This is a modern-English version of The Idea of Progress: An Inquiry into Its Origin and Growth, originally written by Bury, J. B. (John Bagnell). It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.





THE IDEA OF PROGRESS

AN INQUIRY INTO ITS ORIGIN AND GROWTH



By J. B. Bury

Regius Professor Of Modern History,
And Fellow Of King's College, In The University Of Cambridge










Dedicated to the memories of Charles Francois Castel de Saint-Pierre,
Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas Caritat de Condorcet, Auguste Comte, Herbert
Spencer, and other optimists mentioned in this volume.


Tantane uos generis tenuit fiducia uestri?










PREFACE

We may believe in the doctrine of Progress or we may not, but in either case it is a matter of interest to examine the origins and trace the history of what is now, even should it ultimately prove to be no more than an idolum saeculi, the animating and controlling idea of western civilisation. For the earthly Progress of humanity is the general test to which social aims and theories are submitted as a matter of course. The phrase CIVILISATION AND PROGRESS has become stereotyped, and illustrates how we have come to judge a civilisation good or bad according as it is or is not progressive. The ideals of liberty and democracy, which have their own ancient and independent justifications, have sought a new strength by attaching themselves to Progress. The conjunctions of "liberty and progress," "democracy and progress," meet us at every turn. Socialism, at an early stage of its modern development, sought the same aid. The friends of Mars, who cannot bear the prospect of perpetual peace, maintain that war is an indispensable instrument of Progress. It is in the name of Progress that the doctrinaires who established the present reign of terror in Russia profess to act. All this shows the prevalent feeling that a social or political theory or programme is hardly tenable if it cannot claim that it harmonises with this controlling idea.

We might believe in the idea of Progress or we might not, but either way, it’s interesting to explore the origins and history of what has become, even if it turns out to be just a contemporary illusion, the driving and defining concept of Western civilization. The earthly Progress of humanity serves as the main standard to which social goals and theories are routinely held. The term CIVILISATION AND PROGRESS has become a cliché, illustrating how we now assess a civilization as good or bad based on whether it is progressive or not. The ideals of freedom and democracy, which have their own ancient and valid reasons, have sought new strength by linking themselves to Progress. We frequently encounter phrases like "liberty and progress," and "democracy and progress." Early on in its modern development, socialism sought the same support. Advocates of war, who cannot tolerate the idea of lasting peace, argue that war is an essential tool for Progress. It is under the banner of Progress that the ideologues who established the current regime of terror in Russia claim to operate. All of this reflects the common belief that a social or political theory or agenda is hardly defendable if it can't assert that it aligns with this central idea.

In the Middle Ages Europeans followed a different guiding star. The idea of a life beyond the grave was in control, and the great things of this life were conducted with reference to the next. When men's deepest feelings reacted more steadily and powerfully to the idea of saving their souls than to any other, harmony with this idea was the test by which the opportuneness of social theories and institutions was judged. Monasticism, for instance, throve under its aegis, while liberty of conscience had no chance. With a new idea in control, this has been reversed. Religious freedom has thriven under the aegis of Progress; monasticism can make no appeal to it.

In the Middle Ages, Europeans were guided by a different star. The belief in life after death was dominant, and the important things in this life were viewed in relation to the next. When people's strongest emotions were more influenced by the idea of saving their souls than anything else, alignment with this idea became the standard for judging the relevance of social theories and institutions. For example, monasticism flourished in this environment, while freedom of conscience had no chance. With a new guiding idea in place, this has changed completely. Religious freedom has thrived under the banner of Progress; monasticism no longer holds sway.

For the hope of an ultimate happy state on this planet to be enjoyed by future generations—or of some state, at least, that may relatively be considered happy—has replaced, as a social power, the hope of felicity in another world. Belief in personal immortality is still very widely entertained, but may we not fairly say that it has ceased to be a central and guiding idea of collective life, a criterion by which social values are measured? Many people do not believe in it; many more regard it as so uncertain that they could not reasonably permit it to affect their lives or opinions. Those who believe in it are doubtless the majority, but belief has many degrees; and one can hardly be wrong in saying that, as a general rule, this belief does not possess the imaginations of those who hold it, that their emotions react to it feebly, that it is felt to be remote and unreal, and has comparatively seldom a more direct influence on conduct than the abstract arguments to be found in treatises on morals.

The hope for a truly happy life on this planet for future generations—or at least a life that can be seen as happy—has taken the place of the hope for happiness in an afterlife as a driving social force. While many still believe in personal immortality, can we honestly say that it remains a core and guiding concept in our collective lives, a standard against which social values are judged? A lot of people don’t believe in it; even more see it as so uncertain that they wouldn't reasonably let it shape their lives or beliefs. Although those who believe in it are probably the majority, belief comes in many levels; and it’s fair to say that, generally, this belief does not captivate the imaginations of those who hold it, their emotions respond to it weakly, it feels distant and unreal, and it rarely has a more direct impact on behavior than the theoretical discussions found in moral philosophy.

Under the control of the idea of Progress the ethical code recognised in the Western world has been reformed in modern times by a new principle of far-reaching importance which has emanated from that idea. When Isocrates formulated the rule of life, "Do unto others," he probably did not mean to include among "others" slaves or savages. The Stoics and the Christians extended its application to the whole of living humanity. But in late years the rule has received a vastly greater extension by the inclusion of the unborn generations of the future. This principle of duty to posterity is a direct corollary of the idea of Progress. In the recent war that idea, involving the moral obligation of making sacrifices for the sake of future ages, was constantly appealed to; just as in the Crusades, the most characteristic wars of our medieval ancestors, the idea of human destinies then in the ascendant lured thousands to hardship and death.

Under the influence of the idea of Progress, the ethical code recognized in the Western world has been updated in modern times by a new principle of significant importance that has come from that idea. When Isocrates stated the rule of life, "Do unto others," he likely didn’t consider slaves or those he deemed as savages to be "others." The Stoics and Christians broadened its application to encompass all of humanity. However, in recent years, this rule has been greatly expanded to include future unborn generations. This principle of responsibility to future generations is a direct result of the idea of Progress. During the recent war, that idea, which involves the moral duty to make sacrifices for future generations, was frequently referenced; much like during the Crusades, the defining wars of our medieval ancestors, when the prevailing idea of human destinies inspired thousands to endure hardship and face death.

The present attempt to trace the genesis and growth of the idea in broad outline is a purely historical inquiry, and any discussion of the great issue which is involved lies outside its modest scope. Occasional criticisms on particular forms which the creed of Progress assumed, or on arguments which were used to support it, are not intended as a judgment on its general validity. I may, however, make two observations here. The doubts which Mr. Balfour expressed nearly thirty years ago, in an Address delivered at Glasgow, have not, so far as I know, been answered. And it is probable that many people, to whom six years ago the notion of a sudden decline or break-up of our western civilisation, as a result not of cosmic forces but of its own development, would have appeared almost fantastic, will feel much less confident to-day, notwithstanding the fact that the leading nations of the world have instituted a league of peoples for the prevention of war, the measure to which so many high priests of Progress have looked forward as meaning a long stride forward on the road to Utopia.

The current effort to outline the origins and development of the idea is purely a historical examination, and any discussion of the significant issues involved is beyond its limited scope. Occasional critiques of specific forms the belief in Progress has taken, or of the arguments used to back it up, are not meant as a judgment on its overall validity. However, I would like to make two points here. The doubts that Mr. Balfour raised nearly thirty years ago in a speech he gave in Glasgow haven't, as far as I know, been addressed. It's likely that many people who, six years ago, would have found the idea of a sudden decline or collapse of our Western civilization—due not to cosmic forces but to its own evolution—almost unbelievable, now feel much less certain today, despite the fact that the leading nations of the world have established a league of nations aimed at preventing war, which so many proponents of Progress have anticipated as a significant step forward on the path to Utopia.

The preponderance of France's part in developing the idea is an outstanding feature of its history. France, who, like ancient Greece, has always been a nursing-mother of ideas, bears the principal responsibility for its growth; and if it is French thought that will persistently claim our attention, this is not due to an arbitrary preference on my part or to neglect of speculation in other countries.

The significant role of France in shaping this idea is a remarkable aspect of its history. France, which, like ancient Greece, has always been a source of inspiration for ideas, holds the main responsibility for its development; and if French thought consistently captures our attention, it’s not because of personal bias or oversight of intellectual contributions from other countries.

J. B. BURY. January, 1920.

J.B. BURY. January 1920.










CONTENTS


PREFACE

INTRODUCTION


CHAPTER I.   SOME INTERPRETATIONS OF UNIVERSAL HISTORY: BODIN AND LE ROY

CHAPTER II.   UTILITY THE END OF KNOWLEDGE: BACON

CHAPTER III.   CARTESIANISM

CHAPTER IV.   THE DOCTRINE OF DEGENERATION: THE ANCIENTS AND MODERNS

CHAPTER V.   THE PROGRESS OF KNOWLEDGE: FONTENELLE

CHAPTER VI.   THE GENERAL PROGRESS OF MAN: ABBE DE SAINT-PIERRE

CHAPTER VII.   NEW CONCEPTIONS OF HISTORY: MONTESQUIEU, VOLTAIRE, TURGOT

CHAPTER VIII.   THE ENCYCLOPAEDISTS AND ECONOMISTS

CHAPTER IX.   WAS CIVILISATION A MISTAKE? ROUSSEAU, CHASTELLUX

CHAPTER X.   THE YEAR 2440

CHAPTER XI.   THE FRENCH REVOLUTION: CONDORCET

CHAPTER XII.   THE THEORY OF PROGRESS IN ENGLAND

CHAPTER XIII.   GERMAN SPECULATIONS ON PROGRESS

CHAPTER XIV.   CURRENTS OF THOUGHT IN FRANCE AFTER THE REVOLUTION

CHAPTER XV.   THE SEARCH FOR A LAW OF PROGRESS:

CHAPTER XVI.   THE SEARCH FOR A LAW OF PROGRESS: II. COMTE

CHAPTER XVII.   "PROGRESS" IN THE FRENCH REVOLUTIONARY MOVEMENT (1830-1851)

CHAPTER XVIII.     MATERIAL PROGRESS: THE EXHIBITION OF 1851

CHAPTER XIX.   PROGRESS IN THE LIGHT OF EVOLUTION

EPILOGUE

CONTENTS


__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_0__

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_1__


__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_2__ PERSPECTIVES ON WORLD HISTORY: BODIN AND LE ROY

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_3__ THE LIMITS OF KNOWLEDGE: BACON

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_4__ CARTESIAN THOUGHT

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_5__ THE THEORY OF DECLINE: THE ANCIENTS AND MODERNS

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_6__ THE ADVANCEMENT OF KNOWLEDGE: FONTENELLE

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_7__ THE OVERALL PROGRESS OF HUMANITY: ABBE DE SAINT-PIERRE

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_8__ NEW PERSPECTIVES ON HISTORY: MONTESQUIEU, VOLTAIRE, TURGOT

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_9__ THE ENCYCLOPAEDISTS AND ECONOMISTS

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_10__ WAS CIVILIZATION A MISTAKE? ROUSSEAU, CHASTELLUX

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_11__ THE YEAR 2440

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_12__ THE FRENCH REVOLUTION: CONDORCET

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_13__ THE THEORY OF PROGRESS IN ENGLAND

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_14__ GERMAN THEORIES ON PROGRESS

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_15__ TRENDS IN THOUGHT IN FRANCE AFTER THE REVOLUTION

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_16__ THE SEARCH FOR A LAW OF PROGRESS:

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_17__ THE SEARCH FOR A LAW OF PROGRESS: II. COMTE

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_18__ "PROGRESS" IN THE FRENCH REVOLUTIONARY MOVEMENT (1830-1851)

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_19__ MATERIAL PROGRESS: THE EXHIBITION OF 1851

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_20__ PROGRESS IN THE CONTEXT OF EVOLUTION

__A_TAG_PLACEHOLDER_21__












INTRODUCTION

When we say that ideas rule the world, or exercise a decisive power in history, we are generally thinking of those ideas which express human aims and depend for their realisation on the human will, such as liberty, toleration, equality of opportunity, socialism. Some of these have been partly realised, and there is no reason why any of them should not be fully realised, in a society or in the world, if it were the united purpose of a society or of the world to realise it. They are approved or condemned because they are held to be good or bad, not because they are true or false. But there is another order of ideas that play a great part in determining and directing the course of man's conduct but do not depend on his will—ideas which bear upon the mystery of life, such as Fate, Providence, or personal immortality. Such ideas may operate in important ways on the forms of social action, but they involve a question of fact and they are accepted or rejected not because they are believed to be useful or injurious, but because they are believed to be true or false.

When we say that ideas control the world or play a crucial role in history, we're usually talking about ideas that represent human goals and rely on human will for their realization, like freedom, tolerance, equal opportunity, and socialism. Some of these have been partially achieved, and there's no reason they can't be fully realized in society or globally if everyone collectively decides to pursue them. They are judged as good or bad based on moral standards, not because they are inherently true or false. However, there’s another set of ideas that significantly influence and guide human behavior but don’t rely on our choices—concepts related to the mysteries of life, like Fate, Providence, or personal immortality. These ideas might have an important impact on social actions, but they involve questions of fact and are accepted or rejected based on whether they are believed to be true or false, rather than useful or harmful.

The idea of the progress of humanity is an idea of this kind, and it is important to be quite clear on the point. We now take it so much for granted, we are so conscious of constantly progressing in knowledge, arts, organising capacity, utilities of all sorts, that it is easy to look upon Progress as an aim, like liberty or a world-federation, which it only depends on our own efforts and good-will to achieve. But though all increases of power and knowledge depend on human effort, the idea of the Progress of humanity, from which all these particular progresses derive their value, raises a definite question of fact, which man's wishes or labours cannot affect any more than his wishes or labours can prolong life beyond the grave.

The concept of human progress is a significant one, and it's crucial to be completely clear about it. We now take it for granted and are constantly aware of our growth in knowledge, arts, organizational ability, and various utilities, making it easy to see Progress as a goal, much like freedom or global cooperation, that we can achieve with our own efforts and goodwill. However, while all advancements in power and knowledge rely on human effort, the idea of humanity's Progress — from which all these specific advancements gain their worth — raises a concrete question of fact that human desires or efforts cannot change, just as they cannot extend life beyond death.

This idea means that civilisation has moved, is moving, and will move in a desirable direction. But in order to judge that we are moving in a desirable direction we should have to know precisely what the destination is. To the minds of most people the desirable outcome of human development would be a condition of society in which all the inhabitants of the planet would enjoy a perfectly happy existence. But it is impossible to be sure that civilisation is moving in the right direction to realise this aim. Certain features of our "progress" may be urged as presumptions in its favour, but there are always offsets, and it has always been easy to make out a case that, from the point of view of increasing happiness, the tendencies of our progressive civilisation are far from desirable. In short, it cannot be proved that the unknown destination towards which man is advancing is desirable. The movement may be Progress, or it may be in an undesirable direction and therefore not Progress. This is a question of fact, and one which is at present as insoluble as the question of personal immortality. It is a problem which bears on the mystery of life.

This idea suggests that civilization has moved, is moving, and will continue to move in a positive direction. However, to assess whether we are heading in a positive direction, we need to know exactly what that destination is. For most people, the ideal outcome of human development would be a society where all inhabitants of the planet enjoy a perfectly happy life. But it’s impossible to be certain that civilization is progressing in the right way to achieve that goal. Some aspects of our "progress" can be argued as evidence supporting this view, but there are always counterarguments, and it's often easy to make the case that, from the perspective of increasing happiness, the trends in our advancing civilization are far from ideal. In short, it's unprovable that the unknown destination toward which humanity is moving is indeed positive. This movement could be Progress, or it might lead us in an undesirable direction, thus not being Progress at all. This is a matter of fact and remains as unsolvable as the question of personal immortality. It’s a problem that touches on the mystery of life.

Moreover, even if it is admitted to be probable that the course of civilisation has so far been in a desirable direction, and such as would lead to general felicity if the direction were followed far enough, it cannot be proved that ultimate attainment depends entirely on the human will. For the advance might at some point be arrested by an insuperable wall. Take the particular case of knowledge, as to which it is generally taken for granted that the continuity of progress in the future depends altogether on the continuity of human effort (assuming that human brains do not degenerate). This assumption is based on a strictly limited experience. Science has been advancing without interruption during the last three or four hundred years; every new discovery has led to new problems and new methods of solution, and opened up new fields for exploration. Hitherto men of science have not been compelled to halt, they have always found means to advance further. But what assurance have we that they will not one day come up against impassable barriers? The experience of four hundred years, in which the surface of nature has been successfully tapped, can hardly be said to warrant conclusions as to the prospect of operations extending over four hundred or four thousand centuries. Take biology or astronomy. How can we be sure that some day progress may not come to a dead pause, not because knowledge is exhausted, but because our resources for investigation are exhausted—because, for instance, scientific instruments have reached the limit of perfection beyond which it is demonstrably impossible to improve them, or because (in the case of astronomy) we come into the presence of forces of which, unlike gravitation, we have no terrestrial experience? It is an assumption, which cannot be verified, that we shall not soon reach a point in our knowledge of nature beyond which the human intellect is unqualified to pass.

Moreover, even if we agree that civilization has been progressing in a positive direction and that this path could lead to widespread happiness if we continue on it long enough, we cannot prove that reaching ultimate goals solely depends on human will. The progress might be halted at some point by an insurmountable barrier. Take knowledge, for example; it’s generally assumed that our future progress relies entirely on the ongoing efforts of humans (assuming our brains don’t decline). This assumption is built on a very limited experience. Science has been advancing steadily for the last three or four hundred years; each new discovery has created new problems and introduced new ways to solve them, opening up new areas for exploration. Until now, scientists haven’t been forced to stop; they’ve always managed to find ways to move forward. But what guarantees do we have that they won’t eventually encounter unmovable obstacles? The experience of the past four hundred years, where we’ve successfully explored nature’s surface, hardly justifies conclusions about the potential for advancements over four hundred or four thousand centuries. Consider biology or astronomy. How can we be sure that one day progress won’t come to a complete stop, not because we’ve run out of knowledge, but because our means of investigation have run out—because, for example, scientific instruments have reached a level of perfection that can’t be improved upon, or because (in the case of astronomy) we face forces we have no earthly experience with, unlike gravity? It’s an assumption that can’t be confirmed that we won’t soon hit a limit in our understanding of nature that human intellect simply cannot surpass.

But it is just this assumption which is the light and inspiration of man's scientific research. For if the assumption is not true, it means that he can never come within sight of the goal which is, in the case of physical science, if not a complete knowledge of the cosmos and the processes of nature, at least an immeasurably larger and deeper knowledge than we at present possess.

But this assumption is exactly what drives and inspires human scientific research. If the assumption isn’t true, it means he can never approach the goal, which in the case of physical science, is not necessarily complete knowledge of the universe and the workings of nature, but at least a vastly greater and deeper understanding than we currently have.

Thus continuous progress in man's knowledge of his environment, which is one of the chief conditions of general Progress, is a hypothesis which may or may not be true. And if it is true, there remains the further hypothesis of man's moral and social "perfectibility," which rests on much less impressive evidence. There is nothing to show that he may not reach, in his psychical and social development, a stage at which the conditions of his life will be still far from satisfactory, and beyond which he will find it impossible to progress. This is a question of fact which no willing on man's part can alter. It is a question bearing on the mystery of life.

Thus, ongoing progress in humanity's understanding of its environment, which is one of the main factors for overall Progress, is a theory that may or may not be true. And if it is true, there's still the additional theory of humanity's moral and social "perfectibility," which relies on much less convincing evidence. There's no proof that humanity can't reach a point in its psychological and social development where the conditions of life are still far from ideal, and beyond which it will be impossible to make further progress. This is a matter of fact that no amount of human willingness can change. It's a question related to the mystery of life.

Enough has been said to show that the Progress of humanity belongs to the same order of ideas as Providence or personal immortality. It is true or it is false, and like them it cannot be proved either true or false. Belief in it is an act of faith.

Enough has been said to show that the Progress of humanity is related to the same concepts as Providence or personal immortality. It is either true or false, and like those concepts, it cannot be definitively proven true or false. Believing in it is an act of faith.

The idea of human Progress then is a theory which involves a synthesis of the past and a prophecy of the future. It is based on an interpretation of history which regards men as slowly advancing—pedetemtim progredientes—in a definite and desirable direction, and infers that this progress will continue indefinitely. And it implies that, as

The idea of human progress is a theory that combines the past with predictions about the future. It interprets history as a slow but steady advancement—pedetemtim progredientes—in a clear and positive direction, suggesting that this progress will go on forever. It also implies that, as

   The issue of the earth's great business,
The issue of the earth's great business,

a condition of general happiness will ultimately be enjoyed, which will justify the whole process of civilisation; for otherwise the direction would not be desirable. There is also a further implication. The process must be the necessary outcome of the psychical and social nature of man; it must not be at the mercy of any external will; otherwise there would be no guarantee of its continuance and its issue, and the idea of Progress would lapse into the idea of Providence.

A state of overall happiness will eventually be achieved, which will validate the entire process of civilization; otherwise, the direction wouldn't be worth pursuing. There's another point to consider. This process must be an essential result of human psychological and social nature; it shouldn't be controlled by any outside influence; otherwise, there would be no assurance of its persistence and results, and the concept of Progress would degenerate into mere chance.

As time is the very condition of the possibility of Progress, it is obvious that the idea would be valueless if there were any cogent reasons for supposing that the time at the disposal of humanity is likely to reach a limit in the near future. If there were good cause for believing that the earth would be uninhabitable in A.D. 2000 or 2100 the doctrine of Progress would lose its meaning and would automatically disappear. It would be a delicate question to decide what is the minimum period of time which must be assured to man for his future development, in order that Progress should possess value and appeal to the emotions. The recorded history of civilisation covers 6000 years or so, and if we take this as a measure of our conceptions of time-distances, we might assume that if we were sure of a period ten times as long ahead of us the idea of Progress would not lose its power of appeal. Sixty thousand years of HISTORICAL time, when we survey the changes which have come to pass in six thousand, opens to the imagination a range vast enough to seem almost endless.

Since time is essential for Progress to happen, it’s clear that the concept would be worthless if we had strong reasons to believe that humanity’s time is about to be limited in the near future. If there were solid reasons to think that the Earth would become uninhabitable by A.D. 2000 or 2100, the idea of Progress would lose its significance and vanish altogether. It would be a tricky question to determine the minimum amount of time that must be guaranteed for humanity's future development in order for Progress to have value and resonate emotionally. Recorded history covers around 6,000 years, and if we take that as our reference for time spans, we might propose that if we were certain of having a period ten times longer ahead of us, the idea of Progress would still hold its appeal. Sixty thousand years of historical time, when we look at the changes that have occurred in six thousand, presents a scope large enough to seem almost limitless.

This psychological question, however, need not be decided. For science assures us that the stability of the present conditions of the solar system is certified for many myriads of years to come. Whatever gradual modifications of climate there may be, the planet will not cease to support life for a period which transcends and flouts all efforts of imagination. In short, the POSSIBILITY of Progress is guaranteed by the high probability, based on astro-physical science, of an immense time to progress in.

This psychological question doesn't need to be settled. Science tells us that the stability of our solar system's current conditions is secure for countless years ahead. No matter what slow changes in climate occur, the planet will continue to support life for a time that surpasses and defies all imagination. In short, the POSSIBILITY of Progress is assured by the strong likelihood, based on astrophysical science, of having a vast amount of time to evolve.

It may surprise many to be told that the notion of Progress, which now seems so easy to apprehend, is of comparatively recent origin. It has indeed been claimed that various thinkers, both ancient (for instance, Seneca) and medieval (for instance, Friar Bacon), had long ago conceived it. But sporadic observations—such as man's gradual rise from primitive and savage conditions to a certain level of civilisation by a series of inventions, or the possibility of some future additions to his knowledge of nature—which were inevitable at a certain stage of human reflection, do not amount to an anticipation of the idea. The value of such observations was determined, and must be estimated, by the whole context of ideas in which they occurred. It is from its bearings on the future that Progress derives its value, its interest, and its power. You may conceive civilisation as having gradually advanced in the past, but you have not got the idea of Progress until you go on to conceive that it is destined to advance indefinitely in the future. Ideas have their intellectual climates, and I propose to show briefly in this Introduction that the intellectual climates of classical antiquity and the ensuing ages were not propitious to the birth of the doctrine of Progress. It is not till the sixteenth century that the obstacles to its appearance definitely begin to be transcended and a favourable atmosphere to be gradually prepared.

It might surprise many to learn that the idea of Progress, which now seems so straightforward, is actually relatively new. Some say that various thinkers, both ancient (like Seneca) and medieval (like Friar Bacon), had already thought about it long ago. However, sporadic observations—like humanity’s gradual advancement from primitive and savage conditions to a certain level of civilization through various inventions, or the potential for future additions to our understanding of nature—don’t truly reflect an anticipation of the concept. The importance of these observations was shaped by the broader context of ideas in which they appeared. Progress gets its value, interest, and power from its implications for the future. You might view civilization as having gradually developed in the past, but you haven’t grasped the idea of Progress until you also think that it’s meant to continue advancing indefinitely into the future. Ideas thrive in their intellectual environments, and I aim to briefly explain in this Introduction that the intellectual climates of classical antiquity and the following ages were not conducive to the emergence of the doctrine of Progress. It’s not until the sixteenth century that the barriers to its emergence start to be overcome and a supportive atmosphere begins to take shape.

[Footnote: The history of the idea of Progress has been treated briefly and partially by various French writers; e.g. Comte, Cours de philosophie positive, vi. 321 sqq.; Buchez, Introduction a la science de l'histoire, i. 99 sqq. (ed. 2, 1842); Javary, De l'idee de progres (1850); Rigault, Histoire de la querelle des Anciens et des Modernes (1856); Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophie cartesienne (1854); Caro, Problemes de la morale sociale (1876); Brunetiere, La Formation de l'idee de progres, in Etudes critiques, 5e serie. More recently M. Jules Delvaille has attempted to trace its history fully, down to the end of the eighteenth century. His Histoire de l'idee de progres (1910) is planned on a large scale; he is erudite and has read extensively. But his treatment is lacking in the power of discrimination. He strikes one as anxious to bring within his net, as theoriciens du progres, as many distinguished thinkers as possible; and so, along with a great deal that is useful and relevant, we also find in his book much that is irrelevant. He has not clearly seen that the distinctive idea of Progress was not conceived in antiquity or in the Middle Ages, or even in the Renaissance period; and when he comes to modern times he fails to bring out clearly the decisive steps of its growth. And he does not seem to realise that a man might be "progressive" without believing in, or even thinking about, the doctrine of Progress. Leonardo da Vinci and Berkeley are examples. In my Ancient Greek Historians (1909) I dwelt on the modern origin of the idea (p. 253 sqq.). Recently Mr. R. H. Murray, in a learned appendix to his Erasmus and Luther, has developed the thesis that Progress was not grasped in antiquity (though he makes an exception of Seneca),—a welcome confirmation.]

[Footnote: The concept of Progress has been discussed briefly and partially by various French writers; for example, Comte in Cours de philosophie positive, vi. 321 sqq.; Buchez in Introduction a la science de l'histoire, i. 99 sqq. (ed. 2, 1842); Javary in De l'idee de progres (1850); Rigault in Histoire de la querelle des Anciens et des Modernes (1856); Bouillier in Histoire de la philosophie cartesienne (1854); Caro in Problemes de la morale sociale (1876); and Brunetiere in La Formation de l'idee de progres, found in Etudes critiques, 5e serie. More recently, M. Jules Delvaille has tried to trace its history comprehensively, up to the end of the eighteenth century. His Histoire de l'idee de progres (1910) is designed on a grand scale; he is knowledgeable and has read widely. However, his analysis lacks clear discrimination. He seems eager to include as many notable thinkers as possible among the theorists of Progress, which leads to a mix of useful and relevant material alongside much that is off-topic. He hasn't recognized that the specific idea of Progress wasn't developed in ancient times, the Middle Ages, or even during the Renaissance; and when he addresses modern times, he doesn't clearly highlight the key stages of its evolution. He also appears unaware that a person could be "progressive" without subscribing to or even contemplating the doctrine of Progress, as seen with figures like Leonardo da Vinci and Berkeley. In my Ancient Greek Historians (1909), I focused on the modern origins of the idea (p. 253 sqq.). Recently, Mr. R. H. Murray, in a scholarly appendix to his Erasmus and Luther, has elaborated on the argument that Progress wasn't recognized in ancient times (with the exception of Seneca), which is a welcome confirmation.]

I

I

It may, in particular, seem surprising that the Greeks, who were so fertile in their speculations on human life, did not hit upon an idea which seems so simple and obvious to us as the idea of Progress. But if we try to realise their experience and the general character of their thought we shall cease to wonder. Their recorded history did not go back far, and so far as it did go there had been no impressive series of new discoveries suggesting either an indefinite increase of knowledge or a growing mastery of the forces of nature. In the period in which their most brilliant minds were busied with the problems of the universe men might improve the building of ships, or invent new geometrical demonstrations, but their science did little or nothing to transform the conditions of life or to open any vista into the future. They were in the presence of no facts strong enough to counteract that profound veneration of antiquity which seems natural to mankind, and the Athenians of the age of Pericles or of Plato, though they were thoroughly, obviously "modern" compared with the Homeric Greeks, were never self-consciously "modern" as we are.

It might seem surprising that the Greeks, known for their rich speculations on human life, never embraced an idea that feels so simple and obvious to us today: the idea of Progress. However, if we consider their experiences and the overall nature of their thought, this wonder fades. Their recorded history wasn’t extensive, and even what little there was hadn’t shown an impressive series of new discoveries that suggested an endless growth in knowledge or an increased control over nature. During the time when their greatest minds were grappling with universal issues, people could improve shipbuilding or create new geometric proofs, but their science did little to change life's conditions or to provide a glimpse into the future. They faced no compelling facts that could diminish the deep respect for the past that seems intrinsic to humanity, and although the Athenians of the era of Pericles or Plato were much more "modern" compared to the Homeric Greeks, they never consciously identified as "modern" like we do.

1.

Please provide a phrase for me to modernize.

The indications that human civilisation was a gradual growth, and that man had painfully worked his way forward from a low and savage state, could not, indeed, escape the sharp vision of the Greeks. For instance, Aeschylus represents men as originally living at hazard in sunless caves, and raised from that condition by Prometheus, who taught them the arts of life. In Euripides we find a similar recognition of the ascent of mankind to a civilised state, from primitive barbarism, some god or other playing the part of Prometheus. In such passages as these we have, it may be said, the idea that man has progressed; and it may fairly be suggested that belief in a natural progress lay, for Aeschylus as well as for Euripides, behind the poetical fiction of supernatural intervention. But these recognitions of a progress were not incompatible with the widely-spread belief in an initial degeneration of the human race; nor did it usually appear as a rival doctrine. The old legend of a "golden age" of simplicity, from which man had fallen away, was generally accepted as truth; and leading thinkers combined it with the doctrine of a gradual sequence of social and material improvements [Footnote: In the masterly survey of early Greek history which Thucydides prefixed to his work, he traces the social progress of the Greeks in historical times, and finds the key to it in the increase of wealth.] during the subsequent period of decline. We find the two views thus combined, for instance, in Plato's Laws, and in the earliest reasoned history of civilisation written by Dicaearchus, a pupil of Aristotle. [Footnote: Aristotle's own view is not very clear. He thinks that all arts, sciences, and institutions have been repeatedly, or rather an infinite number of times (word in Greek) discovered in the past and again lost. Metaphysics, xi. 8 ad fin.; Politics, iv. 10, cp. ii. 2. An infinite number of times seems to imply the doctrine of cycles.] But the simple life of the first age, in which men were not worn with toil, and war and disease were unknown, was regarded as the ideal State to which man would lie only too fortunate if he could return. He had indeed at a remote time ill the past succeeded in ameliorating some of the conditions of his lot, but such ancient discoveries as fire or ploughing or navigation or law-giving did not suggest the guess that new inventions might lead ultimately to conditions in which life would be more complex but as happy as the simple life of the primitive world.

The signs that human civilization developed gradually and that people worked their way up from a primitive and savage state were clear to the Greeks. For example, Aeschylus depicts humans originally living carelessly in dark caves, later lifted from that state by Prometheus, who taught them the skills for living. Similarly, Euripides acknowledges humanity's rise from early barbarism to a civilized existence, with some deity taking on the role of Prometheus. In these passages, we see the idea that humanity has progressed, and it can be reasonably suggested that Aeschylus and Euripides shared a belief in natural progress, despite it being framed within the poetic concept of supernatural help. However, these ideas of progress were compatible with the widespread belief in an initial decline of the human race, and they often didn't seem to compete with each other. The old myth of a "golden age" of simplicity, which humans had lost, was widely accepted as true, and prominent thinkers merged it with the idea of a gradual sequence of social and material improvements during the later period of decline. We can see these two perspectives combined in Plato's Laws and in the earliest systematic history of civilization written by Dicaearchus, a student of Aristotle. Aristotle's own views are somewhat unclear; he believes all arts, sciences, and institutions have been discovered and lost repeatedly, or rather an infinite number of times. The idea of infinite cycles seems to hint at his theory. Nevertheless, the uncomplicated life of the early age, where people weren’t burdened by labor and war and disease were absent, was viewed as the ideal state to which humanity would be incredibly fortunate to return. Although humanity had once made some improvements in its conditions, such as discovering fire, farming, navigation, or law-making, these ancient advancements didn’t inspire the thought that new inventions could lead to a state of life that, while more complex, could be as joyful as the simple existence of the primitive world.

But, if some relative progress might be admitted, the general view of Greek philosophers was that they were living in a period of inevitable degeneration and decay—inevitable because it was prescribed by the nature of the universe. We have only an imperfect knowledge of the influential speculations of Heraclitus, Pythagoras, and Empedocles, but we may take Plato's tentative philosophy of history to illustrate the trend and the prejudices of Greek thought on this subject. The world was created and set going by the Deity, and, as his work, it was perfect; but it was not immortal and had in it the seeds of decay. The period of its duration is 72,000 solar years. During the first half of this period the original uniformity and order, which were impressed upon it by the Creator, are maintained under his guidance; but then it reaches a point from which it begins, as it were, to roll back; the Deity has loosened his grip of the machine, the order is disturbed, and the second 36,000 years are a period of gradual decay and degeneration. At the end of this time, the world left to itself would dissolve into chaos, but the Deity again seizes the helm and restores the original conditions, and the whole process begins anew. The first half of such a world-cycle corresponds to the Golden Age of legend in which men lived happily and simply; we have now unfortunately reached some point in the period of decadence.

But if we can acknowledge some relative progress, the general perspective of Greek philosophers was that they lived in a time of unavoidable decline and decay—unavoidable because it was dictated by the nature of the universe. We only have a partial understanding of the influential ideas of Heraclitus, Pythagoras, and Empedocles, but we can use Plato's tentative philosophy of history to illustrate the trends and biases of Greek thought on this topic. The world was created and set into motion by a deity, and as his work, it was perfect; however, it was not immortal and contained within it the seeds of decay. The duration of this cycle is 72,000 solar years. During the first half of this period, the original uniformity and order, which were instilled by the Creator, are maintained under his guidance; but then it reaches a point where it begins to, so to speak, roll back; the deity has loosened his grip on the machine, the order is disrupted, and the second 36,000 years represent a gradual period of decay and decline. By the end of this time, if left to itself, the world would crumble into chaos, but the deity takes control again and restores the original conditions, and the whole process starts over. The first half of such a world cycle aligns with the Golden Age of legend when people lived happily and simply; we have unfortunately now reached a point in the period of decline.

Plato applies the theory of degradation in his study of political communities. [Footnote: Plato's philosophy of history. In the myth of the Statesman and the last Books of the Republic. The best elucidation of these difficult passages will be found in the notes and appendix to Book viii. in J. Adam's edition of the Republic (1902).] He conceives his own Utopian aristocracy as having existed somewhere towards the beginning of the period of the world's relapse, when things were not so bad, [Footnote: Similarly he places the ideal society which he describes in the Critias 9000 years before Solon. The state which he plans in the Laws is indeed imagined as a practicable project in his own day, but then it is only a second-best. The ideal state of which Aristotle sketched an outline (Politics, iv. v.) is not set either in time or in place.] and exhibits its gradual deterioration, through the successive stages of timocracy, oligarchy, democracy, and despotism. He explains this deterioration as primarily caused by a degeneration of the race, due to laxity and errors in the State regulation of marriages, and the consequent birth of biologically inferior individuals.

Plato uses the theory of degradation to examine political communities. [Footnote: Plato's philosophy of history. In the myth of the Statesman and the final Books of the Republic. The best explanation of these complex passages can be found in the notes and appendix to Book viii in J. Adam's edition of the Republic (1902).] He imagines his own ideal aristocracy as having existed at the early stages of the world’s decline, when conditions were not as dire, [Footnote: Similarly, he places the ideal society described in the Critias 9000 years before Solon. The state he envisions in the Laws is considered a feasible project for his own time, but it is only a second-best. The ideal state outlined by Aristotle (Politics, iv. v.) is not fixed in either time or location.] and shows its slow decline through the different stages of timocracy, oligarchy, democracy, and despotism. He attributes this decline mainly to a deterioration of the population, resulting from lax regulations and mistakes in state marriage policies, leading to the birth of biologically inferior individuals.

The theories of Plato are only the most illustrious example of the tendency characteristic of Greek philosophical thinkers to idealise the immutable as possessing a higher value than that which varies. This affected all their social speculations. They believed in the ideal of an absolute order in society, from which, when it is once established, any deviation must be for the worse. Aristotle, considering the subject from a practical point of view, laid down that changes in an established social order are undesirable, and should be as few and slight as possible. [Footnote: Politics, ii. 5.] This prejudice against change excluded the apprehension of civilisation as a progressive movement. It did not occur to Plato or any one else that a perfect order might be attainable by a long series of changes and adaptations. Such an order, being an embodiment of reason, could be created only by a deliberate and immediate act of a planning mind. It might be devised by the wisdom of a philosopher or revealed by the Deity. Hence the salvation of a community must lie in preserving intact, so far as possible, the institutions imposed by the enlightened lawgiver, since change meant corruption and disaster. These a priori principles account for the admiration of the Spartan state entertained by many Greek philosophers, because it was supposed to have preserved unchanged for an unusually long period a system established by an inspired legislator.

The theories of Plato are just the most famous example of the tendency among Greek philosophers to idealize the unchanging as having more value than what is subject to change. This mindset influenced all their social theories. They believed in the ideal of a perfect social order, which, once established, should not deviate since any change was seen as a decline. Aristotle, looking at the issue practically, argued that changes in an established social order are undesirable and should be minimal and minor. [Footnote: Politics, ii. 5.] This bias against change prevented them from seeing civilization as a progressive movement. It didn’t occur to Plato or anyone else that a perfect order could be achieved through a long series of changes and adjustments. Such an order, being a manifestation of reason, could only be created by a conscious and immediate act of a thoughtful planner. It might come from the insight of a philosopher or be revealed by a divine being. Therefore, the well-being of a community relied on maintaining, as much as possible, the institutions set by an enlightened lawgiver, since change was equated with corruption and disaster. These underlying principles explain why many Greek philosophers admired the Spartan state; it was believed to have maintained an unchanging system established by an inspired legislator for an unusually long time.

2.

2.

Thus time was regarded as the enemy of humanity. Horace's verse,

Thus, time was seen as humanity's enemy. Horace's verse,

  Damnosa quid non imminuit dies?
What harm does time not diminish?

"time depreciates the value of the world," expresses the pessimistic axiom accepted in most systems of ancient thought.

"time reduces the value of the world," reflects the pessimistic belief embraced in many ancient philosophies.

The theory of world-cycles was so widely current that it may almost be described as the orthodox theory of cosmic time among the Greeks, and it passed from them to the Romans.

The theory of world-cycles was so commonly accepted that it could almost be called the standard theory of cosmic time among the Greeks, and it was adopted by the Romans as well.

[Footnote: Plato's world-cycle. I have omitted details not essential; e.g. that in the first period men were born from the earth and only in the second propagated themselves. The period of 36,000 years, known as the Great Platonic Year, was probably a Babylonian astronomical period, and was in any case based on the Babylonian sexagesimal system and connected with the solar year conceived as consisting of 360 days. Heraclitus seems to have accepted it as the duration of the world between his periodic universal conflagrations. Plato derived the number from predecessors, but based it on operations with the numbers 3, 4, 5, the length of the sides of the Pythagorean right-angled triangle. The Great Year of the Pythagorean Philolaus seems to have been different, and that of the Stoics was much longer (6,570,000 years).

[Footnote: Plato's world-cycle. I've left out details that aren't essential; for example, in the first period, people were born from the earth, and only in the second did they reproduce themselves. The 36,000-year period, known as the Great Platonic Year, was likely based on Babylonian astronomy and was related to the Babylonian base-60 system, connecting to the solar year thought to have 360 days. Heraclitus seems to have accepted it as the time frame of the world between his cyclical universal fires. Plato got the number from his predecessors but based it on calculations involving the numbers 3, 4, and 5, which are the lengths of the sides of a Pythagorean right triangle. The Great Year of the Pythagorean Philolaus appears to have been different, and the Stoics used a much longer duration (6,570,000 years).]

I may refer here to Tacitus, Dialogus c. 16, as an appreciation of historical perspective unusual in ancient writers: "The four hundred years which separate us from the ancients are almost a vanishing quantity if you compare them with the duration of the ages." See the whole passage, where the Magnus Annus of 12,954 years is referred to.]

I may refer here to Tacitus, Dialogus c. 16, as an appreciation of historical perspective that’s uncommon among ancient writers: "The four hundred years that separate us from the ancients are almost negligible when you compare them to the span of the ages." Check out the entire passage, where the Magnus Annus of 12,954 years is mentioned.]

According to some of the Pythagoreans [Footnote: See Simplicius, Phys. 732, 26.] each cycle repeated to the minutest particular the course and events of the preceding. If the universe dissolves into the original chaos, there appeared to them to be no reason why the second chaos should produce a world differing in the least respect from its predecessor. The nth cycle would be indeed numerically distinct from the first, but otherwise would be identical with it, and no man could possibly discover the number of the cycle in which he was living. As no end seems to have been assigned to the whole process, the course of the world's history would contain an endless number of Trojan Wars, for instance; an endless number of Platos would write an endless number of Republics. Virgil uses this idea in his Fourth Eclogue, where he meditates a return of the Golden Age:

According to some Pythagoreans [Footnote: See Simplicius, Phys. 732, 26.], each cycle repeats every detail of the previous one. If the universe breaks down into its original chaos, they saw no reason why the next chaos wouldn’t produce a world exactly like the one before it. The nth cycle would be distinct in number from the first, but in every other way, it would be the same, and no one could possibly figure out which cycle they were living in. Since there seems to be no end to this entire process, the history of the world would feature an infinite number of Trojan Wars, for example; an infinite number of Platos would write an infinite number of Republics. Virgil references this idea in his Fourth Eclogue, where he reflects on a return to the Golden Age:

  Alter erit tum Tiphys, et altera quae uehat Argo
   Delectos heroas; erunt etiam altera bella,
   Atque iterum ad Troiam magnus mittetur Achilles.
  Then there will be another Tiphys, and another ship to carry  
   chosen heroes; there will also be more wars,  
   And once again, great Achilles will be sent to Troy.

The periodic theory might be held in forms in which this uncanny doctrine of absolute identity was avoided; but at the best it meant an endless monotonous iteration, which was singularly unlikely to stimulate speculative interest in the future. It must be remembered that no thinker had any means of knowing how near to the end of his cycle the present hour might be. The most influential school of the later Greek age, the Stoics, adopted the theory of cycles, and the natural psychological effect of the theory is vividly reflected in Marcus Aurelius, who frequently dwells on it in his Meditations. "The rational soul," he says, "wanders round the whole world and through the encompassing void, and gazes into infinite time, and considers the periodic destructions and rebirths of the universe, and reflects that our posterity will see nothing new, and that our ancestors saw nothing greater than we have seen. A man of forty years, possessing the most moderate intelligence, may be said to have seen all that is past and all that is to come; so uniform is the world." [Footnote: xi. I. The cyclical theory was curiously revived in the nineteenth; century by Nietzsche, and it is interesting to note his avowal that it took him a long time to overcome the feeling of pessimism which the doctrine inspired.]

The periodic theory might have been presented in ways that avoided this eerie idea of absolute identity; yet, at its best, it suggested an endless, boring repetition, which was unlikely to spark any genuine interest in the future. It's important to remember that no thinker could know how close to the end of their cycle the present moment might be. The most influential school of thought in the later Greek period, the Stoics, embraced the theory of cycles, and the natural psychological impact of this theory is clearly seen in Marcus Aurelius, who often reflects on it in his Meditations. "The rational soul," he says, "wanders around the entire world and through the vast emptiness, gazing into infinite time, considering the periodic destructions and rebirths of the universe, and reflecting that our descendants will see nothing new, and that our ancestors experienced nothing greater than what we have seen. A man of forty, with even a moderate intellect, can be said to have witnessed everything that is past and everything that is to come; the world is so uniform." [Footnote: xi. I. The cyclical theory was oddly revived in the nineteenth century by Nietzsche, and it’s noteworthy that he admitted it took him a long time to shake off the feeling of pessimism that the doctrine inspired.]

3.

3.

And yet one Stoic philosopher saw clearly, and declared emphatically, that increases in knowledge must be expected in the future.

And yet one Stoic philosopher saw clearly and stated firmly that we should expect increases in knowledge in the future.

"There are many peoples to-day," Seneca wrote, "who are ignorant of the cause of eclipses of the moon, and it has only recently been demonstrated among ourselves. The day will come when time and human diligence will clear up problems which are now obscure. We divide the few years of our lives unequally between study and vice, and it will therefore be the work of many generations to explain such phenomena as comets. One day our posterity will marvel at our ignorance of causes so clear to them.

"There are many people today," Seneca wrote, "who don’t understand why eclipses of the moon happen, and it has only recently been shown to us. The day will come when time and human effort will solve problems that are now unclear. We split the few years of our lives unevenly between learning and bad habits, so it will take many generations to explain phenomena like comets. One day, our descendants will be amazed at how ignorant we were of causes that are so clear to them."

"How many new animals have we first come to know in the present age? In time to come men will know much that is unknown to us. Many discoveries are reserved for future ages, when our memory will have faded from men's minds. We imagine ourselves initiated in the secrets of nature; we are standing on the threshold of her temple."

"How many new animals have we gotten to know in today's world? In the future, people will learn so much that we don't know now. Many discoveries are waiting for future generations, when our memory will have faded from people's minds. We think we understand the secrets of nature; we're standing at the entrance of her temple."

[Footnote: The quotations from Seneca will be found in Naturales Quaestiones, vii. 25 and 31. See also Epist. 64. Seneca implies continuity in scientific research. Aristotle had stated this expressly, pointing out that we are indebted not only to the author of the philosophical theory which we accept as true, but also to the predecessors whose views it has superseded (Metaphysics, i. ii. chap. 1). But he seems to consider his own system as final.]

[Footnote: The quotes from Seneca can be found in Naturales Quaestiones, vii. 25 and 31. Also see Epist. 64. Seneca suggests that scientific research is ongoing. Aristotle clearly stated this as well, highlighting that we owe credit not just to the author of the philosophical theory we believe to be true but also to the predecessors whose ideas it has replaced (Metaphysics, i. ii. chap. 1). However, he appears to view his own system as definitive.]

But these predictions are far from showing that Seneca had the least inkling of a doctrine of the Progress of humanity. Such a doctrine is sharply excluded by the principles of his philosophy and his profoundly pessimistic view of human affairs. Immediately after the passage which I have quoted he goes on to enlarge on the progress of vice. "Are you surprised to be told that human knowledge has not yet completed its whole task? Why, human wickedness has not yet fully developed."

But these predictions don't at all suggest that Seneca had any idea about a doctrine of the Progress of humanity. Such a doctrine is clearly rejected by the principles of his philosophy and his deeply pessimistic view of human affairs. Right after the passage I quoted, he goes on to expand on the rise of vice. "Are you surprised to hear that human knowledge hasn't finished its entire task? Well, human wickedness hasn't fully developed yet."

Yet, at least, it may be said, Seneca believed in a progress of knowledge and recognised its value. Yes, but the value which he attributed to it did not lie in any advantages which it would bring to the general community of mankind. He did not expect from it any improvement of the world. The value of natural science, from his point of view, was this, that it opened to the philosopher a divine region, in which, "wandering among the stars," he could laugh at the earth and all its riches, and his mind "delivered as it were from prison could return to its original home." In other words, its value lay not in its results, but simply in the intellectual activity; and therefore it concerned not mankind at large but a few chosen individuals who, doomed to live in a miserable world, could thus deliver their souls from slavery.

Yet, at the very least, it can be said that Seneca believed in the advancement of knowledge and recognized its worth. However, the value he attributed to it did not stem from any benefits it would bring to humanity as a whole. He did not foresee any improvement in the world from it. From his perspective, the value of natural science was that it opened up a divine realm for the philosopher, allowing him to "wander among the stars," where he could look down at the earth and all its wealth, with his mind "freed, as it were, from prison, returning to its original home." In other words, its worth was not in its outcomes but simply in the intellectual engagement; therefore, it did not concern humanity broadly but a select few individuals who, condemned to exist in a wretched world, could liberate their souls from bondage.

For Seneca's belief in the theory of degeneration and the hopeless corruption of the race is uncompromising. Human life on the earth is periodically destroyed, alternately by fire and flood; and each period begins with a golden age in which men live in rude simplicity, innocent because they are ignorant not because they are wise. When they degenerate from this state, arts and inventions promote deterioration by ministering to luxury and vice.

For Seneca, the belief in the idea of degeneration and the inevitable corruption of humanity is unwavering. Human life on Earth is periodically wiped out, either by fire or flood; and each cycle begins with a golden age where people live simply, innocent not because of wisdom but because of ignorance. As they move away from this state, advancements in arts and inventions actually contribute to decline by catering to luxury and vice.

Interesting, then, as Seneca's observations on the prospect of some future scientific discoveries are, and they are unique in ancient literature, [Footnote: They are general and definite. This distinguishes them, for instance, from Plato's incidental hint in the Republic as to the prospect of the future development of solid geometry.] they were far from adumbrating a doctrine of the Progress of man. For him, as for Plato and the older philosophers, time is the enemy of man. [Footnote: The quotations and the references here will be found in Nat. Quaest. i. Praef.; Epist. 104, Sec. 16 (cp. 110, Sec. 8; 117, Sec. 20, and the fine passage in 65, Sec. 16-21); Nat. Quaest. iii. 28-30; and finally Epist. 90, Sec. 45, cp. Sec. 17. This last letter is a criticism on Posidonius, who asserted that the arts invented in primitive times were due to philosophers. Seneca repudiates this view: omnia enim ista sagacitas hominum, non sapientia inuenit.

Interesting, then, as Seneca's thoughts on future scientific discoveries are, and they are unique in ancient literature, [Footnote: They are general and specific. This sets them apart, for example, from Plato's brief mention in the Republic about the future development of solid geometry.] they did not hint at a theory of human Progress. For him, as for Plato and earlier philosophers, time is an enemy to humanity. [Footnote: The quotations and references can be found in Nat. Quaest. i. Praef.; Epist. 104, Sec. 16 (see also 110, Sec. 8; 117, Sec. 20, and the excellent passage in 65, Sec. 16-21); Nat. Quaest. iii. 28-30; and finally Epist. 90, Sec. 45, see Sec. 17. This last letter critiques Posidonius, who claimed that the arts created in ancient times were due to philosophers. Seneca rejects this view: omnia enim ista sagacitas hominum, non sapientia inuenit.

Seneca touches on the possibility of the discovery of new lands beyond the ocean in a passage in his Medea (374 sqq.) which has been often quoted:

Seneca talks about the potential discovery of new lands beyond the ocean in a well-quoted passage from his Medea (374 sqq.):

        uenient annis
 secula seris, quibus oceanus
 uincula rerum laxet et ingens
 pateat tellus Tiphysque novos
 detegat orbes,...
 nec sit terris ultima Thule.]
uenient annis secula seris, quibus oceanus uincula rerum laxet et ingens pateat tellus Tiphysque novos detegat orbes,... nec sit terris ultima Thule.

4.

4.

There was however a school of philosophical speculation, which might have led to the foundation of a theory of Progress, if the historical outlook of the Greeks had been larger and if their temper had been different. The Atomic theory of Democritus seems to us now, in many ways, the most wonderful achievement of Greek thought, but it had a small range of influence in Greece, and would have had less if it had not convinced the brilliant mind of Epicurus. The Epicureans developed it, and it may be that the views which they put forward as to the history of the human race are mainly their own superstructure. These philosophers rejected entirely the doctrine of a Golden Age and a subsequent degeneration, which was manifestly incompatible with their theory that the world was mechanically formed from atoms without the intervention of a Deity. For them, the earliest condition of men resembled that of the beasts, and from this primitive and miserable condition they laboriously reached the existing state of civilisation, not by external guidance or as a consequence of some initial design, but simply by the exercise of human intelligence throughout a long period. [Footnote: Lucretius v. 1448 sqq. (where the word PROGRESS is pronounced):

There was, however, a line of philosophical thinking that could have led to the development of a theory of Progress if the historical perspective of the Greeks had been broader and if their mindset had been different. The Atomic theory of Democritus seems to us now, in many ways, the most remarkable achievement of Greek thought, but it had limited influence in Greece and would have had even less if it hadn’t convinced the brilliant mind of Epicurus. The Epicureans expanded on it, and it’s possible that the ideas they proposed about the history of humanity are primarily their own construction. These philosophers completely rejected the notion of a Golden Age followed by decline, which clearly clashed with their theory that the world was formed mechanically from atoms without any divine intervention. For them, the earliest human condition was similar to that of animals, and from this primitive and harsh state, they gradually evolved into the current state of civilization, not through external guidance or as a result of some initial plan, but purely through the use of human intelligence over a long period. [Footnote: Lucretius v. 1448 sqq. (where the word PROGRESS is pronounced):

 Usus et impigrae simul experientia mentis
 Paulatim docuit pedetemtim progredientis.
 Sic unum quicquid paulatim protrahit aetas
 In medium ratioque in luminis erigit oras.
 Namque alid ex alio clarescere et ordine debet
 Artibus, ad summum donee uenere cacumen.]
Usus and diligent experience of the mind gradually taught the process of slow progression. Thus, whatever age gradually brings forth promotes and elevates it to the forefront with clarity and structure. For one thing must shine out from another and progress in a certain order through the arts until it reaches the highest peak.

The gradual amelioration of their existence was marked by the discovery of fire and the use of metals, the invention of language, the invention of weaving, the growth of arts and industries, navigation, the development of family life, the establishment of social order by means of kings, magistrates, laws, the foundation of cities. The last great step in the amelioration of life, according to Lucretius, was the illuminating philosophy of Epicurus, who dispelled the fear of invisible powers and guided man from intellectual darkness to light.

The gradual improvement of their lives was highlighted by the discovery of fire and the use of metals, the invention of language, the creation of weaving, the growth of arts and industries, navigation, the development of family life, and the establishment of social order through kings, magistrates, and laws, along with the founding of cities. According to Lucretius, the final significant advancement in improving life was the enlightening philosophy of Epicurus, who eliminated the fear of unseen forces and led people from intellectual darkness into light.

But Lucretius and the school to which he belonged did not look forward to a steady and continuous process of further amelioration in the future. They believed that a time would come when the universe would fall into ruins, [Footnote: Ib. 95.] but the intervening period did not interest them. Like many other philosophers, they thought that their own philosophy was the final word on the universe, and they did not contemplate the possibility that important advances in knowledge might be achieved by subsequent generations. And, in any case, their scope was entirely individualistic; all their speculations were subsidiary to the aim of rendering the life of the individual as tolerable as possible here and now. Their philosophy, like Stoicism, was a philosophy of resignation; it was thoroughly pessimistic and therefore incompatible with the idea of Progress. Lucretius himself allows an underlying feeling of scepticism as to the value of civilisation occasionally to escape. [Footnote: His eadem sunt omnia semper (iii. 945) is the constant refrain of Marcus Aurelius.]

But Lucretius and his school didn’t anticipate a consistent and ongoing improvement in the future. They believed that there would come a time when the universe would collapse into chaos, [Footnote: Ib. 95.] but the time in between didn’t interest them. Like many other philosophers, they thought their philosophy was the ultimate answer about the universe, and they didn’t consider the possibility that future generations might make significant advancements in knowledge. In any case, their focus was entirely on the individual; all of their ideas were aimed at making individual lives as bearable as possible right now. Their philosophy, like Stoicism, was one of resignation; it was thoroughly pessimistic and therefore at odds with the idea of Progress. Lucretius himself occasionally lets slip a sense of skepticism about the value of civilization. [Footnote: His eadem sunt omnia semper (iii. 945) is the constant refrain of Marcus Aurelius.]

Indeed, it might be said that in the mentality of the ancient Greeks there was a strain which would have rendered them indisposed to take such an idea seriously, if it had been propounded. No period of their history could be described as an age of optimism. They were never, by their achievements in art or literature, in mathematics or philosophy, exalted into self-complacency or lured into setting high hopes on human capacity. Man has resourcefulness to meet everything—[words in Greek],—they did not go further than that.

Indeed, you could say that the mindset of the ancient Greeks included a perspective that would have made it difficult for them to take such an idea seriously if it had been suggested. No era in their history could be called an age of optimism. Their accomplishments in art, literature, mathematics, or philosophy never led them to feel self-satisfied or to develop overly optimistic views about human potential. They believed that people had the resourcefulness to face challenges—[words in Greek]—but they didn't go beyond that.

This instinctive pessimism of the Greeks had a religious tinge which perhaps even the Epicureans found it hard entirely to expunge. They always felt that they were in the presence of unknown incalculable powers, and that subtle dangers lurked in human achievements and gains. Horace has taken this feeling as the motif of a criticism on man's inventive powers. A voyage of Virgil suggests the reflection that his friend's life would not be exposed to hazards on the high seas if the art of navigation had never been discovered—if man had submissively respected the limits imposed by nature. But man is audacious:

This instinctive pessimism of the Greeks had a religious aspect that even the Epicureans found hard to completely shake off. They always felt they were surrounded by unknown, unpredictable forces, and that there were hidden dangers in human accomplishments and successes. Horace used this sentiment as the basis for a critique of human creativity. A voyage of Virgil hints at the idea that his friend's life wouldn't be at risk on the open sea if navigation had never been invented—if humans had humbly accepted the boundaries set by nature. But humans are bold:

  Nequiquam deus abscidit
    Prudens oceano dissociabili   Terras.
  Nequiquam deus abscidit
    Prudens oceano dissociabili   Terras.
  In vain a wise god sever'd lands
    By the dissociating sea.
In vain a wise god separated the lands  
    By the dividing sea.

Daedalus violated the air, as Hercules invaded hell. The discovery of fire put us in possession of a forbidden secret. Is this unnatural conquest of nature safe or wise? Nil mortalibus ardui est:

Daedalus broke through the air just like Hercules broke into hell. The discovery of fire gave us access to a forbidden secret. Is this unnatural triumph over nature safe or wise? Nothing is too difficult for mortals:

   Man finds no feat too hard or high;
    Heaven is not safe from man's desire.
    Our rash designs move Jove to ire,
   He dares not lay his thunder by.
   Man finds no challenge too tough or lofty;  
    Heaven isn't off-limits to man's ambition.  
    Our reckless plans provoke Jove's anger,  
   He doesn't dare put his thunder down.

The thought of this ode [Footnote: i. 3.] roughly expresses what would have been the instinctive sense of thoughtful Greeks if the idea of Progress had been presented to them. It would have struck them as audacious, the theory of men unduly elated and perilously at ease in the presence of unknown incalculable powers.

The idea behind this ode [Footnote: i. 3.] roughly captures what thoughtful Greeks would have instinctively felt if the concept of Progress had been introduced to them. They would have found it bold, viewing the notion as one where people were overly confident and dangerously complacent in the face of unknown, unpredictable forces.

This feeling or attitude was connected with the idea of Moira. If we were to name any single idea as generally controlling or pervading Greek thought from Homer to the Stoics, [Footnote: The Stoics identified Moira with Pronoia, in accordance with their theory that the universe is permeated by thought.] it would perhaps be Moira, for which we have no equivalent. The common rendering "fate" is misleading. Moira meant a fixed order in the universe; but as a fact to which men must bow, it had enough in common with fatality to demand a philosophy of resignation and to hinder the creation of an optimistic atmosphere of hope. It was this order which kept things in their places, assigned to each its proper sphere and function, and drew a definite line, for instance, between men and gods. Human progress towards perfection—towards an ideal of omniscience, or an ideal of happiness, would have been a breaking down of the bars which divide the human from the divine. Human nature does not alter; it is fixed by Moira.

This feeling or attitude was tied to the concept of Moira. If we were to pinpoint any single idea that dominated Greek thought from Homer to the Stoics, it would likely be Moira, for which we have no direct equivalent. The usual translation "fate" is misleading. Moira represented a fixed order in the universe; yet, as something people had to accept, it shared enough with fatality to require a philosophy of resignation and to prevent an optimistic atmosphere of hope. It was this order that kept everything in its place, assigned each its rightful role and function, and established clear boundaries, for example, between humans and gods. Human progress toward perfection—toward an ideal of all-knowingness or an ideal of happiness—would have meant breaking down the barriers that separate the human from the divine. Human nature does not change; it is determined by Moira.

5.

5.

We can see now how it was that speculative Greek minds never hit on the idea of Progress. In the first place, their limited historical experience did not easily suggest such a synthesis; and in the second place, the axioms of their thought, their suspiciousness of change, their theories of Moira, of degeneration and cycles, suggested a view of the world which was the very antithesis of progressive development. Epicurean, philosophers made indeed what might have been an important step in the direction of the doctrine of Progress, by discarding the theory of degeneration, and recognising that civilisation had been created by a series of successive improvements achieved by the effort of man alone. But here they stopped short. For they had their eyes fixed on the lot of the individual here and now, and their study of the history of humanity was strictly subordinate to this personal interest. The value of their recognition of human progress in the past is conditioned by the general tenor and purpose of their theory of life. It was simply one item in their demonstration that man owed nothing to supernatural intervention and had nothing to fear from supernatural powers. It is however no accident that the school of thought which struck on a path that might have led to the idea of Progress was the most uncompromising enemy of superstition that Greece produced.

We can now see why speculative Greek thinkers never came up with the idea of Progress. First, their limited historical experience didn’t easily lend itself to such a concept; and second, the principles they operated under, their wariness of change, their beliefs about Fate, degeneration, and cycles, suggested a worldview that was the complete opposite of progressive development. Epicurean philosophers did take an important step toward the idea of Progress by rejecting the theory of degeneration and acknowledging that civilization was created through a series of improvements made by human effort alone. But that’s where they stopped. They were focused on the individual's situation in the present, and their exploration of human history was strictly tied to this personal interest. The value of their acknowledgment of human progress in the past is shaped by the overall tone and goal of their life philosophy. It was just one point in their argument that humans owe nothing to supernatural intervention and have nothing to fear from supernatural forces. It’s no coincidence that the school of thought that ventured into a path that could have led to the idea of Progress was the most steadfast opponent of superstition in Greece.

It might be thought that the establishment of Roman rule and order in a large part of the known world, and the civilising of barbarian peoples, could not fail to have opened to the imagination of some of those who reflected on it in the days of Virgil or of Seneca, a vista into the future. But there was no change in the conditions of life likely to suggest a brighter view of human existence. With the loss of freedom pessimism increased, and the Greek philosophies of resignation were needed more than ever. Those whom they could not satisfy turned their thoughts to new mystical philosophies and religions, which were little interested in the earthly destinies of human society.

It might be thought that the establishment of Roman rule and order over a large part of the known world, along with the civilizing of barbarian peoples, would inevitably have sparked the imagination of some who reflected on it during the days of Virgil or Seneca, offering a glimpse into the future. However, there was no change in life conditions that would suggest a brighter outlook on human existence. With the loss of freedom, pessimism grew, and the Greek philosophies of resignation became more necessary than ever. Those who couldn’t find comfort in them began exploring new mystical philosophies and religions, which were mostly uninterested in the earthly fates of human society.

II 1.

II 1.

The idea of the universe which prevailed throughout the Middle Ages, and the general orientation of men's thoughts were incompatible with some of the fundamental assumptions which are required by the idea of Progress. According to the Christian theory which was worked out by the Fathers, and especially by St. Augustine, the whole movement of history has the purpose of securing the happiness of a small portion of the human race in another world; it does not postulate a further development of human history on earth. For Augustine, as for any medieval believer, the course of history would be satisfactorily complete if the world came to an end in his own lifetime. He was not interested in the question whether any gradual amelioration of society or increase of knowledge would mark the period of time which might still remain to run before the day of Judgment. In Augustine's system the Christian era introduced the last period of history, the old age of humanity, which would endure only so long as to enable the Deity to gather in the predestined number of saved people. This theory might be combined with the widely-spread belief in a millennium on earth, but the conception of such a dispensation does not render it a theory of Progress.

The view of the universe that dominated during the Middle Ages and the general mindset of people were at odds with some of the basic ideas needed for the concept of Progress. The Christian theory developed by the Church Fathers, especially St. Augustine, suggested that the entire course of history aimed to secure the happiness of a small segment of humanity in the afterlife; it didn't assume any further development of human history on earth. For Augustine, as for any medieval believer, history would be perfectly complete if the world ended during his lifetime. He wasn't concerned with whether any gradual improvement in society or increase in knowledge would characterize the time left before Judgment Day. In Augustine's framework, the Christian era marked the final phase of history, the old age of humanity, which would last only long enough for God to gather the predestined number of saved souls. This idea could be tied to the widely held belief in a millennium on earth, but this notion doesn't turn it into a theory of Progress.

Again, the medieval doctrine apprehends history not as a natural development but as a series of events ordered by divine intervention and revelations. If humanity had been left to go its own way it would have drifted to a highly undesirable port, and all men would have incurred the fate of everlasting misery from which supernatural interference rescued the minority. A belief in Providence might indeed, and in a future age would, be held along with a belief in Progress, in the same mind; but the fundamental assumptions were incongruous, and so long as the doctrine of Providence was undisputedly in the ascendant, a doctrine of Progress could not arise. And the doctrine of Providence, as it was developed in Augustine's "City of God," controlled the thought of the Middle Ages.

Once again, the medieval view sees history not as a natural evolution but as a sequence of events guided by divine intervention and revelations. If humanity had been left to its own devices, it would have ended up in a very undesirable situation, and everyone would have faced the fate of eternal misery from which supernatural intervention saved the few. A belief in Providence might indeed, and in a future era would, coexist with a belief in Progress in the same mindset; however, the core assumptions were incompatible, and as long as the belief in Providence was firmly in control, a belief in Progress could not emerge. The concept of Providence, as outlined in Augustine's "City of God," dominated medieval thought.

There was, moreover, the doctrine of original sin, an insuperable obstacle to the moral amelioration of the race by any gradual process of development. For since, so long as the human species endures on earth, every child will be born naturally evil and worthy of punishment, a moral advance of humanity to perfection is plainly impossible. [Footnote: It may be added that, as G. Monod observed, "les hommes du moyen age n'avaient pas conscience des modifications successives que le temps apporte avec lui dans les choses humaines" (Revue Historique, i. p. 8).]

There was also the belief in original sin, which was a major barrier to improving humanity through any gradual development process. Since, as long as the human race exists on earth, every child will be born inherently evil and deserving of punishment, it's clearly impossible for humanity to make moral progress toward perfection. [Footnote: It may be added that, as G. Monod observed, "les hommes du moyen age n'avaient pas conscience des modifications successives que le temps apporte avec lui dans les choses humaines" (Revue Historique, i. p. 8).]

2.

2.

But there are certain features in the medieval theory of which we must not ignore the significance. In the first place, while it maintained the belief in degeneration, endorsed by Hebrew mythology, it definitely abandoned the Greek theory of cycles. The history of the earth was recognised as a unique phenomenon in time; it would never occur again or anything resembling it. More important than all is the fact that Christian theology constructed a synthesis which for the first time attempted to give a definite meaning to the whole course of human events, a synthesis which represents the past as leading up to a definite and desirable goal in the future. Once this belief had been generally adopted and prevailed for centuries men might discard it along with the doctrine of Providence on which it rested, but they could not be content to return again to such views as satisfied the ancients, for whom human history, apprehended as a whole, was a tale of little meaning. [Footnote: It may be observed that Augustine (De Civ. Dei, x. 14) compares the teaching (recta eruditio) of the people of God, in the gradual process of history, to the education of an individual. Prudentius has a similar comparison for a different purpose (c. Symmachum, ii. 315 sqq.):

But there are certain aspects of medieval theory that we shouldn't overlook. First of all, while it upheld the belief in degeneration, supported by Hebrew mythology, it clearly moved away from the Greek theory of cycles. The history of the earth was seen as a unique occurrence in time; it would never happen again or anything similar. More importantly, Christian theology created a synthesis that, for the first time, tried to give a clear meaning to the entire course of human events, a synthesis that portrayed the past as leading to a specific and positive goal in the future. Once this belief was widely accepted and lasted for centuries, people might have dismissed it along with the doctrine of Providence that supported it, but they couldn't simply go back to the views that satisfied the ancients, for whom human history, understood as a whole, was a story of little significance. [Footnote: It may be observed that Augustine (De Civ. Dei, x. 14) compares the teaching (recta eruditio) of the people of God, in the gradual process of history, to the education of an individual. Prudentius has a similar comparison for a different purpose (c. Symmachum, ii. 315 sqq.):

Tardis semper processibus aucta Crescit vita hominis et longo proficit usu. Sic aevi mortalis habet se mobilis ordo, Sic variat natura vices, infantia repit, etc.

Tardis semper processibus aucta Crescit vita hominis et longo proficit usu. Sic aevi mortalis habet se mobilis ordo, Sic variat natura vices, infantia repit, etc.

Floras (Epitome, ad init.) had already divided Roman history into four periods corresponding to infancy, adolescence, manhood, and old age.]

Floras (Epitome, ad init.) had already split Roman history into four stages: infancy, adolescence, adulthood, and old age.

They must seek for some new synthesis to replace it.

They need to find a new synthesis to take its place.

Another feature of the medieval theory, pertinent to our inquiry, was an idea which Christianity took over from Greek and Roman thinkers. In the later period of Greek history, which began with the conquests of Alexander the Great, there had emerged the conception of the whole inhabited world as a unity and totality, the idea of the whole human race as one. We may conveniently call it the ecumenical idea—the principle of the ecumene or inhabited world, as opposed to the principle of the polis or city. Promoted by the vast extension of the geographical limits of the Greek world resulting from Alexander's conquests, and by his policy of breaking down the barriers between Greek and barbarian, the idea was reflected in the Stoic doctrine that all men are brothers, and that a man's true country is not his own particular city, but the ecumene. [Footnote: Plutarch long ago saw the connection between the policy of Alexander and the cosmopolitan teaching of Zeno. De Alexandri Magni virtute, i. Sec. 6.] It soon became familiar, popularised by the most popular of the later philosophies of Greece; and just as it had been implied in the imperial aspiration and polity of Alexander, so it was implied, still more clearly, in the imperial theory of Rome. The idea of the Roman Empire, its theoretical justification, might be described as the realisation of the unity of the world by the establishment of a common order, the unification of mankind in a single world-embracing political organism. The term "world," orbis (terrarum), which imperial poets use freely in speaking of the Empire, is more than a mere poetical or patriotic exaggeration; it expresses the idea, the unrealised ideal of the Empire. There is a stone from Halicarnassus in the British Museum, on which the idea is formally expressed from another point of view. The inscription is of the time of Augustus, and the Emperor is designated as "saviour of the community of mankind." There we have the notion of the human race apprehended as a whole, the ecumenical idea, imposing upon Rome the task described by Virgil as regere imperio populos, and more humanely by Pliny as the creation of a single fatherland for all the peoples of the world. [Footnote: Pliny, Nat. Hist. iii. 6. 39.]

Another aspect of medieval theory that relates to our discussion is an idea that Christianity adopted from Greek and Roman thinkers. During the later period of Greek history, starting with Alexander the Great's conquests, the concept emerged of the entire inhabited world as a single unity, the idea of humanity as one. We can conveniently refer to this as the ecumenical idea—the principle of the ecumene or inhabited world, as opposed to the principle of the polis or city. This notion was encouraged by the extensive geographical expansion of the Greek world that resulted from Alexander's conquests and his efforts to bridge the gap between Greeks and non-Greeks. It was reflected in the Stoic belief that all humans are brothers and that a person's true homeland is not their individual city, but the ecumene. [Footnote: Plutarch long ago saw the connection between the policy of Alexander and the cosmopolitan teaching of Zeno. De Alexandri Magni virtute, i. Sec. 6.] This idea soon became widely known, popularized by the most influential later philosophies of Greece; and just as it was implied in Alexander's imperial aspirations and policies, it was even more evident in the imperial theory of Rome. The concept of the Roman Empire, its theoretical justification, could be described as the realization of global unity by creating a common order, unifying humanity in a single, all-encompassing political entity. The term "world," orbis (terrarum), which imperial poets frequently used in discussing the Empire, represents more than just poetic or nationalistic exaggeration; it conveys the idea, the unrealized ideal of the Empire. There is a stone from Halicarnassus in the British Museum that formally expresses this idea from another perspective. The inscription, dating from the time of Augustus, refers to the Emperor as the "savior of the community of mankind." Here, we see the concept of the human race understood as a whole, the ecumenical idea, imposing upon Rome the duty described by Virgil as regere imperio populos, and more humanely by Pliny as the creation of a single homeland for all the peoples of the world. [Footnote: Pliny, Nat. Hist. iii. 6. 39.]

This idea, which in the Roman Empire and in the Middle Ages took the form of a universal State and a universal Church, passed afterwards into the conception of the intercohesion of peoples as contributors to a common pool of civilisation—a principle which, when the idea of Progress at last made its appearance in the world, was to be one of the elements in its growth.

This idea, which during the Roman Empire and the Middle Ages manifested as a universal State and a universal Church, eventually evolved into the understanding of different peoples as contributors to a shared pool of civilization—a principle that, when the concept of Progress finally emerged in the world, became one of the key factors in its development.

3.

3.

One remarkable man, the Franciscan friar Roger Bacon, [Footnote: c. A.D. 1210-92. Of Bacon's Opus Majus the best and only complete edition is that of J. H. Bridges, 2 vols. 1897 (with an excellent Introduction). The associated works, Opus Minus and Opus Tertium, have been edited by Brewer, Fr. Rogeri Bacon Opera Inedita, 1859.]who stands on an isolated pinnacle of his own in the Middle Ages, deserves particular consideration. It has been claimed for him that he announced the idea of Progress; he has even been compared to Condorcet or Comte. Such claims are based on passages taken out of their context and indulgently interpreted in the light of later theories. They are not borne out by an examination of his general conception of the universe and the aim of his writings.

One remarkable man, the Franciscan friar Roger Bacon, [Footnote: c. A.D. 1210-92. The best and only complete edition of Bacon's Opus Majus is by J. H. Bridges, 2 vols. 1897 (with an excellent Introduction). The related works, Opus Minus and Opus Tertium, have been edited by Brewer, Fr. Rogeri Bacon Opera Inedita, 1859.] who stands alone in the Middle Ages, deserves special attention. Some have claimed that he introduced the idea of Progress; he has even been compared to Condorcet or Comte. These claims are based on quotes taken out of context and interpreted generously through the lens of later theories. They are not supported by a look at his overall view of the universe and the purpose of his writings.

His aim was to reform higher education and introduce into the universities a wide, liberal, and scientific programme of secular studies. His chief work, the "Opus Majus," was written for this purpose, to which his exposition of his own discoveries was subordinate. It was addressed and sent to Pope Clement IV., who had asked Bacon to give him an account of his researches, and was designed to persuade the Pontiff of the utility of science from an ecclesiastical point of view, and to induce him to sanction an intellectual reform, which without the approbation of the Church would at that time have been impossible. With great ingenuity and resourcefulness he sought to show that the studies to which he was devoted—mathematics, astronomy, physics, chemistry—were indispensable to an intelligent study of theology and Scripture. Though some of his arguments may have been urged simply to capture the Pope's good-will, there can be no question that Bacon was absolutely sincere in his view that theology was the mistress (dominatrix) of the sciences and that their supreme value lay in being necessary to it.

His goal was to reform higher education and introduce a broad, liberal, and scientific curriculum focused on secular studies in universities. His main work, the "Opus Majus," was written for this purpose, with his explanation of his own discoveries being secondary. It was addressed to Pope Clement IV, who had asked Bacon for an overview of his research, and was intended to convince the Pope of the importance of science from a church perspective, encouraging him to support an intellectual reform that would have been impossible without the Church's approval at that time. With great creativity and resourcefulness, he aimed to demonstrate that the subjects he was passionate about—mathematics, astronomy, physics, chemistry—were essential for a deeper understanding of theology and Scriptures. While some of his arguments may have been made simply to win the Pope's favor, there's no doubt that Bacon sincerely believed that theology was the master of the sciences and that their greatest value lay in being essential to it.

It was, indeed, on this principle of the close interconnection of all branches of knowledge that Bacon based his plea and his scheme of reform. And the idea of the "solidarity" of the sciences, in which he anticipated a later age, is one of his two chief claims to be remembered. [Footnote: Cp. Opus Tertium, c. iv. p. 18, omnes scientiae sunt connexae et mutuis se fovent auxiliis sicut partes ejusdem totius, quarum quaelibet opus suum peragit non solum propter se sed pro aliis.] It is the motif of the Opus Majus, and it would have been more fully elaborated if he had lived to complete the encyclopaedic work, Scriptum Principale, which he had only begun before his death. His other title to fame is well-known. He realised, as no man had done before him, the importance of the experimental method in investigating the secrets of nature, and was an almost solitary pioneer in the paths to which his greater namesake, more than three hundred years later, was to invite the attention of the world.

It was, in fact, on the principle of the close connection of all areas of knowledge that Bacon based his argument and his plan for reform. The idea of the "solidarity" of the sciences, which he foresaw before his time, is one of his two main reasons to be remembered. [Footnote: Cp. Opus Tertium, c. iv. p. 18, all sciences are interconnected and support each other like parts of a whole, each fulfilling its role not just for itself but for others.] This concept is the theme of the Opus Majus, and it would have been developed more fully if he had lived to finish the comprehensive work, Scriptum Principale, which he had only started before he died. His other reason for being famous is well-known. He understood, as no one had before him, the importance of the experimental method in exploring the secrets of nature, and he was almost a lone pioneer on the paths that his more famous counterpart, over three hundred years later, would lead the world to explore.

But, although Roger Bacon was inspired by these enlightened ideas, although he cast off many of the prejudices of his time and boldly revolted against the tyranny of the prevailing scholastic philosophy, he was nevertheless in other respects a child of his age and could not disencumber himself of the current medieval conception of the universe. His general view of the course of human history was not materially different from that of St. Augustine. When he says that the practical object of all knowledge is to assure the safety of the human race, he explains this to mean "things which lead to felicity in the next life." [Footnote: Opus Majus, vii. p. 366.]

But even though Roger Bacon was inspired by these enlightened ideas, and even though he rejected many of the prejudices of his time and boldly stood up against the constraints of the dominant scholastic philosophy, he was still, in other ways, a product of his era and could not shake off the prevalent medieval view of the universe. His overall perspective on human history wasn't fundamentally different from that of St. Augustine. When he claims that the main purpose of all knowledge is to ensure the safety of humanity, he clarifies this to mean "things that lead to happiness in the next life." [Footnote: Opus Majus, vii. p. 366.]

It is pertinent to observe that he not only shared in the belief in astrology, which was then universal, but considered it one of the most important parts of "mathematics." It was looked upon with disfavour by the Church as a dangerous study; Bacon defended its use in the interests of the Church itself. He maintained, like Thomas Aquinas, the physiological influence of the celestial bodies, and regarded the planets as signs telling us what God has decreed from eternity to come to pass either by natural processes or by acts of human will or directly at his own good pleasure. Deluges, plagues, and earthquakes were capable of being predicted; political and religious revolutions were set in the starry rubric. The existence of six principal religions was determined by the combinations of Jupiter with the other six planets. Bacon seriously expected the extinction of the Mohammedan religion before the end of the thirteenth century, on the ground of a prediction by an Arab astrologer. [Footnote: Ib. iv. p. 266; vii. p. 389.]

It’s important to note that he not only believed in astrology, which was common at the time, but also saw it as one of the most significant aspects of "mathematics." The Church viewed it negatively as a risky pursuit; however, Bacon defended its use for the Church's own benefit. Like Thomas Aquinas, he argued for the physiological impact of celestial bodies and believed the planets were signs indicating what God had determined from eternity to happen, whether through natural processes, human actions, or direct divine intervention. He thought that events like floods, plagues, and earthquakes could be predicted, and that political and religious revolutions were written in the stars. The existence of six major religions was connected to the alignments of Jupiter with the other six planets. Bacon genuinely anticipated the decline of the Muslim faith before the end of the thirteenth century, based on a prediction made by an Arab astrologer. [Footnote: Ib. iv. p. 266; vii. p. 389.]

One of the greatest advantages that the study of astrological lore will bring to humanity is that by its means the date of the coming of Anti-Christ may be fixed with certainty, and the Church may be prepared to face the perils and trials of that terrible time. Now the arrival of Anti-Christ meant the end of the world, and Bacon accepted the view, which he says was held by all wise men, that "we are not far from the times of Anti-Christ." Thus the intellectual reforms which he urged would have the effect, and no more, of preparing Christendom to resist more successfully the corruption in which the rule of Anti-Christ would involve the world. "Truth will prevail," by which he meant science will make advances, "though with difficulty, until Anti-Christ and his forerunners appear;" and on his own showing the interval would probably be short.

One of the biggest benefits of studying astrological knowledge is that it can help determine the date of the Anti-Christ's arrival, allowing the Church to prepare for the dangers and challenges of that dark time. The arrival of the Anti-Christ signified the end of the world, and Bacon believed, as did many wise people, that "we are not far from the times of Anti-Christ." Therefore, the intellectual reforms he promoted would serve to help Christendom more effectively resist the corruption that the Anti-Christ’s rule would bring to the world. "Truth will prevail," meaning that science will progress, "though with difficulty, until the Anti-Christ and his forerunners show up;" and based on his assessment, the time before this would likely be short.

The frequency with which Bacon recurs to this subject, and the emphasis he lays on it, show that the appearance of Anti-Christ was a fixed point in his mental horizon. When he looked forward into the future, the vision which confronted him was a scene of corruption, tyranny, and struggle under the reign of a barbarous enemy of Christendom; and after that, the end of the world. [Footnote: (1) His coming may be fixed by astrology: Opus Majus, iv. p. 269 (inveniretur sufficiens suspicio vel magis certitudo de tempore Antichristi; cp. p. 402). (2) His coming means the end of the world: ib. p. 262. (3) We are not far from it: ib. p. 402. One of the reasons which seem to have made this view probable to Bacon was the irruption of the Mongols into Europe during his lifetime; cp. p. 268 and vii. p. 234. Another was the prevalent corruption, especially of the clergy, which impressed him deeply; see Compendium studii philosophiae, ed. Brewer, p. 402. (4) "Truth will prevail," etc.: Opus Majus, i. pp. 19, 20. He claimed for experimental science that it would produce inventions which could be usefully employed against Antichrist: ib. vii. p. 221.] It is from this point of view that we must appreciate the observations which he made on the advancement of knowledge. "It is our duty," he says, "to supply what the ancients have left incomplete, because we have entered into their labours, which, unless we are asses, can stimulate us to achieve better results"; Aristotle corrected the errors of earlier thinkers; Avicenna and Averroes have corrected Aristotle in some matters and have added much that is new; and so it will go on till the end of the world. And Bacon quotes passages from Seneca's "Physical Inquiries" to show that the acquisition of knowledge is gradual. Attention has been already called to those passages, and it was shown how perverse it is, on the strength of such remarks, to claim Seneca as a teacher of the doctrine of Progress. The same claim has been made for Bacon with greater confidence, and it is no less perverse. The idea of Progress is glaringly incongruous with his vision of the world. If his programme of revolutionising secular learning had been accepted—it fell completely dead, and his work was forgotten for many ages,—he would have been the author of a progressive reform; but how many reformers have there been before and after Bacon on whose minds the idea of Progress never dawned?

The frequency with which Bacon returns to this topic and the emphasis he places on it indicate that the emergence of Anti-Christ was a definite concern for him. When he envisioned the future, he saw a scene filled with corruption, tyranny, and conflict under a savage enemy of Christianity, followed by the end of the world. [Footnote: (1) His arrival might be determined by astrology: Opus Majus, iv. p. 269 (sufficient suspicion or more certainty about the timing of the Anti-Christ; cp. p. 402). (2) His arrival signifies the end of the world: ib. p. 262. (3) We are close to it: ib. p. 402. One reason Bacon found this perspective plausible was the invasion of the Mongols into Europe during his lifetime; cp. p. 268 and vii. p. 234. Another reason was the widespread corruption, especially among the clergy, which significantly impacted him; see Compendium studii philosophiae, ed. Brewer, p. 402. (4) "Truth will prevail," etc.: Opus Majus, i. pp. 19, 20. He argued that experimental science would lead to discoveries that could effectively combat Anti-Christ: ib. vii. p. 221.] It is from this perspective that we need to understand his comments on the progress of knowledge. "It is our responsibility," he says, "to complete what the ancients left unfinished, as we have built upon their work, which should inspire us to achieve greater results"; Aristotle corrected the mistakes of earlier thinkers; Avicenna and Averroes corrected Aristotle on some issues and introduced many new ideas; and this process will continue until the end of the world. Bacon cites passages from Seneca's "Physical Inquiries" to illustrate that gaining knowledge is a gradual process. We have already noted these passages and shown how misguided it is to claim Seneca as a proponent of the Progress doctrine based on such remarks. The same assertion has been made for Bacon with even more confidence, and it is equally misguided. The concept of Progress is notably at odds with his view of the world. If his plan to revolutionize secular learning had been embraced—which ultimately failed, and his work was forgotten for many ages—he would have been the architect of a progressive reform; but how many reformers, before and after Bacon, have operated without ever contemplating the idea of Progress?

[Footnote: Bacon quotes Seneca: See Opus Majus, i. pp. 37, 55, 14.

[Footnote: Bacon quotes Seneca: See Opus Majus, i. pp. 37, 55, 14.]

Much has been made out of a well-known passage in his short Epistle de secretis operibus artis et naturae et de militate magiae, c. iv. (ed. Brewer, p. 533), in which he is said to PREDICT inventions which have been realised in the locomotives, steam navigation, and aeroplanes of modern times. But Bacon predicts nothing. He is showing that science can invent curious and, to the vulgar, incredible things without the aid of magic. All the inventions which he enumerates have, he declares, been actually made in ancient times, with the exception of a flying-machine (instrumentum volandi quod non vidi nec hominem qui vidisset cognovi, sed sapientem qui hoc artificium excogitavit explere cognosco).

Much has been said about a famous passage in his short letter "On the Secret Works of Art and Nature and the Military Use of Magic," c. iv. (ed. Brewer, p. 533), where he is said to PREDICT inventions that have emerged in modern locomotives, steam navigation, and airplanes. But Bacon isn’t predicting anything. He’s demonstrating that science can create amazing and, to the average person, unbelievable things without relying on magic. He claims that all the inventions he lists have actually been made in ancient times, except for a flying machine (instrumentum volandi quod non vidi nec hominem qui vidisset cognovi, sed sapientem qui hoc artificium excogitavit explere cognosco).

Compare the remarks of S. Vogl, Die Physik Roger Bacos (1906), 98 sqq.]

Compare the comments of S. Vogl, Die Physik Roger Bacos (1906), 98 sqq.]

4.

4.

Thus Friar Bacon's theories of scientific reform, so far from amounting to an anticipation of the idea of Progress, illustrate how impossible it was that this idea could appear in the Middle Ages. The whole spirit of medieval Christianity excluded it. The conceptions which were entertained of the working of divine Providence, the belief that the world, surprised like a sleeping household by a thief in the night, might at any moment come to a sudden end, had the same effect as the Greek theories of the nature of change and of recurring cycles of the world. Or rather, they had a more powerful effect, because they were not reasoned conclusions, but dogmas guaranteed by divine authority. And medieval pessimism as to man's mundane condition was darker and sterner than the pessimism of the Greeks. There was the prospect of happiness in another sphere to compensate, but this, engrossing the imagination, only rendered it less likely that any one should think of speculating about man's destinies on earth.

Thus, Friar Bacon's theories on scientific reform, rather than predicting the idea of Progress, show how impossible it was for this idea to emerge during the Middle Ages. The entire spirit of medieval Christianity rejected it. The beliefs about divine Providence and the idea that the world could suddenly end, like a household caught off guard by a thief in the night, had a similar effect as the Greek theories about change and the cyclical nature of the world. In fact, they had an even stronger impact because they were not just reasoned arguments but dogmas backed by divine authority. Additionally, medieval pessimism regarding human existence was bleaker and harsher than that of the Greeks. There was the hope of happiness in another realm to provide some compensation, but this focus on the afterlife made it less likely for anyone to consider speculating about human fate on earth.

III 1.

III 1.

The civilised countries of Europe spent about three hundred years in passing from the mental atmosphere of the Middle Ages into the mental atmosphere of the modern world. These centuries were one of the conspicuously progressive periods in history, but the conditions were not favourable to the appearance of an idea of Progress, though the intellectual milieu was being prepared in which that idea could be born. This progressive period, which is conveniently called the Renaissance, lasted from the fourteenth into the seventeenth century. The great results, significant for our present purpose, which the human mind achieved at this stage of its development were two. Self-confidence was restored to human reason, and life on this planet was recognised as possessing a value independent of any hopes or fears connected with a life beyond the grave.

The civilized countries of Europe spent about three hundred years transitioning from the mindset of the Middle Ages to that of the modern world. These centuries were notably progressive in history, but the conditions weren’t ideal for the emergence of the idea of Progress, even though the intellectual environment was being shaped for it. This progressive period, commonly referred to as the Renaissance, lasted from the fourteenth to the seventeenth century. The significant outcomes relevant to our current discussion that the human mind achieved during this stage of development were twofold. First, human reason regained its self-confidence, and second, life on this planet was recognized as having value independent of any hopes or fears related to an afterlife.

But in discarding medieval naivete and superstition, in assuming a freer attitude towards theological authority, and in developing a new conception of the value of individual personality, men looked to the guidance of Greek and Roman thinkers, and called up the spirit of the ancient world to exorcise the ghosts of the dark ages. Their minds were thus directed backwards to a past civilisation which, in the ardour of new discovery, and in the reaction against medievalism, they enthroned as ideal; and a new authority was set up, the authority of ancient writers. In general speculation the men of the Renaissance followed the tendencies and adopted many of the prejudices of Greek philosophy. Although some great discoveries, with far-reaching, revolutionary consequences, were made in this period, most active minds were engaged in rediscovering, elaborating, criticising, and imitating what was old. It was not till the closing years of the Renaissance that speculation began to seek and feel its way towards new points of departure. It was not till then that a serious reaction set in against the deeper influences of medieval thought.

But in rejecting medieval simplicity and superstition, adopting a more open attitude towards religious authority, and developing a fresh understanding of the importance of individual identity, people looked to the insights of Greek and Roman philosophers and summoned the spirit of the ancient world to drive away the shadows of the dark ages. Their thoughts were oriented towards a past civilization that they idealized in the excitement of new discoveries and in their pushback against medievalism; a new authority emerged, that of ancient writers. Generally, during the Renaissance, thinkers followed the trends and adopted many biases of Greek philosophy. While some groundbreaking discoveries with significant, revolutionary impacts were made in this period, the majority of active minds were focused on rediscovering, elaborating on, critiquing, and imitating what had come before. It wasn't until the late years of the Renaissance that serious exploration began to seek and find new directions. It was only then that a genuine reaction against the deeper influences of medieval thought started to take shape.

2.

2.

To illustrate the limitations of this period let us take Machiavelli, one of the most original thinkers that Italy ever produced.

To show the limitations of this period, let’s consider Machiavelli, one of the most original thinkers Italy has ever produced.

There are certain fundamental principles underlying Machiavelli's science of politics, which he has indicated incidentally in his unsystematic way, but which are essential to the comprehension of his doctrines. The first is that at all times the world of human beings has been the same, varying indeed from land to land, but always presenting the same aspect of some societies advancing towards prosperity, and others declining. Those which are on the upward grade will always reach a point beyond which they cannot rise further, but they will not remain permanently on this level, they will begin to decline; for human things are always in motion and therefore must go up or down. Similarly, declining states will ultimately touch bottom and then begin to ascend. Thus a good constitution or social organisation can last only for a short time. [Footnote: Machiavelli's principle of advance and decline: Discorsi, ii. Introduction; Istorie fiorentine, v. ad init. For the cycle of constitutions through which all states tend to move see Discorsi, ii. 2 (here we see the influence of Polybius).]

There are some basic principles behind Machiavelli's approach to politics, which he has mentioned in a casual way, but these are crucial for understanding his ideas. The first is that, throughout history, human society has remained fundamentally the same, differing from place to place, but always showing some groups moving toward prosperity while others are in decline. Those that are growing will eventually hit a peak beyond which they can’t rise any higher, and they won’t stay at that level forever; they will start to decline because human affairs are always in flux and must either rise or fall. Likewise, declining states will eventually hit rock bottom and then begin to rise again. Therefore, a solid constitution or social structure can only last for a limited time. [Footnote: Machiavelli's principle of advance and decline: Discorsi, ii. Introduction; Istorie fiorentine, v. ad init. For the cycle of constitutions through which all states tend to move see Discorsi, ii. 2 (here we see the influence of Polybius).]

It is obvious that in this view of history Machiavelli was inspired and instructed by the ancients. And it followed from his premisses that the study of the past is of the highest value because it enables men to see what is to come; since to all social events at any period there are correspondences in ancient times. "For these events are due to men, who have and always had the same passions, and therefore of necessity the effects must be the same." [Footnote: Discorsi, iii. 43.]

It’s clear that in this perspective on history, Machiavelli drew inspiration and guidance from the ancients. He believed that studying the past is incredibly valuable because it allows people to anticipate what’s ahead; there are parallels between social events in any era and those in ancient times. "These events result from human behavior, which has always been driven by the same passions, and so the outcomes must inevitably be the same." [Footnote: Discorsi, iii. 43.]

Again, Machiavelli follows his ancient masters in assuming as evident that a good organisation of society can be effected only by the deliberate design of a wise legislator. [Footnote: Ib. iii. 1. The lawgiver must assume for his purposes that all men are bad: ib. i. 3. Villari has useful remarks on these principles in his Machiavelli, Book ii. cap. iii.] Forms of government and religions are the personal creations of a single brain; and the only chance for a satisfactory constitution or for a religion to maintain itself for any length of time is constantly to repress any tendencies to depart from the original conceptions of its creator.

Again, Machiavelli follows his ancient masters by assuming it's clear that a well-organized society can only be achieved through the intentional efforts of a wise lawmaker. [Footnote: Ib. iii. 1. The lawmaker must consider that all men are inherently bad: ib. i. 3. Villari provides useful insights on these principles in his Machiavelli, Book ii. cap. iii.] Forms of government and religions are the personal creations of a single mind; and the only way for a constitution or a religion to last is to consistently suppress any tendencies to stray from the original ideas of its creator.

It is evident that these two assumptions are logically connected. The lawgiver builds on the immutability of human nature; what is good for one generation must be good for another. For Machiavelli, as for Plato, change meant corruption. Thus his fundamental theory excluded any conception of a satisfactory social order gradually emerging by the impersonal work of successive generations, adapting their institutions to their own changing needs and aspirations. It is characteristic, and another point of resemblance with ancient thinkers that he sought the ideal state in the past—republican Rome.

It's clear that these two assumptions are logically connected. The lawmaker relies on the unchanging nature of humanity; what benefits one generation should benefit another. For Machiavelli, just like for Plato, change indicated decay. Therefore, his core theory ruled out any idea of a satisfactory social order developing over time through the collective efforts of successive generations, adjusting their institutions to meet their evolving needs and goals. It's notable, and another similarity with ancient philosophers, that he looked to the past—specifically republican Rome—for the ideal state.

These doctrines, the sameness of human nature and the omnipotent lawgiver, left no room for anything resembling a theory of Progress. If not held afterwards in the uncompromising form in which Machiavelli presented them, yet it has well been pointed out that they lay at the root of some of the most famous speculations of the eighteenth century. [Footnote: Villari, loc. cit.]

These beliefs, the uniformity of human nature and the all-powerful lawgiver, allowed no space for any idea of Progress. Even if they weren't later maintained in the rigid way Machiavelli described them, it's been noted that they were foundational to some of the most notable theories of the eighteenth century. [Footnote: Villari, loc. cit.]

Machiavelli's sameness of human nature meant that man would always have the same passions and desires, weaknesses and vices. This assumption was compatible with the widely prevailing view that man had degenerated in the course of the last fifteen hundred years. From the exaltation of Greek and Roman antiquity to a position of unattainable superiority, especially in the field of knowledge, the degeneration of humanity was an easy and natural inference. If the Greeks in philosophy and science were authoritative guides, if in art and literature they were unapproachable, if the Roman republic, as Machiavelli thought, was an ideal state, it would seem that the powers of Nature had declined, and she could no longer produce the same quality of brain. So long as this paralysing theory prevailed, it is manifest that the idea of Progress could not appear.

Machiavelli believed that human nature remains constant, meaning that people would always have the same passions, desires, weaknesses, and vices. This belief aligned with the common view that humanity had declined over the past fifteen hundred years. The admiration for ancient Greek and Roman culture, seen as superior—especially in knowledge—made the idea of human degeneration seem obvious and natural. If the Greeks were seen as the ultimate authorities in philosophy and science and unmatched in art and literature, and if Machiavelli viewed the Roman republic as a perfect government, it suggested that the powers of Nature had diminished, and it could no longer create such brilliant minds. As long as this limiting theory was accepted, it was clear that the concept of Progress could not emerge.

But in the course of the sixteenth century men began here and there, somewhat timidly and tentatively, to rebel against the tyranny of antiquity, or rather to prepare the way for the open rebellion which was to break out in the seventeenth. Breaches were made in the proud citadel of ancient learning. Copernicus undermined the authority of Ptolemy and his predecessors; the anatomical researches of Vesalius injured the prestige of Galen; and Aristotle was attacked on many sides by men like Telesio, Cardan, Ramus, and Bruno. [Footnote: It has been observed that the thinkers who were rebelling against the authority of Aristotle—the most dangerous of the ancient philosophers, because he was so closely associated with theological scholasticism and was supported by the Church—frequently attacked under the standard of some other ancient master; e.g. Telesio resorted to Parmenides, Justus Lipsius to the Stoics, and Bruno is under the influence of Plotinus and Plato (Bouillier, La Philosophie cartesienne, vol. i. p. 5). The idea of "development" in Bruno has been studied by Mariupolsky (Zur Geschichte des Entwicklungsbegriffs in Berner Studien, Bd. vi. 1897), who pointed out the influence of Stoicism on his thought.] In particular branches of science an innovation was beginning which heralded a radical revolution in the study of natural phenomena, though the general significance of the prospect which these researches opened was but vaguely understood at the time. The thinkers and men of science were living in an intellectual twilight. It was the twilight of dawn. At one extremity we have mysticism which culminated in the speculations of Bruno and Campanella; at the other we have the scepticism of Montaigne, Charron, and Sanchez. The bewildered condition of knowledge is indicated by the fact that while Bruno and Campanella accepted the Copernican astronomy, it was rejected by one who in many other respects may claim to be reckoned as a modern—I mean Francis Bacon.

But during the sixteenth century, people started to slowly and cautiously rebel against the dominance of ancient knowledge, setting the stage for the outright rebellion that would occur in the seventeenth century. There were cracks in the formidable fortress of classical learning. Copernicus challenged the authority of Ptolemy and those before him; Vesalius's work in anatomy diminished the reputation of Galen; and Aristotle faced criticism from thinkers like Telesio, Cardan, Ramus, and Bruno. [Footnote: It has been noted that the thinkers who were challenging Aristotle's authority—the most formidable of the ancient philosophers due to his close ties with theological scholasticism and his support from the Church—often fought under the banner of other ancient philosophers; for example, Telesio turned to Parmenides, Justus Lipsius to the Stoics, and Bruno drew influence from Plotinus and Plato (Bouillier, La Philosophie cartesienne, vol. i. p. 5). The concept of "development" in Bruno has been examined by Mariupolsky (Zur Geschichte des Entwicklungsbegriffs in Berner Studien, Bd. vi. 1897), who highlighted the impact of Stoicism on his ideas.] In certain scientific fields, innovation was beginning that foreshadowed a significant shift in understanding natural phenomena, although the wider implications of these studies were only vaguely recognized at the time. Thinkers and scientists were caught in a hazy intellectual environment. It was the twilight of dawn. On one side, we had mysticism reaching a peak with the theories of Bruno and Campanella; on the other, the skepticism of Montaigne, Charron, and Sanchez. The confused state of knowledge is illustrated by the fact that while Bruno and Campanella embraced Copernican astronomy, it was rejected by someone who could otherwise be considered modern—I mean Francis Bacon.

But the growing tendency to challenge the authority of the ancients does not sever this period from the spirit which informed the Renaissance. For it is subordinate or incidental to a more general and important interest. To rehabilitate the natural man, to claim that he should be the pilot of his own course, to assert his freedom in the fields of art and literature had been the work of the early Renaissance. It was the problem of the later Renaissance to complete this emancipation in the sphere of philosophical thought. The bold metaphysics of Bruno, for which he atoned by a fiery death, offered the solution which was most unorthodox and complete. His deification of nature and of man as part of nature involved the liberation of humanity from external authority. But other speculative minds of the age, though less audacious, were equally inspired by the idea of freely interrogating nature, and were all engaged in accomplishing the programme of the Renaissance—the vindication of this world as possessing a value for man independent of its relations to any supermundane sphere. The raptures of Giordano Bruno and the sobrieties of Francis Bacon are here on common ground. The whole movement was a necessary prelude to a new age of which science was to be the mistress.

But the increasing tendency to question the authority of the ancients doesn’t disconnect this period from the spirit that characterized the Renaissance. Instead, it is secondary or related to a broader and more significant interest. The goal of reconnecting with the natural human, arguing that he should navigate his own path, and asserting his freedom in art and literature was the mission of the early Renaissance. The challenge for the later Renaissance was to fulfill this liberation in the realm of philosophical thought. The bold metaphysics of Bruno, which he paid for with a fiery death, presented a solution that was both unorthodox and comprehensive. His elevation of nature and humanity as part of nature involved freeing people from external authority. However, other thinkers of the time, while less daring, were also motivated by the idea of freely exploring nature and were all working towards completing the Renaissance agenda—the affirmation of this world as having value for humanity independent of any higher realm. The fervor of Giordano Bruno and the seriousness of Francis Bacon find common ground here. The entire movement was a necessary prelude to a new age in which science would be the dominant force.

It is to be noted that there was a general feeling of complacency as to the condition of learning and intellectual pursuits. This optimism is expressed by Rabelais. Gargantua, in a letter to Pantagruel, studying at Paris, enlarges to his son on the vast improvements in learning and education which had recently, he says, been brought about. "All the world is full of savants, learned teachers, large libraries; and I am of opinion that neither in the time of Plato nor of Cicero nor of Papinian were there such facilities for study as one sees now." It is indeed the study of the ancient languages and literatures that Gargantua considers in a liberal education, but the satisfaction at the present diffusion of learning, with the suggestion that here at least contemporaries have an advantage over the ancients, is the significant point. [Footnote: Rabelais, Book ii. chap. 8.] This satisfaction shines through the observation of Ramus that "in one century we have seen a greater progress in men and works of learning than our ancestors had seen in the whole course of the previous fourteen centuries." [Footnote: Praefat. Scholarum Mathematicarum, maiorem doctorum hominum et operum proventum seculo uno vidimus quam totis antea 14 seculis maiores nostri viderent. (Ed. Basel, 1569.)] [Footnote 1. Guillaume Postel observed in his De magistratibus Atheniensium liber (1541) that the ages are always progressing (secula semper proficere), and every day additions are made to human knowledge, and that this process would only cease if Providence by war, or plague, or some catastrophe were to destroy all the accumulated stores of knowledge which have been transmitted from antiquity in books (Praef., B verso). What is known of the life of this almost forgotten scholar has been collected by G. Weill (De Gulielmi Postelli vita et indole, 1892). He visited the East, brought back oriental MSS., and was more than once imprisoned on charges of heresy. He dreamed of converting the Mohammedans, and of uniting the whole world under the empire of France.]

It’s important to recognize that there was a widespread sense of complacency regarding the state of learning and intellectual endeavors. This optimism is highlighted by Rabelais. In a letter to his son Pantagruel, who was studying in Paris, Gargantua elaborates on the significant advancements in learning and education that he claims have recently occurred. "The world is full of scholars, knowledgeable teachers, and extensive libraries; I believe that never during the times of Plato, Cicero, or Papinian were there such opportunities for study as we have today." Gargantua specifically considers the study of ancient languages and literature essential to a well-rounded education, but the key point is the satisfaction with the widespread availability of knowledge, suggesting that in this respect, contemporary scholars have an advantage over the ancients. [Footnote: Rabelais, Book ii. chap. 8.] This satisfaction is evident in Ramus's observation that "in just one century, we've witnessed greater progress in individuals and works of learning than our ancestors saw over the entire previous fourteen centuries." [Footnote: Praefat. Scholarum Mathematicarum, maiorem doctorum hominum et operum proventum seculo uno vidimus quam totis antea 14 seculis maiores nostri viderent. (Ed. Basel, 1569.)] [Footnote 1. Guillaume Postel noted in his De magistratibus Atheniensium liber (1541) that ages are always progressing (secula semper proficere), and every day adds to human knowledge, a process that would only stop if some disaster—war, plague, or catastrophe—were to wipe out all the accumulated knowledge passed down through books from antiquity (Praef., B verso). What little is known about this nearly forgotten scholar has been gathered by G. Weill (De Gulielmi Postelli vita et indole, 1892). He traveled to the East, returned with Eastern manuscripts, and was imprisoned multiple times on heresy charges. He envisioned converting Muslims and uniting the entire world under the French Empire.]

In this last stage of the Renaissance, which includes the first quarter of the seventeenth century, soil was being prepared in which the idea of Progress could germinate, and our history of it origin definitely begins with the work of two men who belong to this age, Bodin, who is hardly known except to special students of political science, and Bacon, who is known to all the world. Both had a more general grasp of the significance of their own time than any of their contemporaries, and though neither of them discovered a theory of Progress, they both made contributions to thought which directly contributed to its subsequent appearance.

In this final phase of the Renaissance, covering the early seventeenth century, the groundwork was being laid for the idea of Progress to take root. Our history of its origins clearly starts with the work of two men from this period: Bodin, who is mostly recognized by political science scholars, and Bacon, who is known worldwide. Both had a broader understanding of the importance of their time than anyone else around them, and while neither created a theory of Progress, their ideas significantly influenced its later development.





CHAPTER I. SOME INTERPRETATIONS OF UNIVERSAL HISTORY: BODIN AND LE ROY

1.

It is a long descent from the genius of Machiavelli to the French historian, Jean Bodin, who published his introduction to historical studies [Footnote: Methodus ad facilem historiarum cognitionem, 1566.] about forty years after Machiavelli's death. His views and his method differ widely from those of that great pioneer, whom he attacks. His readers were not arrested by startling novelties or immoral doctrine; he is safe, and dull.

It’s a significant drop from the brilliance of Machiavelli to the French historian Jean Bodin, who released his introduction to historical studies [Footnote: Methodus ad facilem historiarum cognitionem, 1566.] around forty years after Machiavelli passed away. His ideas and approach are quite different from those of that great trailblazer, whom he criticizes. His readers weren’t captivated by shocking new ideas or unethical teachings; he plays it safe and is boring.

But Bodin had a much wider range of thought than Machiavelli, whose mind was entirely concentrated on the theory of politics; and his importance for us lies not in the political speculations by which he sought to prove that monarchy is the best form of government [Footnote: Les six livres de la Republique, 1576.], but in his attempt to substitute a new theory of universal history for that which prevailed in the Middle Ages. He rejected the popular conception of a golden age and a subsequent degeneration of mankind; and he refuted the view, generally current among medieval theologians, and based on the prophecies of Daniel, which divided the course of history into four periods corresponding to the Babylonian Persian, Macedonian, and Roman monarchies, the last of which was to endure till the day of Judgement. Bodin suggests a division into three great periods: the first, of about two thousand years, in which the South-Eastern peoples were predominant; the second, of the same duration, in which those whom he calls the Middle (Mediterranean) peoples came to the front; the third, in which the Northern nations who overthrew Rome became the leaders in civilisation. Each period is stamped by the psychological character of the three racial groups. The note of the first is religion, of the second practical sagacity, of the third warfare and inventive skill. This division actually anticipates the synthesis of Hegel. [Footnote: Hegel's division is (1) the Oriental, (2) a, the Greek, b, the Roman, and (3) the Germanic worlds.] But the interesting point is that it is based on anthropological considerations, in which climate and geography are taken into account; and, notwithstanding the crudeness of the whole exposition and the intrusion of astrological arguments, it is a new step in the study of universal history. [Footnote: Climates and geography. The fullest discussion will be found in the Republique, Book v. cap. i. Here Bodin anticipated Montesquieu. There was indeed nothing new in the principle; it had been recognised by Hippocrates, Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, and other Greeks, and in a later age by Roger Bacon.

But Bodin had a much broader perspective than Machiavelli, whose focus was entirely on political theory; his significance for us lies not in the political ideas through which he argued that monarchy is the best form of government [Footnote: Les six livres de la Republique, 1576.], but in his effort to replace the prevailing medieval theory of universal history with a new one. He dismissed the common belief in a golden age followed by a decline in humanity; he also refuted the view, widely held among medieval theologians and based on the prophecies of Daniel, which divided history into four periods corresponding to the Babylonian, Persian, Macedonian, and Roman empires, the last of which was said to last until the Day of Judgment. Bodin proposed a division into three major periods: the first, lasting around two thousand years, dominated by the Southeastern peoples; the second, of the same length, during which he called the Middle (Mediterranean) peoples emerged; and the third, in which the Northern nations that toppled Rome became the leaders of civilization. Each period is defined by the psychological traits of the three racial groups. The first period is marked by religion, the second by practical wisdom, and the third by warfare and creativity. This division actually anticipates Hegel's synthesis. [Footnote: Hegel's division is (1) the Oriental, (2) a, the Greek, b, the Roman, and (3) the Germanic worlds.] However, the intriguing aspect is that it is based on anthropological factors, taking climate and geography into account; and despite the roughness of the overall explanation and the inclusion of astrological arguments, it represents a new advancement in the study of universal history. [Footnote: Climates and geography. The fullest discussion will be found in the Republique, Book v. cap. i. Here Bodin anticipated Montesquieu. There was indeed nothing new in the principle; it had been recognized by Hippocrates, Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, and other Greeks, and later by Roger Bacon.]

But Bodin first developed and applied it methodically. This part of his work was ignored, and in the eighteenth century Montesquieu's speculations on the physical factors in history were applauded as a new discovery.]

But Bodin was the first to develop and apply it systematically. This part of his work was overlooked, and in the eighteenth century, Montesquieu's ideas about the physical factors in history were celebrated as a groundbreaking revelation.

I have said that Bodin rejected the theory of the degeneration of man, along with the tradition of a previous age of virtue and felicity. [Footnote: See especially Methodus, cap. v. pp. 124, 130, 136.] The reason which he alleged against it is important. The powers of nature have always been uniform. It is illegitimate to suppose that she could at one time produce the men and conditions postulated by the theory of the golden age, and not produce them at another. In other words, Bodin asserts the principle of the permanent and undiminishing capacities of nature, and, as we shall see in the sequel, this principle was significant. It is not to be confounded with the doctrine of the immutability of human things assumed by Machiavelli. The human scene has vastly changed since the primitive age of man; "if that so-called golden age could be revoked and compared with our own, we should consider it iron." [Footnote: Methodus, cap. VII. p. 353.] For history largely depends on the will of men, which is always changing; every day new laws, new customs, new institutions, both secular and religious, come into being, and new errors. [Footnote: Ib. cap. I. p. 12.]

I have mentioned that Bodin rejected the idea of humanity's decline, along with the belief in a past era of virtue and happiness. [Footnote: See especially Methodus, cap. v. pp. 124, 130, 136.] The reasoning he provided against it is significant. The powers of nature have always been consistent. It’s unreasonable to assume that nature could once produce the men and conditions described by the theory of the golden age and not do so at another time. In other words, Bodin argues for the principle of nature's constant and unchanging capacities, which, as we will see later, is important. This should not be confused with Machiavelli's idea of the unchanging nature of human affairs. The human experience has changed dramatically since the early days of humanity; "if that so-called golden age could be compared to our own, we would consider it iron." [Footnote: Methodus, cap. VII. p. 353.] History largely relies on human will, which is always evolving; every day, new laws, customs, and institutions—both secular and religious—emerge, along with new errors. [Footnote: Ib. cap. I. p. 12.]

But in this changing scene we can observe a certain regularity, a law of oscillation. Rise is followed by fall, and fall by rise; it is a mistake to think that the human race is always deteriorating. [Footnote: Ib. cap. VII. p. 361: "cum aeterna quadam lege naturae conversio rerum omnium velut in orbem redire videatur, ut aeque vitia virtutibus, ignoratio scientiae, turpe honesto consequens sit, atque tenebrae luci, fallunt qui genus hominum semper deterius seipso evadere putant."] If that were so, we should long ago have reached the lowest stage of vice and iniquity. On the contrary, there has been, through the series of oscillations, a gradual ascent. In the ages which have been foolishly designated as gold and silver men lived like the wild beasts; and from that state they have slowly reached the humanity of manners and the social order which prevail to-day. [Footnote: Ib. p. 356.]

But in this changing scene, we can notice a certain regularity, a law of oscillation. Rise is followed by fall, and fall by rise; it’s a mistake to think that humanity is always getting worse. [Footnote: Ib. cap. VII. p. 361: "cum aeterna quadam lege naturae conversio rerum omnium velut in orbem redire videatur, ut aeque vitia virtutibus, ignoratio scientiae, turpe honesto consequens sit, atque tenebrae luci, fallunt qui genus hominum semper deterius seipso evadere putant."] If that were true, we would have reached the lowest point of vice and wickedness long ago. On the contrary, through a series of oscillations, there has been a gradual improvement. In the ages that have been foolishly called the golden and silver ages, people lived like wild animals; and from that state, they have slowly advanced to the civility and social order that exist today. [Footnote: Ib. p. 356.]

Thus Bodin recognises a general progress in the past. That is nothing new; it was the view, for instance, of the Epicureans. But much had passed in the world since the philosophy of Epicurus was alive, and Bodin had to consider twelve hundred years of new vicissitudes. Could the Epicurean theory be brought up to date?

Thus Bodin acknowledges a general progress in the past. That’s nothing new; it was the perspective, for example, of the Epicureans. However, a lot has happened in the world since the philosophy of Epicurus was prevalent, and Bodin had to take into account twelve hundred years of new challenges. Could the Epicurean theory be updated?

2.

2.

Bodin deals with the question almost entirely in respect to human knowledge. In definitely denying the degeneration of man, Bodin was only expressing what many thinkers of the sixteenth century had been coming to feel, though timidly and obscurely. The philosophers and men of science, who criticised the ancients in special departments, did not formulate any general view on the privileged position of antiquity. Bodin was the first to do so.

Bodin tackles the question mainly in relation to human knowledge. By firmly rejecting the idea that humanity has degraded over time, Bodin was simply voicing what many thinkers of the sixteenth century were beginning to sense, albeit hesitantly and vaguely. The philosophers and scientists, who critiqued the ancients in specific areas, did not establish any overarching opinions about the special status of antiquity. Bodin was the first to make a clear statement on that.

Knowledge, letters, and arts have their vicissitudes, he says; they rise, increase, and nourish, and then languish and die. After the decay of Rome there was a long fallow period; but this was followed by a splendid revival of knowledge and an intellectual productivity which no other age has exceeded. The scientific discoveries of the ancients deserve high praise; but the moderns have not only thrown new light on phenomena which they had incompletely explained, they have made new discoveries of equal or indeed greater importance. Take, for instance, the mariner's compass which has made possible the circumnavigation of the earth and a universal commerce, whereby the world has been changed, as it were, into a single state. [Footnote: Cardan had already signalised the compass, printing, and gunpowder as three modern inventions, to which "the whole of antiquity has nothing equal to show." He adds, "I pass over the other inventions of this age which, though wonderful, form rather a development of ancient arts than surpass the intellects of our ancestors." De subtilitate, lib. 3 ad init. (Opera, iii. p. 609).] Take the advances we have made in geography and astronomy; the invention of gunpowder; the development of the woollen and other industries. The invention of printing alone can be set against anything that the ancients achieved. [Footnote: Methodus, cap. VII., pp. 359-61. Bodin also points out that there was an improvement, in some respects, in manners and morals since the early Roman Empire; for instance, in the abolition of gladiatorial spectacles (p. 359).]

Knowledge, literature, and the arts go through ups and downs, he says; they grow, thrive, and then wither away and disappear. After the fall of Rome, there was a long period of stagnation; however, this was followed by an amazing revival of knowledge and an intellectual creativity that no other era has matched. The scientific discoveries of ancient times are highly commendable; but modern thinkers have not only illuminated areas that were only partially understood, they have made new discoveries of equal or even greater significance. For example, consider the mariner's compass, which has made it possible to sail around the world and established global trade, effectively transforming the world into a single community. [Footnote: Cardan had already highlighted the compass, printing, and gunpowder as three modern inventions, to which "the whole of antiquity has nothing equal to show." He adds, "I pass over the other inventions of this age which, though remarkable, are more of a progression of ancient arts than a surpassing of our ancestors' intellects." De subtilitate, lib. 3 ad init. (Opera, iii. p. 609).] Look at the progress we’ve made in geography and astronomy; the invention of gunpowder; the growth of the woolen and other industries. The invention of printing alone can rival anything the ancients accomplished. [Footnote: Methodus, cap. VII., pp. 359-61. Bodin also points out that there has been some improvement in manners and morals since the early Roman Empire; for instance, in the abolition of gladiatorial games (p. 359).]

An inference from all this, obvious to a modern reader, would be that in the future there will be similar oscillations, and new inventions and discoveries as remarkable as any that have been made in the past. But Bodin does not draw this inference. He confines himself to the past and present, and has no word to say about the vicissitudes of the future. But he is not haunted by any vision of the end of the world, or the coming of Antichrist; three centuries of humanism lay between him and Roger Bacon.

An obvious conclusion for a modern reader is that there will be similar ups and downs in the future, along with new inventions and discoveries as impressive as those from the past. However, Bodin does not make this conclusion. He focuses only on the past and present and doesn’t comment on the uncertainties of the future. Yet, he isn’t troubled by any idea of the apocalypse or the arrival of the Antichrist; three centuries of humanism separate him from Roger Bacon.

3.

3.

And yet the influence of medievalism, which it had been the work of those three centuries to overcome, was still pervasively there. Still more the authority of the Greeks and Romans, which had been set up by the revival of learning, was, without their realising it, heavy even upon thinkers like Bodin, who did not scruple freely to criticise ancient authors. And so, in his thoughtful attempt to find a clew to universal history, he was hampered by theological and cosmic theories, the legacy of the past. It is significant of the trend of his mind that when he is discussing the periodic decline of science and letters, he suggests that it may be due to the direct action of God, punishing those who misapplied useful sciences to the destruction of men.

And yet the influence of medieval thinking, which had taken three centuries to overcome, was still very much present. Even more so, the authority of the Greeks and Romans, established by the revival of learning, weighed heavily on thinkers like Bodin, who nonetheless did not hesitate to criticize ancient authors openly. Thus, in his thoughtful attempt to find a clue to universal history, he was constrained by theological and cosmic theories, remnants of the past. It's telling of his mindset that when discussing the periodic decline of science and literature, he suggests it may be due to God’s direct intervention, punishing those who have misused beneficial sciences to harm humanity.

But his speculations were particularly compromised by his belief in astrology, which, notwithstanding the efforts of humanists like Petrarch, Aeneas Sylvius, and Pico to discredit it, retained its hold over the minds of many eminent, otherwise emancipated, thinkers throughout the period of the Renaissance. [Footnote: Bodin was also a firm believer in sorcery. His La Demonomanie (1578) is a monument of superstition.] Here Bodin is in the company of Machiavelli and Lord Bacon. But not content with the doctrine of astral influence on human events, he sought another key to historical changes in the influence of numbers, reviving the ideas of Pythagoras and Plato, but working them out in a way of his own. He enumerates the durations of the lives of many famous men, to show that they can be expressed by powers of 7 and 9, or the product of these numbers. Other numbers which have special virtues are the powers of 12, the perfect number [Footnote: I.e. a number equal to the sum of all its factors.] 496, and various others. He gives many examples to prove that these mystic numbers determine the durations of empires and underlie historical chronology. For instance, the duration of the oriental monarchies from Ninus to the Conquest of Persia by Alexander the Great was 1728 (= 12 cubed) years. He gives the Roman republic from the foundation of Rome to the battle of Actium 729 (=9 cubed) years. [Footnote: Methodus, cap. v. pp. 265 sqq.]

But his ideas were especially undermined by his belief in astrology, which, despite the attempts of humanists like Petrarch, Aeneas Sylvius, and Pico to discredit it, still captivated the minds of many prominent, otherwise liberated, thinkers throughout the Renaissance. [Footnote: Bodin was also a staunch believer in sorcery. His La Demonomanie (1578) is a testament to superstition.] Here, Bodin stands alongside Machiavelli and Lord Bacon. Not satisfied with the concept of astral influence on human events, he sought another explanation for historical changes in the significance of numbers, reviving the theories of Pythagoras and Plato, but developing them in his own way. He lists the lengths of the lives of many notable individuals to demonstrate that they can be expressed as powers of 7 and 9, or the product of these numbers. Other numbers with special meanings include the powers of 12, the perfect number [Footnote: I.e. a number equal to the sum of all its factors.] 496, and various others. He provides numerous examples to argue that these mystical numbers determine the lengths of empires and form the basis of historical chronology. For instance, the duration of the eastern monarchies from Ninus to the conquest of Persia by Alexander the Great was 1728 (= 12 cubed) years. He notes that the Roman Republic lasted from the founding of Rome to the Battle of Actium for 729 (= 9 cubed) years. [Footnote: Methodus, cap. v. pp. 265 sqq.]

4.

4.

From a believer in such a theory, which illustrates the limitations of men's outlook on the world in the Renaissance period, we could perhaps hardly expect a vision of Progress. The best that can be said for it is that, both here and in his astrological creed, Bodin is crudely attempting to bring human history into close connection with the rest of the universe, and to establish the view that the whole world is built on a divine plan by which all the parts are intimately interrelated. [Footnote: Cp. Baudrillart, J. Bodin et son temps, p. 148 (1853). This monograph is chiefly devoted to a full analysis of La Republique.] He is careful, however, to avoid fatalism. He asserts, as we have seen, that history depends largely on the will of men. And he comes nearer to the idea of Progress than any one before him; he is on the threshold.

From a believer in this theory, which shows the limitations of people's views during the Renaissance, we probably shouldn't expect a vision of Progress. The best we can say is that, in both this and his astrological beliefs, Bodin is clumsily trying to link human history with the universe and to establish the idea that the whole world is based on a divine plan where all parts are closely connected. [Footnote: Cp. Baudrillart, J. Bodin et son temps, p. 148 (1853). This monograph is chiefly devoted to a full analysis of La Republique.] However, he is careful to avoid fatalism. As we've seen, he argues that history largely depends on human will. He is closer to the idea of Progress than anyone before him; he is on the brink.

For if we eliminate his astrological and Pythagorean speculations, and various theological parentheses which do not disturb his argument, his work announces a new view of history which is optimistic regarding man's career on earth, without any reference to his destinies in a future life. And in this optimistic view there are three particular points to note, which were essential to the subsequent growth of the idea of Progress. In the first place, the decisive rejection of the theory of degeneration, which had been a perpetual obstacle to the apprehension of that idea. Secondly, the unreserved claim that his own age was fully equal, and in some respects superior, to the age of classical antiquity, in respect of science and the arts. He leaves the ancients reverently on their pedestal, but he erects another pedestal for the moderns, and it is rather higher. We shall see the import of this when we come to consider the intellectual movement in which the idea of Progress was afterwards to emerge. In the third place, he had a conception of the common interest of all the peoples of the earth, a conception which corresponded to the old ecumenical idea of the Greeks and Romans, [Footnote: See above, p. 23.] but had now a new significance through the discoveries of modern navigators. He speaks repeatedly of the world as a universal state, and suggests that the various races, by their peculiar aptitudes and qualities, contribute to the common good of the whole. This idea of the "solidarity" of peoples was to be an important element in the growth of the doctrine of Progress. [Footnote: Republique, Book v. cap. 1 (p. 690; ed. 1593); Methodus, cap. vi. p. 194; cap. vii. p. 360.]

If we set aside his astrological and Pythagorean theories, along with the various theological add-ons that don’t disrupt his argument, his work presents a fresh perspective on history that is optimistic about humanity's journey on earth, without tying it to any future existence. This optimistic view highlights three key points that were crucial for the later development of the idea of Progress. First, he decisively rejects the theory of degeneration, which had continually hindered the understanding of this idea. Second, he boldly claims that his own time is equal to, and in some ways better than, the classical era regarding science and the arts. He respectfully acknowledges the ancients on their pedestal, but he constructs a higher pedestal for the moderns. We’ll see the significance of this when we explore the intellectual movement that ultimately gave rise to the idea of Progress. Third, he envisions a shared interest among all the peoples of the world, an idea that echoes the ancient ecumenical concept of the Greeks and Romans, but gains new importance with the discoveries of modern explorers. He often refers to the world as a universal state, suggesting that different races contribute to the common good through their unique skills and qualities. This notion of "solidarity" among peoples was set to be a vital aspect of the rise of the doctrine of Progress.

These ideas were in the air. Another Frenchman, the classical scholar, Louis Le Roy, translator of Plato and Aristotle, put forward similar views in a work of less celebrity, On the Vicissitude or Variety of the Things in the Universe. [Footnote: De la vicissitude ou variete des choses en l'univers, 1577, 2nd ed. (which I have used), 1584.] It contains a survey of great periods in which particular peoples attained an exceptional state of dominion and prosperity, and it anticipates later histories of civilisation by dwelling but slightly on political events and bringing into prominence human achievements in science, philosophy, and the arts. Beginning with the advance of man from primitive rudeness to ordered society—a sketch based on the conjectures of Plato in the Protagoras—Le Roy reviews the history, and estimates the merits, of the Egyptians, Assyrians and Persians, the Greeks, Romans and Saracens, and finally of the modern age. The facts, he thinks, establish the proposition that the art of warfare, eloquence, philosophy, mathematics, and the fine arts, generally flourish and decline together.

These ideas were in the air. Another Frenchman, the classic scholar Louis Le Roy, who translated Plato and Aristotle, proposed similar thoughts in a less well-known work, On the Vicissitude or Variety of the Things in the Universe. [Footnote: De la vicissitude ou variétédes choses en l'univers, 1577, 2nd ed. (which I have used), 1584.] It offers an overview of significant periods when certain societies achieved remarkable dominance and prosperity, and it foreshadows future histories of civilization by focusing less on political events and highlighting human accomplishments in science, philosophy, and the arts. Starting with humanity's journey from primitive chaos to structured society—a concept inspired by Plato's ideas in the Protagoras—Le Roy examines the history and assesses the contributions of the Egyptians, Assyrians, Persians, Greeks, Romans, and Saracens, as well as the modern era. He believes that the evidence supports the idea that the arts of war, rhetoric, philosophy, mathematics, and fine arts tend to rise and fall together.

But they do decline. Human things are not perpetual; all pass through the same cycle—beginning, progress, perfection, corruption, end. This, however, does not explain the succession of empires in the world, the changes of the scene of prosperity from one people or set of peoples to another. Le Roy finds the cause in providential design. God, he believes, cares for all parts of the universe and has distributed excellence in arms and letters now to Asia, now to Europe, again to Africa, letting virtue and vice, knowledge and ignorance travel from country to country, that all in their turn may share in good and bad fortune, and none become too proud through prolonged prosperity.

But they do decline. Human things aren’t permanent; everything goes through the same cycle—beginning, growth, peak, decline, and end. However, this doesn’t explain the rise and fall of empires in the world, or how prosperity shifts from one group or country to another. Le Roy believes the reason lies in a divine plan. He thinks that God looks after all parts of the universe and has spread greatness in power and knowledge, first to Asia, then to Europe, and also to Africa, allowing virtue and vice, knowledge and ignorance to move from one country to another, so that all may experience both good and bad fortunes, and none grow too arrogant from lasting success.

But what of the modern age in Western Europe? It is fully the equal, he assevers, of the most illustrious ages of the past, and in some respects it is superior. Almost all the liberal and mechanical arts of antiquity, which had been lost for about 1200 years, have been restored, and there have been new inventions, especially printing, and the mariner's compass, and "I would give the third place to gunnery but that it seems invented rather for the ruin than for the utility of the human race." In our knowledge of astronomy and cosmography we surpass the ancients. "We can affirm that the whole world is now known, and all the races of men; they can interchange all their commodities and mutually supply their needs, as inhabitants of the same city or world-state." And hence there has been a notable increase of wealth.

But what about the modern era in Western Europe? It is just as notable, he insists, as the greatest ages of the past, and in some ways, it’s even better. Almost all the arts and technologies of ancient times, which had been forgotten for about 1200 years, have been revived, along with new inventions, especially printing and the mariner's compass. “I would place gunnery in third place, but it seems designed more for the destruction than the benefit of humanity.” In our understanding of astronomy and cosmography, we excel the ancients. “We can confidently say that the entire world is now known, along with all its peoples; they can exchange all their goods and meet each other’s needs, like residents of the same city or global community.” As a result, there has been a significant increase in wealth.

Vice and suffering, indeed, are as grave as ever, and we are afflicted by the trouble of heresies; but this does not prove a general deterioration of morals. If that inveterate complaint, the refrain chanted by old men in every age, were true, the world would already have reached the extreme limit of wickedness, and integrity would have disappeared utterly. Seneca long ago made the right criticism. Hoc maiores nostri questi sunt, hoc nos querimur, hoc posteri nostri querentur, eversos esse mores.... At ista stant loco eodem. Perhaps Le Roy was thinking particularly of that curious book the Apology for Herodotus, in which the eminent Greek scholar, Henri Estienne, exposed with Calvinistic prejudice the iniquities of modern times and the corruption of the Roman Church. [Footnote: L'Introduction au traite de la conformite des merveilles anciennes avec les modernes, ou traite preparatif a l'Apologie pour Herodote, ed. Ristelhuber, 2 vols., 1879. The book was published in 1566.]

Vice and suffering are still serious issues, and we are troubled by heresies; however, this doesn’t mean that morals have universally deteriorated. If the constant complaint, repeated by older generations throughout history, were true, the world would have already hit the highest point of wickedness, and integrity would be completely gone. Seneca criticized this point long ago. "This is what our ancestors complained about, this is what we complain about, and this is what future generations will complain about: that morals have been overthrown.... Yet these things remain the same." Perhaps Le Roy was specifically thinking of that intriguing book, the Apology for Herodotus, in which the distinguished Greek scholar, Henri Estienne, highlighted with a Calvinistic bias the failings of modern times and the corruption of the Roman Church. [Footnote: L'Introduction au traite de la conformite des merveilles anciennes avec les modernes, ou traite preparatif a l'Apologie pour Herodote, ed. Ristelhuber, 2 vols., 1879. The book was published in 1566.]

But if we are to judge by past experience, does it not follow that this modern age must go the same way as the great ages of the past which it rivals or even surpasses? Our civilisation, too, having reached perfection, will inevitably decline and pass away: is not this the clear lesson of history? Le Roy does not shirk the issue; it is the point to which his whole exposition has led and he puts it vividly.

But if we judge by past experiences, doesn't it make sense that this modern era will follow the same path as the great ages before it, which it competes with or even exceeds? Our civilization, having reached its peak, will inevitably decline and fade away: isn't that the clear lesson from history? Le Roy doesn't avoid the issue; it's the point his entire argument has been leading to, and he expresses it clearly.

"If the memory of the past is the instruction of the present and the premonition of the future, it is to be feared that having reached so great excellence, power, wisdom, studies, books, industries will decline, as has happened in the past, and disappear—confusion succeeding to the order and perfection of to-day, rudeness to civilisation, ignorance to knowledge. I already foresee in imagination nations, strange in form, complexion, and costume, overwhelming Europe—like the Goths, Huns, Vandals, Lombards, Saracens of old—destroying our cities and palaces, burning our libraries, devastating all that is beautiful. I foresee in all countries wars, domestic and foreign, factions and heresies which will profane all things human and divine; famines, plagues, and floods; the universe approaching an end, world-wide confusion, and the return of things to their original chaos." [Footnote: It is characteristic of the age that in the last sentence the author goes beyond the issue and contemplates the possibility which still haunted men's minds that the end of the world might not be far off.]

"If the memory of the past teaches us about the present and hints at the future, it’s concerning that, having achieved such greatness, our excellence, power, wisdom, knowledge, books, and industries may decline, just as they have before, and disappear—chaos replacing the order and perfection we have today, barbarism replacing civilization, and ignorance replacing knowledge. I can already imagine nations, strange in appearance, complexion, and attire, overwhelming Europe—like the Goths, Huns, Vandals, Lombards, and Saracens of the past—destroying our cities and palaces, burning our libraries, and ravaging all that is beautiful. I foresee wars in every country, both civil and external, factions and heresies that will tarnish everything human and divine; famines, plagues, and floods; the universe nearing its end, global chaos, and a return to the original disorder." [Footnote: It is characteristic of the age that in the last sentence the author goes beyond the issue and contemplates the possibility which still haunted men's minds that the end of the world might not be far off.]

But having conducted us to this pessimistic conclusion Le Roy finds it repugnant, and is unwilling to acquiesce in it. Like an embarrassed dramatist he escapes from the knot which he has tied by introducing the deus ex machina.

But after leading us to this gloomy conclusion, Le Roy finds it distasteful and refuses to accept it. Like a struggling playwright, he untangles the mess he's created by bringing in a sudden, unexpected solution.

"However much these things proceed according to the fatal law of the world, and have their natural causes, yet events depend principally on Divine Providence which is superior to nature and alone knows the predetermined times of events." That is to say, it depends, after all, on Providence whether the argument from past experience is valid. Who knows whether the modern age may not prove the exception to the law which has hitherto prevailed? Let us act as if it would.

"Although these things happen according to the inevitable laws of the world and have their natural causes, events are mainly dependent on Divine Providence, which is above nature and knows the fixed timings of everything that happens." In other words, it ultimately relies on Providence whether the reasoning from past experiences is applicable. Who's to say that the modern era won't be the exception to the rule that has stood until now? Let's behave as if it will.

This is the practical moral that Le Roy enforces in the last book of his dissertation. We must not allow ourselves to be paralysed or dismayed by the destinies of past civilisations, but must work hard to transmit to posterity all that has been achieved, and augment the discoveries of the past by new researches. For knowledge is inexhaustible. "Let us not be so simple as to believe that the ancients have known and said everything and left nothing to their successors. Or that nature gave them all her favours in order to remain sterile ever after." Here Le Roy lays down Bodin's principle which was to be asserted more urgently in the following century—the permanence of natural forces. Nature is the same now as always, and can produce as great intellects as ever. The elements have the same power, the constellations keep their old order, men are made of the same material. There is nothing to hinder the birth in this age of men equal in brains to Plato, Aristotle, or Hippocrates.

This is the practical lesson that Le Roy emphasizes in the last book of his dissertation. We shouldn't let ourselves be paralyzed or discouraged by the fates of past civilizations, but should instead work hard to pass on everything we've achieved and build on past discoveries with new research. Knowledge is endless. "Let's not be so naive as to think that the ancients knew and said everything and left nothing for their successors. Or that nature bestowed all her gifts on them only for it to be barren forever after." Here, Le Roy establishes Bodin's principle, which would be asserted more strongly in the following century—the permanence of natural forces. Nature is just as it always has been and can still produce great minds. The elements have the same power, the stars maintain their old patterns, and humans are made from the same material. There's nothing stopping the emergence in this age of individuals as intellectually capable as Plato, Aristotle, or Hippocrates.

Philosophically, Le Roy's conclusion is lame enough. We are asked to set aside the data of experience and act on an off-chance. But the determination of the optimist to escape from the logic of his own argument is significant. He has no conception of an increasing purpose or underlying unity in the history of man, but he thinks that Providence—the old Providence of St. Augustine, who arranged the events of Roman history with a view to the coming of Christ—may, for some unknown reason, prolong indefinitely the modern age. He is obeying the instinct of optimism and confidence which was already beginning to create the appropriate atmosphere for the intellectual revolution of the coming century.

Philosophically, Le Roy's conclusion is pretty weak. We're asked to ignore the facts of experience and take a gamble. However, the optimist's determination to dodge the logic of his own argument is telling. He doesn't have any idea of a growing purpose or a unifying theme in human history, but he believes that Providence—the old Providence of St. Augustine, who arranged Roman history to lead to the coming of Christ—might, for some unknown reason, extend the modern age indefinitely. He's following the instinct of optimism and confidence that was already starting to create the right atmosphere for the intellectual revolution of the coming century.

His book was translated into English, but neither in France nor in England had it the same influence as the speculations of Bodin. But it insinuated, as the reader will have observed, the same three views which Bodin taught, and must have helped to propagate them: that the world has not degenerated; that the modern age is not inferior to classical antiquity; and that the races of the earth form now a sort of "mundane republic."

His book was translated into English, but it had nowhere near the same impact in France or England as Bodin's ideas. However, as the reader may have noticed, it subtly conveyed the same three perspectives that Bodin presented, which likely helped spread them: that the world hasn't declined; that the modern era isn't less significant than classical times; and that the races of the world now create a kind of "global community."





CHAPTER II. UTILITY THE END OF KNOWLEDGE: BACON

1.

Among the great precursors of a new order of thought Francis Bacon occupies a unique position. He drew up a definite programme for a "great Renovation" of knowledge; he is more clearly conscious than his contemporaries of the necessity of breaking with the past and making a completely new start; and his whole method of thought seems intellectually nearer to us than the speculations of a Bruno or a Campanella. Hence it is easy to understand that he is often regarded, especially in his own country, as more than a precursor, as the first philosopher, of the modern age, definitely within its precincts. [Footnote: German critics have been generally severe on Bacon as deficient in the scientific spirit. Kuno Fischer, Baco van Verulam (1856). Liebig, Ueber Francis Bacon van Verulam und die Methode der Naturforschung (1863). Lange (Geschichte des Materialismus, i. 195) speaks of "die aberglaubische und eitle Unwissenschaftlichkeit Bacos."]

Among the great pioneers of a new way of thinking, Francis Bacon holds a unique spot. He outlined a clear plan for a "great Renovation" of knowledge; he was more aware than his peers of the need to break away from the past and start fresh completely; and his overall method of thinking feels intellectually closer to us than the ideas of Bruno or Campanella. Therefore, it's easy to see why he is often seen, especially in his own country, as more than just a pioneer, but as the first philosopher of the modern age, firmly within its boundaries. [Footnote: German critics have generally been harsh on Bacon for lacking the scientific spirit. Kuno Fischer, Baco van Verulam (1856). Liebig, Ueber Francis Bacon van Verulam und die Methode der Naturforschung (1863). Lange (Geschichte des Materialismus, i. 195) speaks of "die aberglaubische und eitle Unwissenschaftlichkeit Bacos."]

It is not indeed a matter of fundamental importance how we classify these men who stood on the border of two worlds, but it must be recognised that if in many respects Bacon is in advance of contemporaries who cannot be dissociated from the Renaissance, in other respects, such as belief in astrology and dreams, he stands on the same ground, and in one essential point—which might almost be taken as the test of mental progress at this period—Bruno and Campanella have outstripped him. For him Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo worked in vain; he obstinately adhered to the old geocentric system.

It's not really crucial how we categorize these individuals who stood at the boundary of two worlds, but it's important to note that while Bacon is ahead of his contemporaries who are tied to the Renaissance in many ways, he also shares similar views, like belief in astrology and dreams. In one key aspect—which could almost be seen as a measure of intellectual advancement during this time—Bruno and Campanella have surpassed him. For Bacon, Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo's efforts were all in vain; he stubbornly stuck to the old geocentric model.

It must also be remembered that the principle which he laid down in his ambitious programme for the reform of science—that experiment is the key for discovering the secrets of nature—was not a new revelation. We need not dwell on the fact that he had been anticipated by Roger Bacon; for the ideas of that wonderful thinker had fallen dead in an age which was not ripe for them. But the direct interrogation of nature was already recognised both in practice and in theory in the sixteenth century. What Bacon did was to insist upon the principle more strongly and explicitly, and to formulate it more precisely. He clarified and explained the progressive ideas which inspired the scientific thought of the last period of the European Renaissance, from which he cannot, I think, be dissociated.

It should also be noted that the principle he established in his ambitious plan for reforming science—that experimentation is the key to uncovering the secrets of nature—was not a groundbreaking idea. We don't need to emphasize that Roger Bacon had already anticipated this; his remarkable ideas were overlooked in a time that wasn't ready for them. However, the direct exploration of nature was already acknowledged both practically and theoretically in the sixteenth century. What Bacon did was to stress this principle more strongly and clearly and to define it more accurately. He clarified and elaborated on the progressive ideas that fueled scientific thinking during the last phase of the European Renaissance, which I believe is interconnected with his work.

But in clearing up and defining these progressive ideas, he made a contribution to the development of human thought which had far-reaching importance and has a special significance for our present subject. In the hopes of a steady increase of knowledge, based on the application of new methods, he had been anticipated by Roger Bacon, and further back by Seneca. But with Francis Bacon this idea of the augmentation of knowledge has an entirely new value. For Seneca the exploration of nature was a means of escaping from the sordid miseries of life. For the friar of Oxford the principal use of increasing knowledge was to prepare for the coming of Antichrist. Francis Bacon sounded the modern note; for him the end of knowledge is utility. [Footnote; The passages specially referred to are: De Aug. Sc. vii. i; Nov. Org. i. 81 and 3.]

But by clarifying and defining these progressive ideas, he made a significant contribution to the development of human thought that had a lasting impact and special relevance to our current topic. He was anticipated in his hopes for a steady increase in knowledge through the application of new methods by Roger Bacon and even earlier by Seneca. However, with Francis Bacon, the concept of increasing knowledge takes on a completely new significance. For Seneca, exploring nature was a way to escape the harsh realities of life. For the friar of Oxford, the main purpose of increasing knowledge was to prepare for the arrival of Antichrist. Francis Bacon introduced a modern perspective; for him, the goal of knowledge is practical utility. [Footnote; The passages specially referred to are: De Aug. Sc. vii. i; Nov. Org. i. 81 and 3.]

2.

2.

The principle that the proper aim of knowledge is the amelioration of human life, to increase men's happiness and mitigate their sufferings—commodis humanis inservire—was the guiding star of Bacon in all his intellectual labour. He declared the advancement of "the happiness of mankind" to be the direct purpose of the works he had written or designed. He considered that all his predecessors had gone wrong because they did not apprehend that the finis scientarum, the real and legitimate goal of the sciences, is "the endowment of human life with new inventions and riches"; and he made this the test for defining the comparative values of the various branches of knowledge.

The idea that the true goal of knowledge is to improve human life, enhance people's happiness, and lessen their suffering—serving human needs—was Bacon's guiding principle in all his intellectual efforts. He stated that promoting "the happiness of mankind" was the main purpose of the works he had written or planned. He believed that all his predecessors were mistaken because they didn't understand that the real and legitimate aim of the sciences is "to enrich human life with new inventions and resources"; he used this as a standard to evaluate the relative worth of different fields of knowledge.

The true object, therefore, of the investigation of nature is not, as the Greek philosophers held, speculative satisfaction, but to establish the reign of man over nature; and this Bacon judged to be attainable, provided new methods of attacking the problems were introduced. Whatever may be thought of his daring act in bringing natural science down from the clouds and assigning to her the function of ministering to the material convenience and comfort of man, we may criticise Bacon for his doctrine that every branch of science should be pursued with a single eye towards practical use. Mathematics, he thought, should conduct herself as a humble, if necessary, handmaid, without any aspirations of her own. But it is not thus that the great progress in man's command over nature since Bacon's age has been effected. Many of the most valuable and surprising things which science has succeeded in doing for civilisation would never have been performed if each branch of knowledge were not guided by its own independent ideal of speculative completeness. [Footnote: This was to be well explained by Fontenelle, Preface sur l'utilite des mathematiques, in Oeuvres (ed. 1729), iii, I sqq.] But this does not invalidate Bacon's pragmatic principle, or diminish the importance of the fact that in laying down the utilitarian view of knowledge he contributed to the creation of a new mental atmosphere in which the theory of Progress was afterwards to develop.

The main goal of studying nature is not, as the Greek philosophers believed, just to satisfy curiosity, but to establish human control over nature. Bacon believed this was possible if new methods were introduced to tackle problems. Regardless of what one thinks about his bold move to bring natural science down to earth and give it the role of supporting human comfort and convenience, we can critique Bacon for his idea that every field of science should be pursued solely for practical purposes. He believed that mathematics should act as a humble assistant without any ambitions of its own. However, the significant advances in humanity’s ability to control nature since Bacon’s time have not happened this way. Many of the most valuable and surprising contributions science has made to civilization would not have occurred if each field of knowledge were not driven by its own independent quest for completeness. [Footnote: This was to be well explained by Fontenelle, Preface sur l'utilite des mathematiques, in Oeuvres (ed. 1729), iii, I sqq.] But this does not undermine Bacon’s practical principle or lessen the importance of the fact that by establishing the utilitarian perspective on knowledge, he helped create a new mindset in which the theory of Progress could later develop.

3.

3.

Bacon's respect for the ancients and his familiarity with their writings are apparent on almost every page he wrote. Yet it was one of his principal endeavours to shake off the yoke of their authority, which he recognised to be a fatal obstacle to the advancement of science. "Truth is not to be sought in the good fortune of any particular conjuncture of time"; its attainment depends on experience, and how limited was theirs. In their age "the knowledge both of time and of the world was confined and meagre; they had not a thousand years of history worthy of that name, but mere fables and ancient traditions; they were not acquainted with but a small portion of the regions and countries of the world." [Footnote: Nov. Org. i. 84; 56, 72, 73, 74.] In all their systems and scientific speculation "there is hardly one single experiment that has a tendency to assist mankind." Their theories were founded on opinion, and therefore science has remained stationary for the last two thousand years; whereas mechanical arts, which are founded on nature and experience, grow and increase.

Bacon's respect for the ancients and his familiarity with their writings are clear on almost every page he wrote. Yet, one of his main goals was to break free from their authority, which he saw as a major barrier to the progress of science. "Truth is not to be found in the luck of any particular time"; its discovery relies on experience, and theirs was very limited. In their time, "knowledge of both time and the world was restricted and sparse; they didn't have even a thousand years of significant history, just myths and old traditions; they were only familiar with a tiny part of the world's regions and countries." [Footnote: Nov. Org. i. 84; 56, 72, 73, 74.] In all their systems and scientific thoughts, "there is hardly a single experiment that helps humanity." Their theories were based on opinion, which is why science has stayed stagnant for the last two thousand years; in contrast, the mechanical arts, based on nature and experience, continue to grow and evolve.

In this connection, Bacon points out that the word "antiquity" is misleading, and makes a remark which will frequently recur in writers of the following generations. Antiquitas seculi iuventus mundi; what we call antiquity and are accustomed to revere as such was the youth of the world. But it is the old age and increasing years of the world—the time in which we are now living—that deserves in truth to be called antiquity. We are really the ancients, the Greeks and Romans were younger than we, in respect to the age of the world. And as we look to an old man for greater knowledge of the world than from a young man, so we have good reason to expect far greater things from our own age than from antiquity, because in the meantime the stock of knowledge has been increased by an endless number of observations and experiments. Time is the great discoverer, and truth is the daughter of time, not of authority.

In this context, Bacon notes that the term "antiquity" is misleading and makes a point that will often be echoed by writers in future generations. Antiquitas seculi iuventus mundi; what we refer to as antiquity and hold in high regard was actually the youth of the world. However, it is the old age and the later years of the world—the time we are currently living in—that truly deserve to be called antiquity. We are, in fact, the ancients; the Greeks and Romans were younger than we are concerning the world's age. Just as we look to an older person for greater knowledge than we would from a younger person, we have solid reasons to expect much more from our own age than from antiquity because, in the meantime, the body of knowledge has been enriched by countless observations and experiments. Time is the great discoverer, and truth is the daughter of time, not of authority.

Take the three inventions which were unknown to the ancients-printing, gunpowder, and the compass. These "have changed the appearance and state of the whole world; first in literature, then in warfare, and lastly in navigation; and innumerable changes have been thence derived, so that no empire, sect, or star appears to have exercised a greater power or influence on human affairs than these mechanical discoveries." [Footnote: Nov. Org. 129. We have seen that these three inventions had already been classed together as outstanding by Cardan and Le Roy. They also appear in Campanella. Bodin, as we saw, included them in a longer list.] It was perhaps the results of navigation and the exploration of unknown lands that impressed Bacon more than all, as they had impressed Bodin. Let me quote one passage.

Consider the three inventions that were unknown to the ancients: printing, gunpowder, and the compass. These "have changed the appearance and state of the whole world; first in literature, then in warfare, and lastly in navigation; and countless changes have stemmed from them, so that no empire, movement, or force seems to have had a greater impact or influence on human affairs than these mechanical discoveries." [Footnote: Nov. Org. 129. We have seen that these three inventions had already been recognized as significant by Cardan and Le Roy. They also appear in Campanella. Bodin, as we noted, included them in a longer list.] It was likely the outcomes of navigation and the exploration of unknown lands that impressed Bacon more than anything else, as they had impressed Bodin. Let me quote one passage.

"It may truly be affirmed to the honour of these times, and in a virtuous emulation with antiquity, that this great building of the world had never through-lights made in it till the age of us and our fathers. For although they [the ancients] had knowledge of the antipodes... yet that mought be by demonstration, and not in fact; and if by travel, it requireth the voyage but of half the earth. But to circle the earth, as the heavenly bodies do, was not done nor enterprised till these later times: and therefore these times may justly bear in their word... plus ultra in precedence of the ancient non ultra.... And this proficience in navigation and discoveries may plant also an expectation of the further proficience and augmentation of all sciences, because it may seem that they are ordained by God to be coevals, that is, to meet in one age. For so the prophet Daniel, speaking of the latter times foretelleth, Plurimi pertransibunt, et multiplex erit scientia: as if the openness and through-passage of the world and the increase of knowledge were appointed to be in the same ages; as we see it is already performed in great part: the learning of these later times not much giving place to the former two periods or returns of learning, the one of the Grecians, the other of the Romans." [Footnote: Advancement of Learning, ii. 13, 14.]

"It can truly be said in honor of our times, and in a virtuous rivalry with the past, that this great creation of the world has never had clear insights until our age and that of our ancestors. While the ancients knew about the antipodes... it was more theoretical than factual; their exploration required only half of the earth's journey. However, to fully circumnavigate the globe, like the heavenly bodies do, was not attempted until more recent times. Therefore, our era can rightfully claim... 'more beyond' as opposed to the ancient 'no further.' This progress in navigation and discovery also raises hopes for further advancement and expansion of all sciences, as it seems they are meant by God to emerge simultaneously, that is, to converge in one era. The prophet Daniel, speaking of the latter times, foretells, 'Many will travel to and fro, and knowledge will increase,' suggesting that the opening up of the world and the growth of knowledge were destined to occur in the same ages; as we can see is already happening to a large extent: the learning of our time does not lag behind that of the previous two major periods of learning, one from the Greeks and the other from the Romans." [Footnote: Advancement of Learning, ii. 13, 14.]

In all this we have a definite recognition of the fact that knowledge progresses. Bacon did not come into close quarters with the history of civilisation, but he has thrown out some observations which amount to a rough synthesis. [Footnote: Advancement, ii. 1, 6; Nov. Org. i. 78, 79, 85.] Like Bodin, he divided, history into three periods—(1) the antiquities of the world; (2) the middle part of time which comprised two sections, the Greek and the Roman; (3) "modern history," which included what we now call the Middle Ages. In this sequence three particular epochs stand out as fertile in science and favourable to progress—the Greek, the Roman, and our own—"and scarcely two centuries can with justice be assigned to each." The other periods of time are deserts, so far as philosophy and science are concerned. Rome and Greece are "two exemplar States of the world for arms, learning, moral virtue, policy, and laws." But even in those two great epochs little progress was made in natural philosophy. For in Greece moral and political speculation absorbed men's minds; in Rome, meditation and labour were wasted on moral philosophy, and the greatest intellects were devoted to civil affairs. Afterwards, in the third period, the study of theology was the chief occupation of the Western European nations. It was actually in the earliest period that the most useful discoveries for the comfort of human life were made, "so that, to say the truth, when contemplation and doctrinal science began, the discovery of useful works ceased."

In all this, we clearly recognize that knowledge progresses. Bacon didn’t dive deep into the history of civilization, but he did provide some observations that form a rough synthesis. [Footnote: Advancement, ii. 1, 6; Nov. Org. i. 78, 79, 85.] Like Bodin, he divided history into three periods—(1) the ancient world; (2) the middle period, which includes two sections, the Greek and the Roman; (3) "modern history," which encompasses what we now refer to as the Middle Ages. Within this framework, three specific eras stand out as rich in science and conducive to progress—the Greek, the Roman, and our own—"and hardly two centuries can justly be attributed to each." The other historical periods have been barren in terms of philosophy and science. Rome and Greece serve as "two exemplary states of the world for arms, learning, moral virtue, policy, and laws." Yet, even during those two significant eras, there was little advancement in natural philosophy. In Greece, moral and political thought consumed people’s attention; in Rome, reflection and effort were wasted on moral philosophy, with the greatest minds focused on civic issues. Later, in the third period, the study of theology became the primary pursuit of Western European nations. It was actually in the earliest period that the most beneficial discoveries for human comfort were made, "so that, to be honest, when contemplation and theoretical science began, the discovery of useful inventions stopped."

So much for the past history of mankind, during which many things conspired to make progress in the subjugation of nature slow, fitful, and fortuitous. What of the future? Bacon's answer is: if the errors of the past are understood and avoided there is every hope of steady progress in the modern age.

So much for the history of humanity, during which many factors combined to make progress in overcoming nature slow, inconsistent, and random. What about the future? Bacon's answer is: if we understand and avoid the mistakes of the past, there is every reason to expect steady progress in the modern age.

But it might be asked. Is there not something in the constitution of things which determines epochs of stagnation and vigour, some force against which man's understanding and will are impotent? Is it not true that in the revolutions of ages there are floods and ebbs of the sciences, which flourish now and then decline, and that when they have reached a certain point they can proceed no further? This doctrine of Returns or ricorsi [Footnote: Bodin's conversiones.] is denounced by Bacon as the greatest obstacle to the advancement of knowledge, creating, as it does, diffidence or despair. He does not formally refute it, but he marshals the reasons for an optimistic view, and these reasons supply the disproof The facts on which the fatalistic doctrine of Returns is based can be explained without resorting to any mysterious law. [Footnote: Nov. Org. i. 92 sqq.] Progress has not been steady or continuous on account of the prejudices and errors which hindered men from setting to work in the right way. The difficulties in advancing did not arise from things which are not in our power; they were due to the human understanding, which wasted time and labour on improper objects. "In proportion as the errors which have been committed impeded the past, so do they afford reason to hope for the future."

But one might ask: Is there not something in the nature of things that determines periods of stagnation and vigor, a force against which human understanding and will are powerless? Is it not true that through the ages, there are highs and lows in the sciences, which thrive at times and then decline, and that once they reach a certain point, they cannot progress further? This idea of Cycles or Returns is criticized by Bacon as the greatest barrier to the advancement of knowledge, causing doubt or despair. He doesn't directly refute it, but instead presents reasons for an optimistic perspective, and these reasons effectively counter the idea. The facts that support the fatalistic belief in Cycles can be explained without invoking any mysterious law. Progress hasn’t been steady or continuous due to the prejudices and mistakes that kept people from working effectively. The challenges in making advancements did not stem from things beyond our control; they were a result of human reasoning, which squandered time and effort on the wrong pursuits. "As much as the errors of the past have hindered us, they give us hope for the future."

4.

4.

But will the new period of advance, which Bacon expected and strove to secure, be of indefinite duration? He does not consider the question. His view that he lived in the old age of the world implies that he did not anticipate a vast tract of time before the end of mankind's career on earth. And an orthodox Christian of that time could hardly be expected to predict. The impression we get is that, in his sanguine enthusiasm, he imagined that a "prudent interrogation" of nature could extort all her secrets in a few generations. As a reformer he was so engaged in the immediate prospect of results that his imagination did not turn to the possibilities of a remoter future, though these would logically follow from his recognition of "the inseparable propriety of time which is ever more and more to disclose truth." He hopes everything from his own age in which learning has made her third visitation to the world, a period which he is persuaded will far surpass that of Grecian and Roman learning. [Footnote: Advancement, ii. 24.] If he could have revisited England in 1700 and surveyed what science had performed since his death his hopes might have been more than satisfied.

But will the new era of progress that Bacon expected and worked to secure last indefinitely? He doesn’t address that question. His belief that he lived in the old age of the world suggests he didn't foresee a long stretch of time before humanity's end on earth. And a traditional Christian of that time couldn't realistically have predicted it. The impression we get is that, in his hopeful enthusiasm, he thought that a “careful inquiry” into nature could uncover all her secrets within just a few generations. As a reformer, he was so focused on the immediate outcomes that he didn’t consider the possibilities of a distant future, even though those would logically follow from his understanding of “the inseparable propriety of time which is always revealing more truth.” He hopes all will come from his own time when learning has made its third return to the world, a period he believes will greatly surpass that of Grecian and Roman scholarship. [Footnote: Advancement, ii. 24.] If he could have returned to England in 1700 and seen what science had achieved since his death, his hopes might have been more than fulfilled.

But, animated though he was with the progressive spirit, as Leonardo da Vinci had been before him, all that he says of the prospects of an increase of knowledge fails to amount to the theory of Progress. He prepares the way, he leads up to it; but his conception of his own time as the old age of humanity excludes the conception of an indefinite advance in the future, which is essential if the theory is to have significance and value. And in regard to progress in the past, though he is clearer and more emphatic than Bodin, he hardly adds anything to what Bodin had observed. The novelty of his view lies not in his recognition of the advance of knowledge and its power to advance still further, but in the purpose which he assigned to it. [Footnote: Campanella held its purpose to be the contemplation of the wisdom of God; cp., for instance, De sensu rerum, Bk. iv. epilogus, where the world is described as statua Dei altissimi (p. 370; ed. 1620).] The end of the sciences is their usefulness to the human race. To increase knowledge is to extend the dominion of man over nature, and so to increase his comfort and happiness, so far as these depend on external circumstances. To Plato or Seneca, or to a Christian dreaming of the City of God, this doctrine would seem material and trivial; and its announcement was revolutionary: for it implied that happiness on earth was an end to be pursued for its own sake, and to be secured by co-operation for mankind at large. This idea is an axiom which any general doctrine of Progress must presuppose; and it forms Bacon's great contribution to the group of ideas which rendered possible the subsequent rise of that doctrine.

But although he was inspired by the spirit of progress, like Leonardo da Vinci before him, everything he says about the potential for increasing knowledge doesn't really amount to a full theory of Progress. He paves the way for it and suggests its possibilities, but his view of his own time as the last stage of humanity rules out the idea of an indefinite advance in the future, which is crucial for the theory to have meaning and importance. Regarding progress in the past, while he is clearer and more emphatic than Bodin, he hardly adds anything to what Bodin had already noted. The novelty in his perspective lies not in recognizing the advancement of knowledge and its potential to continue growing, but in the purpose he assigns to it. [Footnote: Campanella believed its purpose was the contemplation of the wisdom of God; see, for example, De sensu rerum, Bk. iv. epilogus, where the world is described as statua Dei altissimi (p. 370; ed. 1620).] The ultimate goal of the sciences is their usefulness to humanity. Increasing knowledge means extending humanity's dominion over nature, which in turn enhances comfort and happiness, as far as these depend on external conditions. To Plato, Seneca, or a Christian envisioning the City of God, this doctrine might seem materialistic and trivial; however, its announcement was groundbreaking: it suggested that happiness on earth is a goal worth pursuing for its own sake, achievable through cooperation for the benefit of all humanity. This idea is a basic assumption any broader theory of Progress must rest upon, and it constitutes Bacon's significant contribution to the set of ideas that made the later emergence of that theory possible.

Finally, we must remember that by Bacon, as by most of his Elizabethan contemporaries, the doctrine of an active intervening Providence, the Providence of Augustine, was taken as a matter of course, and governed more or less their conceptions of the history of civilisation. But, I think, we may say that Bacon, while he formally acknowledged it, did not press it or emphasise it. [Footnote: See Advancement, iii. II. On the influence of the doctrine on historical writing in England at the beginning of the seventeenth century see Firth, Sir Walter Raleigh's History of the World (Proc. of British Academy, vol. viii., 1919), p. 8.]

Finally, we have to keep in mind that for Bacon, like many of his Elizabethan peers, the idea of a proactive intervening Providence—the Providence of Augustine—was accepted without question and shaped their understanding of the history of civilization. However, I believe we can say that Bacon, while he officially acknowledged it, did not emphasize it or highlight it. [Footnote: See Advancement, iii. II. On the influence of the doctrine on historical writing in England at the beginning of the seventeenth century see Firth, Sir Walter Raleigh's History of the World (Proc. of British Academy, vol. viii., 1919), p. 8.]

5.

5.

Bacon illustrated his view of the social importance of science in his sketch of an ideal state, the New Atlantis. He completed only a part of the work, and the fragment was published after his death. [Footnote: In 1627. It was composed about 1623. It seems almost certain that he was acquainted with the Christianopolis of Johann Valentin Andreae (1586-1654), which had appeared in Latin in 1614, and contained a plan for a scientific college to reform the civilised world. Andreae, who was acquainted both with More and with Campanella, placed his ideal society in an island which he called Caphar Salama (the name of a village in Palestine). Andreae's work had also a direct influence on the Nova Solyma of Samuel Gott (1648). See the Introduction of F. E. Held to his edition of Christianopolis (1916). In Macaria, another imaginary state of the seventeenth century (A description of the famous Kingdoms of Macaria, 1641, by Hartlib), the pursuit of science is not a feature.] It is evident that the predominating interest that moved his imagination was different from that which guided Plato. While Plato aimed at securing a permanent solid order founded on immutable principles, the design of Bacon was to enable his imaginary community to achieve dominion over nature by progressive discoveries. The heads of Plato's city are metaphysicians, who regulate the welfare of the people by abstract doctrines established once for all; while the most important feature in the New Atlantis is the college of scientific investigators, who are always discovering new truths which may alter the conditions of life. Here, though only in a restricted field, an idea of progressive improvement, which is the note of the modern age, comes in to modify the idea of a fixed order which exclusively prevailed in ancient speculation.

Bacon showcased his belief in the social significance of science in his depiction of an ideal society, the New Atlantis. He only finished part of the work, and the fragment was published after he died. [Footnote: In 1627. It was written around 1623. It seems almost certain that he was familiar with the Christianopolis by Johann Valentin Andreae (1586-1654), which was released in Latin in 1614 and included a plan for a scientific college to reform the civilized world. Andreae, who knew both More and Campanella, placed his ideal society on an island he called Caphar Salama (the name of a village in Palestine). Andreae's work also had a direct impact on the Nova Solyma by Samuel Gott (1648). See the Introduction of F. E. Held to his edition of Christianopolis (1916). In Macaria, another imagined state from the seventeenth century (A description of the famous Kingdoms of Macaria, 1641, by Hartlib), the pursuit of science is not a focus.] It’s clear that the main interest driving his imagination was different from Plato's. While Plato sought to establish a stable order based on unchanging principles, Bacon's goal was to allow his fictional community to gain control over nature through ongoing discoveries. The leaders of Plato's city are metaphysicians who guide the people's welfare through abstract doctrines set once and for all; on the other hand, the key element in the New Atlantis is the college of scientific researchers, who are continuously uncovering new truths that could change the conditions of life. Here, although only within a limited scope, the concept of ongoing improvement, which characterizes the modern age, begins to shift the notion of a fixed order that predominated in ancient thought.

On the other hand, we must not ignore the fact that Bacon's ideal society is established by the same kind of agency as the ideal societies of Plato and Aristotle. It has not developed; it was framed by the wisdom of an original legislator Solamona. In this it resembles the other imaginary commonwealths of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The organisation of More's Utopia is fixed initially once for all by the lawgiver Utopus. The origin of Campanella's Civitas Solis is not expressly stated, but there can be no doubt that he conceived its institutions as created by the fiat of a single lawgiver. Harrington, in his Oceana, argues with Machiavelli that a commonwealth, to be well turned, must be the work of one man, like a book or a building. [Footnote: Harrington, Oceana, pp. 77-8, 3rd ed. (1747).]

On the other hand, we shouldn't overlook the fact that Bacon's ideal society is created by the same kind of authority as the ideal societies of Plato and Aristotle. It hasn't evolved; it was designed by the wisdom of the original legislator Solamona. In this way, it’s similar to other fictional commonwealths from the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The structure of More's Utopia is established once and for all by the lawmaker Utopus. The origin of Campanella's Civitas Solis isn't explicitly stated, but it's clear that he envisioned its institutions as established by the command of a single lawgiver. Harrington, in his Oceana, argues with Machiavelli that a commonwealth, to be well designed, must be crafted by one person, just like a book or a building. [Footnote: Harrington, Oceana, pp. 77-8, 3rd ed. (1747).]

What measure of liberty Bacon would have granted to the people of his perfect state we cannot say; his work breaks off before he comes to describe their condition. But we receive the impression that the government he conceived was strictly paternal, though perhaps less rigorous than the theocratic despotism which Campanella, under Plato's influence, set up in the City of the Sun. But even Campanella has this in common with More—and we may be sure that Bacon's conception would have agreed here—that there are no hard-and-fast lines between the classes, and the welfare and happiness of all the inhabitants is impartially considered, in contrast with Plato's scheme in the Laws, where the artisans and manual labourers were an inferior caste existing less for their own sake than for the sake of the community as a whole. [Footnote: This however does not apply to the Republic, as is so commonly asserted. See the just criticisms of A. A. Trever, A History of Greek Economic Thought (Chicago, 1916), 49 sqq.]

What level of freedom Bacon would have allowed the people in his ideal state is unclear; his work ends before he describes their situation. However, it seems that the government he envisioned was mainly paternal, though perhaps not as strict as the theocratic tyranny that Campanella, influenced by Plato, established in the City of the Sun. But even Campanella shares a commonality with More—and we can assume that Bacon's vision would align here—in that there are no strict boundaries between classes, and the well-being and happiness of all residents are equally valued, unlike Plato's plan in the Laws, where artisans and manual laborers were seen as an inferior class existing primarily for the benefit of the community as a whole. [Footnote: This, however, does not apply to the Republic, as is often claimed. See the fair criticisms of A. A. Trever, A History of Greek Economic Thought (Chicago, 1916), 49 sqq.]

It may finally be pointed out that these three imaginary commonwealths stand together as a group, marked by a humaner temper than the ancient, and also by another common characteristic which distinguishes them, on one hand, from the ideal states of Plato and, on the other, from modern sketches of desirable societies. Plato and Aristotle conceived their constructions within the geographical limits of Hellas, either in the past or in the present. More, Bacon, and Campanella placed theirs in distant seas, and this remoteness in space helped to create a certain illusion, of reality. [Footnote: Civitas Solis, p. 461 (ed. 1620). Expectancy of end of world: Ib. p. 455.] The modern plan is to project the perfect society into a period of future time. The device of More and his successors was suggested by the maritime explorations of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries; the later method was a result of the rise of the idea of Progress. [Footnote: Similarly the ideal communistic states imagined by Euemerus and Iambulus in the southern seas owed their geographical positions to the popular interest in seafaring in the Indian Ocean in the age after Alexander. One wonders whether Campanella knew the account of the fictitious journey of Iambulus to the Islands of the Sun, in Diodorus Siculus, ii. 55-60.]

It’s important to note that these three fictional commonwealths are grouped together, showing a more humane attitude than the ancient ones, and they share another common trait that sets them apart from Plato's ideal states and from modern visions of desirable societies. Plato and Aristotle imagined their societies within the geographical boundaries of Greece, either historically or currently. In contrast, More, Bacon, and Campanella situated theirs in far-off seas, and this distance added a sense of realism. [Footnote: Civitas Solis, p. 461 (ed. 1620). Expectancy of end of world: Ib. p. 455.] The modern approach is to envision the perfect society in a future time. The strategy used by More and his successors was inspired by the maritime explorations of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries; the later approach emerged from the growing idea of Progress. [Footnote: Similarly, the ideal communist societies imagined by Euemerus and Iambulus in the southern seas were influenced by the popular interest in seafaring in the Indian Ocean after Alexander’s time. One wonders if Campanella was aware of the account of Iambulus's fictional journey to the Islands of the Sun in Diodorus Siculus, ii. 55-60.]

6.

6.

A word or two more may be said about the City of the Sun. Campanella was as earnest a believer in the interrogation of nature as Bacon, and the place which science and learning hold in his state (although research is not so prominent as in the New Atlantis), and the scientific training of all the citizens, are a capital feature. The progress in inventions, to which science may look forward, is suggested. The men of the City of the Sun "have already discovered the one art which the world seemed to lack—the art of flying; and they expect soon to invent ocular instruments which will enable them to see the invisible stars and auricular instruments for hearing the harmony of the spheres." Campanella's view of the present conditions and prospects of knowledge is hardly less sanguine than that of Bacon, and characteristically he confirms his optimism by astrological data. "If you only knew what their astrologers say about the coming age. Our times, they assert, have more history in a hundred years than the whole world in four thousand. More books have been published in this century than in five thousand years before. They dwell on the wonderful inventions of printing, of artillery, and of the use of the magnet,—clear signs of the times—and also instruments for the assembling of the inhabitants of the world into one fold," and show that these discoveries were conditioned by stellar influences.

A word or two more can be said about the City of the Sun. Campanella was just as passionate a believer in exploring nature as Bacon, and the role that science and education play in his society (although research isn't as central as in the New Atlantis), along with the scientific training of all the citizens, is a key aspect. The advancements in inventions that science can look forward to are hinted at. The people of the City of the Sun "have already discovered the one art that the world seemed to be missing—the art of flying; and they expect to soon invent tools that will let them see the invisible stars and instruments for hearing the harmony of the spheres." Campanella's outlook on the current state and future of knowledge is nearly as optimistic as Bacon's, and he characteristically backs his hopefulness with astrological data. "If you only knew what their astrologers say about the coming age. They claim that our times have more history in a hundred years than the entire world does in four thousand. More books have been published in this century than in the previous five thousand years. They focus on the amazing inventions of printing, artillery, and the use of the magnet—clear signs of the times—and also tools for bringing the world's inhabitants together," showing that these discoveries were influenced by the stars.

But Campanella is not very sure or clear about the future. Astrology and theology cause him to hesitate. Like Bacon, he dreams of a great Renovation and sees that the conditions are propitious, but his faith is not secure. The astronomers of his imaginary state scrutinise the stars to discover whether the world will perish or not, and they believe in the oracular saying of Jesus that the end will come like a thief in the night. Therefore they expect a new age, and perhaps also the end of the world.

But Campanella isn't very certain or clear about the future. Astrology and theology make him hesitate. Like Bacon, he dreams of a major Renovation and sees that the conditions are favorable, but his faith isn't solid. The astronomers in his imagined state examine the stars to find out if the world will end or not, and they believe in the prophetic saying of Jesus that the end will come unexpectedly. As a result, they anticipate a new era, and maybe even the apocalypse.

The new age of knowledge was about to begin. Campanella, Bruno, and Bacon stand, as it were, on the brink of the dividing stream, tenduntque manus ripae ulterioris amore.

The new age of knowledge was about to begin. Campanella, Bruno, and Bacon stand, as it were, on the brink of the dividing stream, stretching their hands toward the far bank out of love.





CHAPTER III. CARTESIANISM

If we are to draw any useful lines of demarcation in the continuous flux of history we must neglect anticipations and announcements, and we need not scruple to say that, in the realm of knowledge and thought, modern history begins in the seventeenth century. Ubiquitous rebellion against tradition, a new standard of clear and precise thought which affects even literary expression, a flow of mathematical and physical discoveries so rapid that ten years added more to the sum of knowledge than all that had been added since the days of Archimedes, the introduction of organised co-operation to increase knowledge by the institution of the Royal Society at London, the Academy of Sciences at Paris, Observatories—realising Bacon's Atlantic dream—characterise the opening of a new era.

If we want to draw clear lines in the ongoing flow of history, we need to overlook predictions and announcements. We can confidently say that modern history, in terms of knowledge and thought, starts in the seventeenth century. There was widespread rebellion against tradition, a new standard of clear and precise thinking that even influenced literary expression, and an explosion of mathematical and physical discoveries. In just ten years, more was added to our knowledge than what had accumulated since the time of Archimedes. The establishment of organized collaboration, like the Royal Society in London, the Academy of Sciences in Paris, and observatories—fulfilling Bacon's dream—marks the beginning of a new era.

For the ideas with which we are concerned, the seventeenth century centres round Descartes, whom an English admirer described as "the grand secretary of Nature." [Footnote: Joseph Glanvill, Vanity of Dogmatising, p. 211, 64] Though his brilliant mathematical discoveries were the sole permanent contribution he made to knowledge, though his metaphysical and physical systems are only of historical interest, his genius exercised a more extensive and transforming influence on the future development of thought than any other man of his century.

For the ideas we're focusing on, the seventeenth century revolves around Descartes, whom an English admirer called "the grand secretary of Nature." [Footnote: Joseph Glanvill, Vanity of Dogmatising, p. 211, 64] Although his brilliant mathematical discoveries were his only lasting contribution to knowledge, and his metaphysical and physical systems are mainly of historical interest, his genius had a broader and transformative impact on the future development of thought than any other person of his time.

Cartesianism affirmed the two positive axioms of the supremacy of reason, and the invariability of the laws of nature; and its instrument was a new rigorous analytical method, which was applicable to history as well as to physical knowledge. The axioms had destructive corollaries. The immutability of the processes of nature collided with the theory of an active Providence. The supremacy of reason shook the thrones from which authority and tradition had tyrannised over the brains of men. Cartesianism was equivalent to a declaration of the Independence of Man.

Cartesianism emphasized two main principles: the dominance of reason and the unchanging nature of the laws of nature. Its tool was a new, strict analytical method that could be applied to history as well as to scientific knowledge. However, these principles had troubling implications. The unchangeable processes of nature clashed with the idea of a proactive divine influence. The dominance of reason challenged the authority and tradition that had controlled people's minds. In essence, Cartesianism represented a declaration of human independence.

It was in the atmosphere of the Cartesian spirit that a theory of Progress was to take shape.

It was in the context of the Cartesian mindset that a theory of Progress was about to develop.

1.

1.

Let us look back. We saw that all the remarks of philosophers prior to the seventeenth century, which have been claimed as enunciations of the idea of Progress, amount merely to recognitions of the obvious fact that in the course of the past history of men there have been advances and improvements in knowledge and arts, or that we may look for some improvements in the future. There is not one of them that adumbrates a theory that can be called a theory of Progress. We have seen several reasons why the idea could not emerge in the ancient or in the Middle Ages. Nor could it have easily appeared in the period of the Renaissance. Certain preliminary conditions were required, and these were not fulfilled till the seventeenth century. So long as men believed that the Greeks and Romans had attained, in the best days of their civilisation, to an intellectual plane which posterity could never hope to reach, so long as the authority of their thinkers was set up as unimpeachable, a theory of degeneration held the field, which excluded a theory of Progress. It was the work of Bacon and Descartes to liberate science and philosophy from the yoke of that authority; and at the same time, as we shall see, the rebellion began to spread to other fields.

Let’s take a step back. We observed that all the comments made by philosophers before the seventeenth century, which have been presented as notions of Progress, are simply acknowledgments of the obvious fact that throughout human history, there have been advancements and improvements in knowledge and the arts, or that we can expect some improvements in the future. None of them outline a theory that could be considered a theory of Progress. We have identified several reasons why this idea could not emerge in ancient times or during the Middle Ages. It also wouldn’t have easily arisen during the Renaissance. Certain foundational conditions were necessary, and these weren't met until the seventeenth century. As long as people believed that the Greeks and Romans achieved an intellectual level in the peak of their civilization that later generations could never hope to attain, and as long as the authority of their thinkers was regarded as unquestionable, a theory of degeneration prevailed, which ruled out a theory of Progress. It was the efforts of Bacon and Descartes that freed science and philosophy from the restrictions of that authority; and at the same time, as we will see, the movement began to extend into other areas.

Another condition for the organisation of a theory of Progress was a frank recognition of the value of mundane life and the subservience of knowledge to human needs. The secular spirit of the Renaissance prepared the world for this new valuation, which was formulated by Bacon, and has developed into modern utilitarianism.

Another condition for organizing a theory of Progress was a clear acknowledgment of the value of everyday life and the importance of knowledge in serving human needs. The secular mindset of the Renaissance set the stage for this new appreciation, which was articulated by Bacon and has evolved into modern utilitarianism.

There was yet a third preliminary condition. There can be no certainty that knowledge will continually progress until science has been placed on sure foundations. And science does not rest for us on sure foundations unless the invariability of the laws of nature is admitted. If we do not accept this hypothesis, if we consider it possible that the uniformities of the natural world may be changed from time to time, we have no guarantee that science can progress indefinitely. The philosophy of Descartes established this principle, which is the palladium of science; and thus the third preliminary condition was fulfilled.

There was one more essential condition. We can't be sure that knowledge will keep advancing until science has solid foundations. And science doesn't have solid foundations for us unless we accept that the laws of nature are unchanging. If we reject this idea and think it's possible that the regularities of the natural world can change over time, we have no assurance that science can keep progressing endlessly. The philosophy of Descartes established this principle, which is crucial for science; therefore, the third essential condition was met.

2.

2.

During the Renaissance period the authority of the Greeks and Romans had been supreme in the realm of thought, and in the interest of further free development it was necessary that this authority should be weakened. Bacon and others had begun the movement to break down this tyranny, but the influence of Descartes was weightier and more decisive, and his attitude was more uncompromising. He had none of Bacon's reverence for classical literature; he was proud of having forgotten the Greek which he had learned as a boy. The inspiration of his work was the idea of breaking sharply and completely with the past, and constructing a system which borrows nothing from the dead. He looked forward to an advancement of knowledge in the future, on the basis of his own method and his own discoveries, [Footnote: Cf. for instance his remarks on medicine, at the end of the Discours de la methode.] and he conceived that this intellectual advance would have far-reaching effects on the condition of mankind. The first title he had proposed to give to his Discourse on Method was "The Project of a Universal Science which can elevate our Nature to its highest degree of Perfection." He regarded moral and material improvement as depending on philosophy and science.

During the Renaissance, the authority of the Greeks and Romans was dominant in the world of thought, and to encourage more freedom in development, it was necessary to weaken that authority. Bacon and others started the movement to dismantle this oppression, but Descartes had a stronger and more decisive influence, with a firmer attitude. He didn't share Bacon's respect for classical literature; in fact, he took pride in having forgotten the Greek he learned as a boy. His work was inspired by the desire to completely and sharply break away from the past and create a system that drew nothing from history. He looked ahead to advancements in knowledge based on his own methods and discoveries, [Footnote: Cf. for instance his remarks on medicine, at the end of the Discours de la methode.] believing that this intellectual progress would significantly impact the condition of humanity. The original title he considered for his Discourse on Method was "The Project of a Universal Science that can elevate our Nature to its highest degree of Perfection." He viewed moral and material improvement as reliant on philosophy and science.

The justification of an independent attitude towards antiquity, on the ground that the world is now older and more mature, was becoming a current view. [Footnote: Descartes wrote: Non est quod antiquis multum tribuamus propter antiquitatem, sed nos potius iis seniores dicendi. Jam enim senior est mundus quam tune majoremque habemus rerum experientiam. (A fragment quoted by Baillet, Vie de Descartes, viii. 10.) Passages to the same effect occur in Malebranche, Arnauld, and Nicole. (See Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophie cartesienne, i. 482-3.)

The idea of having an independent view of the past, based on the belief that the world is now older and wiser, was becoming a popular perspective. [Footnote: Descartes wrote: We shouldn't give the ancients too much credit just because they are ancient; rather, we should consider ourselves their seniors. The world is indeed older now than it was then, and we have greater experience of things. (A fragment quoted by Baillet, Vie de Descartes, viii. 10.) Similar passages can be found in Malebranche, Arnauld, and Nicole. (See Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophie cartesienne, i. 482-3.)

A passage in La Mothe Le Vayer's essay Sur l'opiniatrete in Orasius Tubero (ii. 218) is in point, if, as seems probable, the date of that work is 1632-33. "Some defer to the ancients and allow themselves to be led by them like children; others hold that the ancients lived in the youth of the world, and it is those who live to-day who are really the ancients, and consequently ought to carry most weight." See Rigault, Histoire de la querelle des Anciens et des Modernes, p. 52.

A section in La Mothe Le Vayer's essay "Sur l'opiniatrete" in Orasius Tubero (ii. 218) is relevant, especially if the date of that work is indeed 1632-33. "Some people look up to the ancients and let them guide them like children; others believe that the ancients lived in the early days of the world, and it's those who live today who are truly the ancients, and therefore should hold the most significance." See Rigault, Histoire de la querelle des Anciens et des Modernes, p. 52.

The passage of Pascal occurs in the Fragment d'un traite du vide, not published till 1779 (now included in the Pensees, Premiere Partie, Art. I), and therefore without influence on the origination of the theory of progress. It has been pointed out that Guillaume Colletet had in 1636 expressed a similar view (Brunetiere, Etudes critiques, v. 185-6).]

The passage by Pascal appears in the Fragment d'un traite du vide, which wasn't published until 1779 (now included in the Pensees, Premiere Partie, Art. I), and thus did not influence the development of the theory of progress. It's noted that Guillaume Colletet expressed a similar idea in 1636 (Brunetiere, Etudes critiques, v. 185-6).

Descartes expressed it like Bacon, and it was taken up and repeated by many whom Descartes influenced. Pascal, who till 1654 was a man of science and a convert to Cartesian ideas, put it in a striking way. The whole sequence of men (he says) during so many centuries should be considered as a single man, continually existing and continually learning. At each stage of his life this universal man profited by the knowledge he had acquired in the preceding stages, and he is now in his old age. This is a fuller, and probably an independent, development of the comparison of the race to an individual which we found in Bacon. It occurs in a fragment which remained unpublished for more than a hundred years, and is often quoted as a recognition, not of a general progress of man, but of a progress in human knowledge.

Descartes put it similarly to Bacon, and many who were influenced by Descartes repeated it. Pascal, who was a scientist and embraced Cartesian ideas until 1654, expressed it in a powerful way. He suggested that the entire sequence of humans over many centuries should be seen as a single individual, always existing and always learning. At each stage of this collective person’s life, they built on the knowledge gained from earlier stages, and now they are in their old age. This is a more developed, and likely independent, version of the comparison between humanity and an individual that we found in Bacon. It appears in a fragment that was unpublished for over a century and is often cited as acknowledging not just the general progress of humanity but the advancement of human knowledge.

To those who reproached Descartes with disrespect towards ancient thinkers he might have replied that, in repudiating their authority, he was really paying them the compliment of imitation and acting far more in their own spirit than those who slavishly followed them. Pascal saw this point. "What can be more unjust," he wrote, "than to treat our ancients with greater consideration than they showed towards their own predecessors, and to have for them this incredible respect which they deserve from us only because they entertained no such regard for those who had the same advantage (of antiquity) over them?" [Footnote: Pensees, ib.]

To those who criticized Descartes for being disrespectful to ancient thinkers, he could have pointed out that by rejecting their authority, he was actually honoring them through imitation and staying true to their spirit more than those who blindly followed them. Pascal understood this perspective. "What could be more unfair," he wrote, "than to treat our ancient thinkers with more respect than they showed to their own predecessors, and to have for them this incredible respect which they only deserve from us because they had no such regard for those who enjoyed the same advantage of antiquity over them?" [Footnote: Pensees, ib.]

At the same time Pascal recognised that we are indebted to the ancients for our very superiority to them in the extent of our knowledge. "They reached a certain point, and the slightest effort enables us to mount higher; so that we find ourselves on a loftier plane with less trouble and less glory." The attitude of Descartes was very different. Aspiring to begin ab integro and reform the foundations of knowledge, he ignored or made little of what had been achieved in the past. He attempted to cut the threads of continuity as with the shears of Atropos. This illusion [Footnote: He may be reproached himself with scholasticism in his metaphysical reasoning.] hindered him from stating a doctrine of the progress of knowledge as otherwise he might have done. For any such doctrine must take account of the past as well as of the future.

At the same time, Pascal recognized that we owe our advanced knowledge to the ancients. "They reached a certain point, and with just a little effort, we can go further; thus, we find ourselves on a higher level with less effort and less recognition." Descartes had a very different approach. He aimed to start from scratch and revise the foundations of knowledge, disregarding or downplaying what had been accomplished before. He tried to sever the ties of continuity as if cutting with Atropos's shears. This misconception hindered him from articulating a theory of the progress of knowledge, as he could have done otherwise. Any such theory must consider both the past and the future.

But a theory of progress was to grow out of his philosophy, though he did not construct it. It was to be developed by men who were imbued with the Cartesian spirit.

But a theory of progress was to emerge from his philosophy, even though he didn't create it. It was to be developed by people who were inspired by the Cartesian spirit.

3.

3.

The theological world in France was at first divided on the question whether the system of Descartes could be reconciled with orthodoxy or not. The Jesuits said no, the Fathers of the Oratory said yes. The Jansenists of Port Royal were enthusiastic Cartesians. Yet it was probably the influence of the great spiritual force of Jansenism that did most to check the immediate spread of Cartesian ideas. It was preponderant in France for fifty years. The date of the Discourse of Method is 1637. The Augustinus of Jansenius was published in 1640, and in 1643 Arnauld's Frequent Communion made Jansenism a popular power. The Jansenist movement was in France in some measure what the Puritan movement was in England, and it caught hold of serious minds in much the same way. The Jesuits had undertaken the task of making Christianity easy, of finding a compromise between worldliness and religion, and they flooded the world with a casuistic literature designed for this purpose. Ex opinionum varietate jugum Christi suavius deportatur. The doctrine of Jansenius was directed against this corruption of faith and morals. He maintained that there can be no compromise with the world; that casuistry is incompatible with morality; that man is naturally corrupt; and that in his most virtuous acts some corruption is present.

The theological landscape in France was initially split on whether Descartes' system could align with orthodox beliefs. The Jesuits argued that it couldn't, while the Fathers of the Oratory believed it could. The Jansenists at Port Royal were enthusiastic supporters of Cartesian thought. However, it was likely the powerful spiritual influence of Jansenism that slowed the rapid spread of Cartesian ideas. Jansenism was dominant in France for fifty years. Descartes' Discourse of Method was published in 1637, Jansenius's Augustinus came out in 1640, and Arnauld's Frequent Communion in 1643 turned Jansenism into a significant movement. In some ways, the Jansenist movement in France resembled the Puritan movement in England, capturing the attention of serious thinkers in a similar fashion. The Jesuits focused on making Christianity more accessible, seeking a middle ground between worldly living and religion, resulting in a flood of complicated literature aimed at this goal. Ex opinionum varietate jugum Christi suavius deportatur. Jansenius's teachings targeted this corruption of faith and morals. He argued that there could be no compromise with the world, that casuistry contradicts morality, that humans are naturally corrupt, and that even in their most virtuous actions, some corruption is present.

Now the significance of these two forces—the stern ideal of the Jansenists and the casuistry of the Jesuit teachers—is that they both attempted to meet, by opposed methods, the wave of libertine thought and conduct which is a noticeable feature in the history of French society from the reign of Henry IV. to that of Louis XV. [Footnote: For the prevalence of "libertine" thought in France at the beginning of the seventeenth century see the work of the Pere Garasse, La Doctrine curieuse des beaux esprits de ce temps ou pretendus tels, etc. (1623). Cp. also Brunetiere's illuminating study, "Jansenistes et Cartesiens" in Etudes critiques, 4me serie.] This libertinism had its philosophy, a sort of philosophy of nature, of which the most brilliant exponents were Rabelais and Moliere. The maxim, "Be true to nature," was evidently opposed sharply to the principles of the Christian religion, and it was associated with sceptical views which prevailed widely in France from the early years of the seventeenth century. The Jesuits sought to make terms by saying virtually: "Our religious principles and your philosophy of nature are not after all so incompatible in practice. When it comes to the application of principles, opinions differ. Theology is as elastic as you like. Do not abandon your religion on the ground that her yoke is hard." Jansenius and his followers, on the other hand, fought uncompromisingly with the licentious spirit of the time, maintaining the austerest dogmas and denouncing any compromise or condescension. And their doctrine had a wonderful success, and penetrated everywhere. Few of the great literary men of the reign of Louis XIV. escaped it. Its influence can be traced in the Maximes of La Rochefoucauld and the Caracteres of La Bruyere. It was through its influence that Moliere found it difficult to get some of his plays staged. It explains the fact that the court of Louis XIV., however corrupt, was decorous compared with the courts of Henry IV. and Louis XV.; a severe standard was set up, if it was not observed.

Now the significance of these two forces—the strict ideals of the Jansenists and the flexible reasoning of the Jesuit teachers—is that they both tried to address, through opposing methods, the wave of libertine thought and behavior that stood out in the history of French society from the reign of Henry IV to that of Louis XV. [Footnote: For the prevalence of "libertine" thought in France at the beginning of the seventeenth century, see the work of Père Garasse, La Doctrine curieuse des beaux esprits de ce temps ou prétendus tels, etc. (1623). Also, refer to Brunetiere's illuminating study, "Jansenistes et Cartesiens" in Etudes critiques, 4me série.] This libertinism had its own philosophy, a kind of philosophy of nature, with Rabelais and Moliere as its most notable advocates. The saying "Be true to nature" directly opposed the principles of the Christian religion and was linked to the skeptical views that gained wide acceptance in France from the early seventeenth century. The Jesuits tried to find common ground, essentially saying: "Our religious principles and your philosophy of nature aren’t really so incompatible in practice. When it comes to applying principles, opinions vary. Theology is as flexible as you want it to be. Don’t give up your religion just because you think its demands are too tough." On the other hand, Jansenius and his followers fought firmly against the licentious spirit of the time, upholding the strictest dogmas and condemning any compromises or leniency. Their doctrine achieved remarkable success and spread everywhere. Few of the great literary figures of Louis XIV's reign escaped its influence. You can see its impact in the Maximes of La Rochefoucauld and the Caracteres of La Bruyere. It was due to this influence that Moliere struggled to get some of his plays performed. It also explains why the court of Louis XIV, despite its corruption, was more decorous compared to the courts of Henry IV and Louis XV; a strict standard was set, even if it wasn't always followed.

The genius of Pascal made the fortunes of Jansenism. He outlived his Cartesianism and became its most influential spokesman. His Provinciales (1656) rendered abstruse questions of theology more or less intelligible, and invited the general public to pronounce an opinion on them. His lucid exposition interested every one in the abstruse problem, Is man's freedom such as not to render grace superfluous? But Pascal perceived that casuistry was not the only enemy that menaced the true spirit of religion for which Jansenism stood. He came to realise that Cartesianism, to which he was at first drawn, was profoundly opposed to the fundamental views of Christianity. His Pensees are the fragments of a work which he designed in defence of religion, and it is easy to see that this defence was to be specially directed against the ideas of Descartes.

The brilliance of Pascal shaped the success of Jansenism. He outgrew his Cartesian views and became its most influential advocate. His Provinciales (1656) made complicated theological issues more understandable and encouraged the general public to weigh in on them. His clear explanations sparked widespread interest in the complex question, Is human freedom such that it makes grace unnecessary? But Pascal recognized that casuistry wasn’t the only threat to the true spirit of religion that Jansenism represented. He realized that Cartesianism, which he was initially attracted to, fundamentally clashed with the core beliefs of Christianity. His Pensees are fragments of a work he intended to defend religion, and it's clear that this defense was specifically aimed at the ideas of Descartes.

Pascal was perfectly right about the Cartesian conception of the Universe, though Descartes might pretend to mitigate its tendencies, and his fervent disciple, Malebranche, might attempt to prove that it was more or less reconcilable with orthodox doctrine. We need not trouble about the special metaphysical tenets of Descartes. The two axioms which he launched upon the world—the supremacy of reason, and the invariability of natural laws—struck directly at the foundations of orthodoxy. Pascal was attacking Cartesianism when he made his memorable attempt to discredit the authority of reason, by showing that it is feeble and deceptive. It was a natural consequence of his changed attitude that he should speak (in the Pensees) in a much less confident tone about the march of science than he had spoken in the passage which I quoted above. And it was natural that he should be pessimistic about social improvement, and that, keeping his eyes fixed on his central fact that Christianity is the goal of history, he should take only a slight and subsidiary interest in amelioration.

Pascal was spot on about the Cartesian view of the Universe, even though Descartes tried to tone down its implications, and his enthusiastic follower, Malebranche, tried to show that it could align with traditional beliefs. We don't need to worry about the specific metaphysical beliefs of Descartes. The two ideas he introduced—the primacy of reason and the unchanging nature of natural laws—challenged the very foundations of orthodoxy. Pascal was criticizing Cartesianism when he made his famous attempt to undermine the authority of reason by demonstrating its weakness and misleading nature. It makes sense that with his shifted perspective, he would express (in the Pensees) a much less assured attitude about the progress of science than he did in the earlier passage I quoted. Likewise, it’s understandable that he would be pessimistic about social progress and, with his focus on the idea that Christianity is the ultimate purpose of history, show only a minor and secondary interest in improvement.

The preponderant influence of Jansenism only began to wane during the last twenty years of the seventeenth century, and till then it seems to have been successful in counteracting the diffusion of the Cartesian ideas. Cartesianism begins to become active and powerful when Jansenism is beginning to decline. And it is just then that the idea of Progress begins definitely to emerge. The atmosphere in France was favourable for its reception.

The dominant influence of Jansenism only started to decrease in the last twenty years of the seventeenth century, and until then, it seems to have effectively resisted the spread of Cartesian ideas. Cartesianism starts to gain strength and significance as Jansenism begins to fade. It's at this point that the idea of Progress starts to emerge clearly. The environment in France was supportive of its acceptance.

4.

4.

The Cartesian mechanical theory of the world and the doctrine of invariable law, carried to a logical conclusion, excluded the doctrine of Providence. This doctrine was already in serious danger. Perhaps no article of faith was more insistently attacked by sceptics in the seventeenth century, and none was more vital. The undermining of the theory of Providence is very intimately connected with our subject; for it was just the theory of an active Providence that the theory of Progress was to replace; and it was not till men felt independent of Providence that they could organise a theory of Progress.

The Cartesian mechanical view of the world and the belief in unchanging laws, when taken to an extreme, dismissed the idea of Providence. This belief was already at great risk. No aspect of faith faced more persistent challenges from skeptics in the seventeenth century, and none was more crucial. The erosion of the idea of Providence is closely linked to our topic; the concept of an active Providence is what the theory of Progress aimed to replace, and it wasn’t until people felt free from Providence that they were able to form a theory of Progress.

Bossuet was convinced that the question of Providence was the most serious and pressing among all the questions of the day that were at issue between orthodox and heretical thinkers. Brunetiere, his fervent admirer, has named him the theologian of Providence, and has shown that in all his writings this doctrine is a leading note. It is sounded in his early sermons in the fifties, and it is the theme of his most ambitious work, the Discourse on Universal History, which appeared in 1681. [Footnote; It has been shown that on one hand he controverts Spinoza's Tractatus theologico-politicus, and on the other the dangerous methods of Richard Simon, one of the precursors of modern biblical criticism. Brunetiere, op. cit. 74-85.] This book, which has received high praise from those who most heartily dissent from its conclusions, is in its main issue a restatement of the view of history which Augustine had worked out in his memorable book. The whole course of human experience has been guided by Providence for the sake of the Church; that is, for the sake of the Church to which Bossuet belonged. Regarded as a philosophy of history the Discourse may seem little more than the theory of the De Civitate Dei brought up to date; but this is its least important aspect. We shall fail to understand it unless we recognise that it was a pragmatical, opportune work, designed for the needs of the time, and with express references to current tendencies of thought.

Bossuet was convinced that the question of Providence was the most serious and urgent among all the issues of his time that were debated by orthodox and heretical thinkers. Brunetiere, his passionate admirer, called him the theologian of Providence and demonstrated that this doctrine is a central theme in all his writings. It’s present in his early sermons from the fifties and is the focus of his most ambitious work, the Discourse on Universal History, published in 1681. [Footnote; It has been shown that on one hand he counters Spinoza's Tractatus theologico-politicus, and on the other the controversial methods of Richard Simon, one of the forerunners of modern biblical criticism. Brunetiere, op. cit. 74-85.] This book, which has received high praise even from those who strongly disagree with its conclusions, essentially restates the view of history that Augustine developed in his famous work. The entire course of human experience has been guided by Providence for the benefit of the Church; that is, for the Church to which Bossuet belonged. Viewed as a philosophy of history, the Discourse might seem like just a modernized version of the theory in De Civitate Dei; but this is its least significant aspect. We will fail to grasp it unless we recognize that it was a practical, timely work, tailored to the needs of the day, and referencing current trends in thought.

One main motive of Bossuet in his lifelong concern for Providence was his conviction that the doctrine was the most powerful check on immorality, and that to deny it was to remove the strongest restraint on the evil side of human nature. There is no doubt that the free-living people of the time welcomed the arguments which called Providence in question, and Bossuet believed that to champion Providence was the most efficient means of opposing the libertine tendencies of his day. "Nothing," he declared in one of his sermons (1662), "has appeared more insufferable to the arrogance of libertines than to see themselves continually under the observation of this ever-watchful eye of Providence. They have felt it as an importunate compulsion to recognise that there is in Heaven a superior force which governs all our movements and chastises our loose actions with a severe authority. They have wished to shake off the yoke of this Providence, in order to maintain, in independence, an unteachable liberty which moves them to live at their own fancy, without fear, discipline, or restraint." [Passage from Bossuet, quoted by Brunetiere, op. cit. 58.] Bossuet was thus working in the same cause as the Jansenists.

One main reason Bossuet dedicated his life to the idea of Providence was his belief that this doctrine was the strongest deterrent against immorality, and that rejecting it removed the greatest barrier against the darker aspects of human nature. It's clear that the free-spirited individuals of his time embraced the arguments questioning Providence, and Bossuet felt that defending Providence was the best way to fight against the libertine attitudes of his era. "Nothing," he stated in one of his sermons (1662), "has been more unbearable to the arrogance of libertines than the thought of being constantly watched by the ever-observant eye of Providence. They have seen it as an annoying pressure to acknowledge that there is a higher power in Heaven that controls our actions and punishes our reckless behavior with strict authority. They have wanted to shake off the burden of this Providence to maintain an independent, unteachable freedom that allows them to live as they please, without fear, discipline, or restraint." [Passage from Bossuet, quoted by Brunetiere, op. cit. 58.] Bossuet was therefore aligned with the same goals as the Jansenists.

He had himself come under the influence of Descartes, whose work he always regarded with the deepest respect. The cautiousness of the master had done much to disguise the insidious dangers of his thought, and it was in the hands of those disciples who developed his system and sought to reconcile it at all points with orthodoxy that his ideas displayed their true nature. Malebranche's philosophy revealed the incompatibility of Providence—in the ordinary acceptation—with immutable natural laws. If the Deity acts upon the world, as Malebranche maintained, only by means of general laws, His freedom is abolished, His omnipotence is endangered, He is subject to a sort of fatality. What will become of the Christian belief in the value of prayers, if God cannot adapt or modify, on any given occasion, the general order of nature to the needs of human beings? These are some of the arguments which we find in a treatise composed by Fenelon, with the assistance of Bossuet, to demonstrate that the doctrine of Malebranche is inconsistent with piety and orthodox religion. They were right. Cartesianism was too strong a wine to be decanted into old bottles. [Footnote: Fenelon's Refutation of Malebranche's Traite de la nature et de la grace was not published till 1820. This work of Malebranche also provoked a controversy with Arnauld, who urged similar arguments.]

He had come under the influence of Descartes, whose work he always respected deeply. The caution of the master effectively masked the subtle dangers of his ideas, and it was in the hands of those followers who expanded his system and tried to align it with traditional views that his concepts revealed their true nature. Malebranche's philosophy uncovered the conflict between Providence— in the usual sense— and unchanging natural laws. If God influences the world, as Malebranche argued, only through general laws, then His freedom is compromised, His omnipotence is at risk, and He falls subject to a kind of fate. What happens to the Christian belief in the power of prayer if God can't adjust or change the general order of nature to meet human needs in specific situations? These are some of the points made in a treatise written by Fenelon, with help from Bossuet, to show that Malebranche's doctrine conflicts with piety and orthodox religion. They were correct. Cartesianism was too strong a wine to be poured into old bottles. [Footnote: Fenelon's Refutation of Malebranche's Traite de la nature et de la grace was not published till 1820. This work of Malebranche also provoked a controversy with Arnauld, who urged similar arguments.]

Malebranche's doctrine of what he calls divine Providence was closely connected with his philosophical optimism. It enabled him to maintain the perfection of the universe. Admitting the obvious truth that the world exhibits many imperfections, and allowing that the Creator could have produced a better result if he had employed other means, Malebranche argued that, in judging the world, we must take into account not only the result but the methods by which it has been produced. It is the best world, he asserts, that could be framed by general and simple methods; and general and simple methods are the most perfect, and alone worthy of the Creator. Therefore, if we take the methods and the result together, a more perfect world is impossible. The argument was ingenious, though full of assumptions, but it was one which could only satisfy a philosopher. It is little consolation to creatures suffering from the actual imperfections of the system into which they are born to be told that the world might have been free from those defects, only in that case they would not have the satisfaction of knowing that it was created and conducted on theoretically superior principles.

Malebranche's idea of what he calls divine Providence was closely linked to his philosophical optimism. It allowed him to support the idea that the universe is perfect. While acknowledging the obvious fact that the world shows many flaws, and recognizing that the Creator could have achieved a better outcome with different methods, Malebranche argued that when assessing the world, we need to consider not just the outcome but also the ways it was achieved. He claims that this is the best world that could be created using general and simple methods; and those methods are the most perfect and truly worthy of the Creator. So, when we look at both the methods and the outcome together, a more perfect world just isn't possible. The argument was clever, though it was full of assumptions, and it could only truly satisfy a philosopher. It offers little comfort to beings struggling with the actual shortcomings of the system they were born into to be told that the world could have been free from those flaws; in that case, they would miss out on the satisfaction of knowing it was created and governed by theoretically better principles.

Though Malebranche's conception was only a metaphysical theory, metaphysical theories have usually their pragmatic aspects; and the theory that the universe is as perfect as it could be marks a stage in the growth of intellectual optimism which we can trace from the sixteenth century. It was a view which could appeal to the educated public in France, for it harmonised with the general spirit of self-complacency and hopefulness which prevailed among the higher classes of society in the reign of Louis XIV. For them the conditions of life under the new despotism had become far more agreeable than in previous ages, and it was in a spirit of optimism that they devoted themselves to the enjoyment of luxury and elegance. The experience of what the royal authority could achieve encouraged men to imagine that one enlightened will, with a centralised administration at its command, might accomplish endless improvements in civilisation. There was no age had ever been more glorious, no age more agreeable to live in.

Although Malebranche's idea was just a metaphysical theory, such theories usually come with practical implications. The belief that the universe is as perfect as it can be represents a point in the development of intellectual optimism that we can trace back to the sixteenth century. This perspective resonated with the educated public in France, as it aligned with the overall sense of self-satisfaction and hopefulness prevalent among the upper classes during the reign of Louis XIV. For them, life under the new authoritarian regime had become much more enjoyable than in earlier times, and they approached their lives focused on enjoying luxury and elegance with an optimistic mindset. The achievements of royal authority led people to believe that one enlightened leader, with a centralized government at their disposal, could bring about endless advancements in civilization. No era had ever been more glorious, nor had any period been more pleasant to live in.

The world had begun to abandon the theory of corruption, degeneration, and decay.

The world had started to move away from the idea of corruption, degeneration, and decay.

Some years later the optimistic theory of the perfection of the universe found an abler exponent in Leibnitz, whom Diderot calls the father of optimism. [Footnote: See particularly Monadologie, ad fin. published posthumously in German 1720, in Latin 1728; Theodicee, Section 341 (1710); and the paper, De rerum originatione radicali, written in 1697, but not published till 1840 (Opera philosophica, ed. Erdmann, p. 147 sqq).] The Creator, before He acted, had considered all possible worlds, and had chosen the best. He might have chosen one in which humanity would have been better and happier, but that would not have been the best possible, for He had to consider the interests of the whole universe, of which the earth with humanity is only an insignificant part. The evils and imperfections of our small world are negligible in comparison with the happiness and perfection of the whole cosmos. Leibnitz, whose theory is deduced from the abstract proposition that the Creator is perfect, does not say that now or at any given moment the universe is as perfect as it could be; its merit lies in its potentialities; it will develop towards perfection throughout infinite time.

Some years later, the optimistic theory of the perfection of the universe found a more capable advocate in Leibniz, whom Diderot refers to as the father of optimism. [Footnote: See particularly Monadology, ad fin., published posthumously in German 1720, in Latin 1728; Theodicy, Section 341 (1710); and the paper, On the Radical Origin of Things, written in 1697, but not published until 1840 (Philosophical Works, ed. Erdmann, p. 147 sqq).] The Creator, before acting, considered all possible worlds and chose the best one. He could have chosen a world where humanity was better and happier, but that wouldn't have been the best possible choice, as He had to take into account the interests of the entire universe, of which Earth and humanity are just a tiny part. The evils and imperfections of our small world are insignificant compared to the happiness and perfection of the whole cosmos. Leibniz, whose theory is based on the abstract idea that the Creator is perfect, does not claim that the universe is as perfect as it could be at any given moment; its value lies in its potential. It will evolve towards perfection over an infinite period.

The optimism of Leibnitz therefore concerns the universe as a whole, not the earth, and would obviously be quite consistent with a pessimistic view of the destinies of humanity. He does indeed believe that it would be impossible to improve the universal order, "not only for the whole, but for ourselves in particular," and incidentally he notes the possibility that "in the course of time the human race may reach a greater perfection than we can imagine at present." But the significance of his speculation and that of Malebranche lies in the fact that the old theories of degeneration are definitely abandoned.

The optimism of Leibnitz is focused on the universe as a whole rather than just Earth, and it is clearly compatible with a pessimistic outlook on humanity's future. He genuinely believes that improving the universal order is impossible, "not only for the whole, but for us specifically," and he also mentions that "over time, the human race might achieve a level of perfection greater than we can currently imagine." However, the importance of his speculation, along with that of Malebranche, is that the old theories of degeneration are clearly left behind.





CHAPTER IV. THE DOCTRINE OF DEGENERATION: THE ANCIENTS AND MODERNS

1.

Outside the circle of systematic thinkers the prevalent theory of degeneration was being challenged early in the seventeenth century. The challenge led to a literary war, which was waged for about a hundred years in France and England; over the comparative merits of the ancients and the moderns. It was in the matter of literature, and especially poetry, that the quarrel was most acrimonious, and that the interest of the public was most keenly aroused, but the ablest disputants extended the debate to the general field of knowledge. The quarrel of the Ancients and Moderns used commonly to be dismissed as a curious and rather ridiculous episode in the history of literature. [Footnote: The best and fullest work on the subject is Rigault's "Histoire de la querelle des Anciens et des Modernes" (1856).] Auguste Comte was, I think, one of the first to call attention to some of its wider bearings.

Outside the circle of systematic thinkers, the common theory of degeneration was being questioned early in the seventeenth century. This challenge sparked a literary battle that lasted about a hundred years in France and England, focused on the relative merits of the ancients and the moderns. The dispute was most heated in the realm of literature, especially poetry, where public interest was at its highest, but the most skilled debaters expanded the discussion to the broader field of knowledge. The argument between the Ancients and Moderns was often dismissed as a curious and somewhat silly episode in literary history. [Footnote: The best and most comprehensive work on the subject is Rigault's "Histoire de la querelle des Anciens et des Modernes" (1856).] Auguste Comte was, I think, one of the first to highlight some of its broader implications.

The quarrel, indeed, has considerable significance in the history of ideas. It was part of the rebellion against the intellectual yoke of the Renaissance; the cause of the Moderns, who were the aggressors, represented the liberation of criticism from the authority of the dead; and, notwithstanding the perversities of taste of which they were guilty, their polemic, even on the purely literary side, was distinctly important, as M. Brunetiere has convincingly shown, [Footnote: See his "L'evolution des genres dans l'histoire de la litterature."] in the development of French criticism. But the form in which the critical questions were raised forced the debate to touch upon a problem of greater moment. The question, Can the men of to-day contend on equal terms with the illustrious ancients, or are they intellectually inferior? implied the larger issue, Has nature exhausted her powers; is she no longer capable of producing men equal in brains and vigour to those whom she once produced; is humanity played out, or are her forces permanent and inexhaustible?

The argument, indeed, has significant importance in the history of ideas. It was part of the rebellion against the intellectual constraints of the Renaissance; the cause of the Moderns, who were the aggressors, symbolized the liberation of criticism from the authority of the past. Despite their questionable tastes, their debate, even on a purely literary level, was notably important, as M. Brunetiere has convincingly shown, [Footnote: See his "L'evolution des genres dans l'histoire de la litterature."] in the growth of French criticism. However, the way the critical questions were raised pushed the discussion to address a more significant problem. The question, Can today's people compete on equal terms with the great ancients, or are they intellectually inferior? suggested the larger issue: Has nature exhausted her capabilities; is she no longer able to produce individuals equal in intellect and strength to those she once created; has humanity reached its limit, or are its forces permanent and unlimited?

The assertion of the permanence of the powers of nature by the champions of the Moderns was the direct contradiction of the theory of degeneration, and they undoubtedly contributed much towards bringing that theory into discredit. When we grasp this it will not be surprising to find that the first clear assertions of a doctrine of progress in knowledge were provoked by the controversy about the Ancients and Moderns.

The claim that the powers of nature are constant by the supporters of the Moderns directly opposed the theory of degeneration, and they definitely played a significant role in discrediting that theory. When we understand this, it’s easy to see why the first clear statements of a doctrine of progress in knowledge were sparked by the debate between the Ancients and the Moderns.

Although the great scene of the controversy was France, the question had been expressly raised by an Italian, no less a person than Alessandro Tassoni, the accomplished author of that famous ironical poem, "La Secchia rapita," which caricatured the epic poets of his day. He was bent on exposing the prejudices of his time and uttering new doctrine, and he created great scandal in Italy by his attacks on Petrarch, as well as on Homer and Aristotle. The earliest comparison of the merits of the ancients and the moderns will be found in a volume of Miscellaneous Thoughts which he published in 1620. [Footnote: Dieci libri di pensieri diversi (Carpi, 1620). The first nine books had appeared in 1612. The tenth contains the comparison. Rigault was the first to connect this work with the history of the controversy.] He speaks of the question as a matter of current dispute, [Footnote: It was incidental to the controversy which arose over the merits of Tasso's Jerusalem Delivered. That the subject had been discussed long before may be inferred from a remark of Estienne in his Apology for Herodotus, that while some of his contemporaries carry their admiration of antiquity to the point of superstition, others depreciate and trample it underfoot.] on which he proposes to give an impartial decision by instituting a comprehensive comparison in all fields, theoretical, imaginative, and practical.

Although the main stage of the debate was in France, the issue was raised by an Italian, none other than Alessandro Tassoni, the talented author of the famous ironic poem, "La Secchia rapita," which mocked the epic poets of his time. He aimed to challenge the biases of his era and present new ideas, creating quite a scandal in Italy with his critiques of Petrarch, as well as Homer and Aristotle. The first comparison of the merits of the ancients and the moderns can be found in a book of Miscellaneous Thoughts he published in 1620. [Footnote: Dieci libri di pensieri diversi (Carpi, 1620). The first nine books were released in 1612. The tenth book contains the comparison. Rigault was the first to link this work with the history of the debate.] He discusses the question as a matter of ongoing dispute, [Footnote: It was part of the controversy that arose over the merits of Tasso's Jerusalem Delivered. The fact that the topic had been discussed long before can be inferred from a comment by Estienne in his Apology for Herodotus, noting that while some of his contemporaries take their admiration for antiquity to a superstitious level, others belittle and disregard it.] on which he aims to provide an unbiased judgment by making a thorough comparison across all areas, including theoretical, imaginative, and practical.

He begins by criticising the a priori argument that, as arts are brought to perfection by experience and long labour, the modern age must necessarily have the advantage. This reasoning, he says, is unsound, because the same arts and studies are not always uninterruptedly pursued by the most powerful intellects, but pass into inferior hands, and so decline or are even extinguished, as was the case in Italy in the decrepitude of the Roman Empire, when for many centuries the arts fell below mediocrity. Or, to phrase it otherwise, the argument would be admissible only if there were no breaches of continuity. [Footnote: Tassoni argues that a decline in all pursuits is inevitable when a certain point of excellence has been reached, quoting Velleius Paterculus (i. 17): difficilisque in perfecto mora est naturaliterque quod procedere non potest recedit.]

He starts by criticizing the claim that since arts reach their peak through experience and hard work, the modern age must automatically have the upper hand. He argues that this reasoning is flawed because the same arts and studies aren't always carried on by top minds; they can get passed to lesser hands, leading to their decline or even disappearance, just like what happened in Italy during the decline of the Roman Empire when the arts dropped to well below average for many centuries. In other words, this argument would only be valid if there were no interruptions in progress. [Footnote: Tassoni contends that a decline in all fields is inevitable once a certain level of excellence has been achieved, quoting Velleius Paterculus (i. 17): difficilisque in perfecto mora est naturaliterque quod procedere non potest recedit.]

In drawing his comparison Tassoni seeks to make good his claim that he is not an advocate. But while he awards superiority here and there to the ancients, the moderns on the whole have much the best of it. He takes a wide enough survey, including the material side of civilisation, even costume, in contrast with some of the later controversialists, who narrowed the field of debate to literature and art.

In making his comparison, Tassoni tries to support his claim that he's not an advocate. But even though he gives some advantages to the ancients, the moderns, overall, come out on top. He takes a broad look, including the practical aspects of civilization, even fashion, unlike some later debaters who limited the discussion to just literature and art.

Tassoni's Thoughts were translated into French, and the book was probably known to Boisrobert, a dramatist who is chiefly remembered for the part he took in founding the Academie francaise. He delivered a discourse before that body immediately after its institution (February 26, 1635), in which he made a violent and apparently scurrilous attack on Homer. This discourse kindled the controversy in France, and even struck a characteristic note. Homer—already severely handled by Tassoni—was to be the special target for the arrows of the Moderns, who felt that, if they could succeed in discrediting him, their cause would be won.

Tassoni's Thoughts were translated into French, and the book was likely known to Boisrobert, a playwright mostly remembered for helping to establish the Académie française. He gave a speech to that group right after it was formed (February 26, 1635), where he launched a harsh and seemingly derogatory attack on Homer. This speech sparked controversy in France and set a distinct tone. Homer—who had already been criticized by Tassoni—became the main target for the Moderns, who believed that if they could undermine him, their cause would prevail.

Thus the gauntlet was flung—and it is important to note this—before the appearance of the Discourse of Method (1637); but the influence of Descartes made itself felt throughout the controversy, and the most prominent moderns were men who had assimilated Cartesian ideas. This seems to be true even of Desmarets de Saint Sorlin, who, a good many years after the discourse of Boisrobert, opened the campaign. Saint Sorlin had become a fanatical Christian; that was one reason for hating the ancients. [Footnote: For the views of Saint Sorlin see the Preface to his Clovis and his Traite pour juger des poefes grecs, latins, et francais, chap. iv. (1670). Cp. Rigault, Hist. de la querelle, p. 106. The polemic of Saint Sorlin extended over about five years (1669-73).] He was also, like Boisrobert, a bad poet; that was another. His thesis was that the history of Christianity offered subjects far more inspiring to a poet than those which had been treated by Homer and Sophocles, and that Christian poetry must bear off the palm from pagan. His own Clovis and Mary Magdalene or the Triumph of Grace were the demonstration of Homer's defeat. Few have ever heard of these productions; how many have read them? Curiously, about the same time an epic was being composed in England which might have given to the foolish contentions of Saint Sorlin some illusory plausibility.

Thus the challenge was thrown down—and it's important to note this—before the publication of the Discourse of Method (1637); however, Descartes' influence was felt throughout the debate, and the most notable modern thinkers were individuals who had embraced Cartesian ideas. This appears to be true even for Desmarets de Saint Sorlin, who, many years after Boisrobert's discourse, initiated the conflict. Saint Sorlin had become a zealous Christian; that was one reason for his disdain for the ancients. [Footnote: For the views of Saint Sorlin see the Preface to his Clovis and his Traite pour juger des poefes grecs, latins, et francais, chap. iv. (1670). Cp. Rigault, Hist. de la querelle, p. 106. The polemic of Saint Sorlin extended over about five years (1669-73).] He was also, like Boisrobert, a poor poet; that was another factor. His argument was that the history of Christianity provided far more inspiring subjects for a poet than those explored by Homer and Sophocles, and that Christian poetry must surpass pagan works. His own Clovis and Mary Magdalene or the Triumph of Grace served as proof of Homer's defeat. Few have ever heard of these works; how many have actually read them? Interestingly, around the same time, an epic was being written in England that might have lent some illusory credibility to Saint Sorlin's foolish disputes.

But the literary dispute does not concern us here. What does concern us is that Saint Sorlin was aware of the wider aspects of the question, though he was not seriously interested in them. Antiquity, he says, was not so happy or so learned or so rich or so stately as the modern age, which is really the mature old age, and as it were the autumn of the world, possessing the fruits and the spoils of all the past centuries, with the power to judge of the inventions, experiences, and errors of predecessors, and to profit by all that. The ancient world was a spring which had only a few flowers. Nature indeed, in all ages, produces perfect works but it is not so with the creations of man, which require correction; and the men who live latest must excel in happiness and knowledge. Here we have both the assertion of the permanence of the forces of nature and the idea, already expressed by Bacon and others, that the modern age has advantages over antiquity comparable to those of old age over childhood.

But the literary debate isn’t our focus here. What matters is that Saint Sorlin recognized the broader aspects of the issue, even though he wasn’t really interested in them. He argues that antiquity wasn’t as happy, learned, wealthy, or impressive as the modern age, which is essentially the mature old age, like the autumn of the world, holding the fruits and treasures of all previous centuries, with the ability to evaluate the inventions, experiences, and mistakes of those before us and to benefit from it all. The ancient world was like a spring with only a few blooms. Nature, of course, always produces perfect works, but that's not the case with human creations, which need refinement; and those who come later must surpass earlier generations in happiness and knowledge. Here we see both the emphasis on the lasting power of nature and the idea, already put forth by Bacon and others, that the modern age has advantages over antiquity similar to the advantages of old age over childhood.

2.

2.

How seriously the question between the Moderns and the Ancients—on whose behalf Boileau had come forward and crossed swords with Saint Sorlin—was taken is shown by the fact that Saint Sorlin, before his death, solemnly bequeathed the championship of the Moderns to a younger man, Charles Perrault. We shall see how he fulfilled the trust. It is illustrated too by a book which appeared in the seventies, Les Entretiens d'Ariste et Eugene, by Bouhours, a mundane and popular Jesuit Father. In one of these dialogues the question is raised, but with a curious caution and evasiveness, which suggests that the author was afraid to commit himself; he did not wish to make enemies. [Footnote: Rigault notes that he makes one contribution to the subject, the idea that the torch of civilisation has passed from country to country, in different ages, e.g. from Greece to Rome, and recently from Italy to France. In the last century the Italians were first in doctrine and politesse. The present century is for France what the last was for Italy: "We have all the esprit and all the science, all other countries are barbarous in comparison" (p. 239, ed. 1782, Amsterdam). But, as we shall see, he had been anticipated by Hakewill, whose work was unknown to Rigault.]

How seriously the debate between the Moderns and the Ancients—on whose side Boileau had stepped up to challenge Saint Sorlin—was taken is evident from the fact that, before he died, Saint Sorlin officially passed the mantle of the Moderns to a younger man, Charles Perrault. We'll see how he lived up to that trust. This is also illustrated by a book that came out in the seventies, *Les Entretiens d'Ariste et Eugene*, by Bouhours, a worldly and popular Jesuit Father. In one of these dialogues, the question is touched upon, but with a curious caution and reluctance, suggesting that the author was hesitant to take a firm stance; he didn’t want to make enemies. [Footnote: Rigault notes that he makes one contribution to the subject, the idea that the torch of civilization has shifted from country to country over different periods, such as from Greece to Rome, and recently from Italy to France. In the last century, the Italians were leading in doctrine and manners. This century belongs to France just as the last belonged to Italy: "We have all the spirit and all the science, all other countries are barbaric in comparison" (p. 239, ed. 1782, Amsterdam). But, as we will see, he had been preceded by Hakewill, whose work was unknown to Rigault.]

The general atmosphere in France, in the reign of Louis XIV., was propitious to the cause of the Moderns. Men felt that it was a great age, comparable to the age of Augustus, and few would have preferred to have lived at any other time. Their literary artists, Corneille, and then Racine and Moliere, appealed so strongly to their taste that they could not assign to them any rank but the first. They were impatient of the claims to unattainable excellence advanced for the Greeks and Romans. "The ancients," said Moliere, "are the ancients, we are the people of to-day." This might be the motto of Descartes, and it probably expressed a very general feeling.

The overall vibe in France during the reign of Louis XIV was favorable to the Moderns. People sensed they were living in a remarkable time, comparable to the era of Augustus, and few would have wanted to live in any other period. The literary figures like Corneille, and later Racine and Molière, resonated so much with their audience that they were held in the highest regard. They grew frustrated with the impossible standards set by the Greeks and Romans. "The ancients," Molière said, "are the ancients, we are the people of today." This could have been Descartes' motto, and it likely reflected a widely held sentiment.

It was in 1687 that Charles Perrault—who is better remembered for his collection of fairy-tales than for the leading role which he played in this controversy—published his poem on "The Age of Louis the Great." The enlightenment of the present age surpasses that of antiquity,—this is the theme.

It was in 1687 that Charles Perrault—better known for his collection of fairy tales than for his prominent role in this debate—published his poem "The Age of Louis the Great." The theme is that the enlightenment of the present age surpasses that of ancient times.

  La docte Antiquite dans toute sa duree
   A l'egal de nos jours ne fut point eclairee.
  La docte Antiquité dans toute sa durée  
   À l'égal de nos jours, ne fut point éclairée.

Perrault adopts a more polite attitude to "la belle antiquite" than Saint Sorlin, but his criticism is more insidious. Greek and Roman men of genius, he suggests, were all very well in their own times, and might be considered divine by our ancestors. But nowadays Plato is rather tiresome; and the "inimitable Homer" would have written a much better epic if he had lived in the reign of Louis the Great. The important passage, however, in the poem is that in which the permanent power of nature to produce men of equal talent in every age is affirmed.

Perrault has a more respectful view of "the beautiful antiquity" than Saint Sorlin, but his criticism is more subtle. He implies that great Greek and Roman thinkers were impressive in their own times and might have seemed divine to our ancestors. However, today, Plato is a bit tedious, and the "inimitable Homer" would have penned a far superior epic if he had lived during the reign of Louis the Great. The key part of the poem, though, is where it asserts that nature has the constant ability to produce equally talented individuals in every era.

  A former les esprits comme a former les corps
   La Nature en tout temps fait les mesmes efforts;
   Son etre est immuable, et cette force aisee
   Dont elle produit tout ne s'est point epuisee;
.....   De cette mesme main les forces infinies
   Produisent en tout temps de semblables genies.
  To shape minds just like to shape bodies  
   Nature always makes the same effort;  
   Her being is unchanging, and this effortless strength  
   From which she produces all has not worn out;  
.....   With that same hand, infinite forces  
   Constantly produce similar geniuses.  

The "Age of Louis the Great" was a brief declaration of faith. Perrault followed it up by a comprehensive work, his Comparison of the Ancients and the Moderns (Parallele des Anciens et des Modernes), which appeared in four parts during the following years (1688-1696). Art, eloquence, poetry the sciences, and their practical applications are all discussed at length; and the discussion is thrown into the form of conversations between an enthusiastic champion of the modern age, who conducts the debate, and a devotee of antiquity, who finds it difficult not to admit the arguments of his opponent, yet obstinately persists in his own views.

The "Age of Louis the Great" was a short declaration of faith. Perrault followed it up with a comprehensive work, his Comparison of the Ancients and the Moderns (Parallele des Anciens et des Modernes), which came out in four parts over the next few years (1688-1696). Art, eloquence, poetry, the sciences, and their practical applications are all thoroughly discussed; and the discussion takes the form of conversations between an enthusiastic supporter of the modern age, who leads the debate, and a devotee of antiquity, who finds it hard not to acknowledge his opponent's arguments but stubbornly holds on to his own beliefs.

Perrault bases his thesis on those general considerations which we have met incidentally in earlier writers, and which were now almost commonplaces among those who paid any attention to the matter. Knowledge advances with time and experience; perfection is not necessarily associated with antiquity; the latest comers have inherited from their predecessors and added new acquisitions of their own. But Perrault has thought out the subject methodically, and he draws conclusions which have only to be extended to amount to a definite theory of the progress of knowledge.

Perrault builds his argument on general ideas we've encountered in earlier writers, which are now almost clichés for anyone paying attention. Knowledge grows with time and experience; perfection isn't always linked to the past; newcomers have taken from their predecessors and added their own insights. However, Perrault has systematically considered the topic, and he reaches conclusions that can easily be expanded into a clear theory about the advancement of knowledge.

A particular difficulty had done much to hinder a general admission of progressive improvement in the past. The proposition that the posterior is better and the late comers have the advantage seemed to be incompatible with an obvious historical fact. We are superior to the men of the dark ages in knowledge and arts. Granted. But will you say that the men of the tenth century were superior to the Greeks and Romans? To this question—on which Tassoni had already touched—Perrault replies: Certainly not. There are breaches of continuity. The sciences and arts are like rivers, which flow for part of their course underground, and then, finding an opening, spring forth as abundant as when they plunged beneath the earth. Long wars, for instance, may force peoples to neglect studies and throw all their vigour into the more urgent needs of self-preservation; a period of ignorance may ensue but with peace and felicity knowledge and inventions will begin again and make further advances. [Footnote: The passages in Perrault's Parallele specially referred to in the text will be found in vol. i. pp. 35-7, 60-61, 67, 231-3.]

A particular difficulty has significantly hindered a general acknowledgment of progress in the past. The idea that the newer generations are better and the latecomers have the advantage seems to conflict with a clear historical fact. We are more advanced than the people of the Dark Ages in knowledge and arts. That's true. But would you claim that the people of the tenth century were better than the Greeks and Romans? To this question—which Tassoni already touched on—Perrault responds: Definitely not. There are gaps in continuity. The sciences and arts are like rivers that flow underground for part of their journey and then surface all at once when they find an opening, just as plentiful as when they disappeared beneath the ground. Long wars, for example, may cause societies to neglect education and focus all their energy on the urgent need for survival; a time of ignorance may follow, but with peace and prosperity, knowledge and inventions will emerge again and continue to advance. [Footnote: The passages in Perrault's Parallele specially referred to in the text will be found in vol. i. pp. 35-7, 60-61, 67, 231-3.]

It is to be observed that he does not, claim any superiority in talents or brain power for the moderns. On the contrary, he takes his stand on the principle which he had asserted in the "Age of Louis the Great," that nature is immutable. She still produces as great men as ever, but she does not produce greater. The lions of the deserts of Africa in our days do not differ in fierceness from those the days of Alexander the Great, and the best men of all times are equal in vigour. It is their work and productions that are unequal, and, given equally favourable conditions, the latest must be the best. For science and the arts depend upon the accumulation of knowledge, and knowledge necessarily increases as time goes on.

It’s important to note that he doesn’t claim any superiority in skills or intelligence for modern people. Instead, he stands by the principle he asserted in the "Age of Louis the Great," that nature doesn’t change. She still produces great individuals, but she doesn’t produce anyone greater. The lions in the deserts of Africa today are just as fierce as those in the time of Alexander the Great, and the best people of all times are equal in strength. It’s their work and achievements that are uneven, and with equally favorable conditions, the most recent must be the best. This is because science and the arts rely on the accumulation of knowledge, which naturally increases over time.

But could this argument be applied to poetry and literary art, the field of battle in which the belligerents, including Perrault himself, were most deeply interested? It might prove that the modern age was capable of producing poets and men of letter no less excellent than the ancient masters, but did it prove that their works must be superior? The objection did not escape Perrault, and he answers it ingeniously. It is the function of poetry and eloquence to please the human heart, and in order to please it we must know it. Is it easier to penetrate the secrets of the human heart than the secrets of nature, or will it take less time? We are always making new discoveries about its passions and desires. To take only the tragedies of Corneille you will find there finer and more delicate reflections on ambition, vengeance, and jealousy than in all the books of antiquity. At the close of his Parallel, however, Perrault, while he declares the general superiority of the moderns, makes a reservation in regard to poetry and eloquence "for the sake of peace."

But can this argument be applied to poetry and literary art, the battleground that the adversaries, including Perrault himself, cared about most? It might show that the modern era can produce poets and writers just as excellent as the ancient masters, but does it prove that their works must be better? Perrault was aware of this objection, and he responded cleverly. The purpose of poetry and eloquence is to please the human heart, and to do that, we must understand it. Is it easier to uncover the secrets of the human heart than the secrets of nature, or will it take less time? We're continually uncovering new insights into its passions and desires. Just looking at the tragedies of Corneille, you'll find more refined and nuanced reflections on ambition, revenge, and jealousy than in all the books of antiquity. However, at the end of his Parallel, Perrault, while asserting the overall superiority of the moderns, makes a caveat regarding poetry and eloquence "for the sake of peace."

The discussion of Perrault falls far short of embodying a full idea of Progress. Not only is he exclusively concerned with progress in knowledge—though he implies, indeed, without developing, the doctrine that happiness depends on knowledge—but he has no eyes for the future, and no interest in it. He is so impressed with the advance of knowledge in the recent past that he is almost incapable of imagining further progression. "Read the journals of France and England," he says, "and glance at the publications of the Academies of these great kingdoms, and you will be convinced that within the last twenty or thirty years more discoveries have been made in natural science than throughout the period of learned antiquity. I own that I consider myself fortunate to know the happiness we enjoy; it is a great pleasure to survey all the past ages in which I can see the birth and the progress of all things, but nothing which has not received a new increase and lustre in our own times. Our age has, in some sort, arrived at the summit of perfection. And since for some years the rate of the progress is much slower and appears almost insensible—as the days seem to cease lengthening when the solstice is near—it is pleasant to think that probably there are not many things for which we need envy future generations."

The discussion about Perrault doesn't fully capture the whole idea of Progress. He is only focused on progress in knowledge—though he hints at the idea that happiness depends on knowledge without fully exploring it—but he doesn't look to the future or show any interest in it. He's so impressed by how much knowledge has advanced recently that he can hardly imagine what comes next. "Read the journals from France and England," he says, "and look at the publications from the Academies of these great kingdoms, and you will see that in the last twenty or thirty years, there have been more discoveries in natural science than throughout all of learned antiquity. I admit that I feel lucky to experience the happiness we have; it’s amazing to look back at all the past ages and see the birth and progress of everything, but nothing has gained a new level of brilliance in our time. Our era has, in a way, reached the peak of perfection. And since the rate of progress has slowed down significantly in recent years and seems almost unnoticeable—like how days stop getting longer when the solstice is near—it’s nice to think that there aren’t many things we need to envy future generations for."

Indifference to the future, or even a certain scepticism about it, is the note of this passage, and accords with the view that the world has reached its old age. The idea of the progress of knowledge, which Perrault expounds, is still incomplete.

Indifference to the future, or even a bit of skepticism about it, is the tone of this passage, and it matches the belief that the world has entered its old age. The concept of knowledge progressing, which Perrault discusses, is still not fully realized.

3.

3.

Independently of this development in France, the doctrine of degeneration had been attacked, and the comparison of the ancients with the moderns incidentally raised, in England.

Independently of this development in France, the idea of degeneration had been criticized, and the comparison between the ancients and moderns had been raised incidentally in England.

A divine named George Hakewill published in 1627 a folio of six hundred pages to confute "the common error touching Nature's perpetual and universal decay." [Footnote: An Apologie or Declaration of the Power and Providence of God in the Government of the World, consisting in an Examination and Censure of the common Errour, etc. (1627, 1630, 1635).] He and his pedantic book, which breathes the atmosphere of the sixteenth century, are completely forgotten; and though it ran to three editions, it can hardly have attracted the attention of many except theologians. The writer's object is to prove that the power and providence of God in the government of the world are not consistent with the current view that the physical universe, the heavens and the elements, are undergoing a process of decay, and that man is degenerating physically, mentally, and morally. His arguments in general are futile as well as tedious. But he has profited by reading Bodin and Bacon, whose ideas, it would appear, were already agitating theological minds.

A religious scholar named George Hakewill published a 600-page book in 1627 to challenge "the common mistake about Nature's constant and universal decay." [Footnote: An Apologie or Declaration of the Power and Providence of God in the Government of the World, consisting in an Examination and Censure of the common Errour, etc. (1627, 1630, 1635).] He and his pedantic book, which reflects the spirit of the sixteenth century, have been completely forgotten; and although it went through three editions, it likely didn't attract much attention outside of theologians. The author's goal is to demonstrate that God's power and providence in managing the world are not compatible with the prevailing view that the physical universe, the heavens, and the elements are in a state of decay, and that humanity is physically, mentally, and morally declining. His arguments are generally both pointless and tedious. However, he has benefited from reading Bodin and Bacon, whose ideas seem to have been already stirring theological thinkers.

A comparison between the ancients and the moderns arises in a general refutation of the doctrine of decay, as naturally as the question of the stability of the powers of nature arises in a comparison between the ancients and moderns. Hakewill protests against excessive admiration of antiquity, just because it encourages the opinion of the world's decay. He gives his argument a much wider scope than the French controversialists. For him the field of debate includes not only science, arts, and literature, but physical qualities and morals. He seeks to show that mentally and physically there has been no decay, and that the morals of modern Christendom are immensely superior to those of pagan times. There has been social progress, due to Christianity; and there has been an advance in arts and knowledge.

A comparison between the ancients and the moderns naturally leads to a broader challenge against the idea of decline, just like the question of the stability of nature's powers does in such comparisons. Hakewill argues against the excessive reverence for the past, as it fuels the belief in the world's decline. He expands his argument far beyond what the French debaters do. For him, the discussion covers not just science, art, and literature, but also physical traits and ethics. He aims to show that there has been no decline, either mentally or physically, and that the morals of modern Christianity are significantly better than those of pagan times. There has been social progress, thanks to Christianity, along with advancements in art and knowledge.

  Multa dies uariusque labor mutabilis aeui
   Rettulit in melius.
Multa dies uariusque labor mutabilis aeui  
   Rettulit in melius.

Hakewill, like Tassoni, surveys all the arts and sciences, and concludes that the moderns are equal to the ancients in poetry, and in almost all other things excel them. [Footnote: Among modern poets equal to the ancients, Hakewill signalises Sir Philip Sidney, Spenser, Marot, Ronsard, Ariosto, Tasso (Book iii. chap. 8, Section 3).]

Hakewill, similar to Tassoni, looks at all the arts and sciences and concludes that modern artists are on par with ancient ones in poetry, and in nearly every other area, they surpass them. [Footnote: Among modern poets on par with the ancients, Hakewill highlights Sir Philip Sidney, Spenser, Marot, Ronsard, Ariosto, Tasso (Book iii. chap. 8, Section 3).]

One of the arguments which he urges against the theory of degeneration is pragmatic—its paralysing effect on human energy. "The opinion of the world's universal decay quails the hopes and blunts the edge of men's endeavours." And the effort to improve the world, he implies, is a duty we owe to posterity.

One of the arguments he makes against the theory of degeneration is practical—its paralyzing effect on human energy. "The belief in the world's universal decline dampens hopes and dulls the drive of people's efforts." And the drive to make the world better, he suggests, is a responsibility we have to future generations.

"Let not then the vain shadows of the world's fatal decay keep us either from looking backward to the imitation of our noble predecessors or forward in providing for posterity, but as our predecessors worthily provided, for us, so let our posterity bless us in providing for them, it being still as uncertain to us what generations are still to ensue, as it was to our predecessors in their ages."

"Let’s not allow the empty worries of the world's decline to stop us from learning from our great predecessors or planning for future generations. Just as our predecessors wisely prepared for us, let our future generations be grateful for our efforts in preparing for them, since it’s just as uncertain for us what future generations will come, as it was for our predecessors in their time."

We note the suggestion that history may be conceived as a sequence of improvements in civilisation, but we note also that Hakewill here is faced by the obstacle which Christian theology offered to the logical expansion of the idea. It is uncertain what generations are still to ensue. Roger Bacon stood before the same dead wall. Hakewill thinks that he is living in the last age of the world; but how long it shall last is a question which cannot be resolved, "it being one of those secrets which the Almighty hath locked up in the cabinet of His own counsel." Yet he consoles himself and his readers with a consideration which suggests that the end is not yet very near. [Footnote: See Book i. chap. 2, Section 4, p. 24.] "It is agreed upon all sides by Divines that at least two signs forerunning the world's end remain unaccomplished—the subversion of Rome and the conversion of the Jews. And when they shall be accomplished God only knows, as yet in man's judgment there being little appearance of the one or the other."

We acknowledge the idea that history can be seen as a series of advancements in civilization, but we also recognize that Hakewill encounters the challenge presented by Christian theology, which limits the logical growth of this concept. It remains unclear what future generations will emerge. Roger Bacon faced the same impasse. Hakewill believes he is living in the final age of the world; however, how long it will last is a question that cannot be answered, "as it is one of those secrets that the Almighty has kept locked away in His own wisdom." Still, he offers himself and his readers some reassurance, suggesting that the end isn't that imminent. [Footnote: See Book i. chap. 2, Section 4, p. 24.] "It is agreed upon by theologians that at least two signs indicating the world's end have yet to occur—the fall of Rome and the conversion of the Jews. And when these will happen, only God knows, as currently, there seems to be little sign of either."

It was well to be assured that nature is not decaying or man degenerating. But was the doctrine that the end of the world does not "depend upon the law of nature," and that the growth of human civilisation may be cut off at any moment by a fiat of the Deity, less calculated to "quail the hopes and blunt the edge of men's endeavours?" Hakewill asserted with confidence that the universe will be suddenly wrecked by fire. Una dies dabit exitio. Was the prospect of an arrest which might come the day after to-morrow likely to induce men to exert themselves to make provision for posterity?

It was reassuring to know that nature isn't in decline and humanity isn't deteriorating. But was the idea that the end of the world doesn't "depend on the law of nature," and that the progress of human civilization could be suddenly halted by a decree from God, really less likely to "dampen people's hopes and weaken their determination?" Hakewill confidently claimed that the universe would be abruptly destroyed by fire. Una dies dabit exitio. Was the possibility of a halt that could happen the day after tomorrow really going to motivate people to work towards securing a future for generations to come?

The significance of Hakewill lies in the fact that he made the current theory of degeneration, which stood in the way of all possible theories of progress, the object of a special inquiry. And his book illustrates the close connection between that theory and the dispute over the Ancients and Moderns. It cannot be said that he has added anything valuable to what may be found in Bodin and Bacon on the development of civilisation. The general synthesis of history which he attempts is equivalent to theirs. He describes the history of knowledge and arts, and all things besides, as exhibiting "a kind of circular progress," by which he means that they have a birth, growth, nourishing, failing and fading, and then within a while after a resurrection and reflourishing. [Footnote: Book iii. chap. 6, Section i, p. 259.] In this method of progress the lamp of learning passed from one people to another. It passed from the Orientals (Chaldeans and Egyptians) to the Greeks; when it was nearly extinguished in Greece it began to shine afresh among the Romans; and having been put out by the barbarians for the space of a thousand years it was relit by Petrarch and his contemporaries. In stating this view of "circular progress," Hakewill comes perilously near to the doctrine of Ricorsi or Returns which had been severely denounced by Bacon.

The importance of Hakewill lies in the fact that he focused on the current theory of degeneration, which obstructed any potential theories of progress, through a dedicated inquiry. His book demonstrates the strong link between that theory and the debate over the Ancients and Moderns. It's fair to say he hasn't contributed anything particularly valuable beyond what Bodin and Bacon discussed regarding the development of civilization. His overall synthesis of history is on par with theirs. He describes the history of knowledge and the arts, along with everything else, as showing "a kind of circular progress," meaning they go through a process of birth, growth, nurturing, decline, and eventually fading away, followed by a resurgence and flourishing again. [Footnote: Book iii. chap. 6, Section i, p. 259.] In this cycle of progress, the light of learning moved from one civilization to another. It transitioned from the Orientals (Chaldeans and Egyptians) to the Greeks; just as it was about to go out in Greece, it began to shine again among the Romans. After being extinguished by the barbarians for about a thousand years, it was rekindled by Petrarch and his contemporaries. In presenting this idea of "circular progress," Hakewill comes uncomfortably close to the doctrine of Ricorsi or Returns, which Bacon had strongly criticized.

In one point indeed Hakewill goes far beyond Bodin. It was suggested, as we saw, by the French thinker that in some respects the modern age is superior in conduct and morals to antiquity, but he said little on the matter. Hakewill develops the suggestion at great length into a severe and partial impeachment of ancient manners and morals. Unjust and unconvincing though his arguments are, and inspired by theological motives, his thesis nevertheless deserves to be noted as an assertion of the progress of man in social morality. Bacon, and the thinkers of the seventeenth century generally, confined their views of progress in the past to the intellectual field. Hakewill, though he overshot the mark and said nothing actually worth remembering, nevertheless anticipated the larger problem of social progress which was to come to the front in the eighteenth century.

In one sense, Hakewill goes much further than Bodin. As we noted, the French thinker suggested that in some ways, the modern age has better behavior and morals than ancient times, but he didn't elaborate much on this. Hakewill expands on this idea extensively, launching a strong and biased criticism of ancient customs and morals. Although his arguments are unfair and unconvincing, motivated by religious beliefs, his main point is worth noting as it claims that humanity has made progress in social morality. Bacon and other thinkers from the seventeenth century mainly focused on intellectual progress in the past. Hakewill, even though he missed the mark and had little of lasting value to say, still anticipated the broader issue of social progress that would emerge in the eighteenth century.

4.

4.

During the forty years that followed the appearance of Hakewill's book much had happened in the world of ideas, and when we take up Glanvill's Plus ultra, or the Progress and Advancement of Knowledge since the days of Aristotle, [Footnote: The title is evidently suggested by a passage in Bacon quoted above, p. 55.] we breathe a different atmosphere. It was published in 1668, and its purpose was to defend the recently founded Royal Society which was attacked on the ground that it was inimical to the interests of religion and sound learning. For the Aristotelian tradition was still strongly entrenched in the English Church and Universities, notwithstanding the influence of Bacon; and the Royal Society, which realised "the romantic model" of Bacon's society of experimenters, repudiated the scholastic principles and methods associated with Aristotle's name.

During the forty years after Hakewill's book was published, a lot changed in the world of ideas. When we look at Glanvill's Plus ultra, or the Progress and Advancement of Knowledge since the days of Aristotle, [Footnote: The title is evidently suggested by a passage in Bacon quoted above, p. 55.] we find ourselves in a different environment. It was published in 1668, and its goal was to defend the newly established Royal Society, which faced criticism for allegedly being against religion and proper learning. The Aristotelian tradition was still deeply rooted in the English Church and universities, despite Bacon's influence. The Royal Society, which embodied "the romantic model" of Bacon's society of experimenters, rejected the scholastic principles and methods linked to Aristotle.

Glanvill was one of those latitudinarian clergymen, so common in the Anglican Church in the seventeenth century, who were convinced that religious faith must accord with reason, and were unwilling to abate in its favour any of reason's claims. He was under the influence of Bacon, Descartes, and the Cambridge Platonists, and no one was more enthusiastic than he in following the new scientific discoveries of his time. Unfortunately for his reputation he had a weak side. Enlightened though he was, he was a firm believer in witchcraft, and he is chiefly remembered not as an admirer of Descartes and Bacon, and a champion of the Royal Society, but as the author of Saducismus Triumphatus, a monument of superstition, which probably contributed to check the gradual growth of disbelief in witches and apparitions.

Glanvill was one of those open-minded clergymen, quite common in the Anglican Church during the seventeenth century, who believed that religious faith should align with reason and were unwilling to compromise any of reason's principles for the sake of faith. He was influenced by Bacon, Descartes, and the Cambridge Platonists, and no one was more excited than he was about the new scientific discoveries of his time. Unfortunately for his reputation, he had a weak point. Despite his enlightenment, he strongly believed in witchcraft, and he is mainly remembered not as an admirer of Descartes and Bacon, or as a supporter of the Royal Society, but as the author of Saducismus Triumphatus, a testament to superstition that likely helped to slow the gradual decline of belief in witches and apparitions.

His Plus ultra is a review of modern improvements of useful knowledge. It is confined to mathematics and science, in accordance with its purpose of justifying the Royal Society; and the discoveries of the past sixty years enable the author to present a far more imposing picture of modern scientific progress than was possible for Bodin or Bacon. [Footnote: Bacon indeed could have made out a more impressive picture of the new age if he had studied mathematics and taken the pains to master the evidence which was revolutionising astronomy. Glanvill had the advantage of comprehending the importance of mathematics for the advance of physical science.] He had absorbed Bacon's doctrine of utility. His spirit is displayed in the remark that more gratitude is due to the unknown inventor of the mariners' compass

His Plus Ultra is a review of recent advances in useful knowledge. It focuses on math and science, in line with its goal of supporting the Royal Society; the discoveries from the last sixty years allow the author to present a much more impressive view of modern scientific progress than Bodin or Bacon could. [Footnote: Bacon could have painted a more striking picture of the new age if he had studied math and made an effort to understand the evidence that was transforming astronomy. Glanvill had the advantage of recognizing the importance of math for the development of physical science.] He had embraced Bacon's idea of utility. His viewpoint is captured in the statement that more gratitude is owed to the unknown inventor of the mariners' compass.

"than to a thousand Alexanders and Caesars, or to ten times the number of Aristotles. And he really did more for the increase of knowledge and the advantage of the world by this one experiment than the numerous subtile disputers that have lived ever since the erection of the school of talking."

"than to a thousand Alexanders and Caesars, or to ten times the number of Aristotles. And he actually contributed more to the growth of knowledge and the benefit of humanity with this one experiment than all the clever debaters who have existed since the establishment of the school of rhetoric."

Glanvill, however, in his complacency with what has already been accomplished, is not misled into over-estimating its importance. He knows that it is indeed little compared with the ideal of attainable knowledge. The human design, to which it is the function of the Royal Society to contribute, is laid as low, he says, as the profoundest depths of nature, and reaches as high as the uppermost storey of the universe, extends to all the varieties of the great world, and aims at the benefit of universal mankind. Such a work can only proceed slowly, by insensible degrees. It is an undertaking wherein all the generations of men are concerned, and our own age can hope to do little more than to remove useless rubbish, lay in materials, and put things in order for the building. "We must seek and gather, observe and examine, and lay up in bank for the ages that come after."

Glanvill, however, in his satisfaction with what has already been achieved, isn’t fooled into thinking it’s more important than it really is. He knows that it’s actually very little compared to the ideal of knowledge we can achieve. The human goal, which the Royal Society is meant to support, is as deep as the most profound aspects of nature and as high as the highest points of the universe, covering all the varieties of the great world, and aims for the benefit of all humanity. This kind of work can only move forward slowly, in small increments. It’s an effort that involves all generations of people, and our own time can only hope to do a little more than clear away unnecessary obstacles, gather resources, and organize things for the future. "We must seek and gather, observe and examine, and save up for the ages to come."

These lines on "the vastness of the work" suggest to the reader that a vast future will be needed for its accomplishment. Glanvill does not dwell on this, but he implies it. He is evidently unembarrassed by the theological considerations which weighed so heavily on Hakewill. He does not trouble himself with the question whether Anti-Christ has still to appear. The difference in general outlook between these two clergymen is an indication how the world had travelled in the course of forty years.

These lines about "the vastness of the work" suggest to the reader that a long future will be necessary for its completion. Glanvill doesn’t elaborate on this, but he hints at it. He is clearly not bothered by the theological issues that troubled Hakewill. He doesn't concern himself with whether the Anti-Christ has yet to appear. The difference in perspective between these two clergymen shows how much the world has changed over the past forty years.

Another point in Glanvill's little book deserves attention. He takes into his prospect the inhabitants of the Transatlantic world; they, too, are to share in the benefits which shall result from the subjugation of nature.

Another point in Glanvill's little book deserves attention. He considers the people of the Transatlantic world; they, too, will benefit from the dominance over nature.

"By the gaining that mighty continent and the numerous fruitful isles beyond the Atlantic, we have obtained a larger field of nature, and have thereby an advantage for more phenomena, and more helps both for knowledge and for life, which 'tis very like that future ages will make better use of to such purposes than those hitherto have done; and that science also may at last travel into those parts and enrich Peru with a more precious treasure than that of its golden mines, is not improbable."

"By gaining that vast continent and the many fertile islands across the Atlantic, we've created a larger natural playground that gives us more opportunities for discoveries and tools for knowledge and living. It's likely that future generations will use these advantages more wisely than we have so far. It's also possible that science will eventually expand into those areas and provide Peru with a more valuable treasure than its gold mines."

Sprat, the Bishop of Rochester, in his interesting History of the Royal Society, so sensible and liberal—published shortly before Glanvill's book,—also contemplates the extension of science over the world. Speaking of the prospect of future discoveries, he thinks it will partly depend on the enlargement of the field of western civilisation "if this mechanic genius which now prevails in these parts of Christendom shall happen to spread wide amongst ourselves and other civil nations, or if by some good fate it shall pass farther on to other countries that were yet never fully civilised."

Sprat, the Bishop of Rochester, in his engaging History of the Royal Society—published just before Glanvill's book—also considers the global expansion of science. Discussing the potential for future discoveries, he believes it will partly rely on the growth of western civilization: "if this mechanical genius that currently thrives in this part of Christendom spreads widely among us and other civilized nations, or if by some fortunate chance it reaches further into countries that have never been fully civilized."

This then being imagin'd, that there may some lucky tide of civility flow into those lands which are yet salvage, then will a double improvement thence arise both in respect of ourselves and them. For even the present skilful parts of mankind will be thereby made more skilful, and the other will not only increase those arts which we shall bestow upon them, but will also venture on new searches themselves.

This being imagined, if some fortunate wave of civility reaches those still uncivilized lands, it will lead to a double benefit for both us and them. The current skilled practices of humanity will become even more advanced, and those who are less developed will not only adopt the skills we share with them, but they will also begin to explore new ideas and innovations on their own.

He expects much from the new converts, on the ground that nations which have been taught have proved more capable than their teachers, appealing to the case of the Greeks who outdid their eastern masters, and to that of the peoples of modern Europe who received their light from the Romans but have "well nigh doubled the ancient stock of trades delivered to their keeping."

He has high expectations for the new converts, based on the idea that nations that have been educated have often shown to be more capable than their teachers. He points to the example of the Greeks, who surpassed their eastern masters, and to the peoples of modern Europe, who gained their knowledge from the Romans but have "almost doubled the ancient stock of trades entrusted to them."

5.

5.

The establishment of the Royal Society in 1660 and the Academy of Sciences in 1666 made physical science fashionable in London and Paris. Macaulay, in his characteristic way, describes how "dreams of perfect forms of government made way for dreams of wings with which men were to fly from the Tower to the Abbey, and of double-keeled ships which were never to founder in the fiercest storm. All classes were hurried along by the prevailing sentiment. Cavalier and Roundhead, Churchman and Puritan were for once allied. Divines, jurists, statesmen, nobles, princes, swelled the triumph of the Baconian philosophy." The seeds sown by Bacon had at last begun to ripen, and full credit was given to him by those who founded and acclaimed the Royal Society. The ode which Cowley addressed to that institution might have been entitled an ode in honour of Bacon, or still better—for the poet seized the essential point of Bacon's labours—a hymn on the liberation of the human mind from the yoke of Authority.

The founding of the Royal Society in 1660 and the Academy of Sciences in 1666 made physical science trendy in London and Paris. Macaulay, in his typical style, describes how "dreams of perfect forms of government gave way to dreams of wings that would allow people to fly from the Tower to the Abbey, and of double-hulled ships that would never sink in the fiercest storm. All groups were swept along by the prevailing sentiment. Cavaliers and Roundheads, Churchmen and Puritans were, for once, united. Clergymen, legal experts, politicians, nobles, and princes celebrated the triumph of Bacon’s philosophy." The ideas planted by Bacon had finally started to flourish, and full credit was given to him by those who established and praised the Royal Society. The ode that Cowley wrote for that institution could have been titled an ode in honor of Bacon, or even better—since the poet captured the core of Bacon’s work—a hymn celebrating the liberation of the human mind from the constraints of Authority.

  Bacon has broke that scar-crow Deity.
Bacon has destroyed that scarecrow god.

Dryden himself, in the Annus Mirabilis, had turned aside from his subject, the defeat of the Dutch and England's mastery of the seas, to pay a compliment to the Society, and to prophesy man's mastery of the universe.

Dryden himself, in the Annus Mirabilis, had shifted his focus from the defeat of the Dutch and England's dominance of the seas to give a nod to the Society and to predict humanity's control over the universe.

  Instructed ships shall sail to rich commerce,
    By which remotest regions are allied;
   Which makes one city of the universe,
    Where some may gain and all may be supplied.
  Instructed ships will sail to prosperous trade,
    Connecting distant lands together;
   Creating one city for the whole world,
    Where some may profit and everyone is provided for.
  Then we upon our globe's last verge shall go,
    And view the ocean leaning on the sky,
   From thence our rolling neighbours we shall know,
    And on the lunar world securely pry.
  Then we, at the edge of our globe, will go,  
    And see the ocean stretching up to the sky,  
   From there, we'll know our neighboring planets,  
    And safely observe the lunar world.  

[Footnote: It may be noted that John Wilkins (Bishop of Chester) published in 1638 a little book entitled Discovery of a New World, arguing that the moon is inhabited. A further edition appeared in 1684. He attempted to compose a universal language (Sprat, Hist. of Royal Society, p. 251). His Mercury or the Secret and Swift Messenger (1641) contains proposals for a universal script (chap. 13). There is also an ingenious suggestion for the communication of messages by sound, which might be described as an anticipation of the Morse code. Wilkins and another divine, Seth Ward, the Bishop of Salisbury, belonged to the group of men who founded the Royal Society.]

[Footnote: It’s worth noting that John Wilkins (Bishop of Chester) published a small book in 1638 called Discovery of a New World, where he argued that the moon is inhabited. A new edition was released in 1684. He also tried to create a universal language (Sprat, Hist. of Royal Society, p. 251). His book Mercury or the Secret and Swift Messenger (1641) includes proposals for a universal script (chap. 13). Additionally, there’s an interesting idea for sending messages using sound, which could be seen as an early version of Morse code. Wilkins and another clergyman, Seth Ward, the Bishop of Salisbury, were part of the group that founded the Royal Society.]

Men did not look far into the future; they did not dream of what the world might be a thousand or ten thousand years hence. They seem to have expected quick results. Even Sprat thinks that "the absolute perfection of the true philosophy" is not far off, seeing that "this first great and necessary preparation for its coming"—the institution of scientific co-operation—has been accomplished. Superficial and transient though the popular enthusiasm was, it was a sign that an age of intellectual optimism had begun, in which the science of nature would play a leading role.

Men didn't look too far ahead; they didn't imagine what the world might be like a thousand or ten thousand years from now. They seemed to expect immediate results. Even Sprat believes that "the absolute perfection of the true philosophy" is close at hand, given that "this first great and necessary preparation for its coming"—the establishment of scientific collaboration—has been achieved. Although the popular enthusiasm was shallow and temporary, it signified the start of an era of intellectual optimism, where the science of nature would take center stage.





CHAPTER V. THE PROGRESS OF KNOWLEDGE: FONTENELLE

1.

Nine months before the first part of Perrault's work appeared a younger and more brilliant man had formulated, in a short tract, the essential points of the doctrine of the progress of knowledge. It was Fontenelle.

Nine months before the first part of Perrault's work was published, a younger and more brilliant man had laid out the key ideas of the theory of knowledge advancement in a brief pamphlet. That man was Fontenelle.

Fontenelle was an anima naturaliter moderna. Trained in the principles of Descartes, he was one of those who, though like Descartes himself, too critical to swear by a master, appreciated unreservedly the value of the Cartesian method. Sometimes, he says, a great man gives the tone to his age; and this is true of Descartes, who can claim the glory of having established a new art of reasoning. He sees the effects in literature. The best books on moral and political subjects are distinguished by an arrangement and precision which he traces to the esprit geometrique characteristic of Descartes. [Footnote: Sur l'utilite des mathematiques el de la physique (Oeuvres, iii. p. 6, ed. 1729).] Fontenelle himself had this "geometrical mind," which we see at its best in Descartes and Hobbes and Spinoza.

Fontenelle was a naturally modern thinker. Educated in the principles of Descartes, he was one of those who, like Descartes himself, was too critical to follow a single master but fully appreciated the value of the Cartesian method. He noted that sometimes a great man sets the tone for his time; this is true of Descartes, who can take credit for establishing a new way of reasoning. He observed the effects on literature. The best books on moral and political topics are marked by an organization and clarity that he attributes to the geometrical spirit characteristic of Descartes. [Footnote: Sur l'utilite des mathematiques et de la physique (Oeuvres, iii. p. 6, ed. 1729).] Fontenelle himself possessed this "geometrical mind," which we see exemplified in Descartes, Hobbes, and Spinoza.

He had indeed a considerable aptitude for letters. He wrote poor verses, and could not distinguish good poetry from bad. That perhaps was the defect of l'esprit geometrique. But he wrote lucid prose. There was an ironical side to his temper, and he had an ingenious paradoxical wit, which he indulged, with no little felicity, in his early work, Dialogues of the Dead. These conversations, though they show no dramatic power and are simply a vehicle for the author's satirical criticisms on life, are written with a light touch, and are full of surprises and unexpected turns. The very choice of the interlocutors shows a curious fancy, which we do not associate with the geometrical intellect. Descartes is confronted with the Third False Demetrius, and we wonder what the gourmet Apicius will find to say to Galileo.

He definitely had a strong talent for writing. He wrote mediocre poetry and couldn’t tell good poetry from bad. That might have been the flaw of his analytical mind. However, he crafted clear prose. There was an ironic side to his personality, and he had a clever, paradoxical wit, which he skillfully displayed in his early work, Dialogues of the Dead. These conversations, although lacking dramatic strength and serving mainly as a platform for the author's satirical critiques of life, are written lightly and are full of surprises and unexpected twists. The choice of dialogue partners reflects an interesting whimsy that we don’t typically associate with a logical mind. Descartes is paired with the Third False Demetrius, and we’re curious about what the gourmet Apicius will have to say to Galileo.

2.

2.

In the Dialogues of the Dead, which appeared in 1683, the Ancient and Modern controversy is touched on more than once, and it is the subject of the conversation between Socrates and Montaigne. Socrates ironically professes to expect that the age of Montaigne will show a vast improvement on his own; that men will have profited by the experience of many centuries; and that the old age of the world will be wiser and better regulated than its youth. Montaigne assures him that it is not so, and that the vigorous types of antiquity, like Pericles, Aristides, and Socrates himself, are no longer to be found. To this assertion Socrates opposes the doctrine of the permanence of the forces of Nature. Nature has not degenerated in her other works; why should she cease to produce reasonable men?

In the Dialogues of the Dead, which came out in 1683, the debate between the Ancient and Modern worlds is mentioned more than once, particularly during the conversation between Socrates and Montaigne. Socrates ironically claims that Montaigne's era should show a significant improvement over his own; that people would have learned from centuries of experience; and that the world's old age would be wiser and better organized than its youth. Montaigne counters that this isn't the case, and that the strong figures of the past, like Pericles, Aristides, and Socrates himself, are no longer around. In response, Socrates argues for the idea that the forces of Nature are enduring. Nature hasn’t deteriorated in her other creations; so why wouldn’t she continue to produce rational people?

He goes on to observe that antiquity is enlarged and exalted by distance: "In our own day we esteemed our ancestors more than they deserved, and now our posterity esteems us more than we deserve. There is really no difference between our ancestors, ourselves, and our posterity. C'est toujours la meme chose." But, objects Montaigne, I should have thought that things were always changing; that different ages had their different characters. Are there not ages of learning and ages of ignorance, rude ages and polite? True, replies Socrates, but these are only externalities. The heart of man does not change with the fashions of his life. The order of Nature remains constant (l'ordre general de la Nature a l'air bien constant).

He notes that the past seems greater when viewed from a distance: "In our time, we think more highly of our ancestors than they deserve, and now future generations think more highly of us than we deserve. There’s really no difference between our ancestors, ourselves, and our descendants. It’s always the same.” But, Montaigne argues, I would have thought that things are always changing; that different eras have their own characteristics. Aren’t there eras of learning and eras of ignorance, rough times and refined ones? True, Socrates replies, but those are just surface-level differences. The core of humanity doesn’t change with the trends of life. The natural order stays consistent (l'ordre general de la Nature a l'air bien constant).

This conclusion harmonises with the general spirit of the Dialogues. The permanence of the forces of Nature is asserted, but for the purpose of dismissing the whole controversy as rather futile. Elsewhere modern discoveries, like the circulation of the blood and the motions of the earth, are criticised as useless; adding nothing to the happiness and pleasures of mankind. Men acquired, at an early period, a certain amount of useful knowledge, to which they have added nothing; since then they have been slowly discovering things that are unnecessary. Nature has not been so unjust as to allow one age to enjoy more pleasures than another. And what is the value of civilisation? It moulds our words, and embarrasses our actions; it does not affect our feelings. [Footnote: See the dialogues of Harvey with Erasistratus (a Greek physician of the third century B.C.); Galileo with Apicius; Montezuma with Fernando Cortez.]

This conclusion aligns with the overall message of the Dialogues. It asserts that the forces of Nature are constant but suggests that the entire debate is fairly pointless. In other parts, modern discoveries like blood circulation and the movements of the Earth are criticized as insignificant, contributing nothing to human happiness or enjoyment. Early on, people gained a certain amount of practical knowledge, but they haven’t added much to it since then; instead, they have gradually uncovered things that are unnecessary. Nature has not been unfair enough to let one era experience more pleasures than another. And what is the worth of civilization? It shapes our language and complicates our actions, but it doesn't change our feelings. [Footnote: See the dialogues of Harvey with Erasistratus (a Greek physician of the third century B.C.); Galileo with Apicius; Montezuma with Fernando Cortez.]

One might hardly have expected the author of these Dialogues to come forward a few years later as a champion of the Moderns, even though, in the dedicatory epistle to Lucian, he compared France to Greece. But he was seriously interested in the debated question, as an intellectual problem, and in January 1688 he published his Digression on the Ancients and Moderns, a short pamphlet, but weightier and more suggestive than the large work of his friend Perrault, which began to appear nine months later.

One might not have anticipated that the author of these Dialogues would later emerge as a supporter of the Moderns, even though in the dedicatory letter to Lucian, he likened France to Greece. However, he was genuinely engaged in the ongoing debate as an intellectual challenge, and in January 1688, he published his Digression on the Ancients and Moderns, a brief pamphlet, but more substantial and thought-provoking than the lengthy work of his friend Perrault, which started to come out nine months later.

3.

3.

The question of pre-eminence between the Ancients and Moderns is reducible to another. Were trees in ancient times greater than to-day? If they were, then Homer, Plato, and Demosthenes cannot be equalled in modern times; if they were not, they can.

The issue of whether the Ancients or Moderns are superior comes down to another question. Were trees in ancient times taller than they are today? If they were, then Homer, Plato, and Demosthenes cannot be matched in modern times; if they were not, then they can be.

Fontenelle states the problem in this succinct way at the beginning of the Digression. The permanence of the forces of Nature had been asserted by Saint Sorlin and Perrault; they had offered no proof, and had used the principle rather incidentally and by way of illustration. But the whole inquiry hinged on it. If it can be shown that man has not degenerated, the cause of the Moderns is practically won. The issue of the controversy must be decided not by rhetoric but by physics. And Fontenelle offers what he regards as a formal Cartesian proof of the permanence of natural forces.

Fontenelle presents the issue clearly at the start of the Digression. Saint Sorlin and Perrault claimed that the forces of Nature are constant; however, they provided no evidence and only mentioned the principle casually as an example. Yet, the entire investigation depended on this claim. If it's demonstrated that humanity hasn't declined, the case for the Moderns is almost secured. The debate should be settled based on facts, not persuasive language. Fontenelle then provides what he believes is a formal Cartesian proof of the constancy of natural forces.

If the Ancients had better intellects than ours, the brains of that age must have been better arranged, formed of firmer or more delicate fibres, fuller of "animal spirits." But if such a difference existed, Nature must have been more vigorous; and in that case the trees must have profited by that superior vigour and have been larger and finer. The truth is that Nature has in her hands a certain paste which is always the same, which she is ever turning over and over again in a thousand ways, and of which she forms men, animals, and plants. She has not formed Homer, Demosthenes, and Plato of a finer or better kneaded clay than our poets, orators, and philosophers. Do not object that minds are not material. They are connected by a material bond with the brain, and it is the quality of this material bond that determines intellectual differences.

If the Ancients had more intelligence than we do, their brains must have been better organized, made up of stronger or more delicate fibers, and fuller of "animal spirits." But if such a difference existed, Nature must have been more robust, which means the trees had to have benefited from that superior strength and been bigger and better. The truth is that Nature has a certain substance that is always the same, which she constantly reshapes in a thousand ways to create humans, animals, and plants. She didn’t create Homer, Demosthenes, and Plato from finer or better-mixed clay than our own poets, speakers, and thinkers. Don’t argue that minds aren’t material. They are linked by a physical connection to the brain, and it’s the quality of this connection that determines intellectual differences.

But although natural processes do not change from age to age, they differ in their effects in different climates. "It is certain that as a result of the reciprocal dependence which exists between all parts of the material world, differences of climate, which so clearly affect the life of plants, must also produce some effect on human brains." May it not be said then that, in consequence of climatic conditions, ancient Greece and Rome produced men of mental qualities different from those which could be produced in France? Oranges grow easily in Italy; it is more difficult to cultivate them in France. Fontenelle replies that art and cultivation exert a much greater influence on human brains than on the soil; ideas can be transported more easily from one country to another than plants; and as a consequence of commerce and mutual influence, peoples do not retain the original mental peculiarities due to climate. This may not be true of the extreme climates in the torrid and glacial zones, but in the temperate zone we may discount entirely climatic influence. The climates of Greece and Italy and that of France are too similar to cause any sensible difference between the Greeks or Latins and the French.

But even though natural processes remain consistent over time, their effects vary in different climates. "It's clear that the interconnectedness of all aspects of the material world means that climate differences, which significantly impact plant life, must also have an effect on human brains." Can we then say that, because of climatic conditions, ancient Greece and Rome produced individuals with mental qualities different from those developed in France? Oranges grow easily in Italy, but they're harder to cultivate in France. Fontenelle argues that art and cultivation have a much stronger impact on human intellect than the soil does; ideas can be shared between countries more easily than plants can be. As a result of trade and mutual influence, cultures don't maintain the original mental traits tied to their climate. This might not apply to extreme climates in tropical and polar regions, but in temperate zones, we can largely disregard climatic influence. The climates of Greece, Italy, and France are too similar to create any noticeable differences between the Greeks or Latins and the French.

Saint Sorlin and Perrault had argued directly from the permanence of vigour in lions or trees to the permanence of vigour in man. If trees are the same as ever, brains must also be the same. But what about the minor premiss? Who knows that trees are precisely the same? It is an indemonstrable assumption that oaks and beeches in the days of Socrates and Cicero were not slightly better trees than the oaks and beeches of to-day. Fontenelle saw the weakness of this reasoning. He saw that it was necessary to prove that the trees, no less than human brains, have not degenerated. But his a priori proof is simply a statement of the Cartesian principle of the stability of natural processes, which he put in a thoroughly unscientific form. The stability of the laws of nature is a necessary hypothesis, without which science would be impossible. But here it was put to an illegitimate use. For it means that, given precisely the same conditions, the same physical phenomena will occur. Fontenelle therefore was bound to show that conditions had not altered in such a way as to cause changes in the quality of nature's organic productions. He did not do this. He did not take into consideration, for instance, that climatic conditions may vary from age to age as well as from country to country.

Saint Sorlin and Perrault argued that since lions and trees remain vigorous over time, human vigor must also stay the same. If trees haven’t changed, then our brains must be unchanged too. But what about the minor premise? Who can say that trees are exactly the same? It’s an unprovable assumption that oaks and beeches in the days of Socrates and Cicero weren’t slightly better than the ones today. Fontenelle recognized the flaw in this reasoning. He understood that it was essential to prove that trees, just like human brains, haven’t declined. However, his a priori proof is merely a reiteration of the Cartesian principle of the stability of natural processes, which he presented in a completely unscientific way. The stability of the laws of nature is a necessary assumption; without it, science wouldn't be possible. But here it was misused, as it implies that under identical conditions, the same physical phenomena will happen. Therefore, Fontenelle needed to demonstrate that conditions hadn’t changed in a manner that could affect the quality of nature's organic products. He failed to do this. For example, he didn’t consider that climatic conditions can vary from era to era and from one country to another.

4.

4.

Having established the natural equality of the Ancients and Moderns, Fontenelle inferred that whatever differences exist are due to external conditions—(1) time; (2) political institutions and the estate of affairs in general.

Having established the natural equality of the Ancients and Moderns, Fontenelle concluded that any differences that exist are due to external factors—(1) time; (2) political institutions and the overall state of affairs.

The ancients were prior in time to us, therefore they were the authors of the first inventions. For that, they cannot be regarded as our superiors. If we had been in their place we should have been the inventors, like them; if they were in ours, they would add to those inventions, like us. There is no great mystery in that. We must impute equal merit to the early thinkers who showed the way and to the later thinkers who pursued it. If the ancient attempts to explain the universe have been recently replaced by the discovery of a simple system (the Cartesian), we must consider that the truth could only be reached by the elimination of false routes, and in this way the numbers of the Pythagoreans, the ideas of Plato, the qualities of Aristotle, all served indirectly to advance knowledge. "We are under an obligation to the ancients for having exhausted almost all the false theories that could be formed." Enlightened both by their true views and by their errors, it is not surprising that we should surpass them.

The ancients existed before us, so they were the ones who came up with the first inventions. Because of this, we can't see them as our superiors. If we were in their position, we would have been the inventors, just like they were; and if they were in ours, they would contribute to those inventions, like we do. There isn't a big mystery in that. We should give equal credit to the early thinkers who paved the way and to the later ones who continued it. If the ancient attempts to explain the universe have recently been replaced by a simpler system (the Cartesian), we need to recognize that the truth could only be reached by eliminating false paths, and in this way, the numbers of the Pythagoreans, the ideas of Plato, and the qualities of Aristotle all helped indirectly to advance knowledge. "We owe a debt to the ancients for having explored almost all the false theories that could be developed." Enlightened by both their true ideas and their mistakes, it's not surprising that we surpass them.

But all this applies only to scientific studies, like mathematics, physics, and medicine, which depend partly on correct reasoning and partly on experience. Methods of reasoning improve slowly, and the most important advance which has been made in the present age is the method inaugurated by Descartes. Before him reasoning was loose; he introduced a more rigid and precise standard, and its influence is not only manifest in our best works on physics and philosophy, but is even discernible in books on ethics and religion.

But all this only applies to scientific studies like math, physics, and medicine, which rely partly on sound reasoning and partly on experience. Methods of reasoning evolve gradually, and the biggest advancement in our time is the method introduced by Descartes. Before him, reasoning was informal; he brought in a stricter and more precise standard, and its impact is evident not just in our best works on physics and philosophy, but even noticeable in books on ethics and religion.

We must expect posterity to excel us as we excel the Ancients, through improvement of method, which is a science in itself—the most difficult and least studied of all—and through increase of experience. Evidently the process is endless (il est evident que tout cela n'a point de fin), and the latest men of science must be the most competent.

We should expect future generations to surpass us just as we surpass the Ancients, thanks to advancements in methodology, which is a science in its own right—one of the hardest and least explored of all—and through a greater pool of experience. Clearly, this process has no limit (il est evident que tout cela n'a point de fin), and the most recent scientists should be the most skilled.

But this does not apply to poetry or eloquence, round which the controversy has most violently raged. For poetry and eloquence do not depend on correct reasoning. They depend principally on vivacity of imagination, and "vivacity of imagination does not require a long course of experiments, or a great multitude of rules, to attain all the perfection of which it is capable." Such perfection might be attained in a few centuries. If the ancients did achieve perfection in imaginative literature, it follows that they cannot be surpassed; but we have no right to say, as their admirers are fond of pretending, that they cannot be equalled.

But this doesn’t apply to poetry or eloquence, which are the topics that have sparked the most intense debate. Poetry and eloquence aren’t based on correct reasoning. They mainly rely on the liveliness of imagination, and "liveliness of imagination doesn’t need a long series of experiments or a huge number of rules to reach all the perfection it can." Such perfection could be achieved in a few centuries. If the ancients did reach perfection in imaginative literature, it means they can’t be surpassed; but we shouldn’t claim, as their fans often do, that they can’t be equaled.

5.

5.

Besides the mere nature of time, we have to take into account external circumstances in considering this question.

Besides the basic nature of time, we also need to consider outside factors when thinking about this question.

If the forces of nature are permanent, how are we to explain the fact that in the barbarous centuries after the decline of Rome—the term Middle Ages has not yet come into currency—ignorance was so dense and deep? This breach of continuity is one of the plausible arguments of the advocates of the Ancients. Those ages, they say, were ignorant and barbarous because the Greek and Latin writers had ceased to be read; as soon as the study of the classical models revived there was a renaissance of reason and good taste. That is true, but it proves nothing. Nature never forgot how to mould the head of Cicero or Livy. She produces in every age men who might be great men; but the age does not always allow them to exert their talents. Inundations of barbarians, universal wars, governments which discourage or do not favour science and art, prejudices which assume all variety of shapes—like the Chinese prejudice against dissecting corpses—may impose long periods of ignorance or bad taste.

If the forces of nature are constant, how can we explain the fact that during the brutal centuries following the fall of Rome—the term Middle Ages hasn’t even been established—ignorance was incredibly widespread? This gap in continuity is one of the convincing arguments made by supporters of the Ancients. They argue that those times were ignorant and savage because the works of Greek and Latin writers were no longer read; as soon as people started studying classical models again, there was a revival of reason and good taste. That’s true, but it doesn’t prove anything. Nature never forgot how to shape the minds of great thinkers like Cicero or Livy. It produces individuals in every era who could be exceptional; however, the times don’t always allow them to showcase their abilities. Waves of barbarians, widespread wars, governments that discourage or don’t support science and art, and prejudices that take on various forms—like the Chinese aversion to dissecting corpses—can lead to long stretches of ignorance or poor taste.

But observe that, though the return to the study of the ancients revived, as at one stroke, the aesthetic ideals which they had created and the learning which they had accumulated, yet even if their works had not been preserved we should, though it would have cost us many long years of labour, have discovered for ourselves "ideas of the true and the beautiful." Where should we have found them? Where the ancients themselves found them, after much groping.

But notice that, although the revival of studying the ancients suddenly brought back the aesthetic ideals they created and the knowledge they accumulated, even if their works hadn’t been preserved, we still would have ultimately discovered "ideas of the true and the beautiful" after many long years of effort. Where would we have found them? Where the ancients themselves found them, after a lot of searching.

6.

6.

The comparison of the life of collective humanity to the life of a single man, which had been drawn by Bacon and Pascal, Saint Sorlin and Perrault, contains or illustrates an important truth which bears on the whole question. Fontenelle puts it thus. An educated mind is, as it were, composed of all the minds of preceding ages; we might say that a single mind was being educated throughout all history. Thus this secular man, who has lived since the beginning of the world, has had his infancy in which he was absorbed by the most urgent needs of life; his youth in which he succeeded pretty well in things of imagination like poetry and eloquence, and even began to reason, but with more courage than solidity. He is now in the age of manhood, is more enlightened, and reasons better; but he would have advanced further if the passion for war had not distracted him and given him a distaste for the sciences to which he has at last returned.

The comparison between the collective experience of humanity and that of an individual, made by thinkers like Bacon and Pascal, Saint Sorlin and Perrault, highlights an important truth relevant to the entire discussion. Fontenelle expresses it this way: an educated mind is, in a sense, made up of all the thoughts from earlier generations; we could say that a single mind has been educated throughout all of history. This secular person, who has existed since the dawn of time, went through a childhood focused on the basic necessities of life; a youth where they excelled in imaginative pursuits like poetry and oratory, and even started to reason, though often with more enthusiasm than depth. Now, they are in the stage of adulthood, more enlightened and reasoning better; however, they could have progressed even more if the obsession with war hadn’t drawn their attention away and caused them to lose interest in the sciences, which they have finally come back to.

Figures, if they are pressed, are dangerous; they suggest unwarrantable conclusions. It may be illuminative to liken the development of humanity to the growth of an individual; but to infer that the human race is now in its old age, merely on the strength of the comparison, is obviously unjustifiable. That is what Bacon and the others had done. The fallacy was pointed out by Fontenelle.

Figures, when pushed too far, can be misleading; they imply conclusions that aren't justified. It might be insightful to compare the progress of humanity to the growth of a person; however, concluding that the human race is now in its old age based solely on that comparison is clearly unfounded. That's exactly what Bacon and others did. Fontenelle pointed out this fallacy.

From his point of view, an "old age" of humanity, which if it meant anything meant decay as well as the wisdom of experience, was contrary to the principle of the permanence of natural forces. Man, he asserts, will have no old age. He will be always equally capable, of achieving the successes of his youth; and he will become more and more expert in the things which become the age of virility. Or "to drop metaphor, men will never degenerate." In ages to come we may be regarded—say in America—with the same excess of admiration with which we regard the ancients. We might push the prediction further. In still later ages the interval of time which divides us from the Greeks and Romans will appear so relatively small to posterity that they will classify us and the ancients as virtually contemporary; just in the same way as we group together the Greeks and Romans, though the Romans in their own day were moderns in relation to the Greeks. In that remote period men will be able to judge without prejudice the comparative merits of Sophocles and Corneille.

From his perspective, an "old age" for humanity, which would imply both decline and the wisdom that comes with experience, contradicts the idea that natural forces are permanent. He claims that humans will never age. They will always have the same ability to achieve the successes of their youth, and they will continue to become more skilled in the things that mark the prime of life. Or to put it plainly, people will never degenerate. In the future, we may be viewed—say in America—with the same overwhelming admiration we have for the ancients. We could even take this prediction further. In even later times, the gap between us and the Greeks and Romans will seem so relatively small to future generations that they will consider us and the ancients as almost contemporary; just as we group together the Greeks and Romans, even though the Romans were modern in their own time compared to the Greeks. In that distant future, people will be able to assess without bias the relative merits of Sophocles and Corneille.

Unreasonable admiration for the ancients is one of the chief obstacles to progress (le progres des choses). Philosophy not only did not advance, but even fell into an abyss of unintelligible ideas, because, through devotion to the authority of Aristotle, men sought truth in his enigmatic writings instead of seeking it in nature. If the authority of Descartes were ever to have the same fortune, the results would be no less disastrous.

Unreasonable admiration for the ancients is one of the main barriers to progress. Philosophy didn’t just stagnate; it even plunged into a pit of confusing ideas because, out of devotion to Aristotle’s authority, people looked for truth in his puzzling writings rather than in nature. If Descartes’ authority were ever to suffer the same fate, the outcomes would be equally disastrous.

7.

7.

This memorable brochure exhibits, without pedantry, perspicuous arrangement and the "geometrical" precision on which Fontenelle remarked as one of the notes of the new epoch introduced by Descartes. It displays too the author's open-mindedness, and his readiness to follow where the argument leads. He is able already to look beyond Cartesianism; he knows that it cannot be final. No man of his time was more open-minded and free from prejudice than Fontenelle. This quality of mind helped him to turn his eyes to the future. Perrault and his predecessors were absorbed in the interest of the present and the past. Descartes was too much engaged in his own original discoveries to do more than throw a passing glance at posterity.

This notable brochure showcases, without being overly formal, a clear layout and the "geometrical" accuracy that Fontenelle noted as a hallmark of the new era brought in by Descartes. It also reflects the author's open-mindedness and willingness to follow the argument wherever it goes. He is already able to see beyond Cartesianism; he understands that it can't be the final word. No one among his contemporaries was more open-minded and free from bias than Fontenelle. This trait allowed him to look toward the future. Perrault and his predecessors were focused on the concerns of the present and the past. Descartes was too immersed in his own original discoveries to do more than give a brief nod to future generations.

Now the prospect of the future was one of the two elements which were still needed to fashion the theory of the progress of knowledge. All the conditions for such a theory were present. Bodin and Bacon, Descartes and the champions of the Moderns—the reaction against the Renaissance, and the startling discoveries of science—had prepared the way; progress was established for the past and present. But the theory of the progress of knowledge includes and acquires its value by including the indefinite future. This step was taken by Fontenelle. The idea had been almost excluded by Bacon's misleading metaphor of old age, which Fontenelle expressly rejects. Man will have no old age; his intellect will never degenerate; and "the sound views of intellectual men in successive generations will continually add up."

Now the outlook for the future was one of the two key elements still needed to shape the theory of knowledge progress. All the conditions for this theory were in place. Bodin and Bacon, Descartes and the advocates of the Moderns—the response to the Renaissance, and the groundbreaking scientific discoveries—had paved the way; progress was established in both the past and present. However, the theory of knowledge progress gains its significance by encompassing the endless future. This was a step taken by Fontenelle. The idea had been nearly eliminated by Bacon's misleading metaphor of old age, which Fontenelle explicitly rejects. Humanity will not experience old age; our intellect will never decline; and "the sound views of intellectual people in successive generations will continually accumulate."

But progress must not only be conceived as extending indefinitely into the future; it must also be conceived as necessary and certain. This is the second essential feature of the theory. The theory would have little value or significance, if the prospect of progress in the future depended on chance or the unpredictable discretion of an external will. Fontenelle asserts implicitly the certainty of progress when he declares that the discoveries and improvements of the modern age would have been made by the ancients if they exchanged places with the moderns; for this amounts to saying that science will progress and knowledge increase independently of particular individuals. If Descartes had not been born, some one else would have done his work; and there could have been no Descartes before the seventeenth century. For, as he says in a later work, [Footnote: Preface des elemens de la geometrie de l'infini (OEuvres, x. p. 40, ed. 1790).] "there is an order which regulates our progress. Every science develops after a certain number of preceding sciences have developed, and only then; it has to await its turn to burst its shell."

But progress shouldn’t just be seen as going on forever into the future; it should also be seen as necessary and certain. This is the second crucial aspect of the theory. The theory wouldn’t hold much value or meaning if the chance of progress in the future relied on luck or the unpredictable choices of an external force. Fontenelle implicitly suggests the certainty of progress when he states that the discoveries and improvements of the modern age would have been achieved by the ancients if they had swapped places with the moderns; this means that science will advance and knowledge will grow regardless of individual contributions. If Descartes hadn’t been born, someone else would have taken his place; and there couldn’t have been a Descartes before the seventeenth century. As he later states, [Footnote: Preface des elemens de la geometrie de l'infini (OEuvres, x. p. 40, ed. 1790).] "there is an order that governs our progress. Every science develops after a certain number of prior sciences have developed, and only then; it has to wait its turn to break free."

Fontenelle, then, was the first to formulate the idea of the progress, of knowledge, as a complete doctrine. At the moment the import and far-reaching effects of the idea were not realised, either by himself or by others, and his pamphlet, which appeared in the company of a perverse theory of pastoral poetry, was acclaimed merely as an able defence of the Moderns.

Fontenelle was the first to articulate the concept of the progress of knowledge as a complete theory. At that time, neither he nor others fully understood the significance and profound impact of this idea, and his pamphlet, which was published alongside a misguided theory of pastoral poetry, was only praised as a strong defense of the Moderns.

8.

8.

If the theory of the indefinite progress of knowledge is true, it is one of those truths which were originally established by false reasoning. It was established on a principle which excluded degeneration, but equally excluded evolution; and the whole conception of nature which Fontenelle had learned from Descartes is long since dead and buried.

If the theory of endless advancements in knowledge is correct, it's one of those truths that was initially founded on flawed reasoning. It was based on a principle that ruled out decline, but also ruled out development; and the entire idea of nature that Fontenelle learned from Descartes is long gone and forgotten.

But it is more important to observe that this principle, which seemed to secure the indefinite progress of knowledge, disabled Fontenelle from suggesting a theory of the progress of society. The invariability of nature, as he conceived it, was true of the emotions and the will, as well as of the intellect. It implied that man himself would be psychically always the same—unalterable, incurable. L'ordre general de la Nature a Fair bien constant. His opinion of the human race was expressed in the Dialogues of the Dead, [Footnote: It may be seen too in the Plurality of Worlds.] and it never seems to have varied. The world consists of a multitude of fools, and a mere handful of reasonable men. Men's passions will always be the same and will produce wars in the future as in the past. Civilisation makes no difference; it is little more than a veneer.

But it’s more important to note that this principle, which seemed to guarantee endless progress in knowledge, prevented Fontenelle from proposing a theory about the progress of society. The unchanging nature, as he saw it, applied to emotions and will, as well as to intellect. It suggested that humanity would always remain the same on a psychological level—unchangeable and incurable. L'ordre general de la Nature a Fair bien constant. His views on humanity were expressed in the Dialogues of the Dead, [Footnote: It may be seen too in the Plurality of Worlds.] and they never seemed to change. The world is full of fools, with only a few reasonable people. Human passions will always remain the same and will lead to wars in the future just as they have in the past. Civilization doesn’t make a difference; it’s barely more than a superficial layer.

Even if theory had not stood in his way, Fontenelle was the last man who was likely to dream dreams of social improvement. He was temperamentally an Epicurean, of the same refined stamp as Epicurus himself, and he enjoyed throughout his long life—he lived to the age of a hundred—the tranquillity which was the true Epicurean ideal. He was never troubled by domestic cares, and his own modest ambition was satisfied when, at the age of forty, he was appointed permanent Secretary of the Academy of Sciences. He was not the man to let his mind dwell on the woes and evils of the world; and the follies and perversities which cause them interested him only so far as they provided material for his wit.

Even if theory hadn’t gotten in his way, Fontenelle was the last person who would dream of making society better. He had an Epicurean temperament, the same sophisticated nature as Epicurus himself, and he enjoyed throughout his long life—he lived to be a hundred—the peace that was the true Epicurean ideal. He was never burdened by family troubles, and his modest ambition was fulfilled when, at the age of forty, he was made permanent Secretary of the Academy of Sciences. He wasn’t the type to dwell on the problems and injustices of the world; the foolishness and wrongdoings that caused them only interested him to the extent that they gave him material for his humor.

It remains, however, noteworthy that the author of the theory of the progress of knowledge, which was afterwards to expand into a general theory of human Progress, would not have allowed that this extension was legitimate; though it was through this extension that Fontenelle's idea acquired human value and interest and became a force in the world.

It is important to note that the creator of the theory of knowledge advancement, which later developed into a broad theory of human progress, would not have considered this expansion legitimate; however, it was through this expansion that Fontenelle's idea gained human significance and appeal, becoming a powerful influence in the world.

9.

9.

Fontenelle did a good deal more than formulate the idea. He reinforced it by showing that the prospect of a steady and rapid increase of knowledge in the future was certified.

Fontenelle did a lot more than just come up with the idea. He backed it up by demonstrating that the promise of a consistent and fast growth of knowledge in the future was guaranteed.

The postulate of the immutability of the laws of nature, which has been the indispensable basis for the advance of modern science, is fundamental with Descartes. But Descartes did not explicitly insist on it, and it was Fontenelle, perhaps more than any one else, who made it current coin. That was a service performed by the disciple; but he seems to have been original in introducing the fruitful idea of the sciences as confederate and intimately interconnected [Footnote: Roger Bacon, as we saw, had a glimpse of this principle.]; not forming a number of isolated domains, as hitherto, but constituting a system in which the advance of one will contribute to the advance of the others. He exposed with masterly ability the reciprocal relations of physics and mathematics. No man of his day had a more comprehensive view of all the sciences, though he made no original contributions to any. His curiosity was universal, and as Secretary of the Academy he was obliged, according to his own high standard of his duty, to keep abreast of all that was being done in every branch of knowledge. That was possible then; it would be impossible now.

The idea that the laws of nature don’t change, which has been essential for the progress of modern science, is fundamental to Descartes. However, Descartes didn’t emphasize it explicitly, and it was Fontenelle, perhaps more than anyone else, who popularized it. This was a service carried out by the disciple; but he also introduced the important notion of sciences being connected and intertwined [Footnote: Roger Bacon, as we saw, had a glimpse of this principle.]; instead of being separate fields, they form a system where progress in one helps advance the others. He skillfully demonstrated the interconnections between physics and mathematics. No one in his time had a broader understanding of all the sciences, even though he didn’t make original contributions to any. His curiosity was vast, and as Secretary of the Academy, he felt it was his duty to stay informed about everything happening in all areas of knowledge. That was possible then; it would be impossible now.

In the famous series of obituary discourses which he delivered on savants who were members of the Academy, Fontenelle probably thought that he was contributing to the realisation of this ideal of "solidarity," for they amounted to a chronicle of scientific progress in every department. They are free from technicalities and extraordinarily lucid, and they appealed not only to men of science, but to those of the educated public who possessed some scientific curiosity. This brings us to another important role of Fontenelle—the role of interpreter of the world of science to the world outside. It is closely related to our subject.

In the well-known series of obituary speeches he gave about scholars who were members of the Academy, Fontenelle likely believed he was contributing to the realization of the ideal of "solidarity," as they served as a record of scientific progress in every field. They are free of technical jargon and incredibly clear, appealing not only to scientists but also to educated individuals with some scientific curiosity. This leads us to another important role of Fontenelle—his role as a bridge between the world of science and the general public. This is closely tied to our topic.

For the popularisation of science, which was to be one of the features of the nineteenth century, was in fact a condition of the success of the idea of Progress. That idea could not insinuate itself into the public mind and become a living force in civilised societies until the meaning and value of science had been generally grasped, and the results of scientific discovery had been more or less diffused. The achievements of physical science did more than anything else to convert the imaginations of men to the general doctrine of Progress.

For the popularization of science, which would be a key aspect of the nineteenth century, was actually essential for the success of the idea of Progress. This idea couldn't take root in the public consciousness and become a powerful force in civilized societies until people generally understood the meaning and importance of science, and the outcomes of scientific discovery were fairly widespread. The accomplishments of physical science did more than anything else to engage people's imaginations with the overall concept of Progress.

Before the later part of the seventeenth century, the remarkable physical discoveries of recent date had hardly escaped beyond academic circles. But an interest in these subjects began to become the fashion in the later years of Louis XIV. Science was talked in the salons; ladies studied mechanics and anatomy. Moliere's play, Les Femmes savantes, which appeared in 1672, is one of the first indications. In 1686 Fontenelle published his Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds, in which a savant explains the new astronomy to a lady in the park of a country house. [Footnote: The Marquise of the Plurality of Worlds is supposed to be Madame de la Mesangere, who lived near Rouen, Fontenelle's birthplace. He was a friend and a frequent visitor at her chateau. See Maigron, Fontenelle, p. 42. The English translation of 1688 was by Glanvill. A new translation was published at Dublin as late as 1761.] It is the first book—at least the first that has any claim to be remembered—in the literature of popular science, and it is one of the most striking. It met with the success which it deserved. It was reprinted again and again, and it was almost immediately translated into English.

Before the later part of the seventeenth century, the incredible physical discoveries of the time had mostly stayed within academic circles. However, interest in these subjects started to become fashionable during the later years of Louis XIV. Science was a topic of conversation in salons; women studied mechanics and anatomy. Molière's play, Les Femmes savantes, which came out in 1672, is one of the first signs of this trend. In 1686, Fontenelle published his Conversations on the Plurality of Worlds, where a scholar explains the new astronomy to a woman in the park of a country house. [Footnote: The Marquise of the Plurality of Worlds is thought to be Madame de la Mesangere, who lived near Rouen, Fontenelle's birthplace. He was a friend and frequent visitor at her chateau. See Maigron, Fontenelle, p. 42. The English translation of 1688 was done by Glanvill. A new translation was published in Dublin as late as 1761.] It is the first book—at least the first that is noteworthy—in the literature of popular science, and it is one of the most remarkable. It received the success it deserved, was reprinted multiple times, and was almost immediately translated into English.

The significance of the Plurality of Worlds is indeed much greater than that of a pioneer work in popularisation and a model in the art of making technical subjects interesting. We must remember that at this time the belief that the sun revolves round the earth still prevailed. Only the few knew better. The cosmic revolution which is associated with the names of Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo was slow in producing its effects. It was rejected by Bacon; and the condemnation of Galileo by the Church made Descartes, who dreaded nothing so much as a collision with the ecclesiastical authorities unwilling to insist on it. [Footnote: Cp. Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophie cartesienne, i. p. 42-3.] Milton's Raphael, in the Eighth Book of Paradise Lost (published 1667), does not venture to affirm the Copernican system; he explains it sympathetically, but leaves the question open. [Footnote: Masson (Milton's Poetical Works, vol. 2) observes that Milton's life (1608-74) "coincides with the period of the struggle between the two systems" (p. 90). Milton's friends, the Smectymnians, in answer to Bishop Hall's Humble Remonstrance (1641), "had cited the Copernican doctrine as an unquestionable instance of a supreme absurdity." Masson has some apposite remarks on the influence of the Ptolemaic system "upon the thinkings and imaginations of mankind everywhere on all subjects whatsoever till about two hundred years ago."] Fontenelle's book was an event. It disclosed to the general public a new picture of the universe, to which men would have to accustom their imaginations.

The importance of the Plurality of Worlds is far greater than just being a pioneering work in popularizing ideas or serving as a model for making technical subjects engaging. We must keep in mind that at this time, the belief that the sun revolved around the earth was still common. Only a few people knew otherwise. The cosmic revolution linked to Copernicus, Kepler, and Galileo took time to have an impact. It was dismissed by Bacon, and Galileo's condemnation by the Church made Descartes, who feared conflict with religious authorities, hesitant to support it. [Footnote: Cp. Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophie cartesienne, i. p. 42-3.] Milton's Raphael, in the Eighth Book of Paradise Lost (published 1667), does not dare to endorse the Copernican system; he discusses it sympathetically but leaves the debate unresolved. [Footnote: Masson (Milton's Poetical Works, vol. 2) notes that Milton's life (1608-74) "coincides with the period of the struggle between the two systems" (p. 90). Milton's friends, the Smectymnians, replied to Bishop Hall's Humble Remonstrance (1641) by citing the Copernican doctrine as a clear example of supreme absurdity. Masson provides relevant comments on the Ptolemaic system's influence "on the thoughts and imaginations of people everywhere on all subjects until about two hundred years ago."] Fontenelle's book was significant. It introduced the general public to a new view of the universe that people would need to get used to.

We may perhaps best conceive all that this change meant by supposing what a difference it would make to us if it were suddenly discovered that the old system which Copernicus upset was true after all, and that we had to think ourselves back into a strictly limited universe of which the earth is the centre. The loss of its privileged position by our own planet; its degradation, from a cosmic point of view, to insignificance; the necessity of admitting the probability that there may be many other inhabited worlds—all this had consequences ranging beyond the field of astronomy. It was as if a man who dreamed that he was living in Paris or London should awake to discover that he was really in an obscure island in the Pacific Ocean, and that the Pacific Ocean was immeasurably vaster than he had imagined. The Marquise, in the Plurality of Worlds, reacts to the startling illumination: "Voila l'univers si grand que je m'y perds, je ne sais plus ou je suis; je ne suis plus rien.—La terre est si effroyablement petite!"

We can probably best understand what this change meant by imagining how different our lives would be if it turned out that the old system Copernicus challenged was actually correct, and we had to accept that we live in a strictly limited universe with the Earth at its center. The loss of our planet's special status; its demotion to something insignificant from a cosmic perspective; and the need to consider that there might be many other inhabited worlds—this had implications that went beyond just astronomy. It was like a person who dreamed they were in Paris or London suddenly waking up to find they're actually on a tiny island in the Pacific Ocean, realizing that the Pacific Ocean is much larger than they ever thought. The Marquise, in the Plurality of Worlds, responds to this shocking realization: "Here is the universe so vast that I lose myself in it; I no longer know where I am; I am nothing now.—The Earth is terrifyingly small!"

Such a revolution in cosmic values could not fail to exert a penetrating influence on human thought. The privileged position of the earth had been a capital feature of the whole doctrine, as to the universe and man's destinies, which had been taught by the Church, and it had made that doctrine more specious than it might otherwise have seemed. Though the Churches could reform their teaching to meet the new situation, the fact remained that the Christian scheme sounded less plausible when the central importance of the human race was shown to be an illusion. Would man, stripped of his cosmic pretensions, and finding himself lost in the immensities of space, invent a more modest theory of his destinies confined to his own little earth—si effroyablement petite? The eighteenth century answered this question by the theory of Progress.

Such a revolution in cosmic values was bound to have a significant impact on human thought. The Earth's privileged position had been a key aspect of the entire teaching about the universe and humanity's fate, as promoted by the Church, which made that doctrine seem more convincing than it might have otherwise appeared. Even though the Churches could adjust their teachings to adapt to the new reality, the truth was that the Christian narrative seemed less believable when the notion of humanity's central importance was revealed to be an illusion. Would humanity, stripped of its cosmic pretensions and feeling lost in the vastness of space, create a more modest theory of its fate limited to its own tiny planet—so horrendously small? The eighteenth century responded to this question with the theory of Progress.

10.

10.

Fontenelle is one of the most representative thinkers of that period—we have no distinguishing name for it—which lies between the characteristic thinkers of the seventeenth century and the characteristic thinkers of the eighteenth. It is a period of over sixty years, beginning about 1680, for though Montesquieu and Voltaire were writing long before 1740, the great influential works of the "age of illumination" begin with the Esprit des lois in 1748. The intellectual task of this intervening period was to turn to account the ideas provided by the philosophy of Descartes, and use them as solvents of the ideas handed down from the Middle Ages. We might almost call it the Cartesian period for, though Descartes was dead, it was in these years that Cartesianism performed its task and transformed human thought.

Fontenelle is one of the key thinkers of that period—we don’t have a specific name for it—which comes between the prominent thinkers of the seventeenth century and those of the eighteenth. This period spans over sixty years, starting around 1680, since Montesquieu and Voltaire were writing well before 1740, but the major influential works of the "age of enlightenment" begin with the Esprit des lois in 1748. The main intellectual goal of this transitional period was to utilize the ideas from Descartes' philosophy and apply them to challenge the ideas inherited from the Middle Ages. We could almost refer to it as the Cartesian period because, even though Descartes had died, it was during these years that Cartesianism took effect and reshaped human thought.

When we speak of Cartesianism we do not mean the metaphysical system of the master, or any of his particular views such as that of innate ideas. We mean the general principles, which were to leave an abiding impression on the texture of thought: the supremacy of reason over authority, the stability of the laws of Nature, rigorous standards of proof. Fontenelle was far from accepting all the views of Descartes, whom he does not scruple to criticise; but he was a true Cartesian in the sense that he was deeply imbued with these principles, which generated, to use an expression of his own, "des especes de rebelles, qui conspiraient contre l'ignorance et les prejuges dominants." [Footnote: Eloge de M. Lemery.] And of all these rebels against ruling prejudices he probably did more than any single man to exhibit the consequences of the Cartesian ideas and drive them home.

When we talk about Cartesianism, we aren't referring to the master’s metaphysical system or any specific beliefs like innate ideas. We're talking about the fundamental principles that have profoundly influenced how we think: the importance of reason over authority, the consistency of the laws of nature, and strict criteria for evidence. Fontenelle didn’t accept all of Descartes' views and wasn’t afraid to critique him; however, he was undeniably a Cartesian because he was deeply influenced by these principles, which produced, in his own words, "a kind of rebels who conspired against ignorance and dominant prejudices." [Footnote: Eloge de M. Lemery.] Among all these rebels challenging prevalent prejudices, he likely did more than anyone else to illustrate and reinforce the implications of Cartesian ideas.

The Plurality of Worlds was a contribution to the task of transforming thought and abolishing ancient error; but the History of Oracles which appeared in the following year was more characteristic. It was a free adaptation of an unreadable Latin treatise by a Dutchman, which in Fontenelle's skilful hands becomes a vehicle for applying Cartesian solvents to theological authority. The thesis is that the Greek oracles were a sacerdotal imposture, and not, as ecclesiastical tradition said, the work of evil spirits, who were stricken silent at the death of Jesus Christ. The effect was to discredit the authority of the early Fathers of the Church, though the writer has the discretion to repudiate such an intention. For the publication was risky; and twenty years later a Jesuit Father wrote a treatise to confute it, and exposed the secret poison, with consequences which might have been disastrous for Fontenelle if he had not had powerful friends among the Jesuits themselves. Fontenelle had none of the impetuosity of Voltaire, and after the publication of the History of Oracles he confined his criticism of tradition to the field of science. He was convinced that "les choses fort etablies ne peuvent etre attaquees que par degrez." [Footnote: Eloge de M. Lemery.]

The Plurality of Worlds was a major contribution to changing perspectives and correcting old mistakes; however, the History of Oracles that came out the following year was even more significant. It was a free adaptation of an unreadable Latin treatise by a Dutchman, which in Fontenelle's skilled hands transformed into a tool for applying Cartesian reasoning to religious authority. The main argument is that the Greek oracles were a priestly deception, not, as church tradition claimed, the work of evil spirits that fell silent at Jesus Christ's death. This effectively undermined the authority of the early Church Fathers, although the author wisely claims no such intention. The publication was risky, and twenty years later, a Jesuit Father wrote a treatise to refute it, revealing the hidden dangers, which could have had serious consequences for Fontenelle if he hadn't had influential friends among the Jesuits. Fontenelle lacked Voltaire's impulsiveness and after publishing the History of Oracles, he limited his critiques of tradition to the realm of science. He believed that "established things can only be attacked gradually." [Footnote: Eloge de M. Lemery.]

The secret poison, of which Fontenelle prepared this remarkable dose with a touch which reminds us of Voltaire, was being administered in the same Cartesian period, and with similar precautions, by Bayle. Like Fontenelle, this great sceptic, "the father of modern incredulity" as he was called by Joseph de Maistre, stood between the two centuries and belonged to both. Like Fontenelle, he took a gloomy view of humanity; he had no faith in that goodness of human nature which was to be a characteristic dogma of the age of illumination. But he was untouched by the discoveries of science; he took no interest in Galileo or Newton; and while the most important work of Fontenelle was the interpretation of the positive advances of knowledge, Bayle's was entirely subversive.

The secret poison, which Fontenelle prepared in this impressive way that reminds us of Voltaire, was being given during the same Cartesian period, and with similar precautions, by Bayle. Like Fontenelle, this great skeptic, "the father of modern disbelief" as Joseph de Maistre called him, was positioned between the two centuries and belonged to both. Like Fontenelle, he had a bleak view of humanity; he didn’t believe in the goodness of human nature that was set to be a key belief of the Age of Enlightenment. But he was unaffected by scientific discoveries; he wasn’t interested in Galileo or Newton; and while the most significant work of Fontenelle was about explaining the positive progress of knowledge, Bayle's was entirely subversive.

The principle of unchangeable laws in nature is intimately connected with the growth of Deism which is a note of this period. The function of the Deity was virtually confined to originating the machine of nature, which, once regulated, was set beyond any further interference on His part, though His existence might be necessary for its conservation. A view so sharply opposed to the current belief could not have made way as it did without a penetrating criticism of the current theology. Such criticism was performed by Bayle. His works were a school for rationalism for about seventy years. He supplied to the thinkers of the eighteenth century, English as well as French, a magazine of subversive arguments, and he helped to emancipate morality both from theology and from metaphysics.

The idea of unchangeable laws in nature is closely linked to the rise of Deism, which is a characteristic of this period. The role of the Deity was mainly to create the natural world, which, once put in motion, was left to operate without further intervention from Him, although His existence might still be necessary for its upkeep. A perspective so drastically different from popular belief couldn't have gained traction without a thorough critique of the existing theology. This critique was carried out by Bayle. His works served as a foundation for rationalism for about seventy years. He provided thinkers of the eighteenth century, both English and French, with a wealth of challenging ideas, helping to free morality from both theology and metaphysics.

This intellectual revolutionary movement, which was propagated in salons as well as by books, shook the doctrine of Providence which Bossuet had so eloquently expounded. It meant the enthronement of reason—Cartesian reason—before whose severe tribunal history as well as opinions were tried. New rules of criticism were introduced, new standards of proof. When Fontenelle observed that the existence of Alexander the Great could not be strictly demonstrated and was no more than highly probable, [Footnote: Plurality des mondes, sixieme soir.] it was an undesigned warning that tradition would receive short shrift at the hands of men trained in analytical Cartesian methods.

This intellectual revolutionary movement, which spread through salons and books, challenged the doctrine of Providence that Bossuet had so passionately defended. It brought reason—Cartesian reason—into the spotlight, putting history and opinions on trial under its rigorous standards. New rules for critique emerged, along with new benchmarks for proof. When Fontenelle noted that the existence of Alexander the Great couldn't be strictly proven and was only highly probable, it served as an unintended warning that traditional views would be quickly dismissed by those trained in analytical Cartesian methods.

11.

11.

That the issue between the claims of antiquity and the modern age should have been debated independently in England and France indicates that the controversy was an inevitable incident in the liberation of the human spirit from the authority of the ancients. Towards the end of the century the debate in France aroused attention in England and led to a literary quarrel, less important but not less acrimonious than that which raged in France. Sir William Temple's Essay, Wotton's Reflexions, and Swift's satire the Battle of the Books are the three outstanding works in the episode, which is however chiefly remembered on account of its connection with Bentley's masterly exposure of the fabricated letters of Phalaris.

The fact that the debate over ancient claims versus modern perspectives was discussed separately in England and France shows that the argument was a necessary step in freeing the human spirit from the control of ancient authority. By the end of the century, the discussion in France caught the attention of England and sparked a literary dispute that was less significant but just as heated as the one in France. Sir William Temple's Essay, Wotton's Reflexions, and Swift's satire the Battle of the Books are the three key works from this period, which is mainly remembered because of Bentley's brilliant exposure of the fake letters of Phalaris.

The literary debate in France, indeed, could not have failed to reverberate across the Channel; for never perhaps did the literary world in England follow with more interest, or appreciate more keenly the productions of the great French writers of the time. In describing Will's coffee-house, which was frequented by Dryden and all who pretended to be interested in polite letters, Macaulay says, "there was a faction for Perrault and the moderns, a faction for Boileau and the ancients." In the discussions on this subject a remarkable Frenchman who had long lived in England as an exile, M. de Saint Evremond, must have constantly taken part. The disjointed pieces of which Saint Evremond's writings consist are tedious and superficial, but they reveal a mind of much cultivation and considerable common sense. His judgement on Perrault's Parallel is that the author "has discovered the defects of the ancients better than he has made out the advantage of the moderns; his book is good and capable of curing us of abundance of errors." [Footnote: In a letter to the Duchess of Mazarin, Works, Eng. tr., iii. 418.] He was not a partisan. But his friend, Sir William Temple, excited by the French depreciations of antiquity, rushed into the lists with greater courage than discretion.

The literary debate in France definitely echoed across the Channel, as the literary scene in England had never been more engaged or appreciative of the works of the great French writers of that time. Describing Will's coffee-house, a popular spot for Dryden and others interested in literature, Macaulay notes that "there was a faction for Perrault and the moderns, a faction for Boileau and the ancients." A remarkable Frenchman, M. de Saint Evremond, who had lived in England as an exile, likely participated in these discussions. While the scattered writings of Saint Evremond can be tedious and superficial, they show a cultivated mind with a good sense of practicality. He judged Perrault's Parallel by saying that the author "has discovered the defects of the ancients better than he has demonstrated the advantages of the moderns; his book is good and capable of curing us of many errors." [Footnote: In a letter to the Duchess of Mazarin, Works, Eng. tr., iii. 418.] He wasn't biased. However, his friend, Sir William Temple, spurred by the French criticism of antiquity, entered the debate with more bravery than caution.

Temple was ill equipped for the controversy, though his Essay on Ancient and Modern Learning (1690) is far from deserving the disdain of Macaulay, who describes its matter as "ludicrous and contemptible to the last degree." [Footnote: The only point in it which need be noted here is that the author questioned the cogency of Fontenelle's argument, that the forces of nature being permanent human ability is in all ages the same. "May there not," he asks, "many circumstances concur to one production that do not to any other in one or many ages?" Fontenelle speaks of trees. It is conceivable that various conditions and accidents "may produce an oak, a fig, or a plane-tree, that shall deserve to be renowned in story, and shall not perhaps be paralleled in other countries or times. May not the same have happened in the production, growth, and size of wit and genius in the world, or in some parts or ages of it, and from many more circumstances that contributed towards it than what may concur to the stupendous growth of a tree or animal?"] And it must be confessed that the most useful result of the Essay was the answer which it provoked from Wotton. For Wotton had a far wider range of knowledge, and a more judicious mind, than any of the other controversialists, with the exception of Fontenelle; and in knowledge of antiquity he was Fontenelle's superior. His inquiry stands out as the most sensible and unprejudiced contribution to the whole debate. He accepts as just the reasoning of Fontenelle "as to the comparative force of the geniuses of men in the several ages of the world and of the equal force of men's understandings absolutely considered in all times since learning first began to be cultivated amongst mankind." But this is not incompatible with the thesis that in some branches the ancients excelled all who came after them. For it is not necessary to explain such excellence by the hypothesis that there was a particular force of genius evidently discernible in former ages, but extinct long since, and that nature is now worn out and spent. There is an alternative explanation. There may have been special circumstances "which might suit with those ages which did exceed ours, and with those things wherein they did exceed us, and with no other age nor thing besides."

Temple was not well-prepared for the controversy, although his Essay on Ancient and Modern Learning (1690) certainly doesn't deserve the contempt of Macaulay, who calls its content "ridiculous and utterly despicable." [Footnote: The only point worth mentioning here is that the author questioned Fontenelle's argument that the forces of nature are constant and that human ability remains the same throughout all ages. "Could there not," he asks, "be many factors that contribute to a single outcome that wouldn't apply to any other time or event?" Fontenelle refers to trees. It's conceivable that different conditions and occurrences "may produce an oak, a fig, or a plane tree, which could become famous in history, and perhaps wouldn't be matched in other places or times. Could the same not be true for the emergence, development, and talent of wit and genius in the world, or in certain periods or regions, due to many more factors that contributed to it than those that lead to the remarkable growth of a tree or animal?"] It must be acknowledged that the most valuable outcome of the Essay was the response it triggered from Wotton. Wotton possessed a broader knowledge base and a more discerning mind than any of the other debaters, except for Fontenelle; he even surpassed Fontenelle when it came to understanding antiquity. His inquiry stands out as the most reasonable and impartial contribution to the entire discussion. He reasonably accepts Fontenelle's view "regarding the comparative strength of men's genius throughout various ages and the equal capacity of human understanding considered universally since learning first started to be pursued among people." However, this doesn't conflict with the idea that in certain fields, the ancients surpassed anyone who came after them. There is no need to attribute such superiority to the theory that there was a specific force of genius clearly observable in earlier ages, which has since vanished, and that nature is now exhausted and depleted. There is another explanation. It’s possible that special circumstances "may have aligned with those ages, which exceeded ours, and with the things they excelled in, without applying to any other age or thing."

But we must begin our inquiry by sharply distinguishing two fields of mental activity—the field of art, including poetry, oratory, architecture, painting, and statuary; and the field of knowledge, including mathematics, natural science, physiology, with all their dependencies. In the case of the first group there is room for variety of opinion; but the superiority of the Greeks and Romans in poetry and literary style may be admitted without prejudice to the mental equality of the moderns, for it may be explained partly by the genius of their languages and partly by political circumstances—for example, in the case of oratory, [Footnote: This had been noted by Fontenelle in his Digression.] by the practical necessity of eloquence. But as regards the other group, knowledge is not a matter of opinion or taste, and a definite judgement is possible. Wotton then proceeds to review systematically the field of science, and easily shows, with more completeness and precision than Perrault, the superiority of modern methods and the enormous strides which had been made.

But we have to start our investigation by clearly distinguishing two areas of mental activity—the area of art, which includes poetry, public speaking, architecture, painting, and sculpture; and the area of knowledge, which includes math, natural science, and physiology, along with all their related fields. In the first group, there’s room for differing opinions; however, we can acknowledge the superiority of the Greeks and Romans in poetry and literary style without undermining the mental equality of modern times. This can be explained partly by the unique qualities of their languages and partly by political factors—like the need for effective eloquence in the case of public speaking, [Footnote: This had been noted by Fontenelle in his Digression.] But when it comes to the other group, knowledge isn’t subjective; we can reach clear judgments. Wotton then goes on to systematically explore the field of science and convincingly demonstrates, with more thoroughness and accuracy than Perrault, the superiority of modern methods and the significant progress that has been achieved.

As to the future, Wotton expresses himself cautiously. It is not easy to say whether knowledge will advance in the next age proportionally to its advance in this. He has some fears that there may be a falling away, because ancient learning has still too great a hold over modern books, and physical and mathematical studies tend to be neglected. But he ends his Reflexions by the speculation that "some future age, though perhaps not the next, and in a country now possibly little thought of, may do that which our great men would be glad to see done; that is to say, may raise real knowledge, upon foundations laid in this age, to the utmost possible perfection to which it may be brought by mortal men in this imperfect state."

As for the future, Wotton speaks cautiously. It’s hard to tell if knowledge will progress in the next age as much as it has in this one. He worries that there might be a decline, since ancient learning still has too much influence over modern books, and physical and mathematical studies often get overlooked. However, he concludes his Reflexions with the hope that "some future age, though maybe not the next, and in a country that is perhaps not much considered now, may achieve what our great minds would be pleased to see happen; that is, may elevate real knowledge, built on the foundations laid in this age, to the highest possible perfection that can be achieved by humans in this flawed state."

The distinction, on which Wotton insisted, between the sciences which require ages for their development and the imaginative arts which may reach perfection in a short time had been recognised by Fontenelle, whose argument on this point differs from that of his friend Perrault. For Perrault contended that in literature and art, as well as in science, later generations can, through the advantage of time and longer experience, attain to a higher excellence than their predecessors. Fontenelle, on the other hand, held that poetry and eloquence have a restricted field, and that therefore there must be a time at which they reach a point of excellence which cannot be exceeded. It was his personal opinion that eloquence and history actually reached the highest possible perfection in Cicero and Livy.

The distinction that Wotton emphasized between sciences, which take centuries to develop, and the imaginative arts, which can achieve perfection in a short time, was acknowledged by Fontenelle. His argument on this matter differs from that of his friend Perrault. Perrault believed that in literature and art, just like in science, later generations can achieve a higher level of excellence than their predecessors due to the benefits of time and greater experience. In contrast, Fontenelle argued that poetry and eloquence have a limited scope, and therefore there comes a time when they reach a level of excellence that cannot be surpassed. He personally believed that eloquence and history attained their maximum perfection in the works of Cicero and Livy.

But neither Fontenelle nor Wotton came into close quarters with the problem which was raised—not very clearly, it is true—by Perrault. Is there development in the various species of literature and art? Do they profit and enrich themselves by the general advance of civilisation? Perrault, as we have seen, threw out the suggestion that increased experience and psychological study enabled the moderns to penetrate more deeply into the recesses of the human soul, and therefore to bring to a higher perfection the treatment of the character, motives, and passions of men. This suggestion admits of being extended. In the Introduction to his Revolt of Islam, Shelley, describing his own intellectual and aesthetic experiences, writes:

But neither Fontenelle nor Wotton tackled the issue that Perrault raised—not very clearly, it’s true. Is there growth in the different forms of literature and art? Do they benefit and develop through the overall progress of society? Perrault, as we’ve seen, proposed the idea that increased experience and psychological insight allowed modern creators to delve deeper into the complexities of the human soul, thus enhancing the way they portray character, motivations, and emotions. This idea can be expanded. In the Introduction to his Revolt of Islam, Shelley describes his own intellectual and aesthetic experiences, writing:

The poetry of ancient Greece and Rome, and modern Italy, and our own country, has been to me like external nature, a passion and an enjoyment.... I have considered poetry in its most comprehensive sense; and have read the poets and the historians and the metaphysicians whose writings have been accessible to me—and have looked upon the beautiful and majestic scenery of the earth—as common sources of those elements which it is the province of the Poet to embody and combine. And he appends a note:

The poetry of ancient Greece and Rome, modern Italy, and our own country has felt to me like the natural world, filled with passion and joy. I've thought about poetry in its broadest sense; I've read the poets, historians, and philosophers whose work I could find—and I've appreciated the stunning and grand landscapes of the earth—as shared sources of the elements that it is the job of the Poet to portray and blend. And he adds a note:

In this sense there may be such a thing as perfectibility in works of fiction, notwithstanding the concession often made by the advocates of human improvement, that perfectibility is a term applicable only to science.

In this way, there could be such a thing as perfection in works of fiction, even though supporters of human progress often agree that perfection is a term that only applies to science.

In other words, all the increases of human experience, from age to age, all the speculative adventures of the intellect, provide the artist, in each succeeding generation, with more abundant sources for aesthetic treatment. As years go on, life in its widest sense offers more and more materials "which it is the province of the Poet to embody and combine." This is evidently true; and would it not seem to follow that literature is not excluded from participating in the common development of civilisation? One of the latest of the champions of the Moderns, the Abbe Terrasson, maintained that "to separate the general view of the progress of the human mind in regard to natural science, and in regard to belles-lettres, would be a fitting expedient to a man who had two souls, but it is useless to him who has only one." [Footnote: Abbe Terrasson, 1670-1750. His Philosophie applicable a tons les objets de l'esprit et de la raison was issued posthumously in 1754. His Dissertation critique sur l'Iliade appeared in 1715.]He put the matter in too abstract a way to carry conviction; but the nineteenth century was to judge that he was not entirely wrong. For the question was, as we shall see, raised anew by Madame de Stael, and the theory was finally to emerge that art and literature, like laws and institutions, are an expression of society and therefore inextricably linked with the other elements of social development—a theory, it may be observed, which while it has discredited the habit of considering works of art in a vacuum, dateless and detached, as they were generally considered by critics of the seventeenth century, leaves the aesthetic problem much where it was.

In other words, all the growth of human experience, from one era to the next, all the imaginative endeavors of the mind, give artists in each new generation a richer pool of inspiration for their work. As time passes, life in its broadest sense provides more and more material "which it is the role of the Poet to embody and combine." This is clearly true; wouldn't it seem logical that literature isn't excluded from sharing in the overall progress of civilization? One of the most recent advocates for modern thought, Abbe Terrasson, argued that "to separate the overall view of the progress of the human mind in regard to natural science and in regard to literature would be suitable for someone with two souls, but it's useless for someone with only one." [Footnote: Abbe Terrasson, 1670-1750. His Philosophie applicable a tons les objets de l'esprit et de la raison was published posthumously in 1754. His Dissertation critique sur l'Iliade was released in 1715.] He raised the issue in a way that was too abstract to be convincing; however, the nineteenth century would recognize that he wasn’t entirely wrong. The debate would be rekindled by Madame de Stael, and the idea eventually emerged that art and literature, like laws and institutions, reflect society and are therefore closely linked to other aspects of social development—a perspective that has discredited the tendency to view art in isolation, timeless and detached, as critics did in the seventeenth century, yet it leaves the aesthetic problem largely unresolved.

Perrault's suggestion as to the enrichment of the material of the artist by new acquisitions would have served to bring literature and art into the general field of human development, without compromising the distinction on which Wotton and others insisted between the natural sciences and the aesthetic arts. But that distinction, emphatically endorsed by Voltaire, had the effect of excluding literature and art from the view of those who in the eighteenth century recognised progress in the other activities of man.

Perrault's idea of enhancing an artist's resources through new acquisitions could have integrated literature and art into the broader scope of human development, without losing sight of the separation that Wotton and others highlighted between the natural sciences and the aesthetic arts. However, that distinction, strongly supported by Voltaire, led to the exclusion of literature and art from the perspective of those in the eighteenth century who acknowledged advancements in other human endeavors.

12.

12.

It is notable that in this literary controversy the Moderns, even Fontenelle, seem curiously negligent of the import of the theory which they were propounding of the intellectual progress of man. They treat it almost incidentally, as part of the case for the defence, not as an immensely important conclusion. Its bearings were more definitely realised by the Abbe Terrasson, whom I have just named. A geometer and a Cartesian, he took part in the controversy in its latest stage, when La Motte and Madame Dacier were the principal antagonists. The human mind, he said, has had its infancy and youth; its maturity began in the age of Augustus; the barbarians arrested its course till the Renaissance; in the seventeenth century, through the illuminating philosophy of Descartes, it passed beyond the stage which it had attained in the Augustan age, and the eighteenth century should surpass the seventeenth. Cartesianism is not final; it has its place in a development. It was made possible by previous speculations, and it will be succeeded by other systems. We must not pursue the analogy of humanity with an individual man and anticipate a period of old age. For unlike the individual, humanity "being composed of all ages," is always gaining instead of losing. The age of maturity will last indefinitely, because it is a progressive, not a stationary, maturity. Later generations will always be superior to the earlier, for progress is "a natural and necessary effect of the constitution of the human mind."

It’s interesting to note that in this literary debate, the Moderns, including Fontenelle, seem oddly casual about the significance of the theory they were promoting regarding humanity's intellectual progress. They discuss it almost in passing as part of their defense, rather than treating it as a critically important conclusion. The implications were more clearly understood by the Abbe Terrasson, whom I just mentioned. As a geometer and a Cartesian, he engaged in the debate during its later stage, when La Motte and Madame Dacier were the main opponents. He stated that the human mind has gone through its infancy and youth, with its maturity starting in the Age of Augustus. The barbarians interrupted this development until the Renaissance; then, in the seventeenth century, thanks to Descartes' enlightening philosophy, it moved beyond what it had achieved in the Augustan era, and the eighteenth century should surpass the seventeenth. Cartesianism is not the end; it plays a role in a larger development. It was made possible by earlier ideas and will be followed by other systems. We shouldn't compare humanity's progress to that of an individual and expect a phase of decline. Unlike an individual, humanity, "being composed of all ages," continues to grow rather than diminish. The age of maturity will last indefinitely, as it represents a progressive, not a stagnant, maturity. Future generations will always be more advanced than those that came before, as progress is "a natural and necessary effect of the constitution of the human mind."





CHAPTER VI. THE GENERAL PROGRESS OF MAN: ABBE DE SAINT-PIERRE

The revolutionary speculations on the social and moral condition of man which were the outstanding feature of the eighteenth century in France, and began about 1750, were the development of the intellectual movement of the seventeenth, which had changed the outlook of speculative thought. It was one continuous rationalistic movement. In the days of Racine and Perrault men had been complacently conscious of the enlightenment of the age in which they were living, and as time went on, this consciousness became stronger and acuter; it is a note of the age of Voltaire. In the last years of Louis XIV., and in the years which followed, the contrast between this mental enlightenment and the dark background—the social evils and miseries of the kingdom, the gross misgovernment and oppression—began to insinuate itself into men's minds. What was the value of the achievements of science, and the improvement of the arts of life, if life itself could not be ameliorated? Was not some radical reconstruction possible, in the social fabric, corresponding to the radical reconstruction inaugurated by Descartes in the principles of science and in the methods of thought? Year by year the obscurantism of the ruling powers became more glaring, and the most gifted thinkers, towards the middle of the century, began to concentrate their brains on the problems of social science and to turn the light of reason on the nature of man and the roots of society. They wrought with unscrupulous resolution and with far-reaching effects.

The revolutionary ideas about the social and moral state of humanity that stood out in eighteenth-century France, starting around 1750, were a continuation of the intellectual movement from the seventeenth century, which had transformed the way people thought. It was one ongoing rationalist movement. During the time of Racine and Perrault, people felt confidently aware of the enlightenment of their era, and as time progressed, this awareness became stronger and sharper; this is a hallmark of Voltaire's time. In the final years of Louis XIV and the years that followed, the contrast between this mental enlightenment and the dark backdrop of social issues and suffering in the kingdom, along with poor governance and oppression, started to seep into people's minds. What was the point of scientific achievements and improvements in daily life if life itself couldn't get better? Wasn't it possible to radically reconstruct the social fabric, similar to the radical changes Descartes initiated in the principles of science and ways of thinking? Year by year, the ignorance of those in power became more evident, and by the mid-century, the most talented thinkers began to focus on social science issues and shine the light of reason on human nature and the foundations of society. They worked with determined resolve and achieved significant results.

With the extension of rationalism into the social domain, it came about naturally that the idea of intellectual progress was enlarged into the idea of the general Progress of man. The transition was easy. If it could be proved that social evils were due neither to innate and incorrigible disabilities of the human being nor to the nature of things, but simply to ignorance and prejudices, then the improvement of his state, and ultimately the attainment of felicity, would be only a matter of illuminating ignorance and removing errors, of increasing knowledge and diffusing light. The growth of the "universal human reason"—a Cartesian phrase, which had figured in the philosophy of Malebranche—must assure a happy destiny to humanity.

With the expansion of rationalism into social issues, it naturally followed that the concept of intellectual progress evolved into the idea of general progress for humanity. The shift was seamless. If it could be shown that social problems were not caused by inherent and unchangeable limitations of humans or the nature of reality, but rather by ignorance and prejudice, then improving people's conditions—and eventually achieving happiness—would simply be a matter of enlightening ignorance and correcting misconceptions, of increasing knowledge and spreading understanding. The development of "universal human reason"—a term from Descartes that had appeared in Malebranche's philosophy—should guarantee a positive future for humanity.

Between 1690 and 1740 the conception of an indefinite progress of enlightenment had been making its way in French intellectual circles, and must often have been a topic of discussion in the salons, for instance, of Madame de Lambert, Madame de Tencin, and Madame Dupin, where Fontenelle was one of the most conspicuous guests. To the same circle belonged his friend the Abbe de Saint-Pierre, and it is in his writings that we first find the theory widened in its compass to embrace progress towards social perfection. [Footnote: For his life and works the best book is J. Drouet's monograph, L'Abbe de Saint-Pierre: l'homme et l'oeuvre (1912), but on some points Goumy's older study (1859) is still worth consulting. I have used the edition of his works in 12 volumes published during his lifetime at Rotterdam, 1733-37.]

Between 1690 and 1740, the idea of endless progress in enlightenment was gaining traction in French intellectual circles and was likely a frequent topic of conversation in the salons of Madame de Lambert, Madame de Tencin, and Madame Dupin, where Fontenelle was one of the most notable guests. His friend, the Abbe de Saint-Pierre, also belonged to this circle, and it's in his writings that we first see the theory expanded to include progress toward social perfection. [Footnote: For his life and works, the best book is J. Drouet's monograph, L'Abbe de Saint-Pierre: l'homme et l'oeuvre (1912), but for certain aspects, Goumy's earlier study (1859) is still worth checking out. I used the edition of his works in 12 volumes published during his lifetime in Rotterdam, 1733-37.]

1.

1.

He was brought up on Cartesian principles, and he idealised Descartes somewhat as Lucretius idealised Epicurus. But he had no aptitude for philosophy, and he prized physical science only as far as it directly administered to the happiness of men. He was a natural utilitarian, and perhaps no one was ever more consistent in making utility the criterion of all actions and theories. Applying this standard he obliterated from the roll of great men most of those whom common opinion places among the greatest. Alexander, Julius Caesar, Charlemagne receive short shrift from the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. [Footnote: Compare Voltaire, Lettres sur les Anglais, xii., where Newton is acclaimed as the greatest man who ever lived.] He was superficial in his knowledge both of history and of science, and his conception of utility was narrow and a little vulgar. Great theoretical discoverers like Newton and Leibnitz he sets in a lower rank than ingenious persons who used their scientific skill to fashion some small convenience of life. Monuments of art, like Notre Dame, possessed little value in his eyes compared with a road, a bridge, or a canal.

He was raised on Cartesian principles and idealized Descartes much like Lucretius idealized Epicurus. However, he wasn't suited for philosophy, and he valued physical science only as far as it contributed to people's happiness. He was a natural utilitarian, and perhaps no one was more consistent in using utility as the standard for all actions and theories. Using this criterion, he removed from the list of great figures most of those whom popular opinion regards as the greatest. Alexander, Julius Caesar, and Charlemagne didn’t impress the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. [Footnote: Compare Voltaire, Lettres sur les Anglais, xii., where Newton is celebrated as the greatest person who ever lived.] He had a shallow understanding of both history and science, and his idea of utility was narrow and somewhat base. He ranked great theoretical discoverers like Newton and Leibnitz lower than clever individuals who used their scientific abilities to create minor conveniences in life. He saw works of art, like Notre Dame, as having little value compared to a road, a bridge, or a canal.

Like most of his distinguished contemporaries he was a Deist. On his deathbed he received the usual rites of the Church in the presence of his household, and then told the priest that he did not believe a word of all that. His real views are transparent in some of his works through the conventional disguises in which prudent writers of the time were wont to wrap their assaults on orthodoxy. To attack Mohammedanism by arguments which are equally applicable to Christianity was a device for propagating rationalism in days when it was dangerous to propagate it openly. This is what the Abbe did in his Discourse against Mohammedanism. Again, in his Physical Explanation of an Apparition he remarks: "To diminish our fanatical proclivities, it would be useful if the Government were to establish an annual prize, to be awarded by the Academy of Sciences, for the best explanation, by natural laws, of the extraordinary effects of imagination, of the prodigies related in Greek and Latin literature, and of the pretended miracles told by Protestants, Schismatics, and Mohammedans." The author carefully keeps on the right side of the fence. No Catholic authorities could take exception to this. But no intelligent reader could fail to see that all miracles were attacked. The miracles accepted by the Protestants were also believed in by the Catholics.

Like most of his notable peers, he was a Deist. On his deathbed, he received the usual rites of the Church in front of his family, and then he told the priest that he didn't believe a word of it. His true beliefs are clear in some of his works, despite the conventional disguises that careful writers of the time used to conceal their critiques of orthodox beliefs. He criticized Islam with arguments that also applied to Christianity as a way to promote rationalism in a time when it was risky to do so openly. This is what the Abbe did in his Discourse against Mohammedanism. Additionally, in his Physical Explanation of an Apparition, he stated: "To reduce our fanatical tendencies, it would be helpful if the Government established an annual prize, awarded by the Academy of Sciences, for the best natural explanation of the extraordinary effects of imagination, the wonders recounted in Greek and Latin literature, and the supposed miracles recounted by Protestants, Schismatics, and Mohammedans." The author skillfully stays on the right side of the line. No Catholic authorities could object to this. But any intelligent reader would see that all miracles were being challenged. The miracles accepted by Protestants were also believed in by Catholics.

He was one of the remarkable figures of his age. We might almost say that he was a new type—a nineteenth century humanitarian and pacifist in an eighteenth century environment. He was a born reformer, and he devoted his life to the construction of schemes for increasing human happiness. He introduced the word bienfaisance into the currency of the French language, and beneficence was in his eyes the sovran virtue. There were few departments of public affairs in which he did not point out the deficiencies and devise ingenious plans for improvement. Most of his numerous writings are projets—schemes of reform in government, economics, finance, education, all worked out in detail, and all aiming at the increase of pleasure and the diminution of pain. The Abbe's nimble intelligence had a weak side, which must have somewhat compromised his influence. He was so confident in the reasonableness of his projects that he always believed that if they were fairly considered the ruling powers could not fail to adopt them in their own interests. It is the nature of a reformer to be sanguine, but the optimism of Saint-Pierre touched naivete. Thousands might have agreed with his view that the celibacy of the Catholic clergy was an unwholesome institution, but when he drew up a proposal for its abolition and imagined that the Pope, unable to resist his arguments, would immediately adopt it, they might be excused for putting him down as a crank who could hardly be taken seriously. The form in which he put forward his memorable scheme for the abolition of war exhibits the same sanguine simplicity. All his plans, Rousseau observed, showed a clear vision of what their effects would be, "but he judged like a child of means to bring them about." But his abilities were great, and his actual influence was considerable. It would have been greater if he had possessed the gift of style.

He was one of the standout figures of his time. You could almost say he was a new kind of person—a nineteenth-century humanitarian and pacifist in an eighteenth-century setting. He was a natural reformer, dedicating his life to creating plans that would boost human happiness. He brought the word "bienfaisance" into the French language, and to him, beneficence was the ultimate virtue. There were few areas of public life where he didn’t highlight shortcomings and propose clever solutions for improvement. Most of his many writings are projects—detailed reform plans for government, economics, finance, and education, all aimed at increasing pleasure and reducing pain. The Abbe's quick mind had a flaw that somewhat undermined his influence. He was so sure about the reasonability of his ideas that he believed that if they were fairly considered, the ruling authorities would have no choice but to adopt them for their own benefit. Reformers often have a hopeful view, but Saint-Pierre’s optimism was almost naive. Many people might have agreed with him that the celibacy of the Catholic clergy was a harmful practice, but when he drafted a proposal to abolish it and thought the Pope would be compelled to accept his arguments right away, it was understandable that some would see him as a bit eccentric and not to be taken seriously. The way he presented his memorable plan to abolish war showed the same hopeful simplicity. All his plans, as Rousseau noted, demonstrated a clear understanding of their potential outcomes, "but he thought like a child who has the means to make them happen." Yet, he had significant abilities, and his real influence was notable. It could have been even greater if he had the gift of style.

2.

2.

He was not the first to plan a definite scheme for establishing a perpetual peace. Long ago Emeric Cruce had given to the world a proposal for a universal league, including not only the Christian nations of Europe, but the Turks, Persians, and Tartars, which by means of a court of arbitration sitting at Venice should ensure the settlement of all disputes by peaceful means. [Footnote: Le Nouveau Cynee (Paris, 1623). It has recently been reprinted with an English translation by T. W. Balch, Philadelphia (1909).] The consequence of universal peace, he said, will be the arrival of "that beautiful century which the ancient theologians promise after there have rolled by six thousand years. For they say that then the world will live happily and in repose. Now it happens that that time has nearly expired, and even if it is not, it depends only on the Princes to give beforehand this happiness to their peoples." Later in the century, others had ventilated similar projects in obscure publications, but the Abbe does not refer to any of his predecessors.

He wasn't the first to propose a clear plan for establishing lasting peace. Long ago, Emeric Cruce presented a proposal for a universal league that included not just the Christian nations of Europe, but also the Turks, Persians, and Tartars. This league would use a court of arbitration based in Venice to resolve all disputes peacefully. [Footnote: Le Nouveau Cynee (Paris, 1623). It has recently been reprinted with an English translation by T. W. Balch, Philadelphia (1909).] He claimed that universal peace would bring about "that beautiful century which the ancient theologians promise after six thousand years have passed. For they say that at that time, the world will live happily and peacefully. Now it turns out that this time is almost up, and even if it isn’t, it’s solely up to the Princes to grant this happiness to their people in advance." Later in the century, others proposed similar ideas in less known publications, but the Abbe doesn't mention any of his predecessors.

He was not blinded by the superficial brilliancy of the reign of Louis XIV. to the general misery which the ambitious war-policy of that sovran brought both upon France and upon her enemies. His Annales politiques are a useful correction to the Siecle de Louis Quatorze. It was in the course of the great struggle of the Spanish Succession that he turned his attention to war and came to the conclusion that it is an unnecessary evil and even an absurdity. In 1712 he attended the congress at Utrecht in the capacity of secretary to Cardinal de Polignac, one of the French delegates. His experiences there confirmed his optimistic mind in the persuasion that perpetual peace was an aim which might readily be realised; and in the following year he published the memoir which he had been preparing, in two volumes, to which he added a third four years later.

He wasn’t blinded by the flashy glory of Louis XIV’s reign to the widespread suffering that the monarch's aggressive war tactics caused both in France and among her enemies. His *Annales politiques* serves as a valuable counterpoint to the *Siecle de Louis Quatorze*. During the lengthy conflict over the Spanish Succession, he shifted his focus to war and concluded that it is an unnecessary evil, even a ridiculous one. In 1712, he attended the congress at Utrecht as the secretary to Cardinal de Polignac, one of the French delegates. His experiences there strengthened his belief that lasting peace was an achievable goal; the following year, he published the memoir he had been working on in two volumes, adding a third volume four years later.

Though he appears not to have known the work of Cruce he did not claim
originality. He sheltered his proposal under an august name, entitling
it Project of Henry the Great to render Peace Perpetual, explained
by the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. The reference is to the "great design"
ascribed to Henry IV. by Sully, and aimed at the abasement of the power
of Austria: a federation of the Christian States of Europe arranged
in groups and under a sovran Diet, which would regulate international
affairs and arbitrate in all quarrels. [Footnote: It is described
in Sully's Memoires, Book XXX.] Saint-Pierre, ignoring the fact that
Sully's object was to eliminate a rival power, made it the text for
his own scheme of a perpetual alliance of all the sovrans of Europe
to guarantee to one another the preservation of their states and to
renounce war as a means of settling their differences. He drew up the
terms of such an alliance, and taking the European powers one by
one demonstrated that it was the plain interest of each to sign the
articles. Once the articles were signed the golden age would begin.
[Footnote: For Sully's grand Design compare the interesting article of
Sir Geoffrey Butler in the Edinburgh Review, October 1919.]

 It is not to our present purpose to comment on this plan which the
author with his characteristic simplicity seriously pressed upon the
attention of statesmen. It is easy to criticise it in the light of
subsequent history, and to see that, if the impossible had happened and
the experiment had been tried and succeeded, it might have caused more
suffering than all the wars from that day to this. For it was based on a
perpetuation of the political status quo in Europe. It assumed that the
existing political distribution of power was perfectly satisfactory and
conformable to the best interests of all the peoples concerned. It would
have hindered the Partition of Poland, but it would have maintained the
Austrian oppression of Italians. The project also secured to the sovrans
the heritage of their authority and guarded against civil wars. This
assumed that the various existing constitutions were fundamentally just.
The realisation of the scheme would have perpetuated all the evils of
autocratic governments. Its author did not perceive that the radical
evil in France was irresponsible power. It needed the reign of Louis XV.
and the failure of attempts at reform under his successor to bring this
home. The Abbe even thought that an increase of the despotic authority
of the government was desirable, provided this were accompanied by an
increase in the enlightenment and virtue of its ministers.
Though he seems not to have been familiar with Cruce's work, he didn't claim to be original. He framed his proposal under a respected name, calling it the Project of Henry the Great to Achieve Lasting Peace, as explained by the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. This refers to the "great design" attributed to Henry IV by Sully, which aimed to reduce Austria's power: a federation of the Christian States of Europe organized in groups and overseen by a sovereign Diet, which would manage international affairs and resolve disputes. [Footnote: It is described in Sully's Memoires, Book XXX.] Saint-Pierre, disregarding that Sully's goal was to eliminate a competing power, used it as the basis for his own scheme of a permanent alliance among all the sovereigns of Europe to ensure mutual preservation of their states and to reject war as a way of resolving conflicts. He outlined the terms of such an alliance and showed each European power that it was clearly in their interest to sign the agreements. Once signed, a golden age would commence. [Footnote: For Sully's grand Design, compare the interesting article of Sir Geoffrey Butler in the Edinburgh Review, October 1919.]

It's not our intent here to critique this plan, which the author earnestly presented to statesmen with his typical straightforwardness. It's easy to criticize it with the benefit of hindsight, realizing that if the impossible had occurred and the plan had been both attempted and successful, it might have led to more suffering than all the wars since then. This was because it relied on maintaining the political status quo in Europe. It assumed that the existing distribution of power was perfectly acceptable and aligned with the best interests of all affected peoples. While it would have prevented the Partition of Poland, it would have continued the Austrian oppression of Italians. The project also ensured that sovereigns maintained their authority and protected against civil wars, based on the belief that current constitutions were fundamentally just. If the plan had been realized, it would have perpetuated all the issues of autocratic governments. Its author failed to understand that the core problem in France was irresponsible power. It took the reign of Louis XV and the unsuccessful reform attempts under his successor to highlight this. The Abbe even suggested that an increase in the despotic power of the government was acceptable, provided it came with greater enlightenment and virtue from its leaders.

In 1729 he published an abridgment of his scheme, and here he looks beyond its immediate results to its value for distant posterity. No one, he says, can imagine or foresee the advantages which such an alliance of European states will yield to Europe five hundred years after its establishment. Now we can see the first beginnings, but it is beyond the powers of the human mind to discern its infinite effects in the future. It may produce results more precious than anything hitherto experienced by man. He supports his argument by observing that our primitive ancestors could not foresee the improvements which the course of ages would bring in their rudimentary arrangements for securing social order.

In 1729, he released a shortened version of his plan, and here he looks beyond its immediate outcomes to its significance for future generations. No one, he argues, can imagine or predict the benefits that such an alliance of European states will bring to Europe five hundred years after it's formed. We can recognize the initial steps now, but it's beyond what anyone can comprehend to see its endless effects down the line. It might lead to results more valuable than anything humanity has experienced so far. He backs his point by noting that our early ancestors couldn’t foresee the advancements that time would bring to their basic methods of ensuring social order.

3.

3.

It is characteristic that the Abbe de Saint-Pierre's ideas about Progress were a by-product of his particular schemes. In 1773 he published a Project to Perfect the Government of States, and here he sketched his view of the progressive course of civilisation. The old legend of the golden age, when men were perfectly happy, succeeded by the ages of silver, bronze, and iron, exactly reverses the truth of history. The age of iron came first, the infancy of society, when men were poor and ignorant of the arts; it is the present condition of the savages of Africa and America. The age of bronze ensued, in which there was more security, better laws, and the invention of the most necessary arts began. There followed the age of silver, and Europe has not yet emerged from it. Our reason has indeed reached the point of considering how war may be abolished, and is thus approaching the golden age of the future; but the art of government and the general regulation of society, notwithstanding all the improvements of the past, is still in its infancy. Yet all that is needed is a short series of wise reigns in our European states to reach the age of gold or, in other words, a paradise on earth.

It’s notable that Abbe de Saint-Pierre's ideas about Progress were a result of his specific plans. In 1773, he published a Project to Perfect the Government of States, outlining his perspective on the advancement of civilization. The old story of a golden age, when people were completely happy, followed by the ages of silver, bronze, and iron, completely flips the truth of history. The iron age came first, representing the early days of society, where people were poor and unaware of the arts; it mirrors the current state of some tribes in Africa and America. Next was the bronze age, characterized by greater security, improved laws, and the beginning of essential arts. Then came the silver age, from which Europe has yet to fully progress. We’ve indeed reached a point where we can contemplate the end of war, getting closer to the future's golden age; however, the art of governance and the overall organization of society, despite all past advancements, is still in its early stages. Yet, all we need is a brief period of wise leadership in our European nations to achieve the golden age or, in other words, a paradise on earth.

A few wise reigns. The Abbe shared the illusion of many that government is omnipotent and can bestow happiness on men. The imperfections of governments were, he was convinced, chiefly due to the fact that hitherto the ablest intellects had not been dedicated to the study of the science of governing. The most essential part of his project was the formation of a Political Academy which should do for politics what the Academy of Sciences did for the study of nature, and should act as an advisory body to ministers of state on all questions of the public welfare. If this proposal and some others were adopted, he believed that the golden age would not long be delayed. These observations—hardly more than obiter dicta—show that Saint-Pierre's general view of the world was moulded by a conception of civilisation progressing towards a goal of human happiness. In 1737 he published a special work to explain this conception: the Observations on the Continuous Progress of Universal Reason.

A few wise reigns. The Abbe shared the belief of many that government is all-powerful and can bring happiness to people. He was convinced that the flaws in governments mainly stemmed from the fact that the most capable minds had not been focused on studying the art of governance. The key part of his plan was to create a Political Academy that would do for politics what the Academy of Sciences did for the study of nature and serve as an advisory body to government leaders on all matters related to the public good. If this proposal and a few others were implemented, he believed that a golden age would soon follow. These remarks—barely more than side comments—indicate that Saint-Pierre's overall perspective on the world was shaped by a belief in civilization moving towards a goal of human happiness. In 1737, he published a specific work to elaborate on this idea: the Observations on the Continuous Progress of Universal Reason.

He recurs to the comparison of the life of collective humanity to that of an individual, and, like Fontenelle and Terrasson, accentuates the point where the analogy fails. We may regard our race as composed of all the nations that have been and will be—and assign to it different ages. For instance, when the race is ten thousand years old a century will be what a single year is in the life of a centenarian. But there is this prodigious difference. The mortal man grows old and loses his reason and happiness through the enfeeblement of his bodily machine; whereas the human race, by the perpetual and infinite succession of generations, will find itself at the end of ten thousand years more capable of growing in wisdom and happiness than it was at the end of four thousand.

He compares the life of humanity as a whole to that of an individual and, like Fontenelle and Terrasson, highlights where the analogy breaks down. We can think of our species as made up of all the nations that have existed and will exist—and assign it different ages. For example, when humanity is ten thousand years old, a century will be like a single year in the life of a hundred-year-old person. But there's a huge difference. A mortal man ages and loses his reason and happiness due to the decline of his physical body; however, the human race, through the continuous and infinite succession of generations, will find itself at the end of ten thousand years more capable of growing in wisdom and happiness than it was at the end of four thousand.

At present the race is apparently not more than seven or eight thousand years old, and is only "in the infancy of human reason," compared with what it will be five or six thousand years hence. And when that stage is reached, it will only have entered on what we may call its first youth, when we consider what it will be when it is a hundred thousand years older still, continually growing in reason and wisdom.

Right now, humanity seems to be just seven or eight thousand years old, and we are only "in the early stages of human reason," compared to what we will be in five or six thousand years. When we get to that point, it will only be in what we could call its first youth, especially when we think about what it will be like a hundred thousand years from now, continuously developing in reason and wisdom.

Here we have for the first time, expressed in definite terms, the vista of an immensely long progressive life in front of humanity. Civilisation is only in its infancy. Bacon, like Pascal, had conceived it to be in its old age. Fontenelle and Perrault seem to have regarded it as in its virility; they set no term to its duration, but they did not dwell on future prospects. The Abbe was the first to fix his eye on the remote destinies of the race and name immense periods of time. It did not occur to him to consider that our destinies are bound up with those of the solar system, and that it is useless to operate with millennial periods of progress unless you are assured of a corresponding stability in the cosmic environment.

Here, for the first time, we see clearly the idea of a very long and progressive future for humanity. Civilization is just starting out. Bacon, like Pascal, thought it was already old. Fontenelle and Perrault seemed to believe it was in its prime; they didn’t set a limit on how long it would last, but they didn’t focus on future possibilities. The Abbe was the first to look at the far-off futures of humanity and mention vast periods of time. He didn't think about the fact that our futures are connected to those of the solar system, and that it’s pointless to talk about thousands of years of progress unless we can be sure that the cosmic environment remains stable.

As a test of the progress which reason has already made, Saint-Pierre asserts that a comparison of the best English and French works on morals and politics with the best works of Plato and Aristotle proves that the human race has made a sensible advance. But that advance would have been infinitely greater were it not that three general obstacles retarded it and even, at some times and in some countries, caused a retrogression. These obstacles were wars, superstition, and the Jealousy of rulers who feared that progress in the science of politics would be dangerous to themselves. In consequence of these impediments it was only in the time of Bodin and Bacon that the human race began to start anew from the point which it had reached in the days of Plato and Aristotle.

As a measure of the progress that reason has already made, Saint-Pierre claims that comparing the best English and French works on morals and politics with the top works of Plato and Aristotle shows that humanity has made a meaningful advancement. However, that advancement would have been much greater if it weren't for three main obstacles that slowed it down and even, at certain times and in certain places, caused a setback. These obstacles were wars, superstition, and the jealousy of rulers who feared that progress in political science would threaten their own power. Because of these barriers, it wasn't until the time of Bodin and Bacon that humanity began to renew itself from the point it had reached in the days of Plato and Aristotle.

Since then the rate of progress has been accelerated, and this has been due to several causes. The expansion of sea commerce has produced more wealth, and wealth means greater leisure, and more writers and readers. In the second place, mathematics and physics are more studied in colleges, and their tendency is to liberate us from subjection to the authority of the ancients. Again, the foundation of scientific Academies has given facilities both for communicating and for correcting new discoveries; the art of printing provides a means for diffusing them; and, finally, the habit of writing in the vulgar tongue makes them accessible. The author might also have referred to the modern efforts to popularise science, in which his friend Fontenelle had been one of the leaders.

Since then, the pace of progress has picked up, and this is due to several reasons. The growth of maritime trade has created more wealth, and wealth brings more leisure time, resulting in more writers and readers. Additionally, mathematics and physics are studied more in colleges, and their focus helps free us from reliance on the authority of the ancients. Furthermore, the establishment of scientific academies has made it easier to share and correct new discoveries; the printing press offers a way to spread them; and, finally, writing in everyday language makes information accessible. The author could have also mentioned the modern efforts to make science popular, in which his friend Fontenelle was a key figure.

He proceeds, in this connection, to lay down a rather doubtful principle, that in any two countries the difference in enlightenment between the lowest classes will correspond to the difference between the most highly educated classes. At present, he says, Paris and London are the places where human wisdom has reached the most advanced stage. It is certain that the ten best men of the highest class at Ispahan or Constantinople will be inferior in their knowledge of politics and ethics to the ten most distinguished sages of Paris or London. And this will be true in all classes. The thirty most intelligent children of the age of fourteen at Paris will be more enlightened than the thirty most intelligent children of the same age at Constantinople, and the same proportional difference will be true of the lowest classes of the two cities.

He goes on to express a somewhat questionable idea that in any two countries, the gap in knowledge between the lowest classes will reflect the gap between the most educated classes. Right now, he states, Paris and London are the places where human understanding has developed the furthest. It's clear that the ten most knowledgeable people in Ispahan or Constantinople will be less informed about politics and ethics than the ten leading thinkers from Paris or London. This applies across all classes. The thirty smartest fourteen-year-olds in Paris will have more knowledge than the thirty smartest fourteen-year-olds in Constantinople, and the same difference will hold true for the lowest classes in both cities.

But while the progress of speculative reason has been rapid, practical reason—the distinction is the Abbe's—has made little advance. In point of morals and general happiness the world is apparently much the same as ever. Our mediocre savants know twenty times as much as Socrates and Confucius, but our most virtuous men are not more virtuous than they. The growth of science has added much to the arts and conveniences of life, and to the sum of pleasures, and will add more. The progress in physical science is part of the progress of the "universal human reason," whose aim is the augmentation of our happiness. But there are two other sciences which are much more important for the promotion of happiness—Ethics and Politics—and these, neglected by men of genius, have made little way in the course of two thousand years. It is a grave misfortune that Descartes and Newton did not devote themselves to perfecting these sciences, so incomparably more useful for mankind than those in which they made their great discoveries. They fell into a prevailing error as to the comparative values of the various domains of knowledge, an error to which we must also ascribe the fact that while Academies of Sciences and Belles-Lettres exist there are no such institutions for Politics or Ethics.

But while the advancement of speculative reasoning has been quick, practical reasoning—the distinction made by the Abbe—has hardly progressed. In terms of morals and overall happiness, the world seems pretty much the same as it always has been. Our average scholars know way more than Socrates and Confucius did, but our most virtuous people aren't any more virtuous than they were. The growth of science has added a lot to the arts and comforts of life, and to the overall enjoyment we experience, and it will continue to do so. The advancements in physical science are part of the development of the "universal human reason," whose goal is to increase our happiness. However, there are two other fields that are far more crucial for promoting happiness—Ethics and Politics—and these, overlooked by talented thinkers, have made little progress over the last two thousand years. It's a significant loss that Descartes and Newton didn't focus on improving these fields, which are so much more beneficial for humanity than the ones where they made their groundbreaking discoveries. They fell into a common mistake regarding the relative importance of different areas of knowledge, a mistake that also explains why, while there are Academies of Sciences and Literature, there are no similar institutions for Politics or Ethics.

By these arguments he establishes to his own satisfaction that there are no irremovable obstacles to the Progress of the human race towards happiness, no hindrances that could not be overcome if governments only saw eye to eye with the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. Superstition is already on the decline; there would be no more wars if his simple scheme for permanent peace were adopted. Let the State immediately found Political and Ethical Academies; let the ablest men consecrate their talents to the science of government; and in a hundred years we shall make more progress than we should make in two thousand at the rate we are moving. If these things are done, human reason will have advanced so far in two or three millenniums that the wisest men of that age will be as far superior to the wisest of to-day as these are to the wisest African savages. This "perpetual and unlimited augmentation of reason" will one day produce an increase in human happiness which would astonish us more than our own civilisation would astonish the Kaffirs.

Through these arguments, he convincingly proves to himself that there are no permanent barriers to humanity's advancement towards happiness, and no obstacles that couldn't be overcome if governments aligned with the Abbe de Saint-Pierre's vision. Superstition is already fading; wars would cease if his straightforward plan for lasting peace were put into action. The State should promptly establish Political and Ethical Academies; the most talented individuals should dedicate their skills to the study of governance. If we do this, we will achieve more in a hundred years than we would in two thousand at our current pace. If these actions are taken, human reason will evolve so much in two or three thousand years that the wisest individuals of that future time will be far superior to today's smartest, just as today's wise are above the most enlightened African tribes. This "endless and limitless growth of reason" will eventually lead to a level of human happiness that will astonish us more than our own civilization would amaze the Kaffirs.

4.

4.

The Abbe de Saint-Pierre was indeed terribly at ease in confronting the deepest and most complex problems which challenge the intellect of man. He had no notion of their depth and complexity, and he lightly essayed them, treating human nature, as if it were an abstraction, by a method which he would doubtless have described as Cartesian. He was simply operating with the ideas which were all round him in a society saturated with Cartesianism,—supremacy of human reason, progressive enlightenment, the value of this life for its own sake, and the standard of utility. Given these ideas and the particular bias of his own mind, it required no great ingenuity to advance from the thought of the progress of science to the thought of progress in man's moral nature and his social conditions. The omnipotence of governments to mould the destinies of peoples, the possibility of the creation of enlightened governments, and the indefinite progress of enlightenment—all articles of his belief—were the terms of an argument of the sorites form, which it was a simple matter to develop in his brief treatise.

The Abbe de Saint-Pierre was remarkably comfortable tackling the deepest and most complex problems that challenge human thought. He had no real understanding of their depth and intricacy, and he approached them lightly, treating human nature as if it were just an idea, using a method he would likely call Cartesian. He was merely engaging with the concepts prevalent in a society steeped in Cartesian thought—emphasizing the supremacy of human reason, progressive enlightenment, the value of life for its own sake, and practicality. Given these ideas and his own mindset, it wasn’t difficult to connect the notion of scientific progress to the idea of progress in human morality and social conditions. The power of governments to shape the futures of their people, the potential for creating enlightened governments, and the endless possibility for enlightenment—all of which he believed—formed a straightforward argument he could easily lay out in his brief treatise.

But we must not do him injustice. He was a much more considerable thinker than posterity for a long time was willing to believe. It is easy to ridicule some of his projets, and dismiss him as a crank who was also somewhat of a bore. The truth, however, is that many of his schemes were sound and valuable. His economic ideas, which he thought out for himself, were in advance of his time, and he has even been described by a recent writer as "un contemporain egare au xviii siecle." Some of his financial proposals were put into practice by Turgot. But his significance in the development of the revolutionary ideas which were to gain control in the second half of the eighteenth century has hardly been appreciated yet, and it was imperfectly appreciated by his contemporaries.

But we shouldn't do him a disservice. He was a much more significant thinker than people for a long time were willing to acknowledge. It's easy to mock some of his ideas and dismiss him as an eccentric who was also a bit tedious. The reality, however, is that many of his plans were sound and valuable. His economic ideas, which he developed independently, were ahead of his time, and a recent writer has even described him as "an out-of-place contemporary in the 18th century." Some of his financial proposals were implemented by Turgot. However, his importance in the development of the revolutionary ideas that took hold in the second half of the 18th century has barely been recognized, and his contemporaries appreciated him only to a limited extent.

It is easy to see why. His theories are buried in his multitudinous projets. If, instead of working out the details of endless particular reforms, he had built up general theories of government and society, economics and education, they might have had no more intrinsic value, but he would have been recognised as the precursor of the Encyclopaedists.

It’s easy to understand why. His theories are hidden in his countless projects. If, instead of focusing on the details of endless specific reforms, he had developed broad theories of government and society, economics, and education, they might not have had any more inherent value, but he would have been acknowledged as a forerunner of the Encyclopaedists.

For his principles are theirs. The omnipotence of government and laws to mould the morals of peoples; the subordination of all knowledge to the goddess of utility; the deification of human reason; and the doctrine of Progress. His crude utilitarianism led him to depreciate the study of mathematical and physical sciences—notwithstanding his veneration for Descartes—as comparatively useless, and he despised the fine arts as waste of time and toil which might be better spent. He had no knowledge of natural science and he had no artistic susceptibility. The philosophers of the Encyclopaedia did not go so far, but they tended in this direction. They were cold and indifferent towards speculative science, and they were inclined to set higher value on artisans than on artists.

For his principles align with theirs. The total power of government and laws to shape people's morals; the prioritization of all knowledge for practical use; the idolization of human reason; and the belief in Progress. His basic utilitarianism made him undervalue the study of math and science—despite his respect for Descartes—considering them relatively useless, and he viewed the fine arts as a waste of time and effort that could be better spent elsewhere. He lacked knowledge of natural science and had no appreciation for art. The philosophers of the Encyclopedia didn’t go as far, but they leaned in that direction. They were cold and indifferent towards speculative science and valued artisans more than artists.

In his religious ideas the Abbe differed from Voltaire and the later social philosophers in one important respect, but this very difference was a consequence of his utilitarianism. Like them he was a Deist, as we saw; he had imbibed the spirit of Bayle and the doctrine of the English rationalists, which were penetrating French society during the later part of his life. His God, however, was more than the creator and organiser of the Encyclopaedists, he was also the "Dieu vengeur et remunerateur" in whom Voltaire believed. But here his faith was larger than Voltaire's. For while Voltaire referred the punishments and rewards to this life, the Abbe believed in the immortality of the soul, in heaven and hell. He acknowledged that immortality could not be demonstrated, that it was only probable, but he clung to it firmly and even intolerantly. It is clear from his writings that his affection for this doctrine was due to its utility, as an auxiliary to the magistrate and the tutor, and also to the consideration that Paradise would add to the total of human happiness.

In his religious beliefs, the Abbe differed from Voltaire and later social philosophers in one key way, but this distinction was a result of his utilitarian views. Like them, he was a Deist, as we noted; he had absorbed the ideas of Bayle and the teachings of the English rationalists, which were influencing French society during the later part of his life. However, his concept of God went beyond the creator and organizer of the Encyclopaedists; he also believed in a "vengeful and rewarding God," a belief that Voltaire held. Yet, his faith was broader than Voltaire's. While Voltaire associated punishments and rewards with this life, the Abbe had faith in the immortality of the soul, in heaven and hell. He recognized that immortality couldn’t be proven and was only likely, but he held onto it firmly and even dogmatically. His writings clearly show that his fondness for this belief stemmed from its practicality as a support for authorities and educators, as well as the idea that Paradise would contribute to overall human happiness.

But though his religion had more articles, he was as determined a foe of "superstition" as Voltaire, Diderot, and the rest. He did not go so far as they in aggressive rationalism—he belonged to an older generation—but his principles were the same.

But even though his beliefs had more points, he was just as fierce an opponent of "superstition" as Voltaire, Diderot, and the others. He didn't take it as far as they did with their aggressive rationalism—he was from an older generation—but his principles were the same.

The Abbe de Saint-Pierre thus represents the transition from the earlier Cartesianism, which was occupied with purely intellectual problems, to the later thought of the eighteenth century, which concentrated itself on social problems. He anticipated the "humanistic" spirit of the Encyclopaedists, who were to make man, in a new sense, the centre of the world. He originated, or at least was the first to proclaim, the new creed of man's destinies, indefinite social progress.

The Abbe de Saint-Pierre represents the shift from earlier Cartesianism, which focused solely on intellectual issues, to the later ideas of the eighteenth century that centered on social issues. He anticipated the "humanistic" approach of the Encyclopaedists, who would later make humanity, in a new way, the center of the universe. He originated, or at least was the first to declare, the new belief in humanity's destinies and the notion of endless social progress.





CHAPTER VII. NEW CONCEPTIONS OF HISTORY: MONTESQUIEU, VOLTAIRE, TURGOT

The theory of human Progress could not be durably established by abstract arguments, or on the slender foundations laid by the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. It must ultimately be judged by the evidence afforded by history, and it is not accidental that, contemporaneously with the advent of this idea, the study of history underwent a revolution. If Progress was to be more than the sanguine dream of an optimist it must be shown that man's career on earth had not been a chapter of accidents which might lead anywhere or nowhere, but is subject to discoverable laws which have determined its general route, and will secure his arrival at the desirable place. Hitherto a certain order and unity had been found in history by the Christian theory of providential design and final causes. New principles of order and unity were needed to replace the principles which rationalism had discredited. Just as the advance of science depended on the postulate that physical phenomena are subject to invariable laws, so if any conclusions were to be drawn from history some similar postulate as to social phenomena was required.

The theory of human progress couldn't be firmly established through abstract arguments or the flimsy ideas put forth by the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. Ultimately, it must be assessed based on historical evidence, and it’s no coincidence that, around the same time this idea emerged, the study of history experienced a transformation. If progress was meant to be more than just an optimistic fantasy, it had to be demonstrated that humanity's journey on earth was not just a series of random events leading to uncertain ends but rather governed by discoverable laws that shape its overall path and ensure it reaches a favorable outcome. Until now, a certain order and unity in history were found through the Christian notion of divine purpose and ultimate reasons. New principles of order and unity were necessary to replace the ideas that rationalism had undermined. Just as scientific advancement relied on the assumption that physical phenomena follow consistent laws, any conclusions drawn from history would require a similar assumption regarding social phenomena.

It was thus in harmony with the general movement of thought that about the middle of the eighteenth century new lines of investigation were opened leading to sociology, the history of civilisation, and the philosophy of history. Montesquieu's De l'esprit des lois, which may claim to be the parent work of modern social science, Voltaire's Essai sur les moeurs, and Turgot's plan of a Histoire universelle begin a new era in man's vision of the past.

It was in line with the overall shift in thinking that around the middle of the eighteenth century, new areas of study emerged, paving the way for sociology, the history of civilization, and the philosophy of history. Montesquieu's *De l'esprit des lois*, which can be considered the foundational text of modern social science, Voltaire's *Essai sur les moeurs*, and Turgot's plan for a *Histoire universelle* herald a new era in humanity's understanding of the past.

1.

Please provide the text you would like me to modernize.

Montesquieu was not among the apostles of the idea of Progress. It never secured any hold upon his mind. But he had grown up in the same intellectual climate in which that idea was produced; he had been nurtured both on the dissolving, dialectic of Bayle, and on the Cartesian enunciation of natural law. And his work contributed to the service, not of the doctrine of the past, but of the doctrine of the future.

Montesquieu was not one of the champions of the idea of Progress. It never really resonated with him. However, he was raised in the same intellectual environment where that idea emerged; he was influenced both by the critical thinking of Bayle and the Cartesian concept of natural law. His work contributed not to the ideas of the past but to those of the future.

For he attempted to extend the Cartesian theory to social facts. He laid down that political, like physical, phenomena are subject to general laws. He had already conceived this, his most striking and important idea, when he wrote the Considerations on the Greatness and Decadence of the Romans (1734), in which he attempted to apply it:

For he tried to apply the Cartesian theory to social facts. He stated that political phenomena, like physical ones, are governed by general laws. He had already developed this, his most notable and significant idea, when he wrote the Considerations on the Greatness and Decadence of the Romans (1734), where he sought to implement it:

It is not Fortune who governs the world, as we see from the history of the Romans. There are general causes, moral or physical, which operate in every monarchy, raise it, maintain it, or overthrow it; all that occurs is subject to these causes; and if a particular cause, like the accidental result of a battle, has ruined a state, there was a general cause which made the downfall of this state ensue from a single battle. In a word, the principal movement (l'allure principale) draws with it all the particular occurrences.

It’s not luck that runs the world, as we can see from Roman history. There are underlying causes, whether moral or physical, that influence every monarchy, lifting it up, keeping it going, or bringing it down; everything that happens is influenced by these causes. If a specific event, like the outcome of a battle, has led to the fall of a state, there was a broader reason behind why that state collapsed because of just one battle. In short, the main force drives all the specific events.

But if this excludes Fortune it also dispenses with Providence, design, and final causes; and one of the effects of the Considerations which Montesquieu cannot have overlooked was to discredit Bossuet's treatment of history.

But if this leaves out Fortune, it also ignores Providence, design, and ultimate causes; and one of the effects of the Considerations that Montesquieu must have noticed was to undermine Bossuet's approach to history.

The Esprit des lois appeared fourteen years later. Among books which have exercised a considerable influence on thought few are more disappointing to a modern reader. The author had not the gift of what might be called logical architecture, and his work produces the effect of a collection of ideas which he was unable to co-ordinate in the clarity of a system. A new principle, the operation of general causes, is enthroned; but, beyond the obvious distinction of physical and moral, they are not classified. We have no guarantee that the moral causes are fully enumerated, and those which are original are not distinguished from those which are derived. The general cause which Montesquieu impresses most clearly on the reader's mind is that of physical environment—geography and climate.

The Esprit des lois was published fourteen years later. Among the books that have had a significant impact on thought, few are more underwhelming to a modern reader. The author lacked what could be called logical structure, and his work feels like a collection of ideas that he couldn't organize into a clear system. A new principle, the operation of general causes, is established; however, apart from the obvious distinction between physical and moral causes, they aren’t classified. We have no assurance that all moral causes are accounted for, and the original causes aren’t separated from the derived ones. The general cause that Montesquieu makes most evident to the reader is that of physical environment—geography and climate.

The influence of climate on civilisation was not a new idea. In modern times, as we have seen, it was noticed by Bodin and recognised by Fontenelle. The Abbe de Saint-Pierre applied it to explain the origin of the Mohammedan religion, and the Abbe Du Bos in his Reflexions on Poetry and Painting maintained that climate helps to determine the epochs of art and science. Chardin in his Travels, a book which Montesquieu studied, had also appreciated its importance. But Montesquieu drew general attention to it, and since he wrote, geographical conditions have been recognised by all inquirers as an influential factor in the development of human societies. His own discussion of the question did not result in any useful conclusions. He did not determine the limits of the action of physical conditions, and a reader hardly knows whether to regard them as fundamental or accessory, as determining the course of civilisation or only perturbing it. "Several things govern men," he says, "climate, religion, laws, precepts of government, historical examples, morals, and manners, whence is formed as their result a general mind (esprit general)." This co-ordination of climate with products of social life is characteristic of his unsystematic thought. But the remark which the author went on to make, that there is always a correlation between the laws of a people and its esprit general, was important. It pointed to the theory that all the products of social life are closely interrelated.

The idea that climate impacts civilization is not new. In recent times, as we've seen, it was noted by Bodin and acknowledged by Fontenelle. The Abbe de Saint-Pierre used it to explain the origins of the Mohammedan religion, and the Abbe Du Bos, in his *Reflections on Poetry and Painting*, argued that climate influences the periods of art and science. Chardin, in his *Travels*, a book studied by Montesquieu, also recognized its significance. However, Montesquieu brought broader attention to the issue, and since his writing, geographical conditions have been acknowledged by all researchers as a significant factor in the development of human societies. His discussion did not yield any practical conclusions, as he did not define the extent of the impact of physical conditions. Readers often struggle to determine whether to view them as fundamental or secondary, as either driving the course of civilization or merely influencing it. "Several things govern men," he states, "climate, religion, laws, rules of government, historical examples, morals, and manners, which collectively create a general mindset (esprit general)." This connection of climate with social life is typical of his unstructured thinking. Yet, his subsequent observation that there is always a link between a people's laws and its esprit general was significant. It suggested that all aspects of social life are closely connected.

In Montesquieu's time people were under the illusion that legislation has an almost unlimited power to modify social conditions. We have seen this in the case of Saint-Pierre. Montesquieu's conception of general laws should have been an antidote to this belief. It had however less effect on his contemporaries than we might have expected, and they found more to their purpose in what he said of the influence of laws on manners. There may be something in Comte's suggestion that he could not give his conception any real consistency or vigour, just because he was himself unconsciously under the influence of excessive faith in the effects of legislative action.

In Montesquieu's time, people were under the false impression that legislation had almost unlimited power to change social conditions. We saw this in the case of Saint-Pierre. Montesquieu's idea of general laws should have countered this belief, but it actually had less impact on his contemporaries than we might expect. Instead, they were more interested in what he said about the influence of laws on social behavior. Comte suggested that Montesquieu couldn’t give his ideas real consistency or strength because he was unknowingly influenced by an excessive belief in the effects of legislative action.

A fundamental defect in Montesquieu's treatment of social phenomena is that he abstracted them from their relations in time. It was his merit to attempt to explain the correlation of laws and institutions with historical circumstances, but he did not distinguish or connect stages of civilisation. He was inclined to confound, as Sorel has observed, all periods and constitutions. Whatever be the value of the idea of Progress, we may agree with Comte that, if Montesquieu had grasped it, he would have produced a more striking work. His book announces a revolution in the study of political science, but in many ways belongs itself to the pre-Montesquieu era.

A major flaw in Montesquieu's approach to social issues is that he separated them from their historical context. While he made an effort to explain how laws and institutions are linked to historical events, he failed to differentiate or relate the various stages of civilization. As Sorel pointed out, he tended to mix up all periods and types of government. Regardless of how valuable the concept of Progress may be, we can agree with Comte that if Montesquieu had truly understood it, his work would have been much more impactful. His book signals a shift in the study of political science, yet in many ways, it still reflects the era before Montesquieu.

2.

2.

In the same years in which Montesquieu was busy on the composition of the Esprit des lois, Voltaire was writing his Age of Louis XIV. and his Essay on the Manners and Mind of Nations, and on the Principal Facts of History from Charlemagne to the Death of Louis XIII. The former work, which everybody reads still, appeared in 1751. Parts of the Essay, which has long since fallen into neglect, were published in the Mercure de France between 1745 and 1751; it was issued complete in 1756, along with the Age of Louis XIV., which was its continuation. If we add the Precis of the Reign of Louis XV. (1769), and observe that the Introduction and first fourteen chapters of the Essay sketch the history of the world before Charlemagne, and that China, India, and America are included in the survey, Voltaire's work amounts to a complete survey of the civilisation of the world from the earliest times to his own. If Montesquieu founded social science, Voltaire created the history of civilisation, and the Essay, for all its limitations, stands out as one of the considerable books of the century.

In the same years when Montesquieu was working on the Esprit des lois, Voltaire was writing his Age of Louis XIV and his Essay on the Manners and Mind of Nations, as well as the Principal Facts of History from Charlemagne to the Death of Louis XIII. The former work, which everyone still reads today, was published in 1751. Parts of the Essay, which has long been overlooked, were released in the Mercure de France between 1745 and 1751; it was published in full in 1756, along with the Age of Louis XIV, which continued the discussion. If we include the Precis of the Reign of Louis XV (1769) and note that the Introduction and first fourteen chapters of the Essay outline world history before Charlemagne, covering China, India, and America, Voltaire’s work provides a comprehensive overview of world civilization from ancient times to his era. If Montesquieu established social science, Voltaire created the history of civilization, and despite its limitations, the Essay stands out as one of the significant books of the century.

In his Age of Louis XIV. he announced that his object was "to paint not the actions of a single man, but the mind of men (l'esprit des hommes) in the most enlightened age that had ever been," and that "the progress of the arts and sciences" was an essential part of his subject. In the same way he proposed in the Essay to trace "l'histoire de l'esprit humain," not the details of facts, and to show by what steps man advanced "from the barbarous rusticity" of the times of Charlemagne and his successors "to the politeness of our own." To do this, he said, was really to write the history of opinion, for all the great successive social and political changes which have transformed the world were due to changes of opinion. Prejudice succeeded prejudice, error followed error; "at last, with time men came to correct their ideas and learn to think."

In his Age of Louis XIV, he stated that his goal was "to depict not the actions of one individual, but the mindset of people (l'esprit des hommes) in the most enlightened era that ever existed," and that "the advancement of the arts and sciences" was a crucial part of his subject. Similarly, he aimed in the Essay to outline "l'histoire de l'esprit humain," not the specifics of events, and to demonstrate how humanity progressed "from the barbaric simplicity" of the times of Charlemagne and his successors "to the refinement of our own." He argued that this was essentially to write the history of opinion, as all the major social and political shifts that have changed the world stemmed from changes in thought. Prejudice followed prejudice, and error came after error; "eventually, over time, people began to correct their ideas and learn to think."

The motif of the book is, briefly, that wars and religions have been the great obstacles to the progress of humanity, and that if they were abolished, with the prejudices which engender them, the world would rapidly improve.

The main idea of the book is that wars and religions have been the major barriers to humanity's progress, and if they were eliminated, along with the prejudices that create them, the world would quickly get better.

"We may believe," he says, "that reason and industry will always progress more and more; that the useful arts will be improved; that of the evils which have afflicted men, prejudices, which are not their least scourge, will gradually disappear among all those who govern nations, and that philosophy, universally diffused, will give some consolation to human nature for the calamities which it will experience in all ages."

"We might believe," he says, "that reason and hard work will keep advancing; that practical skills will improve; that the harmful issues that have affected humanity, like prejudices, which are among the most damaging threats, will slowly fade away among all those who lead nations, and that widespread philosophy will provide some comfort to human nature for the hardships it will face throughout time."

This indeed is not the tone of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. Voltaire's optimism was always tempered with cynicism. But the idea of Progress is there, though moderately conceived. And it is based on the same principle—universal reason implanted in man, which "subsists in spite of all the passions which make war on it, in spite of all the tyrants who would drown it in blood, in spite of the imposters who would annihilate it by superstition." And this was certainly his considered view. His common sense prevented him from indulging in Utopian speculations about the future; and his cynicism constantly led him to use the language of a pessimist. But at an early stage of his career he had taken up arms for human nature against that "sublime misanthrope" Pascal, who "writes against human nature almost as he wrote against the Jesuits"; and he returned to the attack at the end of his life. Now Pascal's Pensees enshrined a theory of life—the doctrine of original sin, the idea that the object of life is to prepare for death—which was sternly opposed to the spirit of Progress. Voltaire instinctively felt that this was an enemy that had to be dealt with. In a lighter vein he had maintained in a well-known poem, Le Mondain, [Footnote: 1756.] the value of civilisation and all its effects, including luxury, against those who regretted the simplicity of ancient times, the golden age of Saturn.

This is definitely not the perspective of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. Voltaire's optimism was always mixed with a bit of cynicism. However, the idea of Progress is present, though expressed cautiously. It's based on the principle of universal reason inherent in humanity, which "exists despite all the passions that wage war against it, despite all the tyrants who would drown it in blood, despite the frauds who would destroy it with superstition." This was certainly his considered perspective. His common sense kept him from getting lost in idealistic dreams about the future, and his cynicism often made him sound like a pessimist. But early in his career, he had fought for human nature against that "sublime misanthrope" Pascal, who "wrote against human nature almost as he wrote against the Jesuits"; and he revisited this argument later in life. Pascal’s Pensees encapsulated a theory of life—the doctrine of original sin, the belief that the aim of life is to prepare for death—which stood in stark contrast to the spirit of Progress. Voltaire instinctively recognized this as an adversary that needed to be confronted. In a lighter tone, he argued in a well-known poem, Le Mondain, [Footnote: 1756.] for the value of civilization and all its benefits, including luxury, against those who longed for the simplicity of ancient times, the golden age of Saturn.

  O le bon temps que ce siecle de fer!
O the good times that this iron century!

Life in Paris, London, or Rome to-day is infinitely preferable to life in the garden of Eden.

Life in Paris, London, or Rome today is infinitely better than life in the Garden of Eden.

  D'un bon vin frais ou la mousse ou la seve
   Ne gratta point le triste gosier d'Eve.
   La soie et l'or ne brillaient point chez eux.
   Admirez-vous pour cela nos aieux?
   Il leur manquait l'industrie et l'aisance:
   Est-ce vertu? c'etait pure ignorance.
  D'un bon vin frais ou la mousse ou la seve  
   Ne gratta point le triste gosier d'Eve.  
   La soie et l'or ne brillaient point chez eux.  
   Admirez-vous pour cela nos aieux?  
   Il leur manquait l'industrie et l'aisance:  
   Est-ce vertu? c'etait pure ignorance.  

To return to the Essay, it flung down the gage of battle to that conception of the history of the world which had been brilliantly represented by Bossuet's Discours sur l'histoire universelle. This work was constantly in Voltaire's mind. He pointed out that it had no claim to be universal; it related only to four or five peoples, and especially the little Jewish nation which "was unknown to the rest of the world or justly despised," but which Bossuet made the centre of interest, as if the final cause of all the great empires of antiquity lay in their relations to the Jews. He had Bossuet in mind when he said "we will speak of the Jews as we would speak of Scythians or Greeks, weighing probabilities and discussing facts." In his new perspective the significance of Hebrew history is for the first time reduced to moderate limits.

To go back to the Essay, it threw down the challenge to that view of world history that had been expertly presented by Bossuet's Discours sur l'histoire universelle. This work was always on Voltaire's mind. He pointed out that it didn’t truly claim to be universal; it was focused only on four or five peoples, particularly the small Jewish nation which “was unknown to the rest of the world or unfairly looked down upon,” yet Bossuet made it the focal point, as if the main reason for all the great empires of the past depended on their relationships with the Jews. He had Bossuet in mind when he said, “we will talk about the Jews just like we would talk about Scythians or Greeks, weighing probabilities and discussing facts.” With his new outlook, the importance of Hebrew history is for the first time scaled down to reasonable limits.

But it was not only in this particular, though central, point that Voltaire challenged Bossuet's view. He eliminated final causes altogether, and Providence plays no part on his historical stage. Here his work reinforced the teaching of Montesquieu. Otherwise Montesquieu and Voltaire entirely differed in their methods. Voltaire concerned himself only with the causal enchainment of events and the immediate motives of men. His interpretation of history was confined to the discovery of particular causes; he did not consider the operation of those larger general causes which Montesquieu investigated. Montesquieu sought to show that the vicissitudes of societies were subject to law; Voltaire believed that events were determined by chance where they were not consciously guided by human reason. The element of chance is conspicuous even in legislation: "almost all laws have been instituted to meet passing needs, like remedies applied fortuitously, which have cured one patient and kill others."

But it wasn't just with this specific, though key, point that Voltaire challenged Bossuet's perspective. He completely discarded final causes, and Providence has no role in his historical narrative. In this regard, his work supported Montesquieu's teachings. However, Montesquieu and Voltaire were quite different in their approaches. Voltaire focused solely on the causal connection of events and the immediate motivations of people. His understanding of history was limited to identifying specific causes; he didn't consider the larger general causes that Montesquieu examined. Montesquieu aimed to demonstrate that the ups and downs of societies were governed by laws; Voltaire thought that events were determined by chance unless they were intentionally directed by human reason. The element of chance is evident even in legislation: "almost all laws have been created to address immediate needs, like remedies that are applied randomly, which may help one patient but harm others."

On Voltaire's theory, the development of humanity might at any moment have been diverted into a different course; but whatever course it took the nature of human reason would have ensured a progress in civilisation. Yet the reader of the Essay and Louis XIV. might well have come away with a feeling that the security of Progress is frail and precarious. If fortune has governed events, if the rise and fall of empires, the succession of religions, the revolutions of states, and most of the great crises of history were decided by accidents, is there any cogent ground for believing that human reason, the principle to which Voltaire attributes the advance of civilisation, will prevail in the long run? Civilisation has been organised here and there, now and then, up to a certain point; there have been eras of rapid progress, but how can we be sure that these are not episodes, themselves also fortuitous? For growth has been followed by decay, progress by regress; can it be said that history, authorises the conclusion that reason will ever gain such an ascendancy that the play of chance will no longer be able to thwart her will? Is such a conclusion more than a hope, unsanctioned by the data of past experience, merely one of the characteristics of the age of illumination?

On Voltaire's theory, humanity's development could have easily taken a different path at any moment; however, whatever path it followed, the nature of human reason would have driven progress in civilization. Still, readers of the Essay and Louis XIV. may leave with a sense that the certainty of Progress is weak and uncertain. If chance has played a role in events, if the rise and fall of empires, the succession of religions, the revolutions of states, and most of history's significant crises were determined by accidents, is there any solid reason to believe that human reason, which Voltaire sees as the key to civilization's advancement, will ultimately prevail? Civilization has been constructed here and there, at different times, and only to a certain extent; there have been periods of quick progress, but how can we be sure these aren’t just random events? Growth has often led to decline, progress to regression; can we truly say that history supports the idea that reason will ever dominate to the point that chance can no longer disrupt it? Is this belief more than just a hopeful thought, unsupported by historical evidence, merely a trait of the Enlightenment era?

Voltaire and Montesquieu thus raised fundamental questions of great moment for the doctrine of Progress, questions which belong to what was soon to be known as the Philosophy of History, a name invented by Voltaire, though hardly meant by him in the sense which it afterwards assumed.

Voltaire and Montesquieu brought up essential questions that were very important for the idea of Progress, questions that would soon be referred to as the Philosophy of History, a term created by Voltaire, although he likely didn't mean it in the way it came to be understood later.

3.

3.

Six years before Voltaire's Essay was published in its complete form a young man was planning a work on the same subject. Turgot is honourably remembered as an economist and administrator, but if he had ever written the Discourses on Universal History which he designed at the age of twenty-three his position in historical literature might have overshadowed his other claims to be remembered. We possess a partial sketch of its plan, which is supplemented by two lectures he delivered at the Sorbonne in 1750; so that we know his general conceptions.

Six years before Voltaire's Essay was published in its complete form, a young man was working on a project about the same topic. Turgot is well-remembered as an economist and administrator, but if he had ever written the Discourses on Universal History that he planned at the age of twenty-three, his place in historical literature might have overshadowed his other accomplishments. We have a partial outline of its plan, which is backed up by two lectures he gave at the Sorbonne in 1750, giving us insight into his general ideas.

He had assimilated the ideas of the Esprit des lois, and it is probable that he had read the parts of Voltaire's work which had appeared in a periodical. His work, like Voltaire's, was to be a challenge to Bossuet's view of history; his purpose was to trace the fortunes of the race in the light of the idea of Progress. He occasionally refers to Providence but this is no more than a prudent lip-service. Providence has no functions in his scheme. The part which it played in Bossuet is usurped by those general causes which he had learned from Montesquieu. But his systematic mind would have organised and classified the ideas which Montesquieu left somewhat confused. He criticised the inductions drawn in the Esprit des lois concerning the influence of climate as hasty and exaggerated; and he pointed out that the physical causes can only produce their effects by acting on "the hidden principles which contribute to form our mind and character." It follows that the psychical or moral causes are the first element to consider, and it is a fault of method to try to evaluate physical causes till we have exhausted the moral, and are certain that the phenomena cannot be explained by these alone. In other words, the study of the development of societies must be based on psychology; and for Turgot, as for all his progressive contemporaries, psychology meant the philosophy of Locke.

He had taken in the ideas from *The Spirit of the Laws*, and it's likely that he had read parts of Voltaire's work that appeared in a magazine. His work, like Voltaire's, aimed to challenge Bossuet's view of history; his goal was to examine the fate of humanity through the lens of Progress. He sometimes mentions Providence, but this is merely a cautious nod. Providence plays no role in his framework. The role it had in Bossuet's view is replaced by the broader causes he learned from Montesquieu. However, his systematic thinking would have organized and categorized the ideas that Montesquieu left somewhat unclear. He criticized the conclusions drawn in *The Spirit of the Laws* regarding climate's influence as rushed and overstated; he pointed out that physical causes can only produce their effects by influencing "the hidden principles that shape our minds and characters." Thus, the psychological or moral causes are the primary elements to consider, and it is methodologically incorrect to evaluate physical causes until we have fully examined the moral ones and are sure that the phenomena can't be explained solely by them. In other words, studying the development of societies should be grounded in psychology; and for Turgot, as for all his progressive contemporaries, psychology meant Locke's philosophy.

General necessary causes, therefore, which we should rather call conditions, have determined the course of history—the nature of man, his passions, and his reason, in the first place; and in the second, his environment,—geography and climate. But its course is a strict sequence of particular causes and effects, "which bind the state of the world (at a given moment) to all those which have preceded it." Turgot does not discuss the question of free-will, but his causal continuity does not exclude "the free action of great men." He conceives universal history as the progress of the human race advancing as an immense whole steadily, though slowly, through alternating periods of calm and disturbance towards greater perfection. The various units of the entire mass do not move with equal steps, because nature is not impartial with her gifts. Some men have talents denied to others, and the gifts of nature are sometimes developed by circumstances, sometimes left buried in obscurity. The inequalities in the march of nations are due to the infinite variety of circumstances; and these inequalities may be taken to prove that the world had a beginning, for in an eternal duration they would have disappeared.

General necessary causes, which we might better call conditions, have shaped the course of history—first, human nature, including our passions and reasoning; and second, our environment—like geography and climate. However, this course follows a strict chain of specific causes and effects, "which connect the state of the world (at any given moment) to all that has come before it." Turgot doesn’t address the issue of free will, but his idea of causal continuity doesn’t rule out "the free actions of influential individuals." He views universal history as the progress of humanity moving as a huge collective steadily, though slowly, through alternating times of peace and turmoil toward greater perfection. The different parts of this whole don’t progress at the same pace, since nature doesn’t equally distribute her gifts. Some people have talents that others lack, and nature's gifts can sometimes be brought out by circumstances, while at other times they remain hidden in obscurity. The disparities in the progress of nations arise from the countless variety of circumstances; these differences could indicate that the world had a beginning, because if it had existed eternally, those inequalities would have faded away.

But the development of human societies has not been guided by human reason. Men have not consciously made general happiness the end of their actions. They have been conducted by passion and ambition and have never known to what goal they were moving. For if reason had presided, progress would soon have been arrested. To avoid war peoples would have remained in isolation, and the race would have lived divided for ever into a multitude of isolated groups, speaking different tongues. All these groups would have been limited in the range of their ideas, stationary in science, art, and government, and would never have risen above mediocrity. The history of China is an example of the results of restricted intercourse among peoples. Thus the unexpected conclusion emerges, that without unreason and injustice there would have been no progress.

But the growth of human societies hasn’t been driven by human reason. People haven’t intentionally aimed for general happiness with their actions. Instead, they’ve been led by passion and ambition, often unaware of the destination they were heading toward. If reason had been in charge, progress would have quickly come to a halt. To avoid conflict, communities would have stayed isolated, and humanity would have remained broken into countless separate groups, speaking different languages. Each of these groups would have limited their ideas, stagnated in science, art, and government, and never risen above mediocrity. The history of China illustrates the outcomes of limited interaction among peoples. Thus, the surprising conclusion is that without irrationality and injustice, progress wouldn’t have happened.

It is hardly necessary to observe that this argument is untenable. The hypothesis assumes that reason is in control among the primitive peoples, and at the same time supposes that its power would completely disappear if they attempted to engage in peaceful intercourse. But though Turgot has put his point in an unconvincing form, his purpose was to show that as a matter of fact "the tumultuous and dangerous passions" have been driving-forces which have moved the world in a desirable direction till the time should come for reason to take the helm.

It’s hardly worth mentioning that this argument doesn’t hold up. The theory assumes that reason is in charge among primitive peoples, while also claiming that its influence would vanish entirely if they tried to interact peacefully. However, although Turgot presented his point in a weak way, his intention was to demonstrate that, in reality, “the tumultuous and dangerous passions” have been the driving forces that have steered the world in a positive direction until the moment comes for reason to take the lead.

Thus, while Turgot might have subscribed to Voltaire's assertion that history is largely "un ramas de crimes, de folies, et de malheurs," his view of the significance of man's sufferings is different and almost approaches the facile optimism of Pope—"whatever is, is right." He regards all the race's actual experiences as the indispensable mechanism of Progress, and does not regret its mistakes and calamities. Many changes and revolutions, he observes, may seem to have had most mischievous effects; yet every change has brought some advantage, for it has been a new experience and therefore has been instructive. Man advances by committing errors. The history of science shows (as Fontenelle had pointed out) that truth is reached over the ruins of false hypotheses.

Thus, while Turgot might have agreed with Voltaire's claim that history is mostly "a collection of crimes, madness, and misfortunes," his perspective on the importance of human suffering is different and almost resembles Pope's easy optimism—"whatever is, is right." He sees all of humanity's experiences as essential to Progress and does not regret its mistakes and disasters. Many changes and revolutions, he notes, might appear to have caused significant harm; yet every change has provided some benefit, as it has offered a new experience and thus has been enlightening. Humanity progresses by making mistakes. The history of science demonstrates (as Fontenelle pointed out) that truth is achieved by overcoming false hypotheses.

The difficulty presented by periods of decadence and barbarism succeeding epochs of enlightenment is met by the assertion that in such dark times the world has not stood still; there has really been a progression which, though relatively inconspicuous, is not unimportant. In the Middle Ages, which are the prominent case, there were improvements in mechanical arts, in commerce, in some of the habits of civil life, all of which helped to prepare the way for happier times. Here Turgot's view of history is sharply opposed to Voltaire's. He considers Christianity to have been a powerful agent of civilisation, not a hinderer or an enemy. Had he executed his design, his work might well have furnished a notable makeweight to the view held by Voltaire, and afterwards more judicially developed by Gibbon, that "the triumph of barbarism and religion" was a calamity for the world.

Periods of decline and chaos that follow times of enlightenment present challenges, but it's important to recognize that the world hasn’t come to a standstill; there has actually been progress that, while not always obvious, still matters. During the Middle Ages, which is the main example, there were advancements in technology, trade, and some aspects of daily life that all contributed to paving the way for better times ahead. Here, Turgot's perspective on history stands in stark contrast to Voltaire's. He views Christianity as a powerful force for civilization rather than a barrier or foe. If he had completed his vision, his work could have provided significant support to Voltaire's later, more measured argument, as expressed by Gibbon, that "the triumph of barbarism and religion" was a disaster for the world.

Turgot also propounded two laws of development. He observed that when a people is progressing, every step it takes causes an acceleration in the rate of progress. And he anticipated Comte's famous "law" of the three stages of intellectual evolution, though without giving it the extensive and fundamental significance which Comte claimed for it. "Before man understood the causal connection of physical phenomena, nothing was so natural as to suppose they were produced by intelligent beings, invisible and resembling ourselves; for what else would they have resembled?" That is Comte's theological stage. "When philosophers recognised the absurdity of the fables about the gods, but had not yet gained an insight into natural history, they thought to explain the causes of phenomena by abstract expressions such as essences and faculties." That is the metaphysical stage. "It was only at a later period, that by observing the reciprocal mechanical action of bodies hypotheses were formed which could be developed by mathematics and verified by experience." There is the positive stage. The observation assuredly does not possess the far-reaching importance which Comte attached to it; but whatever value it has, Turgot deserves the credit of having been the first to state it.

Turgot also proposed two laws of development. He noted that when a society is advancing, each step it takes speeds up the pace of progress. He anticipated Comte's well-known "law" of the three stages of intellectual evolution, although he didn't give it the extensive and fundamental significance that Comte did. "Before humans understood the causal connection of physical events, it was completely natural to think they were caused by intelligent beings, invisible and similar to ourselves; what else could they have resembled?" That reflects Comte's theological stage. "When philosophers recognized the absurdity of the myths about the gods, but hadn't yet gained insight into natural history, they tried to explain the causes of events through abstract concepts like essences and faculties." That is the metaphysical stage. "It was only later, by observing the interactive mechanical effects of bodies, that hypotheses were formed which could be developed mathematically and tested through experience." There's the positive stage. The observation certainly doesn't have the significant importance that Comte attributed to it; but whatever value it holds, Turgot should be credited as the first to express it.

The notes which Turgot made for his plan permit us to conjecture that his Universal History would have been a greater and more profound work than the Essay of Voltaire. It would have embodied in a digested form the ideas of Montesquieu to which Voltaire paid little attention, and the author would have elaborated the intimate connection and mutual interaction among all social phenomena—government and morals, religion, science, and arts. While his general thesis coincided with that of Voltaire—the gradual advance of humanity towards a state of enlightenment and reasonableness,—he made the idea of Progress more vital; for him it was an organising conception, just as the idea of Providence was for St. Augustine and Bossuet an organising conception, which gave history its unity and meaning. The view that man has throughout been blindly moving in the right direction is the counterpart of what Bossuet represented as a divine plan wrought out by the actions of men who are ignorant of it, and is sharply opposed to the views, of Voltaire and the other philosophers of the day who ascribed Progress exclusively to human reason consciously striving against ignorance and passion.

The notes Turgot made for his plan suggest that his Universal History would have been a more significant and insightful work than Voltaire's Essay. It would have systematically included the ideas of Montesquieu, which Voltaire largely overlooked, and would have detailed the close relationships and interactions among all social aspects—government, morals, religion, science, and the arts. While his main argument aligned with Voltaire's—humanity's gradual journey towards enlightenment and reason—he made the concept of Progress more dynamic; for him, it was an organizing principle, similar to how St. Augustine and Bossuet viewed the idea of Providence as a way to bring unity and meaning to history. The belief that humans have been blindly moving in the right direction aligns with Bossuet's portrayal of a divine plan shaped by the actions of people who are unaware of it and stands in stark contrast to Voltaire and other philosophers of the time, who attributed Progress solely to human reason consciously opposing ignorance and passion.





CHAPTER VIII. THE ENCYCLOPAEDISTS AND ECONOMISTS

1.

The intellectual movement which prepared French opinion for the Revolution and supplied the principles for reconstituting society may be described as humanistic in the sense that man was the centre of speculative interest.

The intellectual movement that set the stage for French thought leading up to the Revolution and laid down the principles for rebuilding society can be described as humanistic in that it placed man at the center of philosophical interest.

"One consideration especially that we ought never to lose from sight," says Diderot, "is that, if we ever banish a man, or the thinking and contemplative being, from above the surface of the earth, this pathetic and sublime spectacle of nature becomes no more than a scene of melancholy and silence... It is the presence of man that gives its interest to the existence of other beings... Why should we not make him a common centre?... Man is the single term from which we ought to set out." [Footnote: The passage from Diderot's article Encyclopedie is given as translated by Morley, Diderot, i, 145.] Hence psychology, morals, the structure of society, were the subjects which riveted attention instead of the larger supra-human problems which had occupied Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibnitz. It mattered little whether the universe was the best that could be constructed; what mattered was the relation of man's own little world to his will and capacities.

"One thing we should never forget," says Diderot, "is that if we ever remove a person, or the thinking and reflective being, from the surface of the earth, this beautiful and awe-inspiring display of nature turns into nothing more than a scene of sadness and silence... It's the presence of humans that makes the existence of other beings interesting... Why shouldn't we make him a common center?... Human beings are the starting point we should focus on." [Footnote: The passage from Diderot's article Encyclopedie is given as translated by Morley, Diderot, i, 145.] Therefore, psychology, ethics, and the structure of society became the main subjects of interest instead of the broader, supra-human issues that had engaged Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibnitz. It was of little importance whether the universe was the best it could be; what truly mattered was the connection between man's own small world and his desires and abilities.

Physical science was important only in so far as it could help social science and minister to the needs of man. The closest analogy to this development of thought is not offered by the Renaissance, to which the description HUMANISTIC has been conventionally appropriated, but rather by the age of illumination in Greece in the latter half of the fifth century B.C., represented by Protagoras, Socrates, and others who turned from the ultimate problems of the cosmos, hitherto the main study of philosophers, to man, his nature and his works.

Physical science mattered only to the extent that it could assist social science and meet human needs. The best comparison for this shift in thinking isn’t the Renaissance, which is typically labeled HUMANISTIC, but instead the Age of Enlightenment in Greece during the latter half of the fifth century B.C. This period was marked by thinkers like Protagoras and Socrates, who shifted their focus from the fundamental issues of the cosmos—previously the main interest of philosophers—to exploring humanity, its nature, and its achievements.

In this revised form of "anthropo-centrism" we see how the general movement of thought has instinctively adapted itself to the astronomical revolution. On the Ptolemaic system it was not incongruous or absurd that man, lord of the central domain in the universe, should regard himself as the most important cosmic creature. This is the view, implicit in the Christian scheme, which had been constructed on the old erroneous cosmology. When the true place of the earth was shown and man found himself in a tiny planet attached to one of innumerable solar worlds, his cosmic importance could no longer be maintained. He was reduced to the condition of an insect creeping on a "tas de boue," which Voltaire so vividly illustrated in Micromegas. But man is resourceful; [words in Greek]. Displaced, along with his home, from the centre of things, he discovers a new means of restoring his self-importance; he interprets his humiliation as a deliverance. Finding himself in an insignificant island floating in the immensity of space, he decides that he is at last master of his own destinies; he can fling away the old equipment of final causes, original sin, and the rest; he can construct his own chart and, bound by no cosmic scheme, he need take the universe into account only in so far as he judges it to be to his own profit. Or, if he is a philosopher, he may say that, after all, the universe for him is built out of his own sensations, and that by virtue of this relativity "anthropo-centrism" is restored in a new and more effective form.

In this updated version of "anthropo-centrism," we see how the overall movement of thought has instinctively adapted to the astronomical revolution. In the Ptolemaic system, it wasn't unreasonable or ridiculous for humans, as the rulers of the central domain in the universe, to see themselves as the most significant cosmic beings. This view, implied in the Christian framework, was based on the outdated cosmology. When the true position of the Earth was revealed and humans found themselves on a tiny planet among countless solar systems, their cosmic significance could no longer hold up. They were reduced to the status of an insect crawling on a "tas de boue," which Voltaire vividly depicted in Micromegas. But humans are adaptable; [words in Greek]. Displaced, along with their home, from the center of everything, they discover a new way to reclaim their self-importance; they interpret their humiliation as a liberation. Finding themselves on an inconsequential island in the vastness of space, they decide they are finally in control of their own destinies; they can discard the old notions of final causes, original sin, and the rest; they can create their own map and, unbound by any cosmic framework, they only need to consider the universe insofar as it benefits them. Or, if they are philosophers, they might argue that, after all, the universe for them is shaped by their own sensations and that, because of this relativity, "anthropo-centrism" is renewed in a new and more powerful way.

Built out of his own sensations: for the philosophy of Locke was now triumphant in France. I have used the term Cartesianism to designate, not the metaphysical doctrines of Descartes (innate ideas, two substances, and the rest), but the great principles which survived the passing of his metaphysical system—the supremacy of reason, and the immutability of natural laws, not subject to providential interventions. These principles still controlled thought, but the particular views of Descartes on mental phenomena were superseded in France by the psychology of Locke, whose influence was established by Voltaire and Condillac. The doctrine that all our ideas are derived from the senses lay at the root of the whole theory of man and society, in the light of which the revolutionary thinkers, Diderot, Helvetius, and their fellows, criticised the existing order and exposed the reigning prejudices. This sensationalism (which went beyond what Locke himself had really meant) involved the strict relativity of knowledge and led at once to the old pragmatic doctrine of Protagoras, that man is the measure of all things. And the spirit of the French philosophers of the eighteenth century was distinctly pragmatic. The advantage of man was their principle, and the value of speculation was judged by its definite service to humanity. "The value and rights of truth are founded on its utility," which is "the unique measure of man's judgements," one thinker asserts; another declares that "the useful circumscribes everything," l'utile circonscrit tout; another lays down that "to be virtuous is to be useful; to be vicious is to be useless or harmful; that is the sum of morality." Helvetius, anticipating Bentham, works out the theory that utility is the only possible basis of ethics. Bacon, the utilitarian, was extolled like Locke. [Footnote: The passages quoted on utility are from d'Holbach, Systems de la nature, i. c. 12, p. 224; c. 15, p. 312; Diderot, De I'interpretation de la nature in OEuvres, ii. p. 13; Raynal, Histoire des deux Indes, vii. p. 416. The effectiveness of the teaching may be illustrated from the Essay on Man, by Antoine Rivarol, whom Burke called the Tacitus of the Revolution. "The virtues are only virtues because they are useful to the human race." OEuvres choisis (ed. de Lescure), i. p. 211.] As, a hundred years before, his influence had inspired the foundation of the Royal Society, so now his name was invoked by the founders of the Encyclopaedia. [Footnote: See d'Alembert's tribute to him in the Discours preliminaire.]

Built from his own experiences, as Locke's philosophy was now prevailing in France. I use the term Cartesianism to refer not to Descartes' metaphysical beliefs (like innate ideas, two substances, and so on), but to the key principles that survived his metaphysical system—the dominance of reason and the unchanging nature of natural laws, which are not influenced by divine intervention. These principles continued to shape thought, but Descartes' specific ideas on mental phenomena were replaced in France by Locke's psychology, which was promoted by Voltaire and Condillac. The idea that all our thoughts come from our senses formed the basis of the entire theory of humanity and society, through which revolutionary thinkers like Diderot, Helvetius, and their peers critiqued the current system and challenged existing biases. This sensationalism (which exceeded Locke's original views) involved the strict relativity of knowledge and directly led to the old pragmatic idea from Protagoras that man is the measure of all things. The essence of the French philosophers of the eighteenth century was clearly pragmatic. Their principle was the benefit of mankind, and they assessed speculative ideas based on their clear contribution to humanity. "The value and rights of truth are based on its usefulness," which is "the sole measure of man’s judgments," one philosopher claims; another proclaims that "the useful encompasses everything," l'utile circonscrit tout; and yet another states that "to be virtuous is to be useful; to be vicious is to be useless or harmful; that is the essence of morality." Helvetius, anticipating Bentham, developed the theory that utility is the only viable foundation for ethics. Bacon, the utilitarian, was praised just like Locke. [Footnote: The passages quoted on utility are from d'Holbach, Systems de la nature, i. c. 12, p. 224; c. 15, p. 312; Diderot, De I'interpretation de la nature in OEuvres, ii. p. 13; Raynal, Histoire des deux Indes, vii. p. 416. The effectiveness of the teaching can be illustrated from the Essay on Man, by Antoine Rivarol, whom Burke called the Tacitus of the Revolution. "The virtues are only virtues because they are useful to the human race." OEuvres choisis (ed. de Lescure), i. p. 211.] Just as, a hundred years earlier, his influence had motivated the establishment of the Royal Society, now his name was invoked by the founders of the Encyclopaedia. [Footnote: See d'Alembert's tribute to him in the Discours preliminaire.]

Beneath all philosophical speculation there is an undercurrent of emotion, and in the French philosophers of the eighteenth century this emotional force was strong and even violent. They aimed at practical results. Their work was a calculated campaign to transform the principles and the spirit of governments and to destroy sacerdotalism. The problem for the human race being to reach a state of felicity by its own powers, these thinkers believed that it was soluble by the gradual triumph of reason over prejudice and knowledge over ignorance. Violent revolution was far from their thoughts; by the diffusion of knowledge they hoped to create a public opinion which would compel governments to change the tenor of their laws and administration and make the happiness of the people their guiding principle. The optimistic confidence that man is perfectible, which means capable of indefinite improvement, inspired the movement as a whole, however greatly particular thinkers might differ in their views.

Beneath all philosophical speculation, there's an emotional current, and in the French philosophers of the eighteenth century, this emotional force was strong and even intense. They aimed for practical outcomes. Their work was a deliberate effort to change the principles and spirit of governments and to dismantle religious authority. With the human race striving to achieve happiness through its own capabilities, these thinkers believed that it could be attained through the gradual victory of reason over prejudice and knowledge over ignorance. Violent revolution was far from their minds; they hoped that by spreading knowledge, they could foster a public opinion that would pressure governments to change their laws and administration, making the happiness of the people their main focus. The optimistic belief that humanity can be improved indefinitely inspired the movement as a whole, even though individual thinkers had varying perspectives.

Belief in Progress was their sustaining faith, although, occupied by the immediate problems of amelioration, they left it rather vague and ill-defined. The word itself is seldom pronounced in their writings. The idea is treated as subordinate to the other ideas in the midst of which it had grown up: Reason, Nature, Humanity, Illumination (lumieres). It has not yet entered upon an independent life of its own and received a distinct label, though it is already a vital force.

Belief in Progress was their core faith, but as they focused on the immediate issues of improvement, they kept it pretty vague and unclear. The term is rarely mentioned in their writing. The concept is considered secondary to the other ideas that shaped it: Reason, Nature, Humanity, Enlightenment (lumieres). It hasn't developed a life of its own with a clear label yet, but it’s already a significant force.

In reviewing the influences which were forming a new public opinion during the forty years before the Revolution, it is convenient for the present purpose to group together the thinkers (including Voltaire) associated with the Encyclopaedia, who represented a critical and consciously aggressive force against traditional theories and existing institutions. The constructive thinker Rousseau was not less aggressive, but he stands apart and opposed, by his hostility to modern civilisation. Thirdly, we must distinguish the school of Economists, also reformers and optimists, but of more conservative temper than the typical Encyclopaedists.

In examining the influences that were shaping a new public opinion during the forty years leading up to the Revolution, it's helpful to group together the thinkers (including Voltaire) linked to the Encyclopaedia, who were a critical and intentionally confrontational force against traditional ideas and existing institutions. The constructive thinker Rousseau was equally confrontational, but he differs from them due to his opposition to modern civilization. Lastly, we need to recognize the group of Economists, who were also reformers and optimists, but were more conservative in nature than the typical Encyclopaedists.

2.

2.

The Encyclopaedia (1751-1765) has rightly been pronounced the central work of the rationalistic movement which made the France of 1789 so different from the France of 1715. [Footnote: The general views which governed the work may be gathered from d'Alembert's introductory discourse and from Diderot's article Encyclopedie. An interesting sketch of the principal contributors will be found in Morley's Diderot, i. chap. v. Another modern study of the Encyclopaedic movement is the monograph of L. Ducros, Les Encyclopidistes (1900). Helvetius has recently been the subject of a study by Albert Keim (Helvetius, sa vie et son oeuvre, 1907). Among other works which help the study of the speculations of this age from various points of view may be mentioned: Marius Roustan, Les Philosophes et la societe francaise au xviii siecle(1906); Espinas, La Philosophie sociale du xviii siecle et la Revolution (1898); Lichtenberger, Le Socialisme au xviii siecle(1895). I have not mentioned in the text Boullanger (1722-1758), who contributed to the Encyclopaedia the article on Political Economy (which has nothing to do with economics but treats of ancient theocracies); the emphasis laid on his views on progress by Buchez (op. cit. i. III sqq.) is quite excessive.] It was the organised section of a vast propaganda, speculative and practical, carried on by men of the most various views, most of whom were associated directly with it. As has well been observed, it did for the rationalism of the eighteenth century in France much what the Fortnightly Review, under the editorship of Mr. Morley (from 1868 to 1882) did for that of the nineteenth in England, as an organ for the penetrating criticism of traditional beliefs. If Diderot, who directed the Encyclopaedia with the assistance of d'Alembert the mathematician, had lived a hundred years later he would probably have edited a journal.

The Encyclopaedia (1751-1765) has rightly been recognized as the central work of the rationalist movement that transformed France from 1715 to 1789. [Footnote: The overarching ideas behind the work can be found in d'Alembert's introductory discourse and in Diderot's article on Encyclopedie. An interesting overview of the main contributors is available in Morley's Diderot, i. chap. v. Another modern study of the Encyclopaedic movement is L. Ducros's monograph, Les Encyclopidistes (1900). Helvetius was recently the subject of a study by Albert Keim (Helvetius, sa vie et son oeuvre, 1907). Other works that provide various perspectives on the speculations of this era include: Marius Roustan, Les Philosophes et la societe francaise au xviii siecle (1906); Espinas, La Philosophie sociale du xviii siecle et la Revolution (1898); Lichtenberger, Le Socialisme au xviii siecle (1895). I have not included Boullanger (1722-1758), who contributed the article on Political Economy to the Encyclopaedia (which actually discusses ancient theocracies, not economics); the emphasis on his views about progress by Buchez (op. cit. i. III sqq.) is quite overstated.] It was a well-organized part of a broad campaign, both speculative and practical, carried out by individuals with a wide range of beliefs, most of whom were directly involved in it. As has been pointed out, it did for the rationalism of the eighteenth century in France much like the Fortnightly Review, under Mr. Morley's editorship (from 1868 to 1882), did for the nineteenth century in England, serving as a platform for critical analysis of traditional beliefs. If Diderot, who directed the Encyclopaedia with help from mathematician d'Alembert, had lived a hundred years later, he probably would have edited a journal.

We saw that the "solidarity" of the sciences was one of the conceptions associated with the theory of intellectual progress, and that the popularisation of knowledge was another. Both these conceptions inspired the Encyclopaedia, which was to gather up and concentrate the illumination of the modern age. It was to establish the lines of communication among all departments, "to enclose in the unity of a system the infinitely various branches of knowledge." And it was to be a library of popular instruction. But it was also intended to be an organ of propaganda. In the history of the intellectual revolution it is in some ways the successor of the Dictionary of Bayle, which, two generations before, collected the material of war to demolish traditional doctrines. The Encyclopaedia carried on the campaign against authority and superstition by indirect methods, but it was the work of men who were not sceptics like Bayle, but had ideals, positive purposes, and social hopes. They were not only confident in reason and in science, but most of them had also a more or less definite belief in the possibility of an advance of humanity towards perfection.

We saw that the "solidarity" of the sciences was one of the ideas linked to the theory of intellectual progress, and that making knowledge accessible was another. Both of these ideas inspired the Encyclopaedia, which aimed to gather and concentrate the enlightenment of the modern age. It was meant to establish connections among all fields, "to unify the infinitely varied branches of knowledge." And it was intended to be a resource for popular education. But it also aimed to be a tool for advocacy. In the history of the intellectual revolution, it can be seen as a successor to Bayle's Dictionary, which, two generations earlier, gathered materials to challenge traditional beliefs. The Encyclopaedia continued the fight against authority and superstition through indirect ways, but it was created by people who were not skeptical like Bayle; they had ideals, clear goals, and hopes for society. They were not only confident in reason and science, but most of them also held a more or less clear belief in the potential for humanity to achieve perfection.

As one of their own band afterwards remarked, they were less occupied in enlarging the bounds of knowledge than in spreading the light and making war on prejudice. [Footnote: Condorcet, Esquisse, p. 206 (ed. 1822).] The views of the individual contributors differed greatly, and they cannot be called a school, but they agreed so far in common tendencies that they were able to form a co-operative alliance.

As one of their own members later noted, they were more focused on spreading awareness and fighting against prejudice than on expanding the limits of knowledge. [Footnote: Condorcet, Esquisse, p. 206 (ed. 1822).] The perspectives of the individual contributors varied widely, and they can't be classified as a school, but they shared enough common ground in their tendencies to form a cooperative alliance.

The propaganda of which the Encyclopaedia was the centre was reinforced by the independent publications of some of the leading men who collaborated or were closely connected with their circle, notably those of Diderot himself, Baron d'Holbach, and Helvetius.

The propaganda centered around the Encyclopaedia was strengthened by the independent publications of some of the key figures who collaborated with or were closely associated with that group, particularly the works of Diderot himself, Baron d'Holbach, and Helvetius.

3.

3.

The optimism of the Encyclopaedists was really based on an intense consciousness of the enlightenment of their own age. The progressiveness of knowledge was taken as axiomatic, but was there any guarantee that the light, now confined to small circles, could ever enlighten the world and regenerate mankind? They found the guarantee they required, not in an induction from the past experience of the race, but in an a priori theory: the indefinite malleability of human nature by education and institutions. This had been, as we saw, assumed by the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. It pervaded the speculation of the age, and was formally deduced from the sensational psychology of Locke and Condillac. It was developed, in an extreme form, in the work of Helvetius, De l'esprit (1758).

The optimism of the Encyclopaedists was really rooted in a strong awareness of the enlightenment of their own time. They saw the progress of knowledge as a given, but was there any assurance that the insights, currently limited to small groups, could ever illuminate the entire world and transform humanity? They found the assurance they needed, not from a conclusion drawn from the past experiences of humanity, but from a theory based on reason: the endless adaptability of human nature through education and institutions. This assumption was, as we noted, made by the Abbe de Saint-Pierre. It influenced the thinking of the era and was formally derived from the empirical psychology of Locke and Condillac. It was expanded, in a more extreme way, in the work of Helvetius, De l'esprit (1758).

In this book, which was to exert a large influence in England, Helvetius sought, among other things, to show that the science of morals is equivalent to the science of legislation, and that in a well-organised society all men are capable of rising to the highest point of mental development. Intellectual and moral inequalities between man and man arise entirely from differences in education and social circumstances. Genius itself is not a gift of nature; the man of genius is a product of circumstances—social, not physical, for Helvetius rejects the influence of climate. It follows that if you change education and social institutions you can change the character of men.

In this book, which had a significant impact in England, Helvetius aimed, among other things, to demonstrate that the study of ethics is the same as the study of laws, and that in a well-structured society, everyone has the potential to reach the highest levels of intellectual development. Differences in intelligence and morality among people arise solely from variations in education and social conditions. Genius is not an inherent trait; a genius is shaped by their circumstances—social, not physical, as Helvetius dismisses the role of climate. Therefore, if you change education and social systems, you can change people's character.

The error of Helvetius in ignoring the irremovable physical differences between individuals, the varieties of cerebral organisation, was at once pointed out by Diderot. This error, however, was not essential to the general theory of the immeasurable power of social institutions over human character, and other thinkers did not fall into it. All alike, indeed, were blind to the factor of heredity. But the theory in its collective application contains a truth which nineteenth century critics, biassed by their studies in heredity, have been prone to overlook. The social inheritance of ideas and emotions to which the individual is submitted from infancy is more important than the tendencies physically transmitted from parent to child. The power of education and government in moulding the members of a society has recently been illustrated on a large scale in the psychological transformation of the German people in the life of a generation.

The mistake Helvetius made by overlooking the unavoidable physical differences between individuals and the variations in brain structure was quickly highlighted by Diderot. However, this mistake wasn't crucial to the overall theory about the immense influence of social institutions on human character, and other thinkers didn't fall into the same trap. In fact, they were all, more or less, oblivious to the role of heredity. Yet, the theory, when applied collectively, holds a truth that 19th-century critics, who were influenced by their studies of heredity, often missed. The social inheritance of ideas and emotions that individuals are exposed to from infancy is more significant than the traits passed down from parent to child. The influence of education and governance in shaping the members of a society has recently been demonstrated on a large scale through the psychological transformation of the German people over a generation.

It followed from the theory expounded by Helvetius that there is no impassable barrier between the advanced and the stationary or retrograde races of the earth. [Footnote: The most informing discussion of the relations between the Advanced and Backward races is Bryce's Romanes Lecture (1902).] "True morality," Baron d'Holbach wrote, "should be the same for all the inhabitants of the globe. The savage man and the civilised; the white man, the red man, the black man; Indian and European, Chinaman and Frenchman, Negro and Lapp have the same nature. The differences between them are only modifications of the common nature produced by climate, government, education, opinions, and the various causes which operate on them. Men differ only in the ideas they form of happiness and the means which they have imagined to obtain it." Here again the eighteenth century theorists held a view which can no longer be dismissed as absurd. Some are coming round to the opinion that enormous differences in capacity which seem fundamental are a result of the differences in social inheritance, and that these again are due to a long sequence of historical circumstances; and consequently that there is no people in the world doomed by nature to perpetual inferiority or irrevocably disqualified by race from playing a useful part in the future of civilisation.

It follows from the theory presented by Helvetius that there is no unbridgeable gap between the advanced and the stagnant or regressive races of the earth. [Footnote: The most insightful discussion of the relationships between the Advanced and Backward races is Bryce's Romanes Lecture (1902).] "True morality," Baron d'Holbach wrote, "should be the same for everyone on the globe. The primitive person and the civilized one; the white person, the red person, the black person; Indian and European, Chinese and French, Black and Lapp share the same nature. The differences between them are merely variations of the common nature influenced by climate, government, education, beliefs, and the various factors affecting them. People differ only in the ideas they have about happiness and the ways they believe they can achieve it." Again, the eighteenth-century theorists held a perspective that can no longer be dismissed as ridiculous. Some are beginning to think that the significant differences in abilities that seem essential are actually a result of differences in social background, which are in turn due to a long series of historical events; thus, there is no group in the world doomed by nature to perpetual inferiority or irrevocably disqualified by race from contributing meaningfully to the future of civilization.

4.

4.

This doctrine of the possibility of indefinitely moulding the characters of men by laws and institutions—whether combined or not with a belief in the natural equality of men's faculties—laid a foundation on which the theory of the perfectibility of humanity could be raised. It marked, therefore, an important stage in the development of the doctrine of Progress.

This idea that we can shape people's characters endlessly through laws and institutions—whether or not it's tied to a belief in the natural equality of people's abilities—set the stage for the theory that humanity can be perfected. It represented a significant moment in the evolution of the idea of Progress.

It gave, moreover, a new and larger content to that doctrine by its applicability, not only to the peoples which are at present in the van of civilisation, but also to those which have lagged far behind and may appear irreclaimably barbarous—thus potentially including all humanity in the prospect of the future. Turgot had already conceived "the total mass of the human race moving always slowly forward"; he had declared that the human mind everywhere contains the germs of progress and that the inequality of peoples is due to the infinite variety of their circumstances. This enlarging conception was calculated to add strength to the idea of Progress, by raising it to a synthesis comprehending not merely the western civilised nations but the whole human world.

It also gave a new and broader meaning to that idea by applying it not just to the advanced civilizations of today, but also to those that have fallen behind and may seem irredeemably primitive—thus potentially including all of humanity in the vision for the future. Turgot had already envisioned "the entire mass of the human race moving slowly forward"; he stated that the human mind everywhere holds the seeds of progress and that the differences between peoples stem from the endless variety of their circumstances. This expansive view was intended to strengthen the concept of Progress by elevating it to a synthesis that includes not just the western civilized nations but the entire human race.

Interest in the remote peoples of the earth, in the unfamiliar civilisations of the East, in the untutored races of America and Africa, was vivid in France in the eighteenth century. Everyone knows how Voltaire and Montesquieu used Hurons or Persians to hold up the glass to Western manners and morals, as Tacitus used the Germans to criticise the society of Rome. But very few ever look into the seven volumes of the Abbe Raynal's History of the Two Indies which appeared in 1772. It is however, one of the remarkable books of the century. Its immediate practical importance lay in the array of facts which it furnished to the friends of humanity in the movement against negro slavery. But it was also an effective attack on the Church and the sacerdotal system. The author's method was the same which his greater contemporary Gibbon employed on a larger scale. A history of facts was a more formidable indictment than any declamatory attack.

Interest in the remote peoples of the world, the unfamiliar civilizations of the East, and the uneducated races of America and Africa was strong in France during the eighteenth century. Everyone knows how Voltaire and Montesquieu used examples from the Huron or Persian cultures to reflect on Western customs and morals, just as Tacitus used the Germans to critique Roman society. However, very few people actually explore the seven volumes of the Abbe Raynal's *History of the Two Indies*, published in 1772. This work is, nonetheless, one of the remarkable books of that century. Its immediate practical importance was in the wealth of facts it provided to those advocating for humanity in the fight against slavery. It also served as a powerful critique of the Church and the religious system. The author's approach mirrored that of his more famous contemporary Gibbon, but on a smaller scale. A history based on facts was a more compelling indictment than any rhetorical criticism.

Raynal brought home to the conscience of Europeans the miseries which had befallen the natives of the New World through the Christian conquerors and their priests. He was not indeed an enthusiastic preacher of Progress. He is unable to decide between the comparative advantages of the savage state of nature and the most highly cultivated society. But he observes that "the human race is what we wish to make it," that the felicity of man depends entirely on the improvement of legislation; and in the survey of the history of Europe to which the last Book of his work is devoted, his view is generally optimistic. [Footnote: cp. Raynal, Histoire, vii. 214, 256. This book was first published anonymously; the author's name appeared in the edition of 1780.]

Raynal made Europeans aware of the suffering that the natives of the New World faced at the hands of Christian conquerors and their priests. He wasn't exactly an enthusiastic advocate for Progress. He couldn’t clearly choose between the benefits of a primitive state of nature and a highly developed society. However, he points out that "the human race is what we choose to make it," and that people's happiness is completely dependent on better laws. In the final Book of his work, which looks at European history, his overall perspective is mostly optimistic. [Footnote: cp. Raynal, Histoire, vii. 214, 256. This book was first published anonymously; the author's name appeared in the edition of 1780.]

5. Baron d'Holbach had a more powerful brain than Helvetius, but his writings had probably less influence, though he was the spiritual father of two prominent Revolutionaries, Hebert and Chaumette. His System of Nature (1770) develops a purely naturalistic theory of the universe, in which the prevalent Deism is rejected: there is no God; material Nature stands out alone, self-sufficing, dominis privata superbis. The book suggests how the Lucretian theory of development might have led to the idea of Progress. But it sent a chilly shock to the hearts of many and probably convinced few. The effective part was the outspoken and passionate indictment of governments and religions as causes of most of the miseries of mankind.

5. Baron d'Holbach had a stronger intellect than Helvetius, but his writings likely had less impact, even though he inspired two notable Revolutionaries, Hebert and Chaumette. His System of Nature (1770) presents a strictly naturalistic view of the universe, rejecting the common Deism: there is no God; material Nature stands alone, self-sufficient, and proud of its dominion. The book hints at how Lucretius's theory of development might have led to the concept of Progress. However, it shocked many and probably didn’t convince most. The most compelling aspect was the direct and passionate critique of governments and religions as the root of much of humanity's suffering.

It is in other works, especially in his Social System, that his views of Progress are to be sought. Man is simply a part of nature; he has no privileged position, and he is born neither good nor bad. Erras, as Seneca said, si existumas vitia nobiscum esse: supervenerunt, ingesta sunt. [Footnote: Seneca, Ep. 124.] We are made good or bad by education, public opinion, laws, government; and here the author points to the significance of the instinct of imitation as a social force, which a modern writer, M. Tarde, has worked into a system.

It is in other works, especially in his Social System, that his ideas about Progress can be found. Humans are just a part of nature; they don’t hold a special status and are born neither good nor bad. Errors, as Seneca said, if you think vices are innate to us: they arise, they are imposed. [Footnote: Seneca, Ep. 124.] We become good or bad through education, public opinion, laws, and government; and here the author highlights the importance of the instinct to imitate as a social force, which a modern writer, M. Tarde, has developed into a system.

The evils, which are due to the errors of tyranny and superstition, the force of truth will gradually diminish if it cannot completely banish them; for our governments and laws may be perfected by the progress of useful knowledge. But the process will be a long one: centuries of continuous mental effort in unravelling the causes of social ill-being and repeated experiments to determine the remedies (des experiences reiterees de la societe). In any case we cannot look forward to the attainment of an unchangeable or unqualified felicity. That is a mere chimera "incompatible with the nature of a being whose feeble machine is subject to derangement and whose ardent imagination will not always submit to the guidance of reason. Sometimes to enjoy, sometimes to suffer, is the lot of man; to enjoy more often than to suffer is what constitutes well-being."

The evils caused by tyranny and superstition will gradually decrease through the power of truth, even if they can't be completely eliminated; our governments and laws can improve with the advancement of useful knowledge. However, this will be a lengthy process: centuries of continuous mental effort to understand the causes of social problems and repeated experiments to find solutions. In any case, we cannot expect to achieve a permanent or absolute happiness. That is just an illusion, "incompatible with the nature of a being whose fragile nature is prone to malfunction and whose passionate imagination will not always follow reason. Sometimes we enjoy, sometimes we suffer; to enjoy more often than to suffer is what defines well-being."

D'Holbach was a strict determinist; he left no room for freewill in the rigorous succession of cause and effect, and the pages in which he drives home the theory of causal necessity are still worth reading. From his naturalistic principles he inferred that the distinction between nature and art is not fundamental; civilisation is as rational as the savage state. Here he was at one with Aristotle.

D'Holbach was a strict determinist; he didn't believe in free will within the strict flow of cause and effect, and the sections where he emphasizes the theory of causal necessity are still worth checking out. From his naturalistic principles, he concluded that the difference between nature and art isn't essential; civilization is as rational as a primitive state. Here he agreed with Aristotle.

All the successive inventions of the human mind to change or perfect man's mode of existence and render it happier were only the necessary consequence of his essence and that of the existences which act upon him. All we do or think, all we are or shall be, is only an effect of what universal nature has made us. Art is only nature acting by the aid of the instruments which she has fashioned. [Footnote: The passages of d'Holbach specially referred to are: Systeme social, i. 1, p. 13; Syst. de la nature, i. 6, p. 88; Syst. soc. i. 15, p. 271; Syst. de la n. i. 1, p. 3.]

All the inventions made by humans to change or improve our way of life and make it happier are just the natural result of who we are and the influences around us. Everything we do or think, everything we are or will become, is just a result of what universal nature has shaped us to be. Art is simply nature creating through the tools it has developed. [Footnote: The passages of d'Holbach specially referred to are: Systeme social, i. 1, p. 13; Syst. de la nature, i. 6, p. 88; Syst. soc. i. 15, p. 271; Syst. de la n. i. 1, p. 3.]

Progress, therefore, is natural and necessary, and to criticise or condemn it by appealing to nature is only to divide the house of nature against itself.

Progress is, therefore, natural and essential, and criticizing or condemning it by referencing nature is just tearing nature apart from itself.

If d'Holbach had pressed his logic further, he would have taken a more indulgent and calmer view of the past history of mankind. He would have acknowledged that institutions and opinions to which modern reason may give short shrift were natural and useful in their day, and would have recognised that at any stage of history the heritage of the past is no less necessary to progress than the solvent power of new ideas. Most thinkers of his time were inclined to judge the past career of humanity anachronistically. All the things that had been done or thought which could not be justified in the new age of enlightenment, were regarded as gratuitous and inexcusable errors. The traditions, superstitions, and customs, the whole "code of fraud and woe" transmitted from the past, weighed then too heavily in France to allow the school of reform to do impartial justice to their origins. They felt a sort of resentment against history. D'Alembert said that it would be well if history could be destroyed; and the general tendency was to ignore the social memory and the common heritage of past experiences which mould a human society and make it something very different from a mere collection of individuals.

If d'Holbach had taken his reasoning further, he would have had a more understanding and relaxed view of humanity's past. He would have recognized that the institutions and beliefs that modern reason often dismisses were natural and helpful in their time, and he would have understood that at any point in history, the legacy of the past is just as essential for progress as the transformative power of new ideas. Most thinkers of his era tended to judge the past of humanity with a lack of context. All the actions and thoughts that couldn't be defended in the new age of enlightenment were seen as unnecessary and unforgivable mistakes. The traditions, superstitions, and customs—the entire "code of fraud and woe" passed down from the past—felt too burdensome in France at that time for the reform movement to fairly assess their origins. They had a certain resentment towards history. D'Alembert suggested it would be better if history could simply be erased; the general inclination was to overlook the social memory and shared experiences of the past that shape a human society and differentiate it from just a collection of individuals.

Belief in Progress, however, took no extravagant form. It did not beguile d'Holbach or any other of the leading thinkers of the Encyclopaedia epoch into optimistic dreams of the future which might await mankind. They had a much clearer conception of obstacles than the good Abbe de Saint-Pierre. Helvetius agrees with d'Holbach that progress will be slow, and Diderot is wavering and sceptical of the question of indefinite social improvement. [Footnote: De l'esprit, Disc. ii. cc. 24, 25.]

Belief in Progress, however, was not exaggerated. It didn’t trap d'Holbach or any of the other prominent thinkers of the Enlightenment era into overly optimistic visions of the future for humanity. They had a much clearer understanding of the challenges than the well-meaning Abbe de Saint-Pierre. Helvetius shares d'Holbach's view that progress will be slow, and Diderot is unsure and doubtful about the idea of endless social improvement. [Footnote: De l'esprit, Disc. ii. cc. 24, 25.]

6.

6.

The reformers of the Encyclopaedia group were not alone in disseminating the idea of Progress. Another group of thinkers, who widely differed in their principles, though some of them had contributed articles to the Encyclopaedia, [Footnote: Quesnay and Turgot, who, though not professedly a Physiocrat, held the same views as the sect.] also did much to make it a power. The rise of the special study of Economics was one of the most significant facts in the general trend of thought towards the analysis of civilisation. Economical students found that in seeking to discover a true theory of the production, distribution, and employment of wealth, they could not avoid the consideration of the constitution and purpose of society. The problems of production and distribution could not be divorced from political theory: production raises the question of the functions of government and the limits of its intervention in trade and industry; distribution involve questions of property, justice, and equality. The employment of riches leads into the domain of morals.

The reformers of the Encyclopaedia group weren't alone in spreading the idea of Progress. Another group of thinkers, who had very different principles, although some of them contributed articles to the Encyclopaedia, [Footnote: Quesnay and Turgot, who, while not officially part of the Physiocrats, shared the same views as the group.] also played a significant role in making it influential. The emergence of specialized studies in Economics was one of the most important developments in the overall shift toward analyzing civilization. Economics students discovered that in their quest to find a true theory of wealth production, distribution, and use, they couldn't ignore the structure and purpose of society. The issues of production and distribution were closely tied to political theory: production raises questions about the role of government and the limits of its involvement in trade and industry; distribution involves issues of property, justice, and equality. The use of wealth touches on moral considerations.

The French Economists or "Physiocrats," as they were afterwards called, who formed a definite school before 1760—Quesnay the master, Mirabeau, Mercier de la Riviere, and the rest—envisaged their special subject from a wide philosophical point of view; their general economic theory was equivalent to a theory of human society. They laid down the doctrine of a Natural Order in political communities, and from it they deduced their economic teaching.

The French Economists, known as "Physiocrats" later on, who established a clear school of thought before 1760—Quesnay as the leader, along with Mirabeau, Mercier de la Riviere, and others—approached their specific subject from a broad philosophical perspective; their overall economic theory was akin to a theory of human society. They proposed the idea of a Natural Order in political communities, from which they derived their economic principles.

They assumed, like the Encyclopaedists, that the end of society is the attainment of terrestrial happiness by its members, and that this is the sole purpose of government. The object of a treatise by Mercier de la Riviere [Footnote: L'ordre naturel et essentiel des societes politiqes, 1767.] (a convenient exposition of the views of the sect) is, in his own words, to discover the natural order for the government of men living in organised communities, which will assure to them temporal felicity: an order in which everything is well, necessarily well, and in which the interests of all are so perfectly and intimately consolidated that all are happy, from the ruler to the least of his subjects.

They believed, like the Encyclopaedists, that the ultimate goal of society is for its members to achieve happiness in this life, and that this is the main purpose of government. The aim of a treatise by Mercier de la Riviere [Footnote: L'ordre naturel et essentiel des societes politiqes, 1767.] (a clear explanation of the sect's views) is, in his own words, to find the natural order for governing people living in organized communities, which will guarantee them happiness in this life: an order where everything is good, necessarily good, and where everyone's interests are so perfectly and closely aligned that all are happy, from the ruler to the lowest of his subjects.

But in what does this happiness consist? His answer is that "humanly speaking, the greatest happiness possible for us consists in the greatest possible abundance of objects suitable to our enjoyment and in the greatest liberty to profit by them." And liberty is necessary not only to enjoy them but also to produce them in the greatest abundance, since liberty stimulates human efforts. Another condition of abundance is the multiplication of the race; in fact, the happiness of men and their numbers are closely bound up together in the system of nature. From these axioms may be deduced the Natural Order of a human society, the reciprocal duties and rights whose enforcement is required for the greatest possible multiplication of products, in order to procure to the race the greatest sum of happiness with the maximum population.

But what does this happiness really involve? He answers that "when it comes to humans, the greatest happiness we can experience consists of having as many enjoyable things as possible and the freedom to take full advantage of them." Freedom is essential not just for enjoying those things but also for creating them in large quantities, as freedom encourages human effort. Another factor for abundance is the growth of the population; in fact, human happiness and population numbers are closely linked within the natural system. From these principles, we can deduce the Natural Order of human society, along with the mutual duties and rights necessary for maximizing production to bring the greatest happiness to the population at large.

Now, individual property is the indispensable condition for full enjoyment of the products of human labour; "property is the measure of liberty, and liberty is the measure of property." Hence, to realise general happiness it is only necessary to maintain property and consequently liberty in all their natural extent. The fatal error which has made history what it is has been the failure to recognise this simple fact; for aggression and conquest, the causes of human miseries, violate the law of property which is the foundation of happiness.

Now, personal property is essential for fully enjoying the results of human labor; "property is the measure of freedom, and freedom is the measure of property." Therefore, to achieve overall happiness, we only need to uphold property and, consequently, freedom in their natural form. The major mistake that has shaped history has been the failure to see this simple truth; aggression and conquest, the sources of human suffering, infringe upon the law of property, which is the basis of happiness.

The practical inference was that the chief function of government was to protect property and that complete freedom should be left to private enterprise to exploit the resources of the earth. All would be well if trade and industry were allowed to follow their natural tendencies. This is what was meant by Physiocracy, the supremacy of the Natural Order. If rulers observed the limits of their true functions, Mercier thought that the moral effect would be immense. "The public system of government is the true education of moral man. Regis ad exemplum totus componitur orbis." [Footnote: The particulars of the Physiocratic doctrine as to the relative values of agriculture and commerce which Adam Smith was soon to criticise do not concern us; nor is it necessary to repeat the obvious criticisms on a theory which virtually reduced the science of society to a science of production and distribution.]

The main takeaway was that the primary role of government is to protect property and that private businesses should have full freedom to use the earth's resources. Everything would run smoothly if trade and industry were allowed to operate naturally. This concept is known as Physiocracy, the idea of the Natural Order being the highest authority. Mercier believed that if leaders respected their true roles, the positive moral impact would be significant. "The public system of government is the true education of moral man. Regis ad exemplum totus componitur orbis." [Footnote: The specifics of the Physiocratic doctrine regarding the relative importance of agriculture and commerce, which Adam Smith would soon critique, are not our focus; nor is it necessary to reiterate the obvious critiques of a theory that essentially reduced the study of society to a study of production and distribution.]

While they advocated a thorough reform of the principles which ruled the fiscal policy of governments, the Economists were not idealists, like the Encyclopaedic philosophers; they sowed no seeds of revolution. Their starting-point was that which is, not that which ought to be. And, apart from their narrower point of view, they differed from the philosophers in two very important points. They did not believe that society was of human institution, and therefore they did not believe that there could be any deductive science of society based simply on man's nature. Moreover, they held that inequality of condition was one of its immutable features, immutable because it is a consequence of the inequality of physical powers.

While they pushed for a complete overhaul of the principles guiding government fiscal policy, the Economists weren't idealists like the Enlightenment philosophers; they didn't incite revolution. Their foundation was based on reality, not what should be. Besides their more limited perspective, they differed from the philosophers in two key areas. They didn't think society was a human creation, and therefore, they didn't believe there could be any deductive science of society that’s solely based on human nature. Additionally, they argued that inequality of condition was one of its unchangeable aspects, unchangeable because it stems from the disparity in physical abilities.

But they believed in the future progress of society towards a state of happiness through the increase of opulence which would itself depend on the growth of justice and "liberty"; and they insisted on the importance of the increase and diffusion of knowledge. Their influence in promoting a belief in Progress is vouched for by Condorcet, the friend and biographer of Turgot. As Turgot stands apart from the Physiocrats (with whom indeed he did not identify himself) by his wider views on civilisation, it might be suspected that it is of him that Condorcet was chiefly thinking. Yet we need not limit the scope of his statement when we remember that as a sect the Economists assumed as their first principle the eudaemonic value of civilisation, declared that temporal happiness is attainable, and threw all their weight into the scales against the doctrine of Regress which had found a powerful advocate in Rousseau.

But they believed in the future development of society towards a state of happiness through increased wealth, which would depend on the growth of justice and "liberty"; and they emphasized the importance of spreading knowledge. Condorcet, the friend and biographer of Turgot, confirms their influence in promoting a belief in Progress. Since Turgot differs from the Physiocrats (with whom he did not align) by having broader views on civilization, it could be assumed that Condorcet was mainly thinking of him. However, we shouldn't restrict the meaning of his statement when we consider that as a group, the Economists accepted as their primary principle the value of civilization for happiness, declared that temporal happiness is achievable, and threw all their support against the idea of Regress, which had found a strong advocate in Rousseau.

7.

7.

By liberty the Economists meant economic liberty. Neither they nor the philosophers nor Rousseau, the father of modern democracy, had any just conception of what political liberty means. They contributed much to its realisation, but their own ideas of it were narrow and imperfect. They never challenged the principle of a despotic government, they only contended that the despotism must be enlightened. The paternal rule of a Joseph or a Catherine, acting under the advice of philosophers, seemed to them the ideal solution of the problem of government; and when the progressive and disinterested Turgot, whom they might regard as one of themselves, was appointed financial minister on the accession of Louis XVI., it seemed that their ideal was about to be realised. His speedy fall dispelled their hopes, but did not teach them the secret of liberty. They had no quarrel with the principle of the censorship, though they writhed under its tyranny; they did not want to abolish it. They only complained that it was used against reason and light, that is against their own writings; and, if the Conseil d'Etat or the Parlement had suppressed the works of their obscurantist opponents, they would have congratulated themselves that the world was marching quickly towards perfection. [Footnote: The principle that intolerance on the part of the wise and strong towards the ignorant and weak is a good thing is not alien to the spirit of the French philosophers, though I do not think any of them expressly asserted it. In the following century it was formulated by Colins, a Belgian (author of two works on social science, 1857-60), who believed that an autocratic government suppressing liberty of conscience is the most effective instrument of Progress. It is possible that democracy may yet try the experiment.]

By liberty, the Economists meant economic freedom. Neither they, nor the philosophers, nor Rousseau, the father of modern democracy, had a clear understanding of what political freedom really means. They contributed a lot to its realization, but their own views were limited and flawed. They never questioned the idea of a despotic government; they only argued that this despotism should be enlightened. The paternal rule of someone like Joseph or Catherine, guided by philosophers, seemed to them to be the ideal solution for governance. When the progressive and altruistic Turgot, whom they saw as one of their own, was appointed financial minister when Louis XVI came to power, it appeared that their ideal was on the verge of being realized. His quick downfall shattered their hopes but didn’t teach them the essence of freedom. They had no issue with the principle of censorship, even though they suffered under its oppression; they didn’t actually want it to be abolished. They only complained that it was used against reason and enlightenment, which meant it was targeting their own writings. If the Conseil d'Etat or the Parlement had suppressed the works of their obscure opponents, they would have felt proud that the world was moving swiftly towards perfection. [Footnote: The notion that intolerance from the wise and powerful towards the ignorant and weak is beneficial isn’t foreign to the spirit of the French philosophers, even though I don’t think any of them explicitly stated it. In the following century, it was articulated by Colins, a Belgian (author of two works on social science, 1857-60), who believed that an autocratic government that suppresses freedom of conscience is the most effective means of Progress. It’s possible that democracy may still attempt this experiment.]





CHAPTER IX. WAS CIVILISATION A MISTAKE? ROUSSEAU, CHASTELLUX. 1.

The optimistic theory of civilisation was not unchallenged by rationalists. In the same year (1750) in which Turgot traced an outline of historical Progress at the Sorbonne, Rousseau laid before the Academy of Dijon a theory of historical Regress. This Academy had offered a prize for the best essay on the question whether the revival of sciences and arts had contributed to the improvement of morals. The prize was awarded to Rousseau. Five years later the same learned body proposed another subject for investigation, the origin of Inequality among men. Rousseau again competed but failed to win the prize, though this second essay was a far more remarkable performance.

The optimistic theory of civilization wasn't without its challengers among rationalists. In the same year (1750) that Turgot outlined a vision of historical progress at the Sorbonne, Rousseau presented a theory of historical regression to the Academy of Dijon. This Academy had announced a prize for the best essay on whether the revival of sciences and arts had improved morals. Rousseau won the prize. Five years later, the same learned body proposed a new topic for exploration: the origin of inequality among men. Rousseau competed again but did not win the prize, even though this second essay was a significantly more impressive work.

The view common to these two discourses, that social development has been a gigantic mistake, that the farther man has travelled from a primitive simple state the more unhappy has his lot become, that civilisation is radically vicious, was not original. Essentially the same issue had been raised in England, though in a different form, by Mandeville's Fable of the Bees, the scandalous book which aimed at proving that it is not the virtues and amiable qualities of man that are the cement of civilised society, but the vices of its members which are the support of all trades and employments. [Footnote: The expanded edition was published in 1723.] In these vices, he said, "we must look for the true origin of all arts and sciences"; "the moment evil ceases the society must be spoiled, if not totally dissolved."

The common view in these two discussions is that social development has been a huge mistake, that the further humanity has moved away from a basic, primitive state, the more unhappy people have become, and that civilization is fundamentally corrupt. This idea wasn't new. A similar topic was explored in England, albeit in a different way, by Mandeville's Fable of the Bees, a controversial book that argued it's not the virtues and nice qualities of people that hold civilized society together, but rather the vices of its members that support all trades and jobs. [Footnote: The expanded edition was published in 1723.] He stated that "we must look for the true origin of all arts and sciences" in these vices; "the moment evil ceases, society must be ruined, if not completely destroyed."

The significance of Mandeville's book lay in the challenge it flung to the optimistic doctrines of Lord Shaftesbury, that human nature is good and all is for the best in this harmonious world. "The ideas he had formed," wrote Mandeville, "of the goodness and excellency of our nature were as romantic and chimerical as they are beautiful and amiable; he laboured hard to unite two contraries that can never be reconciled together, innocence of manners and worldly greatness."

The importance of Mandeville's book was in how it pushed back against Lord Shaftesbury's optimistic beliefs that human nature is good and everything is for the best in this harmonious world. "The views he had about the goodness and excellence of our nature were as unrealistic and imaginary as they are beautiful and appealing; he worked hard to combine two opposites that can never be reconciled, innocence in behavior and worldly success."

Of these two views Rousseau accepted one and rejected the other. He agreed with Shaftesbury as to the natural goodness of man; he agreed with Mandeville that innocence of manners is incompatible with the conditions of a civilised society. He was an optimist in regard to human nature, a pessimist in regard to civilisation.

Of these two views, Rousseau accepted one and rejected the other. He agreed with Shaftesbury about the natural goodness of people; he agreed with Mandeville that innocence in behavior doesn't fit with the realities of a civilized society. He was an optimist when it came to human nature and a pessimist regarding civilization.

In his first Discourse he begins by appreciating the specious splendour of modern enlightenment, the voyages of man's intellect among the stars, and then goes on to assever that in the first place men have lost, through their civilisation, the original liberty for which they were born, and that arts and science, flinging garlands of flowers on the iron chains which bind them, make them love their slavery; and secondly that there is a real depravity beneath the fair semblance and "our souls are corrupted as our sciences and arts advance to perfection." Nor is this only a modern phenomenon; "the evils due to our vain curiosity are as old as the world." For it is a law of history that morals fall and rise in correspondence with the progress and decline of the arts and sciences as regularly as the tides answer to the phases of the moon. This "law" is exemplified by the fortunes of Greece, Rome, and China, to whose civilisations the author opposes the comparative happiness of the ignorant Persians, Scythians, and ancient Germans. "Luxury, dissoluteness, and slavery have been always the chastisement of the ambitious efforts we have made to emerge from the happy ignorance in which the Eternal Wisdom had placed us." There is the theological doctrine of the tree of Eden in a new shape.

In his first Discourse, he starts by recognizing the dazzling brilliance of modern enlightenment, the journeys of human intellect among the stars, and then insists that, first of all, people have lost the original freedom they were born with due to their civilization. He argues that arts and sciences, while adorning the iron chains that bind them with garlands of flowers, actually make them love their slavery. Secondly, he claims there is a true corruption hidden beneath the attractive surface, stating that "our souls are corrupted as our sciences and arts advance to perfection." This isn't just a modern issue; "the evils from our vain curiosity are as old as the world." History demonstrates that morals rise and fall in line with the progress and decline of arts and sciences, just as the tides respond to the moon's phases. This "law" is illustrated by the histories of Greece, Rome, and China, which he contrasts with the relative happiness of the uneducated Persians, Scythians, and ancient Germans. "Luxury, indulgence, and slavery have always been the penalties of our ambitious attempts to break free from the blissful ignorance in which the Eternal Wisdom had placed us." This presents the theological idea of the tree of Eden in a new light.

Rousseau's attempt to show that the cultivation of science produces specific moral evils is feeble, and has little ingenuity; it is a declamation rather than an argument; and in the end he makes concessions which undo the effect of his impeachment. The essay did not establish even a plausible case, but it was paradoxical and suggestive, and attracted more attention than Turgot's thoughtful discourse in the Sorbonne. D'Alembert deemed it worthy of a courteous expression of dissent; [Footnote: In the Disc. Prel. to the Encyclopaedia.] and Voltaire satirised it in his Timon.

Rousseau's effort to demonstrate that the development of science leads to specific moral problems is weak and lacks creativity; it reads more like a speech than a logical argument. In the end, he makes concessions that undermine his accusations. The essay didn't even make a convincing case, but it was paradoxical and thought-provoking, drawing more attention than Turgot's insightful lecture at the Sorbonne. D'Alembert considered it deserving of a polite disagreement; [Footnote: In the Disc. Prel. to the Encyclopaedia.] and Voltaire mocked it in his Timon.

2.

2.

In the Discourse on Inequality Rousseau dealt more directly with the effect of civilisation on happiness. He proposed to explain how it came about that right overcame the primitive reign of might, that the strong were induced to serve the weak, and the people to purchase a fancied tranquillity at the price of a real felicity. So he stated his problem; and to solve it he had to consider the "state of nature" which Hobbes had conceived as a state of war and Locke as a state of peace. Rousseau imagines our first savage ancestors living in isolation, wandering in the forests, occasionally co-operating, and differing from the animals only by the possession of a faculty for improving themselves (la faculte de se perfectionner). After a stage in which families lived alone in a more or less settled condition, came the formation of groups of families, living together in a definite territory, united by a common mode of life and sustenance, and by the common influence of climate, but without laws or government or any social organisation.

In the Discourse on Inequality, Rousseau addressed the impact of civilization on happiness more directly. He aimed to explain how rights began to overpower the primitive principle of strength, how the strong were motivated to support the weak, and how people chose to buy a supposed peace at the cost of true happiness. He framed his issue, and to resolve it, he needed to explore the "state of nature," which Hobbes viewed as a state of war and Locke as a state of peace. Rousseau envisioned our first savage ancestors living in isolation, wandering through forests, occasionally cooperating, and differing from animals only by their ability to improve themselves (la faculte de se perfectionner). After a period during which families lived independently in a relatively stable manner, groups of families formed, living together in a specific territory, united by a shared way of life and sustenance, and influenced by the same climate, but without laws, government, or any social organization.

It is this state, which was reached only after a long period, not the original state of nature, that Rousseau considers to have been the happiest period of the human race.

It is this state, which was achieved only after a long time, not the original state of nature, that Rousseau believes was the happiest period of humanity.

This period of the development of human faculties, holding a just mean between the indolence of the primitive state and the petulant activity of our self-love, must be the happiest and most durable epoch. The more we reflect on it, the more we find that this state was the least exposed to revolutions and the best for man; and that he can have left it only through some fatal chance which, for the common advantage, should never have occurred. The example of the savages who have almost all been found in this state seems to bear out the conclusion that humanity was made to remain in it for ever, that it was the true youth of the world, and that all further progresses have been so many steps, apparently towards the perfection of the individual, and really towards the decrepitude of the species.

This stage in the development of human abilities, striking a balance between the laziness of the primitive state and the restless drive of our ego, must be the happiest and most enduring time. The more we think about it, the more we realize that this condition was the least vulnerable to upheavals and the best for humanity; that we could only have left it due to some disastrous coincidence that, for everyone's sake, should never have happened. The example of the indigenous people who have mostly been found in this condition seems to support the idea that humanity was meant to stay in it forever, that it represented the true youth of the world, and that all further advancements have merely been steps that, while seemingly aimed at perfecting the individual, have actually led to the decline of the species.

He ascribes to metallurgy and agriculture the fatal resolution which brought this Arcadian existence to an end. Agriculture entailed the origin of property in land. Moral and social inequality were introduced by the man who first enclosed a piece of land and said, This is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him. He was the founder of civil society.

He attributes the disastrous decision that ended this idyllic way of life to metallurgy and agriculture. Agriculture led to the concept of owning land. Moral and social inequality began with the person who first fenced off a piece of land and declared, “This is mine,” and found people naive enough to accept it. He was the one who started civil society.

The general argument amounts to this: Man's faculty of improving himself is the source of his other faculties, including his sociability, and has been fatal to his happiness. The circumstances of his primeval life favoured the growth of this faculty, and in making man sociable they made him wicked; they developed the reason of the individual and thereby caused the species to deteriorate. If the process had stopped at a certain point, all would have been well; but man's capacities, stimulated by fortuitous circumstances, urged him onward, and leaving behind him the peaceful Arcadia where he should have remained safe and content, he set out on the fatal road which led to the calamities of civilisation. We need not follow Rousseau in his description of those calamities which he attributes to wealth and the artificial conditions of society. His indictment was too general and rhetorical to make much impression. In truth, a more powerful and comprehensive case against civilised society was drawn up about the same time, though with a very different motive, by one whose thought represented all that was opposed to Rousseau's teaching. Burke's early work, A Vindication of Natural Society, [Footnote: A.D. 1756.] was written to show that all the objections which Deists like Bolingbroke urged against artificial religion could be brought with greater force against artificial society, and he worked out in detail a historical picture of the evils of civilisation which is far more telling than Rousseau's generalities. [Footnote: In his admirable edition of The Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1915), p. 89, Vaughan suggests that in Rousseau's later works we may possibly detect "the first faint beginnings" of a belief in Progress, and attributes this to the influence of Montesquieu.]

The main argument is this: A person's ability to improve themselves is the foundation of their other abilities, including being social, and this has harmed their happiness. The conditions of early human life supported the development of this ability, and in making people social, they also made them corrupt; they enhanced individual reasoning but caused the species to decline. If things had stopped at a certain stage, it would have been fine; but human potentials, encouraged by random circumstances, pushed them forward, making them leave behind the peaceful paradise where they could have stayed safe and happy, and instead, they embarked on the disastrous path toward the troubles of civilization. We don’t need to follow Rousseau in detailing those troubles that he blames on wealth and the artificial aspects of society. His arguments were too broad and dramatic to leave a strong impact. In reality, a more powerful and thorough critique of civilization was made around the same time, although for very different reasons, by someone whose ideas were completely contrary to Rousseau’s. Burke’s early work, A Vindication of Natural Society, [Footnote: A.D. 1756.] was written to demonstrate that all the criticisms that Deists like Bolingbroke made against artificial religion could be applied even more forcefully to artificial society. He provided a detailed historical depiction of the problems of civilization that is much more convincing than Rousseau's general statements. [Footnote: In his excellent edition of The Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1915), p. 89, Vaughan suggests that in Rousseau's later works we may possibly notice "the first faint beginnings" of a belief in Progress, attributing this to the influence of Montesquieu.]

3.

3.

If civilisation has been the curse of man, it might seem that the logical course for Rousseau to recommend was its destruction. This was the inference which Voltaire drew in Timon, to laugh the whole theory out of court. But Rousseau did not suggest a movement to destroy all the libraries and all the works of art in the world, to put to death or silence all the savants, to pull down the cities, and burn the ships. He was not a mere dreamer, and his Arcadia was no more than a Utopian ideal, by the light of which he conceived that the society of his own day might be corrected and transformed. He attached his hopes to equality, democracy, and a radical change in education.

If civilization has been a burden on humanity, it might seem logical for Rousseau to advocate for its destruction. This is the conclusion Voltaire reached in Timon, dismissing the entire theory. However, Rousseau didn’t propose a movement to demolish all libraries and artworks, to execute or silence all scholars, to tear down cities, or to burn ships. He wasn't just a dreamer, and his ideal world was merely a Utopian vision, by which he believed the society of his time could be improved and transformed. He placed his hopes in equality, democracy, and a fundamental change in education.

Equality: this revolutionary idea was of course quite compatible with the theory of Progress, and was soon to be closely associated with it. But it is easy to understand that the two ideas should first have appeared in antagonism to each other. The advance of knowledge and the increase of man's power over nature had virtually profited only a minority. When Fontenelle or Voltaire vaunted the illumination of their age and glorified the modern revolution in scientific thought, they took account only of a small class of privileged people. Higher education, Voltaire observed, is not for cobblers or kitchenmaids; "on n'a jamais pretendu eclairer les cordonniers et les servantes." The theory of Progress had so far left the masses out of account. Rousseau contrasted the splendour of the French court, the luxury of the opulent, the enlightenment of those who had the opportunity of education, with the hard lot of the ignorant mass of peasants, whose toil paid for the luxury of many of the idle enlightened people who amused themselves at Paris. The horror of this contrast, which left Voltaire cold, was the poignant motive which inspired Rousseau, a man of the people, in constructing his new doctrine. The existing inequality seemed an injustice which rendered the self-complacency of the age revolting. If this is the result of progressive civilisation, what is progress worth? The next step is to declare that civilisation is the causa malorum and that what is named progress is really regress. But Rousseau found a way of circumventing pessimism. He asked himself, cannot equality be realised in an organised state, founded on natural right? The Social Contract was his answer, and there we can see the living idea of equality detaching itself from the dead theory of degradation. [Footnote: The consistency of the Social Contract with the Discourse on Inequality has been much debated. They deal with two distinct problems, and the Social Contract does not mark any change in the author's views. Though it was not published till 1762 he had been working at it since 1753.]

Equality: this revolutionary idea was, of course, perfectly aligned with the theory of Progress and would soon be closely linked with it. However, it's easy to see why the two ideas initially appeared to oppose each other. The advancement of knowledge and the growth of human power over nature had primarily benefited only a small group. When Fontenelle or Voltaire praised the enlightenment of their time and celebrated the modern revolution in scientific thinking, they considered only a privileged few. Higher education, as Voltaire pointed out, isn’t meant for cobblers or kitchenmaids; "no one has ever claimed to enlighten the cobblers and the maids." The theory of Progress had so far overlooked the masses. Rousseau highlighted the contrast between the grandeur of the French court, the luxury of the wealthy, the enlightenment of those who had access to education, and the tough lives of the ignorant peasantry, whose hard work financed the luxury enjoyed by many idle intellectuals in Paris. The starkness of this contrast, which Voltaire considered trivial, deeply motivated Rousseau, a man of the people, in formulating his new doctrine. The existing inequality seemed like an injustice that made the self-satisfaction of the era appalling. If this is the outcome of progressive civilization, what value does progress hold? The next conclusion would be to say that civilization is the source of all problems and that what’s called progress is actually regression. But Rousseau found a way to avoid pessimism. He wondered if equality could be achieved in a structured society based on natural rights. The Social Contract was his answer, showcasing the vibrant idea of equality emerging from the stagnant theory of decline. [Footnote: The consistency of the Social Contract with the Discourse on Inequality has been much debated. They address two distinct issues, and the Social Contract does not signify a change in the author's views. Although it was not published until 1762, he had been developing it since 1753.]

Arcadianism, which was thus only a side-issue for Rousseau, was the extreme expression of tendencies which appear in the speculations of other thinkers of the day. Morelly and Mably argued in favour of a reversion to simpler forms of life. They contemplated the foundation of socialistic communities by reviving institutions and practices which belonged to a past period of social evolution. Mably, inspired by Plato, thought it possible by legislation to construct a state of antique pattern. [Footnote: For Mably's political doctrines see Guerrier's monograph, L'Abbe de Mably (1886), where it is shown that among "the theories which determined in advance the course of the events of 1789" the Abbe's played a role which has not been duly recognised.] They ascribed evils of civilisation to inequality arising from the existence of private property, but Morelly rejected the view of the "bold sophist" Rousseau that science and art were to blame. He thought that aided by science and learning man might reach a state based on communism, resembling the state of nature but more perfect, and he planned an ideal constitution in his romance of the Floating Islands. [Footnote: Naufrage des isles flottantes ou Basiliade du celebre Pilpai (1753). It begins: "je chante le regne aimable de la Verite et de la Nature." Morelly's other work, Code de la Nature, appeared in 1755.] Different as these views were, they represent the idea of regress; they imply a condemnation of the tendencies of actual social development and recommend a return to simpler and more primitive conditions.

Arcadianism, which was just a minor issue for Rousseau, was the ultimate expression of ideas that appeared in the thoughts of other thinkers of the time. Morelly and Mably advocated for a return to simpler ways of life. They envisioned the creation of socialist communities by reviving institutions and practices from an earlier stage of social development. Mably, influenced by Plato, believed it was possible through legislation to build a state reminiscent of ancient times. [Footnote: For Mably's political doctrines see Guerrier's monograph, L'Abbe de Mably (1886), which shows that among "the theories that predetermined the course of the events of 1789," the Abbe's had a role that has not been properly recognized.] They attributed the problems of civilization to inequality caused by private property, but Morelly dismissed the argument of the "bold sophist" Rousseau that science and art were the culprits. He believed that with the help of science and education, humanity could achieve a state based on communism, similar to the state of nature but better, and he proposed an ideal constitution in his novel, the Floating Islands. [Footnote: Naufrage des isles flottantes ou Basiliade du celebre Pilpai (1753). It starts: "I sing the delightful reign of Truth and Nature." Morelly's other work, Code de la Nature, was published in 1755.] Although these perspectives differed, they all represent the idea of regression; they criticize the trends of contemporary social development and advocate for a return to simpler and more primitive conditions.

Even Diderot, though he had little sympathy with Utopian speculations, was attracted by the idea of the simplification of society, and met Rousseau so far as to declare that the happiest state was a mean between savage and civilised life.

Even Diderot, although he wasn't very into Utopian ideas, was drawn to the concept of simplifying society and agreed with Rousseau about the notion that the happiest state lies somewhere between a primitive and a civilized life.

"I am convinced," he wrote, "that the industry of man has gone too far and that if it had stopped long ago and if it were possible to simplify the results, we should not be the worse. I believe there is a limit in civilisation, a limit more conformable to the felicity of man in general and far less distant from the savage state than is imagined; but how to return to it, having left it, or how to remain in it, if we were there? I know not." [Footnote: Refutation de l'ouvrage d'Helvetius in OEuvres ii. p. 431. Elsewhere (p. 287) he argues that in a community without arts and industries there are fewer crimes than in a civilised state, but men are not so happy.]

"I am convinced," he wrote, "that humanity has gone too far in its pursuits, and if we had paused long ago and made the results simpler, we wouldn't be worse off. I believe there’s a limit to civilization, one that aligns better with the overall happiness of people and is much closer to a primitive state than we think; but how do we return to it after leaving, or how do we stay in it if we were there? I don’t know." [Footnote: Refutation de l'ouvrage d'Helvetius in OEuvres ii. p. 431. Elsewhere (p. 287) he argues that in a community without arts and industries there are fewer crimes than in a civilized state, but people are not as happy.]

His picture of the savages of Tahiti in the Supplement au voyage de Bougainville was not seriously meant, but it illustrates the fact that in certain moods he felt the fascination of Rousseau's Arcadia.

His portrayal of the Tahitian natives in the Supplement au voyage de Bougainville was not meant to be taken seriously, but it shows that at times he was captivated by Rousseau's idea of paradise.

D'Holbach met all these theories by pointing out that human development, from the "state of nature" to social life and the ideas and commodities of civilisation, is itself natural, given the innate tendency of man to improve his lot. To return to the simpler life of the forests—or to any bygone stage—would be denaturer l'homme, it would be contrary to nature; and if he could do so, it would only be to recommence the career begun by his ancestors and pass again through the same successive phases of history. [Footnote: Syst. soc. i. 16, p. 190.]

D'Holbach countered all these theories by arguing that human development, from the "state of nature" to social life and the ideas and goods of civilization, is itself natural, given humanity's inherent desire to better their situation. Going back to the simpler life of the forests—or to any previous stage—would be to denature humanity; it would go against nature. Even if it could happen, it would only lead to repeating the journey started by our ancestors and going through the same stages of history again. [Footnote: Syst. soc. i. 16, p. 190.]

There was, indeed, one question which caused some embarrassment to believers in Progress. The increase of wealth and luxury was evidently a salient feature in modern progressive states; and it was clear that there was an intimate connection between the growth of knowledge and the growth of commerce and industrial arts, and that the natural progress of these meant an ever-increasing accumulation of riches and the practice of more refined luxury. The question, therefore, whether luxury is injurious to the general happiness occupied the attention of the philosophers. [Footnote: D'Holbach, ib. iii. 7; Diderot, art. Luxe in the Encylopaedia; Helvetius, De l'esprit, i. 3.] If it is injurious, does it not follow that the forces on which admittedly Progress depends are leading in an undesirable direction? Should they be obstructed, or is it wiser to let things follow their natural tendency (laisser aller les choses suivant leur pente naturelle)? Voltaire accepted wealth with all its consequences. D'Holbach proved to his satisfaction that luxury always led to the ruin of nations. Diderot and Helvetius arrayed the arguments which could be urged on both sides. Perhaps the most reasonable contribution to the subject was an essay of Hume.

There was definitely one question that made believers in Progress a bit uncomfortable. The rise of wealth and luxury was obviously a prominent feature in modern progressive societies, and it was clear that there was a close link between the increase in knowledge and the growth of commerce and industry. This natural progress led to a continuous accumulation of wealth and a trend towards more sophisticated luxury. The question of whether luxury harms overall happiness caught the philosophers' attention. [Footnote: D'Holbach, ib. iii. 7; Diderot, art. Luxe in the Encyclopedia; Helvetius, De l'esprit, i. 3.] If it does harm, doesn't that mean the forces that clearly drive Progress are leading us the wrong way? Should we try to stop them, or is it smarter to let things unfold naturally? Voltaire embraced wealth with all its implications. D'Holbach was convinced that luxury always resulted in the downfall of nations. Diderot and Helvetius laid out arguments for both sides. Perhaps the most sensible take on the issue came from an essay by Hume.

4.

4.

It is obvious that Rousseau and all other theorists of Regress would be definitely refuted if it could be proved by an historical investigation that in no period in the past had man's lot been happier than in the present. Such an inquiry was undertaken by the Chevalier de Chastellux. His book On Public Felicity, or Considerations on the lot of Men in the various Epochs of History, appeared in 1772 and had a wide circulation. [Footnote: There was a new edition in 1776 with an important additional chapter.] It is a survey of the history of the western world and aims at proving the certainty of future Progress. It betrays the influence both of the Encyclopaedists and of the Economists. Chastellux is convinced that human nature can be indefinitely moulded by institutions; that enlightenment is a necessary condition of general happiness; that war and superstition, for which governments and priests are responsible, are the principal obstacles.

It’s clear that Rousseau and other theorists of Regress would be completely disproven if historical research could show that no time in the past was better for humanity than today. This investigation was carried out by the Chevalier de Chastellux. His book, On Public Felicity, or Considerations on the Lot of Men in the Various Epochs of History, was published in 1772 and gained widespread popularity. [Footnote: There was a new edition in 1776 with an important additional chapter.] The book reviews the history of the western world and seeks to demonstrate the certainty of future progress. It reflects the influence of both the Encyclopaedists and the Economists. Chastellux believes that human nature can be shaped indefinitely by institutions; that enlightenment is a crucial condition for overall happiness; and that war and superstition, for which governments and priests are to blame, are the main obstacles.

But he attempted to do what none of his masters had done, to test the question methodically from the data of history. Turgot, and Voltaire in his way, had traced the growth of civilisation; the originality of Chastellux lay in concentrating attention on the eudaemonic issue, in examining each historical period for the purpose of discovering whether people on the whole were happy and enviable. Has there ever been a time, he inquired, in which public felicity was greater than in our own, in which it would have been desirable to remain for ever, and to which it would now be desirable to return?

But he tried to do what none of his teachers had done: to methodically examine the question using historical data. Turgot, and Voltaire in his own way, had traced the development of civilization; the uniqueness of Chastellux was in focusing on the question of happiness, analyzing each historical period to find out if, overall, people were happy and had a good life. He asked, has there ever been a time when public happiness was greater than it is now, when it would have been ideal to stay forever, and to which we would want to return?

He begins by brushing away the hypothesis of an Arcadia. We know really nothing about primitive man, there is not sufficient evidence to authorise conjectures. We know man only as he has existed in organised societies, and if we are to condemn modern civilisation and its prospects, we must find our term of comparison not in an imaginary golden age but in a known historical epoch. And we must be careful not to fall into the mistakes of confusing public prosperity with general happiness, and of considering only the duration or aggrandisement of empires and ignoring the lot of the common people.

He starts by dismissing the idea of an Arcadia. We really know very little about early humans; there isn’t enough evidence to support any guesses. We only understand humans as they have existed in organized societies, and if we’re going to criticize modern civilization and its future, we need to compare it with a real historical period, not a fictional golden age. We also need to be cautious not to confuse public wealth with overall happiness, and not to focus solely on the expansion or longevity of empires while overlooking the experiences of ordinary people.

His survey of history is summary and superficial enough. He gives reasons for believing that no peoples from the ancient Egyptians and Assyrians to the Europeans of the Renaissance can be judged happy. Yet what about the Greeks? Theirs was an age of enlightenment. In a few pages he examines their laws and history, and concludes, "We are compelled to acknowledge that what is called the bel age of Greece was a time of pain and torture for humanity." And in ancient history, generally, "slavery alone sufficed to make man's condition a hundred times worse than it is at present." The miseries of life in the Roman period are even more apparent than in the Greek. What Englishman or Frenchman would tolerate life as lived in ancient Rome? It is interesting to remember that four years later an Englishman who had an incomparably wider and deeper knowledge of history declared it to be probable that in the age of the Antonines civilised Europe enjoyed greater happiness than at any other period.

His overview of history is brief and shallow enough. He argues that no people, from the ancient Egyptians and Assyrians to the Europeans of the Renaissance, can be considered truly happy. But what about the Greeks? They experienced an age of enlightenment. In just a few pages, he looks at their laws and history, concluding, "We must admit that what is called the beautiful age of Greece was a time of pain and suffering for humanity." And in ancient history as a whole, "slavery alone made man's situation a hundred times worse than it is today." The hardships of life during the Roman era are even more obvious than in Greece. What Englishman or Frenchman would put up with life in ancient Rome? It's worth noting that four years later, an Englishman with a far broader and deeper understanding of history claimed it was likely that during the age of the Antonines, civilized Europe experienced more happiness than at any other time.

Rome declined and Christianity came. Its purpose was not to render men happy on earth, and we do not find that it made rulers less avaricious or less sanguinary, peoples more patient or quiet, crimes rarer, punishments less cruel, treaties more faithfully observed, or wars waged more humanely. The conclusion is that it is only those who are profoundly ignorant of the past who can regret "the good old times."

Rome fell and Christianity emerged. Its goal wasn't to make people happy on Earth, and we don't see that it made rulers less greedy or less violent, people more patient or peaceful, crimes less common, punishments less harsh, treaties more reliably kept, or wars fought more humanely. The takeaway is that only those who are deeply unaware of history can long for "the good old days."

Throughout this survey Chastellux does not, like Turgot, make any attempt to show that the race was progressing, however slowly. On the contrary, he sets the beginning of continuous Progress in the Renaissance—here agreeing with d'Alembert and Voltaire. The intellectual movement, which originated then and resulted in the enlightenment of his own day, was a condition of social progress. But alone it would not have been enough, as is proved by the fact that the intellectual brilliancy of the great age of Greece exerted no beneficent effects on the well-being of the people. Nor indeed was there any perceptible improvement in the prospect of happiness for the people at large during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, notwithstanding the progress of science and the arts. But the terrible wars of this period exhausted Europe, and this financial exhaustion has supplied the requisite conditions for attaining a measure of felicity never realised in the past.

Throughout this survey, Chastellux doesn’t, like Turgot, try to show that humanity was progressing, even if slowly. On the contrary, he marks the start of continuous progress in the Renaissance—here he agrees with d'Alembert and Voltaire. The intellectual movement that began then and led to the enlightenment of his own time was essential for social progress. But on its own, it wouldn’t have been enough, as shown by the fact that the intellectual brilliance of ancient Greece didn’t positively impact the well-being of its people. In fact, there was no noticeable improvement in the overall happiness of the general population during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, despite advancements in science and the arts. However, the devastating wars of this period drained Europe, and this financial strain has created the conditions necessary for achieving a level of happiness never experienced before.

Peace is an advantageous condition for the progress of reason, but especially when it is the result of the exhaustion of peoples and their satiety of fighting. Frivolous ideas disappear; political bodies, like organisms, have the care of self-preservation impressed upon them by pain; the human mind, hitherto exercised on agreeable objects, falls back with more energy on useful objects; a more successful appeal can be made to the rights of humanity; and princes, who have become creditors and debtors of their subjects, permit them to be happy in order that they may be more solvent or more patient.

Peace is a beneficial state for the advancement of reason, especially when it comes from the exhaustion of people and their weariness of fighting. Shallow ideas fade away; political entities, much like living organisms, are driven by the need for self-preservation triggered by pain; the human mind, previously focused on pleasant things, redirects with greater energy toward practical matters; a stronger case can be made for human rights; and rulers, who find themselves as creditors and debtors to their subjects, allow them to be happy so they can be more financially stable or more tolerant.

This is not very lucid or convincing; but the main point is that intellectual enlightenment would be ineffective without the co-operation of political events, and no political events would permanently help humanity without the progress of knowledge.

This isn’t very clear or persuasive; but the main point is that intellectual growth wouldn’t be effective without the support of political events, and no political events would permanently benefit humanity without the advancement of knowledge.

Public felicity consists—Chastellux follows the Economists—in external and domestic peace, abundance and liberty, the liberty of tranquil enjoyment of one's own; and ordinary signs of it are flourishing agriculture, large populations, and the growth of trade and industry. He is at pains to show the superiority of modern to ancient agriculture, and he avails himself of the researches of Hume to prove the comparatively greater populousness of modern European countries. As for the prospect of peace, he takes a curiously optimistic view. A system of alliances has made Europe a sort of confederated republic, and the balance of power has rendered the design of a universal monarchy, such as that which Louis XIV. essayed, a chimera. [Footnote: So Rivarol, writing in 1783 (OEuvres, i. pp. 4 and 52): "Never did the world offer such a spectacle. Europe has reached such a high degree of power that history has nothing to compare with it. It is virtually a federative republic, composed of empires and kingdoms, and the most powerful that has ever existed."] All the powerful nations are burdened with debt. War, too, is a much more difficult enterprise than it used to be; every campaign of the king of Prussia has been more arduous than all the conquests of Attila. It looks as if the Peace of 1762-3 possessed elements of finality. The chief danger he discerns in the overseas policy of the English—auri sacra fames. Divination of this kind has never been happy; a greater thinker, Auguste Comte, was to venture on more dogmatic predictions of the cessation of wars, which the event was no less utterly to belie. As for equality among men, Chastellux admits its desirability, but observes that there is pretty much the same amount of happiness (le bonheur se compense assez) in the different classes of society. "Courtiers and ministers are not happier than husbandmen and artisans." Inequalities and disportions in the lots of individuals are not incompatible with a positive measure of felicity. They are inconveniences incident to the perfectibility of the species, and they will be eliminated only when Progress reaches its final term. The best that can be done to remedy them is to accelerate the Progress of the race which will conduct it one day to the greatest possible happiness; not to restore a state of ignorance and simplicity, from which it would again escape.

Public happiness consists—Chastellux follows the Economists—in external and domestic peace, prosperity, and freedom, the freedom to peacefully enjoy one’s own life; and typical signs of it are thriving agriculture, large populations, and the growth of trade and industry. He emphasizes the superiority of modern agriculture over ancient practices and uses Hume's research to demonstrate the relatively higher population of modern European countries. Regarding the prospect of peace, he takes a surprisingly optimistic view. A system of alliances has turned Europe into a sort of confederated republic, and the balance of power has made the idea of a universal monarchy, like the one Louis XIV. attempted, seem unrealistic. [Footnote: So Rivarol, writing in 1783 (OEuvres, i. pp. 4 and 52): "Never did the world offer such a spectacle. Europe has reached such a high degree of power that history has nothing to compare with it. It is virtually a federative republic, composed of empires and kingdoms, and the most powerful that has ever existed."] All the powerful nations are struggling with debt. War is also a much more challenging endeavor than it used to be; every campaign of the King of Prussia has been tougher than all of Attila's conquests. It appears that the Peace of 1762-3 has elements of permanence. The main danger he sees is in the overseas policy of the English—auri sacra fames. Predictions like this have rarely been accurate; a greater thinker, Auguste Comte, would later make more dogmatic predictions about the end of wars, which events would utterly disprove. As for equality among men, Chastellux acknowledges its desirability but notes that there is roughly the same level of happiness (le bonheur se compense assez) across different social classes. "Courtiers and ministers are not happier than farmers and artisans." Inequalities and disparities in individual circumstances are not incompatible with a certain degree of happiness. They are inconveniences that come with the perfectibility of humanity and will only be resolved when Progress reaches its ultimate goal. The best approach to alleviate them is to accelerate the Progress of humanity, which will eventually lead it to the greatest possible happiness; not to revert to a state of ignorance and simplicity, from which it would again break free.

The general argument of the book may be resumed briefly. Felicity has never been realised in any period of the past. No government, however esteemed, set before itself to achieve what ought to be the sole object of government, "the greatest happiness of the greatest number of individuals." Now, for the first time in human history, intellectual enlightenment, other circumstances fortunately concurring, has brought about a condition of things, in which this object can no longer be ignored, and there is a prospect that it will gradually gain the ascendant. In the meantime, things have improved; the diffusion of knowledge is daily ameliorating men's lot, and far from envying any age in the past we ought to consider ourselves much happier than the ancients.

The main argument of the book can be summarized briefly. Happiness has never been fully achieved at any point in history. No government, no matter how respected, has aimed to fulfill what should be the primary goal of government: "the greatest happiness for the greatest number of individuals." Now, for the first time in human history, increased knowledge and other favorable conditions have created a situation where this goal can no longer be overlooked, and there's hope that it will eventually become a reality. In the meantime, things have improved; the spread of knowledge is continuously enhancing people's lives, and instead of envying past eras, we should recognize that we are much happier than those in ancient times.

We may wonder at this writer's easy confidence in applying the criterion of happiness to different societies. Yet the difficulty of such comparisons was, I believe, first pointed out by Comte. [Footnote: Cours de philosophie positive, iv. 379.] It is impossible, he says, to compare two states of society and determine that in one more happiness was enjoyed than in the other. The happiness of an individual requires a certain degree of harmony between his faculties and his environment. But there is always a natural tendency towards the establishment of such an equilibrium, and there is no means of discovering by argument or by direct experience the situation of a society in this respect. Therefore, he concludes, the question of happiness must be eliminated from any scientific treatment of civilisation.

We might question this writer's easy confidence in using happiness as a standard for different societies. However, I believe Comte was the first to highlight the challenges of such comparisons. [Footnote: Cours de philosophie positive, iv. 379.] He argues that it's impossible to compare two societies and determine where more happiness exists. An individual's happiness depends on a certain level of harmony between their abilities and their environment. Yet, there's always a natural drive to achieve this balance, and we cannot find out, through arguments or direct experience, how a society stands in this regard. Therefore, he concludes that the issue of happiness should be excluded from any scientific study of civilization.

Chastellux won a remarkable success. His work was highly praised by Voltaire, and was translated into English, Italian, and German. It condensed, on a single issue, the optimistic doctrines of the philosophers, and appeared to give them a more solid historical foundation than Voltaire's Essay on Manners had supplied. It provided the optimists with new arguments against Rousseau, and must have done much to spread and confirm faith in perfectibility. [Footnote: Soon after the publication of the book of Chastellux—though I do not suggest any direct connection—a society of Illuminati, who also called themselves the Perfectibilists, was founded at Ingoldstadt, who proposed to effect a pacific transformation of humanity. See Javary, De l'idee de progres, p. 73.]

Chastellux achieved remarkable success. His work received high praise from Voltaire and was translated into English, Italian, and German. It summarized, on a single topic, the optimistic ideas of the philosophers, and seemed to provide them with a more solid historical foundation than Voltaire's Essay on Manners had offered. It gave optimists new arguments against Rousseau and likely played a significant role in spreading and reinforcing belief in perfectibility. [Footnote: Soon after the publication of Chastellux's book—though I do not suggest any direct connection—a society of Illuminati, who also called themselves the Perfectibilists, was founded in Ingolstadt, proposing to achieve a peaceful transformation of humanity. See Javary, De l'idee de progres, p. 73.]





CHAPTER X. THE YEAR 2440

1.

The leaders of thought in France did not look far forward into the future or attempt to trace the definite lines on which the human race might be expected to develop. They contented themselves with principles and vague generalities, and they had no illusions as to the slowness of the process of social amelioration; a rational morality, the condition of improvement, was only in its infancy. A passage in a work of the Abbe Morellet probably reflects faithfully enough the comfortable though not extravagant optimism which was current. [Footnote: Reflexions sur les avantages d'ecrire et d'imprimer sur les matieres de l'administration (1764); in Melanges, vol. iii. p. 55. Morellet held, like d'Holbach, that society is only the development and improvement of nature itself (ib. p. 6).]

The thinkers in France didn't look far into the future or try to outline how humanity would likely evolve. They were satisfied with principles and broad generalizations, and they were realistic about the slow pace of social improvement; a rational morality, essential for progress, was still just beginning. A passage from a work by Abbé Morellet likely captures the comfortable yet restrained optimism that was common. [Footnote: Reflexions sur les avantages d'ecrire et d'imprimer sur les matieres de l'administration (1764); in Melanges, vol. iii. p. 55. Morellet believed, like d'Holbach, that society is merely the development and improvement of nature itself (ib. p. 6).]

Let us hope for the amelioration of man's lot as a consequence of the progress of the enlightenment (des lumieres) and labours of the educated (des gens instruits); let us trust that the errors and even the injustices of our age may not rob us of this consoling hope. The history of society presents a continuous alternation of light and darkness, reason and extravagance, humanity and barbarism; but in the succession of ages we can observe good gradually increasing in ever greater proportion. What educated man, if he is not a misanthrope or misled by vain declamations, would really wish he had lived in the barbarous and poetical time which Homer paints in such fair and terrifying colours? Who regrets that he was not born at Sparta among those pretended heroes who made it a virtue to insult nature, practised theft, and gloried in the murder of a Helot; or at Carthage, the scene of human sacrifices, or at Rome amid the proscriptions or under the rule of a Nero or a Caligula? Let as agree that man advances, though slowly, towards light and happiness.

Let’s hope for improvement in humanity's situation thanks to the advancements brought about by enlightenment and the efforts of educated individuals; let’s trust that the mistakes and even the injustices of our time won't take away this comforting hope. The history of society shows a constant back-and-forth between light and darkness, reason and craziness, human kindness and barbarity; but over the ages, we can see goodness gradually increasing in greater amounts. What educated person, unless they’re a misanthrope or tricked by empty rhetoric, would genuinely want to have lived in the brutal and poetic era that Homer describes in such beautiful yet frightening terms? Who wishes they had been born in Sparta among those so-called heroes who made it a point to defy nature, committed theft, and took pride in killing a Helot, or in Carthage, known for human sacrifices, or in Rome during the political purges or under the rule of Nero or Caligula? Let’s agree that humanity is moving forward, even if it’s slowly, toward light and happiness.

But though the most influential writers were sober in speculating about the future, it is significant of their effectiveness in diffusing the idea of Progress that now for the first time a prophetic Utopia was constructed. Hitherto, as I have before observed, ideal states were either projected into the remote past or set in some distant, vaguely-known region, where fancy could build freely. To project them into the future was a new thing, and when in 1770 Sebastien Mercier described what human civilisation would be in A.D. 2440, it was a telling sign of the power which the idea of Progress was beginning to exercise.

But even though the most influential writers were careful when imagining the future, it's important to note how effective they were in spreading the idea of Progress that, for the first time, a prophetic Utopia was created. Until then, as I mentioned before, ideal societies were either envisioned in the distant past or placed in some far-off, vaguely known area where imagination could roam freely. Projecting them into the future was something new; when Sebastien Mercier described what human civilization would look like in A.D. 2440 in 1770, it was a significant indicator of how powerful the idea of Progress was starting to become.

2.

2.

Mercier has been remembered, or rather forgotten, as an inferior dramatist. He was a good deal more, and the researches of M. Beclard into his life and works enable us to appreciate him. If it is an overstatement to say that his soul reflected in miniature the very soul of his age, [Footnote: L. Beclard, Sebastien Mercier, sa vie, son oeuvre, son temps (1903), p. vii.] he was assuredly one of its characteristic products. He reminds us in some ways of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre, who was one of his heroes. All his activities were urged by the dream of a humanity regenerated by reason, all his energy devoted to bringing about its accomplishment. Saint-Pierre's idea of perpetual peace inspired an early essay on the scourge of war.

Mercier is often remembered, or more accurately forgotten, as an inferior playwright. He was much more than that, and M. Beclard's research into his life and works helps us appreciate him. While it might be an exaggeration to say that his soul captured the essence of his time in miniature, [Footnote: L. Beclard, Sebastien Mercier, sa vie, son oeuvre, son temps (1903), p. vii.] he was definitely one of its defining figures. In some ways, he is reminiscent of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre, one of his heroes. All his efforts were driven by the vision of a humanity improved by reason, and all his energy was dedicated to making that vision a reality. Saint-Pierre's concept of perpetual peace inspired an early essay about the horrors of war.

The theories of Rousseau exercised at first an irresistible attraction, but modern civilisation had too strong a hold on him; he was too Parisian in temper to acquiesce for long in the doctrine of Arcadianism. He composed a book on The Savage to illustrate the text that the true standard of morality is the heart of primitive man, and to prove that the best thing we could do is to return to the forest; but in the process of writing it he seems to have come to the conclusion that the whole doctrine was fallacious. [Footnote: Mercier's early essay: Des malheurs de la guerre et des avantages de la paix (1766). On the savage: L'homme sauvage (1767). For the opposite thesis see the Songes philosophiques (1768). He describes a state of perfect happiness in a planet where beings live in perpetual contemplation of the infinite. He appreciates the work of philosophers from Socrates to Leibnitz, and describes Rousseau as standing before the swelling stream, but cursing it. It may be suspected that the writings of Leibnitz had much to do with Mercier's conversion.] The transformation of his opinions was the work of a few months. He then came forward with the opposite thesis that all events have been ordered for man's felicity, and he began to work on an imaginary picture of the state to which man might find his way within seven hundred years.

The ideas of Rousseau initially captivated him, but modern society had too strong a grip on him; he was too much a creature of Paris to accept the idea of Arcadianism for long. He wrote a book called The Savage to illustrate the point that the true measure of morality lies in the heart of primitive man, and to argue that the best choice is to return to nature; but while writing it, he seems to have realized that the whole idea was flawed. [Footnote: Mercier's early essay: Des malheurs de la guerre et des avantages de la paix (1766). On the savage: L'homme sauvage (1767). For the opposite thesis see the Songes philosophiques (1768). He describes a state of perfect happiness on a planet where beings exist in constant contemplation of the infinite. He acknowledges the work of philosophers from Socrates to Leibnitz and depicts Rousseau as standing by a rushing stream, but cursing it. One could suspect that Leibnitz's writings significantly influenced Mercier's change of mind.] The shift in his views took just a few months. He then proposed the opposite idea that all events have been arranged for humanity's happiness and began to work on an imagined vision of the state that man might achieve in seven hundred years.

L'an 2440 was published anonymously at Amsterdam in 1770. [Footnote: The author's name first appeared in the 3rd ed., 1799. A German translation, by C. F. Weisse, was published in London in 1772. The English version, by Dr. Hooper, appeared in the same year, and a new edition in 1802; the translator changed the title to Memoirs of the year Two thousand five hundred.] Its circulation in France was rigorously forbidden, because it implied a merciless criticism of the administration. It was reprinted in London and Neuchatel, and translated into English and German.

L'an 2440 was published anonymously in Amsterdam in 1770. [Footnote: The author’s name first appeared in the 3rd edition, 1799. A German translation by C. F. Weisse was published in London in 1772. The English version by Dr. Hooper came out the same year, with a new edition in 1802; the translator changed the title to Memoirs of the Year Two Thousand Five Hundred.] Its circulation in France was strictly banned because it was a harsh critique of the government. It was reprinted in London and Neuchatel, and translated into English and German.

3.

3.

As the motto of his prophetic vision Mercier takes the saying of Leibnitz that "the present is pregnant of the future." Thus the phase of civilisation which he imagines is proposed as the outcome of the natural and inevitable march of history. The world of A.D. 2440 in which a man born in the eighteenth century who has slept an enchanted sleep awakes to find himself, is composed of nations who live in a family concord rarely interrupted by war. But of the world at large we hear little; the imagination of Mercier is concentrated on France, and particularly Paris. He is satisfied with knowing that slavery has been abolished; that the rivalry of France and England has been replaced by an indestructible alliance; that the Pope, whose authority is still august, has renounced his errors and returned to the customs of the primitive Church; that French plays are performed in China. The changes in Paris are a sufficient index of the general transformation.

As the motto of his prophetic vision, Mercier adopts Leibnitz's saying that "the present is full of potential for the future." Therefore, the phase of civilization he envisions is presented as the result of the natural and inevitable progression of history. The world of A.D. 2440, where a man born in the eighteenth century awakens from an enchanted sleep, consists of nations that exist in a familial harmony rarely disrupted by war. However, we hear little about the world beyond this; Mercier's imagination is focused on France, especially Paris. He is content knowing that slavery has been abolished, that the rivalry between France and England has been replaced by a strong alliance, that the Pope, whose authority remains respected, has renounced his mistakes and reverted to the practices of the early Church, and that French plays are performed in China. The changes in Paris are a clear reflection of the overall transformation.

The constitution of France is still monarchical. Its population has increased by one half; that of the capital remains about the same. Paris has been rebuilt on a scientific plan; its sanitary arrangements have been brought to perfection; it is well lit; and every provision has been made for the public safety. Private hospitality is so large that inns have disappeared, but luxury at table is considered a revolting crime. Tea, coffee, and tobacco are no longer imported. [Footnote: In the first edition of the book commerce was abolished.] There is no system of credit; everything is paid for in ready money, and this practice has led to a remarkable simplicity in dress. Marriages are contracted only through mutual inclination; dowries have been abolished. Education is governed by the ideas of Rousseau, and is directed, in a narrow spirit, to the promotion of morality. Italian, German, English, and Spanish are taught in schools, but the study of the classical languages has disappeared; Latin does not help a man to virtue. History too is neglected and discouraged, for it is "the disgrace of humanity, every page being crowded with crimes and follies." Theatres are government institutions, and have become the public schools of civic duties and morality. [Footnote: In 1769 Mercier began to carry out his programme of composing and adapting plays for instruction and edification. His theory of the true functions of the theatre he explained in a special treatise, Du theatre ou Nouvel Essai sur l'art dramatique (1773).]

The constitution of France is still monarchical. Its population has increased by fifty percent, while that of the capital remains about the same. Paris has been rebuilt with a scientific approach; its sanitation systems are perfected; it is well-lit, and all measures are in place for public safety. Private hospitality is so abundant that inns have disappeared, yet lavish dining is seen as a disgraceful act. Tea, coffee, and tobacco are no longer imported. [Footnote: In the first edition of the book, commerce was abolished.] There is no credit system; everything is paid for in cash, leading to a notable simplicity in clothing. Marriages are formed purely by mutual consent; dowries have been eliminated. Education is based on Rousseau's ideas and is narrowly focused on promoting morality. Italian, German, English, and Spanish are taught in schools, but the study of classical languages has vanished; Latin doesn’t contribute to virtue. History is also neglected and frowned upon, as it is viewed as "the disgrace of humanity, every page filled with crimes and follies." Theatres are government-operated and have become public schools for civic responsibilities and morality. [Footnote: In 1769, Mercier began implementing his plan to create and adapt plays for teaching and inspiring people. He detailed his theory on the true purposes of theatre in a specific treatise, Du theatre ou Nouvel Essai sur l'art dramatique (1773).]

The literary records of the past had been almost all deliberately destroyed by fire. It was found expedient to do away with useless and pernicious books which only obscured truth or contained perpetual repetitions of the same thing. A small closet in the public library sufficed to hold the ancient books which were permitted to escape the conflagration, and the majority of these were English. The writings of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre were placed next those of Fenelon. "His pen was weak, but his heart was sublime. Seven ages have given to his great and beautiful ideas a just maturity. His contemporaries regarded him as a visionary; his dreams, however, have become realities."

The literary records of the past were almost entirely destroyed by fire on purpose. It seemed practical to eliminate useless and harmful books that only clouded the truth or kept repeating the same ideas. A small closet in the public library was enough to hold the ancient books that survived the fire, and most of these were in English. The writings of Abbe de Saint-Pierre were placed next to those of Fenelon. "His writing was weak, but his heart was exceptional. Seven generations have given his great and beautiful ideas the maturity they deserve. His contemporaries saw him as a dreamer; however, his dreams have turned into reality."

The importance of men of letters as a social force was a favourite theme of Mercier, and in A.D. 2440 this will be duly recognised. But the State control which weighed upon them so heavily in 1770 is not to be entirely abolished. There is no preventive censorship to hinder publication, but there are censors. There are no fines or imprisonment, but there are admonitions. And if any one publishes a book defending principles which are considered dangerous, he is obliged to go about in a black mask.

The significance of intellectuals as a social force was a favorite topic of Mercier, and in A.D. 2440, this will be properly acknowledged. However, the government oversight that restricted them so much in 1770 won't be completely eliminated. There's no prior censorship to block publications, but censors still exist. There are no fines or prison sentences, but there are warnings. And if someone publishes a book supporting principles deemed dangerous, they must wear a black mask in public.

There is a state religion, Deism. There is probably no one who does not believe in God. But if any atheist were discovered, he would be put through a course of experimental physics. If he remained obdurate in his rejection of a "palpable and salutary truth," the nation would go into mourning and banish him from its borders.

There is a state religion, Deism. There’s probably no one who doesn’t believe in God. But if any atheist were found, they would be subjected to a course of experimental physics. If they still stubbornly rejected a "clear and beneficial truth," the country would go into mourning and banish them from its borders.

Every one has to work, but labour no longer resembles slavery. As there are no monks, nor numerous domestics, nor useless valets, nor work-men employed on the production of childish luxuries, a few daily hours of labour are sufficient for the public wants. Censors inquire into men's capacities, assign tasks to the unemployed, and if man be found fit for nothing but the consumption of food he is banished from the city.

Everyone has to work, but labor is no longer like slavery. Since there are no monks, no many servants, no unnecessary attendants, and no workers producing trivial luxuries, a few hours of daily work are enough to meet public needs. Officials assess people's abilities, assign tasks to the unemployed, and if someone is deemed fit only for eating, they are exiled from the city.

These are some of the leading features of the ideal future to which Mercier's imagination reached. He did not put it forward as a final term. Later ages, he said, will go further, for "where can the perfectibility of man stop, armed with geometry and the mechanical arts and chemistry?" But in his scanty prophecies of what science might effect he showed curiously little resource. The truth is that this had not much interest for him, and he did not see that scientific discoveries might transmute social conditions. The world of 2440, its intolerably docile and virtuous society, reflects two capital weaknesses in the speculation of the Encyclopaedist period: a failure to allow for the strength of human passions and interests, and a deficient appreciation of the meaning of liberty. Much as the reformers acclaimed and fought for toleration, they did not generally comprehend the value of the principle. They did not see that in a society organised and governed by Reason and Justice themselves, the unreserved toleration of false opinions would be the only palladium of progress; or that a doctrinaire State, composed of perfectly virtuous and deferential people, would arrest development and stifle origiality, by its ungenial if mild tyranny. Mercier's is no exception to the rule that ideal societies are always repellent; and there are probably few who would not rather be set down in Athens in the days of the "vile" Aristophanes, whose works Mercier condemned to the flames, than in his Paris of 2440.

These are some of the key features of the ideal future that Mercier envisioned. He didn’t propose it as the ultimate destination. He suggested that future generations will advance even further, because “where can the perfectibility of man stop, armed with geometry and the mechanical arts and chemistry?” However, in his limited predictions about what science might accomplish, he displayed surprisingly little imagination. The truth is, he wasn’t particularly interested in this, and he failed to recognize that scientific discoveries could change social conditions. The world of 2440, with its annoyingly compliant and virtuous society, reveals two significant weaknesses in the thinking of the Encyclopaedist period: a failure to consider the strength of human passions and interests, and a limited understanding of the concept of liberty. Although reformers celebrated and fought for toleration, they generally did not grasp its true value. They overlooked the fact that in a society organized and governed by Reason and Justice, the unconditional toleration of false opinions would be the only safeguard for progress; or that a rigidly doctrinaire state, made up of perfectly virtuous and obedient people, would halt development and suffocate originality with its unkind yet mild tyranny. Mercier’s vision is no exception to the rule that ideal societies are always unappealing; and there are likely few who would prefer to be in his Paris of 2440 rather than Athens in the days of the “vile” Aristophanes, whose works Mercier condemned to the flames.

4.

4.

That Bohemian man of letters, Restif de la Bretonne, whose unedifying novels the Parisians of 2440 would assuredly have rejected from their libraries, published in 1790 a heroic comedy representing how marriages would be arranged in "the year 2000," by which epoch he conceived that all social equalities would have disappeared in a fraternal society and twenty nations be allied to France under the wise supremacy of "our well-beloved monarch Louis Francois XXII." It was the Revolution that converted Restif to the conception of Progress, for hitherto his master had been Rousseau; but it can hardly be doubted that the motif and title of his play were suggested by the romance of Mercier. L'an 2440 and L'an 2000 are the first examples of the prophetic fiction which Mr. Edward Bellamy's Looking Backward was to popularise a hundred years later.

That Bohemian writer, Restif de la Bretonne, whose not-so-great novels the Parisians of 2440 would definitely have rejected from their libraries, published a heroic comedy in 1790 depicting how marriages would be arranged in "the year 2000." He imagined that by that time, all social inequalities would have vanished in a brotherly society, and twenty nations would be allied with France under the wise rule of "our beloved monarch Louis Francois XXII." It was the Revolution that turned Restif toward the idea of Progress; until then, his inspiration had been Rousseau. However, it’s clear that the theme and title of his play were influenced by Mercier's romance. L'an 2440 and L'an 2000 are the first examples of the prophetic fiction that Mr. Edward Bellamy's Looking Backward would popularize a hundred years later.

The Count de Volney's Ruins was another popular presentation of the hopes which the theory of Progress had awakened in France. Although the work was not published till after the outbreak of the Revolution, [Footnote: Les Ruines des empires, 1789. An English translation ran to a second edition (1795).] the plan had been conceived some years before. Volney was a traveller, deeply interested in oriental and classical antiquities, and, like Louis Le Roy, he approached the problem of man's destinies from the point of view of a student of the revolutions of empires.

The Count de Volney's Ruins was another well-received exploration of the hopes that the theory of Progress had sparked in France. Although it was published after the Revolution started, [Footnote: Les Ruines des empires, 1789. An English translation went into a second edition (1795).] the concept had been developed years earlier. Volney was a traveler with a deep interest in Eastern and classical antiquities, and like Louis Le Roy, he examined the issue of human fate from the perspective of someone studying the upheavals of empires.

The book opens with melancholy reflections amid the ruins of Palmyra. "Thus perish the works of men, and thus do nations and empires vanish away... Who can assure us that desolation like this will not one day be the lot of our own country?" Some traveller like himself will sit by the banks of the Seine, the Thames, or the Zuyder Zee, amid silent ruins, and weep for a people inurned and their greatness changed into an empty name. Has a mysterious Deity pronounced a secret malediction against the earth?

The book starts with sad thoughts among the ruins of Palmyra. "This is how the works of men fade away, and this is how nations and empires disappear... Who can guarantee that destruction like this won't someday be our own fate?" Some traveler, just like him, will sit by the banks of the Seine, the Thames, or the Zuyder Zee, surrounded by silent ruins, and mourn for a people buried and their greatness reduced to an empty name. Has some mysterious deity cast a hidden curse on the earth?

In this disconsolate mood he is visited by an apparition, who unveils the causes of men's misfortunes and shows that they are due to themselves. Man is governed by natural invariable laws, and he has only to study them to know the springs of his destiny, the causes of his evils and their remedies. The laws of his nature are self-love, desire of happiness, and aversion to pain; these are the simple and prolific principles of everything that happens in the moral world. Man is the artificer of his own fate. He may lament his weakness and folly; but "he has perhaps still more reason to be confident in his energies when he recollects from what point he has set out and to what heights he has been capable of elevating himself."

In this gloomy state, he is visited by a spirit that reveals the reasons for people's misfortunes, showing that they stem from within. People are governed by unchanging natural laws, and they just need to study these laws to understand the driving forces behind their fate, the origins of their struggles, and how to fix them. The laws of human nature involve self-love, the pursuit of happiness, and a dislike of pain; these principles are the basic and powerful drivers of everything that occurs in the moral realm. People create their own destiny. They may complain about their weaknesses and mistakes, but "they may have even more reason to trust in their strengths when they remember where they started and how high they have been able to rise."

The supernatural visitant paints a rather rosy picture of the ancient Egyptian and Assyrian kingdoms. But it would be a mistake to infer from their superficial splendour that the inhabitants generally were wise or happy. The tendency of man to ascribe perfection to past epochs is merely "the discoloration of his chagrin." The race is not degenerating; its misfortunes are due to ignorance and the mis-direction of self-love. Two principal obstacles to improvement have been the difficulty of transmitting ideas from age to age, and that of communicating them rapidly from man to man. These have been removed by the invention of printing. The press is "a memorable gift of celestial genius." In time all men will come to understand the principles of individual happiness and public felicity. Then there will be established among the peoples of the earth an equilibrium of forces; there will be no more wars, disputes will be decided by arbitration, and "the whole species will become one great society, a single family governed by the same spirit and by common laws, enjoying all the felicity of which human nature is capable." The accomplishment of this will be a slow process, since the same leaven will have to assimilate an enormous mass of heterogeneous elements, but its operation will be effectual.

The supernatural visitor paints a pretty optimistic picture of the ancient Egyptian and Assyrian kingdoms. However, it would be a mistake to assume that the people there were generally wise or happy just because of their apparent splendor. People have a tendency to idealize past eras, which is just "the fading of their disappointment." Humanity is not declining; its challenges come from ignorance and the misdirection of self-interest. Two main barriers to progress have been the difficulty in passing down ideas through generations and the struggle to communicate them quickly between individuals. These barriers have been eliminated by the invention of printing. The press is "a remarkable gift of celestial genius." Eventually, everyone will come to understand the principles of personal happiness and collective well-being. Then, an equilibrium of forces will be established among the nations of the world; there will be no more wars, conflicts will be resolved through arbitration, and "all of humanity will form one great society, a single family governed by the same spirit and common laws, enjoying all the happiness that human nature can achieve." Achieving this will be a gradual process, as the same influence will need to incorporate an enormous variety of different elements, but its effect will be significant.

Here the genius interrupts his prophecy and exclaims, turning toward the west, "The cry of liberty uttered on the farther shores of the Atlantic has reached to the old continent." A prodigious movement is then visible to their eyes in a country at the extremity of the Mediterranean; tyrants are overthrown, legislators elected, a code of laws is drafted on the principles of equality, liberty, and justice. The liberated nation is attacked by neighbouring tyrants, but her legislators propose to the other peoples to hold a general assembly, representing the whole world, and weigh every religious system in the balance. The proceedings of this congress follow, and the book breaks off incomplete.

Here, the genius stops his prophecy and exclaims, turning toward the west, "The cry for freedom heard on the far shores of the Atlantic has reached the old continent." A huge movement is then visible to them in a country at the edge of the Mediterranean; tyrants are toppled, legislators are elected, and a code of laws is drafted based on the principles of equality, liberty, and justice. The freed nation is attacked by neighboring tyrants, but its legislators invite other nations to join a general assembly that represents the entire world and evaluate every religious system fairly. The events of this congress follow, and the book ends abruptly.

It is not an arresting book; to a reader of the present day it is positively tedious; but it suited contemporary taste, and, appearing when France was confident that her Revolution would renovate the earth, it appealed to the hopes and sentiments of the movement. It made no contribution to the doctrine of Progress, but it undoubtedly helped to popularise it.

It’s not a captivating book; to today’s readers, it’s pretty boring; however, it matched the tastes of its time, and since it came out when France was convinced that its Revolution would change the world, it resonated with the hopes and feelings of the movement. It didn’t add anything to the idea of Progress, but it definitely helped make it more popular.





CHAPTER XI. THE FRENCH REVOLUTION: CONDORCET

I.

The authority which the advanced thinkers of France gained among the middle classes during the third quarter of the eighteenth century was promoted by the influence of fashion. The new ideas of philosophers, rationalists, and men of science had interested the nobles and higher classes of society for two generations, and were a common subject of discussion in the most distinguished salons. Voltaire's intimacy with Frederick the Great, the relations of d'Alembert and Diderot with the Empress Catherine, conferred on these men of letters, and on the ideas for which they stood, a prestige which carried great weight with the bourgeoisie. Humbler people, too, were as amenable as the great to the seduction of theories which supplied simple keys to the universe [Footnote: Taine said of the Contrat Social that it reduces political science to the strict application of an elementary axiom which renders all study unnecessary (La Revolution, vol. i. c. iv. Sec. iii.).] and assumed that everybody was capable of judging for himself on the most difficult problems. As well as the Encyclopaedia, the works of nearly all the leading thinkers were written for the general public not merely for philosophers. The policy of the Government in suppressing these dangerous publications did not hinder their diffusion, and gave them the attraction of forbidden fruit. In 1770 the avocat general (Seguier) acknowledged the futility of the policy. "The philosophers," he said, "have with one hand sought to shake the throne, with the other to upset the altars. Their purpose was to change public opinion on civil and religious institutions, and the revolution has, so to speak, been effected. History and poetry, romances and even dictionaries, have been infected with the poison of incredulity. Their writings are hardly published in the capital before they inundate the provinces like a torrent. The contagion has spread into workshops and cottages." [Footnote: Rocquain, L'Esprit revolutionnaire avant la Revolution, p. 278.]

The influence that the progressive thinkers from France had on the middle class during the late 1700s was boosted by fashion trends. For two generations, the new ideas from philosophers, rationalists, and scientists had intrigued the nobility and upper classes, becoming a popular topic in elite salons. Voltaire's close relationship with Frederick the Great and d'Alembert and Diderot's connections with Empress Catherine gave these intellectuals, along with their ideas, significant respect among the bourgeoisie. Even ordinary people were just as captivated as the elite by theories that offered simple explanations of the universe [Footnote: Taine remarked about the Contrat Social that it simplifies political science to the application of a basic principle, making further study unnecessary (La Revolution, vol. i. c. iv. Sec. iii.).] and assumed that anyone could form an opinion on complex issues. In addition to the Encyclopaedia, almost all major thinkers wrote for the general public, not just philosophers. The government’s attempts to suppress these risky publications did not prevent their spread and instead made them more appealing as forbidden knowledge. In 1770, the attorney general (Seguier) admitted that this effort was ineffective. "The philosophers," he stated, "have with one hand tried to shake the throne and with the other to topple the altars. Their goal was to shift public opinion about civil and religious systems, and the revolution has essentially occurred. History and poetry, novels, and even dictionaries have been tainted by the poison of doubt. Their works barely hit the capital before they flood the provinces like a torrent. The contagion has spread into workshops and homes." [Footnote: Rocquain, L'Esprit revolutionnaire avant la Revolution, p. 278.]

The contagion spread, but the official who wrote these words did not see that it was successful because it was opportune, and that the minds of men were prepared to receive the seed of revolutionary ideas by the unspeakable corruption of the Government and the Church. As Voltaire remarked about the same time, France was becoming Encyclopaedist, and Europe too.

The outbreak spread, but the official who wrote these words didn’t realize it was effective because it came at the right moment, and that people's minds were ready to accept revolutionary ideas due to the unimaginable corruption of the Government and the Church. As Voltaire noted around the same time, France was becoming more like the Encyclopedists, and Europe as well.

2.

2.

The influence of the subversive and rationalistic thinkers in bringing about the events of 1789 has been variously estimated by historians. The truth probably lies in the succinct statement of Acton that "the confluence of French theory with American example caused the Revolution to break out" when it did. The theorists aimed at reform, not at political revolution; and it was the stimulus of the Declaration of Rights of 1774 and the subsequent victory of the Colonies that precipitated the convulsion, at a time when the country had a better prospect of improvement than it ever had before 1774, when Louis XVI. came to the throne. But the theories had prepared France for radical changes, and they guided the phases of the Revolution. The leaders had all the optimism of the Encyclopaedists; yet the most powerful single force was Rousseau, who, though he denied Progress and blasphemed civilisation, had promulgated the doctrine of the sovereignty of the people, giving it an attractive appearance of mathematical precision; and to this doctrine the revolutionaries attached their optimistic hopes. [Footnote: It is interesting to observe how Robespierre, to whom the doctrines of Rousseau were oracles, could break out into admiration of the progress of civilised man, as he did in the opening passage of his speech of 7th May 1794. proposing the decree for the worship of the Supreme Being (see the text in Stephen, Orators of the French Revolution, ii. 391-92).] The theory of equality seemed no longer merely speculative; for the American constitution was founded on democratic equality, whereas the English constitution, which before had seemed the nearest approximation to the ideal of freedom, was founded on inequality. The philosophical polemic of the masters was waged with weapons of violence by the disciples. Chaumette and Hebert, the followers of d'Holbach, were destroyed by the disciples of Rousseau. In the name of the creed of the Vicaire Savoyard the Jacobin Club shattered the bust of Helvetius. Mably and Morelly had their disciples in Babeuf and the socialists.

The impact of subversive and rational thinkers on the events of 1789 has been viewed differently by historians. The truth likely aligns with Acton's concise statement that "the combination of French theory with the American example sparked the Revolution" when it did. The theorists aimed for reform, not political revolution; and it was the inspiration from the Declaration of Rights of 1774 and the Colonies' subsequent victory that triggered the upheaval at a time when the country had better prospects for improvement than it ever had before 1774, when Louis XVI came to the throne. However, these theories had prepared France for radical changes and directed the phases of the Revolution. The leaders were filled with the optimism of the Encyclopaedists, yet the most significant force was Rousseau, who, despite denying Progress and criticizing civilization, promoted the idea of the sovereignty of the people, giving it a compelling sense of mathematical precision; to this idea, the revolutionaries pinned their hopeful aspirations. [Footnote: It is interesting to note how Robespierre, to whom Rousseau's doctrines were like scripture, could express admiration for the advancement of civilized man, as he did in the opening lines of his speech on May 7, 1794, proposing the decree for the worship of the Supreme Being (see the text in Stephen, Orators of the French Revolution, ii. 391-92).] The idea of equality no longer seemed just theoretical; the American constitution was based on democratic equality, while the English constitution, which had once appeared closest to the ideal of freedom, was based on inequality. The philosophical debates of the masters were fought with violent tactics by their followers. Chaumette and Hebert, followers of d'Holbach, were eliminated by the followers of Rousseau. In the name of the beliefs of the Vicaire Savoyard, the Jacobin Club smashed the bust of Helvetius. Mably and Morelly had their disciples in Babeuf and the socialists.

A naive confidence that the political upheaval meant regeneration and inaugurated a reign of justice and happiness pervaded France in the first period of the Revolution, and found a striking expression in the ceremonies of the universal "Federation" in the Champ-de-Mars on 14th July 1790. The festival was theatrical enough, decreed and arranged by the Constituent Assembly, but the enthusiasm and optimism of the people who gathered to swear loyalty to the new Constitution were genuine and spontaneous. Consciously or subconsciously they were under the influence of the doctrine of Progress which leaders of opinion had for several decades been insinuating into the public mind. It did not occur to them that their oaths and fraternal embraces did not change their minds or hearts, and that, as Taine remarked, they remained what ages of political subjection and one age of political literature had made them. The assumption that new social machinery could alter human nature and create a heaven upon earth was to be swiftly and terribly confuted.

A naive belief that the political upheaval signified a fresh start and the beginning of a time of justice and happiness swept through France during the early days of the Revolution, and it found a powerful expression during the ceremonies of the universal "Federation" in the Champ-de-Mars on July 14, 1790. The festival was quite theatrical, organized and enacted by the Constituent Assembly, but the excitement and hope of the people who gathered to pledge their loyalty to the new Constitution were real and spontaneous. Whether consciously or unconsciously, they were influenced by the idea of Progress that opinion leaders had been subtly promoting for many years. They didn’t realize that their vows and brotherly hugs didn’t change their thoughts or feelings, and that, as Taine pointed out, they remained shaped by centuries of political oppression and one era of political literature. The belief that new social systems could transform human nature and create a paradise on earth was about to be quickly and painfully proven wrong.

 Post uarios casus et tot discrimina rerum
 uenimus in Latium,
Post uarios casus et tot discrimina rerum uenimus in Latium,

but Latium was to be the scene of sanguinary struggles.

but Latium was set to be the site of bloody conflicts.

Another allied and fundamental fallacy, into which all the philosophers and Rousseau had more or less fallen, was reflected and exposed by the Revolution. They had considered man in vacuo. They had not seen that the whole development of a society is an enormous force which cannot be talked or legislated away; they had ignored the power of social memory and historical traditions, and misvalued the strength of the links which bind generations together. So the Revolutionaries imagined that they could break abruptly with the past, and that a new method of government, constructed on mathematical lines, a constitution (to use words of Burke) "ready made and ready armed, mature in its birth, a perfect goddess of wisdom and of war, hammered by our blacksmith midwives out of the brain of Jupiter himself," would create a condition of idyllic felicity in France, and that the arrival of the millennium depended only on the adoption of the same principles by other nations. The illusions created by the Declaration of the Rights of Man on the 4th of August died slowly under the shadow of the Terror; but though the hopes of those who believed in the speedy regeneration of the world were belied, some of the thoughtful did not lose heart. There was one at least who did not waver in his faith that the movement was a giant's step on the path of man towards ultimate felicity, however far he had still to travel. Condorcet, one of the younger Encyclopaedists, spent the last months of his life, under the menace of the guillotine, in projecting a history of human Progress.

Another key fallacy that many philosophers, including Rousseau, fell into was highlighted by the Revolution. They viewed humanity in isolation. They failed to recognize that the development of society is a powerful force that can't simply be ignored or legislated away; they overlooked the influence of social memory and historical traditions, and underestimated the strength of the connections that link generations together. The Revolutionaries believed they could sever ties with the past and that a new government, designed with mathematical precision, a constitution (to quote Burke) "ready-made and ready-armed, fully formed at its birth, a perfect goddess of wisdom and war, forged by our blacksmith midwives from the mind of Jupiter himself," would usher in an idyllic state of happiness in France, and that the arrival of a better future depended solely on other nations adopting the same principles. The promises made by the Declaration of the Rights of Man on August 4th faded slowly under the shadow of the Terror; however, even as the hopes of those who envisioned a quick transformation of the world were dashed, some thoughtful individuals remained hopeful. At least one person did not lose faith that the movement represented a significant advance toward ultimate happiness, no matter how far there was still to go. Condorcet, one of the younger Encyclopaedists, spent the final months of his life, facing the threat of the guillotine, working on a history of human Progress.

3.

3.

Condorcet was the friend and biographer of Turgot, and it was not unfitting that he should resume the design of a history of civilisation, in the light of the idea of Progress, for which Turgot had only left luminous suggestions. He did not execute the plan, but he completed an elaborate sketch in which the controlling ideas of the scheme are fully set forth. His principles are to be found almost entirely in Turgot. But they have a new significance for Condorcet. He has given them wings. He has emphasised, and made deductions. Turgot wrote in the calm spirit of an inquirer. Condorcet spoke with the verve of a prophet. He was prophesying under the shadow of death. It is amazing that the optimistic Sketch of a Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind should have been composed when he was hiding from Robespierre in 1793. [Footnote: Published in 1795.]

Condorcet was a friend and biographer of Turgot, and it was fitting for him to take up the task of writing a history of civilization through the lens of the idea of Progress, which Turgot had only hinted at. He didn't complete the plan, but he developed an extensive outline where the main ideas of the project are clearly laid out. His principles mostly come from Turgot, but they hold new meaning for Condorcet. He has given them life and emphasized them through his deductions. Turgot wrote with the calmness of a researcher. Condorcet expressed himself with the passion of a prophet. He was prophesying while living in fear of death. It's remarkable that the optimistic Sketch of a Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind was written while he was in hiding from Robespierre in 1793. [Footnote: Published in 1795.]

Condorcet was penetrated with the spirit of the Encyclopaedists, of whom he had been one, and his attitude to Christianity was that of Voltaire and Diderot. Turgot had treated the received religion respectfully. He had acknowledged Providence, and, though the place which he assigned to Providence was that of a sort of honorary President of the development of civilisation who might disappear without affecting the proceedings, there was a real difference between his views and those of his friend as to the role of Christianity and the civilisation of the Middle Ages.

Condorcet was deeply influenced by the spirit of the Encyclopaedists, of which he was a part, and he viewed Christianity similarly to Voltaire and Diderot. Turgot had approached established religion with respect. He acknowledged a higher power, and even though he considered this higher power to be like an honorary President overseeing the evolution of civilization—someone who could vanish without impacting the process—there was a significant difference between his views and those of his friend regarding the role of Christianity and the civilization of the Middle Ages.

A more important difference between the two thinkers is connected with the different circumstances in which they wrote. Turgot did not believe in the necessity of violent changes; he thought that steady reforms under the existing regime would do wonders for France. Before the Revolution Condorcet had agreed, but he was swept away by its enthusiasm. The victory of liberty in America and the increasing volume of the movement against slavery—one of the causes which most deeply stirred his heart—had heightened his natural optimism and confirmed his faith in the dogma of Progress. He felt the exhilaration of the belief that he was living through "one of the greatest revolutions of the human race," and he deliberately designed his book to be opportune to a crisis of mankind, at which "a picture of revolutions of the past will be the best guide."

A more significant difference between the two thinkers is tied to the different circumstances in which they wrote. Turgot didn't believe in the need for violent changes; he thought that steady reforms under the current regime would greatly benefit France. Before the Revolution, Condorcet agreed, but he got swept up in its enthusiasm. The victory of liberty in America and the growing movement against slavery—one of the issues that moved him deeply—boosted his natural optimism and reinforced his belief in the idea of Progress. He felt the excitement of being part of "one of the greatest revolutions of the human race," and he intentionally designed his book to be relevant to a crisis for humanity, where "a depiction of past revolutions will be the best guide."

Feeling that he is personally doomed, he consoles himself with brooding on the time, however remote, when the sun will shine "on an earth of none but freemen, with no master save reason; for tyrants and slaves, priests and their stupid or hypocritical tools, will all have disappeared." He is not satisfied with affirming generally the certainty of an indefinite progress in enlightenment and social welfare. He sets himself to think out its nature, to forecast its direction, and determine its goal, and insists, as his predecessors had never done, on the prospects of the distant future.

Feeling that he is personally doomed, he comforts himself by thinking about the time, no matter how far off, when the sun will shine "on a world of only free people, with no master but reason; for tyrants and slaves, priests and their foolish or hypocritical tools, will all be gone." He isn't satisfied with just claiming that there will surely be endless progress in knowledge and social well-being. He works to understand what that progress will look like, predict its direction, and identify its goal, stressing, more than his predecessors ever did, the possibilities for the distant future.

4.

4.

His ambitious design is, in his own words, to show "the successive changes in human society, the influence which each instant exerts on the succeeding instant, and thus, in its successive modifications, the advance of the human species towards truth or happiness." Taken literally, this is an impossible design, and to put it forward as a practical proposition is as if a man were to declare his intention of writing a minute diary of the life of Julius Caesar from his birth to his death. By stating his purpose in such terms, Condorcet reveals that he had no notion of the limitations which confine our knowledge of the past, and that even if he had conceived a more modest and practicable programme he would have been incapable of executing it. His formula, however, is worth remembering. For the unattainable ideal which it expresses reminds us how many periods and passages of human experience must always remain books with seven seals.

His ambitious goal is, in his own words, to show "the successive changes in human society, the influence each moment has on the next, and thus, through its continuous modifications, the progress of humanity towards truth or happiness." Taken literally, this is an impossible goal, and suggesting it as a practical plan is like someone declaring their intention to write a detailed diary of Julius Caesar's life from birth to death. By expressing his aim in this way, Condorcet shows that he didn't recognize the limits that restrict our understanding of the past, and even if he had come up with a more realistic and achievable plan, he would have been unable to carry it out. However, his formula is worth noting. For the unattainable ideal it represents reminds us that many periods and moments of human experience will always remain sealed books.

Condorcet distinguished ten periods of civilisation, of which the tenth lies in the future, but he has not justified his divisions and his epochs are not co-ordinate in importance. Yet his arrangement of the map of history is remarkable as an attempt to mark its sections not by great political changes but by important steps in knowledge. The first three periods—the formation of primitive societies, followed by the pastoral age, and the agricultural age—conclude with the invention of alphabetic writing in Greece. The fourth is the history of Greek thought, to the definite division of the sciences in the time of Aristotle. In the fifth knowledge progresses and suffers obscuration under Roman rule, and the sixth is the dark age which continues to the time of the Crusades. The significance of the seventh period is to prepare the human mind for the revolution which would be achieved by the invention of printing, with which the eighth period opens. Some of the best pages of the book develop the vast consequences of this invention. The scientific revolution effected by Descartes begins a new period, which is now closed by the creation of the French Republic.

Condorcet identified ten periods of civilization, with the tenth being in the future, but he didn’t provide strong reasons for his divisions, and his periods aren’t equally significant. Still, his way of mapping history is notable for focusing on major advancements in knowledge rather than just political changes. The first three periods — the development of primitive societies, the pastoral age, and the agricultural age — end with the invention of alphabetic writing in Greece. The fourth period covers Greek thought, marked by the clear division of the sciences during Aristotle's time. In the fifth, knowledge progresses but is also obscured under Roman rule, and the sixth marks the Dark Ages, lasting until the Crusades. The significance of the seventh period is to prepare the human mind for the revolution that would come with the invention of printing, which marks the start of the eighth period. Some of the finest sections of the book explore the vast impacts of this invention. The scientific revolution initiated by Descartes begins a new period, which ends with the establishment of the French Republic.

The idea of the progress of knowledge had created the idea of social Progress and remained its foundation. It was therefore logical and inevitable that Condorcet should take advance in knowledge as the clew to the march of the human race. The history of civilisation is the history of enlightenment. Turgot had justified this axiom by formulating the cohesion of all modes of social activity. Condorcet insists on "the indissoluble union" between intellectual progress and that of liberty, virtue, and the respect for natural rights, and on the effect of science in the destruction of prejudice. All errors in politics and ethics have sprung, he asserts, from false ideas which are closely connected with errors in physics and ignorance of the laws of nature. And in the new doctrine of Progress he sees an instrument of enlightenment which is to give "the last blow to the tottering edifice of prejudices."

The idea of knowledge advancing led to the concept of social progress and became its foundation. It made sense that Condorcet would see the advancement of knowledge as the key to humanity’s progress. The history of civilization is really the history of enlightenment. Turgot supported this idea by outlining how all forms of social activity are connected. Condorcet emphasizes the "indissoluble union" between intellectual progress and the pursuit of liberty, virtue, and respect for natural rights, as well as how science helps to eliminate prejudice. He claims that all mistakes in politics and ethics arise from false ideas that are closely tied to errors in physics and ignorance of the laws of nature. In the new doctrine of progress, he sees a tool for enlightenment that will deliver "the final blow to the crumbling structure of prejudices."

It would not be useful to analyse Condorcet's sketch or dwell on his obsolete errors and the defects of his historical knowledge. His slight picture of the Middle Ages reflects the familiar view of all the eighteenth century philosophers. The only contribution to social amelioration which he can discover in a period of nearly a millennium is the abolition of domestic slavery. And so this period appears as an interruption of the onward march. His inability to appreciate the historical role of the Roman Empire exhibits more surprising ignorance and prejudice. But these particular defects are largely due to a fundamental error which runs through his whole book and was inherent in the social speculations of the Encyclopaedists. Condorcet, like all his circle, ignored the preponderant part which institutions have played in social development. So far as he considered them at all, he saw in them obstacles to the free play of human reason; not the spontaneous expression of a society corresponding to its needs or embodying its ideals, but rather machinery deliberately contrived for oppressing the masses and keeping them in chains. He did not see that if the Progress in which he believed is a reality, its possibility depends on the institutions and traditions which give to societies their stability. In the following generation, it would be pointed out that he fell into a manifest contradiction when he praised the relative perfection reached in some European countries in the eighteenth century, and at the same time condemned as eminently retrograde all the doctrines and institutions which had been previously in control. [Footnote: Comte. Cours de philosophie positive, iv. 228.] This error is closely connected with the other error, previously noticed, of conceiving man abstracted from his social environment and exercising his reason in vacuo.

It wouldn't be helpful to analyze Condorcet's ideas or focus on his outdated mistakes and gaps in historical knowledge. His brief depiction of the Middle Ages mirrors the common perspective held by philosophers in the eighteenth century. The only positive development he could find in nearly a thousand years is the end of domestic slavery. As a result, this era seems like a break in progress. His failure to recognize the historical significance of the Roman Empire shows a surprising lack of knowledge and bias. However, these specific shortcomings largely stem from a fundamental flaw that runs throughout his entire book and was also present in the social theories of the Enlightenment thinkers. Like all his peers, Condorcet overlooked the significant role that institutions play in social progress. Whenever he considered them at all, he viewed them as obstacles to the free exercise of human reason; he saw them not as the natural expressions of a society meeting its needs or reflecting its ideals, but rather as systems intentionally designed to oppress the masses and keep them subjugated. He failed to grasp that if the Progress he believed in is real, its potential hinges on the institutions and traditions that provide stability to societies. In the next generation, it was pointed out that he contradicted himself when he praised the relative advancements achieved in some European nations during the eighteenth century while simultaneously condemning all the doctrines and institutions that had previously dominated. [Footnote: Comte. Cours de philosophie positive, iv. 228.] This mistake is closely related to another error previously mentioned, which involves viewing humanity detached from its social context and exercising reason in a vacuum.

5.

5.

The study of the history of civilisation has, in Condorcet's eyes, two uses. It enables us to establish the fact of Progress, and it should enable us to determine its direction in the future, and thereby to accelerate the rate of progression.

The study of civilization's history has, in Condorcet's view, two purposes. It allows us to confirm the reality of Progress, and it should help us figure out its future direction, which would allow us to speed up the pace of progress.

By the facts of history and the arguments they suggest, he undertakes to show that nature has set no term to the process of improving human faculties, and that the advance towards perfection is limited only by the duration of the globe. The movement may vary in velocity, but it will never be retrograde so long as the earth occupies its present place in the cosmic system and the general laws of this system do not produce some catastrophe or change which would deprive the human race of the faculties and resources which it has hitherto possessed. There will be no relapse into barbarism. The guarantees against this danger are the discovery of true methods in the physical sciences, their application to the needs of men, the lines of communication which have been established among them, the great number of those who study them, and finally the art of printing. And if we are sure of the continuous progress of enlightenment, we may be sure of the continuous improvement of social conditions.

Based on the facts of history and the arguments they present, he aims to demonstrate that nature has not established an endpoint for the development of human abilities, and that the journey towards perfection is only limited by the lifespan of the Earth. The pace of progress may fluctuate, but it will never go backwards as long as the Earth remains in its current position in the universe and the general laws of this system don’t lead to some disaster or change that would take away the abilities and resources humans have previously gained. There won't be a return to barbarism. The safeguards against this threat include the discovery of valid methods in the physical sciences, their application to human needs, the connections that have been formed among people, the large number of individuals studying these subjects, and, ultimately, the invention of printing. If we are confident in the ongoing progress of knowledge, we can also be confident in the continuous improvement of social conditions.

It is possible to foresee events, if the general laws of social phenomena are known, and these laws can be inferred from the history of the past. By this statement Condorcet justifies his bold attempt to sketch his tenth period of human history which lies in the future; and announces the idea which was in the next generation to be worked out by Comte. But he cannot be said to have deduced himself any law of social development. His forecast of the future is based on the ideas and tendencies of his own age. [Footnote: It is interesting to notice that the ablest of medieval Arabic historians, Ibn Khaldun (fourteenth century), had claimed that if history is scientifically studied future events may be predicted.]

It’s possible to predict events if we understand the general laws of social phenomena, which can be derived from historical data. With this statement, Condorcet justifies his ambitious attempt to outline his tenth period of human history that is yet to come; he also introduces the idea that would later be developed by Comte. However, it can’t be said that he himself derived any law of social development. His predictions about the future are based on the ideas and trends of his own time. [Footnote: It's interesting to note that one of the most skilled medieval Arabic historians, Ibn Khaldun (fourteenth century), claimed that if history is studied scientifically, future events can be predicted.]

Apart from scientific discoveries and the general diffusion of a knowledge of the laws of nature on which moral improvement depends, he includes in his prophetic vision the cessation of war and the realisation of the less familiar idea of the equality of the sexes. If he were alive to-day, he could point with triumph to the fact that of these far-reaching projects one is being accomplished in some of the most progressive countries and the other is looked upon as an attainable aim by statesmen who are not visionaries. The equality of the sexes was only a logical inference from the general doctrine of equality to which Condorcet's social theory is reducible. For him the goal of political progress is equality; equality is to be the aim of social effort—the ideal of the Revolution.

Besides scientific discoveries and the widespread understanding of the natural laws that support moral improvement, he envisions the end of war and the realization of the less common idea of gender equality. If he were alive today, he could proudly point out that one of these ambitious goals is being achieved in some of the most progressive countries, while the other is viewed as a reachable target by practical statesmen. Gender equality was simply a logical conclusion drawn from the broader principle of equality that underpins Condorcet's social theory. For him, the ultimate aim of political progress is equality; equality should be the focus of social efforts—the ideal of the Revolution.

For it is the multitude of men that must be considered—the mass of workers, not the minority who live on their labours. Hitherto they have been neglected by the historian as well as by the statesman. The true history of humanity is not the history of some men. The human race is formed by the mass of families who subsist almost entirely on the fruits of their own work, and this mass is the proper subject of history, not great men.

For it’s the large number of people that should be taken into account—the group of workers, not the few who benefit from their labor. Until now, they have been overlooked by both historians and politicians. The real history of humanity isn’t the story of a few individuals. The human race is made up of countless families who rely mostly on the results of their own hard work, and this group is what history should focus on, not just great individuals.

You may establish social equality by means of laws and institutions, yet the equality actually enjoyed may be very incomplete. Condorcet recognises this and attributes it to three principal causes: inequality in wealth; inequality in position between the man whose means of subsistence are assured and can be transmitted to his family and the man whose means depend on his work and are limited by the term of his own life [Footnote: He looked forward to the mitigation of this inequality by the development of life insurance which was then coming to the front.]; and inequality in education. He did not propose any radical methods for dealing with these difficulties, which he thought would diminish in time, without, however, entirely disappearing. He was too deeply imbued with the views of the Economists to be seduced by the theories of Rousseau, Mably, Babeuf, and others, into advocating communism or the abolition of private property.

You can create social equality through laws and institutions, but the actual equality that people experience may still be quite limited. Condorcet acknowledges this and points to three main reasons: inequality in wealth; the difference in status between those who have a guaranteed income that can be passed down to their families and those whose income relies on their work and is only as long as their life [Footnote: He anticipated that this inequality would lessen with the rise of life insurance, which was then becoming more popular.]; and inequality in education. He didn’t suggest any extreme solutions for these issues, believing they would reduce over time, though not completely disappear. He was too strongly influenced by the ideas of the Economists to be tempted by the theories of Rousseau, Mably, Babeuf, and others into supporting communism or the end of private property.

Besides equality among the individuals composing a civilised society, Condorcet contemplated equality among all the peoples of the earth,—a uniform civilisation throughout the world, and the obliteration of the distinction between advanced and retrograde races. The backward peoples, he prophesied, will climb up to the condition of France and the United States of America, for no people is condemned never to exercise its reason. If the dogma of the perfectibility of human nature, unguarded by any restrictions, is granted, this is a logical inference, and we have already seen that it was one of the ideas current among the philosophers.

Aside from equality among the individuals in a civilized society, Condorcet envisioned equality among all the people on Earth—a standard civilization across the globe, eliminating the divide between advanced and less developed races. He predicted that the less developed nations would eventually reach the standards of France and the United States, because no people are doomed to never use their reason. If we accept the belief in the perfectibility of human nature, without any limitations, this becomes a logical conclusion, and we have already noted that this concept was popular among philosophers.

Condorcet does not hesitate to add to his picture adventurous conjectures on the improvement of man's physical organisation, and a considerable prolongation of his life by the advance of medical science. We need only note this. More interesting is the prediction that, even if the compass of the human being's cerebral powers is inalterable, the range, precision, and rapidity of his mental operations will be augmented by the invention of new instruments and methods.

Condorcet doesn't hold back in adding some bold guesses about improving human physical conditions and significantly extending lifespan through advances in medical science. This is worth mentioning. More intriguing is his prediction that, even if the limits of human brainpower remain unchanged, the range, accuracy, and speed of our mental processes will be enhanced by the creation of new tools and techniques.

The design of writing a history of human civilisation was premature, and to have produced a survey of any durable value would have required the equipment of a Gibbon. Condorcet was not even as well equipped as Voltaire. [Footnote: But as he wrote without books the Sketch was a marvellous tour de force.] The significance of his Sketch lies in this, that towards the close of an intellectual movement it concentrated attention on the most important, though hitherto not the most prominent, idea which that movement had disseminated, and as it were officially announced human Progress as the leading problem that claimed the interest of mankind. With him Progress was associated intimately with particular eighteenth century doctrines, but these were not essential to it. It was a living idea; it survived the compromising theories which began to fall into discredit after the Revolution, and was explored from new points of view. Condorcet, however, wedded though his mind was to the untenable views of human nature current in his epoch and his circle, did not share the tendency of leading philosophers to regard history as an unprofitable record of folly and crime which it would be well to obliterate or forget. He recognised the interpretation of history as the key to human development, and this principle controlled subsequent speculations on Progress in France.

The idea of writing a history of human civilization was ahead of its time, and creating a comprehensive account of lasting value would have required someone with the skills of Gibbon. Condorcet wasn't even as well-prepared as Voltaire. [Footnote: However, since he wrote without books, the Sketch was an incredible showcase of talent.] The real significance of his Sketch lies in the fact that towards the end of an intellectual movement, it shifted focus to the most important, though previously less prominent, idea that movement had spread: it formally declared human Progress as the main issue that deserved the attention of humanity. For him, Progress was closely linked to certain 18th-century beliefs, but those beliefs were not crucial to it. It was a vibrant idea; it outlasted the flawed theories that began to lose credibility after the Revolution and was examined from new perspectives. However, despite his mind being tied to the untenable views of human nature prevalent in his time and social circle, Condorcet did not share the tendency of leading philosophers to see history as a useless record of folly and crime that should be erased or forgotten. He understood that interpreting history is key to human development, and this principle influenced later thoughts on Progress in France.

6.

6.

Cabanis, the physician, was Condorcet's literary executor, and a no less ardent believer in human perfectibility. Looking at life and man from his own special point of view, he saw in the study of the physical organism the key to the intellectual and moral improvement of the race. It is by knowledge of the relations between his physical states and moral states that man can attain happiness, through the enlargement of his faculties and the multiplication of enjoyments, and that he will be able to grasp, as it were, the infinite in his brief existence by realising the certainty of indefinite progress. His doctrine was a logical extension of the theories of Locke and Condillac. If our knowledge is wholly derived from sensations, our sensations depend on our sensory organs, and mind becomes a function of the nervous system.

Cabanis, the doctor, was Condorcet's literary executor and just as passionate about the idea of human perfectibility. Viewing life and humanity from his unique perspective, he believed that understanding the physical body was the key to the intellectual and moral improvement of humanity. By understanding the connections between physical and moral states, people can achieve happiness through enhancing their abilities and increasing their pleasures, and they can grasp, in a sense, the infinite during their short lives by realizing the certainty of ongoing progress. His ideas were a logical extension of the theories of Locke and Condillac. If all our knowledge comes from our sensations, then those sensations are reliant on our sensory organs, and the mind becomes a function of the nervous system.

The events of the Revolution quenched in him as little as in Condorcet the sanguine confidence that it was the opening of a new era for science and art, and thereby for the general Progress of man. "The present is one of those great periods of history to which posterity will often look back" with gratitude. [Footnote: Picavet, Les Ideologues, p. 203. Cabanis was born in 1757 and died in 1808.] He took an active part in the coup d'etat of the 18th of Brumaire (1799) which was to lead to the despotism of Napoleon. He imagined that it would terminate oppression, and was as enthusiastic for it as he and Condorcet had been for the Revolution ten years before. "You philosophers," he wrote, [Footnote: Ib. p. 224.] "whose studies are directed to the improvement and happiness of the race, you no longer embrace vain shadows. Having watched, in alternating moods of hope and sadness, the great spectacle of our Revolution, you now see with joy the termination of its last act; you will see with rapture this new era, so long promised to the French people, at last open, in which all the benefits of nature, all the creations of genius, all the fruits of time, labour, and experience will be utilised, an era of glory and prosperity in which the dreams of your philanthropic enthusiasm should end by being realised."

The events of the Revolution dampened his optimism as much as it did Condorcet's, diminishing the belief that it marked the beginning of a new era for science and art, and, consequently, for the general progress of humanity. "The present is one of those great periods of history that future generations will look back on" with appreciation. [Footnote: Picavet, Les Ideologues, p. 203. Cabanis was born in 1757 and died in 1808.] He actively participated in the coup d'état of the 18th of Brumaire (1799), which led to Napoleon's dictatorship. He believed it would end oppression and felt as enthusiastic about it as he and Condorcet had been for the Revolution a decade earlier. "You philosophers," he wrote, [Footnote: Ib. p. 224.] "whose work focuses on the betterment and happiness of humanity, no longer chase empty illusions. After watching the grand spectacle of our Revolution with mixed feelings of hope and sadness, you now see with joy the end of its final act; you will eagerly witness this new era, so long promised to the French people, finally beginning, where all the gifts of nature, all the creations of genius, and all the fruits of time, labor, and experience will be used, an era of glory and prosperity where the dreams of your humanitarian passion will finally come true."

It was an over-sanguine and characteristic greeting of the eighteenth to the nineteenth century. Cabanis was one of the most important of those thinkers who, living into the new period, took care that the ideas of their own generation should not be overwhelmed in the rising flood of reaction.

It was an overly optimistic and typical greeting from the eighteenth to the nineteenth century. Cabanis was one of the key thinkers who, by living into the new era, ensured that the ideas of his own generation wouldn't get lost in the growing tide of reaction.





CHAPTER XII. THE THEORY OF PROGRESS IN ENGLAND

1.

The idea of Progress could not help crossing the Channel. France and England had been at war in the first year of the eighteenth century, they were at war in the last, and their conflict for supremacy was the leading feature of the international history of the whole century. But at no period was there more constant intellectual intimacy or more marked reciprocal influence between the two countries. It was a commonplace that Paris and London were the two great foci of civilisation, and they never lost touch of each other in the intellectual sphere. Many of the principal works of literature that appeared in either country were promptly translated, and some of the French books, which the censorship rendered it dangerous to publish in Paris, were printed in London.

The idea of progress couldn't help but cross the Channel. France and England had been at war in the early years of the eighteenth century, they were at war at the end, and their struggle for dominance was the main event in the international history of the entire century. Yet, there was never a time with more consistent intellectual closeness or stronger mutual influence between the two countries. It was widely recognized that Paris and London were the two major centers of civilization, and they remained connected in the intellectual arena. Many of the key literary works from either country were quickly translated, and some French books, which censorship made it risky to publish in Paris, were printed in London.

It was not indeed to be expected that the theory should have the same kind of success, or exert the same kind of effect in England as in France. England had her revolution behind her, France had hers before her. England enjoyed what were then considered large political liberties, the envy of other lands; France groaned under the tyranny of worthless rulers. The English constitution satisfied the nation, and the serious abuses which would now appear to us intolerable were not sufficient to awaken a passionate desire for reforms. The general tendency of British thought was to see salvation in the stability of existing institutions, and to regard change with suspicion. Now passionate desire for reform was the animating force which propagated the idea of Progress in France. And when this idea is translated from the atmosphere of combat, in which it was developed by French men of letters, into the calm climate of England, it appears like a cold reflection.

It was not really expected that the theory would have the same kind of success or impact in England as it did in France. England had already experienced its revolution, while France was still ahead of hers. England enjoyed what were considered substantial political freedoms, envied by other nations; France suffered under the oppression of ineffective leaders. The English constitution satisfied the nation, and the serious issues that would now strike us as intolerable didn’t spark a strong desire for reform. The general attitude in Britain was to find security in the stability of existing institutions and to view change with skepticism. Meanwhile, the strong desire for reform was the driving force behind the idea of Progress in France. When this idea is translated from the combative atmosphere in which it was shaped by French thinkers into the more subdued environment of England, it comes across as a cold echo.

Again, English thinkers were generally inclined to hold, with Locke, that the proper function of government is principally negative, to preserve order and defend life and property, not to aim directly at the improvement of society, but to secure the conditions in which men may pursue their own legitimate aims. Most of the French theorists believed in the possibility of moulding society indefinitely by political action, and rested their hopes for the future not only on the achievements of science, but on the enlightened activity of governments. This difference of view tended to give to the doctrine of Progress in France more practical significance than in England.

Once again, English thinkers generally agreed with Locke that the main role of government is mostly negative: to maintain order and protect life and property, rather than directly improving society. Their focus is on creating the conditions that allow individuals to pursue their own legitimate goals. In contrast, most French theorists believed in the potential to shape society endlessly through political action, placing their hopes for the future not just on scientific advancements but also on the enlightened efforts of governments. This difference in perspective made the idea of Progress carry more practical significance in France than in England.

But otherwise British soil was ready to receive the idea. There was the same optimistic temper among the comfortable classes in both countries. Shaftesbury, the Deist, had struck this note at the beginning of the century by his sanguine theory, which was expressed in Pope's banal phrase: "Whatever is, is right," and was worked into a system by Hutcheson. This optimism penetrated into orthodox circles. Progress, far from appearing as a rival of Providence, was discussed in the interests of Christianity by the Scotch theologian, Turnbull. [Footnote: The Principles of Modern Philosophy, 1740.]

But otherwise, British soil was ready to embrace the idea. The same optimistic mindset was found among the comfortable classes in both countries. Shaftesbury, the Deist, had set this tone at the beginning of the century with his hopeful theory, which was captured in Pope's cliché phrase: "Whatever is, is right," and further developed into a system by Hutcheson. This optimism spread into orthodox circles. Progress, rather than being seen as a rival to Providence, was discussed in the interest of Christianity by the Scottish theologian, Turnbull. [Footnote: The Principles of Modern Philosophy, 1740.]

2.

2.

The theory of the indefinite progress of civilisation left Hume cold. There is little ground, he argued, to suppose that "the world" is eternal or incorruptible. It is probably mortal, and must therefore, with all things in it, have its infancy, youth, manhood, and old age; and man will share in these changes of state. We must then expect that the human species should, when the world is in the age of manhood, possess greater bodily and mental vigour, longer life, and a stronger inclination and power of generation. But it is impossible to determine when this stage is reached. For the gradual revolutions are too slow to be discernible in the short period known to us by history and tradition. Physically and in mental powers men have been pretty much the same in all known ages. The sciences and arts have flourished now and have again decayed, but when they reached the highest perfection among one people, the neighbouring peoples were perhaps wholly unacquainted with them. We are therefore uncertain whether at present man is advancing to his point of perfection or declining from it. [Footnote: Essay on the Populousness of Ancient Nations, ad init. ]

The idea of civilization constantly improving didn't impress Hume. He believed there's not much reason to think that "the world" is everlasting or unchangeable. It's likely finite and must, like everything else, go through stages of infancy, youth, adulthood, and old age; and humanity will experience these shifts too. So, we can expect that when the world is in its prime, humans will have more physical and mental strength, longer lifespans, and a stronger ability and desire to reproduce. However, it's hard to pinpoint when this stage occurs. The gradual changes are too slow to notice in the brief time that we know from history and tradition. Physically and mentally, people have been quite similar across all known periods. The sciences and arts have thrived and then diminished, but when one culture reached its peak in these areas, nearby cultures may have been completely unaware of them. Therefore, we're not sure if humanity is currently moving toward perfection or moving away from it. [Footnote: Essay on the Populousness of Ancient Nations, ad init.]

The argument is somewhat surprising in an eighteenth century thinker like Hume, but it did not prevent him from recognising the superiority of modern to ancient civilisation. This superiority forms indeed the minor premiss in the general argument by which he confuted the commonly received opinion as to the populousness of ancient nations. He insisted on the improvements in art and industry, on the greater liberty and security enjoyed by modern men. "To one who considers coolly on the subject," he remarked, "it will appear that human nature in general really enjoys more liberty at present in the most arbitrary government of Europe than it ever did during the most flourishing period of ancient times." [Footnote: The justification of this statement was the abolition of slavery in Europe.]

The argument might seem surprising coming from an eighteenth-century thinker like Hume, but it didn’t stop him from recognizing that modern civilization is superior to ancient civilization. This superiority is actually the minor premise in the overall argument he used to challenge the widely held belief about the population of ancient nations. He emphasized the advancements in art and industry, as well as the greater freedom and security that modern people experience. "To someone who thinks about this calmly," he noted, "it will be clear that human nature, in general, enjoys more freedom today under the most arbitrary government in Europe than it ever did during the peak of ancient times." [Footnote: The justification for this statement was the abolition of slavery in Europe.]

He discussed many of the problems of civilisation, especially the conditions in which the arts and sciences flourish, [Footnote: Essay on the Rise of Arts and Sciences.] and drew some general conclusions, but he was too sceptical to suppose that any general synthesis of history is possible, or that any considerable change for the better in the manners of mankind is likely to occur. [Footnote: Cf. Essay on the Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth, ad init.]

He talked about many of the challenges faced by society, particularly the circumstances that allow the arts and sciences to thrive, [Footnote: Essay on the Rise of Arts and Sciences.] and came up with some broad conclusions, but he was too doubtful to believe that a complete understanding of history is achievable, or that any significant improvement in human behavior is likely to happen. [Footnote: Cf. Essay on the Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth, ad init.]

The greatest work dealing with social problems, that Britain produced in the eighteenth century, was Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations, and his luminous exposition of the effects of the division of labour was the most considerable contribution made by British thinkers of the age to the study of human development. It is much more than a treatise on economic principles; it contains a history of the gradual economic progress of human society, and it suggests the expectation of an indefinite augmentation of wealth and well-being. Smith was entirely at one with the French Economists on the value of opulence for the civilisation and happiness of mankind. But it was indirectly perhaps that his work contributed most effectively to the doctrine of the Progress of collective mankind. [Footnote: It has been observed by Mr. Leslie Stephen that the doctrine of the rights of man lies in the background of Adam Smith's speculations.] His teaching that the free commercial intercourse of all the peoples of the world, unfettered by government policies, was to the greatest advantage of each, presented an ideal of the economic "solidarity" of the race, which was one element in the ideal of Progress. And this principle soon began to affect practice. Pitt assimilated it when he was a young man, and it is one of the distinctions of his statesmanship that he endeavoured to apply the doctrines of his master so far as the prevailing prejudices would allow him.

The most significant work addressing social issues that Britain produced in the eighteenth century was Adam Smith's *Wealth of Nations*, and his clear explanation of the effects of the division of labor was the most substantial contribution made by British thinkers of that time to the study of human development. It's much more than just a book on economic principles; it provides a history of the gradual economic progress of society and suggests the expectation of endless growth in wealth and well-being. Smith was completely aligned with the French Economists on the value of wealth for the civilization and happiness of humanity. However, it was perhaps indirectly that his work most effectively contributed to the idea of the Progress of collective humanity. [Footnote: Mr. Leslie Stephen pointed out that the concept of human rights lies in the background of Adam Smith's ideas.] His belief that free trade among all the peoples of the world, free from government interference, would be the greatest benefit to everyone, presented an ideal of economic "solidarity" among people, which was a part of the ideal of Progress. This principle soon started to influence practical actions. Pitt embraced it when he was young, and one of the hallmarks of his leadership is that he tried to apply the ideas of his mentor as much as the existing biases would permit.

3.

3.

A few writers of less weight and fame than Hume or Smith expressly studied history in the light of Progress. It would not help us, in following the growth of the idea, to analyse the works of Ferguson, Dunbar, or Priestley. [Footnote: In his Essay on the History of Civil Society Adam Ferguson treated the growth of civilisation as due to the progressive nature of man, which insists on carrying him forward to limits impossible to ascertain. He formulated the process as a movement from simplicity to complexity, but contributed little to its explanation.] But I will quote one passage from Priestley, the most eminent of the three, and the most enthusiastic for the Progress of man. As the division of labour—the chief principle of organised society—is carried further he anticipates that

A few writers who aren't as prominent or well-known as Hume or Smith specifically examined history through the lens of Progress. It wouldn't benefit us, in tracing the development of the idea, to analyze the works of Ferguson, Dunbar, or Priestley. [Footnote: In his Essay on the History of Civil Society, Adam Ferguson viewed the growth of civilization as a result of humanity's progressive nature, which drives people toward goals that are ultimately impossible to determine. He described this process as a shift from simplicity to complexity but offered little insight into its explanation.] However, I will quote a passage from Priestley, the most distinguished of the three and the most passionate advocate for human Progress. As the division of labor—the fundamental principle of organized society—advances further, he predicts that

... nature, including both its materials and its laws, will be more at our command; men will make their situation in this world abundantly more easy and comfortable; they will probably prolong their existence in it and will grow daily more happy.... Thus, whatever was the beginning of this world, the end will be glorious and paradisiacal beyond what our imaginations can now conceive. Extravagant as some people may suppose these views to be, I think I could show them to be fairly suggested by the true theory of human nature and to arise from the natural course of human affairs.

... nature, including both its materials and its laws, will be more at our disposal; people will make their lives in this world significantly easier and more comfortable; they will likely extend their time here and will become increasingly happy each day. Thus, no matter what the beginning of this world was, the end will be glorious and paradise-like beyond what we can currently imagine. While some may consider these views to be unrealistic, I believe I could demonstrate that they are reasonably suggested by the true theory of human nature and arise from the natural progression of human affairs.

[Footnote: This passage of Priestley occurs in his Essay on the First Principles of Government and on the Nature of Political, Civil, and Religious Liberty (1768, 2nd ed. 1771), pp. 2-4. His Lectures on History and General Policy appeared in 1788.

[Footnote: This passage from Priestley is found in his Essay on the First Principles of Government and on the Nature of Political, Civil, and Religious Liberty (1768, 2nd ed. 1771), pp. 2-4. His Lectures on History and General Policy were published in 1788.]

Priestley was a strict utilitarian, who held that there is nothing intrinsically excellent in justice and veracity apart from their relation to happiness. The degree of public happiness is measured by the excellence of religion, science, government, laws, arts, commerce, conveniences of life, and especially by the degrees of personal security and personal liberty. In all these the ancients were inferior, and therefore they enjoyed less happiness. The present state of Europe is vastly preferable to what it was in any former period. And "the plan of this divine drama is opening more and more." In the future, Knowledge will increase and accumulate and diffuse itself to the lower ranks of society, who, by degrees, will find leisure for speculation; and looking beyond their immediate employment, they will consider the complex machine of society, and in time understand it better than those who now write about it.

Priestley was a strict utilitarian who believed that justice and truth have no inherent value outside of their connection to happiness. The level of public happiness is determined by the quality of religion, science, government, laws, arts, commerce, everyday conveniences, and especially by the levels of personal security and personal freedom. In all these aspects, the ancients were lacking, which is why they experienced less happiness. The current state of Europe is significantly better than it was in any previous era. And "the plan of this divine drama is unfolding more and more." In the future, knowledge will grow, accumulate, and spread to the lower levels of society, who will gradually find time to reflect; looking beyond their immediate tasks, they will analyze the complex structure of society and, eventually, understand it better than those who currently write about it.

See his Lectures, pp. 371, 388 sqq., 528-53.

See his Lectures, pp. 371, 388 and following, 528-53.

The English thinker did not share all the views of his French masters. As a Unitarian, he regarded Christianity as a "great remedy of vice and ignorance," part of the divine plan; and he ascribed to government a lesser role than they in the improvement of humanity. He held, for instance, that the state should not interfere in education, arguing that this art was still in the experimental stage, and that the intervention of the civil power might stereotype a bad system.

The English thinker didn’t agree with all the beliefs of his French counterparts. As a Unitarian, he saw Christianity as a "great remedy for vice and ignorance," an essential part of the divine plan; he believed that government had a smaller role than they did in improving humanity. For example, he argued that the state shouldn’t get involved in education, claiming that this field was still in the experimental phase and that government intervention could reinforce a flawed system.

Not less significant, though less influential, than the writings of Priestley and Ferguson was the work of James Dunbar, Professor of Philosophy at Aberdeen, entitled Essays on the History of Mankind in Rude and Cultivated Ages (2nd ed., 1781). He conceived history as progressive, and inquired into the general causes which determine the gradual improvements of civilisation. He dealt at length with the effects of climate and local circumstances, but unlike the French philosophers did not ignore heredity. While he did not enter upon any discussion of future developments, he threw out incidentally the idea that the world may be united in a league of nations.

Not as significant, but less influential than the writings of Priestley and Ferguson, was the work of James Dunbar, Professor of Philosophy at Aberdeen, titled Essays on the History of Mankind in Rude and Cultivated Ages (2nd ed., 1781). He viewed history as a process of progress and explored the general factors that lead to the gradual improvements in civilization. He extensively examined the effects of climate and local conditions, but unlike the French philosophers, he didn’t overlook the role of heredity. While he didn’t discuss any future developments, he suggested in passing that the world might come together in a league of nations.

Posterity, he wrote, "may contemplate, from a concurrence of various causes and events, some of which are hastening into light, the greater part, or even the whole habitable globe, divided among nations free and independent in all the interior functions of government, forming one political and commercial system" (p. 287).

Posterity, he wrote, "might see that, due to a mix of different causes and events, some of which are coming to light, most or even all of the habitable world is split among nations that are free and independent in all their internal government functions, creating one political and commercial system" (p. 287).

Dunbar's was an optimistic book, but his optimism was more cautious than Priestley's. These are his final words:

Dunbar's was an optimistic book, but his optimism was more cautious than Priestley's. These are his final words:

If human nature is liable to degenerate, it is capable of proportionable improvement from the collected wisdom of ages. It is pleasant to infer from the actual progress of society, the glorious possibilities of human excellence. And, if the principles can be assembled into view, which most directly tend to diversify the genius and character of nations, some theory may be raised on these foundations that shall account more systematically for past occurrences and afford some openings and anticipations into the eventual history of the world.]

If human nature can decline, it can also improve significantly thanks to the accumulated wisdom of the ages. It's encouraging to draw from the current progress of society the exciting potential for human excellence. And if we can clearly identify the principles that primarily contribute to the diversity of nations' talents and characters, we might develop a theory based on these foundations that explains past events more systematically and offers insights into the future history of the world.

The problem of dark ages, which an advocate of Progress must explain, was waved away by Priestley in his Lectures on History with the observation that they help the subsequent advance of knowledge by "breaking the progress of authority." [Footnote: This was doubtless suggested to him by some remarks of Hume in The Rise of Arts and Sciences.] This is not much of a plea for such periods viewed as machinery in a Providential plan. The great history of the Middle Ages, which in the words of its author describes "the triumph of barbarism and religion," had been completed before Priestley's Lectures appeared, and it is remarkable that he takes no account of it, though it might seem to be a work with which a theory of Progress must come to terms.

The issue of the dark ages, which someone who supports Progress needs to clarify, was brushed aside by Priestley in his Lectures on History when he noted that they contribute to the later growth of knowledge by "disrupting the authority's progress." [Footnote: This was likely inspired by some comments from Hume in The Rise of Arts and Sciences.] This isn't much of a defense for such times when looking at them as part of a divine plan. The significant history of the Middle Ages, which its author describes as "the triumph of barbarism and religion," had been finished before Priestley's Lectures were published, and it’s notable that he doesn’t acknowledge it, even though it seems like a work that any theory of Progress should address.

Yet the sceptical historian of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, who was more at home in French literature than any of his fellow-countrymen, was not opposed to the theory of Progress, and he even states it in a moderate form. Having given reasons for believing that civilised society will never again be threatened by such an irruption of barbarians as that which oppressed the arms and institutions of Rome, he allows us to "acquiesce in the pleasing conclusion that every age of the world has increased, and still increases, the real wealth, the happiness, the knowledge and perhaps the virtue of the human race."

Yet the skeptical historian of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, who felt more comfortable in French literature than his fellow countrymen, did not reject the idea of Progress, and he even presents it in a reasonable way. After providing reasons to believe that civilized society will not face another invasion by barbarians like the one that overwhelmed Rome's power and institutions, he lets us "accept the reassuring conclusion that every era of the world has increased, and continues to increase, the real wealth, happiness, knowledge, and maybe even the virtue of humanity."

"The discoveries of ancient and modern navigators, and the domestic history or tradition of the most enlightened nations, represent the HUMAN SAVAGE, naked both in mind and body, and destitute of laws, of arts, of ideas, and almost of language. From this abject condition, perhaps the primitive and universal state of man, he has gradually arisen to command the animals, to fertilise the earth, to traverse the ocean, and to measure the heavens. His progress in the improvement and exercise of his mental and corporeal faculties has been irregular and various, infinitely slow in the beginning, and increasing by degrees with redoubled velocity; ages of laborious ascent have been followed by a moment of rapid downfall; and the several climates of the globe have felt the vicissitudes of light and darkness. Yet the experience of four thousand years should enlarge our hopes and diminish our apprehensions; we cannot determine to what height the human species may aspire in their advances towards perfection; but it may safely be presumed that no people, unless the face of nature is changed, will relapse into their original barbarism." [Footnote: Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, ch. xxxviii. ad fin.]

"The discoveries of ancient and modern navigators, along with the domestic history or tradition of the most enlightened nations, illustrate the human savage, bare both in mind and body, lacking laws, arts, ideas, and nearly language. From this pitiable state, possibly the primitive and universal condition of mankind, he has gradually risen to dominate animals, cultivate the earth, cross the oceans, and explore the heavens. His progress in developing and using his mental and physical abilities has been uneven and varied, incredibly slow at first, then gradually accelerating; ages of hard labor have been followed by moments of swift decline, and different climates around the globe have experienced cycles of light and darkness. However, the lessons of four thousand years should broaden our hopes and lessen our fears; we can’t know how high humanity might reach in their journey toward perfection, but it’s safe to assume that no society, unless the face of nature is changed, will revert to its original barbarism." [Footnote: Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, ch. xxxviii. ad fin.]

But Gibbon treats the whole subject as a speculation, and he treats it without reference to any of the general principles on which French thinkers had based their theory. He admits that his reasons for holding that civilisation is secure against a barbarous cataclysm may be considered fallacious; and he also contemplates the eventuality that the fabric of sciences and arts, trade and manufacture, law and policy, might be "decayed by time." If so, the growth of civilisation would have to begin again, but not ab initio. For "the more useful or at least more necessary arts," which do not require superior talents or national subordination for their exercise, and which war, commerce, and religious zeal have spread among the savages of the world, would certainly survive.

But Gibbon views the entire subject as a speculation and does so without considering any of the general principles that French thinkers based their theories on. He acknowledges that his reasons for believing that civilization is safe from a barbaric collapse might be seen as flawed. He also reflects on the possibility that the foundations of sciences and arts, trade and manufacturing, law and policy could be "eroded by time." If that happens, the advancement of civilization would need to start over, but not from scratch. Because "the more useful or at least more essential arts," which don’t require exceptional skills or hierarchical structure to practice, and which war, trade, and religious fervor have spread among the world's less developed societies, would definitely endure.

These remarks are no more than obiter dicta but they show how the doctrine of Progress was influencing those who were temperamentally the least likely to subscribe to extravagant theories.

These comments are just passing thoughts, but they show how the idea of Progress was impacting those who were least inclined to support extreme theories.

4.

4.

The outbreak of the French Revolution evoked a sympathetic movement among English progressive thinkers which occasioned the Government no little alarm. The dissenting minister Dr. Richard Price, whose Observations on Civil Liberty (1776), defending the action of the American colonies, had enjoyed an immense success, preached the sermon which provoked Burke to write his Reflections; and Priestley, no less enthusiastic in welcoming the Revolution, replied to Burke. The Government resorted to tyrannous measures; young men who sympathised with the French movement and agitated for reforms at home were sent to Botany Bay. Paine was prosecuted for his Rights of Man, which directly preached revolution. But the most important speculative work of the time, William Godwin's Political Justice, escaped the censorship because it was not published at a popular price. [Footnote: Godwin had helped to get Paine's book published in 1791, and he was intimate with the group of revolutionary spirits who were persecuted by the Government. A good account of the episode will be found in Brailsford's Shelley, Godwin, and their Circle.]

The start of the French Revolution sparked a sympathetic response among progressive thinkers in England, which caused the Government considerable alarm. The dissenting minister Dr. Richard Price, whose Observations on Civil Liberty (1776), defending the actions of the American colonies, was immensely successful, delivered the sermon that prompted Burke to write his Reflections; Priestley, equally enthusiastic about the Revolution, responded to Burke. The Government took oppressive actions; young men who supported the French movement and pushed for reforms at home were sent to Botany Bay. Paine was prosecuted for his Rights of Man, which openly advocated for revolution. However, the most significant theoretical work of the time, William Godwin's Political Justice, escaped censorship because it wasn’t published at an affordable price. [Footnote: Godwin had helped get Paine's book published in 1791, and he was close to the group of revolutionary thinkers who were persecuted by the Government. A detailed account of the episode can be found in Brailsford's Shelley, Godwin, and their Circle.]

The Enquiry concerning Political Justice, begun in 1791, appeared in 1793. The second edition, three years later, shows the influence of Condorcet's Sketch, which had appeared in the meantime. Godwin says that his original idea was to produce a work on political science to supersede Montesquieu. The note of Montesquieu's political philosophy was respect for social institutions. Godwin's principle was that social institutions are entirely pernicious, that they perpetuate harmful prejudices, and are an almost insuperable obstacle to improvement. If he particularly denounced monarchical government, he regarded all government as evil, and held that social progress would consist, not in the reformation of government, but in its abolition. While he recognised that man had progressed in the past, he considered history mainly a sequence of horrors, and he was incapable of a calm survey of the course of civilisation. In English institutions he saw nothing that did not outrage the principles of justice and benevolence. The present state of humanity is about as bad as it could be.

The Inquiry into Political Justice, started in 1791, was published in 1793. The second edition, released three years later, reflects the impact of Condorcet's Sketch, which was published in the meantime. Godwin stated that his initial aim was to create a work on political science that would replace Montesquieu. Montesquieu's political philosophy emphasized respect for social institutions. In contrast, Godwin believed that social institutions are completely harmful, as they perpetuate damaging prejudices and are a significant barrier to progress. While he specifically criticized monarchical government, he viewed all government as negative and argued that true social progress would come not from reforming government but from abolishing it altogether. Although he acknowledged that humanity had made progress in the past, he mainly saw history as a series of terrible events and could not maintain a balanced view of civilization's development. He found nothing in English institutions that did not violate the principles of justice and kindness. The current state of humanity is as dire as it can possibly be.

It is easy to see the deep influence which the teaching of Rousseau exercised on Godwin. Without accepting the theory of Arcadia Godwin followed him in unsparing condemnation of existing conditions. Rousseau and Godwin are the two great champions in the eighteenth century of the toiling and suffering masses. But Godwin drew the logical conclusion from Rousseau's premisses which Rousseau hesitated to draw himself. The French thinker, while he extolled the anarchical state of uncivilised society, and denounced government as one of the sources of its corruption, nevertheless sought the remedy in new social and political institutions. Godwin said boldly, government is the evil; government must go. Humanity can never be happy until all political authority and social institutions disappear.

It’s clear how deeply Rousseau’s teachings influenced Godwin. While Godwin didn’t embrace the ideal of Arcadia, he followed Rousseau in strongly criticizing the current state of affairs. Rousseau and Godwin are the two major advocates for the struggling masses in the eighteenth century. However, Godwin took the logical step that Rousseau hesitated to take. The French philosopher praised the anarchic nature of uncivilized society and condemned government as a source of its corruption, yet he still looked for solutions in new social and political institutions. Godwin boldly stated, government is the problem; government must be eliminated. Humanity will never find happiness until all political authority and social institutions are gone.

Now the peculiarity of Godwin's position as a doctrinaire of Progress lies in the fact that he entertained the same pessimistic view of some important sides of civilisation as Rousseau, and at the same time adopted the theories of Rousseau's opponents, especially Helvetius. His survey of human conditions seems to lead inevitably to pessimism; then he turns round and proclaims the doctrine of perfectibility.

Now, the uniqueness of Godwin's stance as a champion of Progress lies in the fact that he shared a pessimistic view of certain key aspects of civilization similar to Rousseau, while also embracing the ideas of Rousseau's opponents, particularly Helvetius. His examination of human circumstances appears to lead directly to pessimism; then he shifts and declares the belief in perfectibility.

The explanation of this argument was the psychological theory of Helvetius. He taught, as we saw, and Godwin developed the view in his own way, that the natures and characters of men are moulded entirely by their environment—not physical, but intellectual and moral environment, and therefore can be indefinitely modified. A man is born into the world without innate tendencies. His conduct depends on his opinions. Alter men's opinions and they will act differently. Make their opinions conformable to justice and benevolence, and you will have a just and benevolent society. Virtue, as Socrates taught, is simply a question of knowledge. The situation, therefore, is not hopeless. For it is not due to the radical nature of man; it is caused by ignorance and prejudice, by governments and institutions, by kings and priests. Transform the ideas of men, and society will be transformed. The French philosopher considered that a reformed system of educating children would be one of the most powerful means for promoting progress and bringing about the reign of reason; and Condorcet worked out a scheme of universal state education. This was entirely opposed to Godwin's principles. State schools would only be another instrument of power in the hands of a government, worse even than a state Church. They would strengthen the poisonous influence of kings and statesmen, and establish instead of abolishing prejudices. He seems to have relied entirely on the private efforts of enlightened thinkers to effect a gradual conversion of public opinion.

The explanation of this argument was the psychological theory of Helvetius. He taught, as we saw, and Godwin expanded on this idea in his own way, that people's natures and characters are shaped entirely by their environment—not physical, but intellectual and moral. This means they can be changed indefinitely. A person is born into the world without any innate tendencies. Their behavior depends on their beliefs. Change people's beliefs, and they will act differently. Align their beliefs with justice and kindness, and you'll create a just and kind society. Virtue, as Socrates taught, is simply a matter of knowledge. Thus, the situation is not hopeless. It's not due to the fundamental nature of humanity; it's caused by ignorance and prejudice, as well as by governments and institutions, kings and priests. Change people's ideas, and society will change. The French philosopher believed that a reformed system of educating children would be one of the most effective ways to promote progress and usher in a reign of reason; Condorcet developed a plan for universal state education. This was completely against Godwin's principles. State schools would just be another tool of power in the hands of the government, even worse than a state Church. They would reinforce the toxic influence of kings and politicians and perpetuate rather than eliminate prejudices. He seems to have relied entirely on the private efforts of enlightened thinkers to gradually shift public opinion.

In his study of the perfectibility of man and the prospect of a future reign of general justice and benevolence, Godwin was even more visionary than Condorcet, as in his political views he was more radical than the Revolutionists. Condorcet had at least sought to connect his picture of the future with a reasoned survey of the past, and to find a chain of connection, but the perfectibility of Godwin hung in the air, supported only by an abstract theory of the nature of man.

In his exploration of humanity's potential for improvement and the possibility of an era of universal justice and kindness, Godwin was even more forward-thinking than Condorcet, and his political beliefs were more extreme than those of the revolutionaries. Condorcet at least tried to link his vision of the future with a logical analysis of the past and identify a connection, whereas Godwin's idea of perfectibility seemed unfounded, relying solely on an abstract idea of human nature.

It can hardly be said that he contributed anything to the theoretical problem of civilisation. His significance is that he proclaimed in England at an opportune moment, and in a more impressive and startling way than a sober apostle like Priestley, the creed of progress taught by French philosophers, though considerably modified by his own anarchical opinions.

It’s tough to claim he added much to the theoretical issue of civilization. What matters is that he announced the idea of progress promoted by French philosophers in England at a crucial time, and he did it in a more dramatic and striking way than a serious thinker like Priestley, even though he altered it quite a bit with his own anarchistic views.

5.

5.

Perfectibility, as expounded by Condorcet and Godwin, encountered a drastic criticism from Malthus, whose Essay on the Principle of Population appeared in its first form anonymously in 1798. Condorcet had foreseen an objection which might be raised as fatal to the realisation of his future state. Will not the progress of industry and happiness cause a steady increase in population, and must not the time come when the number of the inhabitants of the globe will surpass their means of subsistence? Condorcet did not grapple with this question. He contented himself with saying that such a period must be very far away, and that by then "the human race will have achieved improvements of which we can now scarcely form an idea." Similarly Godwin, in his fancy picture of the future happiness of mankind, notices the difficulty and shirks it. "Three-fourths of the habitable globe are now uncultivated. The parts already cultivated are capable of immeasurable improvement. Myriads of centuries of still increasing population may pass away and the earth be still found sufficient for the subsistence of its inhabitants."

Perfectibility, as explained by Condorcet and Godwin, faced severe criticism from Malthus, whose Essay on the Principle of Population was first published anonymously in 1798. Condorcet anticipated an objection that could jeopardize his vision of the future. Wouldn’t the advancement of industry and happiness lead to a steady increase in population, and will there come a time when the number of people on Earth exceeds its resources? Condorcet didn’t tackle this question. He merely stated that such a time must be far off, and by then “the human race will have achieved improvements of which we can now scarcely form an idea.” Similarly, Godwin, in his ideal vision of humanity's future happiness, acknowledges the challenge but avoids it. “Three-fourths of the habitable globe are now uncultivated. The areas already cultivated can be improved immensely. Countless centuries of ever-growing population may pass, and the earth will still be sufficient for the subsistence of its inhabitants.”

Malthus argued that these writers laboured under an illusion as to the actual relations between population and the means of subsistence. In present conditions the numbers of the race are only kept from increasing far beyond the means of subsistence by vice, misery, and the fear of misery. [Footnote: This observation had been made (as Hazlitt pointed out) before Malthus by Robert Wallace (see A Dissertation on the Numbers of Mankind, p. 13, 1753). It was another book of Wallace that suggested the difficulty to Godwin.] In the conditions imagined by Condorcet and Godwin these checks are removed, and consequently the population would increase with great rapidity, doubling itself at least in twenty-five years. But the products of the earth increase only in an arithmetical progression, and in fifty years the food supply would be too small for the demand. Thus the oscillation between numbers and food supply would recur, and the happiness of the species would come to an end.

Malthus claimed that these writers were under a misconception about the actual relationship between population and the resources needed for survival. In current conditions, the population is only kept from growing significantly beyond what the resources can support due to vice, hardship, and the fear of hardship. [Footnote: This observation was made (as Hazlitt pointed out) prior to Malthus by Robert Wallace (see A Dissertation on the Numbers of Mankind, p. 13, 1753). It was another book by Wallace that suggested the challenge to Godwin.] In the scenarios envisioned by Condorcet and Godwin, these limitations would be eliminated, leading to a rapid population increase, potentially doubling in just twenty-five years. However, the earth's resources grow only in a simple arithmetic progression, and in fifty years, the food supply would be insufficient for the demand. As a result, the cycle between population and food supply would repeat, and the species' happiness would come to an end.

Godwin and his adherents could reply that one of the checks on over-population is prudential restraint, which Malthus himself recognised, and that this would come more extensively into operation with that progress of enlightenment which their theory assumed. [Footnote: This is urged by Hazlitt in his criticism of Malthus in the Spirit of the Age.] But the criticisms of Malthus dealt a trenchant blow to the doctrine that human reason, acting through legislation and government, has a virtually indefinite power of modifying the condition of society. The difficulty, which he stated so vividly and definitely, was well calculated to discredit the doctrine, and to suggest that the development of society could be modified by the conscious efforts of man only within restricted limits. [Footnote: The recent conclusions of Mr. Knibbs, statistician to the Commonwealth of Australia, in vol. i. of his Appendix to the Census of the Commonwealth, have an interest in this connection. I quote from an article in the Times of August 5, 1918: "An eminent geographer, the late Mr. E. G. Ravenstein, some years ago, when the population of the earth was estimated at 1400 million, foretold that about the middle of this century population would have reached a limit beyond which increase would be disastrous. Mr. Knibbs is not so pessimistic and is much more precise; though he defers the disastrous culmination, he has no doubt as to its inevitability. The limits of human expansion, he assures us, are much nearer than popular opinion imagines; the difficulty of food supplies will soon be most grave; the exhaustion of sources of energy necessary for any notable increase of population, or advance in the standards of living, or both combined, is perilously near. The present rate of increase in the world's population cannot continue for four centuries."]

Godwin and his supporters might argue that one of the limits on overpopulation is prudential restraint, which Malthus himself acknowledged, and that this would become more effective as society progresses in understanding, as their theory suggests. [Footnote: This point is made by Hazlitt in his critique of Malthus in the Spirit of the Age.] However, Malthus's criticisms significantly undermined the idea that human reason, working through laws and government, has almost unlimited power to change society's conditions. The challenge he articulated clearly and forcefully was likely to discredit that idea, suggesting that social development can only be altered by human effort within certain constraints. [Footnote: The recent findings of Mr. Knibbs, statistician for the Commonwealth of Australia, in volume I of his Appendix to the Census of the Commonwealth, are relevant here. I refer to an article in the Times dated August 5, 1918: "An eminent geographer, the late Mr. E. G. Ravenstein, predicted a few years ago, when the global population was estimated at 1.4 billion, that by the middle of this century, the population would reach a point where any further growth would be harmful. Mr. Knibbs is less pessimistic and more specific; although he postpones the disastrous outcome, he has no doubt about its inevitability. He assures us that the limits of human expansion are much closer than most people think; food supply issues will soon become very serious; and the depletion of energy sources required for significant population growth or improvement in living standards, or both, is dangerously imminent. The current rate of population growth cannot be sustained for another four centuries."]

6.

6.

The Essay of Malthus afterwards became one of the sacred books of the Utilitarian sect, and it is interesting to notice what Bentham himself thought of perfectibility. Referring to the optimistic views of Chastellux and Priestley on progressive amelioration he observed that "these glorious expectations remind us of the golden age of poetry." For perfect happiness "belongs to the imaginary region of philosophy and must be classed with the universal elixir and the philosopher's stone." There will always be jealousies through the unequal gifts of nature and of fortune; interests will never cease to clash and hatred to ensue; "painful labour, daily subjection, a condition nearly allied to indigence, will always be the lot of numbers"; in art and poetry the sources of novelty will probably be exhausted. But Bentham was far from being a pessimist. Though he believes that "we shall never make this world the abode of happiness," he asserts that it may be made a most delightful garden "compared with the savage forest in which men so long have wandered." [Footnote: Works, vol. i. p. 193 seq.]

The Essay of Malthus later became one of the essential texts for the Utilitarian movement, and it's interesting to note what Bentham himself thought about the idea of perfectibility. Referring to the optimistic views of Chastellux and Priestley on gradual improvement, he commented that "these glorious expectations remind us of the golden age of poetry." Perfect happiness "belongs to the imaginary realm of philosophy and should be grouped with the universal elixir and the philosopher's stone." There will always be rivalries due to the unequal gifts of nature and fortune; interests will always clash and lead to hatred; "painful labor, daily subjugation, a condition nearly akin to poverty, will always be the fate of many"; in art and poetry, the sources of novelty will likely be depleted. However, Bentham was far from a pessimist. Even though he believes "we will never make this world a place of happiness," he insists that it can be turned into a beautiful garden "compared to the savage forest in which people have wandered for so long." [Footnote: Works, vol. i. p. 193 seq.]

7.

7.

The book of Malthus was welcomed at the moment by all those who had been thoroughly frightened by the French Revolution and saw in the "modern philosophy," as it was called, a serious danger to society. [Footnote: Both Hazlitt and Shelley thought that Malthus was playing to the boxes, by sophisms "calculated to lull the oppressors of mankind into a security of everlasting triumph" (Revolt of Islam, Preface). Bentham refers in his Book of Fallacies (Works, ii. p. 462) to the unpopularity of the views of Priestley, Godwin, and Condorcet: "to aim at perfection has been pronounced to be utter folly or wickedness."] Vice and misery and the inexorable laws of population were a godsend to rescue the state from "the precipice of perfectibility." We can understand the alarm occasioned to believers in the established constitution of things, for Godwin's work—now virtually forgotten, while Malthus is still appealed to as a discoverer in social science—produced an immense effect on impressionable minds at the time. All who prized liberty, sympathised with the downtrodden, and were capable of falling in love with social ideals, hailed Godwin as an evangelist. "No one," said a contemporary, "was more talked of, more looked up to, more sought after; and wherever liberty, truth, justice was the theme, his name was not far off." Young graduates left the Universities to throw themselves at the feet of the new Gamaliel; students of law and medicine neglected their professional studies to dream of "the renovation of society and the march of mind." Godwin carried with him "all the most sanguine and fearless understandings of the time." [Footnote: Hazlitt, Spirit of the Age: article on Godwin (written in 1814).]

The book by Malthus was welcomed by those who were deeply alarmed by the French Revolution and viewed what they called "modern philosophy" as a serious threat to society. [Footnote: Both Hazlitt and Shelley believed that Malthus was catering to the elite, using arguments "designed to lull the oppressors of mankind into a false sense of everlasting triumph" (Revolt of Islam, Preface). Bentham mentions in his Book of Fallacies (Works, ii. p. 462) the unpopularity of the views of Priestley, Godwin, and Condorcet: "to aim at perfection has been considered utter foolishness or wickedness."] Vice, misery, and the harsh realities of population growth became a blessing to save the state from "the brink of perfectibility." It's easy to understand the panic among supporters of the established order because Godwin's work—now nearly forgotten, while Malthus is still regarded as a pioneer in social science—had a huge impact on sensitive minds at the time. Those who valued liberty, empathized with the oppressed, and could dream of social ideals celebrated Godwin as a prophet. "No one," said a contemporary, "was more talked about, more admired, or more sought after; and wherever liberty, truth, or justice was discussed, his name was close by." Young graduates left the universities to study at the feet of the new teacher; law and medical students abandoned their studies to fantasize about "the renewal of society and the advancement of thought." Godwin brought with him "all the most optimistic and fearless intellects of the time." [Footnote: Hazlitt, Spirit of the Age: article on Godwin (written in 1814).]

The most famous of his disciples were the poets Wordsworth, Coleridge, Southey, and afterwards Shelley. Wordsworth had been an ardent sympathiser with the French Revolution. In its early days he had visited Paris:

The most famous of his disciples were the poets Wordsworth, Coleridge, Southey, and later Shelley. Wordsworth had been a strong supporter of the French Revolution. In its early days, he had traveled to Paris:

         An emporium then
   Of golden expectations and receiving
   Freights every day from a new world of hope.
         A marketplace then
   Of bright expectations and welcoming
   Deliveries every day from a new world of hope.

He became a Godwinian in 1795, when the Terror had destroyed his faith in Revolutionary France. Southey, who had come under the influence of Rousseau, was initiated by Coleridge into Godwin's theories, and in their utopian enthusiasm they formed the design of founding a "pantisocratic" settlement in America, to show how happiness could be realised in a social environment in which duty and interest coincide and consequently all are virtuous. The plan anticipated the experiments of Owen and Cabet; but the pantisocrats did not experience the disappointments of the socialists, for it was never carried out. Coleridge and Southey as well as Wordsworth soon abandoned their Godwinian doctrines. [Footnote: In letters of 1797 and 1798 Coleridge repudiated the French doctrines and Godwin's philosophy. See Cestre, La Revolution francaise et les poetes anglais (1789-1809), pp. 389, 414.] They had, to use a phrase of Hazlitt, lost their way in Utopia, and they gave up the abstract and mechanical view of society which the French philosophy of the eighteenth century taught, for an organic conception in which historic sentiment and the wisdom of our ancestors had their due place. Wordsworth could presently look back and criticise his Godwinian phase as that of

He became a follower of Godwin in 1795, when the Terror shattered his faith in Revolutionary France. Southey, influenced by Rousseau, was introduced to Godwin's theories by Coleridge, and together with their idealistic enthusiasm, they planned to establish a "pantisocratic" settlement in America to demonstrate how happiness could be achieved in a society where duty and self-interest align and everyone is virtuous. Their plan anticipated the experiments of Owen and Cabet, but the pantisocrats avoided the disappointments faced by the socialists, as it was never implemented. Coleridge, Southey, and Wordsworth soon abandoned their Godwinian beliefs. [Footnote: In letters from 1797 and 1798, Coleridge rejected the French doctrines and Godwin's philosophy. See Cestre, La Revolution francaise et les poetes anglais (1789-1809), pp. 389, 414.] They had, to quote Hazlitt, lost their way in Utopia, and they moved away from the abstract and mechanical view of society that the French philosophy of the eighteenth century promoted, toward an organic understanding that valued historical sentiment and the wisdom of our ancestors. Wordsworth could later look back and critique his Godwinian phase as one of

  A proud and most presumptuous confidence
   In the transcendent wisdom of the age
   And its discernment. [Footnote: Excursion, Book ii.]
  A proud and overly confident belief 
   In the incredible wisdom of the time 
   And its judgment. [Footnote: Excursion, Book ii.]

He and Southey became conservative pillars of the state. Yet Southey, reactionary as he was in politics, never ceased to believe in social Progress. [Footnote: See his Colloquies; and Shelley, writing in 1811, says that Southey "looks forward to a state when all shall be perfected and matter become subjected to the omnipotence of mind" (Dowden, Life of Shelley, i. p. 212). Compare below, p. 325.] Amelioration was indeed to be effected by slow and cautious reforms, with the aid of the Church, but the intellectual aberrations of his youth had left an abiding impression.

He and Southey became conservative pillars of the state. However, Southey, as reactionary as he was in politics, never stopped believing in social progress. [Footnote: See his Colloquies; and Shelley, writing in 1811, says that Southey "looks forward to a state when all will be perfected and matter will be subjected to the power of the mind" (Dowden, Life of Shelley, i. p. 212). Compare below, p. 325.] Improvement was indeed to be achieved through slow and careful reforms, with the support of the Church, but the intellectual mistakes of his youth had left a lasting impact.

While these poets were sitting at Godwin's feet, Shelley was still a child. But he came across Political Justice at Eton; in his later life he reread it almost every year; and when he married Godwin's daughter he was more Godwinian than Godwin himself. Hazlitt, writing in 1814, says that Godwin's reputation had "sunk below the horizon," but Shelley never ceased to believe in his theory, though he came to see that the regeneration of man would be a much slower process than he had at first imagined. In the immature poem Queen Mab the philosophy of Godwin was behind his description of the future, and it was behind the longer and more ambitious poems of his maturer years. The city of gold, of the Revolt of Islam, is Godwin's future society, and he describes that poem as "an experiment on the temper of the public mind as to how far a thirst for a happier condition of moral and political society survives, among the enlightened and refined, the tempests which have shaken the age in which we live." As to Prometheus Unbound his biographer observes: [Footnote: Dowden, ib. ii. p. 264. Elsewhere Dowden remarks on the singular insensibility of Shelley's mind "to the wisdom or sentiment of history" (i. p. 55).]

While these poets were gathering around Godwin, Shelley was still a child. But he discovered Political Justice at Eton; in his later years, he reread it nearly every year; and when he married Godwin's daughter, he was even more Godwinian than Godwin himself. Hazlitt, writing in 1814, mentioned that Godwin's reputation had "sunk below the horizon," but Shelley never stopped believing in his theory, although he realized that the regeneration of humanity would be a much slower process than he initially thought. In the immature poem Queen Mab, Godwin's philosophy influenced his vision of the future, and it was also the foundation of the longer and more ambitious poems he wrote later in life. The city of gold in the Revolt of Islam represents Godwin's envisioned future society, and he referred to that poem as "an experiment on the temper of the public mind regarding how far a desire for a better moral and political society persists among the enlightened and refined, despite the upheavals that have shaken our age." Regarding Prometheus Unbound, his biographer notes: [Footnote: Dowden, ib. ii. p. 264. Elsewhere Dowden mentions the remarkable insensitivity of Shelley's mind "to the wisdom or sentiment of history" (i. p. 55).]

All the glittering fallacies of "Political Justice"—now sufficiently tarnished—together with all its encouraging and stimulating truths, may be found in the caput mortuum left when the critic has reduced the poetry of the "Prometheus" to a series of doctrinaire statements.

All the shining falsehoods of "Political Justice"—now pretty worn down—along with all its uplifting and motivating truths, can be found in the remains left over when the critic has transformed the poetry of the "Prometheus" into a list of rigid statements.

The same dream inspired the final chorus of Hellas. Shelley was the poet of perfectibility.

The same dream inspired the final chorus of Hellas. Shelley was the poet of perfection.

8.

8.

The attraction of perfectibility reached beyond the ranks of men of letters, and in Robert Owen, the benevolent millowner of Lanark, it had an apostle who based upon it a very different theory from that of Political Justice and became one of the founders of modern socialism.

The appeal of perfection extended beyond just writers, and in Robert Owen, the kind mill owner from Lanark, it found a champion who built a very different theory from that of Political Justice and became one of the pioneers of modern socialism.

The success of the idea of Progress has been promoted by its association with socialism. [Footnote: The word was independently invented in England and France. An article in the Poor Man's Guardian (a periodical edited by H. Hetherington, afterwards by Bronterre O'Brien), Aug. 24, 1833, is signed "A Socialist"; and in 1834 socialisme is opposed to individualism by P. Leroux in an article in the Revue Encyclopedique. The word is used in the New Moral World, and from 1836 was applied to the Owenites. See Dolleans, Robert Owen (1907), p. 305.] The first phase of socialism, what has been called its sentimental phase, was originated by Saint-Simon in France and Owen in England at about the same time; Marx was to bring it down from the clouds and make it a force in practical politics. But both in its earlier and in its later forms the economical doctrines rest upon a theory of society depending on the assumption, however disguised, that social institutions have been solely responsible for the vice and misery which exist, and that institutions and laws can be so changed as to abolish misery and vice. That is pure eighteenth century doctrine; and it passed from the revolutionary doctrinaires of that period to the constructive socialists of the nineteenth century.

The success of the concept of Progress has been promoted by its connection to socialism. [Footnote: The term was independently created in England and France. An article in the Poor Man's Guardian (a periodical edited by H. Hetherington, later by Bronterre O'Brien), dated August 24, 1833, is signed "A Socialist"; and in 1834, socialisme is contrasted with individualism by P. Leroux in an article in the Revue Encyclopedique. The term is used in the New Moral World, and starting in 1836, it was applied to the Owenites. See Dolleans, Robert Owen (1907), p. 305.] The initial phase of socialism, referred to as its sentimental phase, was started by Saint-Simon in France and Owen in England around the same period; Marx would later bring it down from the lofty ideals and turn it into a practical political force. However, both in its earlier and later forms, the economic theories are based on a societal theory that assumes—regardless of how it’s framed—that social institutions alone are responsible for the vice and suffering that exist, and that institutions and laws can be changed to eliminate suffering and vice. This is a purely eighteenth-century idea, which was passed down from the revolutionary thinkers of that era to the constructive socialists of the nineteenth century.

Owen learned it probably from Godwin, and he did not disguise it. His numerous works enforce it ad nauseam. He began the propagation of his gospel by his "New View of Society, or Essays on the formation of the human character, preparatory to the development of a plan for gradually ameliorating the condition of mankind," which he dedicated to the Prince Regent. [Footnote: 3rd ed. 1817. The Essays had appeared separately in 1813-14.] Here he lays down that "any general character, from the best to the worst, may be given to any community, even to the world at large, by the application of proper means; which means are to a great extent at the command and under the control of those who have influence in the affairs of men." [Footnote: P. 19.] The string on which he continually harps is that it is the cardinal error in government to suppose that men are responsible for their vices and virtues, and therefore for their actions and characters. These result from education and institutions, and can be transformed automatically by transforming those agencies. Owen founded several short-lived journals to diffuse his theories. The first number of the New Moral World (1834-36) [Footnote: This was not a journal, but a series of pamphlets which appeared in 1836-1844. Other publications of Owen were: Outline of the Rational System of Society (6th ed., Leeds, 1840); The Revolution in the Mind and Practice of the Human Race, or the coming change from Irrationality to Rationality (1849); The Future of the Human Race, or a great, glorious and peaceful Revolution, near at hand, to be effected through the agency of departed spirits of good and superior men and women (1853); The New Existence of Man upon Earth, Parts i.-viii., 1854-55.] proclaimed the approach of an ideal society in which there will be no ignorance, no poverty, and no charity—a system "which will ensure the happiness of the human race throughout all future ages," to replace one "which, so long as it shall be maintained, must produce misery to all." His own experimental attempt to found such a society on a miniature scale in America proved a ludicrous failure.

Owen probably learned this from Godwin, and he didn't hide it. His many works emphasize it repeatedly. He started spreading his ideas with "New View of Society, or Essays on the Formation of the Human Character, Preparatory to the Development of a Plan for Gradually Improving the Condition of Mankind," which he dedicated to the Prince Regent. [Footnote: 3rd ed. 1817. The Essays had appeared separately in 1813-14.] Here, he states that "any general character, from the best to the worst, can be assigned to any community, even to the world at large, by applying the right means; and those means are largely available and under the control of those who influence human affairs." [Footnote: P. 19.] The main point he keeps stressing is that it's a major mistake in government to believe that people are responsible for their faults and virtues, and therefore for their actions and character. These arise from education and institutions, and can be changed just by changing those systems. Owen started several short-lived journals to spread his theories. The first issue of the New Moral World (1834-36) [Footnote: This was not a journal, but a series of pamphlets that appeared in 1836-1844. Other publications of Owen included: Outline of the Rational System of Society (6th ed., Leeds, 1840); The Revolution in the Mind and Practice of the Human Race, or the Coming Change from Irrationality to Rationality (1849); The Future of the Human Race, or a Great, Glorious, and Peaceful Revolution, Near at Hand, to be Achieved Through the Agency of Departed Spirits of Good and Superior Men and Women (1853); The New Existence of Man upon Earth, Parts i.-viii., 1854-55.] announced the coming of an ideal society where there would be no ignorance, no poverty, and no charity—a system "that will guarantee the happiness of the human race for all future ages," replacing one "which, as long as it continues, must create misery for everyone." His own experimental attempt to establish such a society on a small scale in America ended in ridiculous failure.

It is to be observed that in these socialist theories the conception of Progress as indefinite tends to vanish or to lose its significance. If the millennium can be brought about at a stroke by a certain arrangement of society, the goal of development is achieved; we shall have reached the term, and shall have only to live in and enjoy the ideal state—a menagerie of happy men. There will be room for further, perhaps indefinite, advance in knowledge, but civilisation in its social character becomes stable and rigid. Once man's needs are perfectly satisfied in a harmonious environment there is no stimulus to cause further changes, and the dynamic character of history disappears.

It’s worth noting that in these socialist theories, the idea of Progress as something endless seems to fade or lose its meaning. If a perfect society can be created all at once through a specific arrangement, then the goal of development has been reached; we will have arrived at the endpoint and will just need to exist in and enjoy this ideal state—a collection of happy people. There may still be room for further, possibly endless, growth in knowledge, but society itself becomes stable and unchanging. Once people’s needs are completely met in a balanced environment, there’s no motivation for further changes, and the dynamic nature of history disappears.

Theories of Progress are thus differentiating into two distinct types, corresponding to two radically opposed political theories and appealing to two antagonistic temperaments. The one type is that of constructive idealists and socialists, who can name all the streets and towers of "the city of gold," which they imagine as situated just round a promontory. The development of man is a closed system; its term is known and is within reach. The other type is that of those who, surveying the gradual ascent of man, believe that by the same interplay of forces which have conducted him so far and by a further development of the liberty which he has fought to win, he will move slowly towards conditions of increasing harmony and happiness. Here the development is indefinite; its term is unknown, and lies in the remote future. Individual liberty is the motive force, and the corresponding political theory is liberalism; whereas the first doctrine naturally leads to a symmetrical system in which the authority of the state is preponderant, and the individual has little more value than a cog in a well-oiled wheel: his place is assigned; it is not his right to go his own way. Of this type the principal example that is not socialistic is, as we shall see, the philosophy of Comte.

Theories of Progress are breaking down into two distinct types, aligned with two completely different political theories and appealing to two conflicting mindsets. One type includes constructive idealists and socialists, who can name all the streets and towers of "the city of gold," which they picture just around the corner. The evolution of humanity is a closed loop; its endpoint is known and within reach. The other type belongs to those who, observing humanity's gradual progress, believe that through the same forces that have brought them this far and by further expanding the freedom they have fought for, people will slowly move towards greater harmony and happiness. Here, development is indefinite; its endpoint is unknown and lies far in the future. Individual freedom is the driving force, and the related political theory is liberalism. In contrast, the first doctrine typically leads to a structured system where the state holds significant authority, and the individual is valued little more than a gear in a well-functioning machine: their role is determined, and it’s not their right to choose their own path. A key example of this type that isn't socialistic is, as we will see, Comte's philosophy.





CHAPTER XIII. GERMAN SPECULATIONS ON PROGRESS

1.

The philosophical views current in Germany during the period in which the psychology of Locke was in fashion in France and before the genius of Kant opened a new path, were based on the system of Leibnitz. We might therefore expect to find a theory of Progress developed there, parallel to the development in France though resting on different principles. For Leibnitz, as we saw, provided in his cosmic optimism a basis for the doctrine of human Progress, and he had himself incidentally pointed to it. This development, however, was delayed. It was only towards the close of the period—which is commonly known as the age of "Illumination"—that Progress came to the front, and it is interesting to observe the reason.

The philosophical ideas prevalent in Germany during the time when Locke's psychology was popular in France, and before Kant's genius introduced a new direction, were rooted in Leibnitz's system. Therefore, we might expect to see a theory of Progress evolving there, similar to the development in France but based on different principles. Leibnitz, as we noted, laid the groundwork for the idea of human Progress through his cosmic optimism, and he had also hinted at it. However, this development was slow to emerge. It wasn't until the end of the period typically referred to as the age of "Enlightenment" that Progress became more prominent, and it's interesting to note the reasons behind this.

Wolf was the leading successor and interpreter of Leibnitz. He constrained that thinker's ideas into a compact logical system which swayed Germany till Kant swept it away. In such cases it usually happens that some striking doctrines and tendencies of the master are accentuated and enforced, while others are suffered to drop out of sight.

Wolf was the main successor and interpreter of Leibnitz. He shaped that philosopher's ideas into a concise logical system that dominated Germany until Kant overthrew it. In these situations, it often happens that some notable doctrines and tendencies of the master are highlighted and enforced, while others are allowed to fade away.

So it was here. In the Wolfian system, Leibnitz's conception of development was suffered to drop out of sight, and the dynamic element which animated his speculation disappeared. In particular, he had laid down that the sum of motive forces in the physical world is constant. His disciples proceeded to the inference that the sum of morality in the ethical world is constant. This dogma obviously eliminates the possibility of ethical improvement for collective humanity. And so we find Mendelssohn, who was the popular exponent of Wolf's philosophy, declaring that "progress is only for the individual; but that the whole of humanity here below in the course of time shall always progress and perfect itself seems to me not to have been the purpose of Providence." [Footnote: See Bock, Jakob Wegelin als Geschichtstheoretiker, in Leipsiger Studien, ix. 4, pp. 23-7 (1902).]

So it was here. In the Wolfian system, Leibnitz's idea of development was allowed to fade away, and the dynamic element that fueled his theories vanished. He had specifically stated that the total amount of motive forces in the physical world is constant. His followers jumped to the conclusion that the total amount of morality in the ethical world is also constant. This belief clearly rules out the possibility of ethical improvement for humanity as a whole. And so we find Mendelssohn, who was the popular advocate of Wolf's philosophy, stating that "progress is only for the individual; but that all of humanity here on Earth will always progress and improve over time seems to me not to have been the purpose of Providence." [Footnote: See Bock, Jakob Wegelin als Geschichtstheoretiker, in Leipsiger Studien, ix. 4, pp. 23-7 (1902).]

The publication of the Nouveaux Essais in 1765 induced some thinkers to turn from the dry bones of Wolf to the spirit of Leibnitz himself. And at the same time French thought was penetrating. In consequence of these influences the final phase of the German "Illumination" is marked by the appearance of two or three works in which Progress is a predominating idea.

The release of the Nouveaux Essais in 1765 caused some thinkers to shift their focus from the rigid ideas of Wolf to the essence of Leibniz himself. Meanwhile, French thought was also making an impact. As a result of these influences, the last phase of the German "Illumination" is characterized by the emergence of two or three works where Progress is a key theme.

We see this reaction against Wolf and his static school in a little work published by Herder in 1774—"a philosophy of history for the cultivation of mankind." There is continuous development, he declares, and one people builds upon the work of another. We must judge past ages, not by the present, but relatively to their own particular conditions. What exists now was never possible before, for everything that man accomplishes is conditioned by time, climate, and circumstances.

We see this reaction against Wolf and his static school in a small work published by Herder in 1774—"a philosophy of history for the cultivation of mankind." He states that there is continuous development, and one society builds upon the achievements of another. We should evaluate past eras not by today's standards but in relation to their own specific conditions. What exists now was never possible before, as everything humans achieve is shaped by time, climate, and circumstances.

Six years later Lessing's pamphlet on the Education of the Human Race appeared, couched in the form of aphoristic statements, and to a modern reader, one may venture to say, singularly wanting in argumentative force. The thesis is that the drama of history is to be explained as the education of man by a progressive series of religions, a series not yet complete, for the future will produce another revelation to lift him to a higher plane than that to which Christ has drawn him up. This interpretation of history proclaimed Progress, but assumed an ideal and applied a measure very different from those of the French philosophers. The goal is not social happiness, but a full comprehension of God. Philosophy of religion is made the key to the philosophy of history. The work does not amount to more than a suggestion for a new synthesis, but it was opportune and arresting.

Six years later, Lessing's pamphlet on the Education of the Human Race came out, presented as a collection of short, impactful statements. To a modern reader, it may seem notably lacking in persuasive power. The main idea is that history should be understood as humanity's education through a progressive series of religions, which is still ongoing, as the future is expected to reveal another insight that will elevate humanity beyond the current understanding brought by Christ. This view of history promotes Progress but relies on an ideal and uses a standard different from that of the French philosophers. The aim isn't social happiness but achieving a complete understanding of God. The philosophy of religion is framed as the key to understanding the philosophy of history. The work doesn't constitute a full argument but rather a suggestion for a new way of thinking, and it was timely and thought-provoking.

Herder meanwhile had been thinking, and in 1784 he gave the German world his survey of man's career—Ideas of the Philosophy of the History of Humanity. In this famous work, in which we can mark the influence of French thinkers, especially Montesquieu, as well as of Leibnitz, he attempted, though on very different lines, the same task which Turgot and Condorcet planned, a universal history of civilisation.

Herder had been reflecting, and in 1784 he presented the German world with his overview of humanity's journey—Ideas of the Philosophy of the History of Humanity. In this well-known work, which shows the influence of French philosophers, especially Montesquieu, along with Leibnitz, he aimed to undertake a similar task to what Turgot and Condorcet envisioned: a universal history of civilization, though he approached it in a very different way.

The Deity designed the world but never interferes in its process, either in the physical cosmos or in human history. Human history itself, civilisation, is a purely natural phenomenon. Events are strictly enchained; continuity is unbroken; what happened at any given time could have happened only then, and nothing else could have happened. Herder's rigid determinism not only excludes Voltaire's chance but also suppresses the free play of man's intelligent will. Man cannot guide his own destinies; his actions and fortunes are determined by the nature of things, his physical organisation and physical environment. The fact that God exists in inactive ease hardly affects the fatalistic complexion of this philosophy; but it is perhaps a mitigation that the world was made for man; humanity is its final cause.

The Deity created the world but never intervenes in its workings, whether in the physical universe or in human history. Human history itself, civilization, is a purely natural occurrence. Events are strictly linked; continuity is unbroken; what happened at any point in time could have only happened then, and nothing else could have occurred. Herder's strict determinism not only rules out Voltaire's notion of chance but also stifles the free exercise of human will. People cannot steer their own destinies; their actions and fortunes are shaped by the nature of things, their physical makeup, and their environment. The fact that God exists in a state of non-interference hardly changes the fatalistic nature of this philosophy; however, it may be somewhat comforting that the world was created for humanity; people are its ultimate purpose.

The variety of the phases of civilisation that have appeared on earth is due to the fact that the possible manifestations of human nature are very numerous and that they must all be realised. The lower forms are those in which the best, which means the most human, faculties of our nature are undeveloped. The highest has not yet been realised. "The flower of humanity, captive still in its germ, will blossom out one day into the true form of man like unto God, in a state of which no terrestrial man can imagine the greatness and the majesty." [Footnote: Ideen, v. 5.]

The different stages of civilization that have emerged on earth are because there are countless ways human nature can express itself, and all of these must come to light. The lower forms are those where our best qualities, which are the most human aspects of our nature, are not fully developed. The highest potential has not yet been achieved. "The flower of humanity, still trapped in its seed, will one day bloom into the true form of man resembling God, in a state that no earthly being can fathom the greatness and majesty of." [Footnote: Ideen, v. 5.]

Herder is not a systematic thinker—indeed his work abounds in contradictions—and he has not made it clear how far this full epiphany results from the experiences of mankind in preceding phases. He believes that life is an education for humanity (he has taken the phrase of Lessing), that good progressively develops, that reason and justice become more powerful. This is a doctrine of Progress, but he distinctly opposes the hypothesis of a final and unique state of perfection as the goal of history, which would imply that earlier generations exist for the sake of the later and suffer in order to ensure the felicity of remote posterity—a theory which offends his sense of justice and fitness. On the contrary, man can realise happiness equally in every stage of civilisation. All forms of society are equally legitimate, the imperfect as well as the perfect; all are ends in themselves, not mere stages on the way to something better. And a people which is happy in one of these inferior states has a perfect right to remain in it.

Herder isn’t a systematic thinker—his work is actually full of contradictions—and he hasn’t clarified how much this complete insight comes from humanity’s experiences in earlier phases. He believes that life is an education for humanity (he borrowed this idea from Lessing), that goodness gradually develops, and that reason and justice become stronger. This represents a belief in progress, but he firmly rejects the idea of a final and unique state of perfection being the ultimate goal of history, which would suggest that earlier generations exist solely for the benefit of later ones and suffer to ensure the happiness of future generations—a concept that goes against his sense of justice and fairness. Instead, he argues that people can find happiness at any level of civilization. All forms of society are equally valid, both the imperfect and the perfect; each is an end in itself, not just a step toward something better. A society that is happy even in one of these less-than-ideal states has every right to remain there.

Thus the Progress which Herder sees is, to use his own geometrical illustration, a sequence of unequal and broken curves, corresponding to different maxima and minima. Each curve has its own equation, the history of each people is subject to the laws of its own environment; but there is no general law controlling the whole career of humanity. [Footnote: Ib. xv. 3. The power of ideas in history, which Herder failed to appreciate, was recognised by a contemporary savant from whom he might have learned. Jakob Wegelin, a Swiss, had, at the invitation of Frederick the Great, settled in Berlin, where he spent the last years of his life and devoted his study to the theory of history. His merit was to have perceived that "external facts are penetrated and governed by spiritual forces and guiding ideas, and that the essential and permanent in history is conditioned by the nature and development of ideas." (Dierauer, quoted by Bock, op. cit. p. 13.) He believed in the progressive development of mankind as a whole, but as his learned brochures seem to have exerted no influence, it would be useless here to examine more closely his views, which are buried in the transactions of the Prussian Academy of Science. In Switzerland he came under the influence of Rousseau and d'Alembert. After he moved to Berlin (1765) he fell under that of Leibnitz. It may be noted (1) that he deprecated attempts at writing a universal history as premature until an adequate knowledge of facts had been gained, and this would demand long preliminary labours; (2) that he discussed the question whether history is an indefinite progression or a series of constant cycles, and decided for the former view. (Memoire sur le cours periodique, 1785). Bock's monograph is the best study of Wegelin; but see also Flint's observations in Philosophy of History, vol. i. (1874).]

So, the progress that Herder talks about is, to use his own geometric analogy, a series of uneven and broken curves, reflecting different peaks and lows. Each curve has its own equation, and the history of each nation follows the laws of its own surroundings; however, there isn’t a single law that governs the entire journey of humanity. [Footnote: Ib. xv. 3. The influence of ideas in history, which Herder didn't fully recognize, was acknowledged by a contemporary scholar from whom he could have learned. Jakob Wegelin, a Swiss, moved to Berlin at the invitation of Frederick the Great, where he spent his final years studying the theory of history. His contribution was noticing that "external facts are penetrated and governed by spiritual forces and guiding ideas, and that what is essential and lasting in history is shaped by the nature and evolution of ideas." (Dierauer, quoted by Bock, op. cit. p. 13.) He believed in the overall progressive development of humanity, but since his scholarly pamphlets seem to have had little impact, it would be pointless to delve deeper into his views, which are now lost in the records of the Prussian Academy of Science. While in Switzerland, he was influenced by Rousseau and d'Alembert. After moving to Berlin in 1765, he came under the influence of Leibnitz. It’s worth noting (1) that he criticized attempts to write a universal history as premature until there was a solid understanding of facts, which would require extensive preliminary efforts; (2) that he debated whether history is an endless progression or a series of constant cycles, ultimately siding with the former perspective. (Memoire sur le cours periodique, 1785). Bock's monograph is the best study of Wegelin; see also Flint's observations in Philosophy of History, vol. i. (1874).]

Herder brought down his historical survey only as far as the sixteenth century. It has been suggested [Footnote: Javary, De l'idee de progres, p. 69.] that if he had come down further he might have comprehended the possibility of a deliberate transformation of societies by the intelligent action of the human will—an historical force to which he does not do justice, apparently because he fancied it incompatible with strict causal sequence. The value of his work does not lie in the philosophical principles which he applied. Nor was it a useful contribution to history; of him it has been said, as of Bossuet, that facts bent like grass under his feet. [Footnote: Jouffroy, Melanges, p. 81.] But it was a notable attempt to do for human phenomena what Leibnitz in his Theodicy sought to do for the cosmos, and it pointed the way to the rationalistic philosophies of history which were to be a feature of the speculations of the following century.

Herder limited his historical survey to the sixteenth century. Some have suggested [Footnote: Javary, De l'idee de progres, p. 69.] that if he had gone further, he might have recognized the potential for societies to be deliberately transformed by the conscious actions of individuals—an historical force that he seems to overlook, most likely because he believed it clashed with strict cause-and-effect relationships. The value of his work isn’t in the philosophical principles he applied. It also didn’t make a significant contribution to history; people have noted that, like Bossuet, he treated facts as pliable. [Footnote: Jouffroy, Melanges, p. 81.] However, it was a significant attempt to address human phenomena similarly to how Leibnitz tried to address the cosmos in his Theodicy, paving the way for the rationalistic philosophies of history that would characterize the following century’s speculations.

2.

2.

The short essay of Kant, which he clumsily called the Idea of a Universal History on a Cosmopolitical Plan, [Footnote: 1784. This work of Kant was translated by De Quincey (Works, vol. ix. 428 sqq., ed. Masson), who is responsible for cosmopolitical as the rendering of weltburgerlich.] approaches the problems raised by the history of civilisation from a new point of view.

The short essay by Kant, awkwardly titled the Idea of a Universal History on a Cosmopolitical Plan, [Footnote: 1784. This work by Kant was translated by De Quincey (Works, vol. ix. 428 sqq., ed. Masson), who is responsible for using cosmopolitical as the translation of weltburgerlich.] looks at the issues brought up by the history of civilization from a fresh perspective.

He starts with the principle of invariable law. On any theory of free will, he says, human actions are as completely under the control of universal-laws of nature as any other physical phenomena. This is illustrated by statistics. Registers of births, deaths, and marriages show that these events occur with as much conformity to laws of nature as the oscillations of the weather.

He begins with the principle of unchanging law. According to any theory of free will, he argues, human actions are just as fully governed by the universal laws of nature as any other physical phenomena. This is demonstrated by statistics. Records of births, deaths, and marriages reveal that these events happen with as much adherence to the laws of nature as the fluctuations in the weather.

It is the same with the great sequence of historical events. Taken alone and individually, they seem incoherent and lawless; but viewed in their connection, as due to the action not of individuals but of the human species, they do not fail to reveal "a regular stream of tendency." Pursuing their own often contradictory purposes, individual nations and individual men are unconsciously promoting a process to which if they perceived it they would pay little regard.

It's the same with the significant flow of historical events. When looked at alone and individually, they appear random and chaotic; however, when seen in context, as a result of the actions of not just individuals but of humanity as a whole, they clearly show "a regular stream of tendency." While following their own often conflicting goals, individual nations and people are unknowingly advancing a process that, if they recognized it, they would likely overlook.

Individual men do not obey a law. They do not obey the laws of instinct like animals, nor do they obey, as rational citizens of the world would do, the laws of a preconcerted plan. If we look at the stage of history we see scattered and occasional indications of wisdom, but the general sum of men's actions is "a web of folly, childish vanity, and often even of the idlest wickedness and spirit of destruction."

Individual men don't follow a law. They don’t follow instinctual rules like animals, nor do they adhere, as rational citizens should, to a established plan. If we examine the course of history, we see random and occasional signs of wisdom, but overall, the actions of men amount to "a web of folly, childish vanity, and often even the most pointless wickedness and spirit of destruction."

The problem for the philosopher is to discover a meaning in this senseless current of human actions, so that the history of creatures who pursue no plan of their own may yet admit of a systematic form. The clew to this form is supplied by the predispositions of human nature.

The challenge for the philosopher is to find meaning in this chaotic flow of human actions, so that the history of beings who have no plan of their own can still take on a structured form. The key to this structure is found in the tendencies of human nature.

I have stated this problem almost in Kant's words, and as he might have stated it if he had not introduced the conception of final causes. His use of the postulate of final causes without justifying it is a defect in his essay. He identifies what he well calls a stream of tendency with "a natural purpose." He makes no attempt to show that the succession of events is such that it cannot be explained without the postulate of a purpose. His solution of the problem is governed by this conception of finality, and by the unwarranted assumption that nature does nothing in vain.

I have described this issue almost in Kant's words, and as he might have articulated it if he hadn’t brought in the idea of final causes. His use of the postulate of final causes without any justification is a flaw in his essay. He equates what he appropriately calls a stream of tendency with "a natural purpose." He doesn’t attempt to demonstrate that the sequence of events is such that it can't be explained without assuming a purpose. His solution to the problem is influenced by this idea of finality and by the baseless assumption that nature does nothing without reason.

He lays down that all the tendencies to which any creature is predisposed by its nature must in the end be developed perfectly and agreeably to their final purpose. Those predispositions in man which serve the use of his reason are therefore destined to be fully developed. This destiny, however, cannot be realised in the individual; it can only be realised in the species. For reason works tentatively, by progress and regress. Each man would require an inordinate length of time to make a perfect use of his natural tendencies. Therefore, as life is short, an incalculable series of generations is needed.

He states that all the natural tendencies any creature is born with must ultimately be developed fully and in line with their intended purpose. The predispositions in humans that support their reasoning are meant to be fully realized. However, this doesn't happen in just one individual; it happens across the entire species. Reason develops gradually, through trial and error. Each person would need an excessive amount of time to use their natural tendencies perfectly. So, since life is short, it takes countless generations to achieve this.

The means which nature employs to develop these tendencies is the antagonism which in man's social state exists between his gregarious and his antigregarious tendencies. His antigregarious nature expresses itself in the desire to force all things to comply to his own humour. Hence ambition, love of honour, avarice. These were necessary to raise mankind from the savage to the civilised state. But for these antisocial propensities men would be gentle as sheep, and "an Arcadian life would arise, of perfect harmony and mutual love, such as must suffocate and stifle all talents in their very germs." Nature, knowing better than man what is good for the species, ordains discord. She is to be thanked for competition and enmity, and for the thirst of power and wealth. For without these the final purpose of realising man's rational nature would remain unfulfilled. This is Kant's answer to Rousseau.

The way nature develops these tendencies is through the conflict that exists in human society between our social instincts and our individualistic instincts. Our individualistic nature shows itself in the desire to make everything conform to our own preferences. This leads to ambition, a desire for honor, and greed. These traits were essential for elevating humanity from a savage state to a civilized one. Without these antisocial instincts, people would be as gentle as sheep, and a perfect Arcadian life would emerge, filled with harmony and mutual love, which would suffocate and stifle all talents in their infancy. Nature, knowing better than humans what benefits the species, introduces discord. We should be grateful for competition and rivalry, as well as the desire for power and wealth. Without these, the ultimate goal of realizing humanity's rational nature would remain unachieved. This is Kant's response to Rousseau.

The full realisation of man's rational nature is possible only in a "universal civil society" founded on political justice. The establishment of such a society is the highest problem for the human species. Kant contemplates, as the political goal, a confederation of states in which the utmost possible freedom shall be united with the most rigorous determination of the boundaries of freedom.

The complete recognition of humanity's rational nature can only happen in a "global civil society" built on political justice. Creating such a society is the greatest challenge for humanity. Kant envisions, as the political aim, a coalition of states where maximum freedom is combined with strict limits on that freedom.

Is it reasonable to suppose that a universal or cosmopolitical society of this kind will come into being; and if so, how will it be brought about? Political changes in the relations of states are generally produced by war. Wars are tentative endeavours to bring about new relations and to form new political bodies. Are combinations and recombinations to continue until by pure chance some rational self-supporting system emerges? Or is it possible that no such condition of society may ever arrive, and that ultimately all progress may be overwhelmed by a hell of evils? Or, finally, is Nature pursuing her regular course of raising the species by its own spontaneous efforts and developing, in the apparently wild succession of events, man's originally implanted tendencies?

Is it reasonable to think that a universal or global society like this will emerge, and if so, how will it happen? Political changes in the relationships between states are usually caused by war. Wars are attempts to create new relationships and form new political entities. Will combinations and recombinations keep happening until, by sheer luck, some rational and self-sustaining system appears? Or could it be that such a condition for society may never happen, and that eventually, all progress could be overwhelmed by a nightmare of evils? Or, finally, is Nature following her normal path of advancing the species through its own spontaneous efforts, developing in the seemingly chaotic flow of events the tendencies originally planted in humans?

Kant accepts the last alternative on the ground that it is not reasonable to assume a final purpose in particular natural processes and at the same time to assume that there is no final purpose in the whole. Thus his theory of Progress depends on the hypothesis of final causes.

Kant accepts the last option because it's not logical to believe that individual natural processes have a final purpose while also believing that the whole has no final purpose. Therefore, his theory of Progress relies on the idea of final causes.

It follows that to trace the history of mankind is equivalent to unravelling a hidden plan of Nature for accomplishing a perfect civil constitution for a universal society; since a universal society is the sole state in which the tendencies of human nature can be fully developed. We cannot determine the orbit of the development, because the whole period is so vast and only a small fraction is known to us, but this is enough to show that there is a definite course.

It follows that tracing the history of humanity is the same as uncovering a hidden design of Nature aimed at creating a perfect civil structure for a global society; since a global society is the only environment where the tendencies of human nature can fully grow. We can't pinpoint the exact path of this development because the entire timeline is so extensive and only a small part is known to us, but that's enough to demonstrate that there is a clear direction.

Kant thinks that such a "cosmopolitical" history, as he calls it, is possible, and that if it were written it would give us a clew opening up "a consolatory prospect into futurity, in which at a remote distance we shall discover the human species seated upon an eminence won by infinite toil, where all the germs are unfolded which nature has implanted and its own destination upon this earth accomplished."

Kant believes that a "cosmopolitical" history, as he refers to it, is achievable, and that if it were written, it would provide us with a clue revealing "a comforting vision of the future, in which we will eventually see humanity positioned on a peak earned through immense effort, where all the potential that nature has instilled will be realized and its purpose on this planet fulfilled."

3.

3.

But to see the full bearing of Kant's discussion we must understand its connection with his ethics. For his ethical theory is the foundation and the motive of his speculation on Progress. The progress on which he lays stress is moral amelioration; he refers little to scientific or material progress. For him morality was an absolute obligation founded in the nature of reason. Such an obligation presupposes an end to be attained, and this end is a reign of reason under which all men obeying the moral law mutually treat each other as ends in themselves. Such an ideal state must be regarded as possible, because it is a necessary postulate of reason. From this point of view it may be seen that Kant's speculation on universal history is really a discussion whether the ideal state, which is required as a subjective postulate in the interest of ethics, is likely to be realised objectively.

But to fully grasp Kant's discussion, we need to understand how it connects to his ethics. His ethical theory serves as the foundation and motivation for his thoughts on Progress. The progress he emphasizes is moral improvement; he hardly mentions scientific or material progress. For him, morality is an absolute obligation based on the nature of reason. Such an obligation assumes a goal to be achieved, and this goal is a society governed by reason, where all individuals, obeying the moral law, treat each other as ends in themselves. This ideal state must be seen as possible because it's a necessary assumption of reason. From this perspective, we can understand that Kant's thoughts on universal history are essentially a discussion about whether this ideal state, which is needed as a subjective assumption for ethics, is likely to be realized in the real world.

Now, Kant does not assert that because our moral reason must assume the possibility of this hypothetical goal civilisation is therefore moving towards it. That would be a fallacy into which he was incapable of falling. Civilisation is a phenomenon, and anything we know about it can only be inferred from experience. His argument is that there are actual indications of progress in this desirable direction. He pointed to the contemporary growth of civil liberty and religious liberty, and these are conditions of moral improvement. So far his argument coincides in principle with that of French theorists of Progress. But Kant goes on to apply to these data the debatable conception of final causes, and to infer a purpose in the development of humanity. Only this inference is put forward as a hypothesis, not as a dogma.

Now, Kant doesn’t claim that just because our moral reasoning must assume the possibility of this hypothetical goal, civilization is therefore moving towards it. That would be a mistake he would never make. Civilization is a phenomenon, and what we know about it can only come from experience. His argument is that there are real signs of progress in this desirable direction. He pointed to the modern growth of civil liberties and religious freedoms, which are conditions for moral advancement. So far, his argument aligns with that of contemporary French theorists of Progress. But Kant goes on to apply these observations to the debated idea of final causes, suggesting there’s a purpose in humanity’s development. However, this inference is presented as a hypothesis, not as a doctrine.

It is probable that what hindered Kant from broaching his theory of Progress with as much confidence as Condorcet was his perception that nothing could be decisively affirmed about the course of civilisation until the laws of its movement had been discovered. He saw that this was a matter for scientific investigation. He says expressly that the laws are not yet known, and suggests that some future genius may do for social phenomena what Kepler and Newton did for the heavenly bodies. As we shall see, this is precisely what some of the leading French thinkers of the next generation will attempt to do.

It’s likely that what held Kant back from discussing his theory of Progress with the same confidence as Condorcet was his belief that nothing could be definitively stated about the path of civilization until the laws governing its progress were uncovered. He recognized that this needed to be studied scientifically. He clearly states that the laws are not yet understood and implies that some future genius might achieve for social phenomena what Kepler and Newton achieved for celestial bodies. As we will explore, this is exactly what some of the prominent French thinkers of the next generation will try to do.

But cautiously though he framed the hypothesis Kant evidently considered Progress probable. He recognised that the most difficult obstacle to the moral advance of man lies in war and the burdens which the possibility of war imposes. And he spent much thought on the means by which war might be abolished. He published a philosophical essay on Perpetual Peace, in which he formulated the articles of an international treaty to secure the disappearance of war. He considered that, while a universal republic would be the positive ideal, we shall probably have to be contented with what he calls a negative substitute, consisting in a federation of peoples bound by a peace-alliance guaranteeing the independence of each member. But to assure the permanence of this system it is essential that each state should have a democratic constitution. For such a constitution is based on individual liberty and civil equality. All these changes should be brought about by legal reforms; revolutions—he was writing in 1795—-cannot be justified.

But although he carefully approached the idea, Kant clearly believed that progress was likely. He recognized that the biggest challenge to humanity's moral progress lies in war and the burdens that the threat of war creates. He devoted a lot of thought to ways in which war could be eliminated. He published a philosophical essay on Perpetual Peace, where he outlined the principles of an international treaty aimed at ending war. He thought that, while a universal republic would be the ideal goal, we would likely have to settle for what he referred to as a negative substitute—a federation of nations united by a peace alliance that guarantees the independence of each member. However, to ensure the lasting nature of this system, it's crucial that each state has a democratic constitution. Such a constitution is founded on personal freedom and social equality. All these changes should be achieved through legal reforms; revolutions—he was writing in 1795—cannot be justified.

We see the influence of Rousseau's Social Contract and that of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre, with whose works Kant was acquainted. There can be little doubt that it was the influence of French thought, so powerful in Germany at this period, that turned Kant's mind towards these speculations, which belong to the latest period of his life and form a sort of appendix to his philosophical system. The theory of Progress, the idea of universal reform, the doctrine of political equality—Kant examined all these conceptions and appropriated them to the service of his own highly metaphysical theory of ethics. In this new association their spirit was changed.

We see the influence of Rousseau's Social Contract and that of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre, whose works Kant was familiar with. There's no doubt that the strong impact of French thought in Germany during this time influenced Kant's thinking, leading him to these ideas, which are part of the later phase of his life and act as a sort of addition to his philosophical system. The theory of Progress, the concept of universal reform, and the principle of political equality—Kant explored all these ideas and adapted them to support his own complex metaphysical theory of ethics. In this new context, their essence was transformed.

In France, as we saw, the theory of Progress was generally associated with ethical views which could find a metaphysical basis in the sensationalism of Locke. A moral system which might be built on sensation, as the primary mental fact, was worked out by Helvetius. But the principle that the supreme law of conduct is to obey nature had come down as a practical philosophy from Rabelais and Montaigne through Moliere to the eighteenth century. It was reinforced by the theory of the natural goodness of man. Jansenism had struggled against it and was defeated. After theology it was the turn of metaphysics. Kant's moral imperative marked the next stage in the conflict of the two opposite tendencies which seek natural and ultra-natural sanctions for morality.

In France, as we observed, the idea of Progress was mostly linked to ethical views that found a philosophical foundation in Locke's sensationalism. Helvetius developed a moral system based on sensation as the primary mental experience. However, the principle that the highest law of behavior is to follow nature had been passed down as a practical philosophy from Rabelais and Montaigne through Moliere to the eighteenth century. This was supported by the belief in the natural goodness of humanity. Jansenism had fought against this idea and was ultimately defeated. After theology, metaphysics became the next battleground. Kant's moral imperative represented the next phase in the ongoing struggle between the two opposing forces that seek natural and supernatural justifications for morality.

Hence the idea of progress had a different significance for Kant and for its French exponents, though his particular view of the future possibly in store for the human species coincided in some essential points with theirs. But his theory of life gives a different atmosphere to the idea. In France the atmosphere is emphatically eudaemonic; happiness is the goal. Kant is an uncompromising opponent of eudaemonism. "If we take enjoyment or happiness as the measure, it is easy," he says, "to evaluate life. Its value is less than nothing. For who would begin one's life again in the same conditions, or even in new natural conditions, if one could choose them oneself, but of which enjoyment would be the sole end?"

Therefore, the concept of progress held a different meaning for Kant compared to its French representatives, although his specific view of the future for humanity shared some key points with theirs. However, his theory of life gives a different vibe to the idea. In France, the atmosphere strongly leans towards eudaemonism; happiness is the ultimate goal. Kant stands firmly against eudaemonism. "If we consider enjoyment or happiness as the standard, it's easy," he says, "to assess life. Its value is less than nothing. For who would choose to live their life again under the same conditions, or even under new natural conditions of their own choosing, if the sole purpose was enjoyment?"

There was, in fact, a strongly-marked vein of pessimism in Kant. One of the ablest men of the younger generation who were brought up on his system founded the philosophical pessimism—very different in range and depth from the sentimental pessimism of Rousseau—which was to play a remarkable part in German thought in the nineteenth century. [Footnote: Kant's pessimism has been studied at length by von Hartmann, in Zur Geschichte und Begrundung des Pessimismus (1880).] Schopenhauer's unpleasant conclusion that of all conceivable worlds this is the worst, is one of the speculations for which Kant may be held ultimately responsible. [Footnote: Schopenhauer recognised progress social, economic, and political, but as a fact that contains no guarantee of happiness; on the contrary, the development of the intelligence increases suffering. He ridiculed the optimistic ideals of comfortable, well-regulated states. His views on historical development have been collected by G. Sparlinsky, Schopenhauers Verhaltnis zur Geschichte, in Berner Studien s. Philosophie, Bd. lxxii. (1910).]

There was indeed a strong streak of pessimism in Kant. One of the most capable thinkers of the younger generation raised on his ideas established philosophical pessimism—very different in scope and depth from the sentimental pessimism of Rousseau—which would play a significant role in German thought in the nineteenth century. [Footnote: Kant's pessimism has been extensively studied by von Hartmann, in Zur Geschichte und Begrundung des Pessimismus (1880).] Schopenhauer's uncomfortable conclusion that among all possible worlds, this is the worst, is one of the ideas for which Kant can ultimately be held accountable. [Footnote: Schopenhauer acknowledged social, economic, and political progress, but noted that it offers no guarantee of happiness; in fact, the advancement of intelligence increases suffering. He mocked the optimistic ideals of comfortable, well-ordered societies. His insights on historical development have been compiled by G. Sparlinsky, Schopenhauers Verhaltnis zur Geschichte, in Berner Studien s. Philosophie, Bd. lxxii. (1910).]

4.

4.

Kant's considerations on historical development are an appendix to his philosophy; they are not a necessary part, wrought into the woof of his system. It was otherwise with his successors the Idealists, for whom his system was the point of departure, though they rejected its essential feature, the limitation of human thought. With Fichte and Hegel progressive development was directly deduced from their principles. If their particular interpretations of history have no permanent value, it is significant that, in their ambitious attempts to explain the universe a priori, history was conceived as progressive, and their philosophies did much to reinforce a conception which on very different principles was making its way in the world. But the progress which their systems involved was not bound up with the interest of human happiness, but stood out as a fact which, whether agreeable or not, is a consequence of the nature of thought.

Kant's views on historical development are an add-on to his philosophy; they aren't a necessary part woven into the fabric of his system. This was not the case for his successors, the Idealists, for whom his system was the starting point, even though they rejected its key aspect—the limitation of human thought. With Fichte and Hegel, progressive development was directly derived from their principles. While their specific interpretations of history may not have lasting value, it's important to note that in their ambitious attempts to explain the universe a priori, they saw history as progressive, and their philosophies contributed significantly to a view that was gaining ground based on very different principles. However, the progress these systems implied was not tied to human happiness; instead, it was simply a fact that, whether welcomed or not, stemmed from the nature of thought.

The process of the universe, as it appeared to Fichte, [Footnote: Fichte's philosophy of history will be found in Die Grundzuge des gegenwartigen Zeitalters (1806), lectures which he delivered at Berlin in 1804-5.] tends to a full realisation of "freedom"; that is its end and goal, but a goal that always recedes. It can never be reached; for its full attainment would mean the complete suppression of Nature. The process of the world, therefore, consists in an indefinite approximation to an unattainable ideal: freedom is being perpetually realised more and more; and the world, as it ascends in this direction, becomes more and more a realm of reason.

The way Fichte viewed the universe, [Footnote: Fichte's philosophy of history is discussed in Die Grundzuge des gegenwartigen Zeitalters (1806), lectures he delivered in Berlin in 1804-5.] is that it aims for a complete realization of "freedom"; that is its ultimate goal, but a goal that always seems just out of reach. It can never be fully achieved because doing so would mean completely overriding Nature. So, the process of the world is about getting closer and closer to an ideal that can never be attained: freedom is continually becoming more realized; and as the world moves in this direction, it increasingly becomes a realm of reason.

What Fichte means by freedom may be best explained by its opposition to instinct. A man acting instinctively may be acting quite reasonably, in a way which any one fully conscious of all the implications and consequences of the action would judge to be reasonable. But in order that his actions should be free he must himself be fully conscious of all those implications and consequences.

What Fichte means by freedom is best understood in relation to instinct. A person acting on instinct can be acting quite reasonably, in a way that someone who is fully aware of all the implications and consequences of the action would see as reasonable. However, for his actions to be considered free, he must be fully aware of all those implications and consequences himself.

It follows that the end of mankind upon earth is to reach a state in which all the relations of life shall be ordered according to reason, not instinctively but with full consciousness and deliberate purpose. This end should govern the ethical rules of conduct, and it determines the necessary stages of history.

It follows that the goal of humanity on earth is to achieve a state where all aspects of life are organized according to reason, not just instinctively, but with full awareness and intentionality. This goal should guide our ethical standards and shapes the essential phases of history.

It gives us at once two main periods, the earliest and the latest: the earliest, in which men act reasonably by instinct, and the latest, in which they are conscious of reason and try to realise it fully. But before reaching this final stage they must pass through an epoch in which reason is conscious of itself, but not regnant. And to reach this they must have emancipated themselves from instinct, and this process of emancipation means a fourth epoch. But they could not have wanted to emancipate themselves unless they had felt instinct as a servitude imposed by an external authority, and therefore we have to distinguish yet another epoch wherein reason is expressed in authoritarian institutions to which men blindly submit. In this way Fichte deduces five historical epochs: two in which progress is blind, two in which it is free, and an intermediate in which it is struggling to consciousness. [Footnote: First Epoch: that of instinctive reason; the age of innocence. Second: that of authoritarian reason. Third: that of enfranchisement; the age of scepticism and unregulated liberty. Fourth: that of conscious reason, as science. Fifth: that of regnant reason, as art.] But there are no locked gates between these periods; they overlap and mingle; each may have some of the characteristics of another; and in each there is a vanguard leading the way and a rearguard lagging behind.

It gives us two main time periods right away: the earliest, where people act reasonably out of instinct, and the latest, where they are aware of reason and strive to fully realize it. However, before reaching this final stage, they must go through a time when reason is aware of itself but not in control. To reach this point, they must have freed themselves from instinct, and this freeing process represents a fourth period. But they wouldn't have wanted to free themselves unless they had experienced instinct as a sort of bondage imposed by an outside authority, which means we need to identify another period where reason is expressed through authoritative institutions that people follow without question. In this way, Fichte outlines five historical periods: two where progress is blind, two where it is free, and one in between where it struggles for awareness. [Footnote: First Epoch: that of instinctive reason; the age of innocence. Second: that of authoritarian reason. Third: that of enfranchisement; the age of skepticism and unregulated freedom. Fourth: that of conscious reason, as science. Fifth: that of dominant reason, as art.] But there are no locked gates between these periods; they overlap and blend; each may share some characteristics of another; and in each, there is a leading edge pushing forward and a trailing edge falling behind.

At present (1804) we are in the third age; we have broken with authority, but do not yet possess a clear and disciplined knowledge of reason. [Footnote: Three years later, however, Fichte maintained in his patriotic Discourses to the German Nation (1807) that in 1804 man had crossed the threshold of the fourth epoch. He asserted that the progress of "culture" and science will depend henceforward chiefly on Germany.] Fichte has deduced this scheme purely a priori without any reference to actual experience. "The philosopher," he says, "follows the a priori thread of the world-plan which is clear to him without any history; and if he makes use of history, it is not to prove anything, since his theses are already proved independently of all history."

Right now (1804), we are in the third age; we've broken away from authority, but we still don't have a clear and organized understanding of reason. [Footnote: However, three years later, Fichte argued in his patriotic Discourses to the German Nation (1807) that in 1804, humanity had entered the fourth epoch. He claimed that the advancement of "culture" and science will now mainly depend on Germany.] Fichte developed this framework purely a priori without considering actual experience. "The philosopher," he states, "follows the a priori thread of the world-plan, which is clear to him without any historical reference; and if he uses history, it’s not to prove anything since his arguments are already validated independently of all history."

Historical development is thus presented as a necessary progress towards a goal which is known but cannot be reached. And this fact as to the destiny of the race constitutes the basis of morality, of which the fundamental law is to act in such a way as to promote the free realisation of reason upon earth. It has been claimed by a recent critic that Fichte was the first modern philosopher to humanise morals. He completely rejected the individualistic conception which underlay Kantian as well as Christian ethics. He asserted that the true motive of morality is not the salvation of the individual man but the Progress of humanity. In fact, with Fichte Progress is the principle of ethics. That the Christian ideal of ascetic saintliness detached from society has no moral value is a plain corollary from the idea of earthly Progress. [Footnote: X. Leon, La Philosophie de Fichte (1902), pp. 477-9.]

Historical development is seen as a necessary journey towards a goal that is understood but ultimately unreachable. This understanding of humanity's destiny forms the foundation of morality, which fundamentally means acting in ways that encourage the true realization of reason on Earth. A recent critic has argued that Fichte was the first modern philosopher to make morals more human. He completely dismissed the individualistic view that underpinned both Kantian and Christian ethics. He claimed that the true motive of morality isn't the salvation of the individual but rather the progression of humanity. For Fichte, Progress is the core principle of ethics. It's clear that the Christian ideal of an ascetic life, disconnected from society, lacks moral worth, following the concept of earthly Progress. [Footnote: X. Leon, La Philosophie de Fichte (1902), pp. 477-9.]

One other point in Fichte's survey of history deserves notice—the social role of the savant. It is the function of the savant to discover the truths which are a condition of moral progress; he may be said to incarnate reason in the world. We shall see how this idea played a prominent part in the social schemes of Saint-Simon and Comte. [Footnote: Fichte, Ueber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten (1794).]

One more point in Fichte's overview of history is worth mentioning—the social role of the scholar. The scholar's job is to uncover the truths that are essential for moral progress; they can be seen as embodying reason in the world. We'll see how this idea was significant in the social theories of Saint-Simon and Comte. [Footnote: Fichte, Ueber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten (1794).]

5.

5.

Hegel's philosophy of history is better known than Fichte's. Like Fichte, he deduced the phases a priori from his metaphysical principles, but he condescended to review in some detail the actual phenomena. He conceived the final cause of the world as Spirit's consciousness of its own freedom. The ambiguous term "freedom" is virtually equivalent to self-consciousness, and Hegel defines Universal History as the description of the process by which Spirit or God comes to the consciousness of its own meaning. This freedom does not mean that Spirit could choose at any moment to develop in a different way; its actual development is necessary and is the embodiment of reason. Freedom consists in fully recognising the fact.

Hegel's philosophy of history is more well-known than Fichte's. Like Fichte, he outlined the stages based on his metaphysical principles, but he took the time to look at the actual events in detail. He viewed the ultimate purpose of the world as the Spirit's awareness of its own freedom. The term "freedom" is almost synonymous with self-awareness, and Hegel defines Universal History as the account of how Spirit or God becomes aware of its own significance. This freedom doesn't mean that Spirit can choose to develop differently at any moment; its actual development is necessary and represents reason. Freedom is about fully acknowledging that fact.

Of the particular features which distinguish Hegel's treatment, the first is that he identifies "history" with political history, the development of the state. Art, religion, philosophy, the creations of social man, belong to a different and higher stage of Spirit's self-revelation. [Footnote: The three phases of Spirit are (1) subjective; (2) objective; (3) absolute. Psychology, e.g., is included in (1), law and history in (2), religion in (3).] In the second place, Hegel ignores the primitive prehistoric ages of man, and sets the beginning of his development in the fully-grown civilisation of China. He conceives the Spirit as continually moving from one nation to another in order to realise the successive stages of its self-consciousness: from China to India, from India to the kingdoms of Western Asia; then from the Orient to Greece, then to Rome, and finally to the Germanic world. In the East men knew only that ONE is free, the political characteristic was despotism; in Greece and Rome they knew that SOME are free, and the political forms were aristocracy and democracy; in the modern world they know that ALL are free, and the political form is monarchy. The first period, he compared to childhood, the second to youth (Greece) and manhood (Rome), the third to old age, old but not feeble. The third, which includes the medieval and modern history of Europe, designated by Hegel as the Germanic world—for "the German spirit is the spirit of the modern world"—is also the final period. In it God realises his freedom completely in history, just as in Hegel's own absolute philosophy, which is final, God has completely understood his own nature.

Of the specific features that set Hegel's approach apart, the first is that he equates "history" with political history, focusing on the development of the state. Art, religion, and philosophy, which are products of social life, exist at a different and higher stage of Spirit's self-revelation. [Footnote: The three phases of Spirit are (1) subjective; (2) objective; (3) absolute. Psychology, for example, falls under (1), law and history under (2), and religion under (3).] Additionally, Hegel overlooks the primitive prehistoric periods of humanity, beginning his analysis with the fully developed civilization of China. He views the Spirit as continuously moving from one nation to another to realize the successive stages of its self-awareness: from China to India, from India to the kingdoms of Western Asia, then from the East to Greece, followed by Rome, and finally to the Germanic world. In the East, people recognized only that ONE is free, characterized by despotism; in Greece and Rome, they acknowledged that SOME are free, with political forms of aristocracy and democracy; in the modern world, they understand that ALL are free, with monarchy as the political structure. He likens the first period to childhood, the second to youth (Greece) and manhood (Rome), and the third to old age—old, but not frail. The third phase, which includes the medieval and modern history of Europe, is designated by Hegel as the Germanic world—because "the German spirit is the spirit of the modern world"—and it represents the final period. In this phase, God realizes His freedom fully in history, just as in Hegel's own absolute philosophy, which is final, God has fully comprehended His own nature.

And here is the most striking difference between the theories of Fichte and Hegel. Both saw the goal of human development in the realisation of "freedom," but, while with Fichte the development never ends as the goal is unattainable, with Hegel the development is already complete, the goal is not only attainable but has now been attained. Thus Hegel's is what we may call a closed system. History has been progressive, but no path is left open for further advance. Hegel views this conclusion of development with perfect complacency. To most minds that are not intoxicated with the Absolute it will seem that, if the present is the final state to which the evolution of Spirit has conducted, the result is singularly inadequate to the gigantic process. But his system is eminently inhuman. The happiness or misery of individuals is a matter of supreme indifference to the Absolute, which, in order to realise itself in time, ruthlessly sacrifices sentient beings.

And here’s the biggest difference between Fichte and Hegel's theories. Both believed that the aim of human development is to achieve "freedom," but while for Fichte this development never truly ends since the goal is unattainable, Hegel thinks that development is already complete, and the goal has not only been achieved but is also now a reality. So, Hegel’s viewpoint could be seen as a closed system. History has progressed, but there’s no path left for further advancement. Hegel looks at this conclusion of development with total assurance. To most people who aren’t caught up in the concept of the Absolute, it may seem that if the present is the final state that the evolution of Spirit has reached, then the outcome is significantly lacking compared to the massive process that led to it. However, his system is decidedly inhumane. The happiness or suffering of individuals doesn’t matter at all to the Absolute, which, to realize itself over time, mercilessly sacrifices living beings.

The spirit of Hegel's philosophy, in its bearing on social life, was thus antagonistic to Progress as a practical doctrine. Progress there had been, but Progress had done its work; the Prussian monarchical state was the last word in history. Kant's cosmopolitical plan, the liberalism and individualism which were implicit in his thought, the democracies which he contemplated in the future, are all cast aside as a misconception. Once the needs of the Absolute Spirit have been satisfied, when it has seen its full power and splendour revealed in the Hegelian philosophy, the world is as good as it can be. Social amelioration does not matter, nor the moral improvement of men, nor the increase of their control over physical forces.

The essence of Hegel's philosophy, when it comes to social life, was fundamentally opposed to the idea of Progress as a practical principle. Progress had occurred, but it had fulfilled its purpose; the Prussian monarchy was seen as the ultimate point in history. Kant's vision of a cosmopolitan world, the liberalism and individualism that were part of his ideas, and the democracies he envisioned for the future are all dismissed as misunderstandings. Once the needs of the Absolute Spirit have been met, and its full power and glory have been unveiled through Hegelian philosophy, the world is as good as it can possibly be. Social improvement, the moral betterment of people, and the increase of their control over nature are of no concern.

6.

6.

The other great representative of German idealism, who took his departure from Kant, also saw in history a progressive revelation of divine reason. But it was the processes of nature, not the career of humanity, that absorbed the best energies of Schelling, and the elaboration of a philosophical idea of organic evolution was the prominent feature of his speculation. His influence—and it was wide, reaching even scientific biologists—lay chiefly in diffusing this idea, and he thus contributed to the formation of a theory which was afterwards to place the idea of Progress on a more imposing base. [Footnote: Schelling's views notoriously varied at various stages of his career. In his System of Transcendental Idealism (1800) he distinguished three historical periods, in the first of which the Absolute reveals itself as Fate, in the second as Nature, in the third as Providence, and asserted that we are still living in the second, which began with the expansion of Rome (Werke, i. 3, p. 603). In this context he says that the conception of an infinite "progressivity" is included in the conception of "history," but adds that the perfectibility of the race cannot be directly inferred. For it may be said that man has no proper history but turns round on a wheel of Ixion. The difficulty of establishing the fact of Progress from the course of events lies in discovering a criterion. Schelling rejects the criterion of moral improvement and that of advance in science and arts as unpractical or misleading. But if we see the sole object of history in a gradual realisation of the ideal state, we have a measure of Progress which can be applied; though it cannot be proved either by theory or by experience that the goal will be attained. This must remain an article of faith (ib. 592 sqq.).]

The other major figure of German idealism, who built upon Kant's ideas, also viewed history as a progressive revelation of divine reason. However, for Schelling, it was the processes of nature rather than the journey of humanity that captured his deepest attention, and the development of a philosophical concept of organic evolution was the key aspect of his thinking. His influence—wide-ranging and even impacting scientific biologists—was primarily in spreading this idea, contributing to the creation of a theory that would later provide a stronger foundation for the idea of Progress. [Footnote: Schelling's views notoriously changed throughout his career. In his System of Transcendental Idealism (1800), he identified three historical periods: in the first, the Absolute reveals itself as Fate; in the second, as Nature; and in the third, as Providence. He claimed that we are still in the second period, which began with the rise of Rome (Werke, i. 3, p. 603). He mentions that the idea of infinite "progressivity" is part of the concept of "history," but he also points out that the perfectibility of humanity cannot be directly assumed. It could be argued that humanity has no true history and simply goes around in a cycle like Ixion. The challenge of establishing the fact of Progress from historical events lies in finding a standard. Schelling dismisses moral improvement and progress in science and arts as impractical or misleading criteria. However, if we consider the primary goal of history to be the gradual realization of an ideal state, we have a measure of Progress that can be applied, even though it can't be proven by theory or experience that the goal will be reached. This must remain a matter of faith (ib. 592 sqq.).]

Schelling influenced, among others, his contemporary Krause, a less familiar name, who worked out a philosophy of history in which this idea is fundamental. Krause conceived history, which is the expression of the Absolute, as the development of life; society as an organism; and social growth as a process which can be deduced from abstract biological principles.

Schelling influenced, among others, his contemporary Krause, a less well-known figure, who developed a philosophy of history where this idea is central. Krause viewed history, as the expression of the Absolute, as the evolution of life; he saw society as an organism; and he regarded social progress as a process that can be derived from basic biological principles.

[Footnote: Krause divided man's earthly career into three Ages—infancy, growth, and maturity. The second of these falls into three periods characterised by (1) polytheism, (2) monotheism (Middle Ages), (3) scepticism and liberty, and we are now in the third of these periods. The third Age will witness the union of humanity in a single social organism, and the universal acceptance of "panentheism" (the doctrine of the unity of all in God), which is the principle of Krause's philosophy and religion. But though this will be the final stage on the earth, Krause contemplates an ulterior career of humanity in other solar systems.

[Footnote: Krause divided humanity's time on earth into three Ages—infancy, growth, and maturity. The second of these is split into three periods characterized by (1) polytheism, (2) monotheism (the Middle Ages), and (3) skepticism and freedom, and we are currently in the third period. The third Age will see humanity united as a single social organism, with the universal acceptance of "panentheism" (the belief in the unity of all within God), which is the foundation of Krause's philosophy and religion. However, while this will be the final stage on earth, Krause envisions a future journey for humanity in other solar systems.]

Krause never attracted attention in England, but he exerted some influence in France and Spain, and especially in Belgium, notwithstanding the grotesque jargon in which he obscured his thoughts. See Flint, Philosophy of History, pp. 474-5. Flint's account of his speculations is indulgent. The main ideas of his philosophy of history will be found in the Introduction a la philosophie (ed. 2, 1880) of G. Tiberghien, a Belgian disciple.]

Krause never drew attention in England, but he had some impact in France and Spain, particularly in Belgium, despite the bizarre language he used to cloud his ideas. See Flint, Philosophy of History, pp. 474-5. Flint's take on his theories is quite lenient. The key concepts of his philosophy of history can be found in the Introduction à la philosophie (2nd ed., 1880) by G. Tiberghien, a Belgian follower.

All these transcendent speculations had this in common that they pretended to discover the necessary course of human history on metaphysical principles, independent of experience. But it has been rightly doubted whether this alleged independence was genuine. We may question whether any of them would have produced the same sequence of periods of history, if the actual facts of history had been to them a sealed book. Indeed we may be sure that they were surreptitiously and subconsciously using experience as a guide, while they imagined that abstract principles were entirely responsible for their conclusions. And this is equivalent to saying that their ideas of progressive movement were really derived from that idea of Progress which the French thinkers of the eighteenth century had attempted to base on experience.

All these lofty ideas had one thing in common: they claimed to figure out the necessary path of human history based on metaphysical principles, separate from actual experience. However, it has been rightly questioned whether this claimed independence was genuine. We can wonder if any of them would have arrived at the same series of historical periods if the actual facts of history had been completely unknown to them. In fact, we can be sure they were secretly and subconsciously using their experiences as a guide, all while believing that abstract principles were solely responsible for their conclusions. This essentially means that their concepts of progress were actually derived from the idea of Progress that French thinkers in the eighteenth century tried to base on experience.

The influence, direct and indirect, of these German philosophers reached far beyond the narrow circle of the bacchants or even the wandbearers of idealism. They did much to establish the notion of progressive development as a category of thought, almost as familiar and indispensable as that of cause and effect. They helped to diffuse the idea of "an increasing purpose" in history. Augustine or Bossuet might indeed have spoken of an increasing purpose, but the "purpose" of their speculations was subsidiary to a future life. The purpose of the German idealists could be fulfilled in earthly conditions and required no theory of personal immortality.

The influence, both direct and indirect, of these German philosophers extended well beyond the limited circle of the bacchants or even the followers of idealism. They played a significant role in establishing the idea of progressive development as a key concept, almost as familiar and essential as cause and effect. They contributed to spreading the notion of "an increasing purpose" in history. Augustine or Bossuet might have referred to an increasing purpose, but the "purpose" in their discussions was secondary to an afterlife. The goal of the German idealists could be achieved in this world and didn't rely on a theory of personal immortality.

This atmosphere of thought affected even intelligent reactionaries who wrote in the interest of orthodox Christianity and the Catholic Church. Progressive development is admitted in the lectures on the Philosophy of History of Friedrich von Schlegel. [Footnote: Translated into English in 2 vols., 1835.] He denounced Condorcet, and opposed to perfectibility the corruptible nature of man. But he asserted that the philosophy of history is to be found in "the principles of social progress." [Footnote: Op. cit. ii, p. 194, sqq.] These principles are three: the hidden ways of Providence emancipating the human race; the freewill of man; and the power which God permits to the agents of evil,—principles which Bossuet could endorse, but the novelty is that here they are arrayed as forces of Progress. In fact, the point of von Schlegel's pretentious, unilluminating book is to rehabilitate Christianity by making it the key to that new conception of life which had taken shape among the enemies of the Church.

This environment of thought influenced even smart reactionaries who wrote in support of orthodox Christianity and the Catholic Church. Progressive development is acknowledged in the lectures on the Philosophy of History by Friedrich von Schlegel. [Footnote: Translated into English in 2 vols., 1835.] He criticized Condorcet and countered the idea of human perfectibility with the corruptible nature of humanity. However, he claimed that the philosophy of history lies in "the principles of social progress." [Footnote: Op. cit. ii, p. 194, sqq.] These principles are three: the hidden paths of Providence freeing the human race; the free will of humanity; and the power that God allows to the agents of evil—principles that Bossuet could support, but the new aspect is that they are presented as forces of Progress. In fact, the main idea of von Schlegel's showy, unclear book is to restore Christianity by positioning it as the key to that new understanding of life that had emerged among the Church's opponents.

7.

7.

As biological development was one of the constant preoccupations of Goethe, whose doctrine of metamorphosis and "types" helped to prepare the way for the evolutionary hypothesis, we might have expected to find him interested in theories of social progress, in which theories of biological development find a logical extension. But the French speculations on Progress did not touch his imagination; they left him cool and sceptical. Towards the end of his life, in conversation with Eckermann, he made some remarks which indicate his attitude. [Footnote: Gesprache mit Goethe, 23 Oktober 1828.] "'The world will not reach its goal so quickly as we think and wish. The retarding demons are always there, intervening and resisting at every point, so that, though there is an advance on the whole, it is very slow. Live longer and you will find that I am right.'

As biological development was one of Goethe's constant concerns, his ideas about metamorphosis and "types" helped lay the groundwork for evolutionary theory. We might expect him to be interested in social progress theories, which logically extend from biological development. However, the French ideas about Progress did not captivate him; he remained indifferent and skeptical. Towards the end of his life, in talks with Eckermann, he shared some thoughts that reveal his perspective. [Footnote: Gesprache mit Goethe, 23 Oktober 1828.] "'The world won't reach its goals as quickly as we think and hope. The delaying forces are always present, interfering and resisting at every turn, so that, while there is overall progress, it is really slow. Live longer and you will see that I am right.'

"'The development of humanity,' said Eckermann, 'appears to be a matter of thousands of years.'

"'The development of humanity,' said Eckermann, 'seems to take thousands of years.'"

"'Who knows?' Goethe replied, 'perhaps of millions. But let humanity last as long as it will, there will always be hindrances in its way, and all kinds of distress, to make it develop its powers. Men will become more clever and discerning, but not better nor happier nor more energetic, at least except for limited periods. I see the time coming when God will take no more pleasure in the race, and must again proceed to a rejuvenated creation. I am sure that this will happen and that the time and hour in the distant future are already fixed for the beginning of this epoch of rejuvenation. But that time is certainly a long way off, and we can still for thousands and thousands of years enjoy ourselves on this dear old playing-ground, just as it is.'"

"'Who knows?' Goethe replied, 'maybe millions. But no matter how long humanity lasts, there will always be obstacles in its path and all sorts of suffering to push it to develop its abilities. People will become more intelligent and perceptive, but not necessarily better, happier, or more energetic, at least not for long stretches. I foresee a time when God will no longer find joy in humanity and will need to start over with a new creation. I'm certain this will happen, and the time for this new beginning is already set for some distant point in the future. But that time is definitely far off, and we can still enjoy ourselves for thousands and thousands of years in this familiar playground, just the way it is.'"

That is at once a plain rejection of perfectibility, and an opinion that intellectual development is no highroad to the gates of a golden city.

That is both a clear rejection of perfection and a belief that intellectual growth isn't a straightforward path to success.





CHAPTER XIV. CURRENTS OF THOUGHT IN FRANCE AFTER THE REVOLUTION

1.

The failure of the Revolution to fulfil the visionary hopes which had dazzled France for a brief period—a failure intensified by the horrors that had attended the experiment—was followed by a reaction against the philosophical doctrines and tendencies which had inspired its leaders. Forces, which the eighteenth century had underrated or endeavoured to suppress, emerged in a new shape, and it seemed for a while as if the new century might definitely turn its back on its predecessor. There was an intellectual rehabilitation of Catholicism, which will always be associated with the names of four thinkers of exceptional talent, Chateaubriand, De Maistre, Bonald, and Lamennais.

The failure of the Revolution to meet the ambitious dreams that briefly captivated France—a failure made worse by the atrocities that accompanied the experiment—led to a backlash against the philosophical ideas and movements that had inspired its leaders. Forces that the eighteenth century had underestimated or tried to suppress reemerged in a new form, and for a time, it seemed like the new century might completely reject the previous one. There was an intellectual revival of Catholicism, which will always be linked to four exceptionally talented thinkers: Chateaubriand, De Maistre, Bonald, and Lamennais.

But the outstanding fame of these great reactionaries must not mislead us into exaggerating the reach of this reaction. The spirit and tendencies of the past century still persisted in the circles which were most permanently influential. Many eminent savants who had been imbued with the ideas of Condillac and Helvetius, and had taken part in the Revolution and survived it, were active under the Empire and the restored Monarchy, still true to the spirit of their masters, and commanding influence by the value of their scientific work. M. Picavet's laborious researches into the activities of this school of thinkers has helped us to understand the transition from the age of Condorcet to the age of Comte. The two central figures are Cabanis, the friend of Condorcet, [Footnote: He has already claimed our notice, above, p. 215.] and Destutt de Tracy. M. Picavet has grouped around them, along with many obscurer names, the great scientific men of the time, like Laplace, Bichat, Lamarck, as all in the direct line of eighteenth century thought. "Ideologists" he calls them. [Footnote: Ideology is now sometimes used to convey a criticism; for instance, to contrast the methods of Lamarck with those of Darwin.] Ideology, the science of ideas, was the word invented by de Tracy to distinguish the investigation of thought in accordance with the methods of Locke and Condillac from old-fashioned metaphysics. The guiding principle of the ideologists was to apply reason to observed facts and eschew a priori deductions. Thinkers of this school had an influential organ, the Decade philosophique, of which J. B. Say the economist was one of the founders in 1794. The Institut, which had been established by the Convention, was crowded with "ideologists," and may be said to have continued the work of the Encyclopaedia. [Footnote: Picavet, op. cit. p. 69. The members of the 2nd Class of the Institut, that of moral and political science, were so predominantly Ideological that the distrust of Napoleon was excited, and he abolished it in 1803, distributing its members among the other Classes.] These men had a firm faith in the indefinite progress of knowledge, general enlightenment, and "social reason."

But the immense fame of these significant reactionaries shouldn't mislead us into overestimating the extent of this reaction. The spirit and trends of the past century remained strong in the circles that were most permanently influential. Many prominent scholars who had embraced the ideas of Condillac and Helvetius and had participated in the Revolution, and survived it, were active during the Empire and the restored Monarchy, still faithful to the spirit of their mentors and influential because of the value of their scientific contributions. M. Picavet's extensive research into the activities of this group of thinkers has helped us understand the transition from the era of Condorcet to the era of Comte. The two central figures are Cabanis, a friend of Condorcet, [Footnote: He has already claimed our notice, above, p. 215.] and Destutt de Tracy. M. Picavet has gathered around them, along with many lesser-known names, the great scientists of the time, like Laplace, Bichat, Lamarck, all in the direct line of eighteenth-century thought. He calls them "Ideologists." [Footnote: Ideology is now sometimes used to convey a criticism; for instance, to contrast the methods of Lamarck with those of Darwin.] Ideology, the science of ideas, was a term coined by de Tracy to differentiate the examination of thought based on the methods of Locke and Condillac from outdated metaphysics. The guiding principle of the ideologists was to use reason based on observed facts and avoid a priori deductions. Thinkers from this school had a significant platform, the Decade philosophique, of which J. B. Say the economist was one of the founders in 1794. The Institut, established by the Convention, was filled with "ideologists" and can be said to have continued the work of the Encyclopaedia. [Footnote: Picavet, op. cit. p. 69. The members of the 2nd Class of the Institut, that of moral and political science, were so predominantly Ideological that the distrust of Napoleon was raised, and he abolished it in 1803, distributing its members among the other Classes.] These individuals had strong faith in the endless progress of knowledge, widespread enlightenment, and "social reason."

2.

2.

Thus the ideas of the "sophists" of the age of Voltaire were alive in the speculative world, not withstanding political, religious, and philosophical reaction. But their limitations were to be transcended, and account taken of facts and aspects which their philosophy had ignored or minimised. The value of the reactionary movement lay in pressing these facts and aspects on the attention, in reopening chambers of the human spirit which the age of Voltaire had locked and sealed.

Thus, the ideas of the “sophists” during Voltaire's time were still alive in the world of speculation, despite political, religious, and philosophical backlash. However, their limitations needed to be overcome, and attention needed to be given to facts and aspects that their philosophy had overlooked or downplayed. The importance of the reactionary movement was in highlighting these facts and aspects, in reopening chambers of the human spirit that the age of Voltaire had closed off.

The idea of Progress was particularly concerned in the general change of attitude, intellectual and emotional, towards the Middle Ages. A fresh interest in the great age of the Church was a natural part of the religious revival, but extended far beyond the circle of ardent Catholics. It was a characteristic feature, as every one knows, of the Romantic movement. It did not affect only creative literature, it occupied speculative thinkers and stimulated historians. For Guizot, Michelet, and Auguste Comte, as well as for Chateaubriand and Victor Hugo, the Middle Ages have a significance which Frenchmen of the previous generation could hardly have comprehended.

The idea of Progress was particularly focused on the overall shift in attitudes, both intellectual and emotional, towards the Middle Ages. A renewed interest in the Church's significant era was a natural part of the religious revival, but it reached far beyond just passionate Catholics. This was a defining aspect, as everyone knows, of the Romantic movement. It didn’t only influence creative literature; it also engaged thinkers and inspired historians. For Guizot, Michelet, and Auguste Comte, as well as for Chateaubriand and Victor Hugo, the Middle Ages held a meaning that French people of the previous generation could hardly understand.

We saw how that period had embarrassed the first pioneers who attempted to trace the course of civilisation as a progressive movement, how lightly they passed over it, how unconvincingly they explained it away. At the beginning of the nineteenth century the medieval question was posed in such a way that any one who undertook to develop the doctrine of Progress would have to explore it more seriously. Madame de Stael saw this when she wrote her book on Literature considered in its Relation to Social Institutions (1801). She was then under the influence of Condorcet and an ardent believer in perfectibility, and the work is an attempt to extend this theory, which she testifies was falling into discredit, to the realm of literature. She saw that, if man regressed instead of progressing for ten centuries, the case for Progress was gravely compromised, and she sought to show that the Middle Ages contributed to the development of the intellectual faculties and to the expansion of civilisation, and that the Christian religion was an indispensable agent. This contention that Progress was uninterrupted is an advance on Condorcet and an anticipation of Saint-Simon and Comte.

We saw how that period embarrassed the first pioneers who tried to outline civilization as a continuous progress, how they brushed over it lightly, and how unconvincingly they dismissed it. At the start of the nineteenth century, the medieval question was raised in such a way that anyone aiming to develop the idea of Progress would have to take it more seriously. Madame de Stael recognized this when she wrote her book *Literature Considered in Its Relation to Social Institutions* (1801). She was then influenced by Condorcet and was a passionate believer in perfectibility, and her work attempts to broaden this theory—already losing credibility—to the field of literature. She noted that if humanity had regressed instead of progressed for ten centuries, the argument for Progress would be seriously weakened. She aimed to show that the Middle Ages contributed to the growth of intellectual capacities and the expansion of civilization, and that Christianity was a crucial factor. This assertion that Progress was continuous builds on Condorcet’s ideas and anticipates those of Saint-Simon and Comte.

A more eloquent and persuasive voice was raised in the following year from the ranks of reaction. Chateaubriand's Genie du Christianisme appeared in 1802, "amidst the ruins of our temples," as the author afterwards said, when France was issuing from the chaos of her revolution. It was a declaration of war against the spirit of the eighteenth century which had treated Christianity as a barbarous system whose fall was demanded in the name of Progress. But it was much more than polemic. Chateaubriand arrayed arguments in support of orthodox dogmas, original sin, primitive degeneration, and the rest; but the appeal of the book did not lie in its logic, it lay in the appreciation of Christianity from a new point of view. He approached it in the spirit of an artist, as an aesthete, not as a philosopher, and so far as he proved anything he proved that Christianity is valuable because it is beautiful, not because it is true. He aimed at showing that it can "enchanter l'ame aussi divinement que les dieux de Virgile et d'Homere." He might call to his help the Fathers of the Church, but it was on Dante, Milton, Racine that his case was really based. The book is an apologia, from the aesthetic standpoint of the Romantic school. "Dieu ne defend pas les routes fleuries quand elles servent a revenir a lui."

A more eloquent and persuasive voice emerged the following year from the ranks of traditionalism. Chateaubriand's "Genius of Christianity" was published in 1802, "amidst the ruins of our temples," as he later stated, when France was coming out of the chaos of her revolution. It was a declaration of war against the mindset of the eighteenth century, which had viewed Christianity as a barbaric system whose downfall was called for in the name of Progress. But it was much more than just a critique. Chateaubriand presented arguments in favor of orthodox beliefs, original sin, primitive degeneration, and more; however, the appeal of the book didn’t lie in its logic, but in its appreciation of Christianity from a fresh perspective. He approached it as an artist, as an aesthete, rather than as a philosopher, and where he proved anything, he demonstrated that Christianity is valuable because it is beautiful, not necessarily because it is true. He aimed to show that it can "enchant the soul as divinely as the gods of Virgil and Homer." He could invoke the Fathers of the Church, but his argument was mainly rooted in Dante, Milton, and Racine. The book is a defense from the aesthetic viewpoint of the Romantic school. "God does not forbid the flowered paths when they lead back to Him."

It was a matter of course that the defender of original sin should reject the doctrine of perfectibility. "When man attains the highest point of civilisation," wrote Chateaubriand in the vein of Rousseau, "he is on the lowest stair of morality; if he is free, he is rude; by civilising his manners, he forges himself chains. His heart profits at the expense of his head, his head at the expense of his heart." And, apart from considerations of Christian doctrine, the question of Progress had little interest for the Romantic school. Victor Hugo, in the famous Preface to his Cromwell (1827), where he went more deeply than Chateaubriand into the contrasts between ancient and modern art, revived the old likeness of mankind to an individual man, and declared that classical antiquity was the time of its virility and that we are now spectators of its imposing old age.

It was expected that someone defending original sin would reject the idea of perfectibility. "When humanity reaches the peak of civilization," wrote Chateaubriand in a Rousseau-inspired style, "it is at the lowest rung of morality; when it is free, it is uncivilized; by refining its behavior, it creates its own chains. The heart benefits at the cost of the head, and the head at the cost of the heart." Besides the aspects of Christian doctrine, the notion of Progress held little appeal for the Romantic school. Victor Hugo, in the famous Preface to his Cromwell (1827), where he explored the differences between ancient and modern art more deeply than Chateaubriand, revived the old analogy of humanity as an individual and declared that classical antiquity was a time of vigor, while we are now witnesses to its grand old age.

From other points of view powerful intellects were reverting to the Middle Ages and eager to blot out the whole development of modern society since the Reformation, as the Encyclopaedic philosophers had wished to blot out the Middle Ages. The ideal of Bonald, De Maistre, and Lamennais was a sacerdotal government of the world, and the English constitution was hardly less offensive to their minds than the Revolution which De Maistre denounced as "satanic." Advocates as they were of the dead system of theocracy, they contributed, however, to the advance of thought, not only by forcing medieval institutions on the notice of the world but also by their perception that society had been treated in the eighteenth century in too mechanical a way, that institutions grow, that the conception of individual men divested of their life in society is a misleading abstraction. They put this in extravagant and untenable forms, but there was a large measure of truth in their criticism, which did its part in helping the nineteenth century to revise and transcend the results of eighteenth century speculation.

From other perspectives, powerful intellects were looking back to the Middle Ages and wanting to erase the entire development of modern society since the Reformation, just like the Encyclopedic philosophers wanted to erase the Middle Ages. The ideal of Bonald, De Maistre, and Lamennais was a priestly government of the world, and the English constitution was nearly as offensive to them as the Revolution that De Maistre condemned as "satanic." Although they were proponents of the outdated system of theocracy, they played a role in advancing thought, not only by bringing medieval institutions to global attention but also by recognizing that society had been viewed too mechanically in the eighteenth century, that institutions evolve, and that the idea of individuals divorced from their social context is a misleading abstraction. They expressed this in extreme and untenable ways, but there was a significant amount of truth in their critique, which contributed to the nineteenth century's efforts to reassess and move beyond the outcomes of eighteenth-century thought.

In this reactionary literature we can see the struggle of the doctrine of Providence, declining before the doctrine of Progress, to gain the upper-hand again. Chateaubriand, Bonald, De Maistre, Lamennais firmly held the dogma of an original golden age and the degradation of man, and denounced the whole trend of progressive thought from Bacon to Condorcet. These writers were unconsciously helping Condorcet's doctrine to assume a new and less questionable shape. [Footnote: Bonald indeed in his treatise De pouvoir adopted the idea of development and applied it to religion (as Newman did afterwards) for the purpose of condemning the Reformation as a retrograde movement.]

In this reactionary literature, we see the struggle of the idea of Providence, which is losing ground to the idea of Progress, trying to regain its dominance. Chateaubriand, Bonald, De Maistre, and Lamennais strongly believed in the concept of a original golden age and the decline of humanity, and they criticized the entire trend of progressive thought from Bacon to Condorcet. These writers were unknowingly helping Condorcet's idea take on a new, less questionable form. [Footnote: Bonald indeed, in his treatise De pouvoir, adopted the idea of development and applied it to religion (as Newman did later) in order to condemn the Reformation as a backward movement.]

3.

3.

Along with the discovery of the Middle Ages came the discovery of German literature. In the intellectual commerce between the two countries in the age of Frederick the Great, France had been exclusively the giver, Germany the recipient. It was due, above all, to Madame de Stael that the tide began to flow the other way. Among the writers of the Napoleonic epoch, Madame de Stael is easily first in critical talent and intellectual breadth. Her study of the Revolution showed a more dispassionate appreciation of that convulsion than any of her contemporaries were capable of forming. But her chef-d'oeuvre is her study of Germany, De l'Allemagne, [Footnote: A.D. 1813.] which revealed the existence of a world of art and thought, unsuspected by the French public. Within the next twenty years Herder and Lessing, Kant and Hegel were exerting their influence at Paris. She did in France what Coleridge was doing in England for the knowledge of German thought.

With the discovery of the Middle Ages came the discovery of German literature. During the intellectual exchange between the two countries in the era of Frederick the Great, France was solely the giver, while Germany was the receiver. It was primarily thanks to Madame de Stael that the tide began to change direction. Among the writers of the Napoleonic period, Madame de Stael easily stands out for her critical talent and intellectual depth. Her examination of the Revolution displayed a more objective understanding of that upheaval than any of her contemporaries could achieve. However, her masterpiece is her study of Germany, De l'Allemagne, [Footnote: A.D. 1813.] which revealed a world of art and thought that the French public had not previously recognized. Within the next twenty years, Herder and Lessing, Kant and Hegel were making their influence felt in Paris. She did in France what Coleridge was doing in England for the understanding of German thought.

Madame de Stael had raised anew the question which had been raised in the seventeenth century and answered in the negative by Voltaire: is there progress in aesthetic literature? Her early book on Literature had clearly defined the issue. She did not propose the thesis that there is any progress or improvement (as some of the Moderns had contended in the famous Quarrel) in artistic form. Within the limits of their own thought and emotional experience the ancients achieved perfection of expression, and perfection cannot be surpassed. But as thought progresses, as the sum of ideas increases and society changes, fresh material is supplied to art, there is "a new development of sensibility" which enables literary artists to compass new kinds of charm. The Genie du Christianisme embodied a commentary on her contention, more arresting than any she could herself have furnished. Here the reactionary joined hands with the disciple of Condorcet, to prove that there is progress in the domain of art. Madame de Stael's masterpiece, Germany, was a further impressive illustration of the thesis that the literature of the modern European nations represents an advance on classical literature, in the sense that it sounds notes which the Greek and Roman masters had not heard, reaches depths which they had not conjectured, unlocks chambers which to them were closed,—as a result of the progressive experiences of the human soul. [Footnote: German literature was indeed already known, in some measure, to readers of the Decade philosophique, and Kant had been studied in France long before 1813, the year of the publication of De l'Allemagne. See Picavet, Les Ideologues, p. 99.] [Footnote: We can see the effect of her doctrine in Guizot's remarks (Histoire de la civilisation en Europe, 2e lecon) where he says of modern literatures that "sous le point de vue du fond des sentiments et des idees elles sont plus fortes et plus riches [than the ancient]. On voit que l'ame humaine a ete remuee sur un plus grand nombre de points a une plus grande profondeur"—and to this very fact he ascribes their comparative imperfection in form.]

Madame de Stael revisited the question that had been posed in the seventeenth century and answered negatively by Voltaire: is there progress in aesthetic literature? Her earlier book on Literature clearly defined the issue. She did not argue that there is any progress or improvement (as some of the Moderns had claimed in the famous Quarrel) in artistic form. Within their own thinking and emotional experiences, the ancients achieved perfection of expression, and that perfection cannot be surpassed. However, as thinking evolves, as the body of ideas grows, and as society changes, new material is provided for art. There is "a new development of sensibility" that allows literary artists to capture new kinds of beauty. The Genie du Christianisme provided a commentary on her argument that was more striking than anything she could have offered herself. Here, the traditionalist joined forces with the follower of Condorcet to demonstrate that there is progress in the realm of art. Madame de Stael's masterpiece, Germany, was another compelling illustration of the idea that the literature of modern European nations represents an advancement over classical literature, in that it explores themes the Greek and Roman masters had not encountered, reaches depths they had not imagined, and opens doors that were closed to them—thanks to the evolving experiences of the human soul. [Footnote: German literature was indeed already known, in some measure, to readers of the Decade philosophique, and Kant had been studied in France long before 1813, the year of the publication of De l'Allemagne. See Picavet, Les Ideologues, p. 99.] [Footnote: We can see the effect of her theory in Guizot's remarks (Histoire de la civilisation en Europe, 2e lecon) where he states about modern literatures that "in terms of the depth of feelings and ideas, they are stronger and richer [than the ancient]. It shows that the human soul has been stirred on a greater number of points to a greater depth"—and this very fact he attributes to their relative imperfection in form.]

This view is based on the general propositions that all social phenomena closely cohere and that literature is a social phenomenon; from which it follows that if there is a progressive movement in society generally, there is a progressive movement in literature. Her books were true to the theory; they inaugurated the methods of modern criticism, which studies literary works in relation to the social background of their period.

This perspective relies on the idea that all social phenomena are interconnected and that literature is one of these social phenomena. Therefore, if society is making progress, literature is too. Her books embodied this theory; they introduced the approaches of modern criticism, which examines literary works in the context of the social environment of their time.

4.

4.

France, then, under the Bourbon Restoration began to seek new light from the obscure profundities of German speculation which Madame de Stael proclaimed. Herder's "Ideas" were translated by Edgar Quinet, Lessing's Education by Eugene Rodrigues. Cousin sat at the feet of Hegel. At the same time a new master, full of suggestiveness for those who were interested in the philosophy of history, was discovered in Italy. The "Scienza nuova" of Vico was translated by Michelet.

France, during the Bourbon Restoration, started to look for new insights from the complex depths of German thought that Madame de Stael highlighted. Herder's "Ideas" were translated by Edgar Quinet, and Lessing's Education was translated by Eugene Rodrigues. Cousin studied under Hegel. At the same time, a new influential figure for those interested in the philosophy of history was found in Italy. Michelet translated Vico's "Scienza nuova."

The book of Vico was now a hundred years old. I did not mention him in his chronological place, because he exercised no immediate influence on the world. His thought was an anachronism in the eighteenth century, it appealed to the nineteenth. He did not announce or conceive any theory of Progress, but his speculation, bewildering enough and confused in its exposition, contained principles which seemed predestined to form the basis of such a doctrine. His aim was that of Cabanis and the ideologists, to set the study of society on the same basis of certitude which had been secured for the study of nature through the work of Descartes and Newton. [Footnote: Vico has sometimes been claimed as a theorist of Progress, but incorrectly. See B. Croce, The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico (Eng. tr., 1913), p. 132—an indispensable aid to the study of Vico. The first edition of the Scienza nuova appeared in 1725; the second, which was a new work, in 1730.

The book by Vico is now a hundred years old. I didn’t mention him when discussing the timeline because he didn’t have an immediate impact on the world. His ideas felt out of place in the eighteenth century but resonated in the nineteenth. He didn’t announce or come up with a theory of Progress, but his complex and somewhat confusing ideas contained principles that seemed destined to be the foundation for such a concept. His goal was similar to that of Cabanis and the ideologists: to establish the study of society with the same level of certainty that was achieved in the study of nature through the work of Descartes and Newton. [Footnote: Vico has sometimes been claimed as a theorist of Progress, but incorrectly. See B. Croce, The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico (Eng. tr., 1913), p. 132—an indispensable aid to the study of Vico. The first edition of the Scienza nuova appeared in 1725; the second, which was a new work, in 1730.]

Vico influenced Ballanche, a writer who enjoyed a considerable repute in his day. He taught the progressive development of man towards liberty and equality within the four corners of the Christian religion, which he regarded as final. His Palingenesie sociale appeared in 1823-30.]

Vico influenced Ballanche, a writer who was well-known in his time. He taught about the progressive evolution of humanity towards freedom and equality within the framework of Christianity, which he viewed as the ultimate truth. His *Palingenesie sociale* was published between 1823 and 1830.

His fundamental idea was that the explanation of the history of societies is to be found in the human mind. The world at first is felt rather than thought; this is the condition of savages in the state of nature, who have no political organisation. The second mental state is imaginative knowledge, "poetical wisdom"; to this corresponds the higher barbarism of the heroic age. Finally, comes conceptual knowledge, and with it the age of civilisation. These are the three stages through which every society passes, and each of these types determines law, institutions, language, literature, and the characters of men.

His main idea was that the history of societies can be explained through the human mind. In the beginning, people experience the world more through feelings than through thoughts; this reflects the condition of primitive societies that lack political organization. The next mental stage is imaginative knowledge, or "poetical wisdom," which corresponds to the more advanced barbarism of the heroic age. Finally, there's conceptual knowledge, marking the era of civilization. These are the three stages that every society goes through, and each stage shapes its laws, institutions, language, literature, and the characteristics of its people.

Vico's strenuous researches in the study of Homer and early Roman history were undertaken in order to get at the point of view of the heroic age. He insisted that it could not be understood unless we transcended our own abstract ways of thinking and looked at the world with primitive eyes, by a forced effort of imagination. He was convinced that history had been vitiated by the habit of ignoring psychological differences, by the failure to recapture the ancient point of view. Here he was far in advance of his own times.

Vico's intense studies of Homer and early Roman history were aimed at understanding the perspective of the heroic age. He argued that we couldn't grasp it unless we went beyond our own abstract ways of thinking and viewed the world through primitive eyes, making a deliberate effort to imagine. He believed that history had been distorted by the tendency to overlook psychological differences and the inability to regain the ancient perspective. In this regard, he was way ahead of his time.

Concentrating his attention above all on Roman antiquity, he adopted—not altogether advantageously for his system—the revolutions of Roman history as the typical rule of social development. The succession of aristocracy (for the early kingship of Rome and Homeric royalty are merely forms of aristocracy in Vico's view), democracy, and monarchy is the necessary sequence of political governments. Monarchy (the Roman Empire) corresponds to the highest form of civilisation. What happens when this is reached? Society declines into an anarchical state of nature, from which it again passes into a higher barbarism or heroic age, to be followed once more by civilisation. The dissolution of the Roman Empire and the barbarian invasions are followed by the Middle Ages, in which Dante plays the part of Homer; and the modern period with its strong monarchies corresponds to the Roman Empire. This is Vico's principle of reflux. If the theory were sound, it would mean that the civilisation of his day must again relapse into barbarism and the cycle begin again. He did not himself state this conclusion directly or venture on any prediction. It is obvious how readily his doctrine could be adapted to the conception of Progress as a spiral movement. Evidently the corresponding periods in his cycles are not identical or really homogeneous. Whatever points of likeness may be discovered between early Greek or Roman and medieval societies, the points of unlikeness are still more numerous and manifest. Modern civilisation differs in fundamental and far-reaching ways from Greek and Roman. It is absurd to pretend that the general movement brings man back again and again to the point from which he started, and therefore, if there is any value in Vico's reflux, it can only mean that the movement of society may be regarded as a spiral ascent, so that each stage of an upward progress corresponds, in certain general aspects, to a stage which has already been traversed, this correspondence being due to the psychical nature of man.

Focusing primarily on Roman history, he adopted the changes in Roman history as the typical pattern of social development, although this wasn’t entirely beneficial for his theory. The progression of aristocracy (since he sees the early kingship of Rome and Homeric royalty as forms of aristocracy), democracy, and monarchy represents the essential sequence of political systems. Monarchy (the Roman Empire) is seen as the peak of civilization. What happens when this peak is reached? Society falls into a chaotic state of nature, from which it eventually transitions into a more advanced barbarism or heroic age, followed again by civilization. The collapse of the Roman Empire and the invasions by barbarians lead to the Middle Ages, with Dante taking on the role of Homer; and the modern era, marked by strong monarchies, aligns with the Roman Empire. This is Vico's principle of reflux. If the theory holds true, it suggests that the civilization of his time would inevitably slide back into barbarism, and the cycle would restart. He did not explicitly articulate this conclusion or make any predictions. It's clear how easily his doctrine could fit into the concept of Progress as a spiral movement. The corresponding periods in his cycles are not the same or truly homogeneous. While there may be similarities between early Greek or Roman societies and medieval ones, the differences are even more numerous and evident. Modern civilization is fundamentally and significantly different from Greek and Roman societies. It's absurd to claim that the general movement brings humanity back to the same starting point repeatedly; therefore, if there is any merit to Vico's reflux, it can only suggest that societal movement can be seen as a spiral ascent, where each stage of advancement corresponds, in certain broad aspects, to a previous stage, due to the psychological nature of humanity.

A conception of this kind could not be appreciated in Vico's day or by the next generation. The "Scienza nuova" lay in Montesquieu's library, and he made no use of it. But it was natural that it should arouse interest in France at a time when the new idealistic philosophies of Germany were attracting attention, and when Frenchmen, of the ideological school, were seeking, like Vico himself, a synthetic principle to explain social phenomena. Different though Vico was in his point of departure as in his methods from the German idealists, his speculations nevertheless had something in common with theirs. Both alike explained history by the nature of mind which necessarily determined the stages of the process; Vico as little as Fichte or Hegel took eudaemonic considerations into account. The difference was that the German thinkers sought their principle in logic and applied it a priori, while Vico sought his in concrete psychology and engaged in laborious research to establish it a posteriori by the actual data of history. But both speculations suggested that the course of human development corresponds to the fundamental character of mental processes and is not diverted either by Providential intervention or by free acts of human will.

A concept like this wasn't appreciated in Vico's time or by the next generation. Montesquieu had the "Scienza nuova" in his library, but he didn't make use of it. However, it was natural for it to spark interest in France when the new idealistic philosophies from Germany were gaining attention, and when French thinkers, aligned with the ideological school, were trying to find a unifying principle to explain social phenomena, similar to Vico himself. Although Vico had a different starting point and methods compared to the German idealists, his ideas still shared some similarities with theirs. Both explained history through the nature of the mind, which inevitably shaped the stages of the process; like Fichte or Hegel, Vico did not consider eudaemonic factors. The main difference was that the German thinkers looked for their principle in logic and applied it a priori, while Vico searched for his in tangible psychology and painstakingly researched to establish it a posteriori using actual historical data. Yet both sets of ideas suggested that the trajectory of human development aligns with the fundamental nature of mental processes and is not altered by divine intervention or by human free will.

5.

5.

These foreign influences co-operated in determining the tendencies of French speculation in the period of the restored monarchy, whereby the idea of Progress was placed on new basements and became the headstone of new "religions." Before we consider the founders of sects, we may glance briefly at the views of some eminent savants who had gained the ear of the public before the July Revolution—Jouffroy, Cousin, and Guizot.

These foreign influences worked together to shape the ideas of French thought during the time of the restored monarchy, establishing the concept of Progress on new foundations and making it central to new "religions." Before we look at the founders of these sects, let’s briefly consider the perspectives of some prominent scholars who had captured public attention before the July Revolution—Jouffroy, Cousin, and Guizot.

Cousin, the chief luminary in the sphere of pure philosophy in France in the first half of the nineteenth century, drew his inspiration from Germany. He was professedly an eclectic, but in the main his philosophy was Hegelian. He might endow God with consciousness and speak of Providence, but he regarded the world-process as a necessary evolution of thought, and he saw, not in religion but in philosophy, the highest expression of civilisation. In 1828 he delivered a course of lectures on the philosophy of history. He divided history into three periods, each governed by a master idea: the first by the idea of the infinite (the Orient); the second by that of the finite (classical antiquity); the third by that of the relation of finite to infinite (the modern age). As with Hegel, the future is ignored, progress is confined within a closed system, the highest circle has already been reached. As an opponent of the ideologists and the sensational philosophy on which they founded their speculations, Cousin appealed to the orthodox and all those to whom Voltairianism was an accursed thing, and for a generation he exercised a considerable influence. But his work—and this is the important point for us—helped to diffuse the idea, which the ideologists were diffusing on very different lines—that human history has been a progressive development.

Cousin, the leading figure in pure philosophy in France during the first half of the nineteenth century, was inspired by Germany. He was openly eclectic, but primarily his philosophy was Hegelian. He might attribute consciousness to God and discuss Providence, yet he saw the world-process as a necessary evolution of thought, believing that the highest expression of civilization lies in philosophy, not religion. In 1828, he gave a series of lectures on the philosophy of history. He classified history into three periods, each governed by a central idea: the first by the idea of the infinite (the Orient); the second by the finite (classical antiquity); and the third by the relationship between the finite and the infinite (the modern age). Like Hegel, he ignored the future, maintaining that progress exists within a closed system, and that the highest circle had already been attained. As a critic of the ideologists and the sensational philosophy that supported their ideas, Cousin found support among the orthodox and others who viewed Voltairianism as a curse, and for a generation, he had a substantial impact. However, his work—and this is the key point for us—contributed to spreading the notion that human history has been a progressive development, a concept also promoted by the ideologists through very different means.

Progressive development was also the theme of Jouffroy in his slight but suggestive introduction to the philosophy of history (1825), [Footnote: "Reflexions sur la philosophie de l'histoire," in Melanges philosophiques, 2nd edition, 1838.] in which he posed the same problem which, as we shall see, Saint-Simon and Comte were simultaneously attempting to solve. He had not fallen under the glamour of German idealism, and his results have more affinity with Vico's than with Hegel's.

Progressive development was also the theme of Jouffroy in his brief but thought-provoking introduction to the philosophy of history (1825), [Footnote: "Reflexions sur la philosophie de l'histoire," in Melanges philosophiques, 2nd edition, 1838.] where he raised the same issue that, as we will see, Saint-Simon and Comte were also trying to address at the same time. He hadn't been dazzled by German idealism, and his conclusions are more in line with Vico's than Hegel's.

He begins with some simple considerations which conduct to the doubtful conclusion that all the historical changes in man's condition are due to the operation of his intelligence. The historian's business is to trace the succession of the actual changes. The business of the philosopher of history is to trace the succession of ideas and study the correspondence between the two developments. This is the true philosophy of history: "the glory of our age is to understand it."

He starts with a few simple thoughts that lead to the uncertain conclusion that all the changes in human history are the result of our intelligence at work. The historian's job is to follow the sequence of actual changes. The job of the philosopher of history is to follow the sequence of ideas and examine how they relate to each other. This is the real philosophy of history: "the greatness of our time is to comprehend it."

Now it is admitted to-day, he says, that the human intelligence obeys invariable laws, so that a further problem remains. The actual succession of ideas has to be deduced from these necessary laws. When that deduction is effected—a long time hence—history will disappear; it will be merged in science.

Now it’s acknowledged today, he says, that human intelligence follows consistent laws, which leaves us with another problem. The actual order of ideas needs to be derived from these essential laws. Once that derivation is achieved—though that may take a while—history will fade away; it will be incorporated into science.

Jouffroy then presented the world with what he calls the FATALITY OF INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT, to take the place of Providence or Destiny. It is a fatality, he is careful to explain, which, so far from compromising, presupposes individual liberty. For it is not like the fatality of sensual impulse which guides the brute creation. What it implies is this: if a thousand men have the same idea of what is good, this idea will govern their conduct in spite of their passions, because, being reasonable and free, they are not blindly submissive to passion, but can deliberate and choose.

Jouffroy then introduced the concept he calls the FATALITY OF INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT, replacing the ideas of Providence or Destiny. He emphasizes that this fatality does not limit individual freedom. Unlike the fatality of base instincts that drives animal behavior, this one means that if a thousand people share the same understanding of what is good, that understanding will dictate their actions despite their desires. This is because, being rational and free, they do not simply follow their passions, but have the ability to think critically and make choices.

This explanation of history as a necessary development of society corresponding to a necessary succession of ideas differs in two important points from the explanations of Hegel and Cousin. The succession of ideas is not conceived as a transcendent logic, but is determined by the laws of the HUMAN mind and belongs to the domain of psychology. Here Jouffroy is on the same ground as Vico. In the second place, it is not a closed system; room remains for an indefinite development in the future.

This explanation of history as a necessary evolution of society that aligns with a necessary sequence of ideas differs in two significant ways from the theories of Hegel and Cousin. The sequence of ideas is not seen as a transcendent logic but is shaped by the laws of the HUMAN mind and falls within the realm of psychology. Here, Jouffroy shares common ground with Vico. Additionally, it is not a closed system; there is still space for endless development in the future.

6.

6.

While Cousin was discoursing on philosophy at Paris in the days of the last Bourbon king, Guizot was drawing crowded audiences to his lectures on the history of European civilisation, [Footnote: Histoire de la civilisation en Europe.] and the keynote of these lectures was Progress. He approached it with a fresh mind, unencumbered with any of the philosophical theories which had attended and helped its growth.

While Cousin was talking about philosophy in Paris during the reign of the last Bourbon king, Guizot was attracting large crowds to his lectures on the history of European civilization, [Footnote: Histoire de la civilisation en Europe.] and the central theme of these lectures was Progress. He tackled it with a fresh perspective, free from the philosophical theories that had accompanied and supported its development.

Civilisation, he said, is the supreme fact so far as man is concerned, "the fact par excellence, the general and definite fact in which all other facts merge." And "civilisation" means progress or development. The word "awakens, when it is pronounced, the idea of a people which is in motion, not to change its place but to change its state, a people whose condition is expanding and improving. The idea of progress, development, seems to me to be the fundamental idea contained in the word CIVILISATION."

Civilization, he said, is the most important thing for humanity, "the ultimate fact, the key fact into which all other facts come together." And "civilization" means progress or development. The word "evokes, when spoken, the image of a society that’s in motion, not to relocate but to transform its situation, a society whose condition is growing and improving. The concept of progress, development, strikes me as the core idea encapsulated in the term CIVILIZATION."

There we have the most important positive idea of eighteenth century speculation, standing forth detached and independent, no longer bound to a system. Fifty years before, no one would have dreamed of defining civilisation like that and counting on the immediate acquiescence of his audience. But progress has to be defined. It does not merely imply the improvement of social relations and public well-being. France in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was behind Holland and England in the sum and distribution of well-being among individuals, and yet she can claim that she was the most "civilised" country in those ages. The reason is that civilisation also implies the development of the individual life, of men's private faculties, sentiments, and ideas. The progress of man therefore includes both these developments. But they are intimately connected. We may observe how moral reformers generally recommend their proposals by promising social amelioration as a result, and that progressive politicians maintain that the progress of society necessarily induces moral improvement. The connection may not always be apparent, and at different times one or other kind of progress predominates. But one is followed by the other ultimately, though it may be after a long interval, for "la Providence a ses aises dans le temps." The rise of Christianity was one of the crises of civilisation, yet it did not in its early stages aim at any improvement of social conditions; it did not attack the great injustices which were wrought in the world. It meant a great crisis because it changed the beliefs and sentiments of individuals; social effects came afterwards.

There we have the most important positive idea of eighteenth-century thinking, standing out on its own, no longer tied to a system. Fifty years earlier, no one would have thought to define civilization this way and expect their audience to agree instantly. But progress must be defined. It doesn't just mean improving social relations and public well-being. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, France lagged behind Holland and England in terms of overall well-being among individuals, yet she could still claim to be the most "civilized" country of that time. The reason is that civilization also involves the development of individual lives, personal abilities, feelings, and ideas. Therefore, human progress includes both types of development. But they are closely linked. We can see how moral reformers usually promote their ideas by promising social improvement as a result, and progressive politicians argue that social progress inevitably leads to moral betterment. The connection may not always be obvious, and at different times, one form of progress may outweigh the other. However, ultimately, one follows the other, even if there’s a long delay, for "la Providence a ses aises dans le temps." The emergence of Christianity was one of civilization's turning points, yet it did not initially aim to improve social conditions; it didn’t challenge the significant injustices present in the world. It represented a major turning point because it transformed individual beliefs and feelings; the social effects came later.

The civilisation of modern Europe has grown through a period of fifteen centuries and is still progressing. The rate of progress has been slower than that of Greek civilisation, but on the other hand it has been continuous, uninterrupted, and we can see "the vista of an immense career."

The civilization of modern Europe has developed over a span of fifteen centuries and continues to evolve. While the pace of progress has been slower than that of Greek civilization, it has been consistent and uninterrupted, and we can perceive "the vista of an immense career."

The effects of Guizot's doctrine in propagating the idea of Progress were all the greater for its divorce from philosophical theory. He did not touch perplexing questions like fatality, or discuss the general plan of the world; he did not attempt to rise above common-sense; and he did not essay any premature scheme of the universal history of man. His masterly survey of the social history of Europe exhibited progressive movement as a fact, in a period in which to the thinkers of the eighteenth century it had been almost invisible. This of course was far from proving that Progress is the key to the history of the world and human destinies. The equation of civilisation with progress remains an assumption. For the question at once arises: Can civilisation reach a state of equilibrium from which no further advance is possible; and if it can, does it cease to be civilisation? Is Chinese civilisation mis-called, or has there been here too a progressive movement all the time, however slow? Such questions were not raised by Guizot. But his view of history was effective in helping to establish the association of the two ideas of civilisation and progress, which to-day is taken for granted as evidently true.

The impact of Guizot's ideas on promoting the concept of Progress was even stronger because it was separate from philosophical theory. He didn’t address complicated issues like fate, nor did he discuss the overall design of the world; he didn’t try to go beyond common sense, and he avoided any premature theories about the universal history of humanity. His impressive analysis of Europe's social history demonstrated that progress was a reality during a time when thinkers of the eighteenth century had nearly missed it. However, this certainly didn’t prove that Progress is the key to understanding the history of the world and human fate. The idea that civilization equals progress remains an assumption. This brings up the question: Can civilization reach a point where no further progress is possible, and if it can, does it stop being civilization? Is Chinese civilization misnamed, or has there been a slow but continuous progress here too? Guizot didn’t pose these questions. Nonetheless, his perspective on history effectively helped connect the ideas of civilization and progress, which today is widely accepted as obviously true.

7.

7.

The views of these eminent thinkers Cousin, Jouffroy, and Guizot show that—quite apart from the doctrines of ideologists and of the "positivists," Saint-Simon and Comte, of whom I have still to speak—there was a common trend in French thought in the Restoration period towards the conception of history as a progressive movement. Perhaps there is no better illustration of the infectiousness of this conception than in the Historical Studies which Chateaubriand gave to the world in 1831. He had learned much, from books as well as from politics, since he wrote the GENIUS OF CHRISTIANITY. He had gained some acquaintance with German philosophy and with Vico. And in this work of his advanced age he accepts the idea of Progress, so far as it could be accepted by an orthodox son of the Church. He believes that the advance of knowledge will lead to social progress, and that society, if it seems sometimes to move backward, is always really moving forward. Bossuet, for whom he had no word of criticism thirty years before, he now convicts of "an imposing error." That great man, he writes, "has confined historical events in a circle as rigorous as his genius. He has imprisoned them in an inflexible Christianity—a terrible hoop in which the human race would turn in a sort of eternity, without progress or improvement." The admission from such a quarter shows eloquently how the wind was setting.

The views of these prominent thinkers Cousin, Jouffroy, and Guizot demonstrate that—regardless of the theories of ideologists and the "positivists," like Saint-Simon and Comte, whom I still need to discuss—there was a shared trend in French thought during the Restoration period toward seeing history as a progressive movement. Perhaps there is no better example of the spread of this idea than in the Historical Studies that Chateaubriand published in 1831. He had learned a lot, both from books and from politics, since he wrote the GENIUS OF CHRISTIANITY. He had gained some understanding of German philosophy and Vico. In this work from his later years, he embraces the idea of Progress, as much as an orthodox son of the Church could. He believes that the advancement of knowledge will lead to social progress, and that society, even if it sometimes seems to regress, is always actually moving forward. Bossuet, who he had never criticized thirty years earlier, he now calls out for "an imposing error." That great man, he writes, "has confined historical events in a circle as strict as his genius. He has imprisoned them in an unyielding Christianity—a terrible hoop in which humanity would turn in a sort of eternity, without progress or improvement." Such an admission from this source clearly shows how the prevailing thoughts were shifting.

The notions of development and continuity which were to control all departments of historical study in the later nineteenth century were at the same time being independently promoted by the young historical school in Germany which is associated with the names of Eichhorn, Savigny, and Niebuhr. Their view that laws and institutions are a natural growth or the expression of a people's mind, represents another departure from the ideas of the eighteenth century. It was a repudiation of that "universal reason" which desired to reform the world and its peoples indiscriminately without taking any account of their national histories.

The ideas of development and continuity that would guide all areas of historical study in the late nineteenth century were also being independently advanced by the young historical school in Germany, associated with Eichhorn, Savigny, and Niebuhr. Their belief that laws and institutions develop naturally or reflect a people's mindset marks a shift away from the ideas of the eighteenth century. It rejected the notion of "universal reason," which aimed to reform the world and its peoples without considering their unique national histories.





CHAPTER XV. THE SEARCH FOR A LAW OF PROGRESS:

I. SAINT-SIMON

Amid the intellectual movements in France described in the last chapter the idea of Progress passed into a new phase of its growth. Hitherto it had been a vague optimistic doctrine which encouraged the idealism of reformers and revolutionaries, but could not guide them. It had waited like a handmaid on the abstractions of Nature and Reason; it had hardly realised an independent life. The time had come for systematic attempts to probe its meaning and definitely to ascertain the direction in which humanity is moving. Kant had said that a Kepler or a Newton was needed to find the law of the movement of civilisation. Several Frenchmen now undertook to solve the problem. They did not solve it; but the new science of sociology was founded; and the idea of Progress, which presided at its birth, has been its principal problem ever since.

Amid the intellectual movements in France described in the last chapter, the concept of Progress entered a new phase of development. Until now, it had been a vague optimistic belief that inspired reformers and revolutionaries but could not provide them with clear guidance. It had lingered like a supportive figure to the abstractions of Nature and Reason, barely achieving an independent existence. The moment had arrived for systematic efforts to explore its meaning and to clearly determine the direction in which humanity is headed. Kant had stated that a Kepler or a Newton was necessary to uncover the laws governing the movement of civilization. Several French thinkers took on the challenge to tackle this issue. They didn't find a solution; however, the new field of sociology was established, and the idea of Progress, which was central to its inception, has remained its main focus ever since.

1.

1.

The three thinkers who claimed to have discovered the secret of social development had also in view the practical object of remoulding society on general scientific principles, and they became the founders of sects, Fourier, Saint-Simon, and Comte. They all announced a new era of development as a necessary sequel of the past, an inevitable and desirable stage in the march of humanity, and delineated its features.

The three thinkers who claimed to have found the secret to social development also aimed to reshape society based on general scientific principles, becoming the founders of movements: Fourier, Saint-Simon, and Comte. They all declared a new era of development as a necessary outcome of the past, an unavoidable and beneficial phase in humanity’s progress, and outlined its characteristics.

Comte was the successor of Saint-Simon, as Saint-Simon himself was the successor of Condorcet. Fourier stands quite apart. He claimed that he broke entirely new ground, and acknowledged no masters. He regarded himself as a Newton for whom no Kepler or Galileo had prepared the way. The most important and sanest part of his work was the scheme for organising society on a new principle of industrial co-operation. His general theory of the universe and man's destinies which lay behind his practical plans is so fantastic that it sounds like the dream of a lunatic. Yet many accepted it as the apocalypse of an evangelist.

Comte followed in the footsteps of Saint-Simon, just as Saint-Simon followed Condorcet. Fourier, however, stood out on his own. He asserted that he was breaking completely new ground and had no teachers. He saw himself as a Newton for whom no Kepler or Galileo had paved the way. The most significant and rational part of his work was his plan for organizing society based on a new principle of industrial cooperation. His overarching theory of the universe and humanity’s fate that underpinned his practical ideas is so outlandish it seems like the fantasy of a madman. Still, many saw it as the revelation of an evangelist.

Fourier was moved by the far-reaching effects of Newton's discovery to seek a law which would coordinate facts in the moral world as the principle of gravitation had co-ordinated facts in the physical world, and in 1808 he claimed to have found the secret in what he called the law of Passional Attraction. [Footnote: Theorie des quatre mouvements et des destinees generales. General accounts of his theories will be found in Charles Fourier, sa vie et sa theorie, by his disciple Dr. Ch. Pellarin (2nd ed., 1843), and in Flint, Hist. of Philosophy of History in France, etc., pp. 408 sqq.] The human passions have hitherto been sources of misery; the problem for man is to make them sources of happiness. If we know the law which governs them, we can make such changes in our environment that none of the passions will need to be curbed, and the free indulgence of one will not hinder or compromise the satisfaction of the others.

Fourier was inspired by the profound impact of Newton's discovery to find a law that would connect events in the moral world, similar to how the principle of gravitation connected events in the physical world. In 1808, he claimed to have uncovered this secret, which he referred to as the law of Passional Attraction. [Footnote: Theorie des quatre mouvements et des destinees generales. General accounts of his theories will be found in Charles Fourier, sa vie et sa theorie, by his disciple Dr. Ch. Pellarin (2nd ed., 1843), and in Flint, Hist. of Philosophy of History in France, etc., pp. 408 sqq.] Human passions have, until now, led to suffering; the challenge for humanity is to transform them into sources of happiness. If we understand the law that governs these passions, we can alter our environment in such a way that no passion needs to be suppressed, and the unrestricted expression of one will not interfere with or diminish the fulfillment of the others.

His worthless law for harmonising the passions without restraining them need not detain us. The structure of society, by which he proposed to realise the benefits of his discovery, was based on co-operation, but was not socialistic. The family as a social unit was to be replaced by a larger unit (PHALANGE), economically self-sufficing, and consisting of about 1800 persons, who were to live together in a vast building (PHALANSTERE), surrounded by a domain sufficient to produce all they required. Private property is not abolished; the community will include both rich and poor; all the products of their work are distributed in shares according to the labour, talents, and capital of each member, but a fixed minimum is assured to every one. The scheme was actually tried on a small scale near the forest of Rambouillet in 1832.

His ineffective plan for balancing emotions without controlling them doesn't require our attention. The structure of society he proposed to achieve the benefits of his idea was based on cooperation but wasn't socialist. The family as a social unit was to be replaced by a larger unit (PHALANGE), economically self-sufficient, made up of about 1,800 people who would live together in a large building (PHALANSTERE), surrounded by land enough to produce everything they needed. Private property wasn't eliminated; the community would include both the wealthy and the poor; all the products of their work would be distributed in shares based on each member's labor, skills, and investment, but a guaranteed minimum would be provided to everyone. The plan was actually implemented on a small scale near the forest of Rambouillet in 1832.

This transformation of society, which is to have the effect of introducing harmony among the passions, will mark the beginning of a new epoch. The duration of man's earthly career is 81,000 years, of which 5000 have elapsed. He will now enter upon a long period of increasing harmony, which will be followed by an equal period of decline—like the way up and the way down of Heraclitus. His brief past, the age of his infancy, has been marked by a decline of happiness leading to the present age of "civilisation" which is thoroughly bad—here we see the influence of Rousseau—and from it Fourier's discovery is the clue to lead humanity forth into the epoch in which harmony begins to emerge. But men who have lived in the bad ages need not be pitied, and those who live to-day need not be pessimistic. For Fourier believed in metempsychosis, and could tell you, as if he were the private secretary of the Deity calculating the arithmetical details of the cosmic plan, how many very happy, tolerably happy, and unhappy lives fall to the lot of each soul during the whole 81,000 years. Nor does the prospect end with the life of the earth. The soul of the earth and the human souls attached to it will live again in comets, planets, and suns, on a system of which Fourier knew all the particulars. [Footnote: Details will be found in the Theorie de l'unite universelle, originally published under the title Association domestique-agricole in 1822.]

This transformation of society, meant to bring harmony among our passions, will signal the start of a new era. Humanity's time on Earth is 81,000 years, and 5,000 of those years have already passed. We are now entering a long stretch of growing harmony, followed by an equal stretch of decline—like Heraclitus's path of ascent and descent. Our brief past, the age of infancy, has been marked by a drop in happiness, leading us to the current age of "civilization," which is completely negative—reflecting Rousseau's influence—and from this, Fourier's discovery serves as the guide to move humanity into the age where harmony starts to emerge. However, people who lived in the bad times shouldn't be pitied, and those of us living today shouldn't be filled with pessimism. Fourier believed in metempsychosis and could tell you, as if he were the private secretary of the Deity calculating the details of the cosmic plan, how many very happy, moderately happy, and unhappy lives each soul experiences over the entire 81,000 years. The outlook doesn't end with life on Earth. The Earth’s soul and the human souls connected to it will live on in comets, planets, and suns, in a system of which Fourier knew all the details. [Footnote: Details will be found in the Theorie de l'unite universelle, originally published under the title Association domestique-agricole in 1822.]

These silly speculations would not deserve even this slight indication of their purport were it not that Fourier founded a sect and had a considerable body of devoted followers. His "discovery" was acclaimed by Beranger:

These silly speculations wouldn't even deserve this slight mention of their meaning if it weren't for the fact that Fourier started a movement and gathered a significant number of loyal followers. His "discovery" was praised by Beranger:

   Fourier nous dit: Sors de la fange,
    Peuple en proie aux deceptions,
    Travaille, groupe par phalange,
    Dans un cercle d'attractions;
    La terre, apres tant de desastres,
    Forme avec le ciel un hymen,
    Et la loi qui regit les astres,
    Donne la paix au genre humain.
   Fourier tells us: Rise from the mud,  
    People caught in deceptions,  
    Work, group by phalanx,  
    In a circle of attractions;  
    The earth, after so many disasters,  
    Joins with the sky in a union,  
    And the law that governs the stars,  
    Brings peace to humankind.  

Ten years after his death (1837) an English writer tells us that "the social theory of Fourier is at the present moment engrossing the attention and exciting the apprehensions of thinking men, not only in France but in almost every country in Europe." [Footnote: R. Blakey, History of the Philosophy of Mind, vol. iv. p. 293 (1848). Fourier, born 1772, died in 1837. His principal disciple was Victor Considerant.] Grotesque as was the theoretical background of his doctrines, he helped to familiarise the world with the idea of indefinite Progress.

Ten years after his death (1837), an English writer notes that "Fourier's social theory is currently capturing the attention and raising concerns among thoughtful people, not just in France but in almost every country in Europe." [Footnote: R. Blakey, History of the Philosophy of Mind, vol. iv. p. 293 (1848). Fourier, born 1772, died in 1837. His main disciple was Victor Considerant.] Despite the bizarre nature of his theories, he played a significant role in making the idea of limitless progress more widely known.

2.

2.

"The imagination of poets has placed the golden age in the cradle of the human race. It was the age of iron they should have banished there. The golden age is not behind us, but in front of us. It is the perfection of social order. Our fathers have not seen it; our children will arrive there one day, and it is for us to clear the way for them."

"The imagination of poets has envisioned the golden age as the beginning of humanity. They should have associated it with the age of iron instead. The golden age isn’t in the past; it’s ahead of us. It represents the ideal social order. Our ancestors didn’t experience it; our children will reach it someday, and it’s our responsibility to pave the path for them."

The Comte de Saint-Simon, who wrote these words in 1814, was one of the liberal nobles who had imbibed the ideas of the Voltairian age and sympathised with the spirit of the Revolution. In his literary career from 1803 to his death in 1825 he passed through several phases of thought, [Footnote: They are traced in G. Weill's valuable monograph, Saint-Simon et son oeuvre, 1894.] but his chief masters were always Condorcet and the physiologists, from whom he derived his two guiding ideas that ethics and politics depend ultimately on physics and that history is progress.

The Comte de Saint-Simon, who wrote these words in 1814, was one of the liberal nobles who embraced the ideas of the Enlightenment era and aligned himself with the spirit of the Revolution. Throughout his literary career from 1803 until his death in 1825, he went through several phases of thought, [Footnote: They are traced in G. Weill's valuable monograph, Saint-Simon et son oeuvre, 1894.] but his main influences were always Condorcet and the physiologists, from whom he gained his two main beliefs: that ethics and politics ultimately rely on physics and that history is a process of progress.

Condorcet had interpreted history by the progressive movement of knowledge. That, Saint-Simon said, is the true principle, but Condorcet applied it narrowly, and committed two errors. He did not understand the social import of religion, and he represented the Middle Ages as a useless interruption of the forward movement. Here Saint-Simon learned from the religious reaction. He saw that religion has a natural and legitimate social role and cannot be eliminated as a mere perversity. He expounded the doctrine that all social phenomena cohere. A religious system, he said, always corresponds to the stage of science which the society wherein it appears has reached; in fact, religion is merely science clothed in a form suitable to the emotional needs which it satisfies. And as a religious system is based on the contemporary phase of scientific development, so the political system of an epoch corresponds to the religious system. They all hang together. Medieval Europe does not represent a temporary triumph of obscurantism, useless and deplorable, but a valuable and necessary stage in human progress. It was a period in which an important principle of social organisation was realised, the right relation of the spiritual and temporal powers.

Condorcet viewed history as a progressive movement of knowledge. Saint-Simon agreed, saying that's the real principle, but he thought Condorcet focused too narrowly and made two mistakes. He failed to grasp the social significance of religion and portrayed the Middle Ages as a pointless break in progress. Here, Saint-Simon learned from the religious backlash. He recognized that religion has a natural and valid social role and can't be dismissed as just a flaw. He explained the idea that all social phenomena are connected. He stated that a religious system always matches the level of science that the society in which it arises has achieved; in fact, religion is simply science presented in a way that meets emotional needs. Just as a religious system is based on the current stage of scientific progress, the political system of a time aligns with the religious system. They are all interconnected. Medieval Europe isn't just a temporary victory of ignorance that's useless and regrettable; it's a crucial and necessary phase in human progress. It was a time when an important principle of social organization was realized: the proper relationship between spiritual and temporal powers.

It is evident that these views transformed the theory of Condorcet into a more acceptable shape. So long as the medieval tract of time appeared to be an awkward episode, contributing nothing to the forward movement but rather thwarting and retarding it, Progress was exposed to the criticism that it was an arbitrary synthesis, only partly borne out by historical facts and supplying no guarantees for the future. And so long as rationalists of the Encyclopaedic school regarded religion as a tiresome product of ignorance and deceit, the social philosophy which lay behind the theory of Progress was condemned as unscientific; because, in defiance of the close cohesion of social phenomena, it refused to admit that religion, as one of the chief of those phenomena, must itself participate and co-operate in Progress.

It’s clear that these perspectives reshaped Condorcet's theory into something more acceptable. As long as the medieval period was seen as an awkward phase that contributed nothing to progress and even hindered it, the idea of Progress faced criticism for being an arbitrary mix that was only partially supported by historical facts and offered no guarantees for the future. Furthermore, as long as rationalists from the Encyclopedic school viewed religion as a frustrating byproduct of ignorance and deceit, the social philosophy behind the theory of Progress was dismissed as unscientific. This was because, despite the strong connection among social phenomena, it refused to acknowledge that religion, as one of the main phenomena, had to be involved in and support Progress.

Condorcet had suggested that the value of history lies in affording data for foreseeing the future. Saint-Simon raised this suggestion to a dogma. But prevision was impossible on Condorcet's unscientific method. In order to foretell, the law of the movement must be discovered, and Condorcet had not found or even sought a law. The eighteenth century thinkers had left Progress a mere hypothesis based on a very insufficient induction; their successors sought to lift it to the rank of a scientific hypothesis, by discovering a social law as valid as the physical law of gravitation. This was the object both of Saint-Simon and of Comte.

Condorcet suggested that the value of history comes from providing information to predict the future. Saint-Simon elevated this idea to a principle. However, predicting the future was impossible with Condorcet's unscientific approach. To make accurate predictions, the law of movement needs to be identified, and Condorcet neither found nor even looked for such a law. The thinkers of the eighteenth century had left Progress as just a theory based on a very limited set of observations; their successors aimed to elevate it to the level of a scientific theory by discovering a social law as valid as the physical law of gravity. This was the goal of both Saint-Simon and Comte.

The "law" which Saint-Simon educed from history was that epochs of organisation or construction, and epochs of criticism or revolution, succeed each other alternately. The medieval period was a time of organisation, and was followed by a critical, revolutionary period, which has now come to an end and must be succeeded by another epoch of organisation. Having discovered the clew to the process, Saint-Simon is able to predict. As our knowledge of the universe has reached or is reaching a stage which is no longer conjectural but POSITIVE in all departments, society will be transformed accordingly; a new PHYSICIST religion will supersede Christianity and Deism; men of science will play the role of organisers which the clergy played in the Middle Ages.

The "law" that Saint-Simon drew from history was that periods of organization or construction alternate with periods of criticism or revolution. The medieval period was a time of organization, followed by a critical, revolutionary period that has now ended and must be succeeded by another period of organization. Having found the key to this process, Saint-Simon can make predictions. As our understanding of the universe has reached or is reaching a point that is no longer based on guesswork but POSITIVE in all areas, society will be transformed accordingly; a new PHYSICIST religion will replace Christianity and Deism; scientists will take on the role of organizers that the clergy held in the Middle Ages.

As the goal of the development is social happiness, and as the working classes form the majority, the first step towards the goal will be the amelioration of the lot of the working classes. This will be the principal problem of government in reorganising society, and Saint-Simon's solution of the problem was socialism. He rejected the watchwords of liberalism—democracy, liberty, and equality—with as much disdain as De Maistre and the reactionaries.

As the aim of development is to enhance social happiness, and since the working class makes up the majority, the first step toward this goal will be improving the conditions of the working class. This will be the main challenge for the government in restructuring society, and Saint-Simon's solution to this challenge was socialism. He dismissed the slogans of liberalism—democracy, freedom, and equality—with just as much contempt as De Maistre and the reactionaries.

The announcement of a future age of gold, which I quoted above, is taken from a pamphlet which he issued, in conjunction with his secretary, Augustin Thierry the historian, after the fall of Napoleon. [Footnote: De la reorganisation de la societe europeenne, p. 111 (1814).] In it he revived the idea of the Abbe de Saint-Pierre for the abolition of war, and proposed a new organisation of Europe more ambitious and Utopian than the Abbe's league of states. At this moment he saw in parliamentary government, which the restored Bourbons were establishing in France, a sovran remedy for political disorder, and he imagined that if this political system were introduced in all the states of Europe a long step would have been taken to the perpetuation of peace. If the old enemies France and England formed a close alliance there would be little difficulty in creating ultimately a European state like the American Commonwealth, with a parliamentary government supreme over the state governments. Here is the germ of the idea of a "parliament of man."

The announcement of a future age of gold, which I quoted above, comes from a pamphlet he published alongside his secretary, Augustin Thierry the historian, after Napoleon's fall. [Footnote: De la reorganisation de la societe europeenne, p. 111 (1814).] In it, he revived the idea of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre about abolishing war and proposed a new organization of Europe that was more ambitious and utopian than the Abbé's league of states. At that time, he viewed parliamentary government, being established by the restored Bourbons in France, as a sovereign remedy for political chaos, and he believed that if this political system were adopted by all the states in Europe, it would take a significant step toward lasting peace. If the traditional rivals, France and England, formed a close alliance, it would be relatively easy to eventually create a European state similar to the American Commonwealth, with a parliamentary government that would be supreme over state governments. This is the seed of the idea of a "parliament of man."

3.

3.

Saint-Simon, however, did not construct a definite system for the attainment of social perfection. He left it to disciples to develop the doctrine which he sketched. In the year of his death (1825) Olinde Rodrigues and Enfantin founded a journal, the Producteur, to present to humanity the one thing which humanity, in the opinion of their master, then most needed, a new general doctrine. [Footnote: The best study of the Saint-Simonian school is that of G. Weill, L'Ecole saint-simonienne, son histoire, son influence jusqu'a nos jours (1896), to which I am much indebted.]

Saint-Simon, however, did not create a specific system for achieving social perfection. He left it to his followers to elaborate on the ideas he outlined. In the year of his death (1825), Olinde Rodrigues and Enfantin started a journal, the Producteur, to present to humanity what they believed was most needed at the time, a new overall doctrine. [Footnote: The best study of the Saint-Simonian school is that of G. Weill, L'Ecole saint-simonienne, son histoire, son influence jusqu'a nos jours (1896), to which I am much indebted.]

History shows that peoples have been moving from isolation to union, from war to peace, from antagonism to association. The programme for the future is association scientifically organised. The Catholic Church in the Middle Ages offered the example of a great social organisation resting on a general doctrine. The modern world must also be a social organisation, but the general doctrine will be scientific, not religious. The spiritual power must reside, not in priests but in savants, who will direct the progress of science and public education. Each member of the community will have his place and duties assigned to him. Society consists of three classes of workers—industrial workers, savants, and artists. A commission of eminent workers of each class will determine the place of every individual according to his capacities. Complete equality is absurd; inequality, based on merit, is reasonable and necessary. It is a modern error to distrust state authority. A power directing national forces is requisite, to propose great ideas and to make the innovations necessary for Progress. Such an organisation will promote progress in all domains: in science by co-operation, in industry by credit, and in art too, for artists will learn to express the ideas and sentiments of their own age. There are signs already of a tendency towards something of this kind; its realisation must be procured, not by revolution but by gradual change.

History shows that people have been moving from isolation to unity, from war to peace, and from conflict to collaboration. The future agenda is a scientifically organized association. The Catholic Church during the Middle Ages was an example of a large social organization based on a universal doctrine. The modern world must also be a social organization, but the universal doctrine will be scientific, not religious. The spiritual power should lie, not with priests, but with scholars, who will guide the advancement of science and public education. Each community member will have their role and responsibilities assigned to them. Society is made up of three groups of workers—industrial workers, scholars, and artists. A commission of distinguished workers from each group will decide the role of every individual based on their abilities. Total equality is unrealistic; inequality based on merit is rational and necessary. It is a modern mistake to be suspicious of state authority. A power that directs national efforts is needed to propose grand ideas and implement the changes necessary for progress. Such an organization will foster progress in all areas: in science through cooperation, in industry through credit, and in art as artists learn to convey the ideas and emotions of their time. Signs of this tendency are already visible; its realization should be achieved not through revolution but through gradual change.

In the authoritarian character of the organisation to which these apostles of Progress wished to entrust the destinies of man we may see the influence of the great theocrat and antagonist of Progress, Joseph de Maistre. He taught them the necessity of a strong central power and the danger of liberty.

In the authoritarian nature of the organization that these advocates of Progress wanted to hand over humanity's future to, we can observe the impact of the prominent theocrat and opponent of Progress, Joseph de Maistre. He taught them the need for a strong central authority and the risks associated with freedom.

But the fullest exposition of the Saint-Simonian doctrine of development was given by Bazard, one of the chief disciples, a few years later. [Footnote: Exposition de la doctrine saint-simonienne, 2 vols., 1830-1.] The human race is conceived as a collective being which unfolds its nature in the course of generations, according to a law—the law of Progress—which may be called the physiological law of the human species, and was discovered by Saint-Simon. It consists in the alternation of ORGANIC and CRITICAL epochs. [Footnote: In the Globe, which became an organ of Saint-Simonism in 1831, Enfantin announced a new principle (Weill, op. cit. 107). He defined the law of history as "the harmony, ceaselessly progressive, of flesh and spirit, of industry and science, of east and west, of woman and man." The role of woman played a large part in the teaching of the sect.

But the most complete explanation of the Saint-Simonian idea of development was provided by Bazard, one of the main followers, a few years later. [Footnote: Exposition de la doctrine saint-simonienne, 2 vols., 1830-1.] Humanity is seen as a collective entity that reveals its essence over generations, following a principle—the principle of Progress—which can be called the physiological law of the human species, and was discovered by Saint-Simon. It involves alternating ORGANIC and CRITICAL periods. [Footnote: In the Globe, which became a voice for Saint-Simonism in 1831, Enfantin introduced a new principle (Weill, op. cit. 107). He defined the law of history as "the constantly evolving harmony of flesh and spirit, of industry and science, of east and west, of woman and man." The role of women was a significant aspect of the sect's teachings.]

Saint-Simon's law of organic and critical ages was definitely accepted by H. de Ferron, a thinker who did not belong to the school, as late as 1867. See his Theorie du progres, vol. ii. p. 433.]

Saint-Simon's law of organic and critical ages was definitively accepted by H. de Ferron, a thinker outside the school, as late as 1867. See his Theorie du progres, vol. ii. p. 433.]

In an organic epoch men discern a destination and harmonise all their energies to reach it. In a critical epoch they are not conscious of a goal, and their efforts are dispersed and discordant. There was an organic period in Greece before the age of Socrates. It was succeeded by a critical epoch lasting to the barbarian invasions. Then came an organic period in the homogeneous societies of Europe from Charlemagne to the end of the fifteenth century, and a new critical period opened with Luther and has lasted till to-day. Now it is time to prepare the advent of the organic age which must necessarily follow.

In a natural era, people see a clear goal and align all their efforts to achieve it. In a critical era, they aren't aware of a specific objective, and their actions are scattered and chaotic. Ancient Greece had an organic period before Socrates’ time. This was followed by a critical era that lasted until the barbarian invasions. Then, there was another organic period in the unified societies of Europe from Charlemagne up until the end of the 15th century, and a new critical period began with Luther that has continued to this day. Now is the time to get ready for the organic age that will inevitably follow.

The most salient fact observable in history is the continual extension of the principle of association, in the series of family, city, nation, supernational Church. The next term must be a still vaster association comprehending the whole race.

The most noticeable fact in history is the ongoing expansion of the principle of association, moving from family to city, then to nation, and to a supranational Church. The next step must be an even larger association that includes the entire human race.

In consequence of the incompleteness of association, the exploitation of the weak by the strong has been a capital feature in human societies, but its successive forms exhibit a gradual mitigation. Cannibalism is followed by slavery, slavery by serfdom, and finally comes industrial exploitation by the capitalist. This latest form of the oppression of the weak depends on the right of property, and the remedy is to transfer the right of inheriting the property of the individual from the family to the state. The society of the future must be socialistic.

Due to the incomplete nature of relationships, the strong have long taken advantage of the weak in human societies, but this has gradually changed over time. Cannibalism gives way to slavery, slavery becomes serfdom, and eventually, we see industrial exploitation by capitalists. This most recent form of oppression relies on property rights, and the solution is to shift the right to inherit property from families to the state. The society of the future needs to be socialist.

The new social doctrine must not only be diffused by education and legislation, it must be sanctioned by a new religion. Christianity will not serve, for Christianity is founded on a dualism between matter and spirit, and has laid a curse on matter. The new religion must be monistic, and its principles are, briefly: God is one, God is all that is, all is God. He is universal love, revealing itself as mind and matter. And to this triad correspond the three domains of religion, science, and industry.

The new social doctrine shouldn't just be spread through education and laws; it needs to be backed by a new religion. Christianity won't work because it's based on a separation between matter and spirit and has a negative view of matter. The new religion needs to be monistic, with principles that can be summed up like this: God is one, God is everything, everything is God. He represents universal love, showing up as both mind and matter. And connected to this triad are the three areas of religion, science, and industry.

In combining their theory with a philosophical religion the Saint-Simonian school was not only true to its master's teaching but obeying an astute instinct. As a purely secular movement for the transformation of society, their doctrine would not have reaped the same success or inspired the same enthusiasm. They were probably influenced too by the pamphlet of Lessing to which Madame de Stael had invited attention, and which one of Saint-Simon's disciples translated.

In blending their theory with a philosophical religion, the Saint-Simonian school not only stayed true to their master’s teachings but also followed a smart instinct. As a purely secular movement aimed at transforming society, their doctrine wouldn’t have achieved the same level of success or inspired as much enthusiasm. They were likely also influenced by the pamphlet from Lessing that Madame de Stael highlighted, which one of Saint-Simon’s followers translated.

The fortunes of the school, the life of the community at Menilmontant under the direction of Enfantin, the persecution, the heresies, the dispersion, the attempt to propagate the movement in Egypt, the philosophical activity of Enfantin and Lemonnier under the Second Empire, do not claim our attention; the curious story is told in M. Weill's admirable monograph. [Footnote: It may be noticed that Saint-Simonians came to the front in public careers after the revolution of 1848; e.g. Carnot, Reynaud, Charton.] The sect is now extinct, but its influence was wide in its day, and it propagated faith in Progress as the key to history and the law of collective life.[Footnote: Two able converts to the ideas of Saint-Simon seceded from the school at an early stage in consequence of Enfantin's aberrations: Pierre Leroux, whom we shall meet again, and P. J. B. Buchez, who in 1833 published a thoughtful "Introduction a la science de l'histoire," where history is defined as "a science whose end is to foresee the social future of the human species in the order of its free activity" (vol. i. p. 60,. ed. 2, 1842).]

The fortunes of the school, the life of the community in Menilmontant under Enfantin's leadership, the persecution, the heresies, the dispersal, the effort to spread the movement in Egypt, and the philosophical activities of Enfantin and Lemonnier during the Second Empire aren't the focus here; that intriguing story is told in M. Weill's excellent monograph. [Footnote: It's worth noting that Saint-Simonians rose to prominence in public life after the 1848 revolution, such as Carnot, Reynaud, and Charton.] The sect no longer exists, but it had a significant influence in its time, promoting the belief in Progress as the key to history and the principle of collective life. [Footnote: Two notable converts to Saint-Simon's ideas left the school early due to Enfantin's oddities: Pierre Leroux, whom we'll encounter again, and P. J. B. Buchez, who published a thoughtful "Introduction a la science de l'histoire" in 1833, defining history as "a science whose purpose is to anticipate the social future of humanity in the context of its free activity" (vol. i. p. 60, ed. 2, 1842).]





CHAPTER XVI. THE SEARCH FOR A LAW OF PROGRESS: II. COMTE

1.

Auguste Comte did more than any preceding thinker to establish the idea of Progress as a luminary which could not escape men's vision. The brilliant suggestions of Saint-Simon, the writings of Bazard and Enfantin, the vagaries of Fourier, might be dismissed as curious rather than serious propositions, but the massive system wrought out by Comte's speculative genius—his organic scheme of human knowledge, his elaborate analysis of history, his new science of sociology—was a great fact with which European thought was forced to reckon. The soul of this system was Progress, and the most important problem he set out to solve was the determination of its laws.

Auguste Comte did more than any previous thinker to establish the concept of Progress as a guiding light that couldn't be ignored. The insightful ideas of Saint-Simon, the writings of Bazard and Enfantin, and the eccentric theories of Fourier may be seen as interesting rather than serious proposals, but the comprehensive system created by Comte's imaginative thinking—his structured approach to human knowledge, his detailed analysis of history, and his innovative science of sociology—was a significant reality that European thought had to address. The core of this system was Progress, and the main challenge he aimed to tackle was figuring out its principles.

His originality is not dimmed by the fact that he owed to Saint-Simon more than he afterwards admitted or than his disciples have been willing to allow. He collaborated with him for several years, and at this time enthusiastically acknowledged the intellectual stimulus he received from the elder savant. [Footnote: Comte collaborated with Saint-Simon from 1818-1822. The final rupture came in 1824. The question of their relations is cleared up by Weill (Saint-Simon, chap. xi.). On the quarrel see also Ostwald, Auguste Comte (1914), 13 sqq.] But he derived from Saint-Simon much more than the stimulation of his thoughts in a certain direction. He was indebted to him for some of the characteristic ideas of his own system. He was indebted to him for the principle which lay at the very basis of his system, that the social phenomena of a given period and the intellectual state of the society cohere and correspond. The conception that the coming age was to be a period of organisation like the Middle Ages, and the idea of the government of savants, are pure Saint-Simonian doctrine. And the fundamental idea of a POSITIVE philosophy had been apprehended by Saint-Simon long before he was acquainted with his youthful associate.

His originality isn't lessened by the fact that he owed more to Saint-Simon than he later admitted or than his followers are willing to acknowledge. He worked closely with him for several years and during that time, he openly recognized the intellectual inspiration he gained from the older scholar. [Footnote: Comte collaborated with Saint-Simon from 1818-1822. The final split occurred in 1824. The details of their relationship are clarified by Weill (Saint-Simon, chap. xi.). For more on the disagreement, see also Ostwald, Auguste Comte (1914), 13 sqq.] However, he gained much more from Saint-Simon than just the stimulation of his ideas in a specific direction. He was also indebted to him for some of the defining concepts of his own system. He relied on him for the principle that the social phenomena of a particular time relate and correspond to the intellectual condition of society. The notion that the upcoming era would be characterized by organization similar to the Middle Ages, and the idea of governance by scholars, are purely Saint-Simon's teachings. Moreover, the core concept of a POSITIVE philosophy was recognized by Saint-Simon long before he met his younger associate.

But Comte had a more methodical and scientific mind, and he thought that Saint-Simon was premature in drawing conclusions as to the reformation of societies and industries before the positive philosophy had been constructed. He published—he was then only twenty-two—in 1822 a "Plan of the scientific operations necessary for the re-organisation of society," which was published under another title two years later by Saint-Simon, and it was over this that the friends quarrelled. This work contains the principles of the positive philosophy which he was soon to begin to work out; it announces already the "law of the Three Stages."

But Comte had a more organized and scientific mindset, and he believed that Saint-Simon was too quick to draw conclusions about the reform of societies and industries before a solid positive philosophy was established. At just twenty-two, he published in 1822 a "Plan of the scientific operations necessary for the re-organization of society," which was released under a different title two years later by Saint-Simon, leading to a dispute between the two friends. This work contains the principles of the positive philosophy that he was about to develop; it already introduces the "law of the Three Stages."

The first volume of the "Cours de philisophie positive" appeared in 1830; it took him twelve years more to complete the exposition of his system. [Footnote: With vol. vi., 1842.]

The first volume of the "Cours de philosophie positive" was published in 1830; it took him another twelve years to finish explaining his system. [Footnote: With vol. vi., 1842.]

2.

2.

The "law of Three Stages" is familiar to many who have never read a line of his writings. That men first attempted to explain natural phenomena by the operation of imaginary deities, then sought to interpret them by abstractions, and finally came to see that they could only be understood by scientific methods, observation, and experiment—this was a generalisation which had already been thrown out by Turgot. Comte adopted it as a fundamental psychological law, which has governed every domain of mental activity and explains the whole story of human development. Each of our principal conceptions, every branch of knowledge, passes successively through these three states which he names the theological, the metaphysical, and the positive or scientific. In the first, the mind invents; in the second, it abstracts; in the third, it submits itself to positive facts; and the proof that any branch of knowledge has reached the third stage is the recognition of invariable natural laws.

The "law of Three Stages" is known by many who have never actually read his work. First, people tried to explain natural events through the actions of imaginary gods, then they looked for explanations through abstract concepts, and finally, they realized that these phenomena could only be understood through scientific methods, observation, and experimentation. This general idea had already been put forth by Turgot. Comte took it on as a key psychological principle that has influenced all areas of mental activity and explains the entire story of human progress. Each of our main ideas, every field of knowledge, goes through these three stages, which he calls theological, metaphysical, and positive or scientific. In the first stage, the mind creates; in the second, it abstracts; and in the third, it adheres to observable facts. The proof that any field of knowledge has reached the third stage is the acknowledgment of unchanging natural laws.

But, granting that this may be the key to the history of the sciences, of physics, say, or botany, how can it explain the history of man, the sequence of actual historical events? Comte replies that history has been governed by ideas; "the whole social mechanism is ultimately based on opinions." Thus man's history is essentially a history of his opinions; and these are subject to the fundamental psychological law.

But, even if this might be the key to understanding the history of the sciences, like physics or botany, how can it explain the history of humanity and the sequence of actual historical events? Comte answers that history has been driven by ideas; "the entire social system is ultimately based on opinions." So, human history is fundamentally a history of opinions, and these are influenced by a basic psychological law.

It must, however, be observed that all branches of knowledge are not in the same stage simultaneously. Some may have reached the metaphysical, while others are still lagging behind in the theological; some may have become scientific, while others have not passed from the metaphysical. Thus the study of physical phenomena has already reached the positive stage; but the study of social phenomena has not. The central aim of Comte, and his great achievement in his own opinion, was to raise the study of social phenomena from the second to the third stage.

It should be noted that not all fields of knowledge progress at the same rate. Some have advanced to the metaphysical level, while others are still stuck in the theological phase; some have become scientific, while others haven’t moved beyond the metaphysical. For instance, the study of physical phenomena has already reached a positive stage, but the study of social phenomena has not. Comte’s main goal and what he considered his greatest achievement was to elevate the study of social phenomena from the second stage to the third.

When we proceed to apply the law of the three stages to the general course of historical development, we are met at the outset by the difficulty that the advance in all the domains of activity is not simultaneous. If at a given period thought and opinions are partly in the theological, partly in the metaphysical, and partly in the scientific state, how is the law to be applied to general development? One class of ideas, Comte says, must be selected as the criterion, and this class must be that of social and moral ideas, for two reasons. In the first place, social science occupies the highest rank in the hierarchy of sciences, on which he laid great stress. [Footnote: Cours de phil. pos. v. 267. Law of consensus: op. cit. iv. 347 sqq., 364, 505, 721, 735.] In the second, those ideas play the principal part for the majority of men, and the most ordinary phenomena are the most important to consider. When, in other classes of ideas, the advance is at any time more rapid, this only means an indispensable preparation for the ensuing period.

When we start applying the law of the three stages to the overall progression of history, we quickly encounter the issue that advances in all areas of activity don’t happen at the same time. If at a certain point in time thoughts and opinions are partly theological, partly metaphysical, and partly scientific, how can we apply this law to general development? One category of ideas, Comte argues, needs to be chosen as the standard, and this category should be social and moral ideas, for two reasons. First, social science holds the highest position in the hierarchy of sciences, which he emphasized greatly. [Footnote: Cours de phil. pos. v. 267. Law of consensus: op. cit. iv. 347 sqq., 364, 505, 721, 735.] Second, these ideas are the most significant for the majority of people, and the most common phenomena are the most crucial to examine. When other ideas progress more quickly, it simply indicates necessary preparation for the upcoming period.

The movement of history is due to the deeply rooted though complex instinct which pushes man to ameliorate his condition incessantly, to develop in all ways the sum of his physical, moral, and intellectual life. And all the phenomena of his social life are closely cohesive, as Saint-Simon had pointed out. By virtue of this cohesion, political, moral, and intellectual progress are inseparable from material progress, and so we find that the phases of his material development correspond to intellectual changes. The principle of consensus or "solidarity," which secures harmony and order in the development, is as important as the principle of the three stages which governs the onward movement. This movement, however, is not in a right line, but displays a series of oscillations, unequal and variable, round a mean motion which tends to prevail. The three general causes of variation, according to Comte, are race, climate, and deliberate political action (such as the retrograde policies of Julian the Apostate or Napoleon). But while they cause deflections and oscillation, their power is strictly limited; they may accelerate or retard the movement, but they cannot invert its order; they may affect the intensity of the tendencies in a given situation, but cannot change their nature.

The flow of history is driven by a deeply ingrained but complex instinct that urges humans to constantly improve their situation and to develop all aspects of their physical, moral, and intellectual lives. All aspects of social life are tightly interconnected, as Saint-Simon noted. Because of this interconnectedness, political, moral, and intellectual progress cannot be separated from material progress, and we see that stages of material development align with intellectual changes. The idea of consensus or "solidarity," which ensures harmony and order in this development, is just as crucial as the principle of the three stages that guides progress. This movement isn't linear; instead, it shows a series of fluctuations, uneven and variable, around an average motion that tends to dominate. According to Comte, the three main causes of variation are race, climate, and intentional political action (like the backward policies of Julian the Apostate or Napoleon). However, while these causes lead to shifts and fluctuations, their influence is limited; they can speed up or slow down the movement, but they cannot reverse its order. They may affect the strength of the tendencies in a specific situation but cannot alter their fundamental nature.

3.

3.

In the demonstration of his laws by the actual course of civilisation, Comte adopts what he calls "the happy artifice of Condorcet," and treats the successive peoples who pass on the torch as if they were a single people running the race. This is "a rational fiction," for a people's true successors are those who pursue its efforts. And, like Bossuet and Condorcet, he confined his review to European civilisation; he considered only the ELITE or advance guard of humanity. He deprecated the introduction of China or India, for instance, as a confusing complication. He ignored the ROLES of Brahmanism, Buddhism, Mohammedanism. His synthesis, therefore, cannot claim to be a synthesis of universal history; it is only a synthesis of the movement of European history. In accordance with the law of the three stages, the development falls into three great periods. The first or Theological came to an end about A.D. 1400, and the second or Metaphysical is now nearing its close, to make way for the third or Positive, for which Comte was preparing the way.

In demonstrating his laws through the actual progression of civilization, Comte uses what he refers to as "the clever trick of Condorcet," treating the successive peoples who carry the torch as if they were a single community running a race. This is "a rational fiction," since a people's true successors are those who continue its efforts. Like Bossuet and Condorcet, he limited his focus to European civilization, considering only the ELITE or vanguard of humanity. He dismissed the inclusion of China or India, for example, as an unnecessary complication. He overlooked the ROLES of Brahmanism, Buddhism, and Islam. Therefore, his synthesis cannot claim to be an overview of universal history; it is merely a synthesis of the movement of European history. According to the law of the three stages, the development is divided into three major periods. The first, or Theological, ended around A.D. 1400, while the second, or Metaphysical, is now nearing its conclusion, paving the way for the third, or Positive, for which Comte was preparing.

The Theological period has itself three stages, in which Fetishism, Polytheism, and Monotheism successively prevail. The chief social characteristics of the Polytheistic period are the institution of slavery and the coincidence or "confusion" of the spiritual and temporal powers. It has two stages: the theocratic, represented by Egypt, and the military, represented by Rome, between which Greece stands in a rather embarrassing and uneasy position.

The Theological period has three stages, where Fetishism, Polytheism, and Monotheism dominate in succession. The main social features of the Polytheistic period are the existence of slavery and the overlap or "confusion" between spiritual and temporal powers. It includes two stages: the theocratic stage, exemplified by Egypt, and the military stage, represented by Rome, with Greece caught in a somewhat awkward and uncomfortable position in between.

The initiative for the passage to the Monotheistic period came from Judaea, and Comte attempts to show that this could not have been otherwise. His analysis of this period is the most interesting part of his survey. The chief feature of the political system corresponding to monotheism is the separation of the spiritual and temporal powers; the function of the spiritual power being concerned with education, and that of the temporal with action, in the wide senses of those terms. The defects of this dual system were due to the irrational theology. But the theory of papal infallibility was a great step in intellectual and social progress, by providing a final jurisdiction, without which society would have been troubled incessantly by contests arising from the vague formulae of dogmas. Here Comte had learned from Joseph de Maistre. But that thinker would not have been edified when Comte went on to declare that in the passage from polytheism to monotheism the religious spirit had really declined, and that one of the merits of Catholicism was that it augmented the domain of human wisdom at the expense of divine inspiration. [Footnote: Cours de philosophic positive, vi. 354.] If it be said that the Catholic system promoted the empire of the clergy rather than the interests of religion, this was all to the good; for it placed the practical use of religion in "the provisional elevation of a noble speculative corporation eminently able to direct opinions and morals."

The push for the shift to the Monotheistic period came from Judaea, and Comte tries to demonstrate that this was unavoidable. His analysis of this period is the most fascinating part of his study. The main characteristic of the political system associated with monotheism is the separation of spiritual and temporal powers; the spiritual power focuses on education, while the temporal power deals with action, broadly defined. The shortcomings of this dual system stemmed from irrational theology. However, the theory of papal infallibility marked a significant advancement in intellectual and social progress by providing a final authority, without which society would have been constantly disturbed by disputes arising from vague dogmas. Comte learned this from Joseph de Maistre. But that thinker would not have been pleased when Comte claimed that in the transition from polytheism to monotheism, the religious spirit had actually diminished, and one of the strengths of Catholicism was that it expanded the realm of human wisdom at the expense of divine inspiration. [Footnote: Cours de philosophic positive, vi. 354.] If it is argued that the Catholic system favored the dominance of the clergy over the interests of religion, that was actually beneficial; it placed the practical application of religion in "the temporary elevation of a noble speculative corporation exceptionally capable of guiding opinions and morals."

But Catholic monotheism could not escape dissolution. The metaphysical spirit began to operate powerfully on the notions of moral philosophy, as soon as the Catholic organisation was complete; and Catholicism, because it could not assimilate this intellectual movement, lost its progressive character and stagnated.

But Catholic monotheism couldn't avoid breaking apart. The metaphysical mindset started to significantly influence moral philosophy as soon as the Catholic organization was fully established; and since Catholicism couldn't adapt to this intellectual shift, it lost its forward momentum and became stagnant.

The decay began in the fourteenth century, where Comte dates the beginning of the Metaphysical period—a period of revolution and disorder. In the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries the movement is spontaneous and unconscious; from the sixteenth till to-day it has proceeded under the direction of a philosophical spirit which is negative and not constructive. This critical philosophy has only accelerated a decomposition which began spontaneously. For as theology progresses it becomes less consistent and less durable, and as its conceptions become less irrational, the intensity of the emotions which they excite decreases. Fetishism had deeper roots than polytheism and lasted longer; and polytheism surpassed monotheism in vigour and vitality.

The decline started in the fourteenth century, which is when Comte marks the start of the Metaphysical period—a time of upheaval and chaos. During the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, the movement was spontaneous and unconscious; from the sixteenth century to today, it has unfolded under the influence of a philosophical spirit that is negative rather than constructive. This critical philosophy has only sped up a breakdown that began on its own. As theology advances, it becomes less coherent and less sustainable, and as its ideas become less irrational, the strength of the emotions they provoke diminishes. Fetishism had deeper roots than polytheism and lasted longer; polytheism was more vigorous and dynamic than monotheism.

Yet the critical philosophy was necessary to exhibit the growing need of solid reorganisation and to prove that the decaying system was incapable of directing the world any longer. Logically it was very imperfect, but it was justified by its success. The destructive work was mainly done in the seventeenth century by Hobbes, Spinoza, and Bayle, of whom Hobbes was the most effective. In the eighteenth all prominent thinkers participated in developing this negative movement, and Rousseau gave it the practical stimulus which saved it from degenerating into an unfruitful agitation. Of particular importance was the great fallacy, which Helvetius propagated, that human intellects are equal. This error was required for the full development of the critical doctrine. For it supported the dogmas of popular sovranty and social equality, and justified the principle of the right of private judgement.

Yet the critical philosophy was necessary to show the growing need for solid reorganization and to prove that the failing system could no longer guide the world. Logically, it was quite flawed, but its success justified it. The destructive work was primarily done in the seventeenth century by Hobbes, Spinoza, and Bayle, with Hobbes being the most influential. In the eighteenth century, all prominent thinkers contributed to this negative movement, and Rousseau provided the practical push that kept it from becoming a pointless agitation. Of particular importance was the major fallacy propagated by Helvetius, which claimed that human intellects are equal. This misconception was essential for the full development of the critical doctrine, as it supported the ideas of popular sovereignty and social equality, and justified the principle of the right to private judgment.

These three principles—popular sovranty, equality, and what he calls the right of free examination—are in Comte's eyes vicious and anarchical.[Footnote #1 Op. cit. iv. 36-38.] But it was necessary that they should be promulgated, because the transition from one organised social system to another cannot be direct; it requires an anarchical interregnum. Popular sovranty is opposed to orderly institutions and condemns all superior persons to dependence on the multitude of their inferiors. Equality, obviously anarchical in its tendency, and obviously untrue (for, as men are not equal or even equivalent to one another, their rights cannot be identical), was similarly necessary to break down the old institutions. The universal claim to the right of free judgement merely consecrates the transitional state of unlimited liberty in the interim between the decline of theology and the arrival of positive philosophy. Comte further remarks that the fall of the spiritual power had led to anarchy in international relations, and if the spirit of nationality were to prevail too far, the result would be a state of things inferior to that of the Middle Ages.

These three principles—popular sovereignty, equality, and what he calls the right to free examination—are, in Comte's view, harmful and chaotic.[Footnote #1 Op. cit. iv. 36-38.] However, it was important for them to be announced because the shift from one organized social system to another can't happen directly; it needs a chaotic transitional period. Popular sovereignty conflicts with orderly institutions and forces all superior individuals into dependence on the masses of their inferiors. Equality, clearly leaning towards chaos and obviously untrue (since people are not equal or even comparable to one another, their rights can't be the same), was also necessary to dismantle the old institutions. The universal claim to the right of free judgment just acknowledges the chaotic state of unrestricted freedom during the period between the decline of theology and the emergence of positive philosophy. Comte also notes that the decline of spiritual authority has caused disorder in international relations, and if the spirit of nationalism goes too far, the outcome would be worse than that of the Middle Ages.

But Comte says for the metaphysical spirit in France that with all its vices it was more disengaged from the prejudices of the old theological regime, and nearer to a true rational positivism than either the German mysticism or the English empiricism of the same period.

But Comte argues that the metaphysical mindset in France, despite its flaws, was more detached from the biases of the old theological system and closer to a genuine rational positivism than both the German mysticism and the English empiricism of that time.

The Revolution was a necessity, to disclose the chronic decomposition of society from which it resulted, and to liberate the modern social elements from the grip of the ancient powers. Comte has praise for the Convention, which he contrasts with the Constituent Assembly with its political fictions and inconsistencies. He pointed out that the great vice in the "metaphysics" of the crisis—that is, in the principles of the revolutionaries—lay in conceiving society out of relation to the past, in ignoring the Middle Ages, and borrowing from Greek and Roman society retrograde and contradictory ideals.

The Revolution was necessary to reveal the ongoing deterioration of society that led to it and to free modern social elements from the hold of ancient powers. Comte praises the Convention, contrasting it with the Constituent Assembly, which he saw as filled with political fictions and inconsistencies. He pointed out that the main flaw in the "metaphysics" of the crisis—that is, in the principles of the revolutionaries—was the idea of viewing society without considering the past, ignoring the Middle Ages, and taking outdated and conflicting ideals from Greek and Roman society.

Napoleon restored order, but he was more injurious to humanity than any other historical person. His moral and intellectual nature was incompatible with the true direction of Progress, which involves the extinction of the theological and military regime of the past. Thus his work, like Julian the Apostate's, exhibits an instance of deflection from the line of Progress. Then came the parliamentary system of the restored Bourbons which Comte designates as a political Utopia, destitute of social principles, a foolish attempt to combine political retrogression with a state of permanent peace.

Napoleon brought back order, but he caused more harm to humanity than any other historical figure. His moral and intellectual values clashed with the true direction of Progress, which aims to eliminate the outdated theological and military systems of the past. Therefore, his achievements, much like those of Julian the Apostate, represent a diversion from the path of Progress. Next, the parliamentary system of the restored Bourbons emerged, which Comte describes as a political Utopia lacking social principles, a misguided effort to merge political backwardness with a constant state of peace.

4.

4.

The critical doctrine has performed its historical function, and the time has come for man to enter upon the Positive stage of his career. To enable him to take this step forward, it is necessary that the study of social phenomena should become a positive science. As social science is the highest in the hierarchy of sciences, it could not develop until the two branches of knowledge which come next in the scale, biology and chemistry, assumed a scientific form. This has recently been achieved, and it is now possible to found a scientific sociology.

The essential theory has fulfilled its historical role, and it's time for humanity to move into the Positive stage of its development. To make this progress, it's crucial for the study of social phenomena to evolve into a positive science. Since social science is the highest in the science hierarchy, it couldn't grow until the two next fields, biology and chemistry, became scientifically established. This has recently happened, and now it's possible to establish a scientific sociology.

This science, like mechanics and biology, has its statics and its dynamics. The first studies the laws of co-existence, the second those of succession; the first contains the theory of order, the second that of progress. The law of consensus or cohesion is the fundamental principle of social statics; the law of the three stages is that of social dynamics. Comte's survey of history, of which I have briefly indicated the general character, exhibits the application of these sociological laws.

This science, like mechanics and biology, has its stability and its change. The first looks at the rules of co-existence, while the second focuses on the rules of progression; the first includes the theory of order, and the second covers the theory of progress. The law of consensus or cohesion is the core principle of social stability; the law of the three stages is the principle of social change. Comte's overview of history, which I’ve briefly outlined, shows how these sociological laws apply.

The capital feature of the third period, which we are now approaching, will be the organisation of society by means of scientific sociology. The world will be guided by a general theory, and this means that it must be controlled by those who understand the theory and will know how to apply it. Therefore society will revive the principle which was realised in the great period of Monotheism, the distinction of a spiritual and a temporal order. But the spiritual order will consist of savants who will direct social life not by theological fictions but by the positive truths of science. They will administer a system of universal education and will draw up the final code of ethics. They will be able, more effectively than the Church, to protect the interests of the lower classes.

The main feature of the third period, which we are now approaching, will be the organization of society through scientific sociology. The world will be guided by a general theory, meaning it will be controlled by those who understand the theory and know how to apply it. As a result, society will revive the principle that was realized during the great era of Monotheism, distinguishing between a spiritual and a temporal order. However, the spiritual order will consist of experts who will guide social life not through theological myths but through the positive truths of science. They will implement a system of universal education and create a final code of ethics. They will be more effective than the Church in safeguarding the interests of the lower classes.

Comte's conviction that the world is prepared for a transformation of this kind is based principally on signs of the decline of the theological spirit and of the military spirit, which he regarded as the two main obstacles to the reign of reason. Catholicism, he says, is now no more than "an imposing historical ruin." As for militarism, the epoch has arrived in which serious and lasting warfare among the ELITE nations will totally cease. The last general cause of warfare has been the competition for colonies. But the colonial policy is now in its decadence (with the temporary exception of England), so that we need not look for future trouble from this source. The very sophism, sometimes put forward to justify war, that it is an instrument of civilisation, is a homage to the pacific nature of modern society.

Comte believes that the world is ready for a change like this mainly because of signs showing the decline of religious thinking and militarism, which he saw as the two biggest barriers to rational thought. He states that Catholicism is now just "an impressive historical relic." Regarding militarism, he argues that we have entered an era where serious and lasting wars among the ELITE nations will completely end. The primary cause of wars has been the race for colonies, but colonial policy is now declining (with the temporary exception of England), so we shouldn't expect future conflicts from this issue. The very argument sometimes used to justify war—that it serves as a means of civilization—is a testament to the peaceful nature of modern society.

We need not follow further the details of Comte's forecast of the Positive period, except to mention that he did not contemplate a political federation. The great European nations will develop each in its own way, with their separate "temporal" organisations. But he contemplated the intervention of a common "spiritual" power, so that all nationalities "under the direction of a homogeneous speculative class will contribute to an identical work, in a spirit of active European patriotism, not of sterile cosmopolitanism."

We don’t need to go into more detail about Comte’s prediction of the Positive period, except to point out that he didn’t foresee a political federation. The major European nations will each grow in their own way, with their own "temporal" structures. However, he did envision the involvement of a shared "spiritual" authority, so that all nationalities "under the guidance of a unified intellectual class will work together on a common goal, in a spirit of active European patriotism, not of empty cosmopolitanism."

Comte claimed, like Saint-Simon, that the data of history, scientifically interpreted, afford the means of prevision. It is interesting to observe how he failed himself as a diviner; how utterly he misapprehended the vitality of Catholicism, how completely his prophecy as to the cessation of wars was belied by the event. He lived to see the Crimean war. [Footnote: He died in 1857.] As a diviner he failed as completely as Saint-Simon and Fourier, whose dream that the nineteenth century would see the beginning of an epoch of harmony and happiness was to be fulfilled by a deadly struggle between capitalism and labour, the civil war in America, the war of 1870, the Commune, Russian pogroms, Armenian massacres, and finally the universal catastrophe of 1914.

Comte argued, similar to Saint-Simon, that the data of history, when interpreted scientifically, provide a way to predict the future. It's interesting to see how he failed as a fortune-teller; he completely misunderstood the strength of Catholicism and his prediction about the end of wars was proven wrong by real events. He lived through the Crimean War. [Footnote: He died in 1857.] As a fortune-teller, he was just as unsuccessful as Saint-Simon and Fourier, whose hope that the nineteenth century would mark the start of an era of peace and happiness was overshadowed by a brutal conflict between capitalism and labor, the American Civil War, the war of 1870, the Commune, Russian pogroms, Armenian massacres, and ultimately the global disaster of 1914.

5.

5.

For the comprehension of history we have perhaps gained as little from Comte's positive laws as from Hegel's metaphysical categories. Both thinkers had studied the facts of history only slightly and partially, a rather serious drawback which enabled them to impose their own constructions with the greater ease. Hegel's method of a PRIORI synthesis was enjoined by his philosophical theory; but in Comte we also find a tendency to a PRIORI treatment. He expressly remarks that the chief social features of the Monotheistic period might almost be constructed a PRIORI.

For understanding history, we might have gained just as little from Comte's positive laws as from Hegel's metaphysical concepts. Both thinkers examined historical facts only to a limited extent, which is a significant shortcoming that allowed them to impose their own interpretations more easily. Hegel's method of a PRIORI synthesis was dictated by his philosophical theory, but Comte also shows a tendency toward a PRIORI analysis. He specifically notes that the key social characteristics of the Monotheistic period could almost be constructed a PRIORI.

The law of the Three Stages is discredited. It may be contended that general Progress depends on intellectual progress, and that theology, metaphysics, and science have common roots, and are ultimately identical, being merely phases in the movement of the intelligence. But the law of this movement, if it is to rank as a scientific hypothesis, must be properly deduced from known causes, and must then be verified by a comparison with historical facts. Comte thought that he fulfilled these requirements, but in both respects his demonstration was defective. [Footnote: Criticism of Comte's assumption that civilisation begins with animism: Weber's criticisms from this point of view are telling (Le Rythme du progres, 73-95). He observes that if Comte had not left the practical and active side of intelligence in the shade and considered only its speculative side, he could not have formulated the law of the Three Stages. He would have seen that "the positive explanation of phenomena has played in every period a preponderant role, though latent, in the march of the human mind." Weber himself suggests a scheme of two states (corresponding to the two-sidedness of the intellect), technical and speculative, practical and theoretical, through the alternation of which intellectual progress has been effected. The first stage was probably practical (he calls it proto-technic). It is to be remembered that when Comte was constructing his system palaeontology was in its infancy.]

The law of the Three Stages is no longer considered valid. One might argue that general progress relies on intellectual progress, and that theology, metaphysics, and science share common origins, ultimately being the same, just different phases in the development of intelligence. However, for this idea to qualify as a scientific hypothesis, it needs to be properly derived from known causes and then validated through a comparison with historical facts. Comte believed he met these criteria, but in both cases, his arguments were lacking. [Footnote: Critique of Comte's belief that civilization starts with animism: Weber's critiques on this point are significant (Le Rythme du progres, 73-95). He notes that if Comte had not overlooked the practical and active dimensions of intelligence and focused solely on its speculative side, he wouldn't have been able to establish the law of the Three Stages. He would have realized that "the positive explanation of phenomena has played a dominant, albeit latent, role in the evolution of human thought." Weber proposes a framework of two states (reflecting the dual nature of intellect), technical and speculative, practical and theoretical, through which intellectual progress has occurred. The first stage was likely practical (which he terms proto-technic). It’s important to remember that when Comte was developing his system, paleontology was just beginning.]

The gravest weakness perhaps in his historical sketch is the gratuitous assumption that man in the earliest stage of his existence had animistic beliefs and that the first phase of his progress was controlled by fetishism. There is no valid evidence that fetishism is not a relatively late development, or that in the myriads of years stretching back beyond our earliest records, during which men decided the future of the human species by their technical inventions and the discovery of fire, they had any views which could be called religious or theological. The psychology of modern savages is no clew to the minds of the people who wrought tools of stone in the world of the mammoth and the RHINOCEROS TICHIRHINUS. If the first stage of man's development, which was of such critical importance for his destinies, was pre-animistic, Comte's law of progress fails, for it does not cover the ground.

The biggest weakness in his historical overview is the unwarranted assumption that early humans had animistic beliefs and that the first stage of their development was driven by fetishism. There's no solid evidence that fetishism isn't a relatively recent development, or that in the countless years before our earliest records, when humans shaped the future of our species through their inventions and the discovery of fire, they had any beliefs that could be called religious or theological. The mindset of modern indigenous people doesn't provide insight into the thoughts of those who made stone tools in the age of mammoths and the RHINOCEROS TICHIRHINUS. If the initial stage of human development, which was crucial for our future, was pre-animistic, then Comte's theory of progress doesn't hold up, as it doesn’t address that aspect.

In another way, Comte's system may be criticised for failing to cover the ground, if it is regarded as a philosophy of history. In accordance with "the happy artifice of Condorcet," he assumes that the growth of European civilisation is the only history that matters, and discards entirely the civilisations, for instance, of India and China. This assumption is much more than an artifice, and he has not scientifically justified it. [Footnote: A propos of the view that only European civilisation matters it has been well observed that "human history is not unitary but pluralistic": F. J. Teggart, The Processes of History, p. 24 (1918).]

In another way, Comte's system can be critiqued for not covering all the bases if we see it as a philosophy of history. Following "the clever construct of Condorcet," he assumes that the advancement of European civilization is the only history that counts, completely ignoring the civilizations of places like India and China. This assumption goes far beyond being just a construct, and he has not scientifically backed it up. [Footnote: Regarding the perspective that only European civilization matters, it has been aptly noted that "human history is not unitary but pluralistic": F. J. Teggart, The Processes of History, p. 24 (1918).]

The reader of the PHILOSOPHIE POSITIVE will also observe that Comte has not grappled with a fundamental question which has to be faced in unravelling the woof of history or seeking a law of events. I mean the question of contingency. It must be remembered that contingency does not in the least affect the doctrine of determinism; it is compatible with the strictest interpretation of the principle of causation. A particular example may be taken to show what it implies. [Footnote: On contingency and the "chapter of accidents" see Cournot, Considerations sur la marche des idees et des evenements dans les temps modernes (1872), i. 16 sqq. I have discussed the subject and given some illustrations in a short paper, entitled "Cleopatra's Nose," in the Annual of the Rationalist Press Association for 1916.]

The reader of the PHILOSOPHIE POSITIVE will also notice that Comte hasn't addressed a key question that needs to be considered when exploring the fabric of history or searching for a pattern in events. I'm talking about the question of contingency. It's important to remember that contingency does not undermine the idea of determinism; it can coexist with the strictest interpretation of causation. A specific example can illustrate what this means. [Footnote: On contingency and the "chapter of accidents" see Cournot, Considerations sur la marche des idees et des evenements dans les temps modernes (1872), i. 16 sqq. I have discussed the subject and given some illustrations in a short paper, entitled "Cleopatra's Nose," in the Annual of the Rationalist Press Association for 1916.]

It may plausibly be argued that a military dictatorship was an inevitable sequence of the French Revolution. This may not be true, but let us assume it. Let us further assume that, given Napoleon, it was inevitable that he should be the dictator. But Napoleon's existence was due to an independent causal chain which had nothing whatever to do with the course of political events. He might have died in his boyhood by disease or by an accident, and the fact that he survived was due to causes which were similarly independent of the causal chain which, as we are assuming, led necessarily to an epoch of monarchical government. The existence of a man of his genius and character at the given moment was a contingency which profoundly affected the course of history. If he had not been there another dictator would have grasped the helm, but obviously would not have done what Napoleon did.

It can be argued that a military dictatorship was a likely outcome of the French Revolution. This might not be accurate, but let's go with that assumption. Additionally, let's assume that with Napoleon in the picture, it was bound to be him who became the dictator. However, Napoleon’s existence stemmed from a separate causal chain that had nothing to do with the political events at play. He could have easily died as a child due to illness or an accident, and the fact that he lived was because of factors that were also unrelated to the chain of events we’re assuming led to a time of monarchical rule. The existence of someone with his talent and character at that specific time was a turning point that significantly changed the course of history. If he hadn’t been there, another dictator would have taken charge, but they clearly wouldn’t have carried out the same actions as Napoleon.

It is clear that the whole history of man has been modified at every stage by such contingencies, which may be defined as the collisions of two independent causal chains. Voltaire was perfectly right when he emphasised the role of chance in history, though he did not realise what it meant. This factor would explain the oscillations and deflections which Comte admits in the movement of historical progression. But the question arises whether it may not also have once and again definitely altered the direction of the movement. Can the factor be regarded as virtually negligible by those who, like Comte, are concerned with the large perspective of human development and not with the details of an episode? Or was Renouvier right in principle when he maintained "the real possibility that the sequence of events from the Emperor Nerva to the Emperor Charlemagne might have been radically different from what it actually was"? [Footnote: He illustrated this proposition by a fanciful reconstruction of European history from 100 to 800 A.D. in his UCHRONIE, 1876. He contended that there is no definite law of progress: "The true law lies in the equal possibility of progress or regress for societies as for individuals."]

It’s evident that the entire history of humanity has been changed at every stage by factors that can be described as the interactions of two independent causal chains. Voltaire was absolutely correct when he highlighted the role of chance in history, even if he didn’t fully grasp its implications. This element would account for the ups and downs that Comte acknowledges in the flow of historical progress. However, the question arises as to whether it might have at times decisively shifted the course of that progress. Can this factor be seen as practically negligible by those, like Comte, who focus on the broader view of human development rather than the specifics of an event? Or was Renouvier fundamentally right when he argued for "the real possibility that the sequence of events from Emperor Nerva to Emperor Charlemagne could have been drastically different from what it actually was"? [Footnote: He demonstrated this idea through a creative reconstruction of European history from 100 to 800 A.D. in his UCHRONIE, 1876. He argued that there is no definite law of progress: "The true law lies in the equal possibility of progress or regress for societies as well as for individuals."]

6.

6.

It does not concern us here to examine the defects of Comte's view of the course of European history. But it interests us to observe that his synthesis of human Progress is, like Hegel's, what I have called a closed system. Just as his own absolute philosophy marked for Hegel the highest and ultimate term of human development, so for Comte the coming society whose organisation he adumbrated was the final state of humanity beyond which there would be no further movement. It would take time to perfect the organisation, and the period would witness a continuous increase of knowledge, but the main characteristics were definitely fixed. Comte did not conceive that the distant future, could he survive to experience it, could contain any surprises for him. His theory of Progress thus differed from the eighteenth century views which vaguely contemplate an indefinite development and only profess to indicate some general tendencies. He expressly repudiated this notion of INDEFINITE progress; the data, he said, justify only the inference of CONTINUOUS progress, which is a different thing.

We don't need to go into the flaws in Comte's view of European history here. However, it’s worth noting that his idea of human Progress, like Hegel's, is what I call a closed system. Just as Hegel's absolute philosophy represented the highest and final stage of human development, for Comte, the future society he envisioned was the ultimate state of humanity, beyond which there would be no more advancement. It would take time to fully develop this organization, and during that time, knowledge would continuously grow, but the main features were firmly established. Comte didn’t believe that the far-off future, if he were to live long enough to see it, would hold any surprises for him. His theory of Progress was different from the vague ideas of the eighteenth century, which considered endless development and only suggested some general trends. He explicitly rejected the idea of INDEFINITE progress; instead, he argued that the evidence only supports the idea of CONTINUOUS progress, which is something entirely different.

A second point in which Comte in his view of Progress differed from the French philosophers of the preceding age is this. Condorcet and his predecessors regarded it exclusively from the eudaemonic point of view. The goal of Progress for them was the attainment of human felicity. With felicity Comte is hardly more concerned than Hegel. The establishment of a fuller harmony between men and their environment in the third stage will no doubt mean happiness. But this consideration lies outside the theory, and to introduce it would only intrude an unscientific element into the analysis. The course of development is determined by intellectual ideas, and he treats these as independent of, and indifferent to, eudaemonic motives.

A second point where Comte's view of Progress differed from that of the French philosophers of the previous era is this. Condorcet and his predecessors looked at it solely from the perspective of human happiness. For them, the aim of Progress was to achieve human well-being. Comte, like Hegel, is hardly focused on well-being. The creation of a deeper harmony between people and their environment in the third stage will likely lead to happiness. However, this aspect is outside the theory, and bringing it in would only add an unscientific element to the analysis. The development trajectory is shaped by intellectual ideas, which he considers independent of, and indifferent to, well-being motives.

A third point to be noted is the authoritarian character of the regime of the future. Comte's ideal state would be as ill to live in for any unfortunate being who values personal liberty as a theocracy or any socialistic Utopia. He had as little sympathy with liberty as Plato or as Bossuet, and less than the eighteenth century philosophers. This feature, common to Comte and the Saint-Simonians, was partly due to the reaction against the Revolution, but it also resulted from the logic of the man of science. If sociological laws are positively established as certainly as the law of gravitation, no room is left for opinion; right social conduct is definitely fixed; the proper functions of every member of society admit of no question; therefore the claim to liberty is perverse and irrational. It is the same argument which some modern exponents of Eugenics use to advocate a state tyranny in the matter of human breeding.

A third point to note is the authoritarian nature of the regime of the future. Comte's ideal state would be just as difficult to live in for anyone who values personal freedom as a theocracy or any socialist Utopia. He had as little sympathy for liberty as Plato or Bossuet, and even less than the philosophers of the eighteenth century. This characteristic, shared by Comte and the Saint-Simonians, was partly a reaction against the Revolution, but it also stemmed from the mindset of a scientist. If sociological laws are established as certainly as the law of gravity, there’s no room for opinion; proper social conduct is clearly defined; the roles of every member of society leave no room for debate; therefore, the claim to liberty is seen as misguided and unreasonable. It’s the same argument some modern proponents of Eugenics use to justify state control over human breeding.

When Comte was writing, the progressive movement in Europe was towards increase of liberty in all its forms, national, civic, political, and economical. On one hand there was the agitation for the release of oppressed nationalities, on the other the growth of liberalism in England and France. The aim of the liberalism of that period was to restrict the functions of government; its spirit was distrust of the state. As a political theory it was defective, as modern Liberals acknowledge, but it was an important expression of the feeling that the interests of society are best furthered by the free interplay of individual actions and aims. It thus implicitly contained or pointed to a theory of Progress sharply opposed to Comte's: that the realisation of the fullest possible measure of individual liberty is the condition of ensuring the maximum of energy and effectiveness in improving our environment, and therefore the condition of attaining public felicity. Right or wrong, this theory reckons with fundamental facts of human nature which Comte ignored.

When Comte was writing, the progressive movement in Europe was focused on expanding liberty in all its forms—national, civic, political, and economic. On one side, there was a push for the liberation of oppressed nationalities, and on the other, the rise of liberalism in England and France. The goal of the liberal movement during that time was to limit the powers of government, stemming from a distrust of the state. As modern Liberals recognize, this political theory had its flaws, but it expressed a significant belief that society's interests are best served by the free exchange of individual actions and goals. It implicitly contained, or hinted at, a theory of Progress that sharply contrasted with Comte's: that achieving the greatest possible level of individual freedom is essential for maximizing energy and effectiveness in improving our surroundings, and thus is key to achieving public happiness. Right or wrong, this theory acknowledges fundamental aspects of human nature that Comte overlooked.

7.

7.

Comte spent the later years of his life in composing another huge work, on social reorganisation. It included a new religion, in which Humanity was the object of worship, but made no other important addition to the speculations of his earlier manhood, though he developed them further.

Comte spent the last years of his life working on another extensive project about social reorganization. It featured a new religion where Humanity was the focus of worship, but it didn’t introduce any major new ideas beyond the thoughts he had developed in his earlier years, although he did elaborate on them further.

The Course of Positive Philosophy was not a book that took the public by storm. We are told by a competent student of social theories in France that the author's name was little known in his own country till about 1855, when his greatness began to win recognition, and his influence to operate. [Footnote: Weill, Hist. du mouvement social, p. 21.] Even then his work can hardly have been widely read. But through men like Littre and Taine, whose conceptions of history were moulded by his teaching, and men like Mill, whom he stimulated, as well as through the disciples who adopted Positivism as a religion, his leading principles, detached from his system, became current in the world of speculation.

The Course of Positive Philosophy wasn't a book that took the public by surprise. A knowledgeable scholar of social theories in France tells us that the author's name was hardly recognized in his own country until around 1855, when he started to gain recognition and his influence began to spread. [Footnote: Weill, Hist. du mouvement social, p. 21.] Even then, it's unlikely his work was widely read. However, through figures like Littre and Taine, whose views on history were shaped by his teachings, and people like Mill, whom he inspired, as well as through followers who embraced Positivism as a belief system, his main ideas, separated from his overall framework, became influential in the world of ideas.

[Footnote: The influence of Comte. The manner in which ideas filter through, as it were, underground and emerge oblivious of their source is illustrated by the German historian Lamprecht's theory of historical development. He surveyed the history of a people as a series of what he called typical periods, each of which is marked by a collective psychical character expressing itself in every department of life. He named this a diapason. Lamprecht had never read Comte, and he imagined that this principle, on which he based his kulturhistorische Methode, was original. But his psychical diapason is the psychical consensus of Comte, whose system, as we have seen, depended on the proposition that a given social organisation corresponds in a definite way to the contemporary stage of mental development; and Comte had derived the principle from Saint-Simon. Cf. his pamphlet Die kulturhistorische Methode (1900). The succession of "typical period" was worked out for Germany in his History of the German People.]

[Footnote: The influence of Comte. The way ideas spread, almost underground, and come to light without awareness of their origins is shown in the German historian Lamprecht's theory of historical development. He looked at the history of a people as a series of what he called typical periods, each marked by a collective psychological character expressed in all areas of life. He referred to this as a diapason. Lamprecht had never read Comte and believed that this principle, which he based his cultural-historical method on, was original. However, his psychological diapason is essentially Comte's psychological consensus, which, as we've seen, was grounded in the idea that a particular social structure corresponds distinctly to the current stage of mental development; and Comte had taken this principle from Saint-Simon. See his pamphlet Die kulturhistorische Methode (1900). The sequence of "typical periods" was developed for Germany in his History of the German People.]

He laid the foundations of sociology, convincing many minds that the history of civilisation is subject to general laws, or, in other words, that a science of society is possible. In England this idea was still a novelty when Mill's System of Logic appeared in 1843.

He established the basics of sociology, persuading many people that the history of civilization follows general laws, or in other words, that a social science is achievable. In England, this concept was still a new idea when Mill's System of Logic was published in 1843.

The publication of this work, which attempted to define the rules for the investigation of truth in all fields of inquiry and to provide tests for the hypotheses of science, was a considerable event, whether we regard its value and range or its prolonged influence on education. Mill, who had followed recent French thought attentively and was particularly impressed by the system of Comte, recognised that a new method of investigating social phenomena had been inaugurated by the thinkers who set out to discover the "law" of human progression. He proclaimed and welcomed it as superior to previous methods, and at the same time pointed out its limitations.

The release of this work, which aimed to define the rules for exploring truth across all fields and to offer tests for scientific hypotheses, was a significant event, considering both its value and impact as well as its lasting influence on education. Mill, who had closely followed recent French thought and was particularly inspired by Comte’s system, acknowledged that a new approach to studying social phenomena had begun with thinkers who aimed to uncover the "law" of human progress. He praised and embraced it as better than earlier methods while also highlighting its limitations.

Till about fifty years ago, he said, generalisations on man and society have erred by implicitly assuming that human nature and society will for ever revolve in the same orbit and exhibit virtually the same phenomena. This is still the view of the ostentatiously practical votaries of common sense in Great Britain; whereas the more reflective minds of the present age, analysing historical records more minutely, have adopted the opinion that the human race is in a state of necessary progression. The reciprocal action between circumstances and human nature, from which social phenomena result, must produce either a cycle or a trajectory. While Vico maintained the conception of periodic cycles, his successors have universally adopted the idea of a trajectory or progress, and are endeavouring to discover its law. [Footnote: Philosophical writers in England in the middle of the century paid more attention to Cousin than to Comte or Saint-Simon. J. D. Morell, in his forgotten History and Critical View of Speculative Philosophy (1846), says that eclecticism is the philosophy of human progress (vol. ii. 635, 2nd ed.). He conceived the movement of humanity as that of a spiral, ever tending to a higher perfection (638).]

Until about fifty years ago, he said, generalizations about humanity and society have been flawed by assuming that human nature and society will always operate in the same way and show nearly the same patterns. This view is still held by the obviously practical supporters of common sense in Great Britain, while the more thoughtful minds of today, examining historical records more closely, believe that humanity is on a path of necessary progression. The interaction between circumstances and human nature, which leads to social phenomena, must either create a cycle or a trajectory. While Vico proposed the idea of periodic cycles, his followers have widely embraced the concept of a trajectory or progress and are trying to uncover its laws. [Footnote: Philosophical writers in England in the middle of the century paid more attention to Cousin than to Comte or Saint-Simon. J. D. Morell, in his forgotten History and Critical View of Speculative Philosophy (1846), claims that eclecticism is the philosophy of human progress (vol. ii. 635, 2nd ed.). He envisioned the movement of humanity as a spiral, always aiming for higher perfection (638).]

But they have fallen into a misconception in imagining that if they can find a law of uniformity in the succession of events they can infer the future from the past terms of the series. For such a law would only be an "empirical law"; it would not be a causal law or an ultimate law. However rigidly uniform, there is no guarantee that it would apply to phenomena outside those from which it was derived. It must itself depend on laws of mind and character (psychology and ethology). When those laws are known and the nature of the dependence is explained, when the determining causes of all the changes constituting the progress are understood, then the empirical law will be elevated to a scientific law, then only will it be possible to predict.

But they've fallen into a misunderstanding by thinking that if they can discover a consistent pattern in the sequence of events, they can predict the future based on past instances. Such a pattern would only be an "empirical law"; it wouldn't be a causal law or a fundamental law. No matter how consistently uniform it is, there's no guarantee it would apply to situations outside of those it's based on. It must rely on laws of the mind and character (psychology and ethology). Once those laws are understood and the nature of their relationships is clarified, and when the determining factors behind all the changes that make up progress are recognized, then the empirical law can be elevated to a scientific law, and only then will it be possible to make predictions.

Thus Mill asserted that if the advanced thinkers who are engaged on the subject succeed in discovering an empirical law from the data of history, it may be converted into a scientific law by deducing it a priori from the principles of human nature. In the meantime, he argued that what is already known of those principles justifies the important conclusion that the order of general human progression will mainly depend on the order of progression in the intellectual convictions of mankind.

Thus, Mill claimed that if the progressive thinkers working on this subject manage to find an empirical law from historical data, it could be transformed into a scientific law by deriving it a priori from the principles of human nature. In the meantime, he argued that what we already know about those principles supports the significant conclusion that the overall progression of humanity will largely depend on the advancement of people's intellectual beliefs.

Throughout his exposition Mill uses "progress" in a neutral sense, without implying that the progression necessarily means improvement. Social science has still to demonstrate that the changes determined by human nature do mean improvement. But in warning the reader of this he declares himself to be personally an optimist, believing that the general tendency, saving temporary exceptions, is in the direction of a better and happier state.

Throughout his explanation, Mill uses "progress" in a neutral way, without suggesting that progress always means improvement. Social science still needs to show that the changes driven by human nature actually lead to improvement. However, in cautioning the reader about this, he reveals that he is personally an optimist, believing that, despite occasional setbacks, the overall trend is towards a better and happier state.

8.

8.

Twenty years later [Footnote: In later editions of the Logic.] Mill was able to say that the conception of history as subject to general laws had "passed into the domain of newspaper and ordinary political discussion." Buckle's HISTORY OF CIVILISATION IN ENGLAND [Footnote: 2 Vol. i. appeared in 1857, vol. ii. in 1861.] which enjoyed an immediate success, did a great deal to popularise the idea. In this stimulating work Buckle took the fact of Progress for granted; his purpose was to investigate its causes. Considering the two general conditions on which all events depend, human nature and external nature, he arrived at two conclusions: (1) In the early stage of history the influence of man's external environment is the more decisive factor; but as time goes on the roles are gradually inverted, and now it is his own nature that is principally responsible for his development. (2) Progress is determined, not by the emotional and moral faculties, but by the intellect; [Footnote: This was the view of Jouffroy, Comte, and Mill; Buckle popularised it.] the emotional and moral faculties are stationary, and therefore religion is not a decisive influence in the onward movement of humanity. "I pledge myself to show that the progress Europe has made from barbarism to civilisation is entirely due to its intellectual activity.... In what may be called the innate and original morals of mankind there is, so far as we are aware, no progress." [Footnote: Buckle has been very unjustly treated by some critics, but has found an able defender in Mr. J.M. Robertson (Buckle and his Critics (1895)). The remarks of Benn (History of Rationalism in the Nineteenth Century, ii. 182 sqq.) are worth reading.]

Twenty years later [Footnote: In later editions of the Logic.] Mill was able to say that the idea of history being governed by general laws had "entered the realm of newspapers and typical political discussions." Buckle's HISTORY OF CIVILISATION IN ENGLAND [Footnote: 2 Vol. i. appeared in 1857, vol. ii. in 1861.] which gained immediate popularity, contributed significantly to spreading this idea. In this thought-provoking work, Buckle assumed the reality of Progress; his goal was to explore its causes. Examining the two fundamental conditions that shape all events, human nature and external nature, he reached two conclusions: (1) In the early phases of history, the impact of man's external environment is the more decisive factor; however, as time progresses, their roles gradually reverse, and it is primarily one’s own nature that drives development. (2) Progress is influenced not by emotional and moral faculties but by intellect; [Footnote: This was the view of Jouffroy, Comte, and Mill; Buckle popularised it.] the emotional and moral faculties remain static, making religion not a key factor in humanity's advancement. "I commit to demonstrating that the progress Europe has made from barbarism to civilization is entirely due to its intellectual activity.... As far as we know, there is no progress in what can be called the innate and original morals of mankind." [Footnote: Buckle has been very unfairly treated by some critics, but he has found a capable defender in Mr. J.M. Robertson (Buckle and his Critics (1895)). The comments of Benn (History of Rationalism in the Nineteenth Century, ii. 182 sqq.) are worth reading.]

Buckle was convinced that social phenomena exhibit the same undeviating regularity as natural phenomena. In this belief he was chiefly influenced by the investigations of the Belgian statistician Quetelet (1835). "Statistics," he said, "has already thrown more light on the study of human nature than all the sciences put together." From the regularity with which the same crimes recur in the same state of society, and many other constant averages, he inferred that all actions of individuals result directly from the state of society in which they live, and that laws are operating which, if we take large enough numbers into account, scarcely undergo any sensible perturbation. [Footnote: Kant had already appealed to statistics in a similar sense; see above, p. 243.] Thus the evidence of statistics points to the conclusion that progress is not determined by the acts of individual men, but depends on general laws of the intellect which govern the successive stages of public opinion. The totality of human actions at any given time depends on the totality of knowledge and the extent of its diffusion.

Buckle believed that social phenomena follow the same consistent patterns as natural phenomena. His views were mainly shaped by the work of the Belgian statistician Quetelet (1835). He stated, "Statistics has already shed more light on the study of human nature than all the sciences combined." From the consistent way the same crimes happen in the same type of society and many other steady averages, he concluded that all individual actions are a direct result of the societal conditions they live in, and that there are underlying laws at play which, when looking at large enough groups, hardly change at all. [Footnote: Kant had already referred to statistics in a similar way; see above, p. 243.] Therefore, statistical evidence suggests that progress isn't driven by individual actions but rather by general laws of thought that guide the changing phases of public opinion. The overall human actions at any moment are determined by the totality of knowledge and how widely it's shared.

There we have the theory that history is subject to general laws in its most unqualified form, based on a fallacious view of the significance of statistical facts. Buckle's attempt to show the operation of general laws in the actual history of man was disappointing. When he went on to review the concrete facts of the historical process, his own political principles came into play, and he was more concerned with denouncing the tendencies of which he did not approve than with extricating general laws from the sequence of events. His comments on religious persecution and the obscurantism of governments and churches were instructive and timely, but they did not do much to exhibit a set of rigid laws governing and explaining the course of human development.

There we have the theory that history is influenced by general laws in its most absolute form, based on a misleading view of the importance of statistical facts. Buckle's attempt to demonstrate the presence of general laws in actual human history was disappointing. When he reviewed the specific facts of historical events, his own political beliefs came into play, and he focused more on criticizing the trends he disagreed with than on identifying general laws from the sequence of events. His observations on religious persecution and the ignorance of governments and churches were insightful and relevant, but they didn’t really showcase a set of strict laws that govern and explain the course of human development.

The doctrine that history is under the irresistible control of law was also popularised by an American physiologist, J. W. Draper, whose HISTORY OF THE INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPE appeared in 1864 and was widely read. His starting-point was a superficial analogy between a society and an individual. "Social advancement is as completely under the control of natural law as a bodily growth. The life of an individual is a miniature of the life of a nation," and "particles" in the individual organism answer to persons in the political organism. Both have the same epochs—infancy, childhood, youth, manhood, old age—and therefore European progress exhibits five phases, designated as Credulity, Inquiry, Faith, Reason, Decrepitude. Draper's conclusion was that Europe, now in the fourth period, is hastening to a long period of decrepitude. The prospect did not dismay him; decrepitude is the culmination of Progress, and means the organisation of national intellect. That has already been achieved in China, and she owes to it her well-being and longevity. "Europe is inevitably hastening to become what China is. In her we may see what we shall be like when we are old."

The idea that history is completely governed by law was also popularized by an American physiologist, J. W. Draper, whose HISTORY OF THE INTELLECTUAL DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPE was published in 1864 and gained wide readership. He began with a basic comparison between society and the individual. "Social progress is as entirely under the control of natural law as physical growth. An individual's life is a small version of a nation's life," and "elements" in the individual body correspond to people in the political body. Both go through the same stages—infancy, childhood, youth, adulthood, and old age—and as a result, European progress shows five phases: Credulity, Inquiry, Faith, Reason, and Decrepitude. Draper's conclusion was that Europe, currently in the fourth phase, is rapidly approaching a long period of decline. This outlook did not trouble him; decline is the peak of Progress and signifies the organization of national intellect. China has already reached this point, which has contributed to its prosperity and longevity. "Europe is inevitably moving towards becoming like China. In China, we can see what we will be like when we are old."

Judged by any standard, Draper's work is much inferior to Buckle's, but both these books, utterly different though they were in both conception and treatment, performed a similar function. Each in its own way diffused the view which had originated in France, that civilisation is progression and, like nature, subject to general laws.

Judged by any standard, Draper's work is far inferior to Buckle's, but both of these books, though completely different in both concept and approach, served a similar purpose. Each, in its own way, spread the idea that originated in France, that civilization is a progression and, like nature, follows general laws.





CHAPTER XVII. "PROGRESS" IN THE FRENCH REVOLUTIONARY MOVEMENT (1830-1851)

1.

In 1850 there appeared at Paris a small book by M. A. Javary, with the title DE L'IDEE DU PROGRES. Its interest lies in the express recognition that Progress was the characteristic idea of the age, ardently received by some, hotly denounced by others. [Footnote: Lamartine denounced in his monthly journal Le Conseiller du peuple, vol. i. (1849), all the progressive gospels of the day, socialist, communist, Saint-Simonian, Fourierist, Icarian—in fact every school of social reform since the First Republic—as purely materialistic, sprung from the "cold seed of the century of Helvetius" (pp. 224, 287).]

In 1850, a small book by M. A. Javary titled DE L'IDEE DU PROGRES was published in Paris. Its significance lies in the clear acknowledgment that Progress was the defining idea of the time, passionately embraced by some and vehemently opposed by others. [Footnote: Lamartine criticized all the progressive ideologies of the day, including socialist, communist, Saint-Simonian, Fourierist, and Icarian movements—essentially every school of social reform since the First Republic—in his monthly journal Le Conseiller du peuple, vol. i. (1849), labeling them as purely materialistic and stemming from the "cold seed of the century of Helvetius" (pp. 224, 287).]

"If there is any idea," he says, "that belongs properly to one century, at least by the importance accorded to it, and that, whether accepted or not, is familiar to all minds, it is the idea of Progress conceived as the general law of history and the future of humanity."

"If there's any idea," he says, "that really belongs to one century, at least by the significance given to it, and that, whether it's accepted or not, is known by everyone, it's the idea of Progress understood as the universal law of history and the future of humanity."

He observes that some, intoxicated by the spectacle of the material improvements of modern civilisation and the results of science, set no limits to man's power or his hopes; while others, unable to deny the facts, say that this progress serves only the lower part of human nature, and refuse to look with complacency on a movement which means, they assert, a continuous decadence of the nobler part. To which it is replied that, If moral decadence is a fact, it is only transient; it is a necessary phase of a development which means moral progress in the end, for it is due to the process by which the beliefs, ideas, and institutions of the past disappear and make way for new and better principles.

He notes that some, overwhelmed by the impressive advancements of modern civilization and scientific achievements, see no limits to human power or potential; while others, unable to overlook the reality, argue that this progress only caters to the baser aspects of human nature and refuse to accept a trend that they claim leads to a continuous decline of the higher self. In response, it is said that if moral decline is a reality, it’s only temporary; it’s a necessary step in a process that ultimately leads to moral progress, as it results from the elimination of outdated beliefs, ideas, and institutions, making room for new and better principles.

And Javary notes a prevailing tendency in France to interpret every contemporary movement as progressive, while all the social doctrinaires justify their particular reforms by invoking the law of Progress. It was quite true that during the July monarchy nearly all serious speculations on society and history were related to that idea. It was common to Michelet and Quinet, who saw in the march of civilisation the gradual triumph of liberty; to Leroux and Cabet, who preached humanitarian communism; to Louis Blanc and to Proudhon; to the bourgeois, who were satisfied with the regime of Louis Philippe and grew rich, following the precept of Guizot, as well as to the workers who overthrew it. It is significant that the journal of Louis Blanc, in which he published his book on the ORGANISATION OF WORK (1839), was entitled REVUS DES PROGRES. The political question as to the due limits between government and individual freedom was discussed in terms of Progress: is personal liberty or state authority the efficient means of progressing? The metaphysical question of necessity and freewill acquired a new interest: is Progress a fatality, independent of human purposes, determined by general, ineluctable, historical laws? Quinet and Michelet argued vigorously against the optimism of Cousin, who with Hegel held that history is just what it ought to be and could not be improved.

And Javary points out a common trend in France to see every modern movement as progressive, while all the social theorists justify their specific reforms by citing the law of Progress. It was indeed true that during the July monarchy, nearly all serious discussions about society and history were connected to that idea. It was shared by Michelet and Quinet, who viewed the advancement of civilization as the gradual victory of freedom; by Leroux and Cabet, who advocated for humanitarian communism; by Louis Blanc and Proudhon; by the bourgeoisie, who were content with Louis Philippe's government and grew wealthy following Guizot's advice, as well as by the workers who toppled it. Notably, the journal of Louis Blanc, where he published his book on the ORGANISATION OF WORK (1839), was titled REVUS DES PROGRES. The political debate regarding the appropriate balance between government and individual freedom was framed in terms of Progress: which is the better path to advancement, personal liberty or state authority? The philosophical question of necessity and free will gained new importance: is Progress an inevitability, beyond human intentions, dictated by universal, inescapable historical laws? Quinet and Michelet strongly opposed Cousin’s optimism, who, along with Hegel, argued that history is exactly as it should be and cannot be improved.

2.

2.

Among the competing theories of the time, and sharply opposed to the views of Comte, was the idea, derived from the Revolution, that the world is moving towards universal equality and the obliteration of class distinctions, that this is the true direction of Progress. This view, represented by leaders of the popular movement against the bourgeois ascendency, derived powerful reinforcement from one of the most enlightened political thinkers of the day. The appearance of de Tocqueville's renowned study of American democracy was the event of 1834. He was convinced that he had discovered on the other side of the Atlantic the answer to the question whither the world is tending. In American society he found that equality of conditions is the generating fact on which every other fact depends. He concluded that equality is the goal of humanity, providentially designed.

Among the competing theories of the time, and in stark contrast to Comte's views, was the idea, rooted in the Revolution, that the world is moving towards universal equality and the elimination of class distinctions; this is the true direction of Progress. This perspective, championed by leaders of the popular movement against the rise of the bourgeoisie, gained strong support from one of the most insightful political thinkers of the era. The release of de Tocqueville's famous study on American democracy marked a significant event in 1834. He believed he had found the answer to where the world is headed across the Atlantic. In American society, he identified that equality of conditions is the foundational fact upon which everything else relies. He concluded that equality is humanity's ultimate goal, designed providentially.

"The gradual development of equality of conditions has the principal characteristics of a providential fact. It is universal, it is permanent, it eludes human power; all events and all men serve this development.... This whole book has been written under the impression of a sort of religious terror produced in the author's soul by the view of this irresistible revolution which for so many centuries has been marching across all obstacles, and which is to-day seen still advancing in the midst of the ruins it has made.... If the men of our time were brought to see that the gradual and progressive development of equality is at once the past and the future of their history, this single discovery would give that development the sacred character of the will of the sovran master."

"The gradual emergence of equality among people has the main traits of a divine occurrence. It is universal, it is lasting, and it transcends human control; every event and every person contributes to this progress.... This entire book was written under the impact of a kind of profound fear that struck the author upon witnessing this unstoppable revolution that has been pushing through all obstacles for centuries and is still seen moving forward amid the ruins it has caused.... If people in our time came to realize that the steady and progressive advancement of equality represents both the past and the future of their history, this single realization would endow that progress with the sacred essence of the will of the supreme ruler."

Here we have a view of the direction of Progress and the meaning of history, pretending to be based upon the study of facts and announced with the most intense conviction. And behind it is the fatalistic doctrine that the movement cannot be arrested or diverted; that it is useless to struggle against it; that men, whatever they may do, cannot deflect the clock-like motion regulated by a power which de Tocqueville calls Providence but to which his readers might give some other name.

Here we have a perspective on the path of Progress and the significance of history, claiming to be grounded in factual study and stated with utmost conviction. And behind it lies the fatalistic belief that this movement cannot be stopped or changed; that it’s pointless to fight against it; that people, no matter what they do, cannot alter the clock-like progression governed by a force that de Tocqueville refers to as Providence, but which his readers might call something else.

3.

3.

It has been conjectured, [Footnote: Georges Sorel, Les Illusions du progres, pp. 247-8 (1908).] and seems probable enough, that de Tocqueville's book was one of the influences which wrought upon the mind of Proudhon. The speculations of this remarkable man, who, like Saint-Simon and Comte, sought to found a new science of society, attracted general attention in the middle of the century. [Footnote: Compare the appreciation by Weill in Histoire du mouvement social en France 1852-1910 (1911, ed. 2), p. 41: "Le grande ecrivain revolutionnaire et anarchiste n'etait au fond ni un revolutionnaire ni un anarchiste, mais un reformateur pratique et modere qui a fait illusion par le ton vibrant de ses pamphlets centre la societe capitaliste."]His hostility to religion, his notorious dictum that "property is theft," his gospel of "anarchy," and the defiant, precipitous phrases in which he clothed his ideas, created an impression that he was a dangerous anti-social revolutionary. But when his ideas are studied in their context and translated into sober language, they are not so unreasonable. Notwithstanding his communistic theory of property and his ideal of equality, he was a strong individualist. He held that the future of civilisation depends on the energy of individuals, that liberty is a condition of its advance, and that the end to be kept in view is the establishment of justice, which means equality. He saw the difficulty of reconciling liberty with complete equality, but hoped that the incompatibility would be overcome by a gradual reduction of the natural differences in men's capacities. He said, "I am an anarchist," but his anarchy only meant that the time would come when government would be superfluous, when every human being could be trusted to act wisely and morally without a restraining authority or external sanctions. Nor was he a Utopian. He comprehended that such a transformation of society would be a long, slow process, and he condemned the schools of Saint-Simon and Fourier for imagining that a millennium might be realised immediately by a change of organisation.

It has been suggested, [Footnote: Georges Sorel, Les Illusions du progres, pp. 247-8 (1908).] and it seems quite likely, that de Tocqueville's book was one of the influences on Proudhon's thinking. The ideas of this remarkable individual, who, like Saint-Simon and Comte, aimed to establish a new science of society, gained widespread attention in the middle of the century. [Footnote: Compare the appreciation by Weill in Histoire du mouvement social en France 1852-1910 (1911, ed. 2), p. 41: "The great revolutionary and anarchist writer was fundamentally neither a revolutionary nor an anarchist, but a practical and moderate reformer who created an illusion with the vibrant tone of his pamphlets against capitalist society."] His criticism of religion, his famous statement that "property is theft," his views on "anarchy," and the bold, striking language he used to express his ideas led many to perceive him as a dangerous anti-social revolutionary. However, when his ideas are examined within their context and translated into plain language, they appear less unreasonable. Despite his communist theory of property and his vision of equality, he was a strong individualist. He believed that the future of civilization relies on the energy of individuals, that liberty is essential for progress, and that the ultimate goal should be the establishment of justice, which equates to equality. He recognized the challenge of balancing liberty with complete equality but hoped the contradiction would be resolved through a gradual diminishing of the natural differences in people's abilities. He stated, "I am an anarchist," but his concept of anarchy simply meant that a time would come when government would be unnecessary, and every individual could be trusted to behave wisely and morally without external authority or enforcement. He was not a Utopian either. He understood that transforming society would be a long, gradual journey, and he criticized the schools of Saint-Simon and Fourier for believing that a better future could be achieved immediately through organizational changes.

He tells us that all his speculations and controversial activities are penetrated with the idea of Progress, which he described as "the railway of liberty"; and his radical criticism on current social theories, whether conservative or democratic, was that they did not take Progress seriously though they invoked it.

He tells us that all his ideas and controversial actions are deeply connected to the concept of Progress, which he referred to as "the railway of liberty." His radical critique of current social theories, whether conservative or democratic, was that they didn’t truly embrace Progress, even though they mentioned it.

"What dominates in all my studies, what forms their beginning and end, their summit and their base, their reason, what makes my originality as a thinker (if I have any), is that I affirm Progress resolutely, irrevocably, and everywhere, and deny the Absolute. All that I have ever written, all I have denied or affirmed, I have written, denied or affirmed in the name of one unique idea, Progress. My adversaries, on the other hand, are all partisans of the Absolute, IN OMNI GENERE, CASU, ET NUMERO, to use the phrase of Sganarelle." [Footnote: Philosophie du progres, Premiere lettre (1851).]

"What dominates all of my studies, what shapes their beginning and end, their peak and foundation, their purpose, what highlights my originality as a thinker (if I have any), is that I firmly and undeniably embrace Progress everywhere and reject the Absolute. Everything I have ever written, everything I have denied or affirmed, I have done so in the name of one unique idea: Progress. My opponents, on the other hand, are all supporters of the Absolute, in every way, case, and number, to borrow a phrase from Sganarelle." [Footnote: Philosophie du progres, Premiere lettre (1851).]

4.

4.

A vague confidence in Progress had lain behind and encouraged the revolution of 1789, but in the revolution of 1848 the idea was definitely enthroned as the regnant principle. It presided over the session of the Committee which drew up the Constitution of the second Republic. Armand Marrast, the most important of the men who framed that document, based the measure of universal suffrage upon "the invisible law which rules societies," the law of progress which has been so long denied but which is rooted in the nature of man. His argument was this: Revolutions are due to the repression of progress, and are the expression and triumph of a progress which has been achieved. But such convulsions are an undesirable method of progressing; how can they be avoided? Only by organising elastic institutions in which new ideas of amelioration can easily be incorporated, and laws which can be accommodated without struggle or friction to the rise of new opinions. What is needed is a flexible government open to the penetration of ideas, and the key to such a government is universal suffrage.

A vague confidence in Progress supported and fueled the revolution of 1789, but by the revolution of 1848, the idea was firmly established as the dominant principle. It guided the session of the Committee that created the Constitution of the Second Republic. Armand Marrast, the key figure among those who drafted that document, based the concept of universal suffrage on "the invisible law which governs societies," the law of progress that has long been denied but is inherent in human nature. His argument was this: Revolutions happen because progress is suppressed, and they reflect and signify a progress that has already been achieved. However, such upheavals are not an ideal way to advance; how can they be avoided? The solution is to create flexible institutions where new ideas for improvement can be easily integrated, and laws that can adapt without conflict or struggle to emerging opinions. What’s essential is a responsive government that welcomes new ideas, and the key to such a government is universal suffrage.

[Footnote: Marrast, "the invisible law"; "Oui," he continues, "toute societe est progressive, parce que tout individu est educable, perfectible; on peut mesurer, limiter, peut-etre les facultes d'un individu; on ne saurait limiter, mesurer ce que peuvent, dans l'ordre des idees, les intelligences dont les produits ne s'ajoutent pas seulement mais se fecondent et se multiplient dans une progression indefinie." No. 393 Republique francoise. Assemblee nationale. Projet de Constitution... precede par un rapport fait au nom de la Commission par le citoyen Armand Marrast. Seance du 30 aout, 1848.]

[Footnote: Marrast, "the invisible law"; "Yes," he continues, "every society is progressive because every individual can be educated and improved; we can measure and limit, perhaps, an individual's abilities, but we cannot measure or limit what the intelligences can achieve in the realm of ideas, as their results not only add up but also stimulate and multiply in an indefinite progression." No. 393 Republic of France. National Assembly. Draft Constitution... preceded by a report presented on behalf of the Commission by citizen Armand Marrast. Session of August 30, 1848.]

Universal suffrage was practical politics, but the success of the revolution fluttered agreeably all the mansions of Utopia, and social reformers of every type sought to improve the occasion. In the history of the political struggles of 1848 the names are written of Proudhon, of Victor Considerant the disciple of Fourier, of Pierre Leroux the humanitarian communist, and his devoted pupil George Sand. The chief title of Leroux to be remembered is just his influence over the soul of the great novelist. Her later romances are pervaded by ideas derived from his teaching. His communism was vague and ineffectual, but he was one of the minor forces in the thought of the period, and there are some features in his theory which deserve to be pointed out.

Universal suffrage was practical politics, but the success of the revolution created a buzz among all the mansions of Utopia, and social reformers of all kinds tried to seize the moment. In the history of the political struggles of 1848, you can find the names of Proudhon, Victor Considerant, a follower of Fourier, Pierre Leroux, the humanitarian communist, and his devoted pupil George Sand. Leroux’s main claim to fame is his influence on the soul of the great novelist. Her later novels are filled with ideas from his teachings. His brand of communism was vague and ineffective, but he was one of the lesser influences on the period's thought, and there are aspects of his theory that deserve attention.

Leroux had begun as a member of the Saint-Simonian school, but he diverged into a path of his own. He reinstated the ideal of equality which Saint-Simon rejected, and made the approach to that ideal the measure of Progress. The most significant process in history, he held, is the gradual breaking down of caste and class: the process is now approaching its completion; "today MAN is synonymous with EQUAL."

Leroux started out as part of the Saint-Simonian school but eventually carved out his own path. He brought back the ideal of equality that Saint-Simon dismissed and made the journey toward that ideal the standard of Progress. He believed the most important process in history is the slow dismantling of caste and class, which is now nearing its end; "today, MAN means EQUAL."

In order to advance to the city of the future we must have a force and a lever. Man is the force, and the lever is the idea of Progress. It is supplied by the study of history which displays the improvement of our faculties, the increase of our power over nature, the possibility of organising society more efficaciously. But the force and the lever are not enough. A fulcrum is also required, and this is to be found in the "solidarity" of the human race. But this conception meant for Leroux something different from what is ordinarily meant by the phrase, a deeper and even mystical bond. Human "solidarity" was a corollary from the pantheistic religion of the Saint-Simonians, but with Leroux, as with Fourier, it was derived from the more difficult doctrine of palingenesis. We of this generation, he believed, are not merely the sons and descendants of past generations, we are the past generations themselves, which have come to birth again in us.

To move toward the city of the future, we need a force and a lever. Humanity is the force, and the lever is the idea of Progress. This idea comes from studying history, which shows how our abilities have improved, how we've gained more power over nature, and how we can organize society more effectively. But the force and the lever aren't enough. We also need a fulcrum, which can be found in the "solidarity" of the human race. However, for Leroux, this idea meant something different than what people usually think; it referred to a deeper and more mystical connection. Human "solidarity" was linked to the pantheistic beliefs of the Saint-Simonians, but for Leroux, like Fourier, it stemmed from the more complex doctrine of palingenesis. He believed that we, in this generation, are not just the children and descendants of past generations; we are those past generations reborn within us.

Through many pages of the two volumes [Footnote: De l'humanite, 1840 (dedicated to Beranger).] in which he set forth his thesis, Leroux expended much useless learning in endeavouring to establish this doctrine, which, were it true, might be the central principle in a new religion of humanity, a transformed Pythagoreanism. It is easy to understand the attractiveness of palingenesis to a believer in Progress: for it would provide a solution of the anomaly that generations after generations are sacrificed for the sake of posterity, and so appear to have no value in themselves. Believers in Progress, who are sensitive to the sufferings of mankind, past and present, need a stoical resolution to face this fact. We saw how Herder refused to accept it. A pantheistic faith, like that of the Saint-Simonian Church, may help some, it cannot do more, to a stoical acquiescence. The palingenesis of Leroux or Fourier removes the radical injustice. The men of each generation are sacrificed and suffer for the sake of their descendants, but as their descendants are themselves come to life again, they are really suffering in their own interests. They will themselves reach the desirable state to which the slow, painful process of history is tending.

Through many pages of the two volumes [Footnote: De l'humanite, 1840 (dedicated to Beranger).] where he laid out his thesis, Leroux wasted a lot of pointless knowledge trying to establish this doctrine, which, if true, could be the central principle of a new religion of humanity, a revamped Pythagoreanism. It’s easy to see why palingenesis is appealing to those who believe in Progress: it would explain the oddity that generations after generations are sacrificed for the sake of future generations, making their own lives seem worthless. Progress believers, who are aware of the suffering of humanity both past and present, need a stoic resolve to accept this reality. We saw how Herder refused to do so. A pantheistic belief, like that of the Saint-Simonian Church, might assist some, but it can't do much more than to encourage a stoic acceptance. Leroux's or Fourier's idea of palingenesis eliminates the fundamental injustice. People of each generation suffer and make sacrifices for their descendants, but since those descendants are essentially reborn, they are really suffering for their own benefit. They will ultimately attain the desired state that the slow, painful course of history is striving towards.

But palingenesis, notwithstanding all the ancient opinions and traditions that the researches of Leroux might muster, could carry little conviction to those who were ceasing to believe in the familiar doctrine of a future life detached from earth, and Madame Dudevant was his only distinguished convert.

But palingenesis, despite all the ancient opinions and traditions that Leroux could gather, didn't convince many people who were starting to doubt the familiar idea of an afterlife separate from Earth, and Madame Dudevant was his only notable follower.

5.

5.

The ascendency of the idea of Progress among thoughtful people in France in the middle of the last century is illustrated by the work which Ernest Renan composed under the immediate impression of the events of 1848. He desired to understand the significance of the current revolutionary doctrines, and was at once involved in speculation on the future of humanity. This is the purport of L'AVENIR DE LA SCIENCE. [Footnote: L'Avenir de la science—Pensees de (1848). Published in 1890.]

The rise of the concept of Progress among thoughtful individuals in France in the middle of the last century is shown through the work that Ernest Renan created in response to the events of 1848. He wanted to grasp the meaning of the revolutionary ideas of the time and quickly became immersed in speculation about the future of humanity. This is the essence of L'AVENIR DE LA SCIENCE. [Footnote: L'Avenir de la science—Pensees de (1848). Published in 1890.]

[Footnote: The ascendency of the idea of Progress at this epoch may be further illustrated by E. Pelletan's Profession de foi du dix-neuvieme siecle, 1852 (4th ed., 1857), where Progress is described as the general law of the universe; and by Jean Reynaud's Philosophie religieuse: Terre et ciel (3rd ed., 1858), a religious but not orthodox book, which acclaims the "sovran principle of perfectibility" (cp. p. 138). I may refer also to the rhetorical pages of E. Vacherot on the Doctrine du progres, printed (as part of an essay on the Philosophy of History) in his Essais de philosophie critique (1864).]

[Footnote: The rise of the idea of Progress during this time can be further seen in E. Pelletan's Profession de foi du dix-neuvieme siecle, 1852 (4th ed., 1857), where Progress is portrayed as the universal law; and in Jean Reynaud's Philosophie religieuse: Terre et ciel (3rd ed., 1858), which is a religious yet non-traditional book that celebrates the "sovereign principle of perfectibility" (cp. p. 138). I can also point to the eloquent sections of E. Vacherot on the Doctrine du progres, published (as part of an essay on the Philosophy of History) in his Essais de philosophie critique (1864).]

The author was then convinced that history has a goal, and that mankind tends perpetually, though in an oscillating line, towards a more perfect state, through the growing dominion of reason over instinct and caprice. He takes the French Revolution as the critical moment in which humanity first came to know itself. That revolution was the first attempt of man to take the reins into his own hands. All that went before we may call, with Owen, the irrational period of human existence.

The author was convinced that history has a purpose, and that humanity constantly moves, though in a back-and-forth way, toward a better state, driven by the increasing dominance of reason over instinct and impulse. He sees the French Revolution as the pivotal moment when humanity first became self-aware. That revolution was humanity's first attempt to take control of its own destiny. Everything that came before can be referred to, as Owen said, as the irrational phase of human existence.

We have now come to a point at which we must choose between two faiths. If we despair of reason, we may find a refuge from utter scepticism in a belief in the external authority of the Roman Church. If we trust reason, we must accept the march of the human mind and justify the modern spirit. And it can be justified only by proving that it is a necessary step towards perfection. Renan affirmed his belief in the second alternative, and felt confident that science—including philology, on the human bearings of which he enlarged,—philosophy, and art would ultimately enable men to realise an ideal civilisation, in which all would be equal. The state, he said, is the machine of Progress, and the Socialists are right in formulating the problem which man has to solve, though their solution is a bad one. For individual liberty, which socialism would seriously limit, is a definite conquest, and ought to be preserved inviolate.

We’ve reached a point where we have to choose between two beliefs. If we give up on reason, we might find safety from complete uncertainty in trusting the authority of the Roman Church. If we believe in reason, we have to embrace the advancement of human thought and support the modern mindset. This mindset can only be justified by showing that it’s a necessary step towards perfection. Renan believed in the second option and was confident that science—including linguistics, which he elaborated on—and philosophy and art would eventually help people achieve an ideal society where everyone is equal. He said that the state is the engine of Progress, and while Socialists correctly identify the problem humanity needs to solve, their solution is flawed. Individual liberty, which socialism would greatly restrict, is a significant achievement and should be defended fiercely.

Renan wrote this work in 1848 and 1849, but did not publish it at the time. He gave it to the world forty years later. Those forty years had robbed him of his early optimism. He continues to believe that the unfortunate conditions of our race might be ameliorated by science, but he denounces the view that men can ever be equal. Inequality is written in nature; it is not only a necessary consequence of liberty, but a necessary postulate of Progress. There will always be a superior minority. He criticises himself too for having fallen into the error of Hegel, and assigned to man an unduly important place in the universe.

Renan wrote this work in 1848 and 1849 but chose not to publish it at that time. He finally shared it with the world forty years later. Those forty years had taken away his early optimism. He still believes that the unfortunate circumstances of our species could be improved by science, but he rejects the idea that humans can ever be equal. Inequality is inherent in nature; it is not just a necessary result of freedom but also a crucial requirement for Progress. There will always be a superior minority. He also criticizes himself for having fallen into Hegel's error by giving humans an overly significant role in the universe.

[Footnote: Renan, speaking of the Socialists, paid a high tribute to Bazard (L'Avenir de la science, p. 104). On the other hand, he criticised Comte severely (p. 149).

[Footnote: Renan, talking about the Socialists, gave high praise to Bazard (L'Avenir de la science, p. 104). On the flip side, he criticized Comte harshly (p. 149).

Renan returned to speculation on the future in 1863, in a letter to M. Marcellin-Berthelot (published in Dialogues et fragments philosophiques, 1876): "Que sera Ie monde quand un million de fois se sera reproduit ce qui s'est passe depuis 1763 quand la chimie, au lieu de quatre-vingt ans de progres, en aura cent millions?" (p. 183). And again in the Dialogues written in 1871 (ib.), where it is laid down that the end of humanity is to produce great men: "le grand oeuvre s'accomplira par la science, non par la democratic. Rien sans grands hommes; le salut se fera par des grands hommes" (p. 103).]

Renan revisited the topic of the future in 1863 in a letter to M. Marcellin-Berthelot (published in *Dialogues et fragments philosophiques*, 1876): "What will the world be like when a million times has repeated what happened since 1763, when chemistry, instead of having progressed for eighty years, will have for a hundred million?" (p. 183). And again in the *Dialogues* written in 1871 (ib.), where it is stated that the purpose of humanity is to produce great individuals: "The great work will be achieved through science, not through democracy. Nothing happens without great individuals; salvation will come through great individuals" (p. 103).

In 1890 there was nothing left of the sentimental socialism which he had studied in 1848; it had been blown away by the cold wind of scientific socialism which Marx and Engels created. And Renan had come to think that in this new form socialism would triumph. [Footnote: He reckoned without the new forces, opposed to socialism as well as to parliamentary democracy, represented by Bakunin and men like Georges Sorel.] He had criticised Comte for believing that "man lives exclusively by science, or rather little verbal tags, like geometrical theorems, dry formulae." Was he satisfied by the concrete doctrine of Marx that all the phenomena of civilisation at a given period are determined by the methods of production and distribution which then prevail? But the future of socialism is a minor issue, and the ultimate goal of humanity is quite uncertain. "Ce qu'il y a de consolant, c'est qu'on arrive necessairement quelque part." We may console ourselves with the certainty that we must get somewhere.

In 1890, the sentimental socialism he had studied in 1848 was all but gone; it had been swept away by the harsh realities of scientific socialism created by Marx and Engels. Renan began to believe that this new form of socialism would succeed. [Footnote: He overlooked the new forces opposing socialism as well as parliamentary democracy, represented by Bakunin and figures like Georges Sorel.] He had criticized Comte for thinking that "man lives solely by science, or rather by simple concepts, like geometric theorems and dry formulas." Was he satisfied with Marx's concrete doctrine that all aspects of civilization at any given time are shaped by the prevailing methods of production and distribution? However, the future of socialism is a minor concern, and the ultimate goal of humanity remains quite unclear. "What is comforting is that we will inevitably arrive somewhere." We can take solace in the certainty that we must end up somewhere.

6.

6.

Proudhon described the idea of Progress as the railway of liberty. It certainly supplied motive power to social ideals which were repugnant and alarming to the authorities of the Catholic Church. At the Vatican it was clearly seen that the idea was a powerful engine driven by an enemy; and in the famous SYLLABUS of errors which Pope Pius IX. flung in the face of the modern world at the end of 1864, Progress had the honour of being censured. The eightieth error, which closes the list, runs thus:

Proudhon described the idea of Progress as the train of freedom. It definitely fueled social ideals that were disturbing and threatening to the authorities of the Catholic Church. At the Vatican, it was evident that this idea was a strong force driven by an adversary; and in the famous SYLLABUS of errors that Pope Pius IX threw at the modern world at the end of 1864, Progress was notably condemned. The eightieth error, which wraps up the list, states:

Romanus Pontifex potest ac debet cum progressu, cum liberalismo et cum recenti civilitate sese reconciliare et componere.

Romanus Pontifex can and should reconcile and come to terms with progress, liberalism, and recent civility.

"The Roman Pontiff can, and ought to, be reconciled and come to terms with progress, with liberalism, and with modern civilisation."

"The Pope can and should reconcile with progress, liberalism, and modern civilization."

No wonder, seeing that Progress was invoked to justify every movement that offended the nostrils of the Vatican—liberalism, toleration, democracy, and socialism. And the Roman Church well understood the intimate connection of the idea with the advance of rationalism.

No surprise, considering that Progress was used to justify every action that displeased the Vatican—liberalism, tolerance, democracy, and socialism. The Roman Church clearly recognized the close link between the idea and the rise of rationalism.





CHAPTER XVIII. MATERIAL PROGRESS: THE EXHIBITION OF 1851

1.

It is not easy for a new idea of the speculative order to penetrate and inform the general consciousness of a community until it has assumed some external and concrete embodiment or is recommended by some striking material evidence. In the case of Progress both these conditions were fulfilled in the period 1820 to 1850. In the Saint-Simonian Church, and in the attempts of Owen and Cabet to found ideal societies, people saw practical enterprises inspired by the idea. They might have no sympathy with these enterprises, but their attention was attracted. And at the same time they were witnessing a rapid transformation of the external conditions of life, a movement to the continuation of which there seemed no reason for setting any limit in the future. The spectacular results of the advance of science and mechanical technique brought home to the mind of the average man the conception of an indefinite increase of man's power over nature as his brain penetrated her secrets. This evident material progress which has continued incessantly ever since has been a mainstay of the general belief in Progress which is prevalent to-day.

It’s not easy for a new speculative idea to break into and influence the general consciousness of a community until it takes on some tangible form or is supported by striking evidence. From 1820 to 1850, both these conditions were met with the idea of Progress. In the Saint-Simonian Church and in the efforts of Owen and Cabet to create ideal societies, people saw practical projects inspired by that idea. They might not have supported these projects, but they grabbed their attention. At the same time, they were experiencing a rapid change in their living conditions, a wave of change that seemed to have no limit in sight. The impressive outcomes of advances in science and technology made the average person aware of the endless potential for man’s power over nature as he uncovered its mysteries. This clear material progress, which has continued without interruption ever since, has been a cornerstone of the widespread belief in Progress that exists today.

England was the leader in this material progress, of which the particulars are familiar and need not be enumerated here. The discovery of the power of steam and the potentialities of coal revolutionised the conditions of life. Men who were born at the beginning of the century had seen, before they had passed the age of thirty, the rapid development of steam navigation, the illumination of towns and houses by gas, the opening of the first railway.

England was at the forefront of this material progress, the details of which are well-known and don’t need to be listed here. The discovery of steam power and the possibilities of coal completely transformed daily life. People born at the start of the century had witnessed, before turning thirty, the swift advancement of steam navigation, the lighting of cities and homes with gas, and the launch of the first railway.

It was just before this event, the opening of the Liverpool and Manchester railway, which showed how machinery would abbreviate space as it had SIR THOMAS MORE, OR COLLOQUIES ON THE PROGRESS OF SOCIETY (1829). There we see the effect of the new force on his imagination. "Steam," he says, "will govern the world next,... and shake it too before its empire is established." The biographer of Nelson devotes a whole conversation to the subject of "steam and war." But the theme of the book is the question of moral and social progress, on which the author inclines to the view that "the world will continue to improve, even as it has hitherto been continually improving; and that the progress of knowledge and the diffusion of Christianity will bring about at last, when men become Christian in reality as well as in name, something like that Utopian state of which philosophers have loved to dream." This admission of Progress, cautious though it was, circumscribed by reserves and compromised by hesitations, coming from such a conservative pillar of Church and State as Southey, is a notable sign of the times, when we remember that the idea was still associated then with revolution and heresy.

It was just before the opening of the Liverpool and Manchester railway, which demonstrated how machinery would shorten distances, much like SIR THOMAS MORE, OR COLLOQUIES ON THE PROGRESS OF SOCIETY (1829). We can see how the new force impacted his imagination. "Steam," he states, "will control the world next,... and it will also shake it before its empire is established." The biographer of Nelson dedicates an entire conversation to "steam and war." However, the main focus of the book is the issue of moral and social progress, where the author tends to believe that "the world will keep improving, just as it has been continuously improving; and that the advancement of knowledge and the spread of Christianity will eventually result in, when people become Christian in reality as well as in name, something resembling that Utopian state that philosophers have long dreamed about." This acknowledgment of Progress, although careful and surrounded by reservations and uncertainty, coming from such a conservative figure in Church and State as Southey, is a significant sign of the times, especially considering the idea was still linked to revolution and heresy back then.

It is significant too that at the same time an octogenarian mathematician of Aberdeen was composing a book on the same subject. Hamilton's PROGRESS OF SOCIETY is now utterly forgotten, but it must have contributed in its day to propagating the same moderate view of Progress, consistent with orthodoxy, which Southey held. "The belief of the perfectibility of human nature and the attainment of a golden age in which vice and misery have no place, will only be entertained by an enthusiast; but an inquiry into the means of improving our nature and enlarging our happiness is consistent with sober reason, and is the most important subject, merely human, that can engage the mind of man." [Footnote: P. 13. The book was published posthumously by Murray in 1830, a year after the author's death.] [Footnote: "Progress of Society." The phrase was becoming common; e.g. Russell's History of Modern Europe (1822) has the sub-title A view of the Progress of Society, etc. The didactic poem of Payne Knight, The Progress of Civil Society (1796), a very dull performance, was quite unaffected by the dreams of Priestley or Godwin. It was towards the middle of the nineteenth century that Progress, without any qualifying phrase, came into use.]

It’s also important to note that around the same time, an eighty-year-old mathematician from Aberdeen was writing a book on the same topic. Hamilton's PROGRESS OF SOCIETY is now completely forgotten, but it must have played a role in promoting the same moderate view of Progress, in line with orthodoxy, that Southey believed in. "The belief in the perfectibility of human nature and the idea of reaching a golden age where vice and suffering have no place will only be held by an enthusiast; however, exploring ways to improve our nature and enhance our happiness is reasonable and is the most important purely human subject that can occupy the mind of man." [Footnote: P. 13. The book was published posthumously by Murray in 1830, a year after the author's death.] [Footnote: "Progress of Society." This phrase was becoming common; for instance, Russell's History of Modern Europe (1822) has the subtitle A view of the Progress of Society, etc. The didactic poem by Payne Knight, The Progress of Civil Society (1796), a rather dull work, was quite unaffected by the visions of Priestley or Godwin. It was around the middle of the nineteenth century that Progress, without any additional qualifiers, began to be used.]

2.

2.

We have been told by Tennyson that when he went by the first train from Liverpool to Manchester (1830) he thought that the wheels ran in grooves.

We were told by Tennyson that when he took the first train from Liverpool to Manchester in 1830, he thought the wheels ran in tracks.

"Then I made this line:

"Then I created this line:"

Let the great world spin for ever down the ringing grooves of change." [Footnote: See Tennyson, Memoir by his Son, vol. i. p. 195.]

Let the world keep turning endlessly down the loud paths of change." [Footnote: See Tennyson, Memoir by his Son, vol. i. p. 195.]

LOCKSLEY HALL, which was published in 1842, illustrates how the idea of Progress had begun to creep into the imagination of Englishmen. Though subsidiary to a love story, it is the true theme of the poem. The pulsation of eager interest in the terrestrial destinies of humanity, the large excitement of living in a "wondrous Mother-age," dreams of the future, quicken the passion of the hero's youth. His disappointment in love disenchants him; he sees the reverse side of civilisation, but at last he finds an anodyne for his palsied heart in a more sober version of his earlier faith, a chastened belief in his Mother-age. He can at least discern an increasing purpose in history, and can be sure that "the thoughts of men are widened with the process of the suns." The novelty of the poem lay in finding a cathartic cure for a private sorrow, not in religion or in nature, but in the modern idea of Progress. It may be said to mark a stage in the career of the idea.

LOCKSLEY HALL, published in 1842, shows how the idea of Progress started to take hold in the minds of English people. While it’s mainly a love story, that’s not its real theme. The excitement of the potential futures for humanity, living in a "wondrous Mother-age," and dreams about what’s to come energize the young hero. His heartbreak leaves him disillusioned; he sees the darker side of civilization, but ultimately he finds relief for his troubled heart in a more realistic version of his earlier beliefs, a tempered faith in his Mother-age. He can at least recognize an ongoing purpose in history and can trust that "the thoughts of men are widened with the process of the suns." The uniqueness of the poem lies in finding a healing solution for personal grief not through religion or nature, but through the modern concept of Progress. It can be said to represent a turning point in how that idea developed.

The view of civilisation which Tennyson took as his MOTIF had no revolutionary implications, suggested no impatience or anger with the past. The startling prospect unfolding itself before "the long result of time," and history is justified by the promise of to-day:

The view of civilization that Tennyson used as his MOTIF had no revolutionary implications and showed no impatience or anger toward the past. The surprising vision unfolding before "the long result of time" and history is validated by today's promise:

The centuries behind me like a fruitful land reposed.

The centuries behind me feel like a rich, restful landscape.

Very different was the spirit in which another great poet composed, nearly twenty years later, a wonderful hymn of Progress. Victor Hugo's PLEIN CEIL, in his epic LA LEGENDE DES SIECLES,[Footnote: A.D. 1859.] announces a new era of the world in which man, the triumphant rebel, delivered from his past, will move freely forward on a glorious way. The poet is inspired not by faith in a continuous development throughout the ages, but by the old spirit of the Revolution, and he sees in the past only a heavy chain which the race at last flings off. The horrible past has gone, not to return: "ce monde est mort"; and the poem is at once a paean on man's victorious rebellion against it and a dithyramb on the prospect of his future.

Very different was the spirit in which another great poet wrote, nearly twenty years later, a wonderful hymn of Progress. Victor Hugo's PLEIN CEIL, in his epic LA LEGENDE DES SIECLES,[Footnote: A.D. 1859.] announces a new era for the world in which man, the triumphant rebel, liberated from his past, will move forward freely on a glorious path. The poet is inspired not by faith in continuous development through the ages, but by the old spirit of the Revolution, and he sees the past only as a heavy chain that humanity finally breaks free from. The horrible past is gone, never to return: "ce monde est mort"; and the poem is both a celebration of man's victorious rebellion against it and an enthusiastic ode to the promise of his future.

Man is imagined as driving through the heavens an aerial car to which the four winds are harnessed, mounting above the clouds, and threatening to traverse the ether.

Man is envisioned as piloting an airship through the skies, with the four winds at his command, soaring above the clouds and poised to cross the atmosphere.

 Superbe, il plane, avec un hymne en ses agres;
 Et l'on voit voir passer la strophe du progres.
 Il est la nef, il est le phare!
 L'homme enfin prend son sceptre et jette son baton.
 Et l'on voit s'envoler le calcul de Newton
 Monte sur l'ode de Pindare.
Superb, it glides with a hymn in its wings;  
And we see the verse of progress pass by.  
It is the ship, it is the lighthouse!  
Finally, man takes his scepter and throws down his staff.  
And we see Newton's calculus take flight  
Rising on the ode of Pindar.

But if this vision foreshadows the conquest of the air, its significance is symbolic rather than literal, and, like Pindar checking the steeds of his song, Hugo returns to earth:

But if this vision hints at the domination of the skies, its importance is more symbolic than literal, and, like Pindar reining in the horses of his poem, Hugo brings himself back to reality:

 Pas si loin! pas si haut! redescendons.
 Restons L'homme, restons Adam; mais non l'homme a tatons,
 Mais non l'Adam tombe! Tout autre reve altere
 L'espece d'ideal qui convient a la terre.
 Contentons-nous du mot: meilleur! ecrit partout.
Pas si loin! pas si haut! redescendons.  
Restons L'homme, restons Adam; mais non l'homme a tatons,  
Mais non l'Adam tombe! Tout autre reve altere  
L'espece d'ideal qui convient a la terre.  
Contentons-nous du mot: meilleur! ecrit partout.

Dawn has appeared, after six thousand years in the fatal way, and man, freed by "the invisible hand" from the weight of his chains, has embarked for new shores:

Dawn has arrived, after six thousand years of hardship, and humanity, liberated by "the invisible hand" from the burden of its chains, has set sail for new horizons:

 Ou va-t-il ce navire? II va, de jour vetu,
 A l'avenir divin et pur, a la vertu,
 A la science qu'on voit luire,
 A la mort des fleaux, a l'oubli genereux,
 A l'abondance, au caime, au rire, a l'homme heureux,
 Il va, ce glorieux navire.
 Où va-t-il ce navire? Il va, de jour vêtu,  
 À l'avenir divin et pur, à la vertu,  
 À la science qu'on voit briller,  
 À la mort des fléaux, à l'oubli généreux,  
 À l'abondance, au calme, au rire, à l'homme heureux,  
 Il va, ce glorieux navire.
 Oh! ce navire fait le voyage sacre!
 C'est l'ascension bleue a son premier degre;
 Hors de l'antique et vil decombre,
 Hors de la pesanteur, c'est l'avenir fonde;
 C'est le destin de l'homme a la fin evade,
 Qui leve l'ancre et sort de l'ombre!
Oh! This ship makes the sacred journey!  
It's the blue ascent at its first degree;  
Out of the ancient and vile wreckage,  
Out of the heaviness, it's the future founded;  
It's the man's destiny finally escaped,  
Who lifts anchor and leaves the shadows!  

The union of humanity in a universal commonwealth, which Tennyson had expressed as "the Parliament of Man, the Federation of the World," the goal of many theorists of Progress, becomes in Hugo's imagination something more sublime. The magic ship of man's destiny is to compass the cosmopolis of the Stoics, a terrestrial order in harmony with the whole universe.

The unity of humanity in a global community, which Tennyson described as "the Parliament of Man, the Federation of the World," the aim of many advocates of Progress, transforms in Hugo's vision into something even more profound. The remarkable journey of humanity's destiny is to encompass the cosmopolis of the Stoics, a world that exists in harmony with the entire universe.

 Nef magique et supreme! elle a, rien qu'eri marchant,
 Change le cri terrestre en pur et joyeux chant,
 Rajeuni les races fletries,
 Etabli l'ordre vrai, montre le chemin sur,
 Dieu juste! et fait entrer dans l'homme tant d'azur
 Qu'elle a supprime les patries!
Nef magical and supreme! It has, just by walking,  
Changed the earthly cry into pure and joyful song,  
Revived the withered races,  
Established true order, shown the straight path,  
Just God! And has brought so much blue into man  
That it has erased the homelands!
 Faisant a l'homme avec le ciel une cite,
 Une pensee avec toute l'immensite,
 Elle abolit les vieilles regles;
 Elle abaisse les monts, elle annule les tours;
 Splendide, elle introduit les peuples, marcheurs lourds,
 Dans la communion des aigles.
Faisant a l'homme avec le ciel une cite,  
Une pensee avec toute l'immensite,  
Elle abolit les vieilles regles;  
Elle abaisse les monts, elle annule les tours;  
Splendide, elle introduit les peuples, marcheurs lourds,  
Dans la communion des aigles.  

3.

3.

Between 1830 and 1850 railway transport spread throughout Great Britain and was introduced on the Continent, and electricity was subdued to man's use by the invention of telegraphy. The great Exhibition of London in 1851 was, in one of its aspects, a public recognition of the material progress of the age and the growing power of man over the physical world. Its aim, said a contemporary, was "to seize the living scroll of human progress, inscribed with every successive conquest of man's intellect."[Footnote: Edinburgh Review (October 1851), p. 562, in a review of the Official Catalogue of the Exhibition.] The Prince Consort, who originated the Exhibition, explained its significance in a public speech:

Between 1830 and 1850, rail transport expanded across Great Britain and made its way to the Continent, while electricity was harnessed for human use with the invention of the telegraph. The Great Exhibition in London in 1851 served as a public acknowledgment of the era's material advancements and humanity's growing control over the physical world. Its goal, as a contemporary noted, was "to capture the living document of human progress, marked by every successive achievement of human intellect." [Footnote: Edinburgh Review (October 1851), p. 562, in a review of the Official Catalogue of the Exhibition.] The Prince Consort, who initiated the Exhibition, explained its importance in a public address:

"Nobody who has paid any attention to the peculiar features of our present era will doubt for a moment that we are living at a period of most wonderful transition, which tends rapidly to accomplish that great end to which indeed all history points—THE REALISATION OF THE UNITY OF MANKIND.... The distances which separated the different nations and parts of the globe are rapidly vanishing before the achievements of modern invention, and we can traverse them with incredible ease; the languages of all nations are known, and their acquirements placed within the reach of everybody; thought is communicated with the rapidity, and even by the power, of lightning. On the other hand, the GREAT PRINCIPLE OF DIVISION OF LABOUR, which may be called the moving power of civilisation, is being extended to all branches of science, industry, and art... Gentlemen, the Exhibition of 1851 is to give us a true test and a living picture of the point of development at which the whole of mankind has arrived in this great task, and a new starting-point from which all nations will be able to direct their further exertions." [Footnote: Martin, Life of the Prince Consort (ed. 3), iii. p. 247. The speech was delivered at a banquet at the Mansion House on March 21, 1850.]

"Anyone who has noticed the unique aspects of our current era will not doubt for a second that we are living in a time of extraordinary change, which is quickly progressing toward that ultimate goal all of history points toward—THE REALIZATION OF THE UNITY OF MANKIND.... The distances that once separated different nations and regions of the world are disappearing rapidly thanks to modern inventions, allowing us to cross them with incredible ease; the languages of all countries are now accessible, and their knowledge is available to everyone; ideas are shared with the speed and even the force of lightning. On the other hand, the GREAT PRINCIPLE OF DIVISION OF LABOR, which can be considered the driving force of civilization, is being applied across all fields of science, industry, and art... Ladies and gentlemen, the Exhibition of 1851 will provide us with a genuine measure and a vivid snapshot of the level of development humanity has reached in this significant endeavor, and a new starting point from which all nations can focus their future efforts." [Footnote: Martin, Life of the Prince Consort (ed. 3), iii. p. 247. The speech was delivered at a banquet at the Mansion House on March 21, 1850.]

The point emphasised here is the "solidarity" of the world. The Exhibition is to bring home to men's consciousness the community of all the inhabitants of the earth. The assembled peoples, wrote Thackeray, in his "May-day Ode," [Footnote: Published in the Times, April 30, 1851. The Exhibition was opened on May I.] See the sumptuous banquet set, The brotherhood of nations met Around the feast.

The key idea being highlighted here is the "solidarity" of the world. The Exhibition aims to make people aware of the interconnectedness of all the inhabitants of the planet. The gathered nations, as Thackeray mentioned in his "May-day Ode," [Footnote: Published in the Times, April 30, 1851. The Exhibition was opened on May 1.] Look at the lavish banquet laid out, The brotherhood of nations gathered Around the feast.

And this was the note struck in the leading article of the Times on the opening day: "The first morning since the creation that all peoples have assembled from all parts of the world and done a common act." It was claimed that the Exhibition signified a new, intelligent, and moral movement which "marks a great crisis in the history of the world," and foreshadows universal peace.

And this was the message highlighted in the main article of the Times on the opening day: "The first morning since the beginning of time that all nations have come together from every corner of the globe to take part in a shared event." It was stated that the Exhibition represented a new, informed, and ethical movement that "marks a significant turning point in world history" and predicts global peace.

England, said another writer, produced Bacon and Newton, the two philosophers "who first lent direction and force to the stream of industrial science; we have been the first also to give the widest possible base to the watch-tower of international progress, which seeks the formation of the physical well-being of man and the extinction of the meaner jealousies of commerce."[Footnote: Edinburgh Review, loc. cit.]

England, as another writer noted, gave rise to Bacon and Newton, the two philosophers "who first guided and energized the flow of industrial science; we have also been the first to provide the broadest possible foundation for the watchtower of international progress, which aims for the improvement of human physical well-being and the elimination of petty commercial rivalries."[Footnote: Edinburgh Review, loc. cit.]

These quotations show that the great Exhibition was at the time optimistically regarded, not merely as a record of material achievements, but as a demonstration that humanity was at last well on its way to a better and happier state, through the falling of barriers and the resulting insight that the interests of all are closely interlocked. A vista was suggested, at the end of which far-sighted people might think they discerned Tennyson's "Federation of the World."

These quotes show that the Great Exhibition was viewed optimistically at the time, not just as a record of material accomplishments, but as proof that humanity was finally on its way to a better and happier future, thanks to the breaking down of barriers and the realization that everyone's interests are closely connected. A vision was hinted at, where forward-thinking individuals might believe they could see Tennyson's "Federation of the World."

4.

4.

Since the Exhibition, western civilisation has advanced steadily, and in some respects more rapidly than any sober mind could have predicted—civilisation, at least, in the conventional sense, which has been not badly defined as "the development of material ease, of education, of equality, and of aspirations to rise and succeed in life." [Footnote: B. Kidd, Social Evolution, p. 368.] The most striking advance has been in the technical conveniences of life—that is, in the control over natural forces. It would be superfluous to enumerate the discoveries and inventions since 1850 which have abridged space, economised time, eased bodily suffering, and reduced in some ways the friction of life, though they have increased it in others. This uninterrupted series of technical inventions, proceeding concurrently with immense enlargements of all branches of knowledge, has gradually accustomed the least speculative mind to the conception that civilisation is naturally progressive, and that continuous improvement is part of the order of things.

Since the Exhibition, Western civilization has steadily progressed, and in some ways more quickly than anyone could have expected—civilization, at least in the traditional sense, which can be described as "the development of material comfort, education, equality, and aspirations to rise and succeed in life." [Footnote: B. Kidd, Social Evolution, p. 368.] The most notable advancement has been in the technological conveniences of life—that is, in our ability to control natural forces. It would be unnecessary to list the discoveries and inventions since 1850 that have shortened distances, saved time, alleviated physical suffering, and reduced some of life's struggles, even though they have increased it in other areas. This ongoing stream of technical innovations, happening alongside significant expansions in all fields of knowledge, has gradually led even the least speculative mind to accept the idea that civilization is naturally progressive and that continuous improvement is simply part of how things are.

So far the hopes of 1851 have been fulfilled. But against all this technical progress, with the enormous expansion of industry and commerce, dazzling to the man in the market-place when he pauses to reflect, have to be set the exploitation and sufferings of industrial workers, the distress of intense economic competition, the heavier burdens of preparation for modern war. The very increase of "material ease" seemed unavoidably to involve conditions inconsistent with universal happiness; and the communications which linked the peoples of the world together modified the methods of warfare instead of bringing peace. "Toutes nos merveilleuses inventions sont aussi puissantes pour le mal que pour le bien." [Footnote: H. de Ferron, Theorie du progres (1867), ii. 439.] One fact indeed might be taken as an index that humanity was morally advancing—the abolition of slavery in America at the price of a long and sanguinary war. Yet some triumphs of philanthropy hardly seemed to endanger the conclusion that, while knowledge is indefinitely progressive, there is no good reason for sanguine hopes that man is "perfectible" or that universal happiness is attainable. A thoughtful writer observed, discussing Progress in 1864, that the innumerable individual steps in the growth of knowledge and business organisation have not been combined, so far, to produce a general advance in the happiness of life; each step brings increase of pressure. [Footnote: Lotze, Microcosmus (Eng. tr.), vol. ii. p. 396.]

So far, the hopes of 1851 have come true. But alongside all this technical advancement, with the massive growth of industry and commerce that's truly impressive to anyone in the marketplace when they stop to think, we must also recognize the exploitation and suffering of industrial workers, the strain of fierce economic competition, and the heavier burdens of preparing for modern warfare. The very rise in "material comfort" seems inevitably to create situations that are inconsistent with universal happiness; and the connections that link people around the world have changed the nature of warfare rather than fostering peace. "All our wonderful inventions are just as powerful for harm as they are for good." [Footnote: H. de Ferron, Theorie du progres (1867), ii. 439.] One fact could be seen as evidence that humanity is making moral progress—the abolition of slavery in America, achieved at the cost of a long and bloody war. Yet some humanitarian victories hardly challenge the idea that, while knowledge continues to grow, there's no strong reason to believe that humanity is "perfectible" or that universal happiness can be achieved. A thoughtful writer noted, while discussing Progress in 1864, that the countless individual advances in knowledge and business organization have not, so far, resulted in a general improvement in the happiness of life; each step just adds more pressure. [Footnote: Lotze, Microcosmus (Eng. tr.), vol. ii. p. 396.]

Yet in spite of all adverse facts and many eminent dissenters the belief in social Progress has on the whole prevailed. This triumph of optimism was promoted by the victory of a revolutionary hypothesis in another field of inquiry, which suddenly electrified the world. [Footnote: Against Lotze we might set many opinions which do not seem to have been influenced by the doctrine of evolution. For instance, the optimism of M. Marcellin-Berthelot in a letter to Renan in 1863. He says (Renan, Dialogues, p. 233) that one of the general results of historical study is "the fact of the incessant progress of human societies in science, in material conditions, and in morality, three correlatives.... Societies become more and more civilised, and I will venture to say more and more virtuous. The sum of good is always increasing, and the sum of evil diminishing, in the same measure as the sum of truth increases and the sum of ignorance diminishes."

Yet despite all the negative facts and numerous well-known critics, the belief in social progress has largely prevailed. This victory of optimism was fueled by the emergence of a revolutionary hypothesis in another area of study that suddenly captured the world's attention. [Footnote: Against Lotze, we could cite many opinions that don’t appear to have been influenced by the theory of evolution. For example, M. Marcellin-Berthelot's optimism in a letter to Renan in 1863. He states (Renan, Dialogues, p. 233) that one of the overall results of historical study is "the fact of the continuous progress of human societies in science, in material conditions, and in morality, three interrelated aspects.... Societies are becoming increasingly civilized, and I would dare to say increasingly virtuous. The amount of good is constantly growing, while the amount of evil is diminishing, in the same measure that the amount of truth increases and the amount of ignorance decreases."

In 1867 Emerson delivered an address at Harvard on the "Progress of Culture" (printed in his Letters and Social Aims), in which he enumerates optimistically the indications of social advance: "the new scope of social science; the abolition of capital punishment and of imprisonment for debt: the improvement of prisons; the efforts for the suppression of intemperance, vice, etc.," and asks: "Who would live in the stone age, or the bronze, or the iron, or the lacustrine? Who does not prefer the age of steel, of gold, of coal, petroleum, cotton, steam, electricity, and the spectroscope?"

In 1867, Emerson gave a talk at Harvard on the "Progress of Culture" (printed in his Letters and Social Aims), where he optimistically listed the signs of social progress: "the new scope of social science; the abolition of the death penalty and imprisonment for debt; improvements in prisons; efforts to combat alcoholism, vice, etc.," and he asked: "Who would want to live in the Stone Age, or the Bronze Age, or the Iron Age, or even the Lake Dwelling period? Who doesn’t prefer the age of steel, gold, coal, petroleum, cotton, steam, electricity, and the spectroscope?"

The discursive Thoughts on the Future of the Human Race, published in 1866, by W. Ellis (1800-81), a disciple of J. S. Mill, would have been remarkable if it had appeared half a century earlier. He is untouched by the theory of evolution, and argues on common-sense grounds that Progress is inevitable.]

The essay Thoughts on the Future of the Human Race, published in 1866 by W. Ellis (1800-81), a follower of J. S. Mill, would have been noteworthy if it had been published fifty years earlier. He is unaffected by the theory of evolution and argues from a common-sense perspective that Progress is unavoidable.





CHAPTER XIX. PROGRESS IN THE LIGHT OF EVOLUTION

1.

In the sixties of the nineteenth century the idea of Progress entered upon the third period of its history. During the FIRST period, up to the French Revolution, it had been treated rather casually; it was taken for granted and received no searching examination either from philosophers or from historians. In the SECOND period its immense significance was apprehended, and a search began for a general law which would define and establish it. The study of sociology was founded, and at the same time the impressive results of science, applied to the conveniences of life, advertised the idea. It harmonised with the notion of "development" which had become current both in natural science and in metaphysics. Socialists and other political reformers appealed to it as a gospel.

In the 1860s, the concept of Progress entered its third phase. During the FIRST phase, which lasted until the French Revolution, it was viewed quite casually; it was accepted without question and didn’t receive serious examination from philosophers or historians. In the SECOND phase, its tremendous importance was recognized, leading to a search for a universal principle that would define and establish it. The field of sociology was created, and at the same time, the remarkable achievements of science, applied to everyday life, promoted the idea. It aligned with the concept of "development," which had become popular in both natural science and metaphysics. Socialists and other political reformers embraced it as a core belief.

By 1850 it was a familiar idea in Europe, but was not yet universally accepted as obviously true. The notion of social Progress had been growing in the atmosphere of the notion of biological development, but this development still seemed a highly precarious speculation. The fixity of species and the creation of man, defended by powerful interests and prejudices, were attacked but were not shaken. The hypothesis of organic evolution was much in the same position as the Copernican hypothesis in the sixteenth century. Then in 1859 Darwin intervened, like Galileo. The appearance of the ORIGIN OF SPECIES changed the situation by disproving definitely the dogma of fixity of species and assigning real causes for "transformism." What might be set aside before as a brilliant guess was elevated to the rank of a scientific hypothesis, and the following twenty years were enlivened by the struggle around the evolution of life, against prejudices chiefly theological, resulting in the victory of the theory.

By 1850, it was a well-known idea in Europe, but it wasn’t yet widely accepted as obviously true. The concept of social progress was developing alongside the idea of biological evolution, but this concept still appeared to be a risky theory. The belief in the permanence of species and the creation of humans, supported by strong interests and biases, was challenged but remained intact. The idea of organic evolution was in a similar position as the Copernican theory in the sixteenth century. Then in 1859, Darwin stepped in, much like Galileo. The publication of the ORIGIN OF SPECIES changed everything by definitively disproving the belief in the permanence of species and providing real explanations for "transformism." What might have previously been dismissed as a brilliant guess was now considered a scientific hypothesis, and the next twenty years were filled with debates about the evolution of life, primarily against theological prejudices, leading to the triumph of the theory.

The ORIGIN OF SPECIES led to the THIRD stage of the fortunes of the idea of Progress. We saw how the heliocentric astronomy, by dethroning man from his privileged position in the universe of space and throwing him back on his own efforts, had helped that idea to compete with the idea of a busy Providence. He now suffers a new degradation within the compass of his own planet. Evolution, shearing him of his glory as a rational being specially created to be the lord of the earth, traces a humble pedigree for him. And this second degradation was the decisive fact which has established the reign of the idea of Progress.

The ORIGIN OF SPECIES marked the THIRD stage in the development of the idea of Progress. We’ve seen how heliocentric astronomy, by removing man from his privileged spot in the universe and forcing him to rely on his own efforts, allowed that idea to compete with the notion of a busy Providence. Now, he faces a new decline right here on his own planet. Evolution strips him of his status as a uniquely created rational being who rules the earth and presents a more humble lineage for him. This second decline was the key factor that solidified the dominance of the idea of Progress.

2.

2.

Evolution itself, it must be remembered, does not necessarily mean, applied to society, the movement of man to a desirable goal. It is a neutral, scientific conception, compatible either with optimism or with pessimism. According to different estimates it may appear to be a cruel sentence or a guarantee of steady amelioration. And it has been actually interpreted in both ways.

Evolution itself, it’s important to note, doesn’t inherently imply that society is moving towards a positive outcome. It is a neutral, scientific concept that can align with either optimism or pessimism. Depending on one's perspective, it can seem like a harsh verdict or a promise of continuous improvement. In fact, it has been understood in both ways.

In order to base Progress on Evolution two distinct arguments are required. If it could be shown that social life obeys the same general laws of evolution as nature, and also that the process involves an increase of happiness, then Progress would be as valid a hypothesis as the evolution of living forms. Darwin had concluded his treatise with these words:

In order to ground Progress in Evolution, two separate arguments are needed. If it can be demonstrated that social life follows the same general laws of evolution as nature, and also that this process leads to greater happiness, then Progress would be as credible a concept as the evolution of living things. Darwin concluded his treatise with these words:

As all the living forms of life are the lineal descendants of those which lived long before the Silurian epoch, we may feel certain that the ordinary succession by generation has never once been broken, and that no cataclysm has desolated the whole world. Hence we may look with some confidence to a secure future of equally inappreciable length. And as natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental environments will tend to progress towards perfection.

As all living organisms are direct descendants of those that existed long before the Silurian period, we can be confident that the typical process of reproduction has never been interrupted and that no disaster has wiped out the entire planet. Therefore, we can look forward to a secure future of an immeasurable length. Since natural selection operates solely for the benefit of each individual, all physical and mental environments will likely evolve towards perfection.

Here the evolutionist struck the note of optimism. And he suggested that laws of Progress would be found in other quarters than those where they had hitherto been sought.

Here, the evolutionist expressed a sense of optimism. He proposed that the laws of Progress would be discovered in places other than where they had traditionally been looked for.

The ablest and most influential development of the argument from evolution to Progress was the work of Spencer. He extended the principle of evolution to sociology and ethics, and was the most conspicuous interpreter of it in an optimistic sense. He had been an evolutionist long before Darwin's decisive intervention, and in 1851 he had published his Social Statics, which, although he had not yet worked out the evolutionary laws which he began to formulate soon afterwards and was still a theist, exhibits the general trend of his optimistic philosophy. Progress here appears as the basis of a theory of ethics. The title indicates the influence of Comte, but the argument is sharply opposed to the spirit of Comte's teaching, and sociology is treated in a new way. [Footnote: Social Statics, or the Conditions Essential to Human Happiness specified, and the first of them developed, is the full title.]

The most capable and influential development of the argument connecting evolution to Progress was done by Spencer. He broadened the concept of evolution to include sociology and ethics, becoming the most prominent interpreter of it in an optimistic way. He had been an evolutionist long before Darwin made his significant contributions, and in 1851 he published his Social Statics, which, although he hadn’t yet fully developed the evolutionary laws that he would soon start to define and was still a theist, shows the general direction of his optimistic philosophy. Progress, in this context, serves as the foundation of a theory of ethics. The title reflects the influence of Comte, but the argument directly contrasts with Comte's teachings, approaching sociology in a new light. [Footnote: Social Statics, or the Conditions Essential to Human Happiness specified, and the first of them developed, is the full title.]

Spencer begins by arguing that the constancy of human nature, so frequently alleged, is a fallacy. For change is the law of all things, of every single object as well as of the universe. "Nature in its infinite complexity is ever growing to a new development." It would be strange if, in this universal mutation, man alone were unchangeable, and it is not true. "He also obeys the law of indefinite variation." Contrast the houseless savages with Newtons and Shakespeares; between these extremes there are countless degrees of difference. If then humanity is indefinitely variable, perfectibility is possible.

Spencer starts by arguing that the idea of a constant human nature, often claimed, is a misconception. Everything, including every single object and the universe itself, is subject to change. "Nature, in its infinite complexity, is always evolving into something new." It would be odd if, amidst this universal change, humans alone remained unchanged, and that's simply not the case. "Humans also follow the law of endless variation." Compare the homeless savages with Newtons and Shakespeares; there are countless variations in between these extremes. If humanity can change indefinitely, then perfection is achievable.

In the second place, evil is not a permanent necessity. For all evil results from the non-adaptation of the organism to its conditions; this is true of everything that lives. And it is equally true that evil perpetually tends to disappear. In virtue of an essential principle of life, this non-adaptation of organisms to their conditions is ever being rectified, and one or both continue to be modified until the adaptation is perfect. And this applies to the mental as well as to the physical sphere.

In the second place, evil is not a constant requirement. All evil comes from the organism's failure to adapt to its conditions; this holds true for everything that lives. It's also true that evil continually seeks to vanish. Due to a fundamental principle of life, this failure of organisms to adjust to their conditions is always being corrected, and one or both keep changing until the adaptation is complete. This applies to both the mental and physical aspects.

In the present state of the world men suffer many evils, and this shows that their characters are not yet adjusted to the social state. Now the qualification requisite for the social state is that each individual shall have such desires only as may fully be satisfied without trenching upon the ability of others to obtain similar satisfaction. This qualification is not yet fulfilled, because civilised man retains some of the characteristics which were suitable for the conditions of his earlier predatory life. He needed one moral constitution for his primitive state, he needs quite another for his present state. The resultant is a process of adaptation which has been going on for a long time, and will go on for a long time to come.

In today’s world, people experience many problems, showing that their characters are not yet aligned with society. The requirement for a social environment is that each person should only have desires that can be completely fulfilled without interfering with others' ability to achieve similar fulfillment. This requirement is still not met, because modern humans still possess some traits that were suitable for their earlier, more predatory existence. They needed one set of moral guidelines for their primitive life and a completely different one for the current society. The result is an ongoing process of adaptation that has been happening for a long time and will continue for a long time to come.

Civilisation represents the adaptations which have already been accomplished. Progress means the successive steps of the process. That by this process man will eventually become suited to his mode of life, Spencer has no doubts. All excess and deficiency of suitable faculties must disappear; in other words, all imperfection. "The ultimate development of the ideal man is logically certain—as certain as any conclusion in which we place the most implicit faith; for instance, that all men will die." Here is the theory of perfectibility asserted, on new grounds, with a confidence not less assured than that of Condorcet or Godwin.

Civilization reflects the adaptations that have already been made. Progress refers to the ongoing steps of this process. Spencer is certain that through this process, humanity will ultimately become well-suited to its way of life. Any excess or lack of appropriate abilities will fade away; in other words, all imperfections will vanish. "The ultimate development of the ideal person is logically inevitable—just as certain as any conclusion we trust implicitly; for example, that all humans will die." This is the theory of perfectibility stated with renewed confidence, as assured as that of Condorcet or Godwin.

Progress then is not an accident, but a necessity. Civilisation is a part of nature, being a development of man's latent capabilities under the action of favourable circumstances which were certain at some time or other to occur. Here Spencer's argument assumes a final cause. The ultimate purpose of creation, he asserts, is to produce the greatest amount of happiness, and to fulfil this aim it is necessary that each member of the race should possess faculties enabling him to experience the highest enjoyment of life, yet in such a way as not to diminish the power of others to receive like satisfaction. Beings thus constituted cannot multiply in a world tenanted by inferior creatures; these, therefore, must be dispossessed to make room; and to dispossess them aboriginal man must have an inferior constitution to begin with; he must be predatory, he must have the desire to kill. In general, given an unsubdued earth, and the human being "appointed" to overspread and occupy it, then, the laws of life being what they are, no other series of changes than that which has actually occurred could have occurred.

Progress is not just a coincidence; it’s essential. Civilization is part of nature, reflecting the development of human potential under favorable circumstances that were bound to happen eventually. Here, Spencer’s argument introduces a final cause. He claims the ultimate goal of creation is to generate the most happiness, and to achieve this, every individual must have the abilities to enjoy life fully, without reducing others' capacity to experience the same joy. Beings designed this way cannot thrive in a world occupied by lesser creatures; therefore, these creatures must be removed to make space. To remove them, early humans must have started with a weaker nature; they needed to be predatory and possess a desire to kill. Generally speaking, with an untamed earth and humanity meant to spread across it, the existing laws of life ensure that no other series of events could have unfolded beyond what has actually happened.

The argument might be put in a form free from the assumption of a final cause, and without introducing the conception of a divine Providence which in this work Spencer adopted, though in his later philosophy it was superseded by the conception of the Unknowable existing behind all phenomena. But the ROLE of the Divine ruler is simply to set in motion immutable forces to realise his design. "In the moral as in the material world accumulated evidence is gradually generating the conviction that events are not at bottom fortuitous, but that they are wrought out in a certain inevitable way by unchanging forces."

The argument can be expressed without assuming a final cause and without bringing in the idea of divine Providence, which Spencer used in this work but later replaced with the concept of the Unknowable behind all phenomena. However, the ROLE of the Divine ruler is just to set in motion unchanging forces to achieve his purpose. "In both the moral and material worlds, accumulating evidence is slowly building the belief that events are not random at their core, but are shaped in a certain inevitable manner by constant forces."

The optimism of Spencer's view could not be surpassed. "After patient study," he writes, "this chaos of phenomena into the midst of which he [man] was born has begun to generalise itself to him"; instead of confusion he begins to discern "the dim outlines of a gigantic plan. No accidents, no chance, but everywhere order and completeness One by one exceptions vanish, and all becomes systematic."

The optimism in Spencer's perspective was unmatched. "After careful study," he writes, "this chaotic world into which he [man] was born has started to make sense to him"; instead of confusion, he starts to see "the faint outlines of a massive plan. No accidents, no randomness, but everywhere there is order and wholeness. One by one, exceptions disappear, and everything becomes systematic."

Always towards perfection is the mighty movement—towards a complete development and a more unmixed good; subordinating in its universality all petty irregularities and fallings back, as the curvature of the earth subordinates mountains and valleys. Even in evils the student learns to recognise only a struggling beneficence. But above all he is struck with the inherent sufficingness of things.

Always striving for perfection is the powerful movement—toward a complete development and a more pure good; overriding in its universality all minor irregularities and setbacks, just like the curvature of the earth encompasses mountains and valleys. Even in challenges, the learner comes to see only a striving for good. But most of all, he is impressed by the inherent sufficiency of things.

But the movement towards harmony, the elimination of evil, will not be effected by idealists imposing their constructions upon the world or by authoritarian governments. It means gradual adaptation, gradual psychological change, and its life is individual liberty. It proceeds by the give and take of opposed opinions. Guizot had said, "Progress, and at the same time resistance." And Spencer conceives that resistance is beneficial, so long as it comes from those who honestly think that the institutions they defend are really the best and the proposed innovations absolutely wrong.

But the push for harmony and the removal of evil won't happen through idealists forcing their ideas on the world or through authoritarian governments. It involves a gradual adjustment, a slow psychological shift, and at its core is individual freedom. It happens through the exchange of opposing views. Guizot once said, "Progress, and at the same time resistance." And Spencer believes that resistance is helpful, as long as it's from those who genuinely believe that the institutions they support are the best and that the suggested changes are completely misguided.

It will be observed that Spencer's doctrine of perfectibility rests on an entirely different basis from the doctrine of the eighteenth century. It is one thing to deduce it from an abstract psychology which holds that human nature is unresistingly plastic in the hands of the legislator and the instructor. It is another to argue that human nature is subject to the general law of change, and that the process by which it slowly but continuously tends to adapt itself more and more to the conditions of social life—children inheriting the acquired aptitudes of their parents—points to an ultimate harmony. Here profitable legislation and education are auxiliary to the process of unconscious adaptation, and respond to the psychological changes in the community, changes which reveal themselves in public opinion.

You’ll notice that Spencer's idea of perfectibility is based on a completely different foundation than the ideas from the eighteenth century. It’s one thing to derive it from an abstract understanding of psychology that claims human nature is easily shaped by lawmakers and teachers. It’s another to argue that human nature follows the general law of change, and that the way it gradually but continuously adjusts itself to the demands of social life—where children inherit their parents' developed skills—indicates a final harmony. In this context, effective laws and education support the process of unconscious adaptation and respond to the psychological shifts in society, which are reflected in public opinion.

3.

3.

During the following ten years Spencer was investigating the general laws of evolution and planning his Synthetic Philosophy which was to explain the development of the universe. [Footnote: In an article on "Progress: its Law and Cause," in the Westminster Review, April 1857, Spencer explained that social progress, rightly understood, is not the increase of material conveniences or widening freedom of action, but changes of structure in the social organism which entail such consequences, and proceeded to show that the growth of the individual organism and the growth of civilisation obey the same law of advance from homogeneity to heterogeneity of structure. Here he used progress in a neutral sense; but recognising that a word is required which has no teleological implications (Autobiography, i. 500), he adopted evolution six months later in an article on "Transcendental Physiology" (National Review, Oct. 1857). In his study of organic laws Spencer was indirectly influenced by the ideas of Schelling through von Baer.] He aimed at showing that laws of change are discoverable which control all phenomena alike, inorganic, biological, psychical, and social. In the light of this hypothesis the actual progression of humanity is established as a necessary fact, a sequel of the general cosmic movement and governed by the same principles; and, if that progression is shown to involve increasing happiness, the theory of Progress is established. The first section of the work, FIRST PRINCIPLES, appeared in 1862. The BIOLOGY, the PSYCHOLOGY, and finally the SOCIOLOGY, followed during the next twenty years; and the synthesis of the world-process which these volumes lucidly and persuasively developed, probably did more than any other work, at least in England, both to drive home the significance of the doctrine of evolution and to raise the doctrine of Progress to the rank of a commonplace truth in popular estimation, an axiom to which political rhetoric might effectively appeal.

During the next ten years, Spencer was researching the general laws of evolution and developing his Synthetic Philosophy, which aimed to explain how the universe develops. [Footnote: In an article titled "Progress: its Law and Cause," published in the Westminster Review in April 1857, Spencer clarified that social progress, when properly understood, is not just about more material conveniences or greater freedom to act, but about changes in the structure of the social organism that lead to such outcomes. He went on to demonstrate that the growth of individual organisms and the growth of civilization follow the same principle of moving from simplicity to complexity in structure. He used "progress" in a neutral way here, but realizing that a term without teleological implications was needed (Autobiography, i. 500), he chose "evolution" six months later in an article on "Transcendental Physiology" (National Review, Oct. 1857). In his exploration of organic laws, Spencer was indirectly influenced by Schelling’s ideas through von Baer.] He aimed to show that there are discoverable laws of change that govern all phenomena, whether inorganic, biological, psychological, or social. According to this hypothesis, the actual progress of humanity is a necessary fact, a result of the general cosmic movement and governed by the same principles; and if this progress leads to increased happiness, then the theory of Progress is validated. The first section of his work, FIRST PRINCIPLES, was published in 1862. The BIOLOGY, PSYCHOLOGY, and finally SOCIOLOGY followed in the next twenty years; and the synthesis of the world-process presented in these volumes clearly and convincingly contributed more than any other work, at least in England, to emphasize the importance of the doctrine of evolution and to elevate the doctrine of Progress to a commonly accepted truth in public perception, an axiom that political rhetoric could effectively utilize.

Many of those who were allured by Spencer's gigantic synthesis hardly realised that his theory of social evolution, of the gradual psychical improvement of the race, depends upon the validity of the assumption that parents transmit to their children faculties and aptitudes which they have themselves acquired. On this question experts notoriously differ. Some day it will probably be definitely decided, and perhaps in Spencer's favour. But the theory of continuous psychical improvement by a process of nature encounters an obvious difficulty, which did not escape some critics of Spencer, in the prominent fact of history that every great civilisation of the past progressed to a point at which instead of advancing further it stood still and declined, to become the prey of younger societies, or, if it survived, to stagnate. Arrest, decadence, stagnation has been the rule. It is not easy to reconcile this phenomenon with the theory of mental improvement.

Many people who were drawn in by Spencer's huge synthesis didn't really realize that his theory of social evolution, which suggests gradual psychological improvement of the race, relies on the belief that parents pass on abilities and skills they've developed to their children. Experts famously disagree on this issue. One day, it will likely be settled, potentially in Spencer's favor. However, the idea of ongoing psychological improvement through natural processes faces an obvious challenge, noted by some of Spencer's critics, in the historical fact that every major civilization in the past progressed to a point where, instead of advancing further, it stagnated and declined, falling prey to younger societies or, if it managed to survive, fell into stagnation. Stagnation, decline, and decay have been the norm. It's not easy to align this phenomenon with the theory of mental improvement.

The receptive attitude of the public towards such a philosophy as Spencer's had been made possible by Darwin's discoveries, which were reinforced by the growing science of palaeontology and the accumulating material evidence of the great antiquity of man. By the simultaneous advances of geology and biology man's perspective in time was revolutionised, just as the Copernican astronomy had revolutionised his perspective in space. Many thoughtful and many thoughtless people were ready to discern—as Huxley suggested—in man's "long progress through the past, a reasonable ground of faith in his attainment of a nobler future." and Winwood Reade, a young African traveller, exhibited it in a vivid book as a long-drawn-out martyrdom. But he was a disciple of Spencer, and his hopes for the future were as bright as his picture of the past was dark. THE MARTYRDOM OF MAN, published in 1872, was so widely read that it reached an eighth edition twelve years later, and may be counted as one of the agencies which popularised Spencer's optimism.

The public's openness to a philosophy like Spencer's was made possible by Darwin's discoveries, which were supported by the growing field of paleontology and the mounting evidence of humanity's ancient history. The combined advances in geology and biology transformed humanity's view of time, just as Copernican astronomy had changed its view of space. Many reflective and many unreflective individuals were ready to see—as Huxley suggested—in humanity's "long progress through the past, a reasonable basis for believing in its attainment of a better future." Winwood Reade, a young African traveler, portrayed this in a vivid book as a prolonged struggle. However, he was a follower of Spencer, and his hopes for the future were as bright as his depiction of the past was bleak. THE MARTYRDOM OF MAN, published in 1872, became so popular that it reached its eighth edition twelve years later, and can be regarded as one of the factors that helped spread Spencer's optimism.

That optimism was not endorsed by all the contemporary leaders of thought. Lotze had asserted emphatically in 1864 that "human nature will not change," and afterwards he saw no reason to alter his conviction.

That optimism wasn't shared by all the leading thinkers of the time. Lotze strongly stated in 1864 that "human nature will not change," and he saw no reason to change his belief afterward.

Never one fold and one shepherd, never one uniform culture for all mankind, never universal nobleness. Our virtue and happiness can only flourish amid an active conflict with wrong. If every stumbling-block were smoothed away, men would no longer be like men, but like a flock of innocent brutes, feeding on good things provided by nature as at the very beginning of their course. [Footnote: Microcosmus, Bk. vii. 5 ad fin. (Eng. trans. p. 300). The first German edition (three vols.) appeared in 1856-64, the third, from which the English translation was made, in 1876. Lotze was optimistic as to the durability of modern civilisation: "No one will profess to foreknow the future, but as far as men may judge it seems that in our days there arc greater safeguards than there were in antiquity against unjustifiable excesses and against the external forces which might endanger the continued existence of civilisation."]

Never one fold and one shepherd, never one uniform culture for all mankind, never universal nobleness. Our virtue and happiness can only thrive amid an active struggle against wrong. If every obstacle were removed, people would no longer be human, but like a herd of innocent animals, merely consuming the good things provided by nature just as at the very start of their journey. [Footnote: Microcosmus, Bk. vii. 5 ad fin. (Eng. trans. p. 300). The first German edition (three vols.) appeared in 1856-64, the third, from which the English translation was made, in 1876. Lotze was optimistic about the longevity of modern civilization: "No one will claim to foresee the future, but as far as people can judge, it seems that today there are greater protections than there were in ancient times against unjustifiable excesses and against the external forces that could threaten the continued existence of civilization."]

But even if we reject with Spencer the old dictum, endorsed by Lotze as by Fontenelle, that human nature is immutable, the dictum of ultimate harmony encounters the following objection. "If the social environment were stable," it is easy to argue, "it could be admitted that man's nature, variable EX HYPOTHESI, could gradually adapt itself to it, and that finally a definite equilibrium would be established. But the environment is continually changing as the consequence of man's very efforts to adapt himself; every step he takes to harmonise his needs and his conditions produces a new discord and confronts him with a new problem. In other words, there is no reason to believe that the reciprocal process which goes on in the growth of society between men's natures and the environment they are continually modifying will ever reach an equilibrium, or even that, as the character of the discords changes, the suffering which they cause diminishes."

But even if we reject, along with Spencer, the old saying, supported by Lotze and Fontenelle, that human nature doesn’t change, the idea of ultimate harmony faces a major issue. "If the social environment were stable," one could easily argue, "we could accept that human nature, theoretically, might gradually adapt to it, leading to a final state of balance. But the environment is constantly shifting due to man's very efforts to adjust himself; every step he takes to align his needs with his circumstances creates new conflicts and presents him with new challenges. In other words, there's no reason to believe that the ongoing interaction between human nature and the ever-changing environment will ever achieve a balance, or even that, as the nature of these conflicts evolves, the suffering they bring will lessen."

In fact, upon the neutral fact of evolution a theory of pessimism may be built up as speciously as a theory of optimism. And such a theory was built up with great power and ability by the German philosopher E. von Hartmann, whose PHILOSOPHY OF THE UNCONSCIOUS appeared in 1869. Leaving aside his metaphysics and his grotesque theory of the destiny of the universe, we see here and in his subsequent works how plausibly a convinced evolutionist could revive the view of Rousseau that civilisation and happiness are mutually antagonistic, and that Progress means an increase of misery.

In fact, on the neutral basis of evolution, a theory of pessimism can be constructed just as convincingly as a theory of optimism. This kind of theory was developed powerfully and skillfully by the German philosopher E. von Hartmann, whose PHILOSOPHY OF THE UNCONSCIOUS was published in 1869. Setting aside his metaphysics and his bizarre theory of the universe's destiny, we can see here and in his later works how a dedicated evolutionist could effectively revive Rousseau's idea that civilization and happiness are in conflict with each other, and that Progress actually leads to more misery.

Huxley himself, [Footnote: See Agnosticism in Nineteenth Century (Feb. 1889); Government: Anarchy or Regimentation, ib. (May 1890); Essays on Evolution and Ethics (1894).] one of the most eminent interpreters of the doctrine of evolution, did not, in his late years at least, entertain very sanguine views of mankind. "I know of no study which is so saddening as that of the evolution of humanity as it is set forth in the annals of history.... Man is a brute, only more intelligent than other brutes"; and "even the best of modern civilisations appears to me to exhibit a condition of mankind which neither embodies any worthy ideal nor even possesses the merit of stability." There may be some hope of a large improvement, but otherwise he would "welcome a kindly comet to sweep the whole affair away." And he came to the final conclusion that such an improvement could only set in by deliberately resisting, instead of co-operating with, the processes of nature. "Social progress means the checking of the cosmic process at every step and the substitution for it of another which may be called the ethical process." [Footnote: Huxley considers progress exclusively from an ethical, not from an eudaemonic point of view.] How in a few centuries can man hope to gain the mastery over the cosmic process which has been at work for millions of years? "The theory of evolution encourages no millennial anticipations."

Huxley himself, [Footnote: See Agnosticism in Nineteenth Century (Feb. 1889); Government: Anarchy or Regimentation, ib. (May 1890); Essays on Evolution and Ethics (1894).] one of the most prominent interpreters of the theory of evolution, did not, at least in his later years, have very optimistic views about humanity. "I know of no study that is as disheartening as the evolution of humanity as it's presented in the records of history.... Man is a brute, just more intelligent than other brutes"; and "even the best of modern civilizations seems to show a state of humanity that embodies neither any worthy ideal nor even has the merit of stability." There might be some hope for significant improvement, but otherwise he would "welcome a friendly comet to wipe the whole thing away." He ultimately concluded that such an improvement could only happen by actively resisting, rather than cooperating with, the processes of nature. "Social progress means stopping the cosmic process at every turn and replacing it with another which could be called the ethical process." [Footnote: Huxley considers progress exclusively from an ethical, not from an eudaemonic point of view.] How can humanity expect to gain control over the cosmic process that has been in motion for millions of years in just a few centuries? "The theory of evolution offers no expectations of a utopian future."

I have quoted these views to illustrate that evolution lends itself to a pessimistic as well as to an optimistic interpretation. The question whether it leads in a desirable direction or not is answered according to the temperament of the inquirer. In an age of prosperity and self-complacency the affirmative answer was readily received, and the term evolution attracted to itself in common speech the implications of value which belong to Progress.

I have quoted these opinions to show that evolution can be seen in both a negative and a positive light. Whether it moves in a worthwhile direction or not depends on the outlook of the person asking. During a time of wealth and self-satisfaction, the positive answer was quickly embraced, and the term evolution came to carry the same positive associations as Progress in everyday language.

It may be noticed that the self-complacency of the age was promoted by the popularisation of scientific knowledge. A rapidly growing demand (especially in England) for books and lectures, making the results of science accessible and interesting to the lay public, is a remarkable feature of the second half of the nineteenth century; and to supply this demand was a remunerative enterprise. This popular literature explaining the wonders of the physical world was at the same time subtly flushing the imaginations of men with the consciousness that they were living in an era which, in itself vastly superior to any age of the past, need be burdened by no fear of decline or catastrophe, but trusting in the boundless resources of science might securely defy fate.

It’s noticeable that the self-satisfaction of the era was fueled by the rise of scientific knowledge. There was a rapidly growing demand (especially in England) for books and lectures that made science accessible and interesting to the general public, which was a significant aspect of the second half of the nineteenth century. Meeting this demand became a profitable venture. This popular literature, which explained the wonders of the physical world, was also subtly filling people's imaginations with the awareness that they were living in a time that was vastly superior to any previous era and didn’t have to worry about decline or disaster; instead, they could confidently trust in the limitless resources of science to face whatever came their way.

4.

4.

[It was said in 1881 by an American writer (who strongly dissented from Spencer's theory) that the current view was "fatalistic." See Henry George, Progress and Poverty. But it may be doubted whether those of the general public who optimistically accepted evolution without going very deeply into the question really believed that the future of man is taken entirely out of his hands and is determined exclusively by the nature of the cosmic process. Bagehot was a writer who had a good deal of influence in his day; and in Physics and Politics (1872), where he discusses Progress, there is no suggestion of fatalism. In France, the chief philosophical writers who accepted Progress as a fact protested against a fatalistic interpretation (Renouvier, Cournot, Caro; and cf. L. Carrau's article on Progress in the Revue des deux Mondes (Oct. 1875)).

[In 1881, an American writer (who strongly disagreed with Spencer's theory) claimed that the current perspective was "fatalistic." See Henry George, Progress and Poverty. However, it’s questionable whether the general public, who optimistically embraced evolution without delving deeply into the issue, really thought that humanity's future was entirely out of their control and determined solely by the nature of cosmic processes. Bagehot was a significant influencer of his time; in Physics and Politics (1872), where he talks about Progress, there is no hint of fatalism. In France, the main philosophical writers who accepted Progress as a reality opposed a fatalistic interpretation (Renouvier, Cournot, Caro; and see L. Carrau's article on Progress in the Revue des deux Mondes (Oct. 1875)).]

Progress was discussed by Fiske in his Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy (1874), vol. ii. 192 sqq. For him (p. 201) "the fundamental characteristic of social progress is the continuous weakening of selfishness and the continuous strengthening of sympathy."]

Progress was discussed by Fiske in his Outlines of Cosmic Philosophy (1874), vol. ii. 192 sqq. For him (p. 201) "the fundamental characteristic of social progress is the ongoing decrease of selfishness and the ongoing increase of sympathy."

Thus in the seventies and eighties of the last century the idea of Progress was becoming a general article of faith. Some might hold it in the fatalistic form that humanity moves in a desirable direction, whatever men do or may leave undone; others might believe that the future will depend largely on our own conscious efforts, but that there is nothing in the nature of things to disappoint the prospect of steady and indefinite advance. The majority did not inquire too curiously into such points of doctrine, but received it in a vague sense as a comfortable addition to their convictions. But it became a part of the general mental outlook of educated people.

Thus, in the 1970s and 1980s, the idea of Progress became widely accepted. Some viewed it in a fatalistic way, believing that humanity is moving in a positive direction, no matter what actions we take or don't take; others thought the future largely depends on our own efforts but felt there's nothing in the nature of things that could ruin the possibility of continuous and unlimited growth. Most people didn’t dig too deeply into these beliefs but accepted it as a comforting addition to their views. It became a part of the overall mindset of educated individuals.

When Mr. Frederic Harrison delivered in 1889 at Manchester an eloquent discourse on the "New Era," in which the dominant note is "the faith in human progress in lieu of celestial rewards of the separate soul," his general argument could appeal to immensely wider circles than the Positivists whom he was specially addressing.

When Mr. Frederic Harrison gave a powerful speech in 1889 in Manchester about the "New Era," emphasizing "faith in human progress instead of heavenly rewards for individual souls," his overall message resonated with much broader audiences than just the Positivists he was specifically addressing.

The dogma—for a dogma it remains, in spite of the confidence of Comte or of Spencer that he had made it a scientific hypothesis—has produced an important ethical principle. Consideration for posterity has throughout history operated as a motive of conduct, but feebly, occasionally, and in a very limited sense. With the doctrine of Progress it assumes, logically, a preponderating importance; for the centre of interest is transferred to the life of future generations who are to enjoy conditions of happiness denied to us, but which our labours and sufferings are to help to bring about. If the doctrine is held in an extreme fatalistic form, then our duty is to resign ourselves cheerfully to sacrifices for the sake of unknown descendants, just as ordinary altruism enjoins the cheerful acceptance of sacrifices for the sake of living fellow-creatures. Winwood Reade indicated this when he wrote, "Our own prosperity is founded on the agonies of the past. Is it therefore unjust that we also should suffer for the benefit of those who are to come?" But if it is held that each generation can by its own deliberate acts determine for good or evil the destinies of the race, then our duties towards others reach out through time as well as through space, and our contemporaries are only a negligible fraction of the "neighbours" to whom we owe obligations. The ethical end may still be formulated, with the Utilitarians, as the greatest happiness of the greatest number; only the greatest number includes, as Kidd observed, "the members of generations yet unborn or unthought of." This extension of the moral code, if it is not yet conspicuous in treatises on Ethics, has in late years been obtaining recognition in practice.

The belief—despite Comte or Spencer's confidence in turning it into a scientific hypothesis—remains a belief, but it has generated an important ethical principle. Throughout history, consideration for future generations has driven behavior, though weakly and occasionally, and in a very limited way. With the idea of Progress, it logically takes on much greater significance; the focus shifts to the lives of future generations who will experience happiness that we are denied, but that our efforts and struggles will help create. If this idea is viewed in an extreme fatalistic way, then our duty is to cheerfully accept sacrifices for the sake of unknown descendants, just as basic altruism encourages us to accept sacrifices for the benefit of living beings. Winwood Reade pointed this out when he wrote, "Our own prosperity is founded on the agonies of the past. Is it therefore unjust that we also should suffer for the benefit of those who are to come?" However, if it's believed that each generation can shape the future for better or worse through its own choices, then our responsibilities toward others extend across time as well as space, and our contemporaries are just a small fraction of the "neighbors" we owe obligations to. The ethical goal can still be expressed, along with the Utilitarians, as the greatest happiness for the greatest number; but this greatest number includes, as Kidd noted, "the members of generations yet unborn or unthought of." This broadening of the moral code may not yet be prominent in discussions on Ethics, but it has been gaining recognition in practice in recent years.

5.

5.

Within the last forty years nearly every civilised country has produced a large literature on social science, in which indefinite Progress is generally assumed as an axiom. But the "law" whose investigation Kant designated as the task for a Newton, which Saint-Simon and Comte did not find, and to which Spencer's evolutionary formula would stand in the same relation as it stands to the law of gravitation, remains still undiscovered. To examine or even glance at this literature, or to speculate how theories of Progress may be modified by recent philosophical speculation, lies beyond the scope of this volume, which is only concerned with tracing the origin of the idea and its growth up to the time when it became a current creed.

In the past forty years, almost every developed country has created a vast body of work on social science, where indefinite progress is commonly taken as a given. However, the "law" that Kant proposed for investigation, which Saint-Simon and Comte could not identify, and to which Spencer’s evolutionary theory would relate similarly as the law of gravitation does, remains unexplored. To review or even briefly consider this literature or to speculate on how recent philosophical ideas might alter theories of progress is beyond the scope of this book, which is only focused on tracing the origins of the idea and its evolution until it became a widely accepted belief.

Looking back on the course of the inquiry, we note how the history of the idea has been connected with the growth of modern science, with the growth of rationalism, and with the struggle for political and religious liberty. The precursors (Bodin and Bacon) lived at a time when the world was consciously emancipating itself from the authority of tradition and it was being discovered that liberty is a difficult theoretical problem. The idea took definite shape in France when the old scheme of the universe had been shattered by the victory of the new astronomy and the prestige of Providence, CUNCTA SUPERCILIO MOUENTIS, was paling before the majesty of the immutable laws of nature. There began a slow but steady reinstatement of the kingdom of this world. The otherworldly dreams of theologians,

Looking back on the course of the inquiry, we see how the history of the idea has been linked to the development of modern science, the rise of rationalism, and the fight for political and religious freedom. The early thinkers (Bodin and Bacon) lived in a time when the world was actively freeing itself from traditional authority, and it was becoming clear that liberty is a complex theoretical issue. The idea began to take shape in France when the old view of the universe was shattered by the triumph of the new astronomy, and the significance of Providence, CUNCTA SUPERCILIO MOUENTIS, was fading in the presence of the unchanging laws of nature. This marked the beginning of a slow but steady restoration of the earthly kingdom. The otherworldly visions of theologians,

     ceux qui reniaient la terre pour patrie,
those who abandoned their homeland,

which had ruled so long lost their power, and men's earthly home again insinuated itself into their affections, but with the new hope of its becoming a place fit for reasonable beings to live in. We have seen how the belief that our race is travelling towards earthly happiness was propagated by some eminent thinkers, as well as by some "not very fortunate persons who had a good deal of time on their hands." And all these high-priests and incense-bearers to whom the creed owes its success were rationalists, from the author of the Histoire des oracles to the philosopher of the Unknowable.

which had ruled for so long lost their power, and people started to feel attached to their earthly home again, but with the new hope that it could become a place suitable for rational beings to live in. We have seen how the belief that humanity is moving towards earthly happiness was spread by some prominent thinkers, as well as by some "not very lucky people who had a lot of time on their hands." And all these high-priests and incense-bearers to whom the belief owes its success were rationalists, from the author of the Histoire des oracles to the philosopher of the Unknowable.





EPILOGUE

In achieving its ascendency and unfolding its meaning, the Idea of Progress had to overcome a psychological obstacle which may be described as THE ILLUSION OF FINALITY.

In achieving its rise and revealing its significance, the Idea of Progress had to overcome a psychological barrier that can be described as THE ILLUSION OF FINALITY.

It is quite easy to fancy a state of society, vastly different from ours, existing in some unknown place like heaven; it is much more difficult to realise as a fact that the order of things with which we are familiar has so little stability that our actual descendants may be born into a world as different from ours as ours is from that of our ancestors of the pleistocene age.

It’s pretty easy to imagine a society that’s completely different from ours, somewhere like heaven; it’s a lot harder to understand that the way things are right now is so unstable that our future generations might be born into a world as different from ours as ours is from that of our ancestors from the Pleistocene era.

The illusion of finality is strong. The men of the Middle Ages would have found it hard to imagine that a time was not far off in which the Last Judgement would have ceased to arouse any emotional interest. In the sphere of speculation Hegel, and even Comte, illustrate this psychological limitation: they did not recognise that their own systems could not be final any more than the system of Aristotle or of Descartes. It is science, perhaps, more than anything else—the wonderful history of science in the last hundred years—that has helped us to transcend this illusion.

The illusion of finality is very strong. The men of the Middle Ages would have found it hard to imagine that a time would come when the Last Judgment would no longer spark any emotional interest. In the realm of speculation, Hegel, and even Comte, show this psychological limitation: they didn't realize that their own systems couldn't be final any more than Aristotle's or Descartes's. It’s science, perhaps more than anything else—the remarkable history of science over the last hundred years—that has helped us move beyond this illusion.

But if we accept the reasonings on which the dogma of Progress is based, must we not carry them to their full conclusion? In escaping from the illusion of finality, is it legitimate to exempt that dogma itself? Must not it, too, submit to its own negation of finality? Will not that process of change, for which Progress is the optimistic name, compel "Progress" too to fall from the commanding position in which it is now, with apparent security, enthroned? [words in Greek]... A day will come, in the revolution of centuries, when a new idea will usurp its place as the directing idea of humanity. Another star, unnoticed now or invisible, will climb up the intellectual heaven, and human emotions will react to its influence, human plans respond to its guidance. It will be the criterion by which Progress and all other ideas will be judged. And it too will have its successor.

But if we accept the reasoning behind the idea of Progress, should we not take it to its logical conclusion? In breaking free from the illusion of finality, is it valid to exempt that idea itself? Shouldn’t it also undergo its own challenge to finality? Isn’t it likely that the process of change, which we call Progress, will force "Progress" to lose its current, seemingly secure position? A day will come, through the passage of centuries, when a new idea will take its place as the guiding principle for humanity. Another star, currently unnoticed or unseen, will rise in the intellectual sky, and human emotions will respond to its influence, human plans will follow its direction. It will be the standard by which Progress and all other ideas are evaluated. And it too will eventually have its successor.

In other words, does not Progress itself suggest that its value as a doctrine is only relative, corresponding to a certain not very advanced stage of civilisation; just as Providence, in its day, was an idea of relative value, corresponding to a stage somewhat less advanced? Or will it be said that this argument is merely a disconcerting trick of dialectic played under cover of the darkness in which the issue of the future is safely hidden by Horace's prudent god?

In other words, does Progress itself imply that its value as a belief is only relative, linked to a specific, not very advanced stage of civilization? Just as Providence, in its time, was a concept of relative worth, tied to a somewhat less advanced stage? Or will it be said that this argument is just a confusing trick of dialectic, hidden in the darkness where the future's issues are safely concealed by Horace's wise god?










Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!