when He knows that the armed band which is coming to arrest Him is already on the way. Literal history does not exist for Him, only the will of God; and this is exalted even above eschatological necessity.

Here, it is once again made clear that for Jesus, the necessity of His death is based on doctrine, not on external historical events. Above this doctrinal eschatological necessity, however, stands the all-powerful nature of God, which is not limited by anything. Just as Jesus taught His followers in the Lord's Prayer to seek deliverance from temptation, and as He encouraged the three to pray for the same, He now prays for deliverance Himself, even in this final moment when He knows the armed group coming to arrest Him is already on its way. For Him, literal history doesn’t exist; only the will of God matters, and this takes precedence even over eschatological necessity.

But how did this exact agreement between the fate of Jesus and His predictions come about? Why did the authorities strike at Him only, not at His whole following, not even at the disciples? [pg 391] He was arrested and condemned on account of His Messianic claims. But how did the High Priest know that Jesus claimed to be the Messiah? And why does he put the accusation as a direct question without calling witnesses in support of it? Why was the attempt first made to bring up a saying about the Temple which could be interpreted as blasphemy in order to condemn Him on this ground (Mark xiv. 57-59)? Before that again, as is evident from Mark's account, they had brought up a whole crowd of witnesses in the hope of securing evidence sufficient to justify His condemnation; and the attempt had not succeeded.

But how did this exact alignment between Jesus' fate and His predictions come about? Why did the authorities target Him specifically, rather than going after His entire following or even the disciples? [pg 391] He was arrested and condemned because of His claims to be the Messiah. But how did the High Priest know that Jesus claimed to be the Messiah? And why does he ask the accusation as a direct question without calling on witnesses to support it? Why was there an initial attempt to reference a statement about the Temple that could be taken as blasphemy to condemn Him on that basis (Mark xiv. 57-59)? Before that, as we can see from Mark's account, they had brought in a whole bunch of witnesses in hopes of gathering enough evidence to justify His condemnation; and that attempt had failed.

It was only after all these attempts had failed that the High Priest brought his accusation concerning the Messianic claim, and he did so without citing the three necessary witnesses. Why so? Because he had not got them. The condemnation of Jesus depended on His own admission. That was why they had endeavoured to convict Him upon other charges.302

It was only after all these attempts had failed that the High Priest brought his accusation about the Messianic claim, and he did this without mentioning the three required witnesses. Why? Because he didn't have them. The conviction of Jesus relied on His own confession. That’s why they tried to find Him guilty on different charges.302

This wholly unintelligible feature of the trial confirms what is evident also from the discourses and attitude of Jesus at Jerusalem, viz. that He had not been held by the multitude to be the Messiah, that the idea of His making such claims had not for a moment occurred to them—lay in fact for them quite beyond the range of possibility. Therefore He cannot have made a Messianic entry.

This completely confusing aspect of the trial confirms what is also clear from Jesus' words and behavior in Jerusalem, namely, that the crowd did not view Him as the Messiah, and the idea that He would claim such a title had never even crossed their minds—it was simply out of the question for them. Therefore, He could not have made a Messianic entry.

According to Havet, Brandt, Wellhausen, Dalman, and Wrede the ovation at the entry had no Messianic character whatever. It is wholly mistaken, as Wrede quite rightly remarks, to represent matters as if the Messianic ovation was forced upon Jesus—that He accepted it with inner repugnance and in silent passivity. For that would involve the supposition that the people had for a moment regarded Him as Messiah and then afterwards had shown themselves as completely without any suspicion of His Messiahship as though they had in the interval drunk of the waters of Lethe. The exact opposite is true: Jesus Himself made the preparations for the Messianic entry. Its Messianic features were due to His arrangements. He made a point of riding upon the ass, not because He was weary, but because He desired that the Messianic prophecy of Zech. ix. 9 should be secretly fulfilled.

According to Havet, Brandt, Wellhausen, Dalman, and Wrede, the uproar at the entrance had no Messianic significance at all. It's completely wrong, as Wrede rightly points out, to portray the situation as if the Messianic celebration was forced on Jesus—that He accepted it with inner discomfort and silent resignation. That would imply that the people briefly saw Him as the Messiah and then later showed themselves completely oblivious to His Messiahship, as if they had drunk from the waters of Lethe in the meantime. The exact opposite is true: Jesus Himself prepared for the Messianic entry. Its Messianic elements were a result of His planning. He intentionally rode on the donkey, not because He was tired, but because He wanted to subtly fulfill the Messianic prophecy of Zech. ix. 9.

The entry is therefore a Messianic act on the part of Jesus, an action in which His consciousness of His office breaks through, as it did at the sending forth of the disciples, in the explanation that [pg 392] the Baptist was Elias, and in the feeding of the multitude. But others can have had no suspicion of the Messianic significance of that which was going on before their eyes. The entry into Jerusalem was therefore Messianic for Jesus, but not Messianic for the people.

The entry was a Messianic act by Jesus, a moment when His awareness of His role came to light, just like when He sent out the disciples, explained that [pg 392] the Baptist was Elijah, and during the feeding of the multitude. However, others likely had no idea of the Messianic meaning of what was happening right in front of them. So, while the entry into Jerusalem was Messianic for Jesus, it wasn’t seen as such by the people.

But what was He for the people? Here Wrede's theory that He was a teacher again refutes itself. In the triumphal entry there is more than the ovation offered to a teacher. The jubilations have reference to “Him who is to come”; it is to Him that the acclamations are offered and because of Him that the people rejoice in the nearness of the Kingdom, as in Mark, the cries of jubilation show; for here, as Dalman rightly remarks, there is actually no mention of the Messiah.

But who was He for the people? Here Wrede's theory that He was a teacher falls apart. In the triumphal entry, there's more than just applause for a teacher. The celebrations are in reference to “The one who is coming”; it's for Him that the cheers are given and because of Him that the people celebrate the coming of the Kingdom, as shown by the joyful shouts in Mark; because here, as Dalman correctly points out, there is no actual mention of the Messiah.

Jesus therefore made His entry into Jerusalem as the Prophet, as Elias. That is confirmed by Matthew (xxi. 11), although Matthew gives a Messianic colouring to the entry itself by bringing in the acclamation in which He was designated the Son of David, just as, conversely, he reports the Baptist's question rightly, and introduces it wrongly, by making the Baptist hear of the “works of the Christ.”

Jesus entered Jerusalem as the Prophet, like Elijah. This is confirmed by Matthew (xxi. 11), although Matthew adds a Messianic touch to the entry by including the cheers where He is called the Son of David. Conversely, he accurately reports the Baptist's question but incorrectly presents it by having the Baptist hear about the “deeds of Christ.”

Was Mark conscious, one wonders, that it was not a Messianic entry that he was reporting? We do not know. It is not inherently impossible that, as Wrede asserts, “he had no real view concerning the historical life of Jesus,” did not know whether Jesus was recognised as Messiah, and took no interest in the question from an historical point of view. Fortunately for us! For that is why he simply hands on tradition and does not write a Life of Jesus.

Was Mark aware, one might wonder, that he wasn't reporting a Messianic entry? We don't know. It's not completely impossible that, as Wrede claims, “he had no genuine perspective on the historical life of Jesus,” was unsure if Jesus was seen as the Messiah, and didn’t care about the question from a historical perspective. Luckily for us! Because that's why he just passes on the tradition and doesn't write a Life of Jesus.

The Marcan hypothesis went astray in conceiving this Gospel as a Life of Jesus written with either complete or partial historical consciousness, and interpreting it on these lines, on the sole ground that it only brings in the name Son of Man twice prior to the incident at Caesarea Philippi. The Life of Jesus cannot be arrived at by following the arrangement of a single Gospel, but only on the basis of the tradition which is preserved more or less faithfully in the earliest pair of Synoptic Gospels.

The Marcan hypothesis missed the mark by viewing this Gospel as a biography of Jesus written with either full or partial awareness of history, and interpreting it this way simply because it mentions the title Son of Man only twice before the event at Caesarea Philippi. We can't fully understand the Life of Jesus by just looking at one Gospel; we need to base our understanding on the tradition that is more or less faithfully preserved in the earliest two Synoptic Gospels.

Questions of literary priority, indeed literary questions in general, have in the last resort, as Keim remarked long ago, nothing to do with the gaining of a clear idea of the course of events, since the Evangelists had not themselves a clear idea of it before their minds; it can only be arrived at hypothetically by an experimental reconstruction based on the necessary inner connexion of the incidents.

Questions about literary importance, and really literary questions overall, ultimately have nothing to do with understanding the sequence of events, as Keim pointed out long ago, since the Evangelists didn’t have a clear understanding of it in their minds either; it can only be achieved hypothetically through an experimental reconstruction based on the necessary connections between the events.

But who could possibly have had in early times a clear conception of the Life of Jesus? Even its most critical moments were totally unintelligible to the disciples who had themselves shared in the experiences, and who were the only sources for the tradition.

But who could have possibly had a clear understanding of the Life of Jesus in early times? Even the most critical moments were completely confusing to the disciples who had lived through those experiences themselves, and they were the only ones providing the tradition.

[pg 393]

They were simply swept through these events by the momentum of the purpose of Jesus. That is why the tradition is incoherent. The reality had been incoherent too, since it was only the secret Messianic self-consciousness of Jesus which created alike the events and their connexion. Every Life of Jesus remains therefore a reconstruction on the basis of a more or less accurate insight into the nature of the dynamic self-consciousness of Jesus which created the history.

They were just carried along by the force of Jesus's mission. That’s why the tradition seems inconsistent. The reality was inconsistent too, since it was only Jesus’s hidden Messianic self-awareness that connected the events. Every account of Jesus's life is therefore a retelling based on a more or less accurate understanding of the dynamic self-awareness of Jesus that shaped history.

The people, whatever Mark may have thought, did not offer Jesus a Messianic ovation at all; it was He who, in the conviction that they were wholly unable to recognise it, played with His Messianic self-consciousness before their eyes, just as He did at the time after the sending forth of the disciples, when, as now, He thought the end at hand. It was in the same way, too, that He closed the invective against the Pharisees with the words “I say unto you, ye shall see me no more until ye shall say, Blessed is he that cometh in the name of the Lord” (Matt. xxiii. 39). This saying implies His Parousia.

The people, no matter what Mark may have thought, did not give Jesus a heroic welcome at all; it was He who, believing they were completely unable to see it, showcased His Messianic identity right in front of them, just like He did after sending out the disciples, when, as now, He believed the end was near. He also concluded His criticism of the Pharisees with the words “I tell you, you won’t see me again until you say, Blessed is he who comes in the name of the Lord.” (Matt. xxiii. 39). This statement hints at His return.

Similarly He is playing with His secret in that crucial question regarding the Messiahship in Mark xii. 35-37. There is no question of dissociating the Davidic Sonship from the Messiahship.303 He asks only how can the Christ in virtue of His descent from David be, as his son, inferior to David, and yet be addressed by David in the Psalm as his Lord? The answer is; by reason of the metamorphosis and Parousia in which natural relationships are abolished and the scion of David's line who is the predestined Son of Man shall take possession of His unique glory.

Similarly, He is playing with His secret in that crucial question about the Messiahship in Mark 12:35-37. There’s no way to separate the Davidic Sonship from the Messiahship.303 He asks how the Christ, because of His descent from David, can be inferior to David as his son, yet still be called Lord by David in the Psalm? The answer is that, due to the transformation and arrival, natural relationships are abolished, and the descendant of David's line, who is the chosen Son of Man, will take possession of His unique glory.

Far from rejecting the Davidic Sonship in this saying, Jesus, on the contrary, presupposes His possession of it. That raises the question whether He did not really during His lifetime regard Himself as a descendant of David and whether He was not regarded as such. Paul, who otherwise shows no interest in the earthly phase of the existence of the Lord, certainly implies His descent from David.

Far from dismissing the idea of being the Son of David in this statement, Jesus actually assumes He has that title. This brings up the question of whether He truly thought of Himself as a descendant of David during His life, and whether others saw Him that way too. Paul, who typically doesn't focus on Jesus' earthly life, definitely suggests His lineage from David.

The blind man at Jericho, too, cries out to the Nazarene prophet as “Son of David” (Mark x. 47). But in doing so he does not mean to address Jesus as Messiah, for afterwards, when he is brought to Him he simply calls Him “Rabbi” (Mark x. 51). And the people thought nothing further about what he had said. When the expectant people bid him keep silence they do not do so because the expression Son of David offends them, but because his clamour annoys them. Jesus, however, was struck by this cry, stood still and caused him, as he was standing timidly behind the [pg 394] eager multitude, to be brought to Him. It is possible, of course, that this address is a mere mistake in the tradition, the same tradition which unsuspectingly brought in the expression Son of Man at the wrong place.

The blind man at Jericho calls out to the Nazarene prophet as "David's Son" (Mark x. 47). However, he doesn’t actually mean to refer to Jesus as the Messiah; when he is brought to Him, he simply calls Him “Rabbi” (Mark x. 51). The people didn’t think much about what he said. When the crowd tells him to be quiet, it’s not because they’re offended by the title Son of David, but because his shouting is bothering them. Jesus, on the other hand, was moved by this cry; He stopped and had the man, who was nervously standing behind the [pg 394] eager crowd, brought to Him. It’s possible that this title is simply a mistake in the tradition, just like how the expression Son of Man was mistakenly included in the wrong context.

So much, however, is certain: the people were not made aware of the Messiahship of Jesus by the cry of the blind man any more than by the outcries of the demoniacs. The entry into Jerusalem was not a Messianic ovation. All that history is concerned with is that this fact should be admitted on all hands. Except Jesus and the disciples, therefore, no one knew the secret of His Messiahship even in those days at Jerusalem. But the High Priest suddenly showed himself in possession of it. How? Through the betrayal of Judas.

So much is clear: the people weren’t made aware of Jesus’ Messiahship by the blind man’s shout any more than by the cries of the demoniacs. The entry into Jerusalem wasn’t a celebration of the Messiah. History only cares that everyone acknowledges this fact. So, except for Jesus and the disciples, no one knew His secret identity as the Messiah even back then in Jerusalem. But the High Priest suddenly revealed that he knew. How? Through Judas’s betrayal.

For a hundred and fifty years the question has been historically discussed why Judas betrayed his Master. That the main question for history was what he betrayed was suspected by few and they touched on it only in a timid kind of way—indeed the problems of the trial of Jesus may be said to have been non-existent for criticism.

For a hundred and fifty years, people have debated why Judas betrayed his Master. However, very few considered the primary question for history to be what he gave up, and those who did only approached it cautiously—truly, the issues surrounding the trial of Jesus have largely been ignored by critics.

The traitorous act of Judas cannot have consisted in informing the Sanhedrin where Jesus was to be found at a suitable place for an arrest. They could have had that information more cheaply by causing Jesus to be watched by spies. But Mark expressly says that Judas when he betrayed Jesus did not yet know of a favourable opportunity for the arrest, but was seeking such an opportunity. Mark xiv. 10, 11, “And Judas Iscariot, one of the twelve, went unto the chief priests, to betray him unto them. And when they heard it, they were glad, and promised to give him money. And he sought how he might conveniently betray him.”

The betrayal by Judas can't just be about telling the Sanhedrin where to find Jesus so they could arrest him. They could have easily gathered that information by sending spies to follow him. However, Mark clearly states that when Judas betrayed Jesus, he didn't know of a good opportunity for the arrest yet; he was looking for one. Mark xiv. 10, 11, "Judas Iscariot, one of the twelve disciples, went to the chief priests to betray Jesus. When they heard this, they were pleased and agreed to pay him money. He looked for a way to betray him effectively."

In the betrayal, therefore, there were two points, a more general and a more special: the general fact by which he gave Jesus into their power, and the undertaking to let them know of the next opportunity when they could arrest Him quietly, without publicity. The betrayal by which he brought his Master to death, in consequence of which the rulers decided upon the arrest, knowing that their cause was safe in any case, was the betrayal of the Messianic secret. Jesus died because two of His disciples had broken His command of silence: Peter when he made known the secret of the Messiahship to the Twelve at Caesarea Philippi; Judas Iscariot by communicating it to the High Priest. But the difficulty was that Judas was the sole witness. Therefore the betrayal was useless so far as the actual trial was concerned unless Jesus admitted the charge. So they first tried to secure His condemnation on other grounds, and only when these attempts broke down did the High Priest put, in the form of a question, the charge in support of which he could have brought no witnesses.

In the betrayal, there were two points: a general one and a specific one. The general fact was that he handed Jesus over to them, and the specific point was his agreement to let them know the next opportunity to arrest Him quietly, without drawing attention. The betrayal that led to his Master's death caused the rulers to decide to arrest Him, knowing their case was solid regardless. This was the betrayal of the Messianic secret. Jesus died because two of His disciples broke His command to stay silent: Peter revealed the secret of His Messiahship to the Twelve at Caesarea Philippi, and Judas Iscariot informed the High Priest. However, the problem was that Judas was the only witness. So, the betrayal didn’t really help in the actual trial unless Jesus confessed to the charges. They first tried to find other reasons to condemn Him, and only when those efforts failed did the High Priest ask the question that he had no witnesses to support.

[pg 395]

But Jesus immediately admitted it, and strengthened the admission by an allusion to His Parousia in the near future as Son of Man.

But Jesus immediately acknowledged it and reinforced His admission by referencing His upcoming arrival as the Son of Man.

The betrayal and the trial can only be rightly understood when it is realised that the public knew nothing whatever of the secret of the Messiahship.304

The betrayal and the trial can only be properly understood when we recognize that the public knew nothing at all about the secret of the Messiahship.304

It is the same in regard to the scene in the presence of Pilate. The people on that morning knew nothing of the trial of Jesus, but came to Pilate with the sole object of asking the release of a prisoner, as was the custom at the feast (Mark xv. 6-8). The idea then occurs to Pilate, who was just about to hand over, willingly enough, this troublesome fellow and prophet to the priestly faction, to play off the people against the priests and work on the multitude to petition for the release of Jesus. In this way he would have secured himself on both sides. He would have condemned Jesus to please the priests, and after condemning Him would have released Him to please the people. The priests are greatly embarrassed by the presence of the multitude. They had done everything so quickly and quietly that they might well have hoped to get Jesus crucified before any one knew what was happening or had had time to wonder at His non-appearance in the Temple.

It’s the same with the scene in front of Pilate. The people that morning knew nothing about Jesus' trial but came to Pilate just to ask for the release of a prisoner, as was the custom during the feast (Mark 15:6-8). Then Pilate came up with the idea to play the people against the priests and get the crowd to ask for Jesus' release. This way, he could cover himself from both sides—he could condemn Jesus to please the priests and then release him afterward to please the people. The priests were really uncomfortable with the crowd around. They had moved so quickly and quietly that they likely hoped to have Jesus crucified before anyone even noticed what was happening or questioned His absence in the Temple.

The priests therefore go among the people and induce them not to agree to the Procurator's proposal. How? By telling them why He was condemned, by revealing to them the Messianic secret. That makes Him at once from a prophet worthy of honour into a deluded enthusiast and blasphemer. That was the explanation of the “fickleness” of the Jerusalem mob which is always so eloquently described, without any evidence for it except this single inexplicable case.

The priests go among the people and encourage them not to support the Procurator's proposal. How? By explaining why He was condemned and revealing the Messianic secret to them. This shifts Him from being a respected prophet to a misguided fanatic and blasphemer. This is the reason behind the so-called "fickleness" of the Jerusalem crowd, which is often described so eloquently, with no evidence for it except this one puzzling incident.

At midday of the same day—it was the 14th Nisan, and in the evening the Paschal lamb would be eaten—Jesus cried aloud and expired. He had chosen to remain fully conscious to the last.

At noon that same day—it was the 14th of Nisan, and in the evening the Passover lamb would be eaten—Jesus shouted and died. He chose to stay completely aware until the end.

[pg 396]

XX. Outcomes

Those who are fond of talking about negative theology can find their account here. There is nothing more negative than the result of the critical study of the Life of Jesus.

Those who enjoy discussing negative theology will find this relevant. There’s nothing more negative than the outcome of the critical examination of the Life of Jesus.

The Jesus of Nazareth who came forward publicly as the Messiah, who preached the ethic of the Kingdom of God, who founded the Kingdom of Heaven upon earth, and died to give His work its final consecration, never had any existence. He is a figure designed by rationalism, endowed with life by liberalism, and clothed by modern theology in an historical garb.

The Jesus of Nazareth who publicly presented himself as the Messiah, preached the ethics of the Kingdom of God, established the Kingdom of Heaven on earth, and died to finalize His mission, never really existed. He is a character created by rationalism, brought to life by liberalism, and dressed in modern theology with a historical appearance.

This image has not been destroyed from without, it has fallen to pieces, cleft and disintegrated by the concrete historical problems which came to the surface one after another, and in spite of all the artifice, art, artificiality, and violence which was applied to them, refused to be planed down to fit the design on which the Jesus of the theology of the last hundred and thirty years had been constructed, and were no sooner covered over than they appeared again in a new form. The thoroughgoing sceptical and the thoroughgoing eschatological school have only completed the work of destruction by linking the problems into a system and so making an end of the Divide et impera of modern theology, which undertook to solve each of them separately, that is, in a less difficult form. Henceforth it is no longer permissible to take one problem out of the series and dispose of it by itself, since the weight of the whole hangs upon each.

This image hasn’t been erased from the outside; it has shattered, split, and crumbled due to the concrete historical problems that surfaced one after another. Despite all the tricks, art, artificiality, and violence used to address them, these issues refused to be smoothed out to fit the design on which the interpretation of Jesus in theology over the last 130 years was based. As soon as they were covered up, they reemerged in a new form. The radical skeptical and the radical eschatological schools have only completed the destruction by linking the problems together into a system, putting an end to the Divide and conquer of modern theology, which tried to solve each issue separately, in a less complicated way. From now on, it is no longer acceptable to take one problem out of the series and address it alone, as the weight of the entire situation depends on each individual issue.

Whatever the ultimate solution may be, the historical Jesus of whom the criticism of the future, taking as its starting-point the problems which have been recognised and admitted, will draw the portrait, can never render modern theology the services which it claimed from its own half-historical, half-modern, Jesus. He will be a Jesus, who was Messiah, and lived as such, either on the ground of a literary fiction of the earliest Evangelist, or on the ground of a purely eschatological Messianic conception.

Whatever the final answer turns out to be, the historical Jesus, whom future criticism will portray based on the problems that have been recognized and accepted, cannot provide modern theology the support it claimed from its own mix of a historical and contemporary Jesus. This Jesus will be one who was the Messiah and lived as such, either based on a literary invention by the earliest Evangelist or on a purely eschatological Messianic idea.

In either case, He will not be a Jesus Christ to whom the [pg 397] religion of the present can ascribe, according to its long-cherished custom, its own thoughts and ideas, as it did with the Jesus of its own making. Nor will He be a figure which can be made by a popular historical treatment so sympathetic and universally intelligible to the multitude. The historical Jesus will be to our time a stranger and an enigma.

In either case, He will not be a Jesus Christ that the [pg 397] religion of today can attribute, according to its long-standing tradition, its own thoughts and ideas, as it did with the Jesus of its own creation. Nor will He be a figure that can be shaped by a mainstream historical interpretation that is so sympathetic and universally understandable to everyone. The historical Jesus will remain a stranger and an enigma in our time.

The study of the Life of Jesus has had a curious history. It set out in quest of the historical Jesus, believing that when it had found Him it could bring Him straight into our time as a Teacher and Saviour. It loosed the bands by which He had been riveted for centuries to the stony rocks of ecclesiastical doctrine, and rejoiced to see life and movement coming into the figure once more, and the historical Jesus advancing, as it seemed, to meet it. But He does not stay; He passes by our time and returns to His own. What surprised and dismayed the theology of the last forty years was that, despite all forced and arbitrary interpretations, it could not keep Him in our time, but had to let Him go. He returned to His own time, not owing to the application of any historical ingenuity, but by the same inevitable necessity by which the liberated pendulum returns to its original position.

The study of the Life of Jesus has had a fascinating journey. It started out seeking the historical Jesus, believing that once it found Him, it could bring Him into our modern world as a Teacher and Savior. It broke the ties that had kept Him bound for centuries to rigid church doctrines and celebrated the renewed life and movement around His figure, as the historical Jesus seemed to step forward to meet it. But He doesn't stay; He moves past our time and goes back to His own. What surprised and troubled theology over the last forty years was that, despite all the forced and arbitrary interpretations, it couldn't keep Him in our era but had to let Him go. He returned to His own time, not because of any clever historical reasoning, but due to the same unavoidable principle that causes a freed pendulum to return to its resting position.

The historical foundation of Christianity as built up by rationalistic, by liberal, and by modern theology no longer exists; but that does not mean that Christianity has lost its historical foundation. The work which historical theology thought itself bound to carry out, and which fell to pieces just as it was nearing completion, was only the brick facing of the real immovable historical foundation which is independent of any historical confirmation or justification.

The historical foundation of Christianity, developed by rationalistic, liberal, and modern theology, is no longer intact; however, that doesn’t mean Christianity has lost its historical foundation. The task that historical theology felt obligated to complete, which fell apart just as it was almost done, was merely the outer layer of the true, enduring historical foundation that exists independently of any historical evidence or validation.

Jesus means something to our world because a mighty spiritual force streams forth from Him and flows through our time also. This fact can neither be shaken nor confirmed by any historical discovery. It is the solid foundation of Christianity.

Jesus holds significance in our world because a powerful spiritual energy radiates from Him and continues to influence our time. This truth cannot be undermined or validated by any historical findings. It is the firm foundation of Christianity.

The mistake was to suppose that Jesus could come to mean more to our time by entering into it as a man like ourselves. That is not possible. First because such a Jesus never existed. Secondly because, although historical knowledge can no doubt introduce greater clearness into an existing spiritual life, it cannot call spiritual life into existence. History can destroy the present; it can reconcile the present with the past; can even to a certain extent transport the present into the past; but to contribute to the making of the present is not given unto it.

The mistake was to think that Jesus could become more relevant to our time by coming into it as a man like us. That’s not possible. First, because such a Jesus never existed. Second, while historical knowledge can certainly bring more clarity to an existing spiritual life, it can't create spiritual life from scratch. History can undermine the present; it can help the present connect with the past; it can even to some extent bring the present into the past; but it cannot help in making the present.

But it is impossible to over-estimate the value of what German research upon the Life of Jesus has accomplished. It is a uniquely great expression of sincerity, one of the most significant events in the whole mental and spiritual life of humanity. What has been done for the religious life of the present and the [pg 398] immediate future by scholars such as P. W. Schmidt, Bousset, Jülicher, Weinel, Wernle—and their pupil Frenssen—and the others who have been called to the task of bringing to the knowledge of wider circles, in a form which is popular without being superficial, the results of religious-historical study, only becomes evident when one examines the literature and social culture of the Latin nations, who have been scarcely if at all touched by the influence of these thinkers.

But it is impossible to overestimate the value of what German research on the Life of Jesus has achieved. It represents a remarkable expression of sincerity, one of the most significant events in the entire mental and spiritual life of humanity. The contributions made for the religious life of today and the [pg 398] immediate future by scholars like P. W. Schmidt, Bousset, Jülicher, Weinel, Wernle—and their student Frenssen—and others tasked with presenting the findings of religious-historical study to a broader audience in a way that is engaging without being shallow, become clear only when we look at the literature and social culture of the Latin nations, which have been barely, if at all, influenced by these thinkers.

And yet the time of doubt was bound to come. We modern theologians are too proud of our historical method, too proud of our historical Jesus, too confident in our belief in the spiritual gains which our historical theology can bring to the world. The thought that we could build up by the increase of historical knowledge a new and vigorous Christianity and set free new spiritual forces, rules us like a fixed idea, and prevents us from seeing that the task which we have grappled with and in some measure discharged is only one of the intellectual preliminaries of the great religious task. We thought that it was for us to lead our time by a roundabout way through the historical Jesus, as we understood Him, in order to bring it to the Jesus who is a spiritual power in the present. This roundabout way has now been closed by genuine history.

And yet, the time of doubt was bound to arrive. We modern theologians are too proud of our historical approach, too proud of our historical Jesus, and too confident in our belief in the spiritual benefits that our historical theology can offer the world. The idea that we could create a new and vibrant Christianity through the accumulation of historical knowledge, unleashing new spiritual forces, dominates our thinking like an obsession and blinds us to the fact that the work we've undertaken and somewhat completed is merely one of the intellectual preliminaries of the larger religious challenge. We believed it was our role to guide our era in a roundabout way through the historical Jesus, as we interpreted Him, to ultimately bring it to the Jesus who represents a spiritual force in the present. That roundabout path has now been blocked by genuine history.

There was a danger of our thrusting ourselves between men and the Gospels, and refusing to leave the individual man alone with the sayings of Jesus.

There was a risk of us stepping in between people and the Gospels, preventing the individual from engaging directly with the teachings of Jesus.

There was a danger that we should offer them a Jesus who was too small, because we had forced Him into conformity with our human standards and human psychology. To see that, one need only read the Lives of Jesus written since the 'sixties, and notice what they have made of the great imperious sayings of the Lord, how they have weakened down His imperative world-contemning demands upon individuals, that He might not come into conflict with our ethical ideals, and might tune His denial of the world to our acceptance of it. Many of the greatest sayings are found lying in a corner like explosive shells from which the charges have been removed. No small portion of elemental religious power needed to be drawn off from His sayings to prevent them from conflicting with our system of religious world-acceptance. We have made Jesus hold another language with our time from that which He really held.

There was a risk that we could present a Jesus who was too limited because we had forced Him to fit our human standards and psychology. To realize this, you only have to read the Lives of Jesus written since the '60s and see how they’ve diluted His powerful teachings, how they’ve softened His strong, world-denying demands on individuals so He wouldn’t clash with our ethical ideals and so His rejection of the world would match our acceptance of it. Many of His greatest sayings are left ignored, like unused explosive shells with the charges removed. A significant amount of the raw religious power needed to be toned down from His words to avoid conflicting with our approach of accepting the world. We’ve made Jesus speak a different language compared to what He truly expressed.

In the process we ourselves have been enfeebled, and have robbed our own thoughts of their vigour in order to project them back into history and make them speak to us out of the past. It is nothing less than a misfortune for modern theology that it mixes history with everything and ends by being proud of the skill with which it finds its own thoughts—even to its beggarly pseudo-metaphysic [pg 399] with which it has banished genuine speculative metaphysic from the sphere of religion—in Jesus, and represents Him as expressing them. It had almost deserved the reproach: “he who putteth his hand to the plough, and looketh back, is not fit for the Kingdom of God.”

In the process, we've made ourselves weaker and stripped our ideas of their strength just to project them back into history and make them speak to us from the past. It's truly unfortunate for modern theology that it mixes history with everything and ends up being proud of how well it finds its own ideas—even to its meager pseudo-metaphysics [pg 399] that has pushed genuine speculative metaphysics out of the realm of religion—in Jesus, and portrays Him as if He is expressing them. It has almost earned the criticism: "Anyone who starts working and keeps looking back isn't fit for the Kingdom of God."

It was no small matter, therefore, that in the course of the critical study of the Life of Jesus, after a resistance lasting for two generations, during which first one expedient was tried and then another, theology was forced by genuine history to begin to doubt the artificial history with which it had thought to give new life to our Christianity, and to yield to the facts, which, as Wrede strikingly said, are sometimes the most radical critics of all. History will force it to find a way to transcend history, and to fight for the lordship and rule of Jesus over this world with weapons tempered in a different forge.

It was significant, therefore, that during the critical examination of the Life of Jesus, after resisting for two generations—during which various strategies were tried—theology was compelled by real history to start questioning the fabricated history it believed would revitalize our Christianity. It had to yield to the facts, which, as Wrede pointedly noted, can sometimes be the most radical critics of all. History will compel it to seek a way to go beyond history and to advocate for the authority and reign of Jesus over this world using tools shaped in a different way.

We are experiencing what Paul experienced. In the very moment when we were coming nearer to the historical Jesus than men had ever come before, and were already stretching out our hands to draw Him into our own time, we have been obliged to give up the attempt and acknowledge our failure in that paradoxical saying: “If we have known Christ after the flesh yet henceforth know we Him no more.” And further we must be prepared to find that the historical knowledge of the personality and life of Jesus will not be a help, but perhaps even an offence to religion.

We are experiencing what Paul went through. At the moment when we were getting closer to the historical Jesus than anyone ever had before, and were already reaching out to bring Him into our present, we were forced to abandon the effort and admit our failure in that paradoxical statement: "If we used to know Christ in a physical way, we won't know Him like that anymore." Moreover, we need to be ready to realize that knowing the historical facts about Jesus' personality and life won’t actually help; it might even be a hindrance to faith.

But the truth is, it is not Jesus as historically known, but Jesus as spiritually arisen within men, who is significant for our time and can help it. Not the historical Jesus, but the spirit which goes forth from Him and in the spirits of men strives for new influence and rule, is that which overcomes the world.

But the truth is, it’s not the historical Jesus that matters, but the spiritually awakened Jesus within people that is important for our time and can make a difference. It’s not the historical figure of Jesus, but the spirit that comes from Him and strives for new influence and authority within the hearts of people that ultimately conquers the world.

It is not given to history to disengage that which is abiding and eternal in the being of Jesus from the historical forms in which it worked itself out, and to introduce it into our world as a living influence. It has toiled in vain at this undertaking. As a water-plant is beautiful so long as it is growing in the water, but once torn from its roots, withers and becomes unrecognisable, so it is with the historical Jesus when He is wrenched loose from the soil of eschatology, and the attempt is made to conceive Him “historically” as a Being not subject to temporal conditions. The abiding and eternal in Jesus is absolutely independent of historical knowledge and can only be understood by contact with His spirit which is still at work in the world. In proportion as we have the Spirit of Jesus we have the true knowledge of Jesus.

History cannot separate what is lasting and eternal in the essence of Jesus from the historical forms in which it manifested, and bring it into our world as a living influence. This effort has been in vain. Just as an aquatic plant looks beautiful while it's thriving in water, but withers and becomes unrecognizable once it’s pulled from its roots, so too does the historical Jesus lose significance when detached from the context of eschatology, and attempts to perceive Him “historically” as an entity unbound by temporal conditions fall short. The lasting and eternal aspects of Jesus stand entirely apart from historical knowledge and can only be understood through an engagement with His spirit, which is still active in the world. The more we embody the Spirit of Jesus, the more we attain genuine knowledge of Him.

Jesus as a concrete historical personality remains a stranger to our time, but His spirit, which lies hidden in His words, is known in simplicity, and its influence is direct. Every saying contains in its own way the whole Jesus. The very strangeness and [pg 400] unconditionedness in which He stands before us makes it easier for individuals to find their own personal standpoint in regard to Him.

Jesus, as a real historical figure, feels distant in our time, but His spirit, which is revealed in His words, is understood simply, and its impact is immediate. Each saying somehow encompasses the entirety of Jesus. The very unfamiliarity and unconditional nature with which He presents Himself make it easier for people to establish their own personal views about Him.

Men feared that to admit the claims of eschatology would abolish the significance of His words for our time; and hence there was a feverish eagerness to discover in them any elements that might be considered not eschatologically conditioned. When any sayings were found of which the wording did not absolutely imply an eschatological connexion there was great jubilation—these at least had been saved uninjured from the coming débâcle.

Men were worried that accepting eschatological claims would undermine the relevance of His words for today; therefore, there was a frantic desire to find any elements in them that could be seen as unrelated to eschatology. When any sayings were discovered that didn't clearly indicate an eschatological connection, there was much celebration—at least these had been preserved intact from the impending debacle.

But in reality that which is eternal in the words of Jesus is due to the very fact that they are based on an eschatological world-view, and contain the expression of a mind for which the contemporary world with its historical and social circumstances no longer had any existence. They are appropriate, therefore, to any world, for in every world they raise the man who dares to meet their challenge, and does not turn and twist them into meaninglessness, above his world and his time, making him inwardly free, so that he is fitted to be, in his own world and in his own time, a simple channel of the power of Jesus.

But in reality, what makes Jesus's words eternal comes from their foundation in an eschatological worldview. They reflect a mindset that sees the contemporary world, with all its historical and social circumstances, as irrelevant. Because of this, these words are relevant to any era. They elevate anyone who bravely faces their challenge and doesn't distort them into meaninglessness, lifting them above their own world and time. This makes them inwardly free, enabling them to be, in their own world and time, a straightforward channel for the power of Jesus.

Modern Lives of Jesus are too general in their scope. They aim at influencing, by giving a complete impression of the life of Jesus, a whole community. But the historical Jesus, as He is depicted in the Gospels, influenced individuals by the individual word. They understood Him so far as it was necessary for them to understand, without forming any conception of His life as a whole, since this in its ultimate aims remained a mystery even for the disciples.

Modern accounts of Jesus are too broad in their perspective. They try to shape the beliefs of entire communities by providing a full picture of His life. However, the historical Jesus, as described in the Gospels, affected individuals through personal interactions and teachings. Each person grasped His message to the extent they needed, without forming a complete understanding of His life as a whole, which ultimately remained a mystery even for His disciples.

Because it is thus preoccupied with the general, the universal, modern theology is determined to find its world-accepting ethic in the teaching of Jesus. Therein lies its weakness. The world affirms itself automatically; the modern spirit cannot but affirm it. But why on that account abolish the conflict between modern life, with the world-affirming spirit which inspires it as a whole, and the world-negating spirit of Jesus? Why spare the spirit of the individual man its appointed task of fighting its way through the world-negation of Jesus, of contending with Him at every step over the value of material and intellectual goods—a conflict in which it may never rest? For the general, for the institutions of society, the rule is: affirmation of the world, in conscious opposition to the view of Jesus, on the ground that the world has affirmed itself! This general affirmation of the world, however, if it is to be Christian, must in the individual spirit be Christianised and transfigured by the personal rejection of the world which is preached in the sayings of Jesus. It is only by means of the tension thus set up that religious energy can be communicated to our time. There [pg 401] was a danger that modern theology, for the sake of peace, would deny the world-negation in the sayings of Jesus, with which Protestantism was out of sympathy, and thus unstring the bow and make Protestantism a mere sociological instead of a religious force. There was perhaps also a danger of inward insincerity, in the fact that it refused to admit to itself and others that it maintained its affirmation of the world in opposition to the sayings of Jesus, simply because it could not do otherwise.

Because it is focused on the general and the universal, modern theology aims to find its world-accepting ethics in the teachings of Jesus. This is where its weakness lies. The world automatically affirms itself; the modern spirit cannot help but agree with it. But why, because of this, remove the conflict between modern life, with its world-affirming spirit, and the world-negating spirit of Jesus? Why deny individuals the necessary challenge of working through Jesus' world-negation, engaging with Him continuously about the value of material and intellectual goods—a struggle that can never be fully settled? For society and its institutions, the rule is: a positive affirmation of the world, consciously opposing Jesus' perspective, based on the idea that the world has already affirmed itself! However, for this general affirmation of the world to be Christian, it must be personalized and transformed in the individual spirit through the personal rejection of the world that Jesus' teachings promote. Only through this created tension can religious energy be communicated to our time. There was a risk that modern theology, in pursuit of harmony, would deny Jesus' world-negation—something Protestantism was not aligned with—and thus weaken its impact, turning Protestantism from a religious force into merely a sociological one. There might also have been a danger of inner dishonesty, as it refused to acknowledge to itself and others that it maintained its world-affirming stance in contradiction to Jesus' words, simply because it felt it had no other choice.

For that reason it is a good thing that the true historical Jesus should overthrow the modern Jesus, should rise up against the modern spirit and send upon earth, not peace, but a sword. He was not teacher, not a casuist; He was an imperious ruler. It was because He was so in His inmost being that He could think of Himself as the Son of Man. That was only the temporally conditioned expression of the fact that He was an authoritative ruler. The names in which men expressed their recognition of Him as such, Messiah, Son of Man, Son of God, have become for us historical parables. We can find no designation which expresses what He is for us.

For that reason, it is a good thing for the real historical Jesus to challenge the modern Jesus, to rise against the modern mindset and bring not peace to the earth, but a sword. He was not a teacher, nor was He a mere philosopher; He was a commanding leader. It was because He was so at His core that He could see Himself as the Son of Man. That was just a temporary way of expressing the fact that He was an authoritative ruler. The titles that people used to show their acknowledgment of Him, like Messiah, Son of Man, and Son of God, have become historical symbols for us. We can't find a label that truly captures what He means to us.

He comes to us as One unknown, without a name, as of old, by the lake-side, He came to those men who knew Him not. He speaks to us the same word: “Follow thou me!” and sets us to the tasks which He has to fulfil for our time. He commands. And to those who obey Him, whether they be wise or simple, He will reveal Himself in the toils, the conflicts, the sufferings which they shall pass through in His fellowship, and, as an ineffable mystery, they shall learn in their own experience Who He is.

He comes to us as someone unknown, without a name, just like in the past, by the lake, He came to those men who didn’t recognize Him. He speaks to us the same message: "Come with me!" and assigns us the tasks He needs us to do for our time. He commands. And to those who obey Him, whether they are wise or simple, He will reveal Himself in the struggles, conflicts, and sufferings they will go through in His companionship, and, as an indescribable mystery, they will learn through their own experiences Who He is.

[pg 403]

Authors and Works Index

(Including Reference To English Translations)

Including Reference to English Translations

Ammon, Christoph Friedrich von. Fortbildung des Christentums (Leipzig, 1840);
Die Geschichte des Lebens Jesu mit steter Rücksicht auf die vorhandenen Quellen (1842-1847), 11, 97, 104 f., 117 f.
Anonymous Works—
Das Leben Napoleons kritisch geprüft. Aus dem Englischen (see under Whateley) nebst einigen Nutzanwendungen auf das Leben-Jesu von Strauss (1836), 112
Did Jesus live 100 b.c.? (London and Benares, Theosophical Publishing Society, 1903), 327
Dr. Strauss und die Züricher Kirche (Basle, 1839), 103
Wichtige Enthüllungen über die wirkliche Todesart Jesu (5th ed., Leipzig, 1849);
Historische Enthüllungen über die wirklichen Ereignisse der Geburt und Jugend Jesu (2nd ed., Leipzig, 1849), 161 f.
Zwei Gespräche über die Ansicht des Herrn Dr. Strauss von der evangelischen Geschichte (Jena, 1839), 100
Baader, Franz. Über das Leben-Jesu von Strauss (Munich, 1836), 100
Bahrdt, Karl Friedrich. Briefe über die Bibel im Volkston (1782);
Ausführung des Plans und Zwecks Jesu (1784-1792);
Die sämtlichen Reden Jesu aus den Evangelien ausgezogen (1786), 4, 5, 38, 39 f., 46, 53, 59, 299, 313
Baldensperger, Wilhelm. Das Selbstbewusstsein Jesu im Lichte der messianischen Hoffnungen seiner Zeit (Strassburg, 1888, 2nd ed. 1892, 3rd ed. pt. i. 1903), 12, 233-237, 250, 266, 278 f., 365, 366
Barth, Fritz. Die Hauptprobleme des Lebens Jesu (1st ed. 1899, 2nd ed. 1903), 301
Bauer, Bruno. Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte des Johannes (Bremen, 1840);
Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte der Synoptiker (Leipzig, 1841-1842);
Kritik der Evangelien und Geschichte ihres Ursprungs (Berlin, 1850-1851);
Kritik der Apostelgeschichte (1850);
Kritik der Paulinischen Briefe (Berlin, 1850-1852);
Philo, Strauss, Renan und das Urchristentum (Berlin, 1874);
Christus und die Cäsaren (Berlin, 1877);
Die gute Sache der Freiheit und meine eigene Angelegenheit (Zurich, 1843), 5, 9, 10, 12, 137-160, 186 f., 221, 231, 256-258, 305 f., 312, 315, 328, 332, 335 f., 338, 342, 346, 358, 368, 388
Baumer, Friedrich. Schwarz, Strauss, Renan (Leipzig, 1864), 191
Baur, Ferdinand Christian. Kritische Untersuchungen über die kanonischen Evangelien (Tübingen, 1847), 25, 58, 68, 87, 89, 124, 182, 195, 201, 229
Bergh van Eysinga, Van den. Indische Einflüsse auf evangelische Erzählungen (Göttingen, 1904), 290
Bernhard ter Haar (Utrecht). Zehn Vorlesungen über Renans "Life of Jesus" (German by H. Doermer, Gotha, 1864), 191
Beyschlag, Willibald. Über das Leben-Jesu von Renan (Berlin, 1864);
Das Leben-Jesu (pt. i. 1885, pt. ii. 1886, 2nd ed. 1887-1888), 6, 10, 190, 215 f., 218
Binder, 68, 69
Bleby, H. W. The Trial of Jesus of Nazareth considered as a Judicial Act (1880), 391
Bleek, 229, 231
[pg 404]
Böklen, E. Die Verwandtschaft der jüdisch-christlichen und der parsischen Eschatologie (1902), 287
Bolten, Johann Adrian. Der Bericht des Matthäus von Jesu dem Messias (Altona, 1792), 271, 276
Bosc, Ernest. La Vie ésotérique de Jésus de Nazareth et les origines orientales du christianisme (Paris, 1902), 294, 327
Bousset, Wilhelm. Jesu Predigt in ihrem Gegensatz zum Judentum. Ein religionsgeschichtlicher Vergleich (Göttingen, 1892);
Die jüdische Apokalyptik in ihrer religionsgeschichtlichen Herkunft und ihrer Bedeutung für das Neue Testament (Berlin, 1903);
Die Religion des Judentums im neutestamentlichen Zeitalter (1902);
Was wissen wir von Jesus? Vorträge im Protestantenverein zu Bremen (Halle, 1904);
Jesus (Religionsgeschichtliche Volksbücher, herausgegeben von Schiele, Halle, 1904) (English translation, Jesus, by J. P. Trevelyan, London, 1906), 241-249, 255 f., 262, 264, 267, 280, 300, 359, 398
Brandt, Wilhelm. Die evangelische Geschichte und der Ursprung des Christentums auf Grund einer Kritik der Berichte über das Leiden und die Auferstehung Jesu (Leipzig, 1893), 241, 256-261, 267, 301, 309, 312, 313, 391
Bretschneider, Karl Gottlob, 85, 118
Brunner, Sebastian. Der Atheist Renan und sein Evangelium (Regensburg, 1864), 190
Bugge, Chr. A. Die Hauptparabeln Jesu. (From the Norwegian) (Giessen, 1903), 263
Bunsen, Christian Karl Josias, Ritter von. Das Leben Jesu, vol. ix. of Bunsen's “Bible study” (published by Holtzmann, 1865), 200
Cairns, John. Falsche Christi und der wahre Christus, oder Verteidigung der evangelischen Geschichte gegen Strauss und Renan. Aus dem Englischen übersetzt (Hamburg, 1864) (Fake Christ and the Real, A sermon delivered before the National Bible Society of Scotland, Edinburgh, 1864), 191
Capitaine, W. Jesus von Nazareth (Regensburg, 1905), 294
Cassel, Paulus. Bericht über Renans Leben-Jesu (Berlin, 1864), 191
"Casuar." Das Leben Luthers kritisch bearbeitet. Herausgegeben von Jul. Ferd. Wurm ("Mexico, 2836"), 112
Chamberlain, H. S. Worte Christi (1901), 310
Charles, R. H. “The Son of Man” (Expos. Times, 1893), 267
Colani, Timothée. Examen de la vie de Jésus de M. Renan (Strassburg, 1864);
Jésus-Christ et les croyances messianiques de son temps (Strassburg, 1864), 182, 189, 209, 221 f., 226, 229, 233, 248, 372
Cone, Orello. “Jesus' Self-Identification in the Synoptic Gospels” (The New World, 1893), 266
Coquerel, Athanase (jun.), 189, 209
Credner, 89
Dalman, Gustaf. Grammatik des jüdisch-palästinensischen Aramäisch (Leipzig, 1894);
Die Worte Jesu. Mit Berücksichtigung des nachkanonischen Schrifttums und der aramäischen Sprache, I. (Leipzig, 1898) (authorised English translation by D. M. Kay, *The Sayings of Jesus*, Edinburgh, 1902), 269, 271, 273-275, 278, 279-281, 286-289, 363, 391 f.
Darboy, Georges. Lettre pastorale de Monseigneur l'Archevêque de Paris sur la divinité de Jésus-Christ, et mandement pour le carême de 1864, 188
Delff, Hugo. Geschichte des Rabbi Jesus von Nazareth (Leipzig, 1889), 11, 323
Delitzsch, Franz, 273, 285
Deutlinger, Martin. Renan und das Wunder. Ein Beitrag zur christlichen Apologetik (Munich, 1864), 190
Didon, Le Père, de l'ordre des frères prêcheurs. Jésus Christ (Paris, 1891, 2 vols., German, 1895) (English translation, Jesus Christ, 2 vols., 1891), 295
Dieu, Louis de, 14
Dillmann, 223
Diodati, Dominicus, 271
Döderlein. Fragmente und Antifragmente (Nuremberg, 1778), 25
Dulk, Albert. Der Irrgang des Lebens Jesu. In geschichtlicher Auffassung dargestellt (pt. i. 1884, pt. ii. 1885), 294, 324
Dupanloup, Félix Antoine Philibert, Évêque d'Orléans. Avertissement à la jeunesse et aux pères de famille sur les attaques dirigées contre la religion par quelques écrivains de nos jours (Paris, 1864), 188
Ebrard, August. Wissenschaftliche Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte (Frankfort, 1842), 97, 116 f.
[pg 405]
Edersheim, Alfred. The Life and Times of Jesus the Messiah (London, 1st ed. 1883, 3rd ed. 1886, 2 vols.), 233
Eerdmanns, B. E. “The Origin of the expression 'Son of Man' as an evangelical Messiah title” (Theol. Tijdschr., 1894), 276
Ehrhardt. Der Grundcharakter der Ethik Jesu in Verhältnis zu den messianischen Hoffnungen seines Volkes und zu seinem eigenen Messiasbewusstsein (Freiburg, 1895);
Le Principe de la morale de Jésus (Paris, 1896), 249
Eichhorn, Johann Gottfried, 78, 89
Emmerich, Anna Katharina. Das bittere Leiden unseres Herrn Jesu Christi. Herausgegeben von Brentano (1858-1860, new ed. 1895) (English translation, The Sorrowful Passion of Our Lord Jesus Christ, London, 1862);
Das Leben Jesu, 3 vols. (1858-1860), 109 f., 295
Ewald, Georg Heinrich August. "History of Christ and his era," vol. v. of the “History of the People of Israel” (Göttingen, 1855, 2nd ed. 1857), English translation of the The Life of Jesus, by Octavius Glover (London, 1865);
Die drei ersten Evangelien (1850), 97, 117, 124, 135
Fiebig, Paul. Der Menschensohn (Tübingen, 1901);
Altjüdische Gleichnisse und die Gleichnisse Jesu (Tübingen, 1904), 278, 286
Frantzen, Wilhelm. Die “Jesus Life” Bewegung seit Strauss (Dorpat, 1898), 12
Frenssen, Gustav. Hilligenlei (Berlin, 1905), pp. 462-593: “Die Handschrift” (English translation, Holy Land, by M. A. Hamilton, London, 1906), 293, 307-309, 398
Freppel, Charles Emile. Examen critique de la vie de Jesus de M. Renan (Paris, 1864) (German by Kollmus, Vienna, 1864), 188, 190
Frick, Otto. Mythus und Evangelium (Heilbronn, 1879), 112
Furrer, Konrad. Vorträge über das Leben Jesu Christi (1902), 301
Gabler, 78
Gardner, P. Exploratio Evangelica. A Brief Examination of the Basis and Origin of Christian Belief (1899, 2nd ed. 1907), 217
Gerlach, Hermann. Gegen Renans Leben-Jesu 1864 (Berlin), 191
Gfrörer, August Friedrich. Kritische Geschichte des Urchristentums (vol. i. 1st ed. 1831, 2nd ed. 1835, vol. ii. 1838), 161, 163-166, 195
Ghillany, Friedrich Wilhelm (“Richard von der Alm”). Theologische Briefe an die Gebildeten der deutschen Nation (3 vols. 1863);
Die Urteile heidnischer und christlicher Schriftsteller der vier ersten christlichen Jahrhunderte über Jesus (1864), 161, 166-172, 240, 363
Godet, F. Das Leben Jesu vor seinem öffentlichen Auftreten (German by M. Reineck, Hanover, 1897), 217
Gratz, 89
Greiling. Das Leben Jesu von Nazareth (1813), 50
Gressman, Hugo, 234
Griesbach, Johann Jakob, 13, 89
Grimm, Eduard. Die Ethik Jesu (Hamburg, 1903), 320
Grimm, Joseph. Das Leben Jesu (Würzburg, 6 vols., 2nd ed. 1890-1903), 294
Grotius, Hugo, 270
Gunkel, Hermann, 277
Hagel, Maurus. Dr. Strauss' Leben-Jesu aus dens Standpunkt des Katholicismus betrachtet (1839), 108
Hahn, Werner. Leben-Jesu (Berlin, 1844), 118
Haneberg, Daniel Bonifacius. Ernest Renans Leben-Jesu (Regensburg, 1864), 190
Hanson, Sir Richard. The Jesus of History (1869), 202
Harless, Adolf. Die kritische Bearbeitung des Lebens Jesu von David Friedrich Strauss nach ihrem wissenschaftlichen Werte beleuchtet (Erlangen, 1836), 98 f.
Harnack, Adolf, 242, 252, 314
Hartmann, Eduard von. Das Christentum des Neuen Testaments, 2nd ed. of the "Letters on the Christian Faith" (Sachsa-in-the-Harz, 1905), 292, 318-320
Hartmann, Julius. Leben Jesu (2 vols., 1837-1839), 101
Hase, Karl August von. Das Leben Jesu (1st ed. 1829);
Geschichte Jesu (Leipzig, 1876), 4, 5, 10, 11, 12, 28, 58 f., 65, 72, 81, 88, 99, 106, 116, 120, 162, 193, 214 f., 218, 220, 229
Haupt, Erich. Die eschatologischen Aussagen Jesu in den synoptischen Evangelien (1895), 241, 250 f.
Hausrath, Adolf. Neutestamentliche Zeitgeschichte (1st ed., Munich, 1868 ff., 3rd ed., vol. i. 1879) (English translation, A History of the [pg 406]New Testament Times, The Time of Jesus, by C. T. Poynting and P. Quenzer, London, 1878), 214
Havet, Ernest. Jésus dans l'histoire. Examen de la vie de Jésus par M. Renan. Extrait de la Revue des deux mondes (Paris, 1863);
Le Christianisme et ses origines, 3me ptie, Le Nouveau Testament (1884), 189, 290, 328, 391
Hegel, Georg Friedrich Wilhelm, 49, 68 f., 79 f., 107, 111, 114 f., 122, 137, 163, 165, 194
Hengstenberg, Ernst Wilhelm, 106 f., 111, 115, 143
Hennell, Charles Christian. An Inquiry concerning the Origin of Christianity (London, 1838) (Untersuchungen über den Ursprung des Christentums. Vorrede von David Friedrich Strauss, 1840), 161
Herder, Johann Gottfried. Vom Erlöser der Menschen. Nach unsern drei ersten Evangelien (1796);
Von Gottes Sohn, der Welt Heiland. Nach Johannes Evangelium (1797), 27, 29, 34, 89, 203
Hess, Johann Jakob. Geschichte der drei letzten Lebensjahre Jesu (1768 ff.), 4, 14, 27-31
Hilgenfeld, Adolf, 124, 222, 266
Hoekstra. "The Christology of the canonical Gospel of Mark, compared to that of the other two synoptic Gospels." (Theol. Tijdschrift, v., 1871), 328
Hoffmann, Wilhelm. Das Leben-Jesu kritisch bearbeitet von Dr. David Fried. Strauss. Geprüft für Theologen und Nicht-Theologen (1836), 99
Holtzmann, Heinrich Julius, 10, 61, 125, 195, 200, 202-205, 209, 218, 220, 229, 231, 235, 237, 277, 294
Holtzmann, Oskar. Das Leben Jesu, (1901) (English translation, The Life of Jesus, by J. T. Bealby and Maurice A. Canney, London, 1904);
Das Messianitätsbewusstsein Jesu und seine neueste Bestreitung. Vortrag (1902);
War Jesus Ekstatiker? (Tübingen, 1903), 208, 293, 295-300, 306 f., 308, 312, 359
Hug, Leonhard. Gutachten über das Leben-Jesu, kritisch bearbeitet von D. Fr. Strauss (Freiburg, 1840), 97, 108, 109, 271
Ingraham, J. H. The Prince of the House of David (London, 1859) (Der Fürst aus Davids Hause, new ed., 1896, Brunswick), 326
Inchofer, 270
Issel, 237
Jacobi, Johann Adolf. Die Geschichte Jesu für denkende und gemütvolle Leser (1816), 27, 34
Jonge, De. Jeschua. Der klassische jüdische Mann. Zerstörung des kirchlichen, Enthüllung des jüdischen Jesus-Bildes (Berlin, 1904), 293, 321 f.
Jülicher, Adolf. Die Gleichnisreden Jesu (pt. i. 1888, pt. ii. 1899);
Die Kultur der Gegenwart (Teubner, Berlin, 1905), pp. 40-69;
"OMG," 241, 262-264, 286, 290, 320, 398
Kalthoff, Albert. Das Christus-Problem. Grundlinien zu einer Sozialtheologie (Leipzig, 1902);
Die Entstehung des Christentums. Neue Beiträge zum Christus-Problem (Leipzig, 1904) (English translation, *The Rise of Christianity*, by Joseph M'Cabe, London, 1907);
Das Leben Jesu. Reden gehalten im prot. Reformverein zu Berlin (1880);
Was wissen wir von Jesus? Eine Abrechnung mit Professor Bousset in Göttingen (Berlin, 1904), 293, 314-318
Kant, Emmanuel, 50, 105, 322
Kapp, W. Das Christus-und Christentum-Problem bei Kalthoff (Strassburg, 1905), 318
Kautzsch, Emil Friedrich, 271
Keim, Theodor. Die Geschichte Jesu von Nazara (3 vols., Zurich, pt. i. 1867, pt. ii. 1871, pt. iii. 1872);
Die Geschichte Jesu. Nach den Ergebnissen heutiger Wissenschaft für weitere Kreise übersichtlich erzählt (Zurich, 1872) (English translation of the larger work, The History of Jesus of Nazareth, by E. M. Geldart and A. Ransom, 6 vols., London, 1873-1883), 11, 61, 193, 200, 209, 211-214, 231 f., 310, 343, 351, 357, 380, 392
Kienlen, 228
Kirchbach, Wolfgang. Was lehrte Jesus? (Berlin, 1897, 2nd ed. 1902);
Das Buch Jesus (Berlin, 1897), 294, 322-324
Koppe, 89
Köstlin, Karl Reinhold, 124
Krabbe. Vorlesungen über das Leben Jesu für Theologen und Nicht-Theologen (Hamburg, 1839), 100
Kralik, Richard von. Jesu Leben und Werk (Kempten-Nürnberg, 1904), 294
Krauss, S. Das Leben Jesu nach jüdischen Quellen (1902), 327
[pg 407]
Krüger-Velthusen, W. Leben Jesu. (Elberfeld, 1872), 217
Kuhn, Johannes von. Leben Jesu (Tübingen, 1840), 108
Kunz, K. Christus medicus (Freiburg, 1905), 325
Lachmann, 89
Lamy. Renans Leben-Jesu vor dem Richterstuhle der Kritik. Übersetzt von Aug. Rohling (Münster, 1864), 190
Lange, Johann Peter. Das Leben Jesu, 5 vols. (1844-1847) (English translation, The Life of the Lord Jesus Christ, by Sophia Taylor, Edinburgh, 1864), 117
Längin, G. Der Christus der Geschichte und sein Christentum (2 vols., 1897-1898), 217
Langsdorf, Karl von. Wohlgeprüfte Darstellung des Lebens Jesu (Mannheim, 1831), 162
Lasserre, Henri. L'Évangile selon Renan (1864, 12 editions, German, Munich, 1864), 188, 190
Lehmann. Renan wider Renan (Zwickau, 1864), 191
Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, 5, 14-16, 75
Levi, Giuseppe. Parabeln, Legenden und Gedanken aus Talmud und Midrasch (2nd ed., Leipzig, 1877), 286
Lichtenstein, Wilhelm Jakob. Leben des Herrn Jesu Christi (Erlangen, 1856), 101
Lietzmann, Hans. Der Menschensohn (Freiburg, 1896);
Zur Menschensohnfrage (1898), 265, 276 f., 285, 289
Lightfoot, John. Horae Hebraicae et Talmudicae in quatuor Evangelistas. Herausgegeben von J. B. Carpzov (Leipzig, 1684), 222, 285
Lillie, A. The Influence of Buddhism on Primitive Christianity (London, 1893), 326
Littré, M., 181
Loisy, Alfred. Le Quatrième Évangile (Paris, 1903);
Les Évangiles synoptiques, 2 vols. (Paris, 1907);
L'Évangile et l'Église (Paris, 1903) (translated by C. Home, The Gospel and the Church, new ed. with a preface by G. Tyrrell, 1908), 295
Lücke, 106
Luthardt, Christoph Ernst. Die modernen Darstellungen des Lebens Jesu. Vortrag (Leipzig, 1864), 191, 209
Luther, 13
Mack, Joseph. Bericht über des Herrn Dr. Strauss' historische Bearbeitung des Lebens Jesu (1837), 108
Manen, van, 286
Marius, Emmanuel. Die Persönlichkeit Jesu mit besonderer Rücksicht auf die Mythologien und Mysterien der alten Völker (Leipzig, 1879), 112
Meinhold, J. Jesus und das Alte Testament (1896), 255
Meuschen, Johann Gerhardt, 285
Meyer, Arnold. Jesu Muttersprache (Leipzig, 1896), 229, 231, 265, 269, 271, 274, 276, 286, 287, 289
Michaelis, 49, 271
Michelis. Renans Roman vom Leben-Jesu (Münster, 1864), 190
Müller, A. Jesus ein Arier (Leipzig, 1904), 327
Müller, Max, 290
Mussard, Eugène. Du système mythique appliqué à l'histoire de la vie de Jésus (1838), 112
Nahor, Pierre (Émilie Lerou), Jésus. (German by Walther Bloch, Berlin, 1905), 325
Neander, August Wilhelm. Das Leben Jesu Christi (Hamburg, 1837) (English translation, *The Life of Jesus Christ*, by J. M'Clintock and C. E. Blumenthal, London, 1851);
Gutachten über das Buch des Dr. Strauss', Leben-Jesu (1836), 72, 97, 101-103, 116, 139
Nestle, 276
Neubauer, Adolf, 273
Neumann, Arno. Jesus wie er geschichtlich war (Freiburg, 1904), 320
Nicolas, Amadée. Renan et sa vie de Jésus sous les rapports moral, légal et littéraire (Paris-Marseille, 1864), 188
Nippold, Friedrich. Der Entwicklungsgang des Lebens Jesu im Wortlaut der drei ersten Evangelien (Hamburg, 1895);
Die psychiatrische Seite der Heilstätigkeit Jesu (1889), 301, 324
Noack, Ludwig. Die Geschichte Jesu (2nd ed., Mannheim, 1876);
Aus der Jordanwiege nach Golgatha (1870-1871), 161 f., 172-179, 185, 322
Nork, J., 285, 286
Notowitsch, Nicolas. La Vie inconnue de Jésus-Christ (Paris, 1894) (German, Stuttgart, 1894), 290, 326
Oort, H. L. Die Uitdrukking ὁ υἱὸς τοῦ ἀνθρώπου in het Nieuwe Testament (Leiden, 1893), 266, 278, 286
Opitz, Ernst August. Geschichte und Characterzüge Jesu (1812), 27, 34
[pg 408]
Osiander, Andreas, 13
Osiander, Johann Ernst. Apologie des Lebens Jesu gegenüber dem neuesten Versuch, es in Mythen aufzulösen (1837), 100
Osterzee, J. J. van (Utrecht). Geschichte oder Roman? Das Leben-Jesu von Ernest Renan vorläufig beleuchtet. (From the Dutch) (Hamburg, 1864), 191
Otto, Rudolf. Leben und Wirken Jesu nach historisch-kritischer Auffassung. Vortrag (Göttingen, 1902), 301
Paul, Ludwig. Die Vorstellung vom Messias und vom Gottesreich bei den Synoptikern (Bonn, 1895), 265
Paulus, Heinrich Eberhard Gottlob. Das Leben Jesu als Grundlage einer reinen Geschichte des Urchristentums (1828), 4, 28, 37, 48 f., 104, 271, 276, 303
Pfleiderer, Otto. Das Urchristentum, seine Schriften und Lehren in geschichtlichem Zusammenhang beschrieben (2nd ed., Berlin, 1902, 2 vols.) (English translation, Early Christianity, vols. i. and ii. (vol. i. of original), London, 1906, 1909);
Die Entstehung des Urchristentums (Munich, 1905) (English translation, Christian Origins, by D. A. Huebsch, London, 1905), 229, 293, 309, 311-313, 384
Plank. Geschichte des Christentums (Göttingen, 1818), 34
Pressel, Theodor. Leben Jesu Christi (1857), 101
Pressensé, Edmond Dehoult de. Jésus-Christ, son temps, sa vie, son œuvre (Paris, 1865) (English translation, Jesus Christ, His Era, His Life, His Contributions, by A. Harwood, 3rd ed., London, 1869);
L'École critique et Jésus-Christ, à propos de la vie de Jésus de M. Renan, 180, 189
Quinet, Edgar, 108
Rauch, C. Jeschua ben Joseph (Deichert, 1899), 326
Régla, Paul de. Jesus von Nazareth, (German by A. Just, Leipzig, 1894), 294, 325
Reimarus, Hermann Samuel. Von dem Zwecke Jesu und seiner Jünger (published by Lessing, Brunswick, 1778) (English translation, The Purpose of Jesus and His Disciples, as Seen in the New Testament, edited by A. Voysey, 1879), 4, 9, 10, 13-26, 75, 94, 107, 120, 159, 166, 172, 221, 239, 264, 303, 312, 319, 345, 365
Reinhard, Franz Volkmar. Versuch über den Plan, welchen der Stifter der christlichen Religion zum Besten der Menschheit entwarf (1798), 4, 31 f., 48, 206
Renan, Ernest. La Vie de Jésus (Paris, 1863), German, 1895 (English translation, *The Life of Jesus*, London, 1864; translated with an introduction by W. G. Hutchison, London, 1898), 11, 75, 108, 180-192, 193 f., 197, 200, 207, 213 f., 219, 225, 229, 252, 259, 290, 295, 303, 309, 310
Resch, 273
Reuss, Eduard, 124, 182, 189, 228
Réville, Albert. La Vie de Jésus de Renan devant les orthodoxes et devant la critique (1864), 125, 189, 249
Ritschl, Albrecht, 1, 124 f., 250, 320
Robertson, J. M. Christianity and Mythology (London, 1900), 290 f.
Rogers, A. K. The Life and Teachings of Jesus: a critical analysis, etc. (London and New York, 1894), 249
Rosegger, Peter. Frohe Botschaft eines armen Sünders (Leipzig, 1906), 326
Rossi, Giambernardo de. Dissertazione della lingua propria di Christo e degli Ebrei nazionali della Palestina da' tempi de' Maccabei in disamina del sentimento di un recente scrittore italiano (Parma, 1772), 271
Salvator. Jésus-Christ et sa doctrine (Paris, 1838, 2 vols.), 162
Sanday, 90
Saumaise, Claude, 270
Scaliger, Justus, 270
Schegg, Peter. Sechs Bücher des Lebens Jesu (Freiburg, 1874-1875), 294
Schell, Hermann. Christus (Mainz, 1903), 294 f.
Schenkel, Daniel. Das Charakterbild Jesu (Wiesbaden, 1st and 2nd ed. 1864, 4th ed. 1873) (English translation, A Profile of the Character of Jesus, London, 1869), 11, 103, 131, 193, 200, 203, 205-210, 215, 218, 220, 229, 310
Scherer, Edmond, 189, 191, 209
Scherer, Edmond, und Athanase Coquerel (jun.). Zwei französische Stimmen über Renans Leben-Jesu (Regensburg, 1864), 189
Schleiermacher, Friedrich Ernst Daniel. Das Leben Jesu (1864), 49, 58, 62 f., 70, 73, 80, 81, 85, 88, 89, 101 f., [pg 409] 108, 116, 127, 139, 195, 197, 218, 233, 320
Schmiedel, Otto. Die Hauptprobleme der Leben-Jesu-Forschung (Tübingen, 1902), 12, 22, 293, 301, 303, 305, 312
Schmiedel, P., 277
Schmidt, N. "Was בן נשא a Messianic Title?" (Journal of the Society for Biblical Literature, xv., 1896), 277
Schmidt, Paul Wilhelm. Die Geschichte Jesu, i. (Freiburg, 1899), ii. (Tübingen, 1904), 265, 278, 293, 301, 304, 308, 398
Schmoller. Über die Lehre vom Reiche Gottes im Neuen Testament, 237
Scholten, 231
Schöttgen, Christian, 285
Schürer, Emil. Geschichte des jüdischen Volkes ins Zeitalter Jesu Christi (2nd ed., 2nd pt., 1886) (English translation, History of the Jewish People during the time of Jesus Christ, Edinburgh, 1885);
Das messianische Selbstbewusstsein Jesu Christi (1903), 234, 241, 254 f., 287
Schwartzkoppf. Die Weissagungen Jesu Christi von seinem Tode, seiner Auferstehung und Wiederkunft und ihre Erfüllung (1895), 267
Schweitzer, Albert. Das Messianitätsund Leidensgeheimnis. Eine Skizze des Lebens Jesu (Tübingen, 1901), 281, 287, 328-330, 332 f., 336, 339 f., 351, 382 f.
Schweizer, Alexander, 118, 127 f., 200, 219, 265
Semler, Johann Salomo. Beantwortung der Fragmente eines Ungenannten, insbesondere vom Zweck Jesu und seiner Jünger (Halle, 1779), 13, 15, 25 f., 49
Sepp, Johann Nepomuk. Das Leben Jesu Christi (Regensburg, 7 vols., 1st ed. 1843-1846, 2nd ed. 1853-1862), 108, 294
Seydel, Rudolf. Das Evangelium Jesu in seinen Verhältnissen zur Buddha-Saga und Buddha-Lehre (Leipzig, 1882);
Die Buddha-Legende und das Leben Jesu nach den Evangelien (2nd ed. 1897);
Buddha und Christus (Breslau, 1884), 269, 290-292
Siegfried, Carl, 285
Simon, Richard, 270
Soden, Hermann Freiherr von. Die wichtigsten Fragen im Leben Jesu (Berlin, 1904), 12, 293, 301-308, 312
Stalker, J. The Life of Jesus Christ (Edinburgh, 1880) (German, Tübingen, 1898), 217
Stapfer, E. La Vie de Jésus (pt. i. 1896, pt. ii. 1897, pt. iii. 1898) (English translation, *Jesus Christ before His Ministry*, by L. S. Houghton, 1897, Jesus Christ in His Ministry, by L. S. Houghton, 1897), 217
Stave, 243
Storr, 89
Strauss, David Friedrich. Der Christus des Glaubens und der Jesus der Geschichte. Eine Kritik des Schleiermacher'schen Lebens Jesu (Berlin, 1865);
Das Leben Jesu (1st ed. 1835 and 1836, 2 vols., 3rd ed., revised, 1838 and 1839, 4th ed. 1840) (The Life of Jesus Analyzed, translated from the 4th German ed. by George Eliot, London, 1846, 3rd ed. with a preface by Otto Pfleiderer, 1898);
Das Leben Jesu für das deutsche Volk bearbeitet (Leipzig, 1864, 8th ed.) (English translation, A New Life of Jesus, London, 1865), 4, 5, 10, 11, 12, 14, 24, 28, 35-37, 58, 60, 62, 65, 79 f., 97 f., 68-121, 125, 129 f., 136, 138, 140, 145, 151, 153, 158, 159, 161, 162, 163, 166, 171, 173, 180 f., 182, 185, 188, 190, 193-199, 200, 201, 209 f., 214, 218, 221, 225, 229, 237, 252, 281, 294, 303, 309, 329, 331, 363
Stricker. Jesus von Nazareth (1868), 202
Tal, T., 286
Tholuck, August. Die Glaubwürdigkeit der evangelischen Geschichte, zugleich eine Kritik des Lebens Jesu von Strauss (Hamburg, 1837) (English translation, The Credibility of Evangelical History, illustrated with reference to The Life of Jesus by Dr. Strauss, London, 1844), 70, 97, 100 f., 116, 119, 122, 139
Titius, Arthur, 250
Uhlhorn, Johann Gerhard Wilhelm. Das Leben Jesu in seinen neueren Darstellungen. Vorträge (1892), 5, 11
Ullmann, 100
Usteri, 78
Venturini, Karl Heinrich. Natürliche Geschichte des grossen Propheten von Nazareth (1st ed. 1800-1802, 2nd ed. 1806), 4, 38, 44, 45, 50, 59, 82, 162, 170, 299, 303, 313, 325, 327
Veuillot, Louis. La Vie de notre Seigneur Jésus-Christ (Paris, 1863), (German by Waldener, Köln-Neuss, 1864), 295
[pg 410]
Volkmar, Gustav. Jesus Nazarenus und die erste christliche Zeit, mit den beiden ersten Erzählern (Zurich, 1882), 11, 210, 225-228, 233, 256, 301, 309, 313, 328
Volz, Paul. Die jüdische Eschatologie von Daniel bis Akiba (Tübingen, 1903), 234
Vossius, 270
Wallon, H. Vie de notre Seigneur Jésus-Christ (Paris, 1865), 295
Walton, Brian, 270
Weber, Ferdinand. System der altsynagogalen palästinensischen Theologie (Leipzig, 1880, 2nd ed. 1897), 269, 285 f.
Weiffenbach, Wilhelm. Der Wiederkunftsgedanke Jesu (1873), 222, 228-233, 237, 250
Weinel, Heinrich. Jesus im neunzehnten Jahrhundert (1904), 12, 398
Weiss, Bernhard. Das Leben Jesu (1st ed. 2 vols. 1882, 2nd ed. 1884) (English translation, *The Life of Jesus*, by J. W. Hope, Edinburgh, 1883), 10, 193, 216-218, 250, 262
Weiss, Johannes. Die Predigt Jesu vom Reiche Gottes (1st ed. 1892, 2nd ed. 1900), 9, 10, 11, 23, 61, 91, 92, 136, 221, 222, 237-240, 249 f., 256, 262, 265-267, 278, 301, 309, 336, 349, 383, 388
Weisse, Christian Hermann. Die evangelische Geschichte kritisch und philosophisch bearbeitet (2 vols., Leipzig, 1838);
Die Evangelienfrage in ihrem gegenwärtigen Stadium (Leipzig, 1856), 12, 118, 120, 121-136, 140, 162, 195, 198, 200, 204 f., 218, 229, 232, 294, 309, 328, 341, 357, 374, 378, 389
Weitbrecht, M. G. Das Leben Jesu nach den vier Evangelien (1881), 217
Weizsäcker, Karl Heinrich. Untersuchungen über die evangelische Geschichte, ihre Quellen und den Gang ihrer Entwicklung (Gotha, 1864), 190, 193, 200-202, 205, 207, 218, 229, 259
Wellhausen, Julius. Israelitische und jüdische Geschichte (3rd ed. 1897, 4th ed. 1902);
Das Evangelium Marci (1903);
Das Evangelium Matthäi (1904);
Das Evangelium Lucae (1904);
Skizzen und Vorarbeiten (1899), 254, 269, 276, 277, 285, 287, 289, 391
Wendt, Hans Heinrich. Die Lehre Jesu (Göttingen, pt. i. 1886, pt. ii. 1890) (English translation, Jesus' Teachings, by J. Wilson, Edinburgh, 1892) (2nd German ed. 1902, 3rd ed. 1903), 219, 249, 265
Wernle, Paul. Die Anfänge unserer Religion (Tübingen-Leipzig, 1901, 2nd ed. 1904) (English translation, The Origins of Christianity, by G. A. Bienemann, London, 1903);
Die Reichgotteshoffnung in den ältesten christlichen Dokumenten und bei Jesus (1903), 241, 252-254, 265, 267, 314, 398
Wette, Wilhelm Martin Leberecht de, 72, 78, 86, 103, 119, 208
Wettstein, Johann Jakob, 285
Whateley, Richard. Historic Doubts relative to Napoleon Bonaparte (London, 1819) (adapted as Das Leben Napoleons kritisch geprüft), 112
Wieseler, Karl Georg. Chronologische Synopse der vier Evangelien (Hamburg, 1843), 117
Wiesinger, Albert. Aphorismen gegen Renans Leben-Jesu (Vienna, 1864), 117, 190
Widmanstadt, Joh. Alb., 270
Wilke, Christian Gottlob. Tradition und Mythe (Leipzig, 1837);
Der Urevangelist (Dresden and Leipzig, 1838), 97, 112-114, 119, 121, 124, 140 f., 148, 195, 202, 225, 328
Wittichen, Karl. Leben Jesu (Jena, 1876), 218
Wrede, Wilhelm. Das Messiasgeheimnis in den Evangelien (Göttingen, 1901), 9, 11, 25, 131, 210, 221, 256, 257, 264, 309, 328-349, 350, 358, 380, 384 f., 389, 391 f., 399
Wünsche, August. Neue Beiträge zur Erläuterung der Evangelien aus Talmud und Midrasch (Göttingen, 1878);
Jesus in seiner Stellung zu den Frauen (1876), 269, 285 f.
Xavier, Hieronymus. Historia Christi persice conscripta (Lugd. 1639), 14
Ziegler, Heinrich. Der geschichtliche Christus (1891), 217
Ziegler, Theobald, 69

References

1.
Cited by Dr. Inge in the Hibbert Journal for January 1910, p. 438 (from Jesus or Christ, p. 32).
2.
“Quest,” p. 4.
3.
An order founded in 1776 by Professor Adam Weishaupt of Ingolstadt in Bavaria. Its aim was the furtherance of rational religion as opposed to orthodox dogma; its organisation was largely modelled on that of the Jesuits. At its most flourishing period it numbered over 2000 members, including the rulers of several German States.—Translator.
4.
D. Fr. Strauss, Conversations by Ulrich von Hutten. Leipzig, 1860.
5.
W. Wrede, The Messiah secret in the Gospels. (The Messianic Secret in the Gospels.) Göttingen, 1901, pp. 280-282.
6.
In the author's usage “the Markan hypothesis” means the theory that the Gospel of Mark is not only the earliest and most valuable source for the facts, but differs from the other Gospels in embodying a more or less clear and historically intelligible view of the connexion of events. See Chaps. X. and XIV. below.—Translator.
7.
Dr. Christoph Friedrich von Ammon, Christian Education, Leipzig, 1840, vol. iv. p. 156 ff.
8.
Hase, Story of Jesus, Leipzig, 1876, pp. 110-162. The second edition, published in 1891, carries the survey no further than the first.
9.
The Life of Jesus in Its Recent Depictions, 1892, five lectures.
10.
W. Frantzen, Die Life of Jesus movement since Strauss, Dorpat, 1898.
11.
Theological Review, ii. 59-67 (1899); iii. 9-19 (1900).
12.
Von Soden's study, The most important questions in the life of Jesus, 1904, belongs here only in a very limited sense, since it does not seek to show how the problems have gradually emerged in the various Lives of Jesus.
13.
Hase, The Story of Jesus, 1876, pp. 112, 113.
14.
The story of Christ thoroughly written and also contaminated in many ways by Hieronymo Xavier, translated into Latin and annotated by Ludovico de Dieu. Lugd. 1639.
15.
Johann Jakob Hess, The Story of the Last Three Years of Jesus' Life. (History of the Last Three Years of the Life of Jesus.) 3 vols. 1768 ff.
16.
D. F. Strauss, Hermann Samuel Reimarus and his defense for the reasonable worshippers of God. (Reimarus and his Apology for the Rational Worshippers of God.) 1862.
17.
The quotations inserted without special introduction are, of course, from Reimarus. It is Dr. Schweitzer's method to lead up by a paragraph of exposition to one of these characteristic phrases.—Translator.
18.
Otto Schmiedel, The main issues of Jesus research. Tübingen, 1902.
19.
Döderlein also wrote a defence of Jesus against the Fragmentist: Fragments and Anti-Fragments. Nuremberg, 1778.
20.
This is perhaps the place to mention the account of the life of Jesus which is given in the first part of Plank's History of Christianity. Göttingen, 1818.
21.
Letters Regarding the Study of Theology, 1st ed., 1780-1781; 2nd ed., 1785-1786; Works, ed. Suphan, vol. x.
22.
A Life of Jesus which is completely dependent on the Commentaries of Paulus is that of Greiling, superintendent at Aschersleben, The Life of Jesus from Nazareth A religious guide for the minds and hearts of Jesus' friends among the educated. (The Life of Jesus of Nazareth, a religious Handbook for the Minds and Hearts of the Friends of Jesus among the Cultured.) Halle, 1813.
23.
Paulus prided himself on a very exact acquaintance with the physical and geographical conditions of Palestine. He had a wide knowledge of the literature of Eastern travel.—Translator.
24.
This interpretation, it ought to be remarked, seems to be implied by the ancient reading. "Only a few things are necessary, or just one." given in the margin of the Revised Version.—Translator.
25.
Associations of students, at that time of a political character.—Translator.
26.
The ground of the inference is that, according to this theory, they did not attach much importance to the keeping of the Feasts at Jerusalem. Dr. Schweitzer reminds us in a footnote that a certain want of clearness is due to the fact of this work having been compiled from lecture-notes.
27.

See Theobald Ziegler, “Zur Biographie von David Friedrich Strauss” (Materials for the Biography of D. F. S.), in the Deutsche Revue, May, June, July 1905. The hitherto unpublished letters to Binder throw some light on the development of Strauss during the formative years before the publication of the Life of Jesus.

See Theobald Ziegler, "On the Biography of David Friedrich Strauss" (Materials for the Biography of D. F. S.), in the German Review, May, June, July 1905. The previously unpublished letters to Binder provide some insight into Strauss's development during the formative years leading up to the publication of the Life of Jesus.

Binder, later Director of the Board of Studies at Stuttgart, was the friend who delivered the funeral allocution at the grave of Strauss. This last act of friendship exposed him to enmity and calumny of all kinds. For the text of his short address, see the Deutsche Revue, 1905, p. 107.

Binder, who later became the Director of the Board of Studies in Stuttgart, was the friend who gave the funeral speech at Strauss's grave. This final act of friendship led to hostility and slander of all sorts against him. For the text of his brief address, see the German Review, 1905, p. 107.

28.
German Review, May 1905, p. 199.
29.
Ibid. p. 201.
30.
German Review, p. 203.
31.
Assistant lecturer.
32.
Ibid., June 1905, p. 343 ff.
33.
See Hase, Life of Jesus, 1876, p. 124. The “textbook” referred to is Hase's first Life of Jesus.
34.

He to whom my plaint is
Knows I shed no tear;
She to whom I say this
Feels I have no fear.

He who hears my complaint
Knows I shed no tears;
She who I say this to
Feels I have no fears.

Time has come for fading,
Like a glimmering ray,
Or a sense-evading
Strain that floats away.

Time has come for fading,
Like a shining beam,
Or an elusive
Tension that drifts away.

May, though fainter, dimmer,
Only, clear and pure,
To the last the glimmer
And the strain endure.

May, although
weaker, less bright,
Still, clear and true,
To the very end the glow
And the effort last.

The persons alluded to in the first verse are his son, who, as a physician, attended him in his illness, and to whom he was deeply attached, and a very old friend to whom the verses were addressed.—Translator.

The people mentioned in the first line are his son, who, as a doctor, took care of him during his sickness, and to whom he was very close, as well as a very old friend to whom the verses were meant for.—Translator.

35.
2 Kings iv. 42-44.
36.
C. Th. Bretschneider modestly presented his findings on the nature and origin of the Gospel and the letters of John the Apostle for the judgment of scholars. Leipzig, 1820.
37.
Dr. Fr. Schleiermacher, On the Writings of Luke. A Critical Attempt. (The Writings of Luke. A critical essay.) C. Reimer, Berlin, 1817.
38.
Koppe, Marcus not epitomizing Matthäi, 1782.
39.
Storr, On the Sources of the Gospels of Matthew and Luke., 1794.
40.
Gratz, New attempt to explain the formation of the first three Gospels, 1812.
41.
V. sup. p. 35 f. For the earlier history of the question see F. C. Baur, Critical Investigations of the Canonical Gospels, Tübingen, 1847, pp. 1-76.
42.
So called because largely based on the reference in Luke i. 1, to the “lots” who had “taken in hand to create a narrative (δεήγησις).”Translator.
43.
We take the translation of this striking image from Sanday's “Survey of the Synoptic Problem,” *The Expositor*, 4th ser. vol. 3, p. 307.
44.
For general title see above. First part: "Mr. Dr. Steudel, or the Self-Deception of the Intellectual Supernaturalism of Our Time." 182 pp. Second part: “Mr. Eschenmayer and Mr. Menzel.” 247 pp. Third part: The Evangelical Church Newspaper, The Yearbooks for Scientific Critique, and Theological Studies and Critiques in relation to my critique of the life of Jesus.” (The attitude taken up by ... in regard to my critical Life of Jesus.) 179 pp. In the Studies and Critiques two reviews had appeared: a critical review by Dr. Ullmann (vol. for 1836, pp. 770-816) and that of Müller, written from the standpoint of the "shared belief" (vol. for 1836, pp. 816-890). In the Evangelical Church Newspaper the articles referred to are the following: Foreword (Editorial Survey), 1836, pp. 1-6, 9-14, 17-23, 25-31, 33-38, 41-45; “The Future of Our Theology” (1836, pp. 281 ff.); “Thoughts inspired by Dr. Strauss's essay on ‘The Relation of Theological Criticism and Speculation to the Church’ (1836, pp. 382 ff.); Strauss's essay had appeared in the General Church Newspaper for 1836, No. 39. The critical assessment of the life of Jesus by D. F. Strauss in terms of its scientific value (An Inquiry into the Scientific Value of D. F. Strauss's Critical Study of the Life of Jesus.) By Prof. Dr. Harless. Erlangen, 1836.
45.
"Everything works out for the chosen ones, even the confusing parts of scripture, because they approach them with respect due to its clear messages; everything works against those who are condemned, even the clear parts of scripture, because they disrespect them since they cannot grasp the confusing aspects." For the title of Harless's essay, see end of previous note.
46.
The Life of Jesus Critically Examined by Dr. D. F. Strauss. Reviewed for theologians and non-theologians, von Wilhelm Hoffmann. 1836. (Strauss's Critical Study of the Life of Jesus examined for the Benefit of Theologians and non-Theologians.)
47.
Apology for the Life of Jesus against the latest attempt to dissolve it into myths. (Defence of the Life of Jesus against the latest attempt to resolve it into myth.) By Joh. Ernst Osiander, Professor at the Evangelical Seminary at Maulbronn.
48.
On the Life of Jesus by Strauss, von Franz Baader, 1836. Here may be mentioned also the lectures which Krabbe (subsequently Professor at Rostock) delivered against Strauss: Lectures on the Life of Jesus for Theologians and Non-Theologians (Lectures on the Life of Jesus for Theologians and non-Theologians), Hamburg, 1839. They are more tolerable to non-theologians than to theologians. The author at a later period distinguished himself by the fanatical zeal with which he urged on the deposition of his colleague, Michael Baumgarten, whose Story of Jesus, published in 1859, though fully accepting the miracles, was weighed in the balance by Krabbe and found light-weight by the Rostock standard.
49.
For the title, see head of chapter. Tholuck was born in 1799 at Breslau, and became in 1826 Professor at Halle, where he worked until his death in 1877. With the possible exception of Neander, he was the most distinguished representative of the mediating theology. His piety was deep and his learning was wide, but his judgment went astray in the effort to steer his freight of pietism safely between the rocks of rationalism and the shoals of orthodoxy.
50.
Stud. u. Krit., 1836, p. 777. In his "Open letter to Dr. Ullmann," Strauss examines this suggestion in a serious and dignified fashion, and shows that nothing would be gained by such expedients.—Pamphlets, 3rd pt., p. 129 ff.
51.

Das Leben Jesu-Christi. Hamburg, 1837. Aug. Wilhelm Neander was born in 1789 at Göttingen, of Jewish parents, his real name being David Mendel. He was baptized in 1806, studied theology, and in 1813 was appointed to a professorship in Berlin, where he displayed a many-sided activity and exercised a beneficent influence. He died in 1850. The best-known of his writings is the Geschichte der Pflanzung und Leitung der christlichen Kirche durch die Apostel (History of the Propagation and Administration of the Christian Church by the Apostles), Hamburg, 1832-1833, of which a reprint appeared as late as 1890. Neander was a man not only of deep piety, but also of great solidity of character.

The Life of Jesus. Hamburg, 1837. Aug. Wilhelm Neander was born in 1789 in Göttingen to Jewish parents, his real name being David Mendel. He was baptized in 1806, studied theology, and in 1813 was appointed to a professorship in Berlin, where he showed diverse talents and had a positive impact. He passed away in 1850. His most famous work is the History of the Spread and Management of the Christian Church by the Apostles (Geschichte der Pflanzung und Leitung der christlichen Kirche durch die Apostel), published in Hamburg from 1832 to 1833, with a reprint that came out as late as 1890. Neander was not only deeply pious but also had a strong character.

Strauss, in his Life of Jesus of 1864, passes the following judgment upon Neander's work: “A book such as in these circumstances Neander's Life of Jesus was bound to be calls forth our sympathy; the author himself acknowledges in his preface that it bears upon it only too clearly the marks of the time of crisis, division, pain, and distress in which it was produced.”

Strauss, in his Life of Jesus from 1864, makes the following remark about Neander's work: “A book like Neander's Life of Jesus, considering the situation, is bound to elicit our sympathy; the author himself acknowledges in his preface that it clearly displays the signs of the crisis, division, pain, and distress during which it was written.”

Of the innumerable “positive” Lives of Jesus which appeared about the end of the 'thirties we may mention that of Julius Hartmann (2 vols., 1837-1839). Among the later Lives of Jesus of the mediating theology may be mentioned that of Theodore Pressel of Tübingen, which was much read at the time of its appearance (1857, 592 pp.). It aims primarily at edification. We may also mention the Leben des Herrn Jesu Christi by Wil. Jak. Lichtenstein (Erlangen, 1856), which reflects the ideas of von Hofmann.

Of the countless “positive” biographies of Jesus that came out around the late 1930s, we should note the one by Julius Hartmann (2 vols., 1837-1839). Among the later biographies of Jesus from the mediating theology, we can mention the one by Theodore Pressel from Tübingen, which gained significant popularity when it was published (1857, 592 pp.). Its main goal is to inspire and uplift. We should also mention the *Leben des Herrn Jesu Christi* by Wil. Jak. Lichtenstein (Erlangen, 1856), which reflects von Hofmann's ideas.

52.
For title see head of chapter.
53.
Aphorisms on the Apology of Dr. Strauss and his Work. Grimma, 1838.
54.
From the Xame Xenien, p. 259 of Goethe's Works, ed. Hempel.
55.
Science and the Church. On the Understanding of the Strauss Matter. (A contribution to the adjustment of opinion regarding the Strauss affair.) By Daniel Schenkel, Licentiate in Theology and Privat-Docent of the University of Basle, with a dedicatory letter to Herr Dr. Lücke, Konsistorialrat. Basle, 1839.
56.
*Dr. Strauss and the Zurich Church. A Voice from Northern Germany. With a Foreword by Dr. W. M. L. de Wette.* (A voice from North Germany. With an introduction by Dr. W. M. L. de Wette.) Basle, 1839.
57.
On theological academic freedom and the choice of teachers for universities. Zurich, 1839.
58.
For full title see head of chapter. Reference may also be made to the same author's Christianity's development into a world religion. (Development of Christianity into a World-religion.) Leipzig, 1833-1835. 4 vols. Ammon was born in 1766 at Bayreuth; became Professor of theology at Erlangen in 1790; was Professor in Göttingen from 1794 to 1804, and, after being back in Erlangen in the meantime, became in 1813 Senior Court Chaplain and “Oberkonsistorialrat” at Dresden, where he died in 1850. He was the most distinguished representative of historico-critical rationalism.
59.
He is at one with Strauss in rejecting the explanation of this miracle on the analogy of an expedited natural process, to which Hase had pointed, and which was first suggested by Augustine in Tract viii. in John.: "That Christ turned water into wine is not surprising to those who recognize God's works. What was done in the water jars is something God does every year with the vine." [Augustine's words are: Miraculum quidem Domini nostri Jesu Christi, quo de aqua vinum fecit, non est mirum eis qui noverunt quia Deus fecit (i.e. that He who did it was God). Ipse enim fecit vinum illo die ... in sex hydriis, qui omni anno facit hoc in vitibus.] Nevertheless the poorest naturalistic explanation is at least better than the resignation of Lücke, who is content to wait “until it pleases God through the continued advancement of Christian thought and life to resolve this riddle in its natural and historical aspects.” Lücke, Johannes Comment, p. 474 ff.
60.
Ernst Wilhelm Hengstenberg was born in 1802 at Fröndenberg in the “county” (County) of Mark, became Professor of Theology in Berlin in 1826, and died there in 1869. He founded the Protestant Church Newspaper in 1827.
61.
Report on Mr. Dr. Strauss' historical treatment of the life of Jesus.
62.
Dr. Strauss' Life of Jesus from the Perspective of Catholicism.
63.
Johann Leonhard Hug was born in 1765 at Constance, and had been since 1791 Professor of New Testament Theology at Freiburg, where he died in 1846. He had a wide knowledge of his own department of theology, and his Introduction to the New Testament Writings won him some reputation among Protestant theologians also.
64.
Among the Catholic "Life of Jesus," of which the authors found their incentive in the desire to oppose Strauss, the first place belongs to that of Kuhn of Tübingen. Unfortunately only the first volume appeared (1838, 488 pp.). Here there is a serious and scholarly attempt to grapple with the problems raised by Strauss. Of less importance is the work of the same title in seven volumes, by the Munich Priest and Professor of History, Nepomuk Sepp (1843-1846; 2nd ed. 1853-1862).
65.
On the Life of Jesus by Doctor Strauss. By Edgar Quinet. Translated from the French by Georg Kleine. Published by J. Erdmann and C. C. Müller, 1839. In 1840 Strauss's book was translated into French by M. Littré. It failed, however, to exercise any influence upon French theology or literature. Strauss is one of those German thinkers who always remain foreign and unintelligible to the French mind. Could Renan have written his Life of Jesus as he did if he had had even a partial understanding of Strauss?
66.

Anna Katharina Emmerich was born in 1774 at Flamske near Coesfeld. Her parents were peasants. In 1803 she took up her abode with the Augustinian nuns of the convent of Agnetenberg at Dülmen. After the dissolution of the convent, she lived in a single room in Dülmen itself. The “stigmata” showed themselves first in 1812. She died on the 9th of February 1824. Brentano had been in her neighbourhood since 1819. Das bittere Leiden unseres Herrn Jesu Christi (The Bitter Sufferings of Our Lord Jesus Christ) was issued by Brentano himself in 1834. The Life of Jesus was published on the basis of notes left by him—he died in 1842—in three volumes, 1858-1860, at Regensburg, under the sanction of the Bishop of Limberg.

Anna Katharina Emmerich was born in 1774 in Flamske near Coesfeld. Her parents were peasants. In 1803, she moved in with the Augustinian nuns at the Agnetenberg convent in Dülmen. After the convent was dissolved, she lived alone in a small room in Dülmen. The “stigmata” first appeared in 1812. She passed away on February 9, 1824. Brentano had been in her area since 1819. The bitter suffering of our Lord Jesus Christ (The Bitter Sufferings of Our Lord Jesus Christ) was published by Brentano in 1834. The The Life of Jesus was based on his notes and was published in three volumes from 1858 to 1860 in Regensburg, with approval from the Bishop of Limberg, after he passed away in 1842.

First volume.—From the death of St. Joseph to the end of the first year after the Baptism of Jesus in Jordan. Communicated between May 1, 1821, and October 1, 1822.

First volume.—From the death of St. Joseph to the end of the first year after the Baptism of Jesus in the Jordan River. Shared between May 1, 1821, and October 1, 1822.

Second volume.—From the beginning of the second year after the Baptism in Jordan to the close of the second Passover in Jerusalem. Communicated between October 1, 1822, and April 30, 1823.

Second volume.—From the start of the second year after the Baptism in Jordan to the end of the second Passover in Jerusalem. Communicated between October 1, 1822, and April 30, 1823.

Third volume.—From the close of the second Passover in Jerusalem to the Mission of the Holy Spirit. Communicated between October 21, 1823, and January 8, 1824, and from July 29, 1820, to May 1821.

Third volume.—From the end of the second Passover in Jerusalem to the Mission of the Holy Spirit. Communicated between October 21, 1823, and January 8, 1824, and from July 29, 1820, to May 1821.

Both works have been frequently reissued, the “Bitter Sufferings” as late as 1894.

Both works have been frequently republished, with the “Bitter Struggles” being reissued as recently as 1894.

67.
Excerpts from the text The Life of Luther Critically Edited. (Extracts from a work entitled "A Critical Study of the Life of Luther.") By Dr. Casuar (“Cassowary”; Strauss = Ostrich). Mexico, 1836. Edited by Julius Ferdinand Wurm.
68.
Critically examined life of Napoleon. (A Critical Examination of the Life of Napoleon.) From the English, with some pertinent applications to Strauss's Life of Jesus, 1836. [The English original referred to seems to have been Whateley's Historical Doubts About Napoleon Bonaparte, published in 1819, and primarily directed against Hume's Essay on Miracles.—Translator.]
69.
The Life of Strauss. Written in the year 1839. Paris, 1839.
70.

Ch. G. Wilke, Tradition und Mythe. A contribution to the historical criticism of the Gospels in general, and in particular to the appreciation of the treatment of myth and idealism in Strauss's “Life of Jesus.” Leipzig, 1837.

Ch. G. Wilke, Tradition and Myth. A contribution to the historical critique of the Gospels overall, and specifically to the understanding of how myth and idealism are handled in Strauss's "Jesus' Life." Leipzig, 1837.

Christian Gottlob Wilke was born in 1786 at Werm, near Zeitz, studied theology and became pastor of Hermannsdorf in the Erzgebirge. He resigned this office in 1837 in order to devote himself to his studies, perhaps also because he had become conscious of an inner unrest. In 1845 he prepared the way for his conversion to Catholicism by publishing a work entitled “Can a Protestant go over to the Roman Church with a good conscience?” He took the decisive step in August 1846. Later he removed to Würzburg. Subsequently he recast his famous Clavis Novi Testamenti Philologica—which had appeared in 1840-1841—in the form of a lexicon for Catholic students of theology. His Hermeneutik des Neuen Testaments, published in 1843-1844, appeared in 1853 as Biblische Hermeneutik nach katholischen Grundsätzen (The Science of Biblical Interpretation according to Catholic principles). He was engaged in recasting his Clavis when he died in 1854.

Christian Gottlob Wilke was born in 1786 in Werm, near Zeitz. He studied theology and became the pastor of Hermannsdorf in the Erzgebirge. He stepped down from this role in 1837 to focus on his studies, possibly also due to a sense of inner unrest. In 1845, he laid the groundwork for his conversion to Catholicism by publishing a work titled “Can a Protestant join the Roman Church with a clear conscience?” He made the definitive move in August 1846. Later, he moved to Würzburg. He then reworked his well-known Philological Keys to the New Testament, which had been published in 1840-1841, into a lexicon for Catholic theology students. His Hermeneutics of the New Testament, published in 1843-1844, came out in 1853 as Biblical Hermeneutics According to Catholic Principles (The Science of Biblical Interpretation according to Catholic principles). He was in the process of reworking his Clavis when he passed away in 1854.

Of later works dealing with the question of myth, we may refer to Emanuel Marius, Die Persönlichkeit Jesu mit besonderer Rücksicht auf die Mythologien und Mysterien der alten Völker (The Personality of Jesus, with special reference to the Mythologies and Mysteries of Ancient Nations), Leipzig, 1879, 395 pp.; and Otto Frick, Mythus und Evangelium (Myth and Gospel), Heilbronn, 1879, 44 pp.

Of later works dealing with the question of myth, we can refer to Emanuel Marius, The personality of Jesus with particular consideration to the mythologies and mysteries of ancient peoples (The Personality of Jesus, with special reference to the Mythologies and Mysteries of Ancient Nations), Leipzig, 1879, 395 pp.; and Otto Frick, Myth and Gospel (Myth and Gospel), Heilbronn, 1879, 44 pp.

71.
See p. 89 above.
72.
Pamphlets. Drittes Heft, pp. 55-126: The Yearbooks for Scientific Critique: i. General Relationship of Hegel's Philosophy to Theological Critique: ii. Hegel's view on the historical significance of the evangelical narrative (Hegel's View of the Historical Value of the Gospel History); iii. Different directions within the Hegelian school regarding Christology (Various Tendencies within the Hegelian School in regard to Christology). 1837.
73.

Wissenschaftliche Kritik der evangelischen Geschichte. (Scientific Criticism of the Gospel History.) August Ebrard. Frankfort, 1842; 3rd ed., 1868.

Scientific Critique of the Gospel History. August Ebrard. Frankfurt, 1842; 3rd ed., 1868.

Johannes Heinrich Aug. Ebrard was born in 1818 at Erlangen, was, first, Professor of Reformed Theology at Zurich and Erlangen, afterwards (1853) went to Speyer as “Konsistorialrat,” but was unable to cope with the Liberal opposition there, and returned in 1861 to Erlangen, where he died in 1888.

Johannes Heinrich Aug. Ebrard was born in 1818 in Erlangen. He was initially a Professor of Reformed Theology in Zurich and Erlangen. In 1853, he moved to Speyer as "Konsistorialrat" but he couldn’t handle the Liberal opposition there. He returned to Erlangen in 1861, where he passed away in 1888.

A characteristic example of Ebrard's way of treating the subject is his method of meeting the objection that a fish with a piece of money in its jaws could not have taken the hook. “The fish might very well,” he explains, “have thrown up the piece of money from its belly into the opening of the jaws in the moment in which Peter opened its mouth.” Upon this Strauss remarks: “The inventor of this argument tosses it down before us as who should say, ‘I know very well it is bad, but it is good enough for you, at any rate so long as the Church has livings to distribute and we Konsistorialrats have to examine the theological candidates.’ ” Strauss, therefore, characterises Ebrard's Life of Jesus as “Orthodoxy restored on a basis of impudence.” The pettifogging character of this work made a bad impression even in Conservative quarters.

A characteristic example of Ebrard's approach to the topic is his way of addressing the argument that a fish with a coin in its mouth couldn’t have taken the hook. "The fish could definitely," he explains, "have vomited the coin from its stomach into its mouth just as Peter opened its jaws." In response, Strauss comments: “The person who proposed this argument presents it to us as if to say, ‘I know it’s not a strong argument, but it’s good enough for you, at least while the Church has positions to fill and we Konsistorialrats are here to assess the theological candidates.’ Strauss, therefore, describes Ebrard's Life of Jesus as "Tradition regained on a basis of boldness." The petty nature of this work created a negative impression even among conservatives.

74.
Chronological Synopsis of the Four Gospels. (Chronological Synopsis of the four Gospels.) By Karl Georg Wieseler. Hamburg, 1843. Wieseler was born in 1813 at Altencelle (Hanover), and was Professor successively at Göttingen, Kiel, and Greifswald. He died in 1883.
75.
Johann Peter Lange, Pastor in Duisburg, afterwards Professor at Zurich in place of Strauss. The Life of Jesus. 5 vols., 1844-1847.
76.

Georg Heinrich August Ewald, Geschichte des Volkes Israel. (History of the People of Israel.) 7 vols. Göttingen, 1843-1859; 3rd ed., 1864-1870. Fifth vol., Geschichte Christus' und seiner Zeit. (History of Christ and His Times.) 1855; 2nd ed., 1857.

Georg Heinrich August Ewald, History of the People of Israel. (7 volumes). Göttingen, 1843-1859; 3rd edition, 1864-1870. Fifth volume, The History of Christ and His Times. (1855; 2nd edition, 1857).

Ewald was born in 1803 at Göttingen, where in 1827 he was appointed Professor of Oriental Languages. Having made a protest against the repeal of the fundamental law of the Hanoverian Constitution he was removed from his office and went to Tübingen, first as Professor of philology; in 1841 he was transferred to the theological faculty. In 1848 he returned to Göttingen. When, in 1866, he refused to take the oath of allegiance to the King of Prussia, he was compulsorily retired, and, in consequence of imprudent expressions of opinion, was also deprived of the right to lecture. The town of Hanover chose him as its representative in the North German and in the German Reichstag, where he sat among the Guelph opposition, in the middle of the centre party. He died in 1875 at Göttingen. His contributions to New Testament studies were much inferior to his Oriental and Old Testament researches. His Life of Jesus, in particular, is worthless, in spite of the Old Testament and Oriental learning with which it was furnished forth. He lays great stress upon making the genitive of “Christus” not “Christi,” but, according to German inflection, “Christus'.”

Ewald was born in 1803 in Göttingen, where he was appointed Professor of Oriental Languages in 1827. After protesting the repeal of the fundamental law of the Hanoverian Constitution, he was removed from his position and moved to Tübingen, initially as a Professor of Philology; in 1841, he was transferred to the theological faculty. In 1848, he returned to Göttingen. When, in 1866, he refused to take the oath of allegiance to the King of Prussia, he was forced into retirement and, due to some imprudent opinions, also lost his right to lecture. The town of Hanover elected him as its representative in the North German and German Reichstag, where he sat among the Guelph opposition, in the center party. He died in 1875 in Göttingen. His contributions to New Testament studies were much weaker than his work on Oriental and Old Testament research. His *Life of Jesus*, in particular, is of little value, despite the Old Testament and Oriental scholarship it includes. He places great emphasis on writing the genitive of "Christ" as “Christ's” instead of "Christi."

77.
Ammon, The author of the Gospel of John was different from the editor of this book., Erlangen, 1811.
78.
No value whatever can be ascribed to the Life of Jesus by Werner Hahn, Berlin, 1844, 196 pp. The "educational presentation of history" which the author offers is not designed to meet the demands of historical criticism. He finds in the Gospels no bare history, but, above all, the inculcation of the principle of love. He casts to the winds all attempt to draw the portrait of Jesus as a true historian, being only concerned with its inner truth and "idealizes artistically and scientifically" the actual course of the outward life of Jesus. "It is never the job of a history," he explains, "to share only the bare truth. It's the job of a random and unstructured account to report everything that happened in a way that simply mirrors the sequence of events."
79.
Hase, History of Jesus, 1876, p. 128.
80.
*Philosophical Dogmatics or Philosophy of Christianity.* Leipzig, 1855-1862.
81.
At the end of his preface he makes the striking remark: "I admit I can't imagine any way that Christianity can become relevant to our time again without the support of philosophy; and I'm happy to believe that many of today's most capable and respected theologians share this view."
82.
Vol. ii. pp. 438-543. *Philosophical conclusion on the religious significance of the personality of Christ and the evangelical tradition.* (Concluding Philosophical Estimate of the Significance of the Person of Christ and of the Gospel Tradition.)
83.

Christian Gottlob Wilke, formerly pastor of Hermannsdorf in the Erzgebirge. Der Urevangelist, oder eine exegetisch-kritische Untersuchung des Verwandschaftsverhältnisses der drei ersten Evangelien. (The Earliest Evangelist, a Critical and Exegetical Inquiry into the Relationship of the First Three Gospels.) The subsequent course of the discussion of the Marcan hypothesis was as follows:—

Christian Gottlob Wilke, who was previously the pastor of Hermannsdorf in the Erzgebirge. The Urevangelist, or an exegetical-critical examination of the relationship among the first three Gospels. (The Earliest Evangelist, a Critical and Exegetical Inquiry into the Relationship of the First Three Gospels.) The following discussion on the Marcan hypothesis proceeded as follows:—

In answer to Wilke there appeared a work signed Philosophotos Aletheias, Die Evangelien, ihr Geist, ihre Verfasser, und ihr Verhältnis zu einander. (The Gospels, their Spirit, their Authors, and their relation to one another.) Leipzig, 1845, 440 pp. The author sees in Paul the evil genius of early Christianity, and thinks that the work of scientific criticism must be directed to detecting and weeding out the Pauline elements in the Gospels. Luke is in his opinion a party-writing, biased by Paulinism; in fact Paul had a share in its preparation, and this is what Paul alludes to when he speaks in Romans ii. 16, xi. 28, and xvi. 25 of “his” Gospel. His hand is especially recognisable in chapters i.-iii., vii., ix., xi., xviii., xx., xxi., and xxiv. Mark consists of extracts from Matthew and Luke; John presupposes the other three. The Tübingen standpoint was set forth by Baur in his work, Kritische Untersuchungen über die kanonischen Evangelien. (A Critical Examination of the Canonical Gospels.) Tübingen, 1847, 622 pp. According to him Mark is based on Matthew and Luke. At the same time, however, the irreconcilability of the Fourth Gospel with the Synoptists is for the first time fully worked out, and the refutation of its historical character is carried into detail.

In response to Wilke, a work appeared under the name Philosophotos Aletheias, The Gospels, their Spirit, their Authors, and their Relationship to Each Other. (The Gospels, their Spirit, their Authors, and their relation to one another.) Leipzig, 1845, 440 pages. The author views Paul as the negative force in early Christianity and believes that scientific criticism should focus on identifying and removing the Pauline influences in the Gospels. According to him, Luke is a biased party piece influenced by Paul, claiming that Paul played a role in its creation, which Paul refers to in Romans ii. 16, xi. 28, and xvi. 25 as “his” Gospel. Paul's influence is particularly noticeable in chapters i.-iii., vii., ix., xi., xviii., xx., xxi., and xxiv. Mark is said to be made up of excerpts from Matthew and Luke; John assumes knowledge of the other three. The Tübingen perspective was presented by Baur in his work, Critical Studies on the Canonical Gospels. (A Critical Examination of the Canonical Gospels.) Tübingen, 1847, 622 pages. Baur argues that Mark is based on Matthew and Luke. However, he also thoroughly explores the incompatibility of the Fourth Gospel with the Synoptic Gospels for the first time, providing a detailed refutation of its historical authenticity.

The order Matthew, Mark, Luke is defended by Adolf Hilgenfeld in his work Die Evangelien. Leipzig, 1854, 355 pp.

The order Matthew, Mark, Luke is defended by Adolf Hilgenfeld in his work The Gospels. Leipzig, 1854, 355 pp.

Karl Reinhold Köstlin's work, Der Ursprung und die Komposition der synoptischen Evangelien (Origin and Composition of the Synoptic Gospels), is rendered nugatory by obscurities and compromises. Stuttgart, 1853, 400 pp. The priority of Mark is defended by Edward Reuss, Die Geschichte der heiligen Schriften des Neuen Testaments (History of the Sacred Writings of the New Testament), 1842; H. Ewald, Die drei ersten Evangelien, 1850; A. Ritschl, Die Entstehung der altkatholischen Kirche (Origin of the ancient Catholic Church), 1850; A. Réville, Études critiques sur l'Évangile selon St. Matthieu, 1862. In 1863 the foundations of the Marcan hypothesis were relaid, more firmly than before, by Holtzmann's work, Die synoptischen Evangelien. Leipzig, 1863, 514 pp.

Karl Reinhold Köstlin's work, The origin and composition of the synoptic gospels (Origin and Composition of the Synoptic Gospels), is rendered worthless by its ambiguities and compromises. Stuttgart, 1853, 400 pp. The priority of Mark is defended by Edward Reuss, The History of the Holy Scriptures of the New Testament (History of the Sacred Writings of the New Testament), 1842; H. Ewald, The first three Gospels, 1850; A. Ritschl, The formation of the Old Catholic Church (Origin of the Ancient Catholic Church), 1850; A. Réville, Critical Studies on the Gospel According to St. Matthew, 1862. In 1863, the foundations of the Marcan hypothesis were reinforced more firmly than before by Holtzmann's work, The Synoptic Gospels. Leipzig, 1863, 514 pp.

84.
Alexander Schweizer, The Gospel of John examined critically for its inner values and significance for the life of Jesus. 1841. (A Critical Examination of the Intrinsic Value of the Gospel of John and of its Importance as a Source for the Life of Jesus.) Alexander Schweizer was born in 1808 at Murten, was appointed Professor of Pastoral Theology at Zurich in 1835, and continued to lecture there until his death in 1888, remaining loyal to the ideas of his teacher Schleiermacher, though handling them with a certain freedom. His best-known work is his Belief system (System of Doctrine), 2 vols., 1863-1872; 2nd ed., 1877.
85.
The German is Miracles, the usual word being Wonder, which, though constantly used in the sense of actual "miracles," has, from its obvious derivation, a certain ambiguity.
86.
"And the glory of the Lord rested on Mount Sinai, and the cloud covered it for six days."
87.

We subjoin the titles of the divisions of this work, which are of some interest:

We include the titles of the sections of this work, which are of some interest:

Vol. i. Book i. The Sources of the Gospel History.
Vol. i. Book ii. The Legends of the Childhood.
Vol. i. Book iii. General Sketch of the Gospel History.
Vol. i. Book iv. The Incidents and Discourses according to Mark.
Vol. ii. Book v. The Incidents and Discourses according to Matthew and Luke.
Vol. ii. Book vi. The Incidents and Discourses according to John.
Vol. ii. Book vii. The Resurrection and the Ascension.
Vol. ii. Book viii. Concluding Philosophical Exposition of the Significance of the Person of Christ and of the Gospel Tradition.

Vol. i. Book i. The Sources of the Gospel History.
Vol. i. Book ii. The Legends of the Childhood.
Vol. i. Book iii. General Sketch of the Gospel History.
Vol. i. Book iv. The Incidents and Teachings according to Mark.
Vol. ii. Book v. The Incidents and Teachings according to Matthew and Luke.
Vol. ii. Book vi. The Incidents and Teachings according to John.
Vol. ii. Book vii. The Resurrection and the Ascension.
Vol. ii. Book viii. Final Philosophical Overview of the Significance of the Person of Christ and the Gospel Tradition.

88.
The story of Christ and his time. (History of Christ and His Times.) By Heinrich Ewald, Göttingen, 1855, 450 pp.
89.
Critique of the History of Revelation.
90.
The discovered Christianity. See also The great cause of freedom and my own matter. (The Good Cause of Freedom, in Connexion with my own Case.) Zurich, 1843.
91.
Critique of the Evangelical History of John.
92.
Here and elsewhere Bauer seems to use “Christology” in the sense of Messianic doctrine, rather than in the more general sense which is usual in theology.—Translator.
93.
We retain the German phrase, which has naturalised itself in Synoptic criticism as the designation of an assumed primary gospel lying behind the canonical Mark.
94.
Critique of the Pauline Letters. (Criticism of the Pauline Epistles.) Berlin, 1850-1852.
95.
Critique of the Gospels and the History of Their Origins. (Criticism of the Gospels and History of their Origin.) 2 vols., Berlin, 1850-1851.
96.
Christ and the Caesars. The Origin of Christianity from Roman Greek Culture. Berlin, 1877.
97.
Hennell, a London merchant, withdrew himself from his business pursuits for two years in order to make the preparatory studies for this Life of Jesus. [He is best known as a friend of George Eliot, who was greatly interested and influenced by the "Question."Translator.] To the same category as Hennell's work belongs the Well-Verified Representation of Jesus' Life (An Account of the Life of Jesus based on the closest Examination) of the Heidelberg mathematician, Karl von Langsdorf, Mannheim, 1831. Supplement, with preface to a future second edition, 1833.
98.
Hase seems not to have recognised that the “Disclosures” were merely a plagiarism from Venturini. He mentions them in connexion with Bruno Bauer and appears to make him responsible for inspiring them; at least that is suggested by his formula of transition when he says: "It was mainly to him that the trivial apocryphal theories were connected." This is quite inaccurate. The anonymous epitomist of Venturini had nothing to do with Bauer, and had probably not read a line of his work. Venturini, whom he had read, he does not name.
99.

One of the most ingenious of the followers of Venturini was the French Jew Salvator. In his Jésus-Christ et sa doctrine (Paris, 2 vols., 1838), he seeks to prove that Jesus was the last representative of a mysticism which, drawing its nutriment from the other Oriental religions, was to be traced among the Jews from the time of Solomon onwards. In Jesus this mysticism allied itself with Messianic enthusiasm. After He had lost consciousness upon the cross He was succoured by Joseph of Arimathea and Pilate's wife, contrary to His own expectation and purpose. He ended His days among the Essenes.

One of the most clever followers of Venturini was the French Jew Salvator. In his Jesus Christ and his teachings (Paris, 2 vols., 1838), he attempts to show that Jesus was the final representative of a mysticism that, drawing its sustenance from other Eastern religions, can be traced among the Jews from the time of Solomon onward. In Jesus, this mysticism combined with Messianic fervor. After He lost consciousness on the cross, He was helped by Joseph of Arimathea and Pilate’s wife, which was unexpected and contrary to His own plans. He spent His final days among the Essenes.

Salvator looks to a spiritualised mystical Mosaism as destined to be the successful rival of Christianity.

Salvator sees a spiritually enriched form of Judaism as set to be a successful competitor to Christianity.

100.
The reference should be Micah iv. 8.—F. C. B.
101.
“I am the spirit that always denies.”—Mephistopheles in Faust.
102.
From the Jordan cradle to Golgotha; four books about the Gospel and the Gospels.
103.
The story of Jesus based on independent historical research about the Gospel and the Gospels.
104.
For Noack's reconstruction of it see Book iii. pp. 196-225.
105.
For the reconstruction see Book iii. pp. 326-386.
106.
Tharraqah and Sunamith. The Song of Solomon in its historical and topographical setting. 1869.
107.
The Life of Jesus by D. Fr. Strauss. Traduite par M. Littré, 1840.
108.
Bruno Bauer in Philo, Strauss, and Renan.
109.
Renan does not hesitate to apply this tasteless parallel.
110.

Charles Émile Freppel (Abbé), Professeur d'éloquence sacrée à la Sorbonne. Examen critique de la vie de Jésus de M. Renan. Paris, 1864. 148 pp.

Charles Émile Freppel (Abbé), Professor of Sacred Eloquence at the Sorbonne. A Critical Study of the Life of Jesus by M. Renan. Paris, 1864. 148 pp.

Henri Lasserre's pamphlet, L'Évangile selon Renan (The Gospel according to Renan), reached its four-and-twentieth edition in the course of the same year.

Henri Lasserre's pamphlet, *The Gospel According to Renan* (The Gospel according to Renan), went into its 24th edition within the same year.

111.
Pastoral Letter from His Excellency the Archbishop of Paris (Georges Darboy) on the divinity of Jesus Christ, and decree for Lent 1864.
112.
See, for example, Félix Antoine Philibert Dupanloup, Bishop of Orléans, Warning to the youth and parents about the attacks on religion by some writers today. (Warning to the Young, and to Fathers of Families, concerning some Attacks directed against Religion by some Writers of our Time.) Paris, 1864. 141 pp.
113.
Amadée Nicolas, Renan and his life of Jesus from moral, legal, and literary perspectives. A call to the reason and conscience of the civilized world. Paris-Marseille, 1864.
114.
Ernest Havet, Professeur au Collège de France, Jesus in history. Analysis of the Life of Jesus by Mr. Renan. Extrait de la Review of the Two Worlds. Paris, 1863. 71 pp.
115.
Two French voices on Renan's Life of Jesus, by Edmond Scherer and Athanase Coquerel, Jr. A contribution to the understanding of French Protestantism. Regensburg, 1864. (Two French utterances in regard to Renan's Life of Jesus, by Edmond Scherer and Athanase Coquerel the younger. A contribution to the understanding of French Protestantism.)
116.
E. de Pressensé, The Critical School and Jesus Christ, regarding the life of Jesus by M. Renan.
117.
E. de Pressensé, Jesus Christ, his time, his life, his work. Paris, 1865. 684 pp. In general the plan of this work follows Renan's. He divides the Life of Jesus into three periods: i. The Time of Public Favour; ii. The Period of Conflict; iii. The Great Week. Death and Victory. By way of introduction there is a long essay on the supernatural which sets forth the supernaturalistic views of the author.
118.
The Life of Jesus by Renan in front of the orthodox and the critics. 1864.
119.
T. Colani, Pasteur, “Examining the Life of Jesus by Mr. Renan,” Theology Review. Issued separately, Strasbourg-Paris, 1864. 74 pp.
120.

Lasserre, Das Evangelium nach Renan. Munich, 1864.

Lasserre, The Gospel According to Renan. Munich, 1864.

Freppel, Kritische Beleuchtung der E. Renan'schen Schrift. Translated by Kallmus. Vienna, 1864.

Freppel, Critical Examination of E. Renan's Writing. Translated by Kallmus. Vienna, 1864.

See also Lamy, Professor of the Theological Faculty of the Catholic University of Louvain, Renans Leben-Jesu vor dem Richterstuhle der Kritik. (Renan's Life of Jesus before the Judgment Seat of Criticism.) Translated by August Rohling, Priest. Münster, 1864.

See also Lamy, Professor of the Theological Faculty at the Catholic University of Louvain, Renan's Life of Jesus before the Judgment Seat of Criticism. (Renan's Life of Jesus before the Judgment Seat of Criticism.) Translated by August Rohling, Priest. Münster, 1864.

121.

Dr. Michelis, Renans Roman vom Leben Jesu. Eine deutsche Antwort auf eine französische Blasphemie. (Renan's Romance on the Life of Jesus. A German answer to a French blasphemy.) Münster, 1864.

Dr. Michelis, Renans Roman about the life of Jesus. A German response to a French blasphemy. (Renan's Novel on the Life of Jesus. A German response to a French blasphemy.) Münster, 1864.

Dr. Sebastian Brunner, Der Atheist Renan und sein Evangelium. (The Atheist Renan and his Gospel.) Regensburg, 1864.

Dr. Sebastian Brunner, The Atheist Renan and His Gospel. Regensburg, 1864.

Albert Wiesinger, Aphorismen gegen Renans Leben-Jesu. Vienna, 1864.

Albert Wiesinger, Aphorisms Against Renan's Life of Jesus. Vienna, 1864.

Dr. Martin Deutlinger, Renan und das Wunder. (Renan and Miracle. A contribution to Christian Apologetic.) Munich, 1864. 159 pp.

Dr. Martin Deutlinger, Renan and the Miracle. (Renan and Miracle. A contribution to Christian Apologetics.) Munich, 1864. 159 pp.

Dr. Daniel Bonifacius Haneberg, Ernest Renans Leben-Jesu. Regensburg, 1864.

Dr. Daniel Bonifacius Haneberg, Ernest Renan's Life of Jesus. Regensburg, 1864.

122.
Willibald Beyschlag, Doctor and Professor of Theology, Life of Jesus by Renan. A Lecture delivered at Halle, January 13, 1864. Berlin.
123.

Chr. Ernst Luthardt, Doctor and Professor of Theology, Die modernen Darstellungen des Lebens Jesu. (Modern Presentations of the Life of Jesus.) A discussion of the writings of Strauss, Renan, and Schenkel, and of the essays of Coquerel the younger, Scherer, Colani, and Keim. A Lecture. Leipzig, 1864.

Chr. Ernst Luthardt, Doctor and Professor of Theology, The modern depictions of the life of Jesus. (Modern Presentations of the Life of Jesus.) A discussion of the writings of Strauss, Renan, and Schenkel, and of the essays of Coquerel the younger, Scherer, Colani, and Keim. A Lecture. Leipzig, 1864.

Of the remaining Protestant polemics we may name:—

Of the remaining Protestant arguments, we can mention:—

Dr. Hermann Gerlach, Gegen Renans Leben-Jesu 1864. Berlin.

Dr. Hermann Gerlach, In Response to Renan's Life of Jesus 1864. Berlin.

Br. Lehmann, Renan wider Renan. (Renan versus Renan.) A Lecture addressed to cultured Germans. Zwickau, 1864.

Br. Lehmann, Renan wider Renan. (Renan vs Renan.) A Lecture addressed to educated Germans. Zwickau, 1864.

Friedrich Baumer, Schwarz, Strauss, Renan. A Lecture. Leipzig, 1864.

Friedrich Baumer, Schwarz, Strauss, Renan. A Lecture. Leipzig, 1864.

John Cairns, D. D. (of Berwick). Falsche Christi und der wahre Christus, oder Verteidigung der evangelischen Geschichte gegen Strauss und Renan. (False Christs and the True, a Defence of the Gospel History against Strauss and Renan.) A Lecture delivered before the Bible Society. Translated from the English. Hamburg, 1864.

John Cairns, D. D. (of Berwick). False Christs and the True Christ, or Defense of the Gospel History against Strauss and Renan. A lecture given to the Bible Society. Translated from the English. Hamburg, 1864.

Bernhard ter Haar, Doctor of Theology and Professor at Utrecht, Zehn Vorlesungen über Renans Leben-Jesu. (Ten Lectures on Renan's Life of Jesus.) Translated by H. Doermer. Gotha, 1864.

Bernhard ter Haar, Doctor of Theology and Professor at Utrecht, Ten Lectures on Renan's Life of Jesus. Translated by H. Doermer. Gotha, 1864.

Paulus Cassel, Professor and Licentiate in Theology, Bericht über Renans Leben-Jesu. (A Report upon Renan's Life of Jesus.)

Paulus Cassel, Professor and Licensed Theologian, Report on Renan's Life of Jesus. (A Report on Renan's Life of Jesus.)

J. J. van Oosterzee, Doctor and Professor of Theology at Utrecht, Geschichte oder Roman? Das Leben-Jesu von Renan vorläufig beleuchtet. (History or Fiction? A Preliminary Examination of Renan's Life of Jesus.) Hamburg, 1864.

J. J. van Oosterzee, Doctor and Professor of Theology at Utrecht, History or Novel? A Preliminary Examination of Renan's Life of Jesus. (History or Fiction? A Preliminary Examination of Renan's Life of Jesus.) Hamburg, 1864.

124.
Strauss's second Life of Jesus appeared in French in 1864.
125.
I can now say without coming off as self-important, and almost without fearing contradiction, that if my Life of Jesus hadn't come out the year after Schleiermacher's death, he wouldn't have been held back for so long. Before that, it would have been welcomed by the theological community as a savior; but because of the damage my work caused to the theology of the time, there was no remedy or support for it. In fact, it showed the author as somewhat responsible for the crisis, as the ideas he had allowed in slowly were now, despite his careful reservations, flooding in uncontrollably.—From the Introduction to The Christ of Faith and the Historical Jesus, 1865.
126.
“Now that Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus is finally available in print, everyone can come together in genuine celebration. The release of any work by Schleiermacher always enriches literature. Anything produced by a mind like his is bound to inspire and energize others. There is certainly no shortage of this kind of work in our current theological literature. Where many who are alive seem nearly lifeless, it is fitting for the deceased to rise and provide testimony. Schleiermacher's lectures, when compared to the work of his students, clearly demonstrate that the great theologian has only passed on his mantle, not his spirit.”Ibid.
127.
The lines of Schleiermacher's work were followed by Bunsen. His Life of Jesus forms vol. ix. of his Bible project. (Edited by Holtzmann, 1865.) He accepts the Fourth Gospel as an historical source and treats the question of miracle as not yet settled. Christian Karl Josias von Bunsen, born in 1791 at Korbach in Waldeck, was Prussian ambassador at Rome, Berne, and London, and settled later in Heidelberg. He was well read in theology and philology, and gradually came, in spite of his friendly relations with Friedrich Wilhelm IV., to entertain more liberal views on religion. The issue of his Bible work for the community was begun in 1858. He died in 1860. (Best known in England as the Chevalier Bunsen.)
128.
Ch. H. Weisse, The Protestant story, Leipzig, 1838. The Gospel Question in its current state. (The Present Position of the Problem of the Gospels.) Leipzig, 1856. He regarded the discourses as historical, the narrative portions as of secondary origin. Alexander Schweizer, again, wished to distinguish a Jerusalem source and a Galilaean source, the latter being unreliable. The Gospel of John according to its inner value and its significance for the life of Jesus, 1841. (The Gospel of John considered in Relation to its Intrinsic Value and its Importance as a Source for the Life of Jesus.) See p. 127 f. Renan takes the narrative portions as authentic and the discourses as secondary.
129.
Karl Heinrich Weizsäcker was born in 1822 at Öhringen in Würtemberg. He qualified as Privat-Docent in 1847 and, after acting in the meantime as Court-Chaplain and Oberkonsistorialrat at Stuttgart, became in 1861 the successor of Baur at Tübingen. He died in 1899.
130.
The works of a Dutch writer named Stricker, Jesus of Nazareth (1868), and of the Englishman Sir Richard Hanson, The Historical Jesus (1869), were based on Mark without any reference to John.
131.
1, Mark i.; 2, Mark ii. 1-iii. 6; 3, Mark iii. 7-19; 4, Mark iii. 19-iv. 34; 5, Mark iv. 35-vi. 6; 6, Mark vi. 7-vii. 37; 7, Mark viii. 1-ix. 50.
132.
Holtzmann, Commentary on the Synoptics, 1889, p. 184. The form of the expression (Escape routes and travel) is derived from Keim.
133.
The life of Jesus moved towards its tragic end, an end He had predicted with increasing clarity, seeing it as the only fitting conclusion for Himself and as part of God’s predetermined plan. The animosity of the Pharisees and the apathy of the people left no other option. This hatred was intensified by the harsh way Jesus revealed the truth about them—a heart void of love, a decaying morality, a façade of virtue, and hypocritical pride. Between such uncompromising opponents—a man seemingly set on harnessing the people's Messianic hopes for his own purposes and a hierarchy fiercely protective of its authority—a permanent rift was inevitable. It was also clear that, even in Galilee, only a small group of people would be willing to confront the dangers of such a divide with Him. The only thing that could have prevented the death sentence that had been anticipated was a series of strong, clear actions from the people. To trigger such actions, Jesus would have needed to momentarily embrace the popular, powerful, and provocative Messianic ideas, or rather, put Himself in alignment with them. His refusal to take even a single step down that path, which would have seemed reasonable from a conventional political standpoint, was the sole reason for His downfall.—Holtzmann, The Synoptic Gospels, 1863, pp. 485, 486.
134.
“A mental realm of transformation.” "Change of heart" corresponds more exactly than "regret" to the Greek μετάνοια (change of mind, change of attitude), but the phrase is no less elliptical in German than in English. The meaning is doubtless “a kingdom centered on repentance, consisting of those who have met this requirement.”
135.
Omitted in some of the best texts.—F. C. B.
136.
Oskar Holtzmann, The Life of Jesus, 1901.
137.
The modern representations of the life of Jesus. (Modern Presentments of the Life of Jesus.) A discussion of the works of Strauss, Renan, and Schenkel, and of the Essays of Coquerel the younger, Scherer, Colani, and Keim. A lecture by Chr. Ernest Luthardt, Leipzig. 1st and 2nd editions, 1864. Luthardt was born in 1823 at Maroldsweisach in Lower Franconia, became Docent at Erlangen in 1851, was called to Marburg as Professor Extraordinary in 1854, and to Leipzig as Ordinary Professor in 1856. He died in 1902.
138.
For guidance on my writing The Character Portrait of Jesus. (Explanations intended to place my work “A Picture of the Character of Jesus” in the proper light.) 1864. The Protestant freedom in its current struggle against ecclesiastical reaction. (Protestant Freedom in its present Struggle with Ecclesiastical Reaction.) 1865.
139.
The Schenkel trade in Baden. (The Schenkel Controversy in Baden.) (A corrected reprint from number 441 of the National Newspaper of September 21, 1864.) An appendix to The Christ of faith and the Jesus of history. 1865.
140.

Theodor Keim, Die Geschichte Jesu von Nazara, in ihrer Verhaltung mit dem Gesamtleben seines Volkes frei untersucht und ausführlich erzählt. (The History of Jesus of Nazara in Relation to the General Life of His People, freely examined and fully narrated.) 3 vols. Zurich, 1867-1872. Vol. i. The Day of Preparation; vol. ii. The Year of Teaching in Galilee; vol. iii. The Death-Passover (Todesostern) in Jerusalem. A short account in a more popular form appeared in 1872, Geschichte Jesu nach den Ergebnissen heutiger Wissenschaft für weitere Kreise übersichtlich erzählt. (The History of Jesus according to the Results of Present-day Criticism, briefly narrated for the General Reader.) 2nd ed., 1875.

Theodor Keim, The story of Jesus of Nazareth, freely examined and told in detail in relation to the overall life of his people.. (The History of Jesus of Nazara in Relation to the General Life of His People, freely examined and fully narrated.) 3 vols. Zurich, 1867-1872. Vol. i. The Day of Preparation; vol. ii. The Year of Teaching in Galilee; vol. iii. The Death-Passover (Death Easter) in Jerusalem. A short account in a more popular form appeared in 1872, The story of Jesus according to the findings of today's science, presented clearly for a broader audience. (The History of Jesus according to the Results of Present-day Criticism, briefly narrated for the General Reader.) 2nd ed., 1875.

Karl Theodor Keim was born in 1825 at Stuttgart, was Repetent at Tübingen from 1851 to 1855, and after he had been five years in the ministry, became Professor at Zurich in 1860. In 1873 he accepted a call to Giessen, where he died in 1878.

Karl Theodor Keim was born in 1825 in Stuttgart. He was a Repetent at Tübingen from 1851 to 1855, and after spending five years in the ministry, he became a professor in Zurich in 1860. In 1873, he accepted a position in Giessen, where he passed away in 1878.

141.
The human development of Jesus Christ. See Holtzmann, The Synoptic Gospels, 1863, pp. 7-9. This dissertation was followed by The historical Christ. 3rd ed., 1866.
142.
The Story of Jesus. 2nd ed., 1875, pp. 228 and 229.
143.
The ultimate reason why Keim deliberately gives such prominence to the eschatology is that he holds to Matthew, and is therefore more under the direct impression of the masses of discourse in this Gospel, charged, as they are, with eschatological ideas, than those writers who find their primary authority in Mark, where these discourses are lacking.
144.

Geschichte Jesu. Nach akademischen Vorlesungen von Dr. Karl Hase. 1876. Special mention ought also to be made of the fine sketch of the Life of Jesus in A. Hausrath's Neutestamentliche Zeitgeschichte (History of New Testament Times), 1st ed., Munich, 1868 ff.; 3rd ed., 1 vol., 1879, pp. 325-515; Die zeitgeschichtlichen Beziehungen des Lebens Jesu (The Relations of the Life of Jesus to the History of His time).

The History of Jesus. Based on lectures by Dr. Karl Hase. 1876. We should also highlight the excellent overview of Jesus's life in A. Hausrath's *History of New Testament Times*, 1st ed., Munich, 1868 ff.; 3rd ed., 1 vol., 1879, pp. 325-515; The Connections Between Jesus' Life and the History of His Time.

Adolf Hausrath was born at Karlsruhe. He was appointed Professor of Theology at Heidelberg in 1867, and died in 1909.

Adolf Hausrath was born in Karlsruhe. He became a Professor of Theology at Heidelberg in 1867 and passed away in 1909.

145.
The Life of Jesus, von Willibald Beyschlag: Pt. i. Preliminary Investigations, 1885, 450 pp.; pt. ii. Narrative, 1886, 495 pp. Joh. Heinr. Christoph Willibald Beyschlag was born in 1823 at Frankfort-on-Main, and went to Halle as Professor in 1860. His splendid eloquence made him one of the chief spokesmen of German Protestantism. As a teacher he exercised a remarkable and salutary influence, although his scientific works are too much under the dominance of an apologetic of the heart. He died in 1900.
146.

Bernhard Weiss, Das Leben Jesu. 2 vols. Berlin, 1882. See also Das Markusevangelium, 1872; Das Matthäusevangelium, 1876; and the Lehrbuch der neutestamentlichen Theologie, 5th ed., 1888. Bernhard Weiss was born in 1827 at Königsberg, where he qualified as Privat-Docent in 1852. In 1863 he went as Ordinary Professor to Kiel, and was called to Berlin in the same capacity in 1877.

Bernhard Weiss, The Life of Jesus. 2 vols. Berlin, 1882. See also The Book of Mark, 1872; Matthew's Gospel, 1876; and the *Textbook of New Testament Theology*, 5th ed., 1888. Bernhard Weiss was born in 1827 in Königsberg, where he became a Privat-Docent in 1852. In 1863, he became an Ordinary Professor in Kiel, and was appointed to Berlin in the same role in 1877.

Among the distinctly liberal Lives of Jesus of an earlier date, that of W. Krüger-Velthusen (Elberfeld, 1872, 271 pp.) might be mentioned if it were not so entirely uncritical. Although the author does not hold the Fourth Gospel to be apostolic he has no hesitation in making use of it as an historical source.

Among the distinctly liberal biographies of Jesus from earlier times, W. Krüger-Velthusen's work (Elberfeld, 1872, 271 pp.) could be noted, although it is completely uncritical. Even though the author does not consider the Fourth Gospel to be apostolic, he readily uses it as a historical source.

There is more sentiment than science, too, in the work of M. G. Weitbrecht, Das Leben Jesu nach den vier Evangelien, 1881.

There is more emotion than science, too, in the work of M. G. Weitbrecht, The Life of Jesus According to the Four Gospels, 1881.

A weakness in the treatment of the Johannine question and a want of clearness on some other points disfigures the three-volume Life of Jesus of the Paris professor, E. Stapfer, which is otherwise marked by much acumen and real depth of feeling. Vol. i. Jésus-Christ avant son ministère (Fischbacher, Paris, 1896); vol. ii. Jésus-Christ pendant son ministère (1897); vol. iii. La Mort et la résurrection de Jésus-Christ (1898).

A weakness in the treatment of the Johannine question and a lack of clarity on some other points detracts from the three-volume Life of Jesus by the Paris professor E. Stapfer, which is otherwise marked by significant insight and genuine depth of feeling. Vol. i. Jesus Christ before his ministry (Fischbacher, Paris, 1896); vol. ii. Jesus Christ during his ministry (1897); vol. iii. The Death and Resurrection of Jesus Christ (1898).

F. Godet writes of “The Life of Jesus before His Public Appearance” (German translation by M. Reineck, Leben Jesu vor seinem öffentlichen Auftreten. Hanover, 1897).

F. Godet writes about "The Life of Jesus Before His Public Ministry" (German translation by M. Reineck, The life of Jesus before his public ministry. Hanover, 1897).

G. Längin founds his Der Christus der Geschichte und sein Christentum (The Christ of History and His Christianity) on a purely Synoptic basis. 2 vols., 1897-1898.

G. Längin bases his The Christ of History and His Christianity (The Christ of History and His Christianity) solely on the Synoptic Gospels. 2 vols., 1897-1898.

The English Life of Jesus Christ, by James Stalker, D. D. (now Professor of Church History in the United Free Church College, Aberdeen), passed through numberless editions (German, 1898; Tübingen, 4th ed., 1901).

The English The life of Jesus, by James Stalker, D. D. (currently a Professor of Church History at the United Free Church College, Aberdeen), has gone through countless editions (German, 1898; Tübingen, 4th ed., 1901).

Very pithy and interesting is Dr. Percy Gardner's Exploratio Evangelica. A Brief Examination of the Basis and Origin of Christian Belief. 1899; 2nd ed., 1907.

Very concise and interesting is Dr. Percy Gardner's Evangelical Exploration. A Short Look at the Foundation and Origin of Christian Belief. 1899; 2nd ed., 1907.

A work which is free from all compromise is H. Ziegler's Der geschichtliche Christus (The Historical Christ). 1891. For this reason the five lectures, delivered in Liegnitz, out of which it is composed, attracted such unfavourable attention that the Ecclesiastical Council took proceedings against the author. (See the Christliche Welt, 1891, pp. 563-568, 874-877.)

A work that is completely uncompromising is H. Ziegler's The historical Christ (The Historical Christ). 1891. Because of this, the five lectures delivered in Liegnitz, which make up the work, drew such negative attention that the Ecclesiastical Council took action against the author. (See the Christian World, 1891, pp. 563-568, 874-877.)

147.

Holtzmann, Neutestamentliche Einleitung, 2nd ed., 1886. Weizsäcker declares himself in the Theologische Literaturzeitung for 1882, No. 23, and Das apostolische Zeitalter, 2nd ed., 1890.

Holtzmann, New Testament Introduction, 2nd ed., 1886. Weizsäcker states his position in the Theological Literature Journal for 1882, No. 23, and The Apostolic Age, 2nd ed., 1890.

Hase and Schenkel accepted this position in principle, but were careful to keep open a line of retreat.

Hase and Schenkel agreed to this position in principle but were careful to leave themselves an escape route.

Towards the end of the 'seventies the rejection of the Fourth Gospel as an historical source was almost universally recognised in the critical camp. It is taken for granted in the Life of Jesus by Karl Wittichen (Jena, 1876, 397 pp.), which might be reckoned one of the most clearly conceived works of this kind based on the Marcan hypothesis if its arrangement were not so bad. It is partly in the form of a commentary, inasmuch as the presentment of the life takes the form of a discussion of sixty-seven sections. The detail is very interesting. It makes an impression of naïveté when we find a series of sections grouped under the title, “The establishment of Christianity in Galilee.” No stress is laid on the significance of Jesus' journey to the north. Wittichen, also, misled by Luke, asserts, just as Weisse had done, that Jesus had worked in Judaea for some time prior to the triumphal entry.

Towards the end of the '70s, the rejection of the Fourth Gospel as a historical source was almost universally accepted in the critical community. This assumption is evident in Karl Wittichen's *Life of Jesus* (Jena, 1876, 397 pp.), which could be considered one of the most clearly thought-out works of its kind based on the Marcan hypothesis if its organization weren't so poor. It's partly structured like a commentary, as it presents the life of Jesus through a discussion of sixty-seven sections. The details are quite interesting. It gives an impression of naivety when we see a series of sections grouped under the title, “The founding of Christianity in Galilee.” There's no emphasis on the importance of Jesus' journey to the north. Wittichen, also misled by Luke, claims, just as Weisse had, that Jesus had been active in Judaea for a while before the triumphal entry.

148.
H. H. Wendt, The teachings of Jesus, vol. i. The Protestant sources report on the teachings of Jesus. (The Record of the Teaching of Jesus in the Gospel Sources.) 354 pp. Göttingen, 1886; vol. ii., 1890; Eng. trans., 1892. Second German edition in one vol., 626 pp., 1901. See also the same writer's The Gospel of John. Investigation of its origins and historical value, 1900. (The Gospel of John: an Investigation of its Origin and Historical Value.) Hans Heinrich Wendt was born in 1853 at Hamburg, qualified as Privat-Docent in 1877 at Göttingen, was subsequently Extraordinary Professor at Kiel and Heidelberg, and now works at Jena.
149.
Johannis Lightfooti, Doctor of English and Head of St. Catherine's College in the University of Cambridge, Hebrew and Talmudic Hours on the Four Gospels ... now published for the second time in Germany along with indexes of Scripture locations, topics, and necessary words from the Museum of Io. Benedicti Carpzovii. Leipzig. Year MDCLXXXIV.
150.
The pioneer works in the study of apocalyptic were Dillmann's Henoch, 1851; and Hilgenfeld's Jewish Apocalypticism, 1857.
151.
Jesus of Nazareth and the Early Christian Period, with the First Two Narrators, von Gustav Volkmar, Zurich, 1882. To which must be added: Markus and the Synoptic Gospels, according to the documentary text; and the historical account of Jesus' life. (Mark and Synoptic Material in the Gospels, according to the original text; and the historical elements in the Life of Jesus.) Zurich, 1869; 2nd edition, 1876, 738 pp. Volkmar was born in 1809, and was living at Fulda as a Gymnasium (High School) teacher, when in 1852 he was arrested by the Hessian Government on account of his political views, and subsequently deprived of his post. In 1853 he went to Zurich, where a new prospect opened to him as a Docent in theology. He died in 1893.
152.
Kienlen, "Jesus' eschatological discourse Matt. xxiv. with parallels." (The Eschatological Discourse of Jesus in Matt. xxiv. with the parallel passages), Yearbook for Theology, 1869, pp. 706-709. Analysis of other attempts directed to the same end in Weiffenbach, Thought of the Second Coming, p. 31 ff.
153.
Wilhelm Weiffenbach, Director of the Seminary for Theological Students at Friedberg, was born in 1842 at Bornheim in Rhenish Hesse.
154.
The English reader will find a constructive analysis of what is known as the “Mini Apocalypse” in Encyclopaedia Biblica, art. “Gospels,” col. 1857. It consists of the verses Matt. xxiv. 6-8, 15-22, 29-31, 34, corresponding to Mark xiii. 7-9a, 14-20, 24-27, 30. According to the theory first sketched by Colani these verses formed an independent Apocalypse which was embedded in the Gospel by the Evangelist.—F. C. B.
155.
Studies on Protestant history, 1864, pp. 121-126.
156.
“About the composition of the eschatological discourse Matt. xxiv. 4 ff.” (The Composition of the Eschatological Discourse in Matt. xxiv. 4 ff.), Journal for Theology vol. xiii., 1868, pp. 134-149.
157.
By “Capernaitic” Weiffenbach apparently means literalistic; cf. John vi. 52 f.
158.
Wilhelm Baldensperger, at present Professor at Giessen, was born in 1856 at Mülhausen in Alsace.
159.

A new edition appeared in 1891. There is no fundamental alteration, but in consequence of the polemic against opponents who had arisen in the meantime it is fuller. The first part of a third edition appeared in 1903 under the title Die messianisch-apokalyptischen Hoffnungen des Judentums.

A new edition came out in 1891. There aren't any major changes, but due to the arguments with critics that emerged in the meantime, it includes more content. The first part of a third edition was released in 1903 under the title Messianic-apocalyptic hopes of Judaism.

See also the interesting use made of Late-Jewish and Rabbinic ideas in Alfred Edersheim's The Life and Times of Jesus the Messiah, 2nd ed., London, 1884, 2 vols.

See also the interesting use of Late-Jewish and Rabbinic ideas in Alfred Edersheim's The Life and Times of Jesus the Messiah, 2nd ed., London, 1884, 2 vols.

160.

Emil Schürer, Geschichte des jüdischen Volkes im Zeitalter Jesu Christi. (History of the Jewish People in the Time of Christ.) 2nd ed., part second, 1886, pp. 417 ff. Here is to be found also a bibliography of the older literature of the subject. 3rd ed., 1889, vol. ii. pp. 498 ff.

Emil Schürer, The Jewish People's History During the Time of Christ. 2nd ed., part two, 1886, pp. 417 ff. This edition also includes a bibliography of earlier literature on the topic. 3rd ed., 1889, vol. ii. pp. 498 ff.

Emil Schürer was born at Augsburg in 1844, and from 1873 onwards was successively Professor at Leipzig, Giessen, and Kiel, and is now (1909) at Göttingen.

Emil Schürer was born in Augsburg in 1844, and from 1873 on, he served as a professor at Leipzig, Giessen, and Kiel, and is currently (1909) at Göttingen.

The latest presentment of Jewish apocalyptic is Die jüdische Eschatologie von Daniel bis Akiba, by Paul Volz, Pastor in Leonberg. Tübingen, 1903. 412 pp. The material is very completely given. Unfortunately the author has chosen the systematic method of treating his subject, instead of tracing the history of its development, the only right way. As a consequence Jesus and Paul occupy far too little space in this survey of Jewish apocalyptic. For a treatment of the origin of Jewish eschatology from the point of view of the history of religion see Hugo Gressmann, now Professor at Berlin, Der Ursprung der israelitisch-jüdischen Eschatologie (The Origin of the Israelitish and Jewish Eschatology), Göttingen, 1905. 377 pp.

The latest presentation of Jewish apocalyptic is Jewish Eschatology from Daniel to Akiba, by Paul Volz, Pastor in Leonberg. Tübingen, 1903. 412 pp. The material is very thoroughly covered. Unfortunately, the author chose a systematic approach to his subject, rather than tracing its historical development, which is the only correct method. As a result, Jesus and Paul are given far too little attention in this overview of Jewish apocalyptic. For a discussion on the origin of Jewish eschatology from a historical perspective, see Hugo Gressmann, now a Professor in Berlin, The origin of Israelite-Jewish eschatology (The Origin of the Israelitish and Jewish Eschatology), Göttingen, 1905. 377 pp.

161.
Johannes Weiss, now Professor at Marburg, was born at Kiel in 1863.
162.
It may be mentioned that this work had been preceded (in 1891) by two Leiden prize dissertations, About the teaching of the Kingdom of God in the New Testament (Concerning the Kingdom of God in the New Testament), one of them by Issel, the other, which lays especially strong emphasis upon the eschatology, by Schmoller.
163.
Wilhelm Bousset, now Professor in Göttingen, born 1865 at Lübeck
164.
Theol. Review (1901), 4, pp. 89-103.
165.
W. Bousset, Jewish apocalypticism in its historical religious origins and its significance for the New Testament. (The Origin of Apocalyptic as indicated by Comparative Religion, and its significance for the understanding of the New Testament.) Berlin, 1903. 67 pp. See also W. Bousset, The Religion of Judaism in the New Testament Era, 512 pp., 1902. For the assertion of Parsic influences see also Stave, The influence of Zoroastrianism on Judaism. Haarlem, 1898.
166.

Der Grundcharakter der Ethik Jesu im Verhältnis zu den messianischen Hoffnungen seines Volkes und zu seinem eigenen Messiasbewusstsein. Freiburg, 1895, 119 pp. See also his inaugural dissertation of 1896, Le Principe de la morale de Jésus. Paris, 1896.

The core nature of Jesus' ethics in connection with the messianic hopes of his people and his own understanding of being the Messiah. Freiburg, 1895, 119 pp. See also his inaugural dissertation of 1896, The Principle of Jesus' Morality. Paris, 1896.

A. K. Rogers, The Life and Teachings of Jesus; a Critical Analysis, etc. (London and New York, 1894), regards Jesus' teaching as purely ethical, refusing to admit any eschatology at all.

A. K. Rogers, The Life and Teachings of Jesus: A Critical Analysis, etc. (London and New York, 1894), sees Jesus' teachings as entirely ethical, rejecting any notion of eschatology.

167.
Paris, 2 vols., 500 and 512 pp.
168.
W. Weiffenbach, The question of Jesus' art. (The Question concerning the Second Coming of Jesus.) Friedberg, 1901.
169.
A. Titius, The New Testament teaching on salvation and its significance for the present. I. Teil: Jesus' teaching on the Kingdom of God. (The New Testament Doctrine of Blessedness and its Significance for the Present. Pt. I., Jesus' Doctrine of the Kingdom of God.) Arthur Titius, now Professor at Kiel, was born in 1864 at Sensburg.
170.
The eschatological statements of Jesus in the synoptic gospels, 167 pp. Erich Haupt, now Professor in Halle, was born in 1841 at Stralsund.
171.
Cf. the preface to the 2nd ed. of Joh. Weiss's The Sermon of Jesus on the Kingdom of God. Göttingen, 1900.
172.
Tübingen-Leipzig, 1901, 410 pp.; 2nd ed., 1904. Paul Wernle, now Professor of Church History at Basle, was born in Zurich, 1872.
173.

Israelitische und jüdische Geschichte, 1st ed., 1894, pp. 163-168; 2nd ed., 1895, pp. 198-204; 3rd ed., 1897; 4th ed., 1901, pp. 380-394. See also his Skizzen (Sketches), pp. 6, 187 ff.

Jewish History, 1st ed., 1894, pp. 163-168; 2nd ed., 1895, pp. 198-204; 3rd ed., 1897; 4th ed., 1901, pp. 380-394. See also his Drawings, pp. 6, 187 ff.

See also J. Wellhausen, Das Evangelium Marci, 1903, 2nd ed., 1909; Das Evangelium Matthäi, 1904; Das Evangelium Lucae, 1904.

See also J. Wellhausen, The Book of Mark, 1903, 2nd ed., 1909; The Book of Matthew, 1904; The Book of Luke, 1904.

Julius Wellhausen, now Professor at Göttingen, was born in 1844 at Hameln.

Julius Wellhausen, who is currently a Professor at Göttingen, was born in 1844 in Hameln.

174.

Emil Schürer, Das messianische Selbstbewusstsein Jesu Christi. (The Messianic Self-consciousness of Jesus Christ.) 1903, 24 pp.

Emil Schürer, The Messianic Self-awareness of Jesus Christ. 1903, 24 pp.

According to J. Meinhold, too, in Jesus und das alte Testament (Jesus and the Old Testament), 1896, Jesus did not purpose to be the Messiah of Israel.

According to J. Meinhold, in Jesus and the Old Testament (Jesus and the Old Testament), 1896, Jesus did not intend to be the Messiah of Israel.

175.

Die evangelische Geschichte und der Ursprung des Christentums auf Grund einer Kritik der Berichte über das Leiden und die Auferstehung Jesu. (The Gospel History and the Origin of Christianity considered in the light of a critical investigation of the Reports of the Suffering and Resurrection of Jesus.) By Dr. W. Brandt, Leipzig, 1893, 588 pp.

The story of the Gospel and the beginnings of Christianity, grounded in a careful analysis of the accounts of Jesus' suffering and resurrection. (The Gospel History and the Origin of Christianity considered in the light of a critical investigation of the Reports of the Suffering and Resurrection of Jesus.) By Dr. W. Brandt, Leipzig, 1893, 588 pp.

Wilhelm Brandt was born in 1855 of German parents in Amsterdam and became a pastor of the Dutch Reformed Church. In 1891 he resigned this office and studied in Strassburg and Berlin. In 1893 he was appointed to lecture in General History of Religion as a member of the theological faculty of Amsterdam.

Wilhelm Brandt was born in 1855 to German parents in Amsterdam and became a pastor of the Dutch Reformed Church. In 1891, he stepped down from this position and studied in Strasbourg and Berlin. In 1893, he was appointed to teach General History of Religion as a member of the theological faculty at Amsterdam.

176.

Ad. Jülicher, Die Gleichnisreden Jesu. Vol. i., 1888. The substance of it had already been published in a different form. Freiburg, 1886.

Ad. Jülicher, Jesus' Parables. Vol. i., 1888. The content had already been published in another format. Freiburg, 1886.

Adolf Jülicher, at present Professor in Marburg, was born in 1857 at Falkenberg.

Adolf Jülicher, currently a professor in Marburg, was born in 1857 in Falkenberg.

177.
W. Bousset, Jesus' preaching in contrast to Judaism. Göttingen, 1892.
178.

Ad. Jülicher, Die Gleichnisreden Jesu, 2nd pt. (Exposition of the Parables in the first three Gospels.) Freiburg, 1899, 641 pp.

Ad. Jülicher, The Teachings of Jesus, 2nd pt. (Exploration of the Parables in the first three Gospels.) Freiburg, 1899, 641 pp.

Chr. A. Bugge, Die Hauptparabeln Jesu (The most important Parables of Jesus), German, from the Norwegian, Giessen, 1903, rightly remarks on the obscure and inexplicable character of some of the parables, but makes no attempt to deal with it from the historical point of view.

Chr. A. Bugge, The Main Parables of Jesus (The most important Parables of Jesus), German, from the Norwegian, Giessen, 1903, accurately comments on the obscure and inexplicable nature of some of the parables but does not attempt to analyze it from a historical perspective.

179.
Arnold Meyer, Jesus' native language, 1896. P. W. Schmidt, too, in his The Story of Jesus (Freiburg, 1899), defends the same interpretation, and seeks to explain this obscure saying by the other about the "narrow gate."
180.
The Sermon of Jesus on the Kingdom of God, 2nd ed., 1900, p. 192 ff.
181.
Stud. Krit., 1836, pp. 90-122.
182.
See also The concepts of the Messiah and the Kingdom of God among the Synoptics. (The Conceptions of the Messiah and the Kingdom of God in the Synoptic Gospels.) By Ludwig Paul. Bonn, 1895. 130 pp. This comprehensive study discusses all the problems which are referred to below. Matt. xi. 12-14 is discussed under the heading "The Obstructers of the Kingdom of God."
183.
A. Hilgenfeld, Journal of Scientific Theology, 1888, pp. 488-498; 1892, pp. 445-464.
184.
Orello Cone, "Jesus' Self-Identification in the Synoptic Gospels," *The New World*, 1893, pp. 492-518.
185.
H. L. Oort, The expression ὁ υἱὸς τοῦ ἀνθρώπου in the New Testament. (The Expression Son of Man in the New Testament.) Leyden, 1893.
186.
R. H. Charles, “The Son of Man,” Expos. Times, 1893.
187.

Die jüdische Apokalyptik in ihrer religionsgeschichtlichen Herkunft und ihrer Bedeutung für das Neue Testament. (Jewish Apocalyptic in its religious-historical origin and in its significance for the New Testament.) 1903.

Jewish Apocalyptic in its religious and historical origins and its importance for the New Testament. 1903.

On the eschatology of Jesus see also Schwartzkoppf, Die Weissagungen Jesu Christi von seinen Tode, seiner Auferstehung und Wiederkunft und ihre Erfüllung. (The Predictions of Jesus Christ concerning His Death, His Resurrection, and Second Coming, and their Fulfilment.) 1895.

On the eschatology of Jesus, see also Schwartzkoppf, The prophecies of Jesus Christ about his death, resurrection, and return, and their fulfillment. (The Predictions of Jesus Christ concerning His Death, His Resurrection, and Second Coming, and their Fulfilment.) 1895.

P. Wernle, Die Reichgotteshofnung in den ältesten christlichen Dokumenten und bei Jesus. (The Hope of the Kingdom of God in the most ancient Christian Documents and as held by Jesus.)

P. Wernle, The Hope of God's Kingdom in the Oldest Christian Texts and as Taught by Jesus.

188.
Arnold Meyer, now Professor of New Testament Theology and Pastoral Theology at Zurich, and formerly at Bonn, was born at Wesel in 1861.
189.
Giambern. de Rossi, Thesis on the language of Christ and the national Jews of Palestine from the Time of the Maccabees, in examination of the views of a recent Italian writer. Parma, 1772.
190.
The account of Matthew regarding Jesus the Messiah. (Matthew's account of Jesus the Messiah.) Altona, 1792. According to Meyer, p. 105 ff., this was a very striking performance.
191.
The name Chaldee was due to the mistaken belief that the language in which parts of Daniel and Ezra were written was really the vernacular of Babylonia. That vernacular, now known to us from cuneiform tablets and inscriptions, is a Semitic language, but quite different from Aramaic.—F. C. B.
192.
Emil Friedrich Kautzsch was born in 1841 at Plauen in Saxony, and studied in Leipzig, where he became Privat-Docent in 1869. In 1872 he was called as Professor to Basle, in 1880 to Tübingen, in 1888 to Halle.
193.
Gustaf Dalman, Professor at Leipzig, was born in 1865 at Niesky. In addition to the works of his named above, see also The Suffering and Dying Messiah (The Suffering and Dying Messiah), 1888; and What does the Talmud say about Jesus? (What does the Talmud say about Jesus?), 1891.
194.
2 Kings xviii. 26 ff.
195.
Biblical Studies I. *Essays in Biblical Archaeology and Criticism and Related Subjects by Members of the University of Oxford*. Clarendon Press, 1885, pp. 39-74. See Meyer, p. 29 ff.
196.

Franz Delitzsch, Die Bücher des Neuen Testaments aus dem Griechischen ins Hebräische übersetzt. 1877. (The Books of the N.T. translated from Greek into Hebrew.) This work has been circulated by thousands among Jews throughout the whole world.

Franz Delitzsch, The New Testament Books Translated from Greek to Hebrew. 1877. This work has been distributed by thousands among Jews all over the world.

Delitzsch was born in 1813 at Leipzig and became Privat-Docent there in 1842, went to Rostock as Professor in 1846, to Erlangen in 1850, and returned in 1867 to Leipzig. By conviction he was a strict Lutheran in theology. He was one of the leading experts in Late-Jewish and Talmudic literature. He died in 1890.

Delitzsch was born in 1813 in Leipzig and became a Privat-Docent there in 1842. He moved to Rostock as a professor in 1846, went to Erlangen in 1850, and returned to Leipzig in 1867. He was a committed Lutheran in his theology. He was one of the top experts in Late Jewish and Talmudic literature. He died in 1890.

197.
See Meyer, p. 47 ff.
198.
See Meyer, p. 61 ff.
199.
Hans Lietzmann, now Professor in Jena, was born in 1875 at Düsseldorf. Until his call to Jena he worked as a Privat-Docent at Bonn. He has done some very meritorious work in the publication of Early Christian writings.
200.
See Meyer, p. 141 ff.
201.
"The Origin of the expression 'Son of Man' as an evangelical Messianic title," Theol. Journal., 1894. (The Origin of the Expression “Son of Man” as a Title of the Messiah in the Gospels.)
202.
H. Lietzmann, “About the Son of Man” (The Son-of-Man Problem), Theological Arb. of the Rhine Scientific Preachers' Association, 1898.
203.
N. Schmidt, “Was בן נשא a title related to the Messiah?” Journal of the Society for Biblical Literature, xv., 1896.
204.
P. Schmiedel, "The Name Son of Man and Jesus' Awareness of the Messiah" (The Designation Son of Man and the Messianic Consciousness of Jesus), 1898, Prot. Monthly 2, pp. 252-267.
205.
H. Gunkel, Z. w. Th., 1899, 42, pp. 581-611.
206.

For the last phase of the discussion we may name:

For the final phase of the discussion, we can call it:

Wellhausen, Skizzen und Vorarbeiten (Sketches and Studies), 1899, pp. 187-215, where he throws further light on Dalman's philological objections; and goes on to deny Jesus' use of the expression.

Wellhausen, Sketches and Preparations (Sketches and Studies), 1899, pp. 187-215, where he further explains Dalman's language-related objections and continues to argue against Jesus' use of the expression.

W. Baldensperger, “Die neueste Forschung über den Menschensohn,” Theol. Rundschau, 1900, 3, pp. 201-210, 243-255.

W. Baldensperger, "The Latest Research on the Son of Man," Theol. Review, 1900, 3, pp. 201-210, 243-255.

P. Fiebig, Der Menschensohn. Tübingen, 1901.

P. Fiebig, The Son of Man. Tübingen, 1901.

P. W. Schmiedel, “Die neueste Auffassung des Namens Menschensohn,” Prot. Monatsh. 5, pp. 333-351, 1901. (The Latest View of the Designation Son of Man.)

P. W. Schmiedel, “The Most Recent View on the Title Son of Man,” Prot. Monats. 5, pp. 333-351, 1901. (The Latest View of the Designation Son of Man.)

P. W. Schmidt, Die Geschichte Jesu, ii. (Erläuterungen—Explanations). Tübingen, 1904, p. 157 ff.

P. W. Schmidt, *The History of Jesus*, ii. (Explanations). Tübingen, 1904, p. 157 ff.

207.
Dalman's reputation as an authority upon Jewish Aramaic is so deservedly high, that it is necessary to point out that his solution did not, as Dr. Schweitzer seems to say, entirely dispose of the linguistic difficulties raised by Lietzmann as to the meaning and use of barnâsh and barnâshâ in Aramaic. The English reader will find the linguistic facts well put in sections 4 and 32 of N. Schmidt's article "Son of Man" in Biblical Encyclopedia (cols. 4708, 4723), or he may consult Prof. Bevan's review of Dalman's Words of Jesus in the Critical Review for 1899, p. 148 ff. The main point is that ὁ ἄνθρωπος and ὁ υἱὸς τοῦ ἀνθρώπου are equally legitimate translations of barnâshâ. Thus the contrast in the Greek between ὁ ἄνθρωπος and ὁ υἱὸς τοῦ ἀνθρώπου in Mark ii. 27 and 28, or again in Mark viii. 36 and 38, disappears on retranslation into the dialect spoken by Jesus. Whether this linguistic fact makes the sayings in which ὁ υἱὸς τοῦ ἀνθρώπου occurs unhistorical is a further question, upon which scholars can take, and have taken, opposite opinions.—F. C. B.
208.
See Words of Jesus, 1898, p. 191 ff. (= E. T. p. 234 ff.).
209.

See the classical discussion in J. Weiss, Die Predigt Jesus vom Reiche Gottes, 1892, 1st ed., p. 52 ff.

See the classical discussion in J. Weiss, The Sermon of Jesus on the Kingdom of God, 1892, 1st ed., p. 52 ff.

In the second edition, of 1900, p. 160 ff., he allows himself to be led astray by the “chiefest apostles” of modern theology to indulge in the subtleties of fine-spun psychology, and explain Jesus' way of speaking of Himself in the third person as the Son of Man as due to the “extreme modesty of Jesus,” a modesty which did not forsake Him in the presence of His judges. This recent access of psychologising exegesis has not conduced to clearness of presentation, and the preference for the Lucan narrative does not so much contribute to throw light on the facts as to discover in the thoughts of Jesus subtleties of which the historical Jesus never dreamt. If the Lord always used the term Son of Man when speaking of His Messiahship, the reason was that this was the only way in which He could speak of it at all, since the Messiahship was not yet realised, but was only to be so at the appearing of the Son of Man. For a consistent, purely historical, non-psychological exposition of the Son-of-Man passages see Albert Schweitzer, Das Messianitäts- und Leidensgeheimnis. (The Secret of the Messiahship and the Passion.) A sketch of the Life of Jesus. Tübingen, 1901.

In the second edition, from 1900, p. 160 ff., he allows himself to be misled by the "top apostles" of modern theology to delve into the complexities of fine-grained psychology, explaining Jesus' reference to Himself in the third person as the Son of Man as a result of the "Jesus's extreme humility," a modesty that did not abandon Him in front of His judges. This recent tendency toward psychological interpretation has not enhanced clarity of presentation, and the preference for the Lucan narrative does not necessarily illuminate the facts but instead attempts to uncover subtleties in Jesus' thoughts that the historical Jesus never considered. If the Lord consistently used the term Son of Man when referring to His role as Messiah, it was because this was the only way He could articulate it, since the Messiahship was not yet fulfilled but would be realized with the arrival of the Son of Man. For a consistent, purely historical, non-psychological analysis of the Son-of-Man passages, see Albert Schweitzer, The mystery of Messiah and suffering. (The Secret of the Messiahship and the Passion.) A sketch of the Life of Jesus. Tübingen, 1901.

210.

See Dalman, p. 60 ff.

See Dalman, p. 60 and following.

John Lightfoot, Horae Hebraicae et Talmudicae in quatuor Evangelistas. Edited by J. B. Carpzov. Leipzig, 1684.

John Lightfoot, Hebrew and Talmudic Hours on the Four Gospels. Edited by J. B. Carpzov. Leipzig, 1684.

Christian Schöttgen, Horae Hebraicae et Talmudicae in universum Novum Testamentum. Dresden-Leipzig, 1733.

Christian Schöttgen, Hebrew and Talmudic Hours in the Entire New Testament. Dresden-Leipzig, 1733.

Joh. Gerh. Meuschen, Novum Testamentum ex Talmude et antiquitatibus Hebraeorum illustratum. Leipzig, 1736.

Joh. Gerh. Meuschen, The New Testament Explained by the Talmud and the Antiquities of the Hebrews. Leipzig, 1736.

J. Jakob. Wettstein, Novum Testamentum Graecum. Amsterdam, 1751 and 1752.

J. Jakob. Wettstein, New Testament Greek. Amsterdam, 1751 and 1752.

F. Nork, Rabbinische Quellen und Parallelen zu neutestamentlichen Schriftstellen, Leipzig, 1839.

F. Nork, Rabbinic Sources and Parallels to New Testament Texts, Leipzig, 1839.

Franz Delitzsch, “Horae Hebraicae et Talmudicae,” in the Luth. Zeitsch., 1876-1878.

Franz Delitzsch, “Hebrew and Talmudic Hours,” in the Luth. Journal, 1876-1878.

Carl Siegfried, Analecta Rabbinica, 1875; “Rabbin. Analekten,” Jahrb. f. prot. Theol., 1876.

Carl Siegfried, Rabbinic Anthology, 1875; “Rabbin. Analects,” Journal for Protestant Theology, 1876.

A. Wünsche, Neue Beiträge zur Erläuterung der Evangelien aus Talmud und Midrasch. (Contributions to the Exposition of the Gospels from Talmud and Midrash.) Göttingen, 1878.

A. Wünsche, New Insights into the Gospels from Talmud and Midrash. (Contributions to the Exposition of the Gospels from Talmud and Midrash.) Göttingen, 1878.

211.
Leipzig, 1880; 2nd ed., 1897.
212.
Cf. for what follows, Jülicher, The Parables of Jesus, i., 1888, p. 164 ff.
213.
Robert Sheringham of Caius College, Cambridge, a royalist divine, published an edition of the Talmudic tractate Yoma. London, 1648.—F. C. B.
214.
T. Tal, Professor Oort and the Talmud, 1880. See upon this Van Manen, Yearbook of Protestant Theology, 1884, p. 569. The best collection of Talmudic parables is, according to Jülicher, that of Prof. Guis. Levi, translated by L. Seligman as Parables, Legends and Thoughts from the Talmud and Midrash. Leipzig, 2nd ed., 1877.
215.
The question may be said to have been provisionally settled by Paul Fiebig's work, Ancient Jewish Parables and the Parables of Jesus (Ancient Jewish Parables and the Parables of Jesus), Tübingen, 1904, in which he gives some fifty Late-Jewish parables, and compares them with those of Jesus, the final result being to show more clearly than ever the uniqueness and absoluteness of His creations.
216.
See the explanation by means of the Aramaic of a selection of the sayings of Jesus in Meyer, pp. 72-90. A Judaism more under Parsee influence is assumed as explaining the origin of Christianity by E. Böklen, The relationship between Jewish-Christian and Persian eschatology (The Relation of Jewish-Christian to Persian Eschatology), 1902, 510 ff.
217.
The same view is expressed by Wellhausen, Israeli and Jewish history, 3rd ed., p. 381, note 2; and by Albert Schweitzer, The mystery of messianicity and suffering, 1901.
218.
See the Apocalypse of Baruch, and Fourth Ezra.
219.
The Unknown Life of Jesus Christ, par Nicolas Notowitsch. Paris, 1894.
220.
See Jülicher, Parables of Jesus, i., 1888, p. 172 ff.
221.
Max Müller, India, what can it teach us? London, 1883, p. 279.
222.

Rudolf Seydel, Professor in the University of Leipzig, Das Evangelium von Jesu in seinen Verhältnissen zu Buddha-Sage und Buddha-Lehre mit fortlaufender Rücksicht auf andere Religionskreise. (The Gospel of Jesus in its relation to the Buddha Legend and the Teaching of Buddha, with constant reference to other religious groups.) Leipzig, 1882, p. 337.

Rudolf Seydel, Professor at the University of Leipzig, The Gospel of Jesus in relation to the Buddha Legend and the Teachings of Buddha, while consistently referring to other religious groups. Leipzig, 1882, p. 337.

Other works by the same author are Buddha und Christus. Deutsche Bücherei No. 33, Breslau, Schottländer, 1884.

Other works by the same author are Buddha and Christ. Deutsche Bücherei No. 33, Breslau, Schottländer, 1884.

Die Buddha-Legende und das Leben Jesu nach den Evangelien. 2nd ed. Weimar, 1897. (Edited by the son of the late author.) 129 pp.

The Buddha Legend and the Life of Jesus According to the Gospels. 2nd ed. Weimar, 1897. (Edited by the late author's son.) 129 pp.

See also on this question Van den Bergh van Eysinga, Indische Einflüsse auf evangelische Erzählungen. Göttingen, 1904. 104 pp.

See also on this question Van den Bergh van Eysinga, *Indian Influences on Protestant Stories*. Göttingen, 1904. 104 pp.

According to J. M. Robertson, Christianity and Mythology (London, 1900), the Christ-Myth is merely a form of the Krishna-Myth. The whole Gospel tradition is to be symbolically interpreted.

According to J. M. Robertson, Christianity and Mythology (London, 1900), the Christ-Myth is just a version of the Krishna-Myth. The entire Gospel tradition should be understood symbolically.

223.
The Christianity of the New Testament, 1905.
224.
Heinrich Julius Holtzmann, Hand commentary. The Synoptics. 1st ed., 1889; 3rd ed., 1901. Textbook of New Testament Theology, 1896, vol. i.
225.

In the Catholic Church the study of the Life of Jesus has remained down to the present day entirely free from scepticism. The reason of that is, that in principle it has remained at a pre-Straussian standpoint, and does not venture upon an unreserved application of historical considerations either to the miracle question or to the Johannine question, and naturally therefore resigns the attempt to take account of and explain the great historical problems.

In the Catholic Church, the study of Jesus' life has remained completely free from skepticism to this day. The reason for this is that, in principle, it has maintained a viewpoint that predates Strauss and does not fully apply historical considerations to either the issue of miracles or the Johannine question. As a result, it naturally gives up the effort to consider and explain the significant historical problems.

We may name the following Lives of Jesus produced by German Catholic writers:—

We can list the following biographies of Jesus created by German Catholic writers:—

Joh. Nep. Sepp, Das Leben Jesu Christi. Regensburg, 1843-1846. 7 vols., 2nd ed., 1853-1862.

Joh. Nep. Sepp, The Life of Jesus. Regensburg, 1843-1846. 7 vols., 2nd ed., 1853-1862.

Peter Schegg, Sechs Bücher des Lebens Jesu. (The Life of Jesus in Six Books.) Freiburg, 1874-1875. c. 1200 pp.

Peter Schegg, Six Books about the Life of Jesus. (The Life of Jesus in Six Books.) Freiburg, 1874-1875. approx. 1200 pp.

Joseph Grimm, Das Leben Jesu. Würzburg, 2nd ed., 1890-1903. 6 vols.

Joseph Grimm, The Life of Jesus. Würzburg, 2nd ed., 1890-1903. 6 vols.

Richard von Kralik, Jesu Leben und Werk. Kempten-Nürnberg, 1904. 481 pp.

Richard von Kralik, The Life and Work of Jesus. Kempten-Nürnberg, 1904. 481 pp.

W. Capitaine, Jesus von Nazareth. Regensburg, 1905. 192 pp.

W. Captain, Jesus from Nazareth. Regensburg, 1905. 192 pp.

How narrow are the limits within which the Catholic study of the life of Jesus moves even when it aims at scientific treatment, is illustrated by Hermann Schell's Christus (Mainz, 1903. 152 pp.). After reading the forty-two questions with which he introduces his narrative one might suppose that the author was well aware of the bearing of all the historical problems of the life of Jesus, and intended to supply an answer to them. Instead of doing so, however, he adopts as the work proceeds more and more the rôle of an apologist, not facing definitely either the miracle question or the Johannine question, but gliding over the difficulties by the aid of ingenious headings, so that in the end his book almost takes the form of an explanatory text to the eighty-nine illustrations which adorn the book and make it difficult to read.

How limited the Catholic study of Jesus' life is, even when it seeks a scientific analysis, is shown by Hermann Schell's Christ (Mainz, 1903. 152 pp.). After going through the forty-two questions he presents at the start of his narrative, one might think the author is fully aware of the historical issues surrounding Jesus' life and intends to address them. However, as the work progresses, he increasingly takes on the role of an apologist, avoiding a clear discussion on the miracle question or the Johannine question, instead skimming over the challenges with clever headings. In the end, his book almost reads like an explanatory guide to the eighty-nine illustrations that fill the book and make it hard to follow.

In France, Renan's work gave the incentive to an extensive Catholic “Life-of-Jesus” literature. We may name the following:—

In France, Renan's work inspired a large amount of Catholic "Life of Jesus" literature. Here are some examples:—

Louis Veuillot, La Vie de notre Seigneur Jésus-Christ. Paris, 1864. 509 pp. German by Waldeyer. Köln-Neuss, 1864. 573 pp.

Louis Veuillot, The Life of Our Lord Jesus Christ. Paris, 1864. 509 pp. Translated by Waldeyer. Köln-Neuss, 1864. 573 pp.

H. Wallon, Vie de notre Seigneur Jésus-Christ. Paris, 1865. 355 pp.

H. Wallon, The Life of Our Lord Jesus Christ. Paris, 1865. 355 pp.

A work which met with a particularly favourable reception was that of Père Didon, the Dominican, Jésus-Christ, Paris, 1891, 2 vols., vol. i. 483 pp., vol. ii. 469 pp. The German translation is dated 1895.

A work that received a particularly positive reception was by Père Didon, the Dominican, Jesus Christ, Paris, 1891, 2 vols., vol. i. 483 pp., vol. ii. 469 pp. The German translation is from 1895.

In the same year there appeared a new edition of the “Bitter Sufferings of Our Lord Jesus Christ” (see above, p. 109 f.) by Katharina Emmerich; the cheap popular edition of the translation of Renan's “Life of Jesus”; and the eighth edition of Strauss's “Life of Jesus for the German People.”

In the same year, a new edition of the "Bitter Sufferings of Our Lord Jesus Christ" (see above, p. 109 f.) by Katharina Emmerich was released; a budget-friendly popular edition of the translation of Renan's "Life of Jesus"; and the eighth edition of Strauss's “Life of Jesus for the German People.”

We may quote from the ecclesiastical Approbation printed at the beginning of Didon's Life of Jesus. “If the author sometimes seems to speak the language of his opponents, it is at once evident that he has aimed at defeating them on their own ground, and he is particularly successful in doing so when he confronts their irreligious a priori theories with the positive arguments of history.”

We can quote from the church's Approval printed at the beginning of Didon's Life of Jesus. “If the author sometimes uses the language of his opponents, it's obvious that he intends to confront them in their own space, and he's particularly effective at this when he counters their irreligious beliefs with strong historical evidence.”

As a matter of fact the work is skilfully written, but without a spark of understanding of the historical questions.

Actually, the work is well-written, but it lacks any insight into the historical issues.

All honour to Alfred Loisy! (Le Quatrième Évangile, Paris, 1903, 960 pp.), who takes a clear view on the Johannine question, and denies the existence of a Johannine historical tradition. But what that means for the Catholic camp may be recognised from the excitement produced by the book and its express condemnation. See also the same writer's L'Évangile et l'Église (German translation, Munich, 1904, 189 pp.), in which Loisy here and there makes good historical points against Harnack's “What is Christianity?”

All respect to Alfred Loisy! (The Fourth Gospel, Paris, 1903, 960 pp.), who offers a clear perspective on the Johannine question and rejects the idea of a Johannine historical tradition. The impact this has on the Catholic community can be seen in the stir caused by the book and its explicit condemnation. Also, check out the same author's The Gospel and the Church (German translation, Munich, 1904, 189 pp.), where Loisy occasionally makes strong historical arguments against Harnack's "What is Christianity?"

226.
Oskar Holtzmann, Professor of Theology at Giessen, was born in 1859 at Stuttgart.
227.
This suggestion reminds us involuntarily of the old rationalistic Lives of Jesus, which are distressed that Jesus should have injured the good people of the country of the Gesarenes by sacrificing their swine in healing the demoniac. A good deal of old rationalistic material crops up in the very latest Lives of Jesus, as cannot indeed fail to be the case in view of the arbitrary interpretation of detail which is common to both. According to Oskar Holtzmann the barren fig-tree has also a symbolical meaning. “It’s a promise from God to Jesus that His faith won’t be embarrassed in the significant work of His life.”
228.
Isaiah lxii. 11, "Tell the daughter of Zion, 'Look, your salvation is coming.'"
229.
“For Jesus Himself,” Oskar Holtzmann argues, "this finding"—he means the antinomy which He had discovered in Psalm cx.—"resolved a doubt that had always troubled him. If He had truly known He was from the Davidic line, He definitely wouldn't have publicly questioned the Davidic ancestry of the Messiah."
230.
Oskar Holtzmann's work, War Jesus Ekstatiker? (Tübingen, 1903, 139 pp.) is in reality a new reading of the life of Jesus. By emphasising the ecstatic element he breaks with the "organic" conception of the life and teaching of Jesus; and, in so far, approaches the eschatological view. But he gives a very wide significance to the term ecstatic, subsuming under it, it might almost be said, all the eschatological thoughts and utterances of Jesus. He explains, for instance, that "The belief in the imminent end of current circumstances is exhilarating." At the same time, the only purpose served by the hypothesis of ecstasy is to enable the author to attribute to Jesus "The belief that the Kingdom of God was already starting in His work and the promise of the Kingdom to individuals can only be seen as ecstatic." The opposites which Bousset brings together by the conception of paradox are united by Holtzmann by means of the hypothesis of ecstasy. That is, however, to play fast and loose with the meaning of “ecstasy.” An ecstasy is, in the usual understanding of the word, an abnormal, transient condition of excitement in which the subject's natural capacity for thought and feeling, and therewith all impressions from without, are suspended, being superseded by an intense mental excitation and activity. Jesus may possibly have been in an ecstatic state at His baptism and at the transfiguration. What O. Holtzmann represents as a kind of permanent ecstatic state is rather an eschatological fixed idea. With eschatology, ecstasy has no essential connexion. It is possible to be eschatologically minded without being an ecstatic, and vice versa. Philo attributes a great importance to ecstasy in his religious life, but he was scarcely, if at all, interested in eschatology.
231.
P. W. Schmidt, now Professor in Basle, was born in Berlin in 1845.
232.

Otto Schmiedel, Professor at the Gymnasium at Eisenach, Die Hauptprobleme der Leben-Jesu-Forschung. Tübingen, 1902. 71 pp. Schmiedel was born in 1858.

Otto Schmiedel, Professor at the Gymnasium in Eisenach, The Key Issues in Studying the Life of Jesus. Tübingen, 1902. 71 pp. Schmiedel was born in 1858.

Hermann Freiherr von Soden, Die wichtigsten Fragen im Leben Jesu. Von Soden, Professor in Berlin, and preacher at the Jerusalem Kirche, was born in 1852.

Hermann Freiherr von Soden, The Key Questions in the Life of Jesus. Von Soden, a professor in Berlin and preacher at the Jerusalem Church, was born in 1852.

We may mention also the following works:—

We can also mention the following works:—

Fritz Barth (born 1856, Professor at Bern), Die Hauptprobleme des Lebens Jesu. 1st ed., 1899; 2nd ed., 1903.

Fritz Barth (born 1856, Professor at Bern), The Key Issues in Jesus' Life. 1st ed., 1899; 2nd ed., 1903.

Friedrich Nippold's Der Entwicklungsgang des Lebens Jesu im Wortlaut der drei ersten Evangelien (The Course of the Life of Jesus in the Words of the First Three Evangelists) (Hamburg, 1895, 213 pp.) is only an arrangement of the sections.

Friedrich Nippold's The Development of Jesus' Life in the Text of the First Three Gospels (The Course of the Life of Jesus in the Words of the First Three Evangelists) (Hamburg, 1895, 213 pp.) is just a structured compilation of the sections.

Konrad Furrer's Vorträge über das Leben Jesu Christi (Lectures on the Life of Jesus Christ) have a special charm by reason of the author's knowledge of the country and the locality. Furrer, who was born in 1838, is Professor at Zurich.

Konrad Furrer's Lectures on the Life of Jesus Christ (Lectures on the Life of Jesus Christ) has a unique appeal due to the author's familiarity with the region and its surroundings. Furrer, born in 1838, is a professor in Zurich.

Another work which should not be forgotten is R. Otto's Leben und Wirken Jesu nach historisch-kritischer Auffassung (Life and Work of Jesus from the Point of View of Historical Criticism). A Lecture. Göttingen, 1902. Rudolf Otto, born in 1869, is Privat-Docent at Göttingen.

Another work that shouldn't be overlooked is R. Otto's The Life and Work of Jesus from a Historical-Critical Perspective (Life and Work of Jesus from the Perspective of Historical Criticism). A Lecture. Göttingen, 1902. Rudolf Otto, born in 1869, is a private lecturer at Göttingen.

233.
Schmiedel is not altogether right in making “Professor Paulus of Heidelberg” follow the same lines as Reimarus, “except that his works from 1804 and 1828 are less harmful, but they're just more boring because of it.” In reality the deistic Life of Jesus by Reimarus, and the rationalistic Life by Paulus have nothing in common. Paulus was perhaps influenced by Venturini, but not by Reimarus. The assertion that Strauss wrote his "Life of Jesus for the German people" because "Renan's fame brought him no peace." is not justified, either by Strauss's character or by the circumstances in which the second Life of Jesus was produced.
234.

Von Soden gives on pp. 24 ff. the passages of Mark which he supposes to be derived from the Petrine tradition in a different order from that in which they occur in Mark, regrouping them freely. He puts together, for instance, Mark i. 16-20, iii. 13-19, vi. 7-16, viii. 27-ix. 1, ix. 33-40, under the title “The formation and training of the band of disciples.” He supposes Mark, the pupil of Peter, to have grouped in this way by a kind of association of ideas “what he had heard Peter relate in his missionary journeys, when writing it down after Peter's death, not connectedly, but giving as much as he could remember of it”; this would be in accordance with the statement of Papias that Mark wrote “not in order.” Papias's statement, therefore, refers to an “Ur-Markus,” which he found lacking in historical order.

Von Soden presents on pages 24 and following the passages from Mark that he believes come from the Petrine tradition, arranged differently than they appear in Mark, and he reorganizes them quite freely. For example, he combines Mark 1:16-20, 3:13-19, 6:7-16, 8:27-9:1, and 9:33-40 under the heading "The creation and training of the group of followers." He theorizes that Mark, Peter's student, grouped these passages based on a kind of association of ideas, "what he had heard Peter share during his missionary trips, when he was writing it down after Peter's death, not in a connected way, but noting as much as he could recall." This aligns with Papias's statement that Mark wrote “out of order.” Therefore, Papias's comment pertains to an “Ur-Markus,” which he found to lack historical order.

But what are we to make of a representative of the early Church thus approaching the Gospels with the demand for historical arrangement? And good, simple old Papias, of all people!

But what are we supposed to think about an early Church representative approaching the Gospels with a demand for historical organization? And good, simple old Papias, of all people!

But if the Marcan plan was not laid down in “Ur-Markus,” there is nothing for it—since the plan was certainly not given in the collection of Logia—but to ascribe it to the author of our Gospel of Mark, to the man, that is, who wrote down for the first time these “Pauline conceptions,” those reflections of experiences of individual believers and of the community, and inserted them into the Gospel. It is proposed, then, to retain the outline which he has given of the life of Jesus, and reject at the same time what he relates. That is to say, he is to be believed where it is convenient to believe him, and silenced where it is inconvenient. No more complete refutation of the Marcan hypothesis could possibly be given than this analysis, for it destroys its very foundation, the confident acceptance of the historicity of the Marcan plan.

But if the Marcan plan wasn't established in "Original Markus" there's nothing we can do—since the plan definitely wasn't provided in the collection of Logia—other than to attribute it to the author of our Gospel of Mark, the person, that is, who first recorded these “Pauline beliefs,” the reflections of experiences from individual believers and the community, and incorporated them into the Gospel. It is suggested, then, to keep the outline he provided of Jesus' life while disregarding what he recounts. In other words, we should believe him where it's convenient and ignore him where it's not. Nothing could more thoroughly disprove the Marcan hypothesis than this analysis, as it undermines its very foundation—the confident acceptance of the historicity of the Marcan plan.

If there is to be an analysis of sources in Mark, then the Marcan plan must be ascribed to “Ur-Markus,” otherwise the analysis renders the Markan hypothesis historically useless. But if “Ur-Markus” is to be reconstructed on the basis of assigning to it the Marcan plan, then we cannot separate the natural from the supernatural, for the supernatural scenes, like the feeding of the multitude and the transfiguration, are among the main features of the Marcan outline.

If we’re going to analyze the sources in Mark, then we need to attribute the Marcan plan to "Ur-Markus," or else the analysis makes the Markan hypothesis historically irrelevant. However, if we’re reconstructing "Original Markus" based on the Marcan plan, we can’t separate the natural from the supernatural, because the supernatural events, like the feeding of the multitude and the transfiguration, are key elements of the Marcan outline.

No hypothetical analysis of “Ur-Markus” has escaped this dilemma; what it can effect by literary methods is historically useless, and what would be historically useful cannot be attained nor “presented” by literary methods.

No hypothetical analysis of “Ur-Markus” has avoided this dilemma; what it can achieve through literary techniques is historically pointless, and what would be historically valuable cannot be achieved or "shown" through literary techniques.

235.

Von Soden, for instance, germanises Jesus when he writes, “and this nature is sound to the core. In spite of its inwardness there is no trace of an exaggerated sentimentality. In spite of all the intensity of prayer there is nothing of ecstasy or vision. No apocalyptic dream-pictures find a lodging-place in His soul.”

Von Soden, for instance, adds a German touch to Jesus when he writes, "and this nature is entirely sound. Even with its depth, there's no trace of excessive sentimentality. Despite the intensity of prayer, there are no feelings of ecstasy or visions. No apocalyptic dream images exist in His soul."

Is a man who teaches a world-renouncing ethic which sometimes soars to the dizzy heights such as that of Matt. xix. 12, according to our conceptions “sound to the core”? And does not the life of Jesus present a number of occasions on which He seems to have been in an ecstasy?

Is a man who teaches a world-renouncing ethic that sometimes reaches dizzying heights, like in Matt. xix. 12, according to our understanding “sound to the core”? And doesn't the life of Jesus show several moments when He appears to have been in an ecstasy?

Thus, von Soden has not simply read his Jesus out of the texts, but has added something of his own, and that something is Germanic in colouring.

Thus, von Soden has not just read his version of Jesus from the texts, but has added something of his own, and that something has a Germanic influence.

236.
i.e. the MS. Life of Jesus written by Kai Jans, one of the characters of the novel. The way in which the whole life-experience of this character prepares him for the writing of the Life is strikingly—if not always acceptably—worked out.—Translator.
237.
Frenssen's Kai Jans professes to have used the "results of all aspects of critical investigation” in writing his work. Among the books which he enumerates and recommends in the after-word, we miss the works of Strauss, Weisse, Keim, Volkmar, and Brandt, and, generally speaking, the names of those who in the past have done something really great and original. Of the moderns, Johannes Weiss is lacking. Wrede is mentioned, but is virtually ignored. Pfleiderer's remarkable and profound presentation of Jesus in the Early Christianity (E. T. “Early Christianity,” vol. ii., 1909) is non-existent so far as he is concerned.
238.
Local art, the ideal that every production of German art should be racy of the soil. It has its relative justification as a protest against the long subservience of some departments of German art to French taste.—Translator.
239.
The Jesus of H. S. Chamberlain's Words of Christ, 1901, 286 pp., is also modern. But the modernity is not so obtrusive, because he describes only the teaching of Jesus, not His life.
240.
Born in 1839 at Stettin. Studied at Tübingen, was appointed Professor in 1870 at Jena and in 1875 at Berlin. (Died 1908.)
241.
Early Christianity, its writings and teachings described in a historical context. 2nd ed. Berlin, 1902. Vol. i. (696 pp.), 615 ff.: The Sermon of Jesus and the Faith of the Early Church (English Translation, "Early Christianity," chap. xvi.). Pfleiderer's latest views are set forth in his work, based on academic lectures, The origins of early Christianity. (How Christianity arose.) Munich, 1905. 255 pp.
242.

Albert Kalthoff, Das Christusproblem. Grundlinien zu einer Sozialtheologie. (The Problem of the Christ: Ground-plan of a Social Theology.) Leipzig, 1902. 87 pp.

Albert Kalthoff, The Christ Problem. Foundations of a Social Theology. (The Problem of the Christ: Ground-plan of a Social Theology.) Leipzig, 1902. 87 pp.

Die Entstehung des Christentums. Neue Beiträge zum Christusproblem. (How Christianity arose.) Leipzig, 1904. 155 pp.

The Origins of Christianity: New Insights into the Christ Issue. (How Christianity arose.) Leipzig, 1904. 155 pp.

Albert Kalthoff was born in 1850 at Barmen, and is engaged in pastoral work in Bremen.

Albert Kalthoff was born in 1850 in Barmen and is involved in pastoral work in Bremen.

243.
The Life of Jesus. Lectures delivered before the Protestant Reform Society at Berlin. Berlin, 1880. 173 pp.
244.
If Kalthoff would only have spoken of the conception of the resurrection instead of the conception of immortality! Then his subjective knowledge would have been more or less tolerable.
245.

Against Kalthoff: Wilhelm Bousset, Was wissen wir von Jesus? (What do we know about Jesus?) Lectures delivered before the Protestantenverein at Bremen. Halle, 1904. 73 pp. In reply: Albert Kalthoff, Was wissen wir von Jesus? A settlement of accounts with Professor Bousset. Berlin, 1904. 43 pp.

Against Kalthoff: Wilhelm Bousset, What Do We Know About Jesus? Lectures given before the Protestant Association in Bremen. Halle, 1904. 73 pages. In response: Albert Kalthoff, What Do We Know About Jesus? A response to Professor Bousset. Berlin, 1904. 43 pages.

A sound historical position is set forth in the clear and trenchant lecture of W. Kapp, Das Christus- und Christentumsproblem bei Kalthoff. (The problem of the Christ and of Christianity as handled by Kalthoff.) Strassburg, 1905. 23 pp.

A solid historical standpoint is presented in the clear and sharp lecture by W. Kapp, The Problem of Christ and Christianity in KALTHOFF. (The problem of Christ and Christianity as discussed by Kalthoff.) Strassburg, 1905. 23 pp.

246.
Eduard von Hartmann, The Christianity of the New Testament. (The Christianity of the N.T.) 2nd, revised and altered, edition of the "Letters on Christianity." Sachsa-in-the-Harz, 1905. 311 pp.
247.
Eduard von Hartmann ought, therefore, to have given his assistance to the others who have made this assertion in proving that there really existed Messianic claimants before and at the time of Jesus.
248.

“Jesus,” by Jülicher, in Die Kultur der Gegenwart. (An encyclopaedic publication which is appearing in parts.) Teubner, Berlin, 1905, pp. 40-69.

“Jesus,” by Jülicher, in Today's Culture. (An encyclopedic publication that is being released in parts.) Teubner, Berlin, 1905, pp. 40-69.

See also W. Bousset, “Jesus,” Religionsgeschichtliche Volksbücher. (A series of religious-historical monographs.) Published by Schiele, Halle, 1904.

See also W. Bousset, “Jesus,” Religious History Folk Books. (A series of religious-historical monographs.) Published by Schiele, Halle, 1904.

Here should be mentioned also the thoughtful book, following very much the lines of Jülicher, by Eduard Grimm, entitled Die Ethik Jesu, Hamburg, 1903, 288 pp. The author, born in 1848, is the chief pastor at the Nicolaikirche in Hamburg.

Here should be mentioned the insightful book, closely following the ideas of Jülicher, by Eduard Grimm, titled The Ethics of Jesus, Hamburg, 1903, 288 pp. The author, who was born in 1848, is the lead pastor at the Nicolaikirche in Hamburg.

Another work which deserves mention is Arno Neumann, Jesu wie er geschichtlich war (Jesus as he historically existed), Freiburg, 1904, 198 pp. (New Paths to the Old God), a Life of Jesus distinguished by a lofty vein of natural poetry and based upon solid theological knowledge. Arno Neumann is headmaster of a school at Apolda.

Another work worth mentioning is Arno Neumann, Jesus as he historically was (Jesus as he historically existed), Freiburg, 1904, 198 pp. (New Paths to the Old God), a biography of Jesus characterized by a noble sense of natural poetry and grounded in strong theological knowledge. Arno Neumann is the principal of a school in Apolda.

249.
Jeshua. The classic Jewish man. Destruction of the church's image, revelation of the Jewish picture of Jesus. Berlin, 1904, 112 pp. Earlier studies of the Life of Jesus from the Jewish point of view had been less ambitious. Dr. Aug. Wünsche had written in 1872 on "Jesus and His attitude toward women" from the Talmudic standpoint (146 pp.), and had described Him from the same standpoint as a Jesus who rejoiced in life, The joyful Jesus of the synoptic gospels in contrast to the suffering Messiah of the Church. Leipzig, 1876, 444 pp. The basis is so far correct, that the eschatological, world-renouncing ethic which we find in Jesus was due to temporary conditions and is therefore transitory, and had nothing whatever to do with Judaism as such. The spirit of the Law is the opposite of world-renouncing. But the Talmud, be its traditions never so trustworthy, could teach us little about Jesus because it has preserved scarcely a trace of that eschatological phase of Jewish religion and ethics.
250.
Wolfgang Kirchbach, What did Jesus teach? Two early gospels. Berlin, 1897, 248 pp.; second greatly enlarged and improved edition, 1902, 339 pp. By the same author, The Book of Jesus. The Urevangelien. Newly documented, translated, organized, and explained from the original language. (The Book of Jesus. The Primitive Gospels. Newly traced, translated, arranged, and explained on the basis of the original.) Berlin, 1897.
251.
Before him, Hugo Delff, in his The History of Rabbi Jesus of Nazareth (Leipzig, 1889, 428 pp.), had confined himself to the Fourth Gospel, and even within that Gospel he drew some critical distinctions. His Jesus at first conceals His Messiahship from the fear of arousing the political expectations of the people, and speaks to them of the Son of Man in the third person. At His second visit to Jerusalem He breaks with the rulers, is subsequently compelled, in consequence of the conflict over the Sabbath, to leave Galilee, and then gives up His own people and turns to the heathen. Delff explains the raising of Lazarus by supposing him to have been buried in a state of trance.
252.
Albert Dulk, The Journey of Jesus' Life. Presented from a historical perspective. First part: The historical roots and the Galilean flourishing., 1884. 395 pp. Part Two: The Entry of the Messiah and the Elevation on the Cross, 1885, 302 pp. (The Error of the Life of Jesus. Historically apprehended and set forth. Pt. i., The Historical Roots and the Galilaean Blossom. Pt. ii., The Messianic Entry and the Crucifixion.) The course of Dulk's own life was somewhat erratic. Born in 1819, he came prominently forward in the revolution of 1848, as a political pamphleteer and agitator. Later, though almost without means, he undertook long journeys, even to Sinai and to Lapland. Finally, he worked as a social democratic reformer. He died in 1884.
253.
A scientific treatment of this subject is supplied by Fr. Nippold, The psychiatric aspect of Jesus' healing ministry (The Psychiatric Side of Jesus' Works of Healing), 1889, in which a luminous review of the medical material is to be found. See also Dr. K. Kunz, Christ the healer, Freiburg in Baden, 1905, 74 pp. The scientific value of this work is, however, very much reduced by the fact that the author has no acquaintance with the preliminary questions belonging to the sphere of history and literature, and regards all the miracles of healing as actual events, believing himself able to explain them from the medical point of view. The tendency of the work is mainly apologetic.
254.
Jesus of Nazareth. An Analysis from the Scientific, Historical, and Social Perspectives. Translated from the French (into German) by A. Just. Leipzig, 1894. The author, whose real name is P. A. Desjardin, is a practising physician. De Régla, too, makes the Fourth Gospel the basis of his narrative.
255.
Pierre Nahor (Emilie Lerou), Jesus. Translated from the French by Walter Bloch. Berlin, 1905. Its motto is: The figure of Jesus belongs, like all mysterious, heroic, or mythical figures, to legend and poetry. In the introduction we find the statement, "This book is a declaration of faith." The narrative is based on the Fourth Gospel.
256.

La Vie inconnue de Jésus-Christ. Paris, 1894. 301 pp. German, under the title Die Lücke im Leben Jesu (The Gap in the Life of Jesus). Stuttgart, 1894. 186 pp. See Holtzmann in the Theol. Jahresbericht, xiv. p. 140.

The Unknown Life of Jesus Christ. Paris, 1894. 301 pages. German edition, titled The Gap in the Life of Jesus, Stuttgart, 1894. 186 pages. See Holtzmann in the Theology Yearly Report, xiv. p. 140.

In a certain limited sense the work of A. Lillie, The Influence of Buddhism on Primitive Christianity (London, 1893), is to be numbered among the fictitious works on the life of Jesus. The fictitious element consists in Jesus being made an Essene by the writer, and Essenism equated with Buddhism.

In a specific way, A. Lillie's work, The Impact of Buddhism on Early Christianity (London, 1893), can be categorized as one of the fictional accounts of Jesus's life. The fictional aspect lies in the author's portrayal of Jesus as an Essene and the association of Essenism with Buddhism.

Among “edifying” romances on the life of Jesus intended for family reading, that of the English writer J. H. Ingraham, The Prince of the House of David, has had a very long lease of life. It appeared in a German translation as early as 1858, and was reissued in 1906 (Brunswick).

Among “enlightening” stories about the life of Jesus meant for family reading, the work by English author J. H. Ingraham, The Prince of the House of David, has had a remarkably long lifespan. It was translated into German as early as 1858 and was reissued in 1906 (Brunswick).

A fictitious life of Jesus of wonderful beauty is Peter Rosegger's I.N.R.I. Frohe Botschaft eines armen Sünders (The Glad Tidings of a poor Sinner). Leipzig, 6th-10th thousand, 1906. 293 pp.

A fictional account of Jesus that's beautifully written is Peter Rosegger's I.N.R.I. Good News from a Poor Sinner (The Glad Tidings of a Poor Sinner). Leipzig, 6th-10th thousand, 1906. 293 pp.

A feminine point of view reveals itself in C. Rauch's Jeschua ben Joseph. Deichert, 1899.

A feminine perspective is highlighted in C. Rauch's Jesus son of Joseph. Deichert, 1899.

257.

La Vie ésotérique de Jésu-Christ et les origines orientales du christianisme. Paris, 1902. 445 pp.

The Hidden Life of Jesus Christ and the Eastern Roots of Christianity. Paris, 1902. 445 pp.

That Jesus was of Aryan race is argued by A. Müller, who assumes a Gaulish immigration into Galilee. Jesus ein Arier. Leipzig, 1904. 74 pp.

That Jesus was of Aryan descent is argued by A. Müller, who suggests there was a Gaulish immigration into Galilee. Jesus was an Aryan. Leipzig, 1904. 74 pp.

258.

Did Jesus live 100 b.c.? London and Benares. Theosophical Publishing Society, 1903. 440 pp.

Did Jesus live 100 B.C.? London and Benares. Theosophical Publishing Society, 1903. 440 pp.

A scientific discussion of the “Toledoth Jeshu,” with citations from the Talmudic tradition concerning Jesus, is offered by S. Krauss, Das Leben Jesu nach jüdischen Quellen, 1902. 309 pp. According to him the Toledoth Jeshu was committed to writing in the fifth century, and he is of opinion that the Jewish legend is only a modified version of the Christian tradition.

A scientific discussion of the “Toledoth Jeshu,” including references from the Talmudic tradition about Jesus, is presented by S. Krauss in The Life of Jesus According to Jewish Sources, 1902. 309 pages. According to him, the Toledoth Jeshu was written down in the fifth century, and he believes that the Jewish legend is just a modified version of the Christian tradition.

259.

William Wrede, born in 1859 at Bücken in Hanover, was Professor at Breslau. (He died in 1907.)

William Wrede, born in 1859 in Bücken, Hanover, was a professor at Breslau. (He passed away in 1907.)

Wrede names as his real predecessors on the same lines Bruno Bauer, Volkmar, and the Dutch writer Hoekstra (“De Christologie van het canonieke Marcus-Evangelie, vergeleken met die van de beide andere synoptische Evangelien,” Theol. Tijdschrift, v., 1871).

Wrede identifies his true predecessors in this area as Bruno Bauer, Volkmar, and the Dutch writer Hoekstra ("The Christology of the canonical Gospel of Mark, compared to that of the other two synoptic Gospels," Theology Journal, v., 1871).

In a certain limited degree the work of Ernest Havet (Le Christianisme et ses origines) has a claim to be classed in the same category. His scepticism refers principally to the entry into Jerusalem and the story of the passion.

In a certain limited degree, the work of Ernest Havet (Christianity and its origins) can be classified in the same category. His skepticism mainly concerns the entry into Jerusalem and the story of the Passion.

260.
These and the following questions are raised more especially in the Outline of the Life of Jesus.
261.
It would perhaps be more historical to say "like a prophet."
262.
The difficulties which the incident at Caesarea Philippi places in the way of Wrede's construction may be realised by placing two of his statements side by side. P. 101: “This clearly shows that this incident has nothing in it that can't be easily understood based on Mark's ideas.” P. 238: "But in another way, this incident directly contradicts the Marcan view of the disciples. It doesn't align with their overall ‘lack of understanding,’ and so it was unlikely to have been created by Mark himself."
263.
The question of the attitude of pre-Origenic theology towards the historical Jesus, and of the influence exercised by dogma upon the evangelical tradition regarding Jesus in the course of the first two centuries, is certainly deserving of a detailed examination.
264.
Certain of the conceptions with which Wrede operates are simply not in accordance with the text, because he gives them a different significance from that which they have in the narrative. Thus, for example, he always takes the “revival,” when it occurs in the mouth of Jesus, as a reference to that resurrection which as an historical fact became a matter of apprehended experience to the apostles. But Jesus speaks without any distinction of His resurrection and of His Parousia. The conception of the resurrection, therefore, if one is to arrive at it inductively from the Marcan text, is most closely bound up with the Parousia. The Evangelist would thus seem to have made Jesus predict a different kind of resurrection from that which actually happened. The resurrection, according to the Marcan text, is an eschatological event, and has no reference whatever to Wrede's "historical revival." Further, if their resurrection experience was the first and fundamental point in the Messianic enlightenment of the disciples, why did they only begin to proclaim it some weeks later? This is a problem which was long ago recognised by Reimarus, and which is not solved by merely assuming that the disciples were afraid.
265.
P. 33 ff. The prohibitions in Mark i. 43 and 44, v. 43, vii. 36, and viii. 26 are put on the same footing with the really Messianic prohibitions in viii. 30 and ix. 9, with which may be associated also the imposition of silence upon the demoniacs who recognise his Messiahship in Mark i. 34 and iii. 12.
266.
The narrative in Matt. xiv. 22-33, according to which the disciples, after seeing Jesus walk upon the sea, hail Him on His coming into the boat as the Son of God, and the description of the deeds of Jesus as “acts of Christ,” in the introduction to the Baptist's question in Matt. xi. 2, do not cancel the old theory even in Matthew, because the Synoptists, differing therein from the fourth Evangelist, do not represent the demand for a sign as a demand for a Messianic sign, nor the cures wrought by Jesus as Messianic proofs of power. The action of the demons in crying out upon Jesus as the Son of God betokens their recognition of Him; it has nothing to do with the miracles of healing as such.
267.
For further examples of the pressing of the theory to its utmost limits, see Wrede, p. 134 ff.
268.
It is always assumed as self-evident that Jesus is speaking of the sufferings and persecutions which would take place after His death, or that the Evangelist, in making Him speak in this way, is thinking of these later persecutions. There is no hint of that in the text.
269.
That the eschatological school showed a certain timidity in drawing the consequences of its recognition of the character of the preaching of Jesus and examining the tradition from the eschatological standpoint can be seen from Johannes Weiss's work, “The Earliest Gospel” (The oldest gospel), Göttingen, 1903, 414 pp. Ingenious and interesting as this work is in detail, one is surprised to find the author of the "Jesus' teachings" here endeavouring to distinguish between Mark and “Ur-Markus,” to point to examples of Pauline influence, to exhibit clearly the “trends” which guided, respectively, the original Evangelist and the redactor—all this as if he did not possess in his eschatological view of the preaching of Jesus a dominant conception which gives him a clue to quite a different psychology from that which he actually applies. Against Wrede he brings forward many arguments which are worthy of attention, but he can hardly be said to have refuted him, because it is impossible for Weiss to treat the question in the exact form in which it was raised by Wrede.
270.
Wrede certainly goes too far in asserting that even in Mark's version the experience at the baptism is conceived as an open miracle, perceptible to others. The way in which the revelations to the prophets are recounted in the Old Testament does not make in favour of this. Otherwise we should have to suppose that the Evangelist described the incident as a miracle which took place in the presence of a multitude without perceiving that in this case the Messianic secret was a secret no longer. If so, the story of the baptism stands on the same footing as the story of the Messianic entry: it is a revelation of the Messiahship which has absolutely no results.
271.
The statement of Mark that Jesus, coming out of the north, appeared for a moment again in Decapolis and Capernaum, and then started off to the north once more (Mark vii. 31-viii. 27), may here provisionally be left out of account since it stands in relation with the twofold account of the feeding of the multitude. So too the enigmatic appearance and disappearance of the people (Mark viii. 34-ix. 30) may here be passed over. These statements make no difference to the fact that Jesus really broke off his work in Galilee shortly after the Mission of the Twelve, since they imply at most a quite transient contact with the people.
272.
On the theory of the successful and unsuccessful periods in the work of Jesus see the "Draft," p. 3 ff., "The four assumptions of the Modern Historical Solution."
273.
Weisse found that there was no hint in the sources of the desertion of the people, since according to these, Jesus was opposed only by the Pharisees, not by the people. The abandonment of the Galilaean work, and the departure to Jerusalem, must, he thought, have been due to some unrecorded fact which revealed to Jesus that the time had come to act in this way. Perhaps, he adds, it was the waning of Jesus' miracle-working power which caused the change in His attitude, since it is remarkable that He performed no further miracles during His sojourn at Jerusalem.
274.
The most logical attitude in regard to it is Bousset's, who proposes to treat the mission and everything connected with it as a "lost and unclear" tradition.
275.

Joel iii. 13, “Put in the sickle for the harvest is ripe!” In the Apocalypse of John, too, the Last Judgment is described as the heavenly harvest: “Thrust in thy sickle and reap; for the time is come for thee to reap; for the harvest of the earth is ripe. And he that sat on the cloud thrust in his sickle on the earth; and the earth was reaped” (Rev. xiv. 15 and 16).

Joel iii. 13, “Prepare the sickle, because it’s time to harvest!” In the Book of Revelation, the Last Judgment is also portrayed as a heavenly harvest: "Use your sickle to gather the harvest because it's time to reap; the earth's harvest is ready. And the one sitting on the cloud swung his sickle over the earth, and the earth was harvested." (Rev. xiv. 15 and 16).

The most remarkable parallel to the discourse at the sending forth of the disciples is offered by the Syriac Apocalypse of Baruch: “Behold, the days come, when the time of the world shall be ripe, and the harvest of the sowing of the good and of the evil shall come, when the Almighty shall bring upon the earth and upon its inhabitants and upon their rulers confusion of spirit and terror that makes the heart stand still; and they shall hate one another and provoke one another to war; and the despised shall have power over them of reputation, and the mean shall exalt themselves over them that are highly esteemed. And the many shall be at the mercy of the few ... and all who shall be saved and shall escape the before-mentioned (dangers) ... shall be given into the hands of my servant, the Messiah.” (Cap. lxx. 2, 3, 9. Following the translation of E. Kautzsch.)

The most remarkable comparison to the conversation at the sending out of the disciples is found in the Syriac Apocalypse of Baruch: "Listen, the time is coming when the world will be ready, and the harvest of both good and evil will take place. The Almighty will bring confusion and fear that stops hearts among the people and their rulers; they will turn against each other and incite wars. Those who are despised will gain power over the respected, and the lowly will rise above the esteemed. Many will be at the mercy of a few... and all those who are saved and escape the dangers mentioned... will be entrusted to my servant, the Messiah." (Cap. lxx. 2, 3, 9. Following the translation of E. Kautzsch.)

The connexion between the ideas of harvest and of judgment was therefore one of the stock features of the apocalyptic writings. And as the Apocalypse of Baruch dates from the period about a.d. 70, it may be assumed that this association of ideas was also current in the Jewish apocalyptic of the time of Jesus. Here is a basis for understanding the secret of the Kingdom of God in the parables of sowing and reaping historically and in accordance with the ideas of the time. What Jesus did was to make known to those who understood Him that the coming earthly harvest was the last, and was also the token of the coming heavenly harvest. The eschatological interpretation is immensely strengthened by these parallels.

The connection between the ideas of harvest and judgment was a key theme in apocalyptic writings. Since the Apocalypse of Baruch comes from around a.d. 70, we can assume that this association of ideas was also present in Jewish apocalyptic thought during Jesus' time. This provides a basis for understanding the secret of the Kingdom of God in the parables of sowing and reaping in a historical context aligned with the ideas of that era. What Jesus revealed to those who understood Him was that the upcoming earthly harvest was the final one and a sign of the upcoming heavenly harvest. The eschatological interpretation is significantly reinforced by these parallels.

276.
With what right does modern critical theology tear apart even the discourse in Matt. xi. in order to make the "shout of joy" into the cry with which Jesus saluted the return of His disciples, and to find lodgment for the woes upon Chorazin and Bethsaida somewhere else in an appropriately gloomy context? Is not all this apparently disconnected material held together by an inner bond of connexion—the secret of the Kingdom of God which is imminently impending over Jesus and the people? Or, is Jesus expected to preach like one who has a thesis to maintain and seeks about for the most logical arrangement? Does not a certain lack of orderly connexion belong to the very idea of prophetic speech?
277.
If, therefore, Jesus at a later point predicted to His disciples His resurrection, He means by that, not a single isolated act, but a complex occurrence consisting of His metamorphosis, translation to heaven, and Parousia as the Son of Man. And with this is associated the general eschatological resurrection of the dead. It is, therefore, one and the same thing whether He speaks of His resurrection or of His coming on the clouds of heaven.
278.
The title of Baldensperger's book, Jesus' Self-awareness in the Context of the Messianic Expectations of His Era, really contains a promise which is impossible of fulfilment. The contemporary “Messianic expectations” can only explain the hopes of Jesus so far as they corresponded thereto, not His view of His own Person, in which He is absolutely original.
279.
Even Baldensperger's book, The messianic-apocalyptic hopes of Judaism (1903), passes at a stride from the Psalms of Solomon to Fourth Ezra. The coming volume is to deal with the eschatology of Jesus. That is a theological but not an historical division of the material. The second volume should properly come in the middle of the first.
280.
The fact that in the Psalms of Solomon the Messiah is designated by the ancient prophetic name of the Son of David is significant of the rising influence of the ancient prophetic literature. This designation has nothing whatever to do with a political ideal of a kingly Messiah. This Davidic King and his Kingdom are, in their character and the manner of their coming, every whit as supernatural as the Son of Man and His coming. The same historical fact was read into both Daniel and the prophets.
281.
Enoch is an offshoot of the Danielic apocalyptic writings. The earliest portion, the Apocalypse of the Ten Weeks, is independent of Daniel and of contemporary origin. The Similitudes (capp. xxxvii.-lxix.), which, with their description of the Judgment of the Son of Man, are so important in connexion with the thoughts of Jesus, may be placed in 80-70 B.C. They do not presuppose the taking of Jerusalem by Pompey.
282.
The Psalms of Solomon are therefore a decade later than the Similitudes.
283.
The Apocalypse of Baruch seems to have been composed not very long after the Fall of Jerusalem. Fourth Ezra is twenty to thirty years later.
284.
The Psalms of Solomon form the last document of Jewish eschatology before the coming of the Baptist. For almost a hundred years, from 60 b.c. until a.d. 30, we have no information regarding eschatological movements! And do the Psalms of Solomon really point to a deep eschatological movement at the time of the taking of Jerusalem by Pompey? Hardly, I think. It is to be noticed in studying the times of Jesus that the surrounding circumstances have no eschatological character. The Fall of Jerusalem marks the next turning-point in the history of the apocalyptic hope, as Baruch and Fourth Ezra show.
285.
Jesus promises them expressly that at the appearing of the Son of Man they shall sit upon twelve thrones, judging the twelve tribes of Israel (Matt. xix. 28). It is to their part in the judgment that belong also the authority to bind and to loose which He entrusts to them—first to Peter personally (Matt. xvi. 19) and afterwards to all the Twelve (Matt. xviii. 18)—in such a way, too, that their present decisions will be somehow or other binding at the Judgment. Or does the “on earth” refer only to the fact that the Messianic Last Judgment will be held on earth? "I give you the Keys of the Kingdom of Heaven, and whatever you bind on earth will be bound in heaven, and whatever you loose on earth will be loosed in heaven." (Matt. xvi. 19). Why should these words not be historical? Is it because in the same context Jesus speaks of the "church" which He will found upon the Rock-disciple? But if one has once got a clear idea from Paul, a Clement, the Epistle to the Hebrews, and the Shepherd of Hermas, what the pre-existing "church" was which was to appear in the last times, it will no longer appear impossible that Jesus might have spoken of the church against which the gates of hell shall not prevail. Of course, if the passage is given an uneschatological reference to the Church as we know it, it loses all real meaning and becomes a treasure-trove to the Roman Catholic exegete, and a terror to the Protestant.
286.
That he could be taken for the Baptist risen from the dead shows how short a time before the death of the Baptist His ministry had begun. He only became known, as the Baptist's question shows, at the time of the mission of the disciples; Herod first heard of Him after the death of the Baptist. Had he known anything of Jesus beforehand, it would have been impossible for him suddenly to identify Him with the Baptist risen from the dead. This elementary consideration has been overlooked in all calculations of the length of the public ministry of Jesus.
287.
That had been rightly remarked by Colani. Later, however, theology lost sight of the fact because it did not know how to make any historical use of it.
288.
Psal. Sol. xv. 8.
289.
That the baptism of John was essentially an act which gave a claim to something future may be seen from the fact that Jesus speaks of His sufferings and death as a special baptism, and asks the sons of Zebedee whether they are willing, for the sake of gaining the thrones on His right hand and His left, to undergo this baptism. If the baptism of John had had no real sacramental significance it would be unintelligible that Jesus should use this metaphor.
290.

The thought of the Messianic feast is found in Isaiah lv. 1 ff. and lxv. 12 ff. It is very strongly marked in Isa. xxv. 6-8, a passage which perhaps dates from the time of Alexander the Great, “and Jahweh of Hosts will prepare upon this mountain for all peoples a feast of fat things, a feast of wine on the lees, of fat things prepared with marrow, of wine on the lees well refined. He shall destroy, in this mountain, among all peoples, the veil which has veiled all peoples and the covering which has covered all nations. He shall destroy death for ever, and the Lord Jahweh shall wipe away the tears from off all faces; and the reproach of His people shall disappear from the earth.” (The German follows Kautzsch's translation.)

The idea of the Messianic feast is mentioned in Isaiah 55:1 and Isaiah 65:12. It’s particularly prominent in Isaiah 25:6-8, a passage that might date back to the time of Alexander the Great, “and the Lord of Hosts will set up a feast on this mountain for everyone, a feast of delicious foods, a feast of aged wines, of flavorful dishes full of marrow, of fine, aged wines. He will eliminate, on this mountain, the veil that covers all people, the cover that hides all nations. He will wipe away the tears from every face and take away the shame of His people from the earth.” (The German follows Kautzsch's translation.)

In Enoch xxiv. and xxv. the conception of the Messianic feast is connected with that of the tree of life which shall offer its fruits to the elect upon the mountain of the King. Similarly in the Testament of Levi, cap. xviii. 11.

In Enoch xxiv. and xxv., the idea of the Messianic feast is linked to the tree of life, which will provide its fruits to the chosen ones on the mountain of the King. Similarly, in the Testament of Levi, cap. xviii. 11.

The decisive passage is in Enoch lxii. 14. After the Parousia of the Son of Man, and after the Judgment, the elect who have been saved “shall eat with the Son of Man, shall sit down and rise up with Him to all eternity.”

The key passage is in Enoch lxii. 14. After the return of the Son of Man and after the Judgment, the chosen ones who have been saved "will eat with the Son of Man and will sit down and rise up with Him forever."

Jesus' references to the Messianic feast are therefore not merely images, but point to a reality. In Matt. viii. 11 and 12 He prophesies that many shall come from the East and from the West to sit at meat with Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. In Matt. xxii. 1-14 the Messianic feast is pictured as a royal marriage, in Matt. xxv. 1-13 as a marriage feast.

Jesus' references to the Messianic feast are not just images; they signify a real event. In Matt. viii. 11 and 12, He predicts that many will come from the East and the West to dine with Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob. In Matt. xxii. 1-14, the Messianic feast is described as a royal wedding, while in Matt. xxv. 1-13, it's depicted as a wedding banquet.

The Apocalypse is dominated by the thought of the feast in all its forms. In Rev. ii. 7 it appears in connexion with the thought of the tree of life; in ii. 17 it is pictured as a feeding with manna; in iii. 21 it is the feast which the Lord will celebrate with His followers; in vii. 16, 17 there is an allusion to the Lamb who shall feed His own so that they shall no more hunger or thirst; chapter xix. describes the marriage feast of the Lamb.

The Apocalypse is centered around the concept of the feast in various forms. In Rev. ii. 7, it relates to the idea of the tree of life; in ii. 17, it is depicted as being nourished by manna; in iii. 21, it represents the feast that the Lord will hold with His followers; in vii. 16, 17, there's a reference to the Lamb who will provide for His own so they will no longer hunger or thirst; chapter xix. describes the marriage feast of the Lamb.

The Messianic feast therefore played a dominant part in the conception of blessedness from Enoch to the Apocalypse of John. From this we can estimate what sacramental significance a guarantee of taking part in that feast must have had. The meaning of the celebration was obvious in itself, and was made manifest in the conduct of it. The sacramental effect was wholly independent of the apprehension and comprehension of the recipient. Therefore, in this also the meal at the lake-side was a true sacrament.

The Messianic feast played a central role in the idea of blessedness from Enoch to the Apocalypse of John. From this, we can understand the sacramental significance that being assured a place at that feast must have had. The purpose of the celebration was clear on its own and became evident through the way it was carried out. The sacramental effect did not rely on the understanding or perception of the person receiving it. Thus, in this regard, the meal at the lakeside was a genuine sacrament.

291.
Weisse rightly remarks that the task of the historian in dealing with Mark must consist in explaining how such "myths" could be accepted by a chronicler who stood so relatively near the events as our Mark does.
292.
It is to be noticed that the cry of Jesus from the cross, "Eli, Eli," was immediately interpreted by the bystanders as referring to Elias.
293.
From this difficulty we can see, too, how impossible it was for any of them to have "slowly came to understand that Jesus was the Messiah."
294.
For the hypothesis of the two sets of narratives which have been worked into one another, see the "Overview of the Life of Jesus," 1901, p. 52 ff., "After the Mission of the Disciples: Literary and Historical Issues." A theory resting on the same principle was lately worked out in detail by Johannes Weiss, The Oldest Gospel (The Earliest Gospel), 1903, p. 205 ff.
295.
It is typical of the constant agreement of the critical conclusions in thoroughgoing scepticism and thoroughgoing eschatology that Wrede also observes: "The transfiguration and Peter's confession are closely linked in meaning." (p. 123). He also clearly perceives the inconsistency in the fact that Peter at Caesarea Philippi gives evidence of possessing a knowledge which he and his fellow-disciples do not show elsewhere (p. 119), but the fact that it is Peter, not Jesus, who reveals the Messianic secret, constitutes a very serious difficulty for Wrede's reading of the facts, since this assumes Jesus to have been the revealer of it.
296.
“After these years, my Son, the Christ, will die along with everyone who has the breath of life. Then the Age will turn into total silence; for seven days, just like in the very beginning, so that no one will be left. After seven days, the Age, which is currently asleep, will awaken, and mortality itself will cease to exist.”
297.

Difficult problems are involved in the prediction of the resurrection in Mark xiv. 28. Jesus there promises His disciples that He will “go before them” into Galilee. That cannot mean that He will go alone into Galilee before them, and that they shall there meet with Him, their risen Master; what He contemplates is that He shall return with them, at their head, from Jerusalem to Galilee. Was it that the manifestation of the Son of Man and of the Judgment should take place there? So much is clear: the saying, far from directing the disciples to go away to Galilee, chains them to Jerusalem, there to await Him who should lead them home. It should not therefore be claimed as supporting the tradition of the Galilaean appearances.

Difficult problems come up when predicting the resurrection in Mark 14:28. There, Jesus promises His disciples that He will “go before them” into Galilee. This doesn’t mean He will go alone to Galilee and that they will meet Him there as their risen Master; rather, He intends to return with them, leading them from Jerusalem to Galilee. Was it that the revelation of the Son of Man and Judgment would happen there? One thing is clear: Jesus's statement does not instruct the disciples to leave for Galilee; instead, it keeps them tied to Jerusalem, where they are to wait for Him to lead them home. Therefore, it shouldn't be used to support the idea of the Galilean appearances.

We find it “corrected” by the saying of the “young man” at the grave, who says to the women, “Go, tell His disciples and Peter that He goeth before you into Galilee. There shall ye see Him as He said unto you.”

We see it "updated" by what the “young guy” says at the grave, telling the women, "Go and tell His disciples and Peter that He is going ahead of you into Galilee. There you will see Him, just as He said."

Here then the idea of following in point of time is foisted upon the words “he goeth before you,” whereas in the original the word has a purely local sense, corresponding to the καὶ ἦν προάγων αὐτοὺς ὁ Ιησοῦς in Mark x. 32.

Here, the concept of following in terms of timing is imposed on the words “he goes ahead of you,” while in the original, the term has a purely locational meaning, corresponding to the καὶ ἦν προάγων αὐτοὺς ὁ Ιησοῦς in Mark x. 32.

But the correction is itself meaningless since the visions took place in Jerusalem. We have therefore in this passage a more detailed indication of the way in which Jesus thought of the events subsequent to His Resurrection. The interpretation of this unfulfilled saying is, however, wholly impossible for us: it was not less so for the earliest tradition, as is shown by the attempt to give it a meaning by the “correction.”

But the correction is meaningless on its own since the visions happened in Jerusalem. Therefore, this passage gives us a clearer idea of how Jesus viewed the events after His Resurrection. However, interpreting this unfulfilled statement is completely impossible for us; it was just as difficult for the earliest traditions, as shown by the attempt to make sense of it through the “update.”

298.
Here it is evident also from the form taken by the prophecy of the sufferings that the section Mark viii. 34 ff. cannot possibly come after the revelation at Caesarea Philippi, since in it, it is the thought of the general sufferings which is implied. For the same reason the predictions of suffering and tribulation in the Synoptic Apocalypse in Mark xiii. cannot be derived from Jesus.
299.

Weisse and Bruno Bauer had long ago pointed out how curious it was that Jesus in the sayings about His sufferings spoke of “many” instead of speaking of “His own” or “the believers.” Weisse found in the words the thought that Jesus died for the nation as a whole; Bruno Bauer that the “for many” in the words of Jesus was derived from the view of the later theology of the Christian community. This explanation is certainly wrong, for so soon as the words of Jesus come into any kind of contact with early theology the “many” disappear to give place to the “believers.” In the Pauline words of institution the form is: My body for you (1 Cor. xi. 24).

Weisse and Bruno Bauer pointed out long ago how odd it was that Jesus, in speaking about His sufferings, referred to "many" instead of saying "His own" or "the believers." Weisse interpreted these words to mean that Jesus died for the entire nation, whereas Bruno Bauer believed that the "for many" in Jesus' words came from later Christian community theology. This interpretation is definitely incorrect, because as soon as Jesus' words are connected to early theology, the "many" is replaced by "believers." In Paul's words of institution, it is stated as: My body for you (1 Cor. xi. 24).

Johannes Weiss follows in the footsteps of Weisse when he interprets the “many” as the nation (Die Predigt Jesu vom Reiche Gottes, 2nd ed., 1909, p. 201). He gives however, quite a false turn to this interpretation by arguing that the “many” cannot include the disciples, since they “who in faith and penitence have received the tidings of the Kingdom of God no longer need a special means of deliverance such as this.” They are the chosen, to them the Kingdom is assured. But a ransom, a special means of salvation, is needful for the mass of the people, who in their blindness have incurred the guilt of rejecting the Messiah. For this grave sin, which is, nevertheless, to some extent excused as due to ignorance, there is a unique atoning sacrifice, the death of the Messiah.

Johannes Weiss follows in the footsteps of Weisse when he interprets the numerous as the nation (The Sermon of Jesus on the Kingdom of God, 2nd ed., 1909, p. 201). However, he distorts this interpretation by arguing that the "lots" cannot include the disciples, since they "Those who, with faith and repentance, have heard the message of the Kingdom of God no longer require a special means of salvation like this." They are the chosen ones, and the Kingdom is guaranteed for them. But a ransom, a special means of salvation, is necessary for the majority of the people, who, in their ignorance, have incurred the guilt of rejecting the Messiah. For this serious sin, which is somewhat excused due to ignorance, there is a unique atoning sacrifice: the death of the Messiah.

This theory is based on a distinction of which there is no hint in the teaching of Jesus; and it takes no account of the predestinarianism which is an integral part of eschatology, and which, in fact, dominated the thoughts of Jesus. The Lord is conscious that He dies only for the elect. For others His death can avail nothing, nor even their own repentance. Moreover, He does not die in order that this one or that one may come into the Kingdom of God; He provides the atonement in order that the Kingdom itself may come. Until the Kingdom comes even the elect cannot possess it.

This theory is based on a distinction that isn't found in Jesus' teachings; it also overlooks the predestinarianism that is a key part of eschatology and, in fact, shaped Jesus' thinking. The Lord knows that He only dies for the elect. For others, His death means nothing, not even their own repentance can change that. Furthermore, He doesn’t die so that this person or that person can enter the Kingdom of God; He provides the atonement so that the Kingdom itself can arrive. Until the Kingdom comes, even the elect cannot have it.

300.
One might use it as a principle of division by which to classify the lives of Jesus, whether they make Him go to Jerusalem to work or to die. Here as in so many other places Weisse's clearness of perception is surprising. Jesus' journey was according to him a pilgrimage to death, not to the Passover.
301.
"That you do not fall into temptation." is the content of the prayer that they are to offer while watching with Him.
302.

As long ago as 1880, H. W. Bleby (The Trial of Jesus considered as a Judicial Act) had emphasised this circumstance as significant. The injustice in the trial of Jesus consisted, according to him, in the fact that He was condemned on His own admission without any witnesses being called. Dalman, it is true, will not admit that this technical error was very serious.

As far back as 1880, H. W. Bleby (The Trial of Jesus Viewed as a Legal Proceeding) pointed out that this situation was important. He argued that the injustice in Jesus's trial was that He was condemned based on His own statement without any witnesses being brought forward. It's true that Dalman does not consider this technical error to be very serious.

But the really important point is not whether the condemnation was legal or not; it is the significant fact that the High Priest called no witnesses. Why did he not call any? This question was obscured for Bleby and Dalman by other problems.

But the really important point isn't whether the condemnation was legal or not; it's the significant fact that the High Priest called no witnesses. Why didn't he call any? This question was overshadowed for Bleby and Dalman by other issues.

303.
That would have been to utter a heresy which would alone have sufficed to secure His condemnation. It would certainly have been brought up as a charge against Him.
304.
When it is assumed that the Messianic claims of Jesus were generally known during those last days at Jerusalem there is a temptation to explain the absence of witnesses in regard to them by supposing that they were too much a matter of common knowledge to require evidence. But in that case why should the High Priest not have fulfilled the prescribed formalities? Why make such efforts first to establish a different charge? Thus the obscure and unintelligible procedure at the trial of Jesus becomes in the end the clearest proof that the public knew nothing of the Messiahship of Jesus.


Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!