This is a modern-English version of Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, originally written by Hume, David. It has been thoroughly updated, including changes to sentence structure, words, spelling, and grammar—to ensure clarity for contemporary readers, while preserving the original spirit and nuance. If you click on a paragraph, you will see the original text that we modified, and you can toggle between the two versions.

Scroll to the bottom of this page and you will find a free ePUB download link for this book.



Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion


by

David Hume




PART 1 PART 2 PART 3 PART 4
PART 5 PART 6 PART 7 PART 8
PART 9 PART 10 PART 11 PART 12



PAMPHILUS TO HERMIPPUS

It has been remarked, my HERMIPPUS, that though the ancient philosophers conveyed most of their instruction in the form of dialogue, this method of composition has been little practised in later ages, and has seldom succeeded in the hands of those who have attempted it. Accurate and regular argument, indeed, such as is now expected of philosophical inquirers, naturally throws a man into the methodical and didactic manner; where he can immediately, without preparation, explain the point at which he aims; and thence proceed, without interruption, to deduce the proofs on which it is established. To deliver a SYSTEM in conversation, scarcely appears natural; and while the dialogue-writer desires, by departing from the direct style of composition, to give a freer air to his performance, and avoid the appearance of Author and Reader, he is apt to run into a worse inconvenience, and convey the image of Pedagogue and Pupil. Or, if he carries on the dispute in the natural spirit of good company, by throwing in a variety of topics, and preserving a proper balance among the speakers, he often loses so much time in preparations and transitions, that the reader will scarcely think himself compensated, by all the graces of dialogue, for the order, brevity, and precision, which are sacrificed to them.

It has been noted, my HERMIPPUS, that while ancient philosophers often shared their teachings through dialogue, this style of writing has been rarely used in modern times and has rarely worked well for those who have tried it. The precise and structured arguments that are now expected from philosophical thinkers naturally lead one to a more methodical and instructional style; where they can clearly and directly explain their point without any buildup, and then proceed smoothly to present the evidence supporting their argument. Presenting a SYSTEM in a conversation doesn’t seem very natural; and while the dialogue writer aims to make their work feel more relaxed by stepping away from the traditional composition style and avoiding the roles of Author and Reader, they often end up creating the impression of Teacher and Student instead. Alternatively, if they engage in a debate with the easygoing spirit of good company by introducing various topics and keeping a fair balance among the speakers, they frequently spend so much time on setup and transitions that the reader may not feel that the charm of dialogue makes up for the order, brevity, and clarity that have been sacrificed.

There are some subjects, however, to which dialogue-writing is peculiarly adapted, and where it is still preferable to the direct and simple method of composition.

There are some topics, however, where writing dialogue is particularly suited, and it’s still better than the straightforward and simple way of writing.

Any point of doctrine, which is so obvious that it scarcely admits of dispute, but at the same time so important that it cannot be too often inculcated, seems to require some such method of handling it; where the novelty of the manner may compensate the triteness of the subject; where the vivacity of conversation may enforce the precept; and where the variety of lights, presented by various personages and characters, may appear neither tedious nor redundant.

Any point of doctrine that is so obvious it hardly invites debate, but at the same time so important that it needs to be repeated often, seems to require a special approach; where the novelty of the style can make up for the familiarity of the topic; where lively discussion can reinforce the message; and where the different perspectives shared by various personas and characters can seem neither boring nor excessive.

Any question of philosophy, on the other hand, which is so OBSCURE and UNCERTAIN, that human reason can reach no fixed determination with regard to it; if it should be treated at all, seems to lead us naturally into the style of dialogue and conversation. Reasonable men may be allowed to differ, where no one can reasonably be positive. Opposite sentiments, even without any decision, afford an agreeable amusement; and if the subject be curious and interesting, the book carries us, in a manner, into company; and unites the two greatest and purest pleasures of human life, study and society.

Any philosophical question that is so unclear and uncertain that human reason can’t come to a definite conclusion about it—if it’s to be discussed at all—seems to naturally lead us into a style of dialogue and conversation. Reasonable people can disagree when no one can be truly certain. Conflicting opinions, even without a resolution, provide enjoyable entertainment; and if the topic is intriguing, the book somewhat transports us into company and combines the two greatest and purest pleasures of human life: learning and social interaction.

Happily, these circumstances are all to be found in the subject of NATURAL RELIGION. What truth so obvious, so certain, as the being of a God, which the most ignorant ages have acknowledged, for which the most refined geniuses have ambitiously striven to produce new proofs and arguments? What truth so important as this, which is the ground of all our hopes, the surest foundation of morality, the firmest support of society, and the only principle which ought never to be a moment absent from our thoughts and meditations? But, in treating of this obvious and important truth, what obscure questions occur concerning the nature of that Divine Being, his attributes, his decrees, his plan of providence? These have been always subjected to the disputations of men; concerning these human reason has not reached any certain determination. But these are topics so interesting, that we cannot restrain our restless inquiry with regard to them; though nothing but doubt, uncertainty, and contradiction, have as yet been the result of our most accurate researches.

Fortunately, all of these circumstances are found in the topic of NATURAL RELIGION. What truth is more obvious and certain than the existence of a God, which even the most uninformed ages have recognized, and for which the most brilliant minds have eagerly sought to offer new proofs and arguments? What truth is more significant than this, which underpins all our hopes, serves as the strongest foundation for morality, provides the firmest support for society, and is the only principle that should never be absent from our thoughts and reflections? However, when discussing this clear and important truth, what complicated questions arise about the nature of that Divine Being, His attributes, His decrees, and His plan for providence? These topics have always sparked debates among people; human reason has yet to find any definite answers about them. Yet, these subjects are so captivating that we can't help but continue our relentless inquiry into them, even though our most thorough investigations have resulted only in doubt, uncertainty, and contradiction.

This I had lately occasion to observe, while I passed, as usual, part of the summer season with CLEANTHES, and was present at those conversations of his with PHILO and DEMEA, of which I gave you lately some imperfect account. Your curiosity, you then told me, was so excited, that I must, of necessity, enter into a more exact detail of their reasonings, and display those various systems which they advanced with regard to so delicate a subject as that of natural religion. The remarkable contrast in their characters still further raised your expectations; while you opposed the accurate philosophical turn of CLEANTHES to the careless scepticism of PHILO, or compared either of their dispositions with the rigid inflexible orthodoxy of DEMEA. My youth rendered me a mere auditor of their disputes; and that curiosity, natural to the early season of life, has so deeply imprinted in my memory the whole chain and connection of their arguments, that, I hope, I shall not omit or confound any considerable part of them in the recital.

I recently had the chance to see this while I spent part of the summer with CLEANTHES as usual, and attended his conversations with PHILO and DEMEA, which I briefly mentioned to you before. You told me your curiosity was so piqued that I needed to give a more detailed account of their arguments and explain the different theories they presented on the sensitive topic of natural religion. The clear contrast in their personalities only heightened your interest; you compared the precise philosophical method of CLEANTHES to the casual skepticism of PHILO, or contrasted either of their approaches with the strict, unyielding orthodoxy of DEMEA. My youth made me just a listener to their debates, and that natural curiosity characteristic of early life has left a strong impression on my memory of the entire sequence and connection of their arguments, so I believe I won't leave out or mix up any significant parts in my retelling.




PART 1

After I joined the company, whom I found sitting in CLEANTHES's library, DEMEA paid CLEANTHES some compliments on the great care which he took of my education, and on his unwearied perseverance and constancy in all his friendships. The father of PAMPHILUS, said he, was your intimate friend: The son is your pupil; and may indeed be regarded as your adopted son, were we to judge by the pains which you bestow in conveying to him every useful branch of literature and science. You are no more wanting, I am persuaded, in prudence, than in industry. I shall, therefore, communicate to you a maxim, which I have observed with regard to my own children, that I may learn how far it agrees with your practice. The method I follow in their education is founded on the saying of an ancient, "That students of philosophy ought first to learn logics, then ethics, next physics, last of all the nature of the gods." [Chrysippus apud Plut: de repug: Stoicorum] This science of natural theology, according to him, being the most profound and abstruse of any, required the maturest judgement in its students; and none but a mind enriched with all the other sciences, can safely be entrusted with it.

After I joined the company, I found DEMEA sitting in CLEANTHES's library. He praised CLEANTHES for the great care he took with my education, and for his tireless dedication and loyalty in all his friendships. He said, "The father of PAMPHILUS was your close friend; the son is your student and can really be seen as your adopted son, judging by the effort you put into teaching him every useful aspect of literature and science. I'm sure you are just as wise as you are hardworking. So, I want to share a principle I've followed with my own children, to see how it aligns with your approach. The way I educate them is based on an ancient saying: 'Philosophy students should first learn logic, then ethics, followed by physics, and lastly the nature of the gods.' [Chrysippus apud Plut: de repug: Stoicorum] According to him, this study of natural theology is the most complex and difficult, requiring the highest level of judgment from its students; and only a mind enriched with all the other sciences is fit to tackle it."

Are you so late, says PHILO, in teaching your children the principles of religion? Is there no danger of their neglecting, or rejecting altogether those opinions of which they have heard so little during the whole course of their education? It is only as a science, replied DEMEA, subjected to human reasoning and disputation, that I postpone the study of Natural Theology. To season their minds with early piety, is my chief care; and by continual precept and instruction, and I hope too by example, I imprint deeply on their tender minds an habitual reverence for all the principles of religion. While they pass through every other science, I still remark the uncertainty of each part; the eternal disputations of men; the obscurity of all philosophy; and the strange, ridiculous conclusions, which some of the greatest geniuses have derived from the principles of mere human reason. Having thus tamed their mind to a proper submission and self-diffidence, I have no longer any scruple of opening to them the greatest mysteries of religion; nor apprehend any danger from that assuming arrogance of philosophy, which may lead them to reject the most established doctrines and opinions.

"Are you really that late," PHILO says, "in teaching your kids about the principles of religion? Isn't there a risk they'll neglect or completely reject beliefs they've barely heard about throughout their education?" "It's only because I see it as a science," DEMEA responds, "subject to human reasoning and debate, that I delay the study of Natural Theology. My main concern is to instill early piety in their minds; and through constant teaching and guidance, and I hope also by setting a good example, I aim to deeply engrain a lasting respect for all religious principles in their young minds. While they navigate through every other subject, I still notice the uncertainty in each area, the endless arguments among people, the confusion in all philosophy, and the bizarre, ridiculous conclusions that some of the greatest thinkers have drawn from purely human reasoning. By preparing their minds to be humble and self-aware, I no longer feel hesitant to introduce them to the greatest mysteries of religion, nor do I see any danger in the overconfident arrogance of philosophy that might lead them to reject the most established doctrines and beliefs."

Your precaution, says PHILO, of seasoning your children's minds early with piety, is certainly very reasonable; and no more than is requisite in this profane and irreligious age. But what I chiefly admire in your plan of education, is your method of drawing advantage from the very principles of philosophy and learning, which, by inspiring pride and self-sufficiency, have commonly, in all ages, been found so destructive to the principles of religion. The vulgar, indeed, we may remark, who are unacquainted with science and profound inquiry, observing the endless disputes of the learned, have commonly a thorough contempt for philosophy; and rivet themselves the faster, by that means, in the great points of theology which have been taught them. Those who enter a little into study and inquiry, finding many appearances of evidence in doctrines the newest and most extraordinary, think nothing too difficult for human reason; and, presumptuously breaking through all fences, profane the inmost sanctuaries of the temple. But CLEANTHES will, I hope, agree with me, that, after we have abandoned ignorance, the surest remedy, there is still one expedient left to prevent this profane liberty. Let DEMEA's principles be improved and cultivated: Let us become thoroughly sensible of the weakness, blindness, and narrow limits of human reason: Let us duly consider its uncertainty and endless contrarieties, even in subjects of common life and practice: Let the errors and deceits of our very senses be set before us; the insuperable difficulties which attend first principles in all systems; the contradictions which adhere to the very ideas of matter, cause and effect, extension, space, time, motion; and in a word, quantity of all kinds, the object of the only science that can fairly pretend to any certainty or evidence. When these topics are displayed in their full light, as they are by some philosophers and almost all divines; who can retain such confidence in this frail faculty of reason as to pay any regard to its determinations in points so sublime, so abstruse, so remote from common life and experience? When the coherence of the parts of a stone, or even that composition of parts which renders it extended; when these familiar objects, I say, are so inexplicable, and contain circumstances so repugnant and contradictory; with what assurance can we decide concerning the origin of worlds, or trace their history from eternity to eternity?

Your caution, PHILO says, about instilling religious values in your children early is definitely sensible and necessary in this disrespectful and godless era. But what I find most impressive about your educational approach is how you leverage the very ideas of philosophy and learning, which often breed arrogance and self-reliance, and have historically undermined religious beliefs. It’s true that ordinary people, who are not familiar with deep studies and complex discussions, tend to have a strong disdain for philosophy, which causes them to cling more firmly to the major tenets of theology they've learned. Those who explore a bit deeper into study and inquiry, encountering various compelling arguments for even the newest and most extraordinary doctrines, often think nothing is too complex for human understanding. They recklessly disregard boundaries and violate the deepest sanctuaries of faith. However, I hope CLEANTHES agrees with me that, aside from overcoming ignorance—which is an essential first step—there's still one method available to counter this reckless freedom. We should enhance and nurture DEMEA’s principles: We need to be fully aware of the limitations, blindness, and frailty of human reason. We must consider its unpredictability and endless contradictions, even in matters of everyday life and actions. We should reflect on the mistakes and deceptions of our own senses; the impossible challenges tied to fundamental principles across all systems; the contradictions inherent in concepts like matter, cause and effect, extension, space, time, motion; and, ultimately, the nature of all quantities, which is the focus of the only study that can genuinely claim any certainty or evidence. When these issues are thoroughly examined, as some philosophers and almost all theologians do, who can maintain such trust in this fragile human reasoning to heed its conclusions on subjects that are so lofty, so complex, and so far removed from everyday life and experiences? When even the connections within a stone or the way its parts yield extension are so baffling and filled with conflicting aspects; how can we confidently determine the origin of worlds or trace their evolution from eternity to eternity?

While PHILO pronounced these words, I could observe a smile in the countenance both of DEMEA and CLEANTHES. That of DEMEA seemed to imply an unreserved satisfaction in the doctrines delivered: But, in CLEANTHES's features, I could distinguish an air of finesse; as if he perceived some raillery or artificial malice in the reasonings of PHILO.

While PHILO was saying this, I noticed a smile on both DEMEA and CLEANTHES's faces. DEMEA's expression showed clear satisfaction with the ideas being expressed, while CLEANTHES's face had a touch of cunning, as if he sensed some teasing or subtle malice in PHILO's arguments.

You propose then, PHILO, said CLEANTHES, to erect religious faith on philosophical scepticism; and you think, that if certainty or evidence be expelled from every other subject of inquiry, it will all retire to these theological doctrines, and there acquire a superior force and authority. Whether your scepticism be as absolute and sincere as you pretend, we shall learn by and by, when the company breaks up: We shall then see, whether you go out at the door or the window; and whether you really doubt if your body has gravity, or can be injured by its fall; according to popular opinion, derived from our fallacious senses, and more fallacious experience. And this consideration, DEMEA, may, I think, fairly serve to abate our ill-will to this humorous sect of the sceptics. If they be thoroughly in earnest, they will not long trouble the world with their doubts, cavils, and disputes: If they be only in jest, they are, perhaps, bad raillers; but can never be very dangerous, either to the state, to philosophy, or to religion.

“You’re saying, PHILO,” CLEANTHES replied, “that you want to base religious faith on philosophical skepticism; and you believe that if certainty or evidence is pushed out of every other area of inquiry, it will all end up in these theological doctrines and gain more power and authority there. Whether your skepticism is as complete and genuine as you claim, we’ll find out later when the gathering ends: We’ll see whether you leave through the door or the window; and whether you truly doubt that your body has weight or can be harmed by falling, based on popular beliefs that come from our misleading senses and even more misleading experiences. And I think this thought, DEMEA, can help lessen our dislike for this amusing group of skeptics. If they’re truly serious, they won’t bother the world with their doubts, arguments, and disputes for long. If they’re just joking around, they might be poor jesters, but they’re unlikely to be very threatening to the state, philosophy, or religion.”

In reality, PHILO, continued he, it seems certain, that though a man, in a flush of humour, after intense reflection on the many contradictions and imperfections of human reason, may entirely renounce all belief and opinion, it is impossible for him to persevere in this total scepticism, or make it appear in his conduct for a few hours. External objects press in upon him; passions solicit him; his philosophical melancholy dissipates; and even the utmost violence upon his own temper will not be able, during any time, to preserve the poor appearance of scepticism. And for what reason impose on himself such a violence? This is a point in which it will be impossible for him ever to satisfy himself, consistently with his sceptical principles. So that, upon the whole, nothing could be more ridiculous than the principles of the ancient PYRRHONIANS; if in reality they endeavoured, as is pretended, to extend, throughout, the same scepticism which they had learned from the declamations of their schools, and which they ought to have confined to them.

Honestly, PHILO, he continued, it seems clear that even if a person, in a moment of humor, after deeply thinking about the many contradictions and flaws of human reasoning, completely gives up all belief and opinion, it’s impossible for him to maintain this total skepticism or show it in his behavior for even a few hours. Outside influences push in on him; emotions urge him on; his philosophical sadness fades; and even the strongest effort to control his own feelings won’t be able to keep up the facade of skepticism for long. And why should he put himself through such effort? This is a question he'll never answer satisfactorily while sticking to his skeptical beliefs. So, overall, nothing could be more absurd than the beliefs of the ancient PYRRHONIANS, if they genuinely tried, as claimed, to spread the same skepticism they learned from the rhetoric of their schools, which they should have kept confined there.

In this view, there appears a great resemblance between the sects of the STOICS and PYRRHONIANS, though perpetual antagonists; and both of them seem founded on this erroneous maxim, That what a man can perform sometimes, and in some dispositions, he can perform always, and in every disposition. When the mind, by Stoical reflections, is elevated into a sublime enthusiasm of virtue, and strongly smit with any species of honour or public good, the utmost bodily pain and sufferings will not prevail over such a high sense of duty; and it is possible, perhaps, by its means, even to smile and exult in the midst of tortures. If this sometimes may be the case in fact and reality, much more may a philosopher, in his school, or even in his closet, work himself up to such an enthusiasm, and support in imagination the acutest pain or most calamitous event which he can possibly conceive. But how shall he support this enthusiasm itself? The bent of his mind relaxes, and cannot be recalled at pleasure; avocations lead him astray; misfortunes attack him unawares; and the philosopher sinks by degrees into the plebeian.

In this perspective, there seems to be a strong similarity between the ST0ICS and PYRRHONIANS, even though they are constant adversaries; both seem to be based on the flawed idea that whatever a person can do occasionally and under certain conditions, they can do always and in every situation. When the mind, through Stoic thinking, is lifted into a high enthusiasm for virtue and strongly moved by any form of honor or public good, even the worst physical pain and suffering won’t overcome this strong sense of duty; it’s possible, perhaps, to smile and rejoice even amid torture. While this may sometimes be true in reality, a philosopher might, in their study or even in solitude, work themselves up to such enthusiasm and bear in their mind the sharpest pain or most disastrous event they can imagine. But how does one maintain this enthusiasm? The focus of their mind weakens and can’t be easily regained; distractions pull them away; misfortunes hit them unexpectedly; and gradually, the philosopher slips back into being an everyday person.

I allow of your comparison between the STOICS and SKEPTICS, replied PHILO. But you may observe, at the same time, that though the mind cannot, in Stoicism, support the highest flights of philosophy, yet, even when it sinks lower, it still retains somewhat of its former disposition; and the effects of the Stoic's reasoning will appear in his conduct in common life, and through the whole tenor of his actions. The ancient schools, particularly that of ZENO, produced examples of virtue and constancy which seem astonishing to present times.

I see your comparison between the Stoics and Skeptics, replied Philo. But you might notice that even though the mind in Stoicism can't reach the highest levels of philosophy, when it does sink lower, it still holds onto some of its former qualities. The impact of the Stoic's reasoning shows in how they behave in everyday life and throughout their actions. The ancient schools, especially Zeno's, provided examples of virtue and resilience that seem remarkable by today's standards.


Vain Wisdom all and false Philosophy.
Yet with a pleasing sorcery could charm
Pain, for a while, or anguish; and excite
Fallacious Hope, or arm the obdurate breast
With stubborn Patience, as with triple steel.

Vain knowledge all and false philosophy.
Yet with an appealing magic could soothe
Pain, for a moment, or distress; and spark
Deceptive hope, or equip the hardened heart
With unyielding patience, like it was covered in steel.


In like manner, if a man has accustomed himself to sceptical considerations on the uncertainty and narrow limits of reason, he will not entirely forget them when he turns his reflection on other subjects; but in all his philosophical principles and reasoning, I dare not say in his common conduct, he will be found different from those, who either never formed any opinions in the case, or have entertained sentiments more favourable to human reason.

In the same way, if a person has gotten used to questioning the uncertainty and limitations of reason, he won't completely disregard these thoughts when he reflects on other topics; however, in all his philosophical beliefs and reasoning, I can’t say the same for his everyday behavior, he will definitely be different from those who either never formed any opinions on the matter, or who hold views that are more positive about human reason.

To whatever length any one may push his speculative principles of scepticism, he must act, I own, and live, and converse, like other men; and for this conduct he is not obliged to give any other reason, than the absolute necessity he lies under of so doing. If he ever carries his speculations further than this necessity constrains him, and philosophises either on natural or moral subjects, he is allured by a certain pleasure and satisfaction which he finds in employing himself after that manner. He considers besides, that every one, even in common life, is constrained to have more or less of this philosophy; that from our earliest infancy we make continual advances in forming more general principles of conduct and reasoning; that the larger experience we acquire, and the stronger reason we are endued with, we always render our principles the more general and comprehensive; and that what we call philosophy is nothing but a more regular and methodical operation of the same kind. To philosophise on such subjects, is nothing essentially different from reasoning on common life; and we may only expect greater stability, if not greater truth, from our philosophy, on account of its exacter and more scrupulous method of proceeding.

No matter how far someone takes their doubts about things, they still have to act, live, and talk like everyone else. For this behavior, they don't need to give any reason other than the simple fact that it's necessary. If they go beyond this necessity and think deeply about natural or moral issues, it's because they find enjoyment and satisfaction in doing so. They also realize that everyone, even in everyday life, has to engage with some form of philosophy; from a young age, we continuously develop broader principles for behavior and reasoning. As we gain more experience and become more rational, we naturally make our principles more general and inclusive. What we call philosophy is just a more organized and systematic way of doing the same thing. Thinking deeply about these topics is basically the same as reasoning about daily life; we can only hope for more consistency, if not more truth, from our philosophical inquiries due to their more precise and careful approach.

But when we look beyond human affairs and the properties of the surrounding bodies: when we carry our speculations into the two eternities, before and after the present state of things; into the creation and formation of the universe; the existence and properties of spirits; the powers and operations of one universal Spirit existing without beginning and without end; omnipotent, omniscient, immutable, infinite, and incomprehensible: We must be far removed from the smallest tendency to scepticism not to be apprehensive, that we have here got quite beyond the reach of our faculties. So long as we confine our speculations to trade, or morals, or politics, or criticism, we make appeals, every moment, to common sense and experience, which strengthen our philosophical conclusions, and remove, at least in part, the suspicion which we so justly entertain with regard to every reasoning that is very subtle and refined. But, in theological reasonings, we have not this advantage; while, at the same time, we are employed upon objects, which, we must be sensible, are too large for our grasp, and of all others, require most to be familiarised to our apprehension. We are like foreigners in a strange country, to whom every thing must seem suspicious, and who are in danger every moment of transgressing against the laws and customs of the people with whom they live and converse. We know not how far we ought to trust our vulgar methods of reasoning in such a subject; since, even in common life, and in that province which is peculiarly appropriated to them, we cannot account for them, and are entirely guided by a kind of instinct or necessity in employing them.

But when we look beyond human matters and the characteristics of the surrounding world; when we extend our thoughts into the two eternities, before and after the current state of things; into the creation and formation of the universe; the existence and qualities of spirits; the powers and actions of one universal Spirit that exists without beginning or end; all-powerful, all-knowing, unchanging, infinite, and beyond comprehension: We must be very cautious not to lean towards skepticism, as we have clearly gone beyond the limits of our understanding. As long as we limit our discussions to trade, morals, politics, or criticism, we constantly rely on common sense and experience, which reinforce our philosophical conclusions and reduce, at least somewhat, the doubts we rightly have about any reasoning that is overly complex or refined. However, in theological discussions, we lack this benefit; meanwhile, we are focused on topics that, we must acknowledge, are too vast for our comprehension and require the greatest effort to understand. We are like outsiders in a foreign land, where everything seems suspicious, and we risk unknowingly breaking the laws and customs of the people we interact with. We don’t know how much we should trust our everyday reasoning in such matters; even in ordinary life, and in the areas specifically meant for it, we can’t fully explain our reasoning processes, and we are entirely guided by a type of instinct or necessity when we use them.

All sceptics pretend, that, if reason be considered in an abstract view, it furnishes invincible arguments against itself; and that we could never retain any conviction or assurance, on any subject, were not the sceptical reasonings so refined and subtle, that they are not able to counterpoise the more solid and more natural arguments derived from the senses and experience. But it is evident, whenever our arguments lose this advantage, and run wide of common life, that the most refined scepticism comes to be upon a footing with them, and is able to oppose and counterbalance them. The one has no more weight than the other. The mind must remain in suspense between them; and it is that very suspense or balance, which is the triumph of scepticism.

All skeptics argue that when reason is looked at in an abstract way, it provides strong arguments against itself; and that we could never hold any beliefs or confidence about anything if the skeptical arguments weren't so intricate and subtle that they can't outweigh the more solid and natural arguments that come from our senses and experiences. But it's clear that whenever our arguments lose this edge and stray from everyday life, the most sophisticated skepticism stands on equal ground with them and can challenge and balance them out. One holds no more weight than the other. The mind has to remain uncertain between them; and that very uncertainty or balance is the victory of skepticism.

But I observe, says CLEANTHES, with regard to you, PHILO, and all speculative sceptics, that your doctrine and practice are as much at variance in the most abstruse points of theory as in the conduct of common life. Wherever evidence discovers itself, you adhere to it, notwithstanding your pretended scepticism; and I can observe, too, some of your sect to be as decisive as those who make greater professions of certainty and assurance. In reality, would not a man be ridiculous, who pretended to reject NEWTON's explication of the wonderful phenomenon of the rainbow, because that explication gives a minute anatomy of the rays of light; a subject, forsooth, too refined for human comprehension? And what would you say to one, who, having nothing particular to object to the arguments of COPERNICUS and GALILEO for the motion of the earth, should withhold his assent, on that general principle, that these subjects were too magnificent and remote to be explained by the narrow and fallacious reason of mankind?

But I notice, says CLEANTHES, regarding you, PHILO, and all speculative skeptics, that your theory and practice are just as inconsistent in the most complex theoretical matters as they are in everyday life. Whenever evidence presents itself, you stick to it, despite your claimed skepticism; and I can also see some of your group being just as definitive as those who express greater certainty and assurance. In reality, wouldn't it be absurd for someone to reject NEWTON's explanation of the amazing phenomenon of the rainbow because that explanation involves a detailed analysis of the rays of light; a topic, it seems, too refined for human understanding? And what would you say to someone who, having no specific objections to the arguments of COPERNICUS and GALILEO regarding the motion of the earth, would withhold their agreement simply because they believe these topics are too grand and distant to be clarified by the limited and often misleading reasoning of humanity?

There is indeed a kind of brutish and ignorant scepticism, as you well observed, which gives the vulgar a general prejudice against what they do not easily understand, and makes them reject every principle which requires elaborate reasoning to prove and establish it. This species of scepticism is fatal to knowledge, not to religion; since we find, that those who make greatest profession of it, give often their assent, not only to the great truths of Theism and natural theology, but even to the most absurd tenets which a traditional superstition has recommended to them. They firmly believe in witches, though they will not believe nor attend to the most simple proposition of Euclid. But the refined and philosophical sceptics fall into an inconsistence of an opposite nature. They push their researches into the most abstruse corners of science; and their assent attends them in every step, proportioned to the evidence which they meet with. They are even obliged to acknowledge, that the most abstruse and remote objects are those which are best explained by philosophy. Light is in reality anatomised. The true system of the heavenly bodies is discovered and ascertained. But the nourishment of bodies by food is still an inexplicable mystery. The cohesion of the parts of matter is still incomprehensible. These sceptics, therefore, are obliged, in every question, to consider each particular evidence apart, and proportion their assent to the precise degree of evidence which occurs. This is their practice in all natural, mathematical, moral, and political science. And why not the same, I ask, in the theological and religious? Why must conclusions of this nature be alone rejected on the general presumption of the insufficiency of human reason, without any particular discussion of the evidence? Is not such an unequal conduct a plain proof of prejudice and passion?

There is definitely a kind of brutish and ignorant skepticism, as you rightly pointed out, that creates a general bias among the masses against things they don't easily understand, making them dismiss any principle that needs detailed reasoning to be proven and established. This type of skepticism is harmful to knowledge, but not to religion; we see that those who profess it the most often accept not only the fundamental truths of Theism and natural theology but also the most ridiculous beliefs that traditional superstitions have handed down to them. They firmly believe in witches, even though they won't accept or consider the simplest propositions of Euclid. However, the more refined and philosophical skeptics have an opposite inconsistency. They delve into the most complex corners of science, and their acceptance aligns with the evidence they find at every step. They even have to admit that the most complex and distant topics are best explained by philosophy. Light is actually broken down. The true system of celestial bodies is discovered and confirmed. Yet, the way bodies are nourished by food remains an inexplicable mystery. The cohesion of matter's parts is still baffling. Therefore, these skeptics are forced to examine each piece of evidence separately in every question and adjust their acceptance based on the specific level of evidence presented. This is their approach in all fields of natural, mathematical, moral, and political sciences. So why not the same in theology and religion? Why must conclusions in this area be solely dismissed based on a general assumption about the limitations of human reason, without any specific examination of the evidence? Isn’t this kind of uneven treatment a clear sign of bias and emotion?

Our senses, you say, are fallacious; our understanding erroneous; our ideas, even of the most familiar objects, extension, duration, motion, full of absurdities and contradictions. You defy me to solve the difficulties, or reconcile the repugnancies which you discover in them. I have not capacity for so great an undertaking: I have not leisure for it: I perceive it to be superfluous. Your own conduct, in every circumstance, refutes your principles, and shows the firmest reliance on all the received maxims of science, morals, prudence, and behaviour.

You say that our senses are deceiving, our understanding is flawed, and our ideas about even the simplest things—like space, time, and movement—are full of nonsense and contradictions. You challenge me to figure out the problems or make sense of the inconsistencies you find in them. I don’t have the ability or time for such a huge task, and it seems unnecessary to me. Your actions in every situation contradict your beliefs and demonstrate a strong trust in all the accepted principles of science, ethics, common sense, and conduct.

I shall never assent to so harsh an opinion as that of a celebrated writer [L'Arte de penser], who says, that the Sceptics are not a sect of philosophers: They are only a sect of liars. I may, however, affirm (I hope without offence), that they are a sect of jesters or raillers. But for my part, whenever I find myself disposed to mirth and amusement, I shall certainly choose my entertainment of a less perplexing and abstruse nature. A comedy, a novel, or at most a history, seems a more natural recreation than such metaphysical subtleties and abstractions.

I will never agree with such a harsh opinion from a famous writer [L'Arte de penser], who claims that the Sceptics are not a group of philosophers but just a group of liars. However, I can say (I hope without causing offense) that they are more like jesters or mockers. For me, whenever I'm in the mood for laughter and fun, I definitely prefer my entertainment to be something less confusing and complex. A comedy, a novel, or at most a history book seems like a much more natural way to relax than dealing with such metaphysical puzzles and abstractions.

In vain would the sceptic make a distinction between science and common life, or between one science and another. The arguments employed in all, if just, are of a similar nature, and contain the same force and evidence. Or if there be any difference among them, the advantage lies entirely on the side of theology and natural religion. Many principles of mechanics are founded on very abstruse reasoning; yet no man who has any pretensions to science, even no speculative sceptic, pretends to entertain the least doubt with regard to them. The COPERNICAN system contains the most surprising paradox, and the most contrary to our natural conceptions, to appearances, and to our very senses: yet even monks and inquisitors are now constrained to withdraw their opposition to it. And shall PHILO, a man of so liberal a genius and extensive knowledge, entertain any general undistinguished scruples with regard to the religious hypothesis, which is founded on the simplest and most obvious arguments, and, unless it meets with artificial obstacles, has such easy access and admission into the mind of man?

The skeptic would futilely try to separate science from everyday life, or one science from another. The arguments used in all of them, if valid, are similar in nature and carry the same weight and evidence. If there is any difference among them, the advantage clearly lies with theology and natural religion. Many principles of mechanics are based on very complex reasoning; yet no one who claims to be scientific, even no speculative skeptic, would dare to doubt them. The COPERNICAN system presents the most astonishing paradox, going against our natural understanding, our observations, and even our senses: yet even monks and inquisitors are now forced to drop their opposition to it. And would PHILO, a man of such open-mindedness and broad knowledge, really have any unfounded doubts about the religious hypothesis, which is based on the most straightforward and clear arguments, and, unless hindered by artificial barriers, easily enters the mind of man?

And here we may observe, continued he, turning himself towards DEMEA, a pretty curious circumstance in the history of the sciences. After the union of philosophy with the popular religion, upon the first establishment of Christianity, nothing was more usual, among all religious teachers, than declamations against reason, against the senses, against every principle derived merely from human research and inquiry. All the topics of the ancient academics were adopted by the fathers; and thence propagated for several ages in every school and pulpit throughout Christendom. The Reformers embraced the same principles of reasoning, or rather declamation; and all panegyrics on the excellency of faith, were sure to be interlarded with some severe strokes of satire against natural reason. A celebrated prelate [Monsr. Huet] too, of the Romish communion, a man of the most extensive learning, who wrote a demonstration of Christianity, has also composed a treatise, which contains all the cavils of the boldest and most determined PYRRHONISM. LOCKE seems to have been the first Christian who ventured openly to assert, that faith was nothing but a species of reason; that religion was only a branch of philosophy; and that a chain of arguments, similar to that which established any truth in morals, politics, or physics, was always employed in discovering all the principles of theology, natural and revealed. The ill use which BAYLE and other libertines made of the philosophical scepticism of the fathers and first reformers, still further propagated the judicious sentiment of Mr. LOCKE: And it is now in a manner avowed, by all pretenders to reasoning and philosophy, that Atheist and Sceptic are almost synonymous. And as it is certain that no man is in earnest when he professes the latter principle, I would fain hope that there are as few who seriously maintain the former.

And here we can notice, he continued, turning to DEMEA, a pretty interesting point in the history of science. After philosophy merged with popular religion at the dawn of Christianity, it became quite common for religious leaders to speak out against reason, against the senses, and against any principle that arose solely from human research and inquiry. The themes of the ancient academics were taken up by the church fathers and were spread for many ages in every school and pulpit across Christendom. The Reformers also adopted these same reasoning principles, or rather declamations; and any praises of the importance of faith were sure to include some sharp criticism of natural reason. A well-known bishop [Monsr. Huet] from the Roman Church, a man of immense knowledge, who wrote a treatise on Christianity, also produced a work that includes all the challenges from the boldest form of PYRRHONISM. LOCKE seems to have been the first Christian to boldly state that faith is merely a kind of reason; that religion is just a branch of philosophy; and that a chain of arguments, similar to those used to validate truths in morals, politics, or physics, is always involved in uncovering all the principles of theology, both natural and revealed. The misuse of the philosophical skepticism of the church fathers and early Reformers by BAYLE and other libertines further spread Mr. LOCKE's insightful thought: and it is now virtually accepted by everyone who claims to engage in reasoning and philosophy that Atheist and Skeptic are nearly synonymous. And since it is clear that no one genuinely holds to the latter principle with sincerity, I hope there are just as few who truly uphold the former.

Don't you remember, said PHILO, the excellent saying of LORD BACON on this head? That a little philosophy, replied CLEANTHES, makes a man an Atheist: A great deal converts him to religion. That is a very judicious remark too, said PHILO. But what I have in my eye is another passage, where, having mentioned DAVID's fool, who said in his heart there is no God, this great philosopher observes, that the Atheists nowadays have a double share of folly; for they are not contented to say in their hearts there is no God, but they also utter that impiety with their lips, and are thereby guilty of multiplied indiscretion and imprudence. Such people, though they were ever so much in earnest, cannot, methinks, be very formidable.

"Don't you remember," PHILO said, "the great saying of LORD BACON about this?" "A little philosophy," replied CLEANTHES, "makes a man an Atheist; a lot of it turns him to religion." "That's a very insightful point too," PHILO agreed. "But what I'm thinking of is another passage where, after mentioning DAVID's fool who said in his heart there is no God, this great philosopher notes that today's Atheists have double the folly. They’re not satisfied just to claim in their hearts that there is no God; they also express that disbelief aloud, making them guilty of even more indiscretion and imprudence. People like that, even if they're truly convinced, don't seem all that threatening to me."

But though you should rank me in this class of fools, I cannot forbear communicating a remark that occurs to me, from the history of the religious and irreligious scepticism with which you have entertained us. It appears to me, that there are strong symptoms of priestcraft in the whole progress of this affair. During ignorant ages, such as those which followed the dissolution of the ancient schools, the priests perceived, that Atheism, Deism, or heresy of any kind, could only proceed from the presumptuous questioning of received opinions, and from a belief that human reason was equal to every thing. Education had then a mighty influence over the minds of men, and was almost equal in force to those suggestions of the senses and common understanding, by which the most determined sceptic must allow himself to be governed. But at present, when the influence of education is much diminished, and men, from a more open commerce of the world, have learned to compare the popular principles of different nations and ages, our sagacious divines have changed their whole system of philosophy, and talk the language of STOICS, PLATONISTS, and PERIPATETICS, not that of PYRRHONIANS and ACADEMICS. If we distrust human reason, we have now no other principle to lead us into religion. Thus, sceptics in one age, dogmatists in another; whichever system best suits the purpose of these reverend gentlemen, in giving them an ascendant over mankind, they are sure to make it their favourite principle, and established tenet.

But even if you put me in the category of fools, I can't help but share a thought that comes to mind from the history of the religious and irreligious skepticism you've presented us. It seems to me that there are clear signs of manipulation by religious leaders in the entire course of this matter. In the ignorant eras that followed the decline of the ancient schools, priests realized that Atheism, Deism, or any form of heresy arose from the arrogant questioning of established beliefs and the assumption that human reason was capable of everything. Education back then held significant sway over people's minds, almost matching the impact of sensory perceptions and common understanding, which even the most resolute skeptic would have to admit would influence them. However, now, with the diminished impact of education and the broader interaction among nations leading people to compare the popular beliefs of different times and places, our insightful clergy have completely shifted their philosophical approach and now speak in the terms of STOICS, PLATONISTS, and PERIPATETICS, rather than PYRRHONIANS and ACADEMICS. If we doubt human reason, we have no other basis to guide us toward religion. So, skeptics in one era and dogmatists in another; whichever doctrine serves these esteemed gentlemen's agenda to maintain control over humanity, they will gladly adopt as their leading principle and established belief.

It is very natural, said CLEANTHES, for men to embrace those principles, by which they find they can best defend their doctrines; nor need we have any recourse to priestcraft to account for so reasonable an expedient. And, surely nothing can afford a stronger presumption, that any set of principles are true, and ought to be embraced, than to observe that they tend to the confirmation of true religion, and serve to confound the cavils of Atheists, Libertines, and Freethinkers of all denominations.

It’s completely understandable, said CLEANTHES, for people to adopt the beliefs that help them best defend their views; we shouldn’t need to resort to religious manipulation to explain such a logical approach. And certainly, nothing suggests more strongly that a set of beliefs is true and should be accepted than seeing that they support genuine faith and effectively counter the arguments made by atheists, libertines, and free thinkers of all kinds.




PART 2

I must own, CLEANTHES, said DEMEA, that nothing can more surprise me, than the light in which you have all along put this argument. By the whole tenor of your discourse, one would imagine that you were maintaining the Being of a God, against the cavils of Atheists and Infidels; and were necessitated to become a champion for that fundamental principle of all religion. But this, I hope, is not by any means a question among us. No man, no man at least of common sense, I am persuaded, ever entertained a serious doubt with regard to a truth so certain and self-evident. The question is not concerning the being, but the nature of God. This, I affirm, from the infirmities of human understanding, to be altogether incomprehensible and unknown to us. The essence of that supreme Mind, his attributes, the manner of his existence, the very nature of his duration; these, and every particular which regards so divine a Being, are mysterious to men. Finite, weak, and blind creatures, we ought to humble ourselves in his august presence; and, conscious of our frailties, adore in silence his infinite perfections, which eye hath not seen, ear hath not heard, neither hath it entered into the heart of man to conceive. They are covered in a deep cloud from human curiosity. It is profaneness to attempt penetrating through these sacred obscurities. And, next to the impiety of denying his existence, is the temerity of prying into his nature and essence, decrees and attributes.

I have to admit, CLEANTHES, said DEMEA, that nothing surprises me more than how you've framed this argument. From the way you've talked, you'd think you were trying to defend the existence of God against the doubts of atheists and skeptics; it seems like you felt you had to be a defender of that basic principle of all religion. But I hope that's not a question between us. No one, at least no reasonable person, I believe, has ever seriously doubted a truth that's so clear and obvious. The question isn’t about whether God exists, but about what God is like. I assert that, due to the limitations of human understanding, we find his essence completely incomprehensible and unknown. The essence of that supreme Mind, his qualities, the way he exists, the very nature of his duration; all of these, and every detail regarding such a divine Being, are mysterious to us. As finite, weak, and blind beings, we should lower ourselves in his majestic presence; aware of our weaknesses, we should silently worship his infinite perfection, which no eye has seen, no ear has heard, and which hasn’t even entered the heart of man to imagine. These truths are shrouded in a deep mist beyond human curiosity. It's disrespectful to try to penetrate these sacred mysteries. And next to the blasphemy of denying his existence is the boldness of trying to pry into his nature, essence, decrees, and attributes.

But lest you should think that my piety has here got the better of my philosophy, I shall support my opinion, if it needs any support, by a very great authority. I might cite all the divines, almost, from the foundation of Christianity, who have ever treated of this or any other theological subject: But I shall confine myself, at present, to one equally celebrated for piety and philosophy. It is Father MALEBRANCHE, who, I remember, thus expresses himself [Recherche de la Verite. Liv. 3. Chap.9]. "One ought not so much," says he, "to call God a spirit, in order to express positively what he is, as in order to signify that he is not matter. He is a Being infinitely perfect: Of this we cannot doubt. But in the same manner as we ought not to imagine, even supposing him corporeal, that he is clothed with a human body, as the ANTHROPOMORPHITES asserted, under colour that that figure was the most perfect of any; so, neither ought we to imagine that the spirit of God has human ideas, or bears any resemblance to our spirit, under colour that we know nothing more perfect than a human mind. We ought rather to believe, that as he comprehends the perfections of matter without being material.... he comprehends also the perfections of created spirits without being spirit, in the manner we conceive spirit: That his true name is, He that is; or, in other words, Being without restriction, All Being, the Being infinite and universal."

But before you think that my faith has overtaken my reasoning, I’ll back up my view with a significant authority. I could mention nearly all the theologians from the beginning of Christianity who have discussed this or any other theological issue. However, I’ll limit myself, for now, to one who is equally renowned for his faith and his philosophy. It's Father MALEBRANCHE, who, as I recall, states [Recherche de la Verite. Liv. 3. Chap.9]: "One shouldn't call God a spirit just to define what He is, but to indicate that He is not matter. He is an infinitely perfect Being: We cannot doubt this. But just as we shouldn’t imagine, even if He were corporeal, that He is dressed in a human body, as the ANTHROPOMORPHITES claimed—suggesting that figure was the most perfect of all—we also shouldn’t think that the spirit of God has human ideas or resembles our spirit, just because we know nothing more perfect than a human mind. We should rather believe that just as He understands the perfections of matter without being material, He also understands the perfections of created spirits without being spirit in the way we think of spirit. His true name is, He that is; or in other words, Being without limitations, All Being, the infinite and universal Being."

After so great an authority, DEMEA, replied PHILO, as that which you have produced, and a thousand more which you might produce, it would appear ridiculous in me to add my sentiment, or express my approbation of your doctrine. But surely, where reasonable men treat these subjects, the question can never be concerning the Being, but only the Nature, of the Deity. The former truth, as you well observe, is unquestionable and self-evident. Nothing exists without a cause; and the original cause of this universe (whatever it be) we call God; and piously ascribe to him every species of perfection. Whoever scruples this fundamental truth, deserves every punishment which can be inflicted among philosophers, to wit, the greatest ridicule, contempt, and disapprobation. But as all perfection is entirely relative, we ought never to imagine that we comprehend the attributes of this divine Being, or to suppose that his perfections have any analogy or likeness to the perfections of a human creature. Wisdom, Thought, Design, Knowledge; these we justly ascribe to him; because these words are honourable among men, and we have no other language or other conceptions by which we can express our adoration of him. But let us beware, lest we think that our ideas anywise correspond to his perfections, or that his attributes have any resemblance to these qualities among men. He is infinitely superior to our limited view and comprehension; and is more the object of worship in the temple, than of disputation in the schools.

After such a significant authority as you, DEMEA, have provided, and a thousand more examples you could give, it seems silly for me to share my opinion or show my approval of your ideas. However, when reasonable people discuss these topics, the debate is never about the existence of God but only about the nature of the Deity. As you rightly point out, the existence of God is indisputable and obvious. Nothing exists without a cause, and the original cause of this universe (whatever it may be) is what we call God; we attribute all forms of perfection to him out of reverence. Anyone who doubts this fundamental truth deserves all the scorn that philosophers can dish out, including the harshest ridicule, disrespect, and disapproval. But since all perfection is relative, we should never assume that we truly understand the attributes of this divine Being or think that his qualities resemble those of humans. We rightly attribute Wisdom, Thought, Design, and Knowledge to him, because these terms are esteemed among people, and we lack other words or ideas to express our worship of him. But we must be careful not to believe that our concepts in any way align with his perfections or that his attributes have any similarity to human qualities. He is infinitely beyond our limited perspective and understanding; he is more worthy of worship in the temple than of debate in academic settings.

In reality, CLEANTHES, continued he, there is no need of having recourse to that affected scepticism so displeasing to you, in order to come at this determination. Our ideas reach no further than our experience. We have no experience of divine attributes and operations. I need not conclude my syllogism. You can draw the inference yourself. And it is a pleasure to me (and I hope to you too) that just reasoning and sound piety here concur in the same conclusion, and both of them establish the adorably mysterious and incomprehensible nature of the Supreme Being.

Actually, CLEANTHES, he continued, there's no need to resort to that forced skepticism that bothers you so much, just to reach this conclusion. Our ideas can only extend as far as our experiences. We don't have any experience with divine qualities and actions. I don't need to finish my argument. You can figure it out yourself. And it makes me happy (and I hope it makes you happy too) that logical reasoning and genuine faith both lead to the same conclusion, which is that the wonderfully mysterious and incomprehensible nature of the Supreme Being is confirmed by both.

Not to lose any time in circumlocutions, said CLEANTHES, addressing himself to DEMEA, much less in replying to the pious declamations of PHILO; I shall briefly explain how I conceive this matter. Look round the world: contemplate the whole and every part of it: You will find it to be nothing but one great machine, subdivided into an infinite number of lesser machines, which again admit of subdivisions to a degree beyond what human senses and faculties can trace and explain. All these various machines, and even their most minute parts, are adjusted to each other with an accuracy which ravishes into admiration all men who have ever contemplated them. The curious adapting of means to ends, throughout all nature, resembles exactly, though it much exceeds, the productions of human contrivance; of human designs, thought, wisdom, and intelligence. Since, therefore, the effects resemble each other, we are led to infer, by all the rules of analogy, that the causes also resemble; and that the Author of Nature is somewhat similar to the mind of man, though possessed of much larger faculties, proportioned to the grandeur of the work which he has executed. By this argument a posteriori, and by this argument alone, do we prove at once the existence of a Deity, and his similarity to human mind and intelligence.

Not to waste any time with unnecessary talk, said CLEANTHES to DEMEA, especially not in responding to PHILO's pious speeches; I’ll briefly explain how I see this. Look around at the world: observe the whole thing and every part of it: You’ll find it to be one big machine, broken down into an infinite number of smaller machines, which can be subdivided even further than our human senses and abilities can understand. All these different machines, and even their tiniest parts, work together with an accuracy that amazes everyone who has ever thought about them. The intricate way that means are adapted to ends in all of nature is exactly like, but far surpasses, what humans create; it reflects human design, thought, wisdom, and intelligence. Therefore, since the effects are similar, we can reasonably infer, following all the rules of analogy, that the causes are similar too; and that the Creator of Nature is somewhat like the human mind, only with much greater abilities, suited to the grandeur of the work he has accomplished. Through this argument based on experience, and this argument alone, we simultaneously prove the existence of a Deity and his similarity to human thought and intelligence.

I shall be so free, CLEANTHES, said DEMEA, as to tell you, that from the beginning, I could not approve of your conclusion concerning the similarity of the Deity to men; still less can I approve of the mediums by which you endeavour to establish it. What! No demonstration of the Being of God! No abstract arguments! No proofs a priori! Are these, which have hitherto been so much insisted on by philosophers, all fallacy, all sophism? Can we reach no further in this subject than experience and probability? I will not say that this is betraying the cause of a Deity: But surely, by this affected candour, you give advantages to Atheists, which they never could obtain by the mere dint of argument and reasoning.

I'll be honest with you, CLEANTHES, said DEMEA, from the very start, I couldn't agree with your conclusion about how similar the Deity is to humans; and I definitely don't support the methods you're using to back it up. What? No proof of God's existence! No abstract reasoning! No a priori arguments! Are all these things, which philosophers have emphasized so much, just nonsense, just tricks? Can we only go as far as experience and probability on this topic? I won't say this is a betrayal of the idea of a Deity: But certainly, with this so-called openness, you're giving Atheists a leg up that they couldn't achieve just through argument and reasoning.

What I chiefly scruple in this subject, said PHILO, is not so much that all religious arguments are by CLEANTHES reduced to experience, as that they appear not to be even the most certain and irrefragable of that inferior kind. That a stone will fall, that fire will burn, that the earth has solidity, we have observed a thousand and a thousand times; and when any new instance of this nature is presented, we draw without hesitation the accustomed inference. The exact similarity of the cases gives us a perfect assurance of a similar event; and a stronger evidence is never desired nor sought after. But wherever you depart, in the least, from the similarity of the cases, you diminish proportionably the evidence; and may at last bring it to a very weak analogy, which is confessedly liable to error and uncertainty. After having experienced the circulation of the blood in human creatures, we make no doubt that it takes place in TITIUS and MAEVIUS. But from its circulation in frogs and fishes, it is only a presumption, though a strong one, from analogy, that it takes place in men and other animals. The analogical reasoning is much weaker, when we infer the circulation of the sap in vegetables from our experience that the blood circulates in animals; and those, who hastily followed that imperfect analogy, are found, by more accurate experiments, to have been mistaken.

What I mainly question about this topic, PHILO said, is not so much that CLEANTHES reduces all religious arguments to experience but that they don't seem to be the most certain and undeniable of that lesser type. We have observed countless times that a stone will fall, that fire will burn, and that the earth is solid; when we see a new instance of this kind, we draw the usual conclusion without hesitation. The exact similarity of the cases gives us complete confidence in a similar outcome, and we never seek any stronger evidence. However, whenever you stray even slightly from the similarity of the cases, you proportionately lessen the evidence and can eventually reduce it to a very weak analogy, which is clearly subject to error and uncertainty. After experiencing blood circulation in humans, we have no doubt that it occurs in TITIUS and MAEVIUS. But when it comes to frogs and fish, we only have a strong presumption through analogy that it happens in humans and other animals. The reasoning by analogy becomes much weaker when we try to infer the circulation of sap in plants from our experience with blood circulation in animals; those who quickly followed that flawed analogy have been found to be mistaken by more precise experiments.

If we see a house, CLEANTHES, we conclude, with the greatest certainty, that it had an architect or builder; because this is precisely that species of effect which we have experienced to proceed from that species of cause. But surely you will not affirm, that the universe bears such a resemblance to a house, that we can with the same certainty infer a similar cause, or that the analogy is here entire and perfect. The dissimilitude is so striking, that the utmost you can here pretend to is a guess, a conjecture, a presumption concerning a similar cause; and how that pretension will be received in the world, I leave you to consider.

If we see a house, CLEANTHES, we can confidently conclude that it had an architect or builder. This is exactly the kind of outcome we know comes from that kind of cause. But surely you won't argue that the universe is so similar to a house that we can infer a similar cause with the same certainty, or that the analogy is completely valid. The differences are so clear that all you can really claim here is a guess, a hypothesis, a presumption about a similar cause; and I leave it to you to think about how that claim will be received in the world.

It would surely be very ill received, replied CLEANTHES; and I should be deservedly blamed and detested, did I allow, that the proofs of a Deity amounted to no more than a guess or conjecture. But is the whole adjustment of means to ends in a house and in the universe so slight a resemblance? The economy of final causes? The order, proportion, and arrangement of every part? Steps of a stair are plainly contrived, that human legs may use them in mounting; and this inference is certain and infallible. Human legs are also contrived for walking and mounting; and this inference, I allow, is not altogether so certain, because of the dissimilarity which you remark; but does it, therefore, deserve the name only of presumption or conjecture?

It would definitely be poorly received, replied CLEANTHES; and I would rightfully be blamed and disliked if I suggested that the evidence for a Deity was just a guess or an assumption. But is the entire way that things are set up to achieve their purposes in a house and in the universe really such a minor similarity? The purpose behind things? The order, balance, and arrangement of every part? Steps on a staircase are clearly designed so that human legs can use them to climb; and this conclusion is certain and undeniable. Human legs are also designed for walking and climbing; and I agree this conclusion isn't entirely certain due to the differences you've pointed out; but does that mean it should only be called a mere assumption or guess?

Good God! cried DEMEA, interrupting him, where are we? Zealous defenders of religion allow, that the proofs of a Deity fall short of perfect evidence! And you, PHILO, on whose assistance I depended in proving the adorable mysteriousness of the Divine Nature, do you assent to all these extravagant opinions of CLEANTHES? For what other name can I give them? or, why spare my censure, when such principles are advanced, supported by such an authority, before so young a man as PAMPHILUS?

Good God! shouted DEMEA, cutting him off, where are we? Passionate defenders of religion admit that the evidence for a Deity isn't perfect! And you, PHILO, whom I counted on to help me demonstrate the wonderful mystery of the Divine Nature, do you agree with all these outrageous views of CLEANTHES? What else can I call them? And why hold back my criticism when such ideas are put forward, backed by such authority, in front of a young man like PAMPHILUS?

You seem not to apprehend, replied PHILO, that I argue with CLEANTHES in his own way; and, by showing him the dangerous consequences of his tenets, hope at last to reduce him to our opinion. But what sticks most with you, I observe, is the representation which CLEANTHES has made of the argument a posteriori; and finding that that argument is likely to escape your hold and vanish into air, you think it so disguised, that you can scarcely believe it to be set in its true light. Now, however much I may dissent, in other respects, from the dangerous principles of CLEANTHES, I must allow that he has fairly represented that argument; and I shall endeavour so to state the matter to you, that you will entertain no further scruples with regard to it.

You seem to not understand, PHILO replied, that I'm debating with CLEANTHES on his own terms; and by highlighting the risky consequences of his beliefs, I hope to eventually bring him around to our viewpoint. But what seems to trouble you the most is the way CLEANTHES has framed the argument a posteriori; and since that argument might slip through your fingers and disappear, you find it so twisted that you can hardly believe it’s being presented accurately. Now, even if I disagree in other ways with CLEANTHES's risky ideas, I must admit that he has accurately represented that argument; and I will do my best to explain it to you in a way that puts your doubts to rest.

Were a man to abstract from every thing which he knows or has seen, he would be altogether incapable, merely from his own ideas, to determine what kind of scene the universe must be, or to give the preference to one state or situation of things above another. For as nothing which he clearly conceives could be esteemed impossible or implying a contradiction, every chimera of his fancy would be upon an equal footing; nor could he assign any just reason why he adheres to one idea or system, and rejects the others which are equally possible.

If a man were to forget everything he knows or has seen, he would be completely unable, based solely on his own thoughts, to figure out what kind of world the universe must be or to prefer one condition or situation over another. Since nothing he clearly imagines could be considered impossible or contradictory, every fanciful idea he has would be treated equally; he wouldn't be able to justify why he sticks to one idea or system while dismissing others that are just as possible.

Again; after he opens his eyes, and contemplates the world as it really is, it would be impossible for him at first to assign the cause of any one event, much less of the whole of things, or of the universe. He might set his fancy a rambling; and she might bring him in an infinite variety of reports and representations. These would all be possible; but being all equally possible, he would never of himself give a satisfactory account for his preferring one of them to the rest. Experience alone can point out to him the true cause of any phenomenon.

Again, after he opens his eyes and considers the world as it really is, it would be impossible for him at first to identify the cause of any single event, let alone the entirety of things or the universe. He might let his imagination wander, and it could present him with countless different reports and images. All of these would be possible, but since they’re all equally plausible, he would never be able to explain why he prefers one over the others. Only experience can reveal the true cause of any phenomenon.

Now, according to this method of reasoning, DEMEA, it follows, (and is, indeed, tacitly allowed by CLEANTHES himself,) that order, arrangement, or the adjustment of final causes, is not of itself any proof of design; but only so far as it has been experienced to proceed from that principle. For aught we can know a priori, matter may contain the source or spring of order originally within itself, as well as mind does; and there is no more difficulty in conceiving, that the several elements, from an internal unknown cause, may fall into the most exquisite arrangement, than to conceive that their ideas, in the great universal mind, from a like internal unknown cause, fall into that arrangement. The equal possibility of both these suppositions is allowed. But, by experience, we find, (according to CLEANTHES), that there is a difference between them. Throw several pieces of steel together, without shape or form; they will never arrange themselves so as to compose a watch. Stone, and mortar, and wood, without an architect, never erect a house. But the ideas in a human mind, we see, by an unknown, inexplicable economy, arrange themselves so as to form the plan of a watch or house. Experience, therefore, proves, that there is an original principle of order in mind, not in matter. From similar effects we infer similar causes. The adjustment of means to ends is alike in the universe, as in a machine of human contrivance. The causes, therefore, must be resembling.

Now, according to this way of thinking, DEMEA, it follows (and is, in fact, implicitly accepted by CLEANTHES himself) that order, arrangement, or the alignment of final causes isn't proof of design by itself; it's only considered so far as we have seen it come from that principle. For all we know a priori, matter could hold the source or origin of order within itself just as mind does; and there's no more difficulty in imagining that the various elements, from an unknown internal cause, might arrange themselves into a perfect order than in imagining that their ideas, in the vast universal mind, fall into that same order due to a similar unknown cause. Both possibilities are equally valid. However, based on experience, we find (according to CLEANTHES) that there’s a difference between them. If you randomly throw several pieces of steel together with no shape or form, they will never organize themselves into a watch. Similarly, stone, mortar, and wood, without an architect, will never build a house. Yet, we see that ideas in a human mind somehow arrange themselves, through an unknown and mysterious process, to create the design for a watch or a house. Experience thus shows that there is an original principle of order in the mind, not in matter. From similar effects, we infer similar causes. The alignment of means to ends is similar in the universe, just as in a machine created by humans. Therefore, the causes must also be similar.

I was from the beginning scandalised, I must own, with this resemblance, which is asserted, between the Deity and human creatures; and must conceive it to imply such a degradation of the Supreme Being as no sound Theist could endure. With your assistance, therefore, DEMEA, I shall endeavour to defend what you justly call the adorable mysteriousness of the Divine Nature, and shall refute this reasoning of CLEANTHES, provided he allows that I have made a fair representation of it.

I have to admit, right from the start, I was shocked by this supposed similarity between God and humans. It seems to suggest a lowering of the Supreme Being that no true Theist could accept. So, with your help, DEMEA, I will try to defend what you rightly call the wonderful mystery of the Divine Nature and counter CLEANTHES's reasoning, as long as he agrees that I've accurately presented it.

When CLEANTHES had assented, PHILO, after a short pause, proceeded in the following manner.

When CLEANTHES agreed, PHILO, after a brief pause, continued as follows.

That all inferences, CLEANTHES, concerning fact, are founded on experience; and that all experimental reasonings are founded on the supposition that similar causes prove similar effects, and similar effects similar causes; I shall not at present much dispute with you. But observe, I entreat you, with what extreme caution all just reasoners proceed in the transferring of experiments to similar cases. Unless the cases be exactly similar, they repose no perfect confidence in applying their past observation to any particular phenomenon. Every alteration of circumstances occasions a doubt concerning the event; and it requires new experiments to prove certainly, that the new circumstances are of no moment or importance. A change in bulk, situation, arrangement, age, disposition of the air, or surrounding bodies; any of these particulars may be attended with the most unexpected consequences: And unless the objects be quite familiar to us, it is the highest temerity to expect with assurance, after any of these changes, an event similar to that which before fell under our observation. The slow and deliberate steps of philosophers here, if any where, are distinguished from the precipitate march of the vulgar, who, hurried on by the smallest similitude, are incapable of all discernment or consideration.

All conclusions, CLEANTHES, about facts are based on experience, and all experimental reasoning is based on the idea that similar causes lead to similar effects, and similar effects point to similar causes. I won't argue much about this right now. But please note how carefully responsible thinkers approach applying their experiments to similar situations. Unless the cases are exactly alike, they don’t fully trust their previous observations to apply to a specific phenomenon. Any change in circumstances raises doubts about the outcome, and new experiments are needed to definitely prove that the new circumstances don't matter. A change in size, position, arrangement, age, air quality, or surrounding objects; any of these factors could lead to unexpected results. Unless we are very familiar with the objects involved, it’s extremely reckless to confidently expect that, after any of these changes, the outcome will be the same as what we previously observed. The careful and measured approach of philosophers here stands in stark contrast to the hasty actions of the common people, who, driven by the slightest similarity, lose all sense of discernment and consideration.

But can you think, CLEANTHES, that your usual phlegm and philosophy have been preserved in so wide a step as you have taken, when you compared to the universe houses, ships, furniture, machines, and, from their similarity in some circumstances, inferred a similarity in their causes? Thought, design, intelligence, such as we discover in men and other animals, is no more than one of the springs and principles of the universe, as well as heat or cold, attraction or repulsion, and a hundred others, which fall under daily observation. It is an active cause, by which some particular parts of nature, we find, produce alterations on other parts. But can a conclusion, with any propriety, be transferred from parts to the whole? Does not the great disproportion bar all comparison and inference? From observing the growth of a hair, can we learn any thing concerning the generation of a man? Would the manner of a leaf's blowing, even though perfectly known, afford us any instruction concerning the vegetation of a tree?

But can you really believe, CLEANTHES, that your usual calmness and philosophy have held up after taking such a broad leap as you have? When you compared the universe to houses, ships, furniture, and machines, and inferred a similarity in their causes based on some similarities, do you think that’s justified? Thought, design, and intelligence, like we see in humans and other animals, are just one of many forces and principles of the universe, alongside heat or cold, attraction or repulsion, and countless others that we observe every day. It acts as a cause, allowing specific parts of nature to create changes in other parts. But can we properly apply a conclusion from parts to the whole? Doesn't the vast difference make any comparison or inference pointless? From watching a hair grow, can we learn anything about how a human is generated? Would knowing how a leaf blows, even perfectly, give us any insight into how a tree grows?

But, allowing that we were to take the operations of one part of nature upon another, for the foundation of our judgement concerning the origin of the whole, (which never can be admitted,) yet why select so minute, so weak, so bounded a principle, as the reason and design of animals is found to be upon this planet? What peculiar privilege has this little agitation of the brain which we call thought, that we must thus make it the model of the whole universe? Our partiality in our own favour does indeed present it on all occasions; but sound philosophy ought carefully to guard against so natural an illusion.

But even if we were to base our understanding of the origin of everything on the operations of one part of nature interacting with another, which shouldn't be accepted, why would we choose such a small, weak, and limited principle, like the reasoning and purpose of animals on this planet? What special privilege does this tiny flurry of activity in our brains, which we call thought, have that we must use it as the model for the entire universe? Our bias towards ourselves definitely makes us see it that way all the time, but solid philosophy should be careful to avoid such a natural illusion.

So far from admitting, continued PHILO, that the operations of a part can afford us any just conclusion concerning the origin of the whole, I will not allow any one part to form a rule for another part, if the latter be very remote from the former. Is there any reasonable ground to conclude, that the inhabitants of other planets possess thought, intelligence, reason, or any thing similar to these faculties in men? When nature has so extremely diversified her manner of operation in this small globe, can we imagine that she incessantly copies herself throughout so immense a universe? And if thought, as we may well suppose, be confined merely to this narrow corner, and has even there so limited a sphere of action, with what propriety can we assign it for the original cause of all things? The narrow views of a peasant, who makes his domestic economy the rule for the government of kingdoms, is in comparison a pardonable sophism.

"Far from agreeing," PHILO continued, "that the workings of a part can give us solid conclusions about the origin of the whole, I won't accept that one part can be a standard for another that is very different from it. Is there any reasonable basis to believe that the inhabitants of other planets have thought, intelligence, reason, or anything similar to human faculties? When nature has shown such incredible variety in how it operates on this small planet, can we really think that it endlessly replicates itself across such an immense universe? And if thought, as we might assume, is limited to this small corner, and even there has such a restricted range of influence, how can we justifiably claim it as the original cause of everything? The narrow perspective of a peasant who uses his household management as a rule for ruling kingdoms is, by comparison, a forgivable fallacy."

But were we ever so much assured, that a thought and reason, resembling the human, were to be found throughout the whole universe, and were its activity elsewhere vastly greater and more commanding than it appears in this globe; yet I cannot see, why the operations of a world constituted, arranged, adjusted, can with any propriety be extended to a world which is in its embryo state, and is advancing towards that constitution and arrangement. By observation, we know somewhat of the economy, action, and nourishment of a finished animal; but we must transfer with great caution that observation to the growth of a foetus in the womb, and still more to the formation of an animalcule in the loins of its male parent. Nature, we find, even from our limited experience, possesses an infinite number of springs and principles, which incessantly discover themselves on every change of her position and situation. And what new and unknown principles would actuate her in so new and unknown a situation as that of the formation of a universe, we cannot, without the utmost temerity, pretend to determine.

But even if we were completely sure that a thought and reason similar to humans existed throughout the universe, and if its activity elsewhere was far greater and more dominant than what we see on this planet, I still don't understand why we could properly apply the workings of a fully developed world to a world that is still in its early stages, evolving towards that development and arrangement. Through observation, we understand a bit about the structure, function, and nourishment of a fully formed animal; however, we must be very cautious when applying that understanding to the growth of a fetus in the womb, and even more so to the development of a tiny organism within the body of its male parent. We see that nature, even with our limited experience, has an infinite number of mechanisms and principles that reveal themselves with every change in her position and circumstances. And what new and unknown principles would come into play in such a unique and unfamiliar situation as the formation of a universe, we cannot, without being extremely reckless, claim to know.

A very small part of this great system, during a very short time, is very imperfectly discovered to us; and do we thence pronounce decisively concerning the origin of the whole?

A tiny fragment of this vast system, for just a brief moment, is poorly understood by us; so should we then make bold claims about the origins of everything?

Admirable conclusion! Stone, wood, brick, iron, brass, have not, at this time, in this minute globe of earth, an order or arrangement without human art and contrivance; therefore the universe could not originally attain its order and arrangement, without something similar to human art. But is a part of nature a rule for another part very wide of the former? Is it a rule for the whole? Is a very small part a rule for the universe? Is nature in one situation, a certain rule for nature in another situation vastly different from the former?

Great conclusion! Stone, wood, brick, iron, and brass don't have any order or arrangement in this small world without human creativity and design; therefore, the universe couldn't have achieved its order and arrangement without something like human creativity. But is a part of nature a guideline for another part that is very different? Is it a guideline for the whole? Can a tiny part serve as a guideline for the universe? Is nature in one context a specific rule for nature in a completely different context?

And can you blame me, CLEANTHES, if I here imitate the prudent reserve of SIMONIDES, who, according to the noted story, being asked by HIERO, What God was? desired a day to think of it, and then two days more; and after that manner continually prolonged the term, without ever bringing in his definition or description? Could you even blame me, if I had answered at first, that I did not know, and was sensible that this subject lay vastly beyond the reach of my faculties? You might cry out sceptic and railler, as much as you pleased: but having found, in so many other subjects much more familiar, the imperfections and even contradictions of human reason, I never should expect any success from its feeble conjectures, in a subject so sublime, and so remote from the sphere of our observation. When two species of objects have always been observed to be conjoined together, I can infer, by custom, the existence of one wherever I see the existence of the other; and this I call an argument from experience. But how this argument can have place, where the objects, as in the present case, are single, individual, without parallel, or specific resemblance, may be difficult to explain. And will any man tell me with a serious countenance, that an orderly universe must arise from some thought and art like the human, because we have experience of it? To ascertain this reasoning, it were requisite that we had experience of the origin of worlds; and it is not sufficient, surely, that we have seen ships and cities arise from human art and contrivance...

And can you really blame me, CLEANTHES, if I imitate the careful restraint of SIMONIDES, who, as the famous story goes, when HIERO asked him what God was, requested a day to think it over, then asked for two more days, and kept extending the time without ever providing his definition or description? Could you even fault me if I had said right away that I didn’t know and that I recognized this subject is far beyond my understanding? You might call me a skeptic and a mocker as much as you want: but having found many other, more familiar subjects filled with the flaws and even contradictions of human reasoning, I would never expect any success from its weak guesses in a topic as profound and distant from our observation. When two types of objects are always seen together, I can infer, based on habit, the existence of one whenever I see the other; and I call this an argument from experience. But how this argument can apply when the objects, like in this case, are unique, singular, without parallels or specific resemblance, is hard to explain. And will anyone seriously tell me that an orderly universe must come from some thought and creativity like ours, simply because we have experience of that? To validate this reasoning, we would need experience of how worlds originate; and surely, it’s not enough that we have seen ships and cities come from human skill and design...

PHILO was proceeding in this vehement manner, somewhat between jest and earnest, as it appeared to me, when he observed some signs of impatience in CLEANTHES, and then immediately stopped short. What I had to suggest, said CLEANTHES, is only that you would not abuse terms, or make use of popular expressions to subvert philosophical reasonings. You know, that the vulgar often distinguish reason from experience, even where the question relates only to matter of fact and existence; though it is found, where that reason is properly analysed, that it is nothing but a species of experience. To prove by experience the origin of the universe from mind, is not more contrary to common speech, than to prove the motion of the earth from the same principle. And a caviller might raise all the same objections to the Copernican system, which you have urged against my reasonings. Have you other earths, might he say, which you have seen to move? Have...

PHILO was going off on a passionate rant, a mix of joking and seriousness, as it seemed to me, when he noticed some impatience in CLEANTHES and suddenly stopped. What I wanted to suggest, CLEANTHES said, is simply that you shouldn't misuse terms or rely on common phrases to undermine philosophical reasoning. You know that people often separate reason from experience, even when the discussion is just about facts and existence; however, if you analyze reason properly, you'll find it's really just a type of experience. Proving that the universe originated from mind using experience is no more out of step with common language than proving Earth's motion based on the same idea. And a skeptic could raise all the same doubts about the Copernican system that you've brought up against my reasoning. He might say, do you have other Earths that you've actually seen move? Have...

Yes! cried PHILO, interrupting him, we have other earths. Is not the moon another earth, which we see to turn round its centre? Is not Venus another earth, where we observe the same phenomenon? Are not the revolutions of the sun also a confirmation, from analogy, of the same theory? All the planets, are they not earths, which revolve about the sun? Are not the satellites moons, which move round Jupiter and Saturn, and along with these primary planets round the sun? These analogies and resemblances, with others which I have not mentioned, are the sole proofs of the COPERNICAN system; and to you it belongs to consider, whether you have any analogies of the same kind to support your theory.

"Yes!" Philo shouted, cutting him off. "We have other worlds. Isn't the moon another world that we see orbiting around its center? Isn't Venus another world where we observe the same thing? Don't the movements of the sun also support this theory by analogy? Aren't all the planets worlds that revolve around the sun? Aren't the moons of Jupiter and Saturn also orbiting these primary planets while they move around the sun? These comparisons and similarities, along with others I haven't mentioned, are the only evidence for the Copernican system. It’s up to you to think about whether you have any similar analogies to back up your theory."

In reality, CLEANTHES, continued he, the modern system of astronomy is now so much received by all inquirers, and has become so essential a part even of our earliest education, that we are not commonly very scrupulous in examining the reasons upon which it is founded. It is now become a matter of mere curiosity to study the first writers on that subject, who had the full force of prejudice to encounter, and were obliged to turn their arguments on every side in order to render them popular and convincing. But if we peruse GALILEO's famous Dialogues concerning the system of the world, we shall find, that that great genius, one of the sublimest that ever existed, first bent all his endeavours to prove, that there was no foundation for the distinction commonly made between elementary and celestial substances. The schools, proceeding from the illusions of sense, had carried this distinction very far; and had established the latter substances to be ingenerable, incorruptible, unalterable, impassable; and had assigned all the opposite qualities to the former. But GALILEO, beginning with the moon, proved its similarity in every particular to the earth; its convex figure, its natural darkness when not illuminated, its density, its distinction into solid and liquid, the variations of its phases, the mutual illuminations of the earth and moon, their mutual eclipses, the inequalities of the lunar surface, &c. After many instances of this kind, with regard to all the planets, men plainly saw that these bodies became proper objects of experience; and that the similarity of their nature enabled us to extend the same arguments and phenomena from one to the other.

In reality, CLEANTHES, he continued, the modern system of astronomy is now widely accepted by all who inquire into it, and has become such an essential part of even our earliest education that we don’t usually take the time to carefully examine the reasons behind it. It’s now more a matter of curiosity to study the early writers on the subject, who had to overcome strong biases and were forced to shape their arguments from various angles to make them popular and convincing. However, if we read GALILEO’s famous Dialogues on the System of the World, we'll find that this great genius, one of the most brilliant minds to ever exist, first focused all his efforts on proving that there was no real basis for the distinction commonly made between earthly and celestial substances. The schools, influenced by sensory illusions, had taken this distinction quite far; they claimed that celestial substances were ungenerated, incorruptible, unchangeable, and impassable, while attributing all the opposite qualities to earthly ones. But GALILEO, starting with the moon, demonstrated its similarities to the earth in every aspect: its round shape, its natural darkness when not lit, its density, its differentiation into solid and liquid, the changes in its phases, the way the earth and moon illuminate each other, their mutual eclipses, the uneven surface of the moon, etc. After many examples of this sort concerning all the planets, people clearly saw that these celestial bodies could be observed and studied in the same way, and that their similar nature allowed us to apply the same arguments and phenomena from one to another.

In this cautious proceeding of the astronomers, you may read your own condemnation, CLEANTHES; or rather may see, that the subject in which you are engaged exceeds all human reason and inquiry. Can you pretend to show any such similarity between the fabric of a house, and the generation of a universe? Have you ever seen nature in any such situation as resembles the first arrangement of the elements? Have worlds ever been formed under your eye; and have you had leisure to observe the whole progress of the phenomenon, from the first appearance of order to its final consummation? If you have, then cite your experience, and deliver your theory.

In this careful approach of the astronomers, you can read your own downfall, CLEANTHES; or rather see that the topic you're involved in goes beyond all human logic and inquiry. Can you really claim there’s any similarity between building a house and creating a universe? Have you ever witnessed nature in a way that resembles the initial arrangement of the elements? Have worlds ever been formed in front of you, where you had the time to observe the entire process from the first sign of order to its final completion? If so, then share your experiences and present your theory.




PART 3

How the most absurd argument, replied CLEANTHES, in the hands of a man of ingenuity and invention, may acquire an air of probability! Are you not aware, PHILO, that it became necessary for Copernicus and his first disciples to prove the similarity of the terrestrial and celestial matter; because several philosophers, blinded by old systems, and supported by some sensible appearances, had denied this similarity? but that it is by no means necessary, that Theists should prove the similarity of the works of Nature to those of Art; because this similarity is self-evident and undeniable? The same matter, a like form; what more is requisite to show an analogy between their causes, and to ascertain the origin of all things from a divine purpose and intention? Your objections, I must freely tell you, are no better than the abstruse cavils of those philosophers who denied motion; and ought to be refuted in the same manner, by illustrations, examples, and instances, rather than by serious argument and philosophy.

How even the most ridiculous argument, replied CLEANTHES, can seem plausible in the hands of a clever and inventive person! Are you not aware, PHILO, that Copernicus and his earliest followers had to demonstrate the similarity between earthly and heavenly matter? This was necessary because many philosophers, blinded by outdated systems and misled by certain sensible observations, denied this similarity. However, it is not at all necessary for Theists to prove that the works of Nature are similar to those of Art, because this similarity is obvious and undeniable. The same matter, a similar form; what else do we need to show a connection between their causes and to confirm that everything originates from a divine purpose and intention? I must honestly tell you that your objections are no better than the complicated arguments of those philosophers who denied motion; they should be countered in the same way, with illustrations, examples, and instances, rather than through serious debate and philosophy.

Suppose, therefore, that an articulate voice were heard in the clouds, much louder and more melodious than any which human art could ever reach: Suppose, that this voice were extended in the same instant over all nations, and spoke to each nation in its own language and dialect: Suppose, that the words delivered not only contain a just sense and meaning, but convey some instruction altogether worthy of a benevolent Being, superior to mankind: Could you possibly hesitate a moment concerning the cause of this voice? and must you not instantly ascribe it to some design or purpose? Yet I cannot see but all the same objections (if they merit that appellation) which lie against the system of Theism, may also be produced against this inference.

Imagine if a clear voice were to echo in the clouds, much louder and more beautiful than anything human creativity could ever produce. Imagine that this voice reached every nation at the same time, speaking to each in its own language and dialect. Imagine that the words not only had accurate meaning but also provided guidance worthy of a kind Being, greater than humanity. Could you possibly doubt the source of this voice? Wouldn't you have to attribute it to some intention or purpose? Yet, I see that all the same objections (if they deserve that label) against the idea of Theism could also be raised against this conclusion.

Might you not say, that all conclusions concerning fact were founded on experience: that when we hear an articulate voice in the dark, and thence infer a man, it is only the resemblance of the effects which leads us to conclude that there is a like resemblance in the cause: but that this extraordinary voice, by its loudness, extent, and flexibility to all languages, bears so little analogy to any human voice, that we have no reason to suppose any analogy in their causes: and consequently, that a rational, wise, coherent speech proceeded, you know not whence, from some accidental whistling of the winds, not from any divine reason or intelligence? You see clearly your own objections in these cavils, and I hope too you see clearly, that they cannot possibly have more force in the one case than in the other.

Could you not argue that all conclusions about facts are based on experience? When we hear a clear voice in the dark and assume it belongs to a man, we are relying on the similarity of the effects to conclude that there is a similar cause. However, this extraordinary voice, with its loudness, range, and ability to adapt to all languages, has so little in common with a human voice that we have no reason to believe the causes are similar. Consequently, the rational, coherent speech might have come from some accidental whistling of the wind, rather than from any divine reason or intelligence. You can clearly see your own objections in these arguments, and I hope you also recognize that they have no more weight in one case than in the other.

But to bring the case still nearer the present one of the universe, I shall make two suppositions, which imply not any absurdity or impossibility. Suppose that there is a natural, universal, invariable language, common to every individual of human race; and that books are natural productions, which perpetuate themselves in the same manner with animals and vegetables, by descent and propagation. Several expressions of our passions contain a universal language: all brute animals have a natural speech, which, however limited, is very intelligible to their own species. And as there are infinitely fewer parts and less contrivance in the finest composition of eloquence, than in the coarsest organised body, the propagation of an Iliad or Aeneid is an easier supposition than that of any plant or animal.

But to make the case even closer to the present concept of the universe, I will put forward two assumptions that are neither absurd nor impossible. Imagine there’s a natural, universal, unchanging language that everyone in the human race shares; and that books are natural products, which continue to exist the same way animals and plants do, through reproduction and inheritance. Many expressions of our emotions contain a universal language: all animals have a natural form of communication, which, although limited, is quite understandable to their own kind. Given that there are far fewer components and less complexity in the best pieces of eloquence than in the simplest organized body, the idea of the Iliad or Aeneid being passed down is easier to accept than that of any plant or animal.

Suppose, therefore, that you enter into your library, thus peopled by natural volumes, containing the most refined reason and most exquisite beauty; could you possibly open one of them, and doubt, that its original cause bore the strongest analogy to mind and intelligence? When it reasons and discourses; when it expostulates, argues, and enforces its views and topics; when it applies sometimes to the pure intellect, sometimes to the affections; when it collects, disposes, and adorns every consideration suited to the subject; could you persist in asserting, that all this, at the bottom, had really no meaning; and that the first formation of this volume in the loins of its original parent proceeded not from thought and design? Your obstinacy, I know, reaches not that degree of firmness: even your sceptical play and wantonness would be abashed at so glaring an absurdity.

So, imagine you walk into your library, filled with natural books that hold the deepest reasoning and the greatest beauty. Could you really open one of them and doubt that its original source had a strong connection to thought and intelligence? When it reasons and discusses, when it debates, argues, and supports its ideas; when it sometimes appeals to pure intellect and other times to emotions; when it gathers, organizes, and enhances every point related to the topic; could you still claim that all of this, at its core, actually has no meaning, and that the creation of this book from its original source didn’t come from thought and intention? I know your stubbornness doesn’t reach that level of determination: even your skeptical games and mischief would be embarrassed by such a blatant absurdity.

But if there be any difference, PHILO, between this supposed case and the real one of the universe, it is all to the advantage of the latter. The anatomy of an animal affords many stronger instances of design than the perusal of LIVY or TACITUS; and any objection which you start in the former case, by carrying me back to so unusual and extraordinary a scene as the first formation of worlds, the same objection has place on the supposition of our vegetating library. Choose, then, your party, PHILO, without ambiguity or evasion; assert either that a rational volume is no proof of a rational cause, or admit of a similar cause to all the works of nature.

But if there’s any difference, PHILO, between this hypothetical situation and the actual state of the universe, it all favors the latter. The structure of an animal presents many more compelling examples of design than reading LIVY or TACITUS does; and any objection you raise regarding the former can also be applied when considering our unusual library. So, choose your side, PHILO, without ambiguity or evasion; either claim that a rational text doesn’t prove a rational cause, or accept that there is a similar cause behind all the works of nature.

Let me here observe too, continued CLEANTHES, that this religious argument, instead of being weakened by that scepticism so much affected by you, rather acquires force from it, and becomes more firm and undisputed. To exclude all argument or reasoning of every kind, is either affectation or madness. The declared profession of every reasonable sceptic is only to reject abstruse, remote, and refined arguments; to adhere to common sense and the plain instincts of nature; and to assent, wherever any reasons strike him with so full a force that he cannot, without the greatest violence, prevent it. Now the arguments for Natural Religion are plainly of this kind; and nothing but the most perverse, obstinate metaphysics can reject them. Consider, anatomise the eye; survey its structure and contrivance; and tell me, from your own feeling, if the idea of a contriver does not immediately flow in upon you with a force like that of sensation. The most obvious conclusion, surely, is in favour of design; and it requires time, reflection, and study, to summon up those frivolous, though abstruse objections, which can support Infidelity. Who can behold the male and female of each species, the correspondence of their parts and instincts, their passions, and whole course of life before and after generation, but must be sensible, that the propagation of the species is intended by Nature? Millions and millions of such instances present themselves through every part of the universe; and no language can convey a more intelligible irresistible meaning, than the curious adjustment of final causes. To what degree, therefore, of blind dogmatism must one have attained, to reject such natural and such convincing arguments?

Let me also point out, continued CLEANTHES, that this religious argument, rather than being weakened by the skepticism you often show, actually gains strength from it and becomes more solid and indisputable. To dismiss all forms of argument or reasoning is either pretentious or insane. The stated goal of every reasonable skeptic is simply to reject deep, distant, and complicated arguments; to stick to common sense and the basic instincts of nature; and to agree when any reasons strike him with such intensity that he cannot, without great effort, ignore them. Now, the arguments for Natural Religion are clearly of this kind; only the most stubborn and twisted metaphysics can dismiss them. Think about it: examine the eye; look at its design and function; and tell me, from your own experience, if the idea of a creator doesn’t immediately come to mind with the same force as a sensation. The most obvious conclusion, without a doubt, favors design; and it takes time, thought, and study to come up with those trivial yet complex objections that might support disbelief. Who can observe the male and female of each species, the alignment of their parts and instincts, their emotions, and their entire life cycle before and after reproduction, without realizing that nature intends for the species to propagate? Millions and millions of such examples exist throughout every part of the universe; and no words can express a clearer, more powerful meaning than the intricate alignment of final causes. To what level of blind dogmatism must someone have reached to reject such natural and compelling arguments?

Some beauties in writing we may meet with, which seem contrary to rules, and which gain the affections, and animate the imagination, in opposition to all the precepts of criticism, and to the authority of the established masters of art. And if the argument for Theism be, as you pretend, contradictory to the principles of logic; its universal, its irresistible influence proves clearly, that there may be arguments of a like irregular nature. Whatever cavils may be urged, an orderly world, as well as a coherent, articulate speech, will still be received as an incontestable proof of design and intention.

Some beautiful pieces of writing we come across seem to go against the rules, yet they capture our hearts and spark our imagination, despite contradicting all the guidelines of criticism and the teachings of established masters in the art. And if the case for Theism is, as you claim, contradictory to the principles of logic, its widespread and undeniable impact clearly shows that there can be arguments of a similar unconventional nature. No matter what objections are raised, a well-ordered world, like a coherent and articulate speech, will still be taken as undeniable evidence of design and intention.

It sometimes happens, I own, that the religious arguments have not their due influence on an ignorant savage and barbarian; not because they are obscure and difficult, but because he never asks himself any question with regard to them. Whence arises the curious structure of an animal? From the copulation of its parents. And these whence? From their parents? A few removes set the objects at such a distance, that to him they are lost in darkness and confusion; nor is he actuated by any curiosity to trace them further. But this is neither dogmatism nor scepticism, but stupidity: a state of mind very different from your sifting, inquisitive disposition, my ingenious friend. You can trace causes from effects: You can compare the most distant and remote objects: and your greatest errors proceed not from barrenness of thought and invention, but from too luxuriant a fertility, which suppresses your natural good sense, by a profusion of unnecessary scruples and objections.

Sometimes, I admit, religious arguments don't have much impact on an ignorant savage or barbarian; not because they are unclear or complicated, but because he never questions them. Where does the unique structure of an animal come from? From the mating of its parents. And where do they come from? From their parents? A few generations back make the origins so distant that they become lost in confusion for him, and he's not curious enough to explore further. But this isn't dogmatism or skepticism; it's just ignorance—a mindset very different from your questioning, curious nature, my clever friend. You can trace causes from effects; you can compare the most distant and unrelated things. Your biggest mistakes don't come from a lack of thought or creativity, but rather from an overabundance of ideas that overwhelm your natural common sense with too many unnecessary doubts and objections.

Here I could observe, HERMIPPUS, that PHILO was a little embarrassed and confounded: But while he hesitated in delivering an answer, luckily for him, DEMEA broke in upon the discourse, and saved his countenance.

Here, I noticed, HERMIPPUS, that PHILO looked a bit embarrassed and confused. But just as he hesitated to respond, fortunately for him, DEMEA jumped into the conversation and saved his face.

Your instance, CLEANTHES, said he, drawn from books and language, being familiar, has, I confess, so much more force on that account: but is there not some danger too in this very circumstance; and may it not render us presumptuous, by making us imagine we comprehend the Deity, and have some adequate idea of his nature and attributes? When I read a volume, I enter into the mind and intention of the author: I become him, in a manner, for the instant; and have an immediate feeling and conception of those ideas which revolved in his imagination while employed in that composition. But so near an approach we never surely can make to the Deity. His ways are not our ways. His attributes are perfect, but incomprehensible. And this volume of nature contains a great and inexplicable riddle, more than any intelligible discourse or reasoning.

Your example, CLEANTHES, he said, comes from books and language and is familiar, which I admit gives it much more strength: but isn’t there some risk in this very fact? Could it not lead us to become arrogant, making us think we can fully understand the Deity and have a complete grasp of His nature and attributes? When I read a book, I immerse myself in the thoughts and intentions of the author: I momentarily become him and immediately feel and grasp the ideas that were in his mind while he was writing. But we can never truly get that close to the Deity. His ways are not our ways. His attributes are perfect but beyond our understanding. And this book of nature holds a great and unfathomable mystery, more than any clear discourse or reasoning.

The ancient PLATONISTS, you know, were the most religious and devout of all the Pagan philosophers; yet many of them, particularly PLOTINUS, expressly declare, that intellect or understanding is not to be ascribed to the Deity; and that our most perfect worship of him consists, not in acts of veneration, reverence, gratitude, or love; but in a certain mysterious self-annihilation, or total extinction of all our faculties. These ideas are, perhaps, too far stretched; but still it must be acknowledged, that, by representing the Deity as so intelligible and comprehensible, and so similar to a human mind, we are guilty of the grossest and most narrow partiality, and make ourselves the model of the whole universe.

The ancient PLATONISTS, as you know, were the most religious and devoted of all the Pagan philosophers; yet many of them, especially PLOTINUS, clearly state that intellect or understanding should not be attributed to the Deity. They believe that our truest worship of Him isn't about acts of veneration, reverence, gratitude, or love; rather, it’s about a certain mysterious self-annihilation or total extinction of all our faculties. These ideas might be a bit extreme, but it must be recognized that by depicting the Deity as so understandable and similar to a human mind, we are committing the most significant act of narrow-mindedness and making ourselves the standard for the entire universe.

All the sentiments of the human mind, gratitude, resentment, love, friendship, approbation, blame, pity, emulation, envy, have a plain reference to the state and situation of man, and are calculated for preserving the existence and promoting the activity of such a being in such circumstances. It seems, therefore, unreasonable to transfer such sentiments to a supreme existence, or to suppose him actuated by them; and the phenomena besides of the universe will not support us in such a theory. All our ideas, derived from the senses, are confessedly false and illusive; and cannot therefore be supposed to have place in a supreme intelligence: And as the ideas of internal sentiment, added to those of the external senses, compose the whole furniture of human understanding, we may conclude, that none of the materials of thought are in any respect similar in the human and in the divine intelligence. Now, as to the manner of thinking; how can we make any comparison between them, or suppose them any wise resembling? Our thought is fluctuating, uncertain, fleeting, successive, and compounded; and were we to remove these circumstances, we absolutely annihilate its essence, and it would in such a case be an abuse of terms to apply to it the name of thought or reason. At least if it appear more pious and respectful (as it really is) still to retain these terms, when we mention the Supreme Being, we ought to acknowledge, that their meaning, in that case, is totally incomprehensible; and that the infirmities of our nature do not permit us to reach any ideas which in the least correspond to the ineffable sublimity of the Divine attributes.

All the feelings of the human mind—gratitude, resentment, love, friendship, approval, blame, pity, ambition, and envy—clearly relate to the condition and situation of humans, helping to sustain our existence and encourage our actions in those situations. Therefore, it seems unreasonable to apply those feelings to a supreme being or to think that such a being is influenced by them; moreover, the phenomena of the universe do not support this idea. All our ideas, which come from our senses, are undeniably false and misleading, so we can't expect them to apply to a supreme intelligence. Since our understanding is made up of both internal feelings and external sensory ideas, we can conclude that the thoughts in human intelligence are not in any way similar to those in divine intelligence. As for the way of thinking, how can we compare them or propose that they resemble each other at all? Our thoughts are constantly changing, uncertain, fleeting, sequential, and mixed; if we were to remove these aspects, we would completely destroy the essence of thought, making it incorrect to call it thought or reason at all. Even if it seems more reverent and respectful (which it truly is) to keep using these terms when we refer to the Supreme Being, we must acknowledge that their meaning, in that context, is entirely incomprehensible; our human weaknesses prevent us from grasping any ideas that truly reflect the awe-inspiring nature of the Divine attributes.




PART 4

It seems strange to me, said CLEANTHES, that you, DEMEA, who are so sincere in the cause of religion, should still maintain the mysterious, incomprehensible nature of the Deity, and should insist so strenuously that he has no manner of likeness or resemblance to human creatures. The Deity, I can readily allow, possesses many powers and attributes of which we can have no comprehension: But if our ideas, so far as they go, be not just, and adequate, and correspondent to his real nature, I know not what there is in this subject worth insisting on. Is the name, without any meaning, of such mighty importance? Or how do you mystics, who maintain the absolute incomprehensibility of the Deity, differ from Sceptics or Atheists, who assert, that the first cause of all is unknown and unintelligible? Their temerity must be very great, if, after rejecting the production by a mind, I mean a mind resembling the human, (for I know of no other,) they pretend to assign, with certainty, any other specific intelligible cause: And their conscience must be very scrupulous indeed, if they refuse to call the universal unknown cause a God or Deity; and to bestow on him as many sublime eulogies and unmeaning epithets as you shall please to require of them.

It seems strange to me, said Cleantes, that you, Demea, who are so sincere about religion, still insist on the mysterious and incomprehensible nature of the Deity, and argue so strongly that He has no likeness or resemblance to humans. I can easily accept that the Deity has many powers and attributes that we can't fully understand. But if our ideas, as far as they go, aren't accurate or don't match His true nature, I'm not sure what’s worth debating about in this topic. Is the name, without any meaning, really that important? Or how do you mystics, who claim that the Deity is completely incomprehensible, differ from skeptics or atheists, who say that the first cause of everything is unknown and unintelligible? Their boldness must be quite considerable, if after rejecting the idea of a mind, especially one that resembles a human mind (since I don’t know of any other), they think they can definitively assign some other specific understandable cause. And they must be very careful with their conscience if they refuse to call the universal unknown cause a God or Deity and to offer Him as many lofty praises and meaningless titles as you might ask for.

Who could imagine, replied DEMEA, that CLEANTHES, the calm philosophical CLEANTHES, would attempt to refute his antagonists by affixing a nickname to them; and, like the common bigots and inquisitors of the age, have recourse to invective and declamation, instead of reasoning? Or does he not perceive, that these topics are easily retorted, and that Anthropomorphite is an appellation as invidious, and implies as dangerous consequences, as the epithet of Mystic, with which he has honoured us? In reality, CLEANTHES, consider what it is you assert when you represent the Deity as similar to a human mind and understanding. What is the soul of man? A composition of various faculties, passions, sentiments, ideas; united, indeed, into one self or person, but still distinct from each other. When it reasons, the ideas, which are the parts of its discourse, arrange themselves in a certain form or order; which is not preserved entire for a moment, but immediately gives place to another arrangement. New opinions, new passions, new affections, new feelings arise, which continually diversify the mental scene, and produce in it the greatest variety and most rapid succession imaginable. How is this compatible with that perfect immutability and simplicity which all true Theists ascribe to the Deity? By the same act, say they, he sees past, present, and future: His love and hatred, his mercy and justice, are one individual operation: He is entire in every point of space; and complete in every instant of duration. No succession, no change, no acquisition, no diminution. What he is implies not in it any shadow of distinction or diversity. And what he is this moment he ever has been, and ever will be, without any new judgement, sentiment, or operation. He stands fixed in one simple, perfect state: nor can you ever say, with any propriety, that this act of his is different from that other; or that this judgement or idea has been lately formed, and will give place, by succession, to any different judgement or idea.

"Who could have imagined," DEMEA replied, "that CLEANTHES, the serene and philosophical CLEANTHES, would try to undermine his opponents by labeling them with a nickname? Like the narrow-minded bigots and inquisitors of our time, he resorts to insults and rants rather than logical arguments? Doesn't he realize that these points can easily be countered, and that calling us Anthropomorphites is as malicious and potentially harmful as the title of Mystic, which he has assigned to us? In reality, CLEANTHES, think about what you’re claiming when you portray the Deity as resembling a human mind and understanding. What is the soul of a person? It's a mix of different faculties, passions, feelings, and ideas; certainly united as one self or person, but still distinct from one another. When it reasons, the ideas that make up its discourse arrange themselves in a particular order; however, that order never lasts for even a moment before it's replaced by another. New opinions, new passions, new feelings emerge, continually changing the mental experience and creating the greatest variety and quickest transitions imaginable. How can this be compatible with the perfect constancy and simplicity that all true Theists attribute to the Deity? They argue that with the same act, He perceives past, present, and future: His love and hatred, His mercy and justice, are all part of a single operation. He exists fully in every point in space and completely in every moment in time. There’s no succession, no change, no gain, no loss. What He is contains no hint of distinction or variation. And what He is this moment, He has always been and will always be, without any new judgment, sentiment, or action. He remains fixed in one simple, perfect state; you can never properly say that this action of His is different from that one, or that this judgment or idea was formed recently and will give way to any different judgment or idea."

I can readily allow, said CLEANTHES, that those who maintain the perfect simplicity of the Supreme Being, to the extent in which you have explained it, are complete Mystics, and chargeable with all the consequences which I have drawn from their opinion. They are, in a word, Atheists, without knowing it. For though it be allowed, that the Deity possesses attributes of which we have no comprehension, yet ought we never to ascribe to him any attributes which are absolutely incompatible with that intelligent nature essential to him. A mind, whose acts and sentiments and ideas are not distinct and successive; one, that is wholly simple, and totally immutable, is a mind which has no thought, no reason, no will, no sentiment, no love, no hatred; or, in a word, is no mind at all. It is an abuse of terms to give it that appellation; and we may as well speak of limited extension without figure, or of number without composition.

“I can easily agree,” said CLEANTHES, “that those who advocate for the absolute simplicity of the Supreme Being, as you’ve described, are true Mystics and are responsible for all the implications I’ve outlined from their view. They are, in short, Atheists without realizing it. While it’s accepted that the Deity has attributes beyond our understanding, we should never attribute any qualities to him that are completely incompatible with the intelligent nature that is essential to him. A mind that has indistinct and non-sequential thoughts and feelings; one that is entirely simple and completely unchanging, is a mind that lacks thought, reason, will, feelings, love, and hatred; or, in simpler terms, is not a mind at all. It’s a misuse of language to call it that; we might as well talk about limited space without shape or numbers without composition.”

Pray consider, said PHILO, whom you are at present inveighing against. You are honouring with the appellation of Atheist all the sound, orthodox divines, almost, who have treated of this subject; and you will at last be, yourself, found, according to your reckoning, the only sound Theist in the world. But if idolaters be Atheists, as, I think, may justly be asserted, and Christian Theologians the same, what becomes of the argument, so much celebrated, derived from the universal consent of mankind?

"Please think about who you are currently criticizing," said PHILO. "You are calling almost all the sound, orthodox theologians, who have discussed this topic, Atheists, and soon you will find yourself, by your own reasoning, as the only true Theist in the world. But if idolaters are Atheists, as I believe can fairly be claimed, and if Christian theologians are the same, then what happens to that much-praised argument based on the universal agreement of humanity?"

But because I know you are not much swayed by names and authorities, I shall endeavour to show you, a little more distinctly, the inconveniences of that Anthropomorphism, which you have embraced; and shall prove, that there is no ground to suppose a plan of the world to be formed in the Divine mind, consisting of distinct ideas, differently arranged, in the same manner as an architect forms in his head the plan of a house which he intends to execute.

But since I know you’re not easily influenced by titles and experts, I’ll try to show you more clearly the downsides of that Anthropomorphism you’ve adopted; and I’ll demonstrate that there’s no reason to believe that a plan for the world exists in the Divine mind, made up of separate ideas arranged differently, like how an architect imagines the design of a house he intends to build.

It is not easy, I own, to see what is gained by this supposition, whether we judge of the matter by Reason or by Experience. We are still obliged to mount higher, in order to find the cause of this cause, which you had assigned as satisfactory and conclusive.

It’s not easy, I admit, to see what’s gained from this assumption, whether we look at it through Reason or Experience. We still have to go further up to find the cause of this cause, which you had stated as satisfactory and definitive.

If Reason (I mean abstract reason, derived from inquiries a priori) be not alike mute with regard to all questions concerning cause and effect, this sentence at least it will venture to pronounce, That a mental world, or universe of ideas, requires a cause as much, as does a material world, or universe of objects; and, if similar in its arrangement, must require a similar cause. For what is there in this subject, which should occasion a different conclusion or inference? In an abstract view, they are entirely alike; and no difficulty attends the one supposition, which is not common to both of them.

If Reason (I mean abstract reasoning, based on prior inquiries) isn't completely silent about all questions concerning cause and effect, it can at least state this: that a mental world, or universe of ideas, needs a cause just as much as a material world, or universe of objects; and if they are similar in their structure, they must require a similar cause. What in this matter could lead to a different conclusion or inference? From an abstract perspective, they are entirely the same; and there's no challenge with one assumption that isn't also common to both.

Again, when we will needs force Experience to pronounce some sentence, even on these subjects which lie beyond her sphere, neither can she perceive any material difference in this particular, between these two kinds of worlds; but finds them to be governed by similar principles, and to depend upon an equal variety of causes in their operations. We have specimens in miniature of both of them. Our own mind resembles the one; a vegetable or animal body the other. Let experience, therefore, judge from these samples. Nothing seems more delicate, with regard to its causes, than thought; and as these causes never operate in two persons after the same manner, so we never find two persons who think exactly alike. Nor indeed does the same person think exactly alike at any two different periods of time. A difference of age, of the disposition of his body, of weather, of food, of company, of books, of passions; any of these particulars, or others more minute, are sufficient to alter the curious machinery of thought, and communicate to it very different movements and operations. As far as we can judge, vegetables and animal bodies are not more delicate in their motions, nor depend upon a greater variety or more curious adjustment of springs and principles.

Once again, when we have to rely on Experience to make a judgment, even on topics that are beyond her reach, she can't see any significant difference between these two types of worlds. Instead, she finds they are both governed by similar rules and rely on an equal variety of causes in how they function. We have mini-examples of both. Our own mind reflects one, while a plant or animal body reflects the other. So let experience determine from these examples. Nothing seems more sensitive, in terms of its causes, than thought; and since these causes don’t operate the same way in two different people, we never find two people who think exactly alike. In fact, no person thinks the same way at two different times. Changes in age, body condition, weather, diet, company, books, or emotions—any of these factors, or even more subtle details, can significantly alter the intricate workings of thought, leading to very different outcomes and processes. To the best of our understanding, plants and animal bodies are not more sensitive in their movements, nor do they rely on a greater variety or more intricate adjustments of mechanisms and principles.

How, therefore, shall we satisfy ourselves concerning the cause of that Being whom you suppose the Author of Nature, or, according to your system of Anthropomorphism, the ideal world, into which you trace the material? Have we not the same reason to trace that ideal world into another ideal world, or new intelligent principle? But if we stop, and go no further; why go so far? why not stop at the material world? How can we satisfy ourselves without going on in infinitum? And, after all, what satisfaction is there in that infinite progression? Let us remember the story of the Indian philosopher and his elephant. It was never more applicable than to the present subject. If the material world rests upon a similar ideal world, this ideal world must rest upon some other; and so on, without end. It were better, therefore, never to look beyond the present material world. By supposing it to contain the principle of its order within itself, we really assert it to be God; and the sooner we arrive at that Divine Being, so much the better. When you go one step beyond the mundane system, you only excite an inquisitive humour which it is impossible ever to satisfy.

How, then, can we find satisfaction regarding the source of that Being whom you consider the Author of Nature, or, in your viewpoint of Anthropomorphism, the ideal world that you trace back to the material? Don’t we have the same grounds to trace that ideal world into another ideal world, or a new intelligent principle? But if we stop and don’t go further, why venture so far? Why not just stay at the material world? How can we feel satisfied without continuing endlessly? And in the end, what satisfaction comes from that infinite progression? Let’s recall the story of the Indian philosopher and his elephant. It’s more relevant now than ever. If the material world stands on a similar ideal world, that ideal world must depend on another, and so forth, endlessly. Therefore, it’s better not to look beyond the current material world. By assuming it holds the principle of its order within itself, we effectively declare it to be God; the sooner we reach that Divine Being, the better. When you take a single step beyond the earthly system, you simply stir up an inquisitive nature that can never be satisfied.

To say, that the different ideas which compose the reason of the Supreme Being, fall into order of themselves, and by their own nature, is really to talk without any precise meaning. If it has a meaning, I would fain know, why it is not as good sense to say, that the parts of the material world fall into order of themselves and by their own nature. Can the one opinion be intelligible, while the other is not so?

To say that the various ideas that make up the reasoning of the Supreme Being arrange themselves and do so naturally doesn't really convey a clear meaning. If it does have a meaning, then I'd like to know why it's sensible to say that the parts of the material world do the same thing. Can one viewpoint be understandable while the other is not?

We have, indeed, experience of ideas which fall into order of themselves, and without any known cause. But, I am sure, we have a much larger experience of matter which does the same; as, in all instances of generation and vegetation, where the accurate analysis of the cause exceeds all human comprehension. We have also experience of particular systems of thought and of matter which have no order; of the first in madness, of the second in corruption. Why, then, should we think, that order is more essential to one than the other? And if it requires a cause in both, what do we gain by your system, in tracing the universe of objects into a similar universe of ideas? The first step which we make leads us on for ever. It were, therefore, wise in us to limit all our inquiries to the present world, without looking further. No satisfaction can ever be attained by these speculations, which so far exceed the narrow bounds of human understanding.

We have indeed seen ideas that naturally organize themselves without any clear reason. However, I believe we have a much greater experience with matter doing the same, such as in all cases of growth and reproduction, where the precise analysis of the cause goes beyond human understanding. We also encounter specific systems of thought and matter that lack order; the former in instances of madness, the latter in cases of decay. So why should we assume that order is more crucial for one than the other? And if both require a cause, what do we really gain by your approach of relating the universe of objects to a similar universe of ideas? Every step we take leads us further on this path. Therefore, it would be wise for us to limit our inquiries to the present world without looking beyond it. No real satisfaction can ever come from these speculations that far exceed the narrow limits of human understanding.

It was usual with the PERIPATETICS, you know, CLEANTHES, when the cause of any phenomenon was demanded, to have recourse to their faculties or occult qualities; and to say, for instance, that bread nourished by its nutritive faculty, and senna purged by its purgative. But it has been discovered, that this subterfuge was nothing but the disguise of ignorance; and that these philosophers, though less ingenuous, really said the same thing with the sceptics or the vulgar, who fairly confessed that they knew not the cause of these phenomena. In like manner, when it is asked, what cause produces order in the ideas of the Supreme Being; can any other reason be assigned by you, Anthropomorphites, than that it is a rational faculty, and that such is the nature of the Deity? But why a similar answer will not be equally satisfactory in accounting for the order of the world, without having recourse to any such intelligent creator as you insist on, may be difficult to determine. It is only to say, that such is the nature of material objects, and that they are all originally possessed of a faculty of order and proportion. These are only more learned and elaborate ways of confessing our ignorance; nor has the one hypothesis any real advantage above the other, except in its greater conformity to vulgar prejudices.

The PERIPATETICS, you know, CLEANTHES, usually responded to questions about the cause of any phenomenon by referring to their inherent qualities or hidden powers. For example, they would say that bread nourishes because of its nourishing quality, and senna works as a laxative due to its purging quality. However, it has been found that this excuse was just a cover for ignorance; these philosophers, while less straightforward, essentially communicated the same thing as skeptics or ordinary people, who openly admitted they didn’t know the cause of these phenomena. Similarly, when asked what causes order in the ideas of the Supreme Being, can you, Anthropomorphites, provide any reason other than that it’s a rational faculty and that’s just the nature of the Deity? But it’s hard to explain why a similar explanation wouldn’t satisfactorily account for the order of the world without invoking some intelligent creator like you insist on. It can only be said that this is the nature of material objects, and they all inherently possess a faculty of order and proportion. These are just more scholarly and complex ways of admitting our ignorance; neither hypothesis has any real advantage over the other, except that one aligns more closely with common beliefs.

You have displayed this argument with great emphasis, replied CLEANTHES: You seem not sensible how easy it is to answer it. Even in common life, if I assign a cause for any event, is it any objection, PHILO, that I cannot assign the cause of that cause, and answer every new question which may incessantly be started? And what philosophers could possibly submit to so rigid a rule? philosophers, who confess ultimate causes to be totally unknown; and are sensible, that the most refined principles into which they trace the phenomena, are still to them as inexplicable as these phenomena themselves are to the vulgar. The order and arrangement of nature, the curious adjustment of final causes, the plain use and intention of every part and organ; all these bespeak in the clearest language an intelligent cause or author. The heavens and the earth join in the same testimony: The whole chorus of Nature raises one hymn to the praises of its Creator. You alone, or almost alone, disturb this general harmony. You start abstruse doubts, cavils, and objections: You ask me, what is the cause of this cause? I know not; I care not; that concerns not me. I have found a Deity; and here I stop my inquiry. Let those go further, who are wiser or more enterprising.

"You’ve made your point strongly," replied CLEANTHES. "You don’t seem to realize how easy it is to respond to it. Even in everyday life, if I explain the reason for any event, is it a valid objection, PHILO, that I can’t identify the reason behind that reason and answer every new question that keeps coming up? What philosophers would agree to such a strict rule? Those who admit that ultimate causes are completely unknown and understand that the most sophisticated principles they use to explain phenomena are still just as baffling to them as these phenomena are to the average person. The order and arrangement of nature, the fascinating adjustment of final causes, the clear purpose and intention of every part and organ—all of these unmistakably indicate an intelligent cause or creator. The heavens and the earth together bear the same witness: the entire chorus of Nature sings a song in praise of its Creator. You alone, or nearly alone, disrupt this overall harmony. You raise complex doubts, criticisms, and objections: you ask me, what is the cause of this cause? I don’t know; I don’t care; that doesn’t concern me. I have found a Deity; and here I conclude my search. Let those go further who are wiser or more adventurous."

I pretend to be neither, replied PHILO: And for that very reason, I should never perhaps have attempted to go so far; especially when I am sensible, that I must at last be contented to sit down with the same answer, which, without further trouble, might have satisfied me from the beginning. If I am still to remain in utter ignorance of causes, and can absolutely give an explication of nothing, I shall never esteem it any advantage to shove off for a moment a difficulty, which, you acknowledge, must immediately, in its full force, recur upon me. Naturalists indeed very justly explain particular effects by more general causes, though these general causes themselves should remain in the end totally inexplicable; but they never surely thought it satisfactory to explain a particular effect by a particular cause, which was no more to be accounted for than the effect itself. An ideal system, arranged of itself, without a precedent design, is not a whit more explicable than a material one, which attains its order in a like manner; nor is there any more difficulty in the latter supposition than in the former.

"I don’t pretend to be either," PHILO replied. "And because of that, I might never have tried to go this far; especially since I realize that I will ultimately have to settle for the same answer that could have satisfied me from the beginning without any further effort. If I am still going to stay completely clueless about causes and can’t truly explain anything, I won’t ever see it as a benefit to temporarily push away a difficulty that, as you acknowledge, will immediately come back to me with the same intensity. Naturalists rightly explain specific effects using more general causes, even though those general causes may end up being totally unexplainable. But they surely never thought it was satisfactory to explain a specific effect with a specific cause, which can't be understood any more than the effect itself. An ideal system that arranges itself without any prior design is not any more understandable than a material one that achieves its order in the same way; nor is there any more difficulty in the latter assumption than in the former."




PART 5

But to show you still more inconveniences, continued PHILO, in your Anthropomorphism, please to take a new survey of your principles. Like effects prove like causes. This is the experimental argument; and this, you say too, is the sole theological argument. Now, it is certain, that the liker the effects are which are seen, and the liker the causes which are inferred, the stronger is the argument. Every departure on either side diminishes the probability, and renders the experiment less conclusive. You cannot doubt of the principle; neither ought you to reject its consequences.

But to show you even more issues, continued PHILO, in your Anthropomorphism, please take another look at your principles. Similar effects indicate similar causes. This is the experimental argument; and you say this is also the only theological argument. Now, it's clear that the more similar the effects are that we observe, and the more similar the inferred causes are, the stronger the argument becomes. Any deviation on either side reduces the probability and makes the experiment less conclusive. You can't question the principle; nor should you dismiss its implications.

All the new discoveries in astronomy, which prove the immense grandeur and magnificence of the works of Nature, are so many additional arguments for a Deity, according to the true system of Theism; but, according to your hypothesis of experimental Theism, they become so many objections, by removing the effect still further from all resemblance to the effects of human art and contrivance. For, if LUCRETIUS[Lib. II. 1094], even following the old system of the world, could exclaim,

All the new discoveries in astronomy, which showcase the immense greatness and beauty of Nature's work, are additional evidence for a God, according to the true system of Theism. However, under your theory of experimental Theism, they become objections, as they distance the effects from any similarity to human art and design. If LUCRETIUS [Lib. II. 1094], even following the old worldview, could exclaim,

Quis regere immensi summam, quis habere profundi
Indu manu validas potis est moderanter habenas?
Quis pariter coelos omnes convertere? et omnes
Ignibus aetheriis terras suffire feraces?
Omnibus inque locis esse omni tempore praesto?

Quis regere immensi summam, quis habere profundi
Indu manu validas potis est moderanter habenas?
Quis pariter coelos omnes convertere? et omnes
Ignibus aetheriis terras suffire feraces?
Omnibus inque locis esse omni tempore praesto?

If TULLY [De. nat. Deor. Lib. I] esteemed this reasoning so natural, as to put it into the mouth of his EPICUREAN:

If TULLY [De. nat. Deor. Lib. I] thought this reasoning was so natural that he put it in the words of his EPICUREAN:

"Quibus enim oculis animi intueri potuit vester Plato fabricam illam tanti operis, qua construi a Deo atque aedificari mundum facit? quae molitio? quae ferramenta? qui vectes? quae machinae? qui ministri tanti muneris fuerunt? quemadmodum autem obedire et parere voluntati architecti aer, ignis, aqua, terra potuerunt?"

"With what eyes could your Plato observe that grand construction, the world, which was made and built by God? What a labor it was! What tools were used? What beams? What machines? What assistants were involved in such a great task? And how could air, fire, water, and earth obey and comply with the will of the architect?"

If this argument, I say, had any force in former ages, how much greater must it have at present, when the bounds of Nature are so infinitely enlarged, and such a magnificent scene is opened to us? It is still more unreasonable to form our idea of so unlimited a cause from our experience of the narrow productions of human design and invention.

If this argument had any weight in the past, how much stronger must it be now, when the limits of Nature have expanded so much, and such a magnificent view is available to us? It's even more unreasonable to shape our understanding of such an infinite cause based on our experiences with the limited outcomes of human design and invention.

The discoveries by microscopes, as they open a new universe in miniature, are still objections, according to you, arguments, according to me. The further we push our researches of this kind, we are still led to infer the universal cause of all to be vastly different from mankind, or from any object of human experience and observation.

The discoveries made through microscopes, which reveal a whole new tiny universe, are still objections to you and arguments to me. The more we delve into this kind of research, the more we are led to conclude that the universal cause of everything is completely different from humanity or anything we’ve experienced or observed.

And what say you to the discoveries in anatomy, chemistry, botany?... These surely are no objections, replied CLEANTHES; they only discover new instances of art and contrivance. It is still the image of mind reflected on us from innumerable objects. Add, a mind like the human, said PHILO. I know of no other, replied CLEANTHES. And the liker the better, insisted PHILO. To be sure, said CLEANTHES.

And what do you think about the discoveries in anatomy, chemistry, and botany?... These are definitely not objections, replied CLEANTHES; they just reveal new examples of skill and invention. It’s still the reflection of the mind we see in countless objects. Add to that a mind like the human one, said PHILO. I don't know of any other, replied CLEANTHES. And the more similar, the better, insisted PHILO. Of course, said CLEANTHES.

Now, CLEANTHES, said PHILO, with an air of alacrity and triumph, mark the consequences. First, By this method of reasoning, you renounce all claim to infinity in any of the attributes of the Deity. For, as the cause ought only to be proportioned to the effect, and the effect, so far as it falls under our cognisance, is not infinite; what pretensions have we, upon your suppositions, to ascribe that attribute to the Divine Being? You will still insist, that, by removing him so much from all similarity to human creatures, we give in to the most arbitrary hypothesis, and at the same time weaken all proofs of his existence.

Now, Cleantes, said Philo, with a sense of eagerness and victory, consider the implications. First, with this way of thinking, you give up any claim to infinity in any of the qualities of God. Since the cause should only match the effect, and the effect, as far as we can see, is not infinite, what basis do we have, based on your assumptions, to attribute that quality to the Divine Being? You will still argue that by distancing him from any resemblance to humans, we are adopting the most arbitrary of hypotheses, while also undermining all evidence of his existence.

Secondly, You have no reason, on your theory, for ascribing perfection to the Deity, even in his finite capacity, or for supposing him free from every error, mistake, or incoherence, in his undertakings. There are many inexplicable difficulties in the works of Nature, which, if we allow a perfect author to be proved a priori, are easily solved, and become only seeming difficulties, from the narrow capacity of man, who cannot trace infinite relations. But according to your method of reasoning, these difficulties become all real; and perhaps will be insisted on, as new instances of likeness to human art and contrivance. At least, you must acknowledge, that it is impossible for us to tell, from our limited views, whether this system contains any great faults, or deserves any considerable praise, if compared to other possible, and even real systems. Could a peasant, if the Aeneid were read to him, pronounce that poem to be absolutely faultless, or even assign to it its proper rank among the productions of human wit, he, who had never seen any other production?

Secondly, based on your theory, you have no reason to attribute perfection to the Deity, even in a limited sense, or to assume that He is free from any errors, mistakes, or inconsistencies in His actions. There are many puzzling challenges in the workings of Nature that, if we accept the existence of a perfect creator based on reasoning alone, are easily understood and just appear to be challenges due to our limited human perspective, which cannot grasp infinite connections. However, according to your line of reasoning, these challenges become fully real; and you might insist they are just more examples of similarities to human skill and design. At the very least, you must admit that it’s impossible for us to determine, from our limited perspective, whether this system has significant flaws or deserves any substantial acclaim compared to other possible, or even existing, systems. Could a peasant, if the Aeneid were read to him, claim that poem to be completely flawless, or even accurately rank it among other works of human creativity, if he had never encountered any other works?

But were this world ever so perfect a production, it must still remain uncertain, whether all the excellences of the work can justly be ascribed to the workman. If we survey a ship, what an exalted idea must we form of the ingenuity of the carpenter who framed so complicated, useful, and beautiful a machine? And what surprise must we feel, when we find him a stupid mechanic, who imitated others, and copied an art, which, through a long succession of ages, after multiplied trials, mistakes, corrections, deliberations, and controversies, had been gradually improving? Many worlds might have been botched and bungled, throughout an eternity, ere this system was struck out; much labour lost, many fruitless trials made; and a slow, but continued improvement carried on during infinite ages in the art of world-making. In such subjects, who can determine, where the truth; nay, who can conjecture where the probability lies, amidst a great number of hypotheses which may be proposed, and a still greater which may be imagined?

But even if this world were the most perfect creation, it would still be uncertain whether all the greatness of the work can truly be credited to the creator. When we look at a ship, we can’t help but admire the skill of the carpenter who built such a complex, useful, and beautiful machine. And how surprised we would be if we discovered that he was just a simple craftsman who copied others and learned an art that had been refined over many generations through numerous attempts, errors, corrections, careful thought, and debates. Many worlds could have been poorly constructed over eternity before this system was developed; countless hours could have been wasted, many unsuccessful attempts made; and a slow, but ongoing improvement in world-making could have taken place over infinite ages. In such matters, who can decide where the truth lies? Or even guess what the likelihood is, among a multitude of theories that could be put forward and even more that could be imagined?

And what shadow of an argument, continued PHILO, can you produce, from your hypothesis, to prove the unity of the Deity? A great number of men join in building a house or ship, in rearing a city, in framing a commonwealth; why may not several deities combine in contriving and framing a world? This is only so much greater similarity to human affairs. By sharing the work among several, we may so much further limit the attributes of each, and get rid of that extensive power and knowledge, which must be supposed in one deity, and which, according to you, can only serve to weaken the proof of his existence. And if such foolish, such vicious creatures as man, can yet often unite in framing and executing one plan, how much more those deities or demons, whom we may suppose several degrees more perfect!

And what kind of argument, continued PHILO, can you come up with from your hypothesis to prove that there is just one God? Many people come together to build a house or a ship, to create a city, or to form a government; why can't several gods work together to create and shape the world? This actually mirrors human activity even more. By dividing the work among multiple deities, we can limit the powers of each one and avoid that vast power and knowledge that would have to be attributed to a single deity, which, according to you, would only weaken the evidence for His existence. And if such foolish and flawed beings as humans can often come together to create and implement a single plan, how much more so could those deities or spirits, who we can assume are several levels more perfect?

To multiply causes without necessity, is indeed contrary to true philosophy: but this principle applies not to the present case. Were one deity antecedently proved by your theory, who were possessed of every attribute requisite to the production of the universe; it would be needless, I own, (though not absurd,) to suppose any other deity existent. But while it is still a question, Whether all these attributes are united in one subject, or dispersed among several independent beings, by what phenomena in nature can we pretend to decide the controversy? Where we see a body raised in a scale, we are sure that there is in the opposite scale, however concealed from sight, some counterpoising weight equal to it; but it is still allowed to doubt, whether that weight be an aggregate of several distinct bodies, or one uniform united mass. And if the weight requisite very much exceeds any thing which we have ever seen conjoined in any single body, the former supposition becomes still more probable and natural. An intelligent being of such vast power and capacity as is necessary to produce the universe, or, to speak in the language of ancient philosophy, so prodigious an animal exceeds all analogy, and even comprehension.

Multiplying causes unnecessarily goes against true philosophy, but this principle doesn't apply here. If your theory had already proven one deity that possessed all the necessary attributes to create the universe, it would be unnecessary, though not absurd, to assume any other deity exists. However, since it's still a question of whether all these attributes are combined in one being or spread out among several independent beings, what phenomena in nature can help us resolve this debate? When we see a weight lifted on one side of a scale, we know there's some hidden weight on the other side balancing it out, but it's still questionable whether that weight is made up of several distinct objects or one solid mass. And if the required weight far exceeds anything we've ever seen together in a single object, the idea of it being made up of several different things becomes even more likely and reasonable. An intelligent being with such immense power and capacity necessary to create the universe, or, in the terms of ancient philosophy, such a remarkable creature, goes beyond all comparison and even understanding.

But further, CLEANTHES: men are mortal, and renew their species by generation; and this is common to all living creatures. The two great sexes of male and female, says MILTON, animate the world. Why must this circumstance, so universal, so essential, be excluded from those numerous and limited deities? Behold, then, the theogony of ancient times brought back upon us.

But further, CLEANTHES: people are mortal and continue their species through reproduction, which is true for all living beings. The two main sexes, male and female, as MILTON says, bring life to the world. Why should this universal and essential aspect be left out from those many limited gods? Look, then, at the theogony of ancient times returning to us.

And why not become a perfect Anthropomorphite? Why not assert the deity or deities to be corporeal, and to have eyes, a nose, mouth, ears, &c.? EPICURUS maintained, that no man had ever seen reason but in a human figure; therefore the gods must have a human figure. And this argument, which is deservedly so much ridiculed by CICERO, becomes, according to you, solid and philosophical.

And why not become a perfect Anthropomorphite? Why not claim that the deity or deities are physical beings with eyes, a nose, mouth, ears, etc.? EPICURUS argued that no one has ever understood reason except through a human form; therefore, the gods must take on a human shape. And this argument, which CICERO rightly mocked, seems solid and philosophical according to you.

In a word, CLEANTHES, a man who follows your hypothesis is able perhaps to assert, or conjecture, that the universe, sometime, arose from something like design: but beyond that position he cannot ascertain one single circumstance; and is left afterwards to fix every point of his theology by the utmost license of fancy and hypothesis. This world, for aught he knows, is very faulty and imperfect, compared to a superior standard; and was only the first rude essay of some infant deity, who afterwards abandoned it, ashamed of his lame performance: it is the work only of some dependent, inferior deity; and is the object of derision to his superiors: it is the production of old age and dotage in some superannuated deity; and ever since his death, has run on at adventures, from the first impulse and active force which it received from him. You justly give signs of horror, DEMEA, at these strange suppositions; but these, and a thousand more of the same kind, are CLEANTHES's suppositions, not mine. From the moment the attributes of the Deity are supposed finite, all these have place. And I cannot, for my part, think that so wild and unsettled a system of theology is, in any respect, preferable to none at all.

In short, CLEANTHES, a person who supports your idea might say that the universe may have come from something resembling design; however, he cannot figure out a single detail beyond that point. He is left to determine every aspect of his beliefs through the greatest freedom of imagination and speculation. This world, for all he knows, is quite flawed and imperfect compared to a higher standard and was merely the first rough attempt by some inexperienced deity who later abandoned it, embarrassed by its imperfections. It might just be the work of a lesser, subordinate deity, ridiculed by those above it. Alternatively, it could be the creation of an old and senile deity, and ever since its demise, it has been moving on its own, driven by the initial impulse and force it received from him. You rightly express horror, DEMEA, at these bizarre ideas; however, these, along with a thousand others of a similar nature, are CLEANTHES's ideas, not mine. Once the attributes of the Deity are assumed to be finite, all these thoughts come into play. Personally, I cannot believe that such a chaotic and unstable theology is in any way better than having none at all.

These suppositions I absolutely disown, cried CLEANTHES: they strike me, however, with no horror, especially when proposed in that rambling way in which they drop from you. On the contrary, they give me pleasure, when I see, that, by the utmost indulgence of your imagination, you never get rid of the hypothesis of design in the universe, but are obliged at every turn to have recourse to it. To this concession I adhere steadily; and this I regard as a sufficient foundation for religion.

These assumptions I completely reject, shouted CLEANTHES: they don’t horrify me, especially when you present them in that wandering way. On the contrary, they please me because I see that, no matter how far you stretch your imagination, you can never fully escape the idea of design in the universe and have to rely on it at every turn. I firmly stand by this concession, and I see it as a solid basis for religion.




PART 6

It must be a slight fabric, indeed, said DEMEA, which can be erected on so tottering a foundation. While we are uncertain whether there is one deity or many; whether the deity or deities, to whom we owe our existence, be perfect or imperfect, subordinate or supreme, dead or alive, what trust or confidence can we repose in them? What devotion or worship address to them? What veneration or obedience pay them? To all the purposes of life the theory of religion becomes altogether useless: and even with regard to speculative consequences, its uncertainty, according to you, must render it totally precarious and unsatisfactory.

It must be a flimsy belief, indeed, said DEMEA, that can stand on such a shaky foundation. While we're unsure whether there is one god or many; whether the god or gods who created us are perfect or imperfect, lesser or greater, alive or dead, what trust or confidence can we place in them? What devotion or worship can we offer them? What respect or obedience can we show them? For all practical purposes, the idea of religion becomes completely pointless: and even regarding theoretical outcomes, its uncertainty, according to you, must make it entirely risky and unsatisfactory.

To render it still more unsatisfactory, said PHILO, there occurs to me another hypothesis, which must acquire an air of probability from the method of reasoning so much insisted on by CLEANTHES. That like effects arise from like causes: this principle he supposes the foundation of all religion. But there is another principle of the same kind, no less certain, and derived from the same source of experience; that where several known circumstances are observed to be similar, the unknown will also be found similar. Thus, if we see the limbs of a human body, we conclude that it is also attended with a human head, though hid from us. Thus, if we see, through a chink in a wall, a small part of the sun, we conclude, that, were the wall removed, we should see the whole body. In short, this method of reasoning is so obvious and familiar, that no scruple can ever be made with regard to its solidity.

To make it even more unsatisfactory, PHILO said, I have another hypothesis that must seem probable based on the reasoning method emphasized by CLEANTHES. The idea that similar effects come from similar causes: he argues that this principle is the foundation of all religion. But there’s another principle just as valid, based on the same source of experience; that when we observe several known circumstances to be similar, the unknown will also likely be similar. For example, if we see the limbs of a human body, we conclude it must also have a human head, even if it's hidden from our view. Likewise, if we see a little part of the sun through a crack in a wall, we assume that if the wall were removed, we would see the entire sun. In short, this method of reasoning is so clear and familiar that there can never really be any doubt about its validity.

Now, if we survey the universe, so far as it falls under our knowledge, it bears a great resemblance to an animal or organised body, and seems actuated with a like principle of life and motion. A continual circulation of matter in it produces no disorder: a continual waste in every part is incessantly repaired: the closest sympathy is perceived throughout the entire system: and each part or member, in performing its proper offices, operates both to its own preservation and to that of the whole. The world, therefore, I infer, is an animal; and the Deity is the SOUL of the world, actuating it, and actuated by it.

Now, if we look at the universe, as much as we understand it, it resembles an animal or a living organism and seems driven by a similar life force and movement. A constant circulation of matter happens without causing any chaos: ongoing decay in every part is continuously repaired: a deep connection is felt throughout the entire system: and every part, while fulfilling its specific role, helps to sustain itself and the whole. Therefore, I conclude that the world is like an animal; and the Deity is the SOUL of the world, giving it life and being influenced by it.

You have too much learning, CLEANTHES, to be at all surprised at this opinion, which, you know, was maintained by almost all the Theists of antiquity, and chiefly prevails in their discourses and reasonings. For though, sometimes, the ancient philosophers reason from final causes, as if they thought the world the workmanship of God; yet it appears rather their favourite notion to consider it as his body, whose organisation renders it subservient to him. And it must be confessed, that, as the universe resembles more a human body than it does the works of human art and contrivance, if our limited analogy could ever, with any propriety, be extended to the whole of nature, the inference seems juster in favour of the ancient than the modern theory.

You know too much, CLEANTHES, to be surprised by this opinion, which was held by almost all the Theists of ancient times and is mostly found in their discussions and arguments. While sometimes ancient philosophers reason from ultimate causes, as if they believed the world was created by God, they seem more inclined to view it as his body, which is structured in a way that serves him. It must be acknowledged that since the universe resembles a human body more than it resembles human-made art and inventions, if our limited comparison could ever reasonably be applied to all of nature, it seems that the ancient view has more merit than the modern one.

There are many other advantages, too, in the former theory, which recommended it to the ancient theologians. Nothing more repugnant to all their notions, because nothing more repugnant to common experience, than mind without body; a mere spiritual substance, which fell not under their senses nor comprehension, and of which they had not observed one single instance throughout all nature. Mind and body they knew, because they felt both: an order, arrangement, organisation, or internal machinery, in both, they likewise knew, after the same manner: and it could not but seem reasonable to transfer this experience to the universe; and to suppose the divine mind and body to be also coeval, and to have, both of them, order and arrangement naturally inherent in them, and inseparable from them.

There are many other benefits in the earlier theory that made it appealing to ancient theologians. Nothing was more against their beliefs—or more contrary to everyday experience—than the idea of a mind existing without a body; a purely spiritual substance that they couldn't perceive or understand, and of which they had never seen a single example in all of nature. They understood both mind and body because they experienced both. They also recognized an order, arrangement, organization, or internal mechanism in both, which led them to reasonably extend this understanding to the universe. They believed that the divine mind and body must also exist together and that both possess an inherent order and arrangement that is essential to their nature.

Here, therefore, is a new species of Anthropomorphism, CLEANTHES, on which you may deliberate; and a theory which seems not liable to any considerable difficulties. You are too much superior, surely, to systematical prejudices, to find any more difficulty in supposing an animal body to be, originally, of itself, or from unknown causes, possessed of order and organisation, than in supposing a similar order to belong to mind. But the vulgar prejudice, that body and mind ought always to accompany each other, ought not, one should think, to be entirely neglected; since it is founded on vulgar experience, the only guide which you profess to follow in all these theological inquiries. And if you assert, that our limited experience is an unequal standard, by which to judge of the unlimited extent of nature; you entirely abandon your own hypothesis, and must thenceforward adopt our Mysticism, as you call it, and admit of the absolute incomprehensibility of the Divine Nature.

Here’s a new type of Anthropomorphism, CLEANTHES, for you to think about; and a theory that doesn’t seem to have any major issues. You’re surely too advanced to let systematic biases make it hard for you to consider that an animal body could, on its own or due to unknown causes, have structure and organization, just like the mind does. However, the common belief that body and mind should always go together shouldn’t be completely dismissed; it’s based on common experience, which is the only guide you claim to follow in these theological discussions. If you argue that our limited experience is an unfair measure for judging the vastness of nature, then you’re completely abandoning your own theory, and you’ll have to embrace our Mysticism, as you call it, and accept the absolute incomprehensibility of the Divine Nature.

This theory, I own, replied CLEANTHES, has never before occurred to me, though a pretty natural one; and I cannot readily, upon so short an examination and reflection, deliver any opinion with regard to it. You are very scrupulous, indeed, said PHILO: were I to examine any system of yours, I should not have acted with half that caution and reserve, in starting objections and difficulties to it. However, if any thing occur to you, you will oblige us by proposing it.

"This theory, I admit," replied CLEANTHES, "has never really crossed my mind before, even though it's quite a natural one; and I can't quickly give any opinion on it after such a brief examination and reflection. You're being very careful, indeed," said PHILO. "If I were to evaluate any of your ideas, I wouldn't have approached it with half that caution and hesitation when raising objections and challenges. However, if anything comes to mind for you, we would appreciate you sharing it."

Why then, replied CLEANTHES, it seems to me, that, though the world does, in many circumstances, resemble an animal body; yet is the analogy also defective in many circumstances the most material: no organs of sense; no seat of thought or reason; no one precise origin of motion and action. In short, it seems to bear a stronger resemblance to a vegetable than to an animal, and your inference would be so far inconclusive in favour of the soul of the world.

Why then, replied CLEANTHES, it seems to me that, while the world does resemble an animal body in many ways, the analogy also falls short in several important aspects: there are no organs of sense, no central place for thought or reason, and no single source of motion and action. In short, it seems to resemble a plant more than an animal, making your argument less convincing in support of the soul of the world.

But, in the next place, your theory seems to imply the eternity of the world; and that is a principle, which, I think, can be refuted by the strongest reasons and probabilities. I shall suggest an argument to this purpose, which, I believe, has not been insisted on by any writer. Those, who reason from the late origin of arts and sciences, though their inference wants not force, may perhaps be refuted by considerations derived from the nature of human society, which is in continual revolution, between ignorance and knowledge, liberty and slavery, riches and poverty; so that it is impossible for us, from our limited experience, to foretell with assurance what events may or may not be expected. Ancient learning and history seem to have been in great danger of entirely perishing after the inundation of the barbarous nations; and had these convulsions continued a little longer, or been a little more violent, we should not probably have now known what passed in the world a few centuries before us. Nay, were it not for the superstition of the Popes, who preserved a little jargon of Latin, in order to support the appearance of an ancient and universal church, that tongue must have been utterly lost; in which case, the Western world, being totally barbarous, would not have been in a fit disposition for receiving the GREEK language and learning, which was conveyed to them after the sacking of CONSTANTINOPLE. When learning and books had been extinguished, even the mechanical arts would have fallen considerably to decay; and it is easily imagined, that fable or tradition might ascribe to them a much later origin than the true one. This vulgar argument, therefore, against the eternity of the world, seems a little precarious.

But next, your theory seems to suggest that the world is eternal, and I believe that idea can be challenged by strong reasons and probabilities. I’ll present an argument on this matter that I don’t think has been emphasized by any writer. Those who argue based on the recent emergence of arts and sciences may have valid points, but they could be disproven by looking at the nature of human society, which is always fluctuating between ignorance and knowledge, freedom and oppression, wealth and poverty. This makes it impossible for us, with our limited experience, to predict with certainty what events might or might not happen. Ancient knowledge and history were at serious risk of being completely lost after the waves of barbarian invasions, and had these disruptions lasted a bit longer or been more intense, we probably wouldn’t have any knowledge of what occurred a few centuries before us. Moreover, if it weren't for the superstitions of the Popes, who kept a bit of Latin jargon to maintain the illusion of an ancient universal church, that language would have been completely forgotten. In that case, the Western world, being entirely barbaric, wouldn’t have been ready to embrace the GREEK language and learning that came to them after the sack of CONSTANTINOPLE. When knowledge and books were extinguished, even practical skills would have significantly declined, and it’s easy to imagine that myths or traditions might attribute a much later origin to them than the actual one. Thus, this common argument against the eternity of the world seems a bit shaky.

But here appears to be the foundation of a better argument. LUCULLUS was the first that brought cherry-trees from ASIA to EUROPE; though that tree thrives so well in many EUROPEAN climates, that it grows in the woods without any culture. Is it possible, that throughout a whole eternity, no EUROPEAN had ever passed into ASIA, and thought of transplanting so delicious a fruit into his own country? Or if the tree was once transplanted and propagated, how could it ever afterwards perish? Empires may rise and fall, liberty and slavery succeed alternately, ignorance and knowledge give place to each other; but the cherry-tree will still remain in the woods of GREECE, SPAIN, and ITALY, and will never be affected by the revolutions of human society.

But here seems to be the basis of a stronger argument. LUCULLUS was the first to bring cherry trees from ASIA to EUROPE; although that tree does so well in many EUROPEAN climates that it grows wild in the woods without any care. Is it possible that for all eternity, no EUROPEAN ever traveled to ASIA and thought about bringing such a delicious fruit back home? Or if the tree was once brought over and cultivated, how could it ever die out afterwards? Empires may rise and fall, freedom and oppression may alternate, ignorance and knowledge may trade places; but the cherry tree will still thrive in the woods of GREECE, SPAIN, and ITALY, and will remain untouched by the changes in human society.

It is not two thousand years since vines were transplanted into FRANCE, though there is no climate in the world more favourable to them. It is not three centuries since horses, cows, sheep, swine, dogs, corn, were known in AMERICA. Is it possible, that during the revolutions of a whole eternity, there never arose a COLUMBUS, who might open the communication between EUROPE and that continent? We may as well imagine, that all men would wear stockings for ten thousand years, and never have the sense to think of garters to tie them. All these seem convincing proofs of the youth, or rather infancy, of the world; as being founded on the operation of principles more constant and steady than those by which human society is governed and directed. Nothing less than a total convulsion of the elements will ever destroy all the EUROPEAN animals and vegetables which are now to be found in the Western world.

It's been less than two thousand years since vines were planted in FRANCE, even though there's no climate on earth that's better for them. It's only been about three centuries since horses, cows, sheep, pigs, dogs, and grains were known in AMERICA. Is it possible that over the vast stretches of time, there was never a COLUMBUS who could connect EUROPE with that continent? It’s like believing that people could wear stockings for ten thousand years without ever thinking to use garters to hold them up. All of this seems to convincingly show the youth, or rather the infancy, of the world, as it’s based on principles that are more constant and steady than those that govern human society. Nothing short of a total upheaval of the natural world will ever wipe out all the EUROPEAN animals and plants currently in the Western world.

And what argument have you against such convulsions? replied PHILO. Strong and almost incontestable proofs may be traced over the whole earth, that every part of this globe has continued for many ages entirely covered with water. And though order were supposed inseparable from matter, and inherent in it; yet may matter be susceptible of many and great revolutions, through the endless periods of eternal duration. The incessant changes, to which every part of it is subject, seem to intimate some such general transformations; though, at the same time, it is observable, that all the changes and corruptions of which we have ever had experience, are but passages from one state of order to another; nor can matter ever rest in total deformity and confusion. What we see in the parts, we may infer in the whole; at least, that is the method of reasoning on which you rest your whole theory. And were I obliged to defend any particular system of this nature, which I never willingly should do, I esteem none more plausible than that which ascribes an eternal inherent principle of order to the world, though attended with great and continual revolutions and alterations. This at once solves all difficulties; and if the solution, by being so general, is not entirely complete and satisfactory, it is at least a theory that we must sooner or later have recourse to, whatever system we embrace. How could things have been as they are, were there not an original inherent principle of order somewhere, in thought or in matter? And it is very indifferent to which of these we give the preference. Chance has no place, on any hypothesis, sceptical or religious. Every thing is surely governed by steady, inviolable laws. And were the inmost essence of things laid open to us, we should then discover a scene, of which, at present, we can have no idea. Instead of admiring the order of natural beings, we should clearly see that it was absolutely impossible for them, in the smallest article, ever to admit of any other disposition.

“What objection do you have to these upheavals?” PHILO asked. There are strong and nearly undeniable proofs that every part of this planet has been completely submerged in water for many ages. Even if we assume that order is inseparable from matter and an inherent quality, matter can still undergo many significant changes over the endless stretches of eternal time. The continual changes that every part of matter experiences suggest some form of general transformations; yet, it is also clear that all the changes and decays we've observed are merely transitions from one state of order to another; matter can never exist in total chaos and disorder. What we observe in the parts can be inferred for the whole; at least, that is the reasoning on which you base your entire theory. If I had to defend any specific system of this kind, which I would prefer not to do, I find none more convincing than the one that attributes an eternal inherent principle of order to the universe, despite being accompanied by significant and ongoing revolutions and changes. This explanation resolves all issues; and while it may not be entirely complete and satisfactory due to its generality, it is at least a theory we will eventually have to consider, regardless of the system we adopt. How could things be as they are if there wasn’t an original inherent principle of order somewhere, either in thought or in matter? It's pretty much the same whether we prefer one over the other. Chance has no role in any hypothesis, be it skeptical or religious. Everything is certainly governed by steady, unwavering laws. And if the fundamental essence of things were revealed to us, we would discover a reality that we currently cannot even imagine. Instead of merely admiring the order of natural entities, we would clearly understand that it was absolutely impossible for them to exist in any other arrangement, even in the smallest detail.

Were any one inclined to revive the ancient Pagan Theology, which maintained, as we learn from HESIOD, that this globe was governed by 30,000 deities, who arose from the unknown powers of nature: you would naturally object, CLEANTHES, that nothing is gained by this hypothesis; and that it is as easy to suppose all men animals, beings more numerous, but less perfect, to have sprung immediately from a like origin. Push the same inference a step further, and you will find a numerous society of deities as explicable as one universal deity, who possesses within himself the powers and perfections of the whole society. All these systems, then, of Scepticism, Polytheism, and Theism, you must allow, on your principles, to be on a like footing, and that no one of them has any advantage over the others. You may thence learn the fallacy of your principles.

If anyone were to try to bring back the old Pagan beliefs, which, as we learn from HESIOD, claimed that this world is ruled by 30,000 gods that came from the unknown forces of nature, you would naturally argue, CLEANTHES, that this idea doesn’t really offer anything useful; and that it’s just as plausible to think that all humans are animals, more numerous but less perfect, who came from a similar origin. Take that idea a step further, and you’ll find a large group of gods is just as understandable as one universal god, who contains all the abilities and qualities of the entire group. So, all these ideas—Skepticism, Polytheism, and Theism—you must admit, based on your beliefs, are equally valid, and none of them has a clear advantage over the others. From this, you can see the flaw in your arguments.




PART 7

But here, continued PHILO, in examining the ancient system of the soul of the world, there strikes me, all on a sudden, a new idea, which, if just, must go near to subvert all your reasoning, and destroy even your first inferences, on which you repose such confidence. If the universe bears a greater likeness to animal bodies and to vegetables, than to the works of human art, it is more probable that its cause resembles the cause of the former than that of the latter, and its origin ought rather to be ascribed to generation or vegetation, than to reason or design. Your conclusion, even according to your own principles, is therefore lame and defective.

But here, PHILO continued, while examining the ancient system of the soul of the world, I suddenly came up with a new idea that, if valid, could greatly undermine all your reasoning and even dismantle your initial conclusions that you rely on so confidently. If the universe resembles animal bodies and plants more than it does human creations, it's more likely that its cause is similar to the former rather than the latter, and its origin should be attributed to generation or growth, rather than reason or design. Therefore, your conclusion, even by your own standards, is flawed and incomplete.

Pray open up this argument a little further, said DEMEA, for I do not rightly apprehend it in that concise manner in which you have expressed it.

“Could you expand on this argument a bit more?” said DEMEA, “because I don’t fully understand it in the brief way you’ve put it.”

Our friend CLEANTHES, replied PHILO, as you have heard, asserts, that since no question of fact can be proved otherwise than by experience, the existence of a Deity admits not of proof from any other medium. The world, says he, resembles the works of human contrivance; therefore its cause must also resemble that of the other. Here we may remark, that the operation of one very small part of nature, to wit man, upon another very small part, to wit that inanimate matter lying within his reach, is the rule by which CLEANTHES judges of the origin of the whole; and he measures objects, so widely disproportioned, by the same individual standard. But to waive all objections drawn from this topic, I affirm, that there are other parts of the universe (besides the machines of human invention) which bear still a greater resemblance to the fabric of the world, and which, therefore, afford a better conjecture concerning the universal origin of this system. These parts are animals and vegetables. The world plainly resembles more an animal or a vegetable, than it does a watch or a knitting-loom. Its cause, therefore, it is more probable, resembles the cause of the former. The cause of the former is generation or vegetation. The cause, therefore, of the world, we may infer to be something similar or analogous to generation or vegetation.

Our friend CLEANTHES, PHILO replied, as you know, believes that since no fact can be proven in any way other than through experience, the existence of a Deity cannot be proven through any other means. He argues that the world is similar to human-made creations, so its cause must also be similar to those creations. We might point out that CLEANTHES evaluates the origin of everything based on the interaction of a very small part of nature, namely humans, with another very small part, specifically the inanimate matter accessible to them. He uses this individual standard to assess things that are vastly different. However, putting aside any issues with this perspective, I assert that there are other aspects of the universe (apart from human-made machines) that closely resemble the structure of the world and thus provide a better idea about the universal origin of this system. These aspects are living beings and plants. The world clearly resembles an animal or a plant more than it resembles a watch or a knitting machine. Therefore, it’s more likely that its cause resembles the cause of the former. The cause of living beings and plants is reproduction and growth. Thus, we can infer that the cause of the world is something similar or analogous to reproduction or growth.

But how is it conceivable, said DEMEA, that the world can arise from any thing similar to vegetation or generation?

But how is it possible, said DEMEA, that the world can come from anything like plants or reproduction?

Very easily, replied PHILO. In like manner as a tree sheds its seed into the neighbouring fields, and produces other trees; so the great vegetable, the world, or this planetary system, produces within itself certain seeds, which, being scattered into the surrounding chaos, vegetate into new worlds. A comet, for instance, is the seed of a world; and after it has been fully ripened, by passing from sun to sun, and star to star, it is at last tossed into the unformed elements which every where surround this universe, and immediately sprouts up into a new system.

"Very easily," replied PHILO. "Just like a tree drops its seeds into nearby fields and grows new trees, the vast vegetable, the world, or this planetary system, creates seeds within itself. These seeds, when scattered into the surrounding chaos, grow into new worlds. A comet, for example, is the seed of a world; and after it has matured by traveling from sun to sun and star to star, it is eventually thrown into the formless elements that surround this universe, immediately sprouting into a new system."

Or if, for the sake of variety (for I see no other advantage), we should suppose this world to be an animal; a comet is the egg of this animal: and in like manner as an ostrich lays its egg in the sand, which, without any further care, hatches the egg, and produces a new animal; so...

Or if, just for variety (since I can't see any other benefit), we consider this world to be an animal; a comet is the egg of this animal: and just like how an ostrich lays its egg in the sand, which, without any additional help, hatches the egg and creates a new animal; so...

I understand you, says DEMEA: But what wild, arbitrary suppositions are these! What data have you for such extraordinary conclusions? And is the slight, imaginary resemblance of the world to a vegetable or an animal sufficient to establish the same inference with regard to both? Objects, which are in general so widely different, ought they to be a standard for each other?

I get what you’re saying, DEMEA replies. But what crazy, random assumptions are these! What evidence do you have for such outrageous conclusions? And is the slight, imaginary similarity between the world and a vegetable or an animal enough to draw the same conclusion about both? Given how different these objects generally are, should they really be used as a standard for each other?

Right, cries PHILO: This is the topic on which I have all along insisted. I have still asserted, that we have no data to establish any system of cosmogony. Our experience, so imperfect in itself, and so limited both in extent and duration, can afford us no probable conjecture concerning the whole of things. But if we must needs fix on some hypothesis; by what rule, pray, ought we to determine our choice? Is there any other rule than the greater similarity of the objects compared? And does not a plant or an animal, which springs from vegetation or generation, bear a stronger resemblance to the world, than does any artificial machine, which arises from reason and design?

"Absolutely," PHILO exclaims. "This is the point I’ve been emphasizing all along. I still maintain that we have no evidence to support any theory of the universe's origin. Our experience is too flawed and limited in both scope and time to provide us with any reasonable guess about everything. But if we must settle on a hypothesis, what criteria should we use to make our choice? Is there any guideline other than the greater resemblance of the things being compared? And doesn't a plant or an animal, which comes from growth or reproduction, resemble the universe more closely than any machine, which is created through reason and design?"

But what is this vegetation and generation of which you talk? said DEMEA. Can you explain their operations, and anatomise that fine internal structure on which they depend?

But what is this plant life and creation you're talking about? said DEMEA. Can you explain how they work and break down that fine internal structure they rely on?

As much, at least, replied PHILO, as CLEANTHES can explain the operations of reason, or anatomise that internal structure on which it depends. But without any such elaborate disquisitions, when I see an animal, I infer, that it sprang from generation; and that with as great certainty as you conclude a house to have been reared by design. These words, generation, reason, mark only certain powers and energies in nature, whose effects are known, but whose essence is incomprehensible; and one of these principles, more than the other, has no privilege for being made a standard to the whole of nature.

As much as CLEANTHES can explain how reason works or break down the internal structure it relies on, replied PHILO. But without going into such detailed discussions, when I see an animal, I conclude that it was produced through reproduction, just as confidently as you assume a house was built with intention. These terms, reproduction and reason, only represent certain powers and energies in nature, whose effects we understand, but whose true nature is beyond our grasp; and one of these principles, more than the other, shouldn't be given special status as the benchmark for all of nature.

In reality, DEMEA, it may reasonably be expected, that the larger the views are which we take of things, the better will they conduct us in our conclusions concerning such extraordinary and such magnificent subjects. In this little corner of the world alone, there are four principles, reason, instinct, generation, vegetation, which are similar to each other, and are the causes of similar effects. What a number of other principles may we naturally suppose in the immense extent and variety of the universe, could we travel from planet to planet, and from system to system, in order to examine each part of this mighty fabric? Any one of these four principles above mentioned, (and a hundred others which lie open to our conjecture,) may afford us a theory by which to judge of the origin of the world; and it is a palpable and egregious partiality to confine our view entirely to that principle by which our own minds operate. Were this principle more intelligible on that account, such a partiality might be somewhat excusable: But reason, in its internal fabric and structure, is really as little known to us as instinct or vegetation; and, perhaps, even that vague, indeterminate word, Nature, to which the vulgar refer every thing, is not at the bottom more inexplicable. The effects of these principles are all known to us from experience; but the principles themselves, and their manner of operation, are totally unknown; nor is it less intelligible, or less conformable to experience, to say, that the world arose by vegetation, from a seed shed by another world, than to say that it arose from a divine reason or contrivance, according to the sense in which CLEANTHES understands it.

Actually, DEMEA, it can be reasonably expected that the broader our perspective on things, the better we'll make conclusions about such extraordinary and magnificent subjects. In this small corner of the world alone, there are four principles—reason, instinct, generation, and vegetation—that are similar to each other and cause similar effects. Just think of how many other principles we could naturally assume exist in the vastness and variety of the universe if we could travel from planet to planet, from system to system, to examine each part of this grand structure? Any one of these four principles mentioned (along with countless others we can only speculate about) could give us a theory to judge the origin of the world. It’s clearly a biased limitation to focus solely on the principle that governs how our own minds work. If this principle were more understandable, such a bias might be somewhat justifiable. But in reality, the internal structure and workings of reason are just as unknown to us as those of instinct or vegetation, and perhaps even that vague, undefined term, Nature, to which people refer everything, is not really any more explainable at its core. We know the effects of these principles from experience, but the principles themselves and how they work are completely unknown; it's equally valid and consistent with experience to say that the world came into being through vegetation from a seed dropped by another world as it is to assert that it originated from divine reason or design, as CLEANTHES interprets it.

But methinks, said DEMEA, if the world had a vegetative quality, and could sow the seeds of new worlds into the infinite chaos, this power would be still an additional argument for design in its author. For whence could arise so wonderful a faculty but from design? Or how can order spring from any thing which perceives not that order which it bestows?

But I think, said DEMEA, if the world had the ability to grow and could plant the seeds of new worlds into the endless chaos, this power would be another reason to believe in its designer. For where could such an incredible ability come from except from a design? Or how can order come from something that doesn’t recognize the order it creates?

You need only look around you, replied PHILO, to satisfy yourself with regard to this question. A tree bestows order and organisation on that tree which springs from it, without knowing the order; an animal in the same manner on its offspring; a bird on its nest; and instances of this kind are even more frequent in the world than those of order, which arise from reason and contrivance. To say, that all this order in animals and vegetables proceeds ultimately from design, is begging the question; nor can that great point be ascertained otherwise than by proving, a priori, both that order is, from its nature, inseparably attached to thought; and that it can never of itself, or from original unknown principles, belong to matter.

You just need to look around you, PHILO replied, to answer this question for yourself. A tree brings order and structure to the tree that grows from it, even without knowing that order; an animal does the same for its young; a bird for its nest; and examples like this happen even more often in the world than those where order comes from reason and planning. Claiming that all this order in animals and plants ultimately comes from design is skipping the question; and that important point can only be established by proving, in advance, that order is inherently linked to thought and that it can never, by itself or from unknown original principles, belong to matter.

But further, DEMEA; this objection which you urge can never be made use of by CLEANTHES, without renouncing a defence which he has already made against one of my objections. When I inquired concerning the cause of that supreme reason and intelligence into which he resolves every thing; he told me, that the impossibility of satisfying such inquiries could never be admitted as an objection in any species of philosophy. "We must stop somewhere", says he; "nor is it ever within the reach of human capacity to explain ultimate causes, or show the last connections of any objects. It is sufficient, if any steps, so far as we go, are supported by experience and observation." Now, that vegetation and generation, as well as reason, are experienced to be principles of order in nature, is undeniable. If I rest my system of cosmogony on the former, preferably to the latter, it is at my choice. The matter seems entirely arbitrary. And when CLEANTHES asks me what is the cause of my great vegetative or generative faculty, I am equally entitled to ask him the cause of his great reasoning principle. These questions we have agreed to forbear on both sides; and it is chiefly his interest on the present occasion to stick to this agreement. Judging by our limited and imperfect experience, generation has some privileges above reason: for we see every day the latter arise from the former, never the former from the latter.

But further, DEMEA, this objection you raise can never be used by CLEANTHES without him giving up a defense he's already made against one of my arguments. When I asked about the ultimate reason and intelligence that he attributes to everything, he said that the impossibility of satisfying such inquiries should never be considered an objection in any type of philosophy. "We have to draw the line somewhere," he says, "and it's never within human ability to explain ultimate causes or to show the final connections of any objects. It's enough if any steps we take are backed by experience and observation." Now, it's undeniable that vegetation and generation, along with reason, are recognized as principles of order in nature. If I base my system of cosmogony on the former over the latter, that's my choice. The matter seems entirely arbitrary. And when CLEANTHES asks me what causes my significant vegetative or generative ability, I'm just as entitled to ask him what causes his significant reasoning ability. We’ve both agreed to avoid those questions, and it’s especially in his interest right now to stick with that agreement. Based on our limited and imperfect experiences, generation has some advantages over reason: we see every day that the latter comes from the former, but never the other way around.

Compare, I beseech you, the consequences on both sides. The world, say I, resembles an animal; therefore it is an animal, therefore it arose from generation. The steps, I confess, are wide; yet there is some small appearance of analogy in each step. The world, says CLEANTHES, resembles a machine; therefore it is a machine, therefore it arose from design. The steps are here equally wide, and the analogy less striking. And if he pretends to carry on my hypothesis a step further, and to infer design or reason from the great principle of generation, on which I insist; I may, with better authority, use the same freedom to push further his hypothesis, and infer a divine generation or theogony from his principle of reason. I have at least some faint shadow of experience, which is the utmost that can ever be attained in the present subject. Reason, in innumerable instances, is observed to arise from the principle of generation, and never to arise from any other principle.

Compare, I ask you, the outcomes on both sides. The world, I say, is like an animal; therefore, it is an animal, and it came from reproduction. The leaps, I admit, are significant; yet there is some slight resemblance in each step. The world, CLEANTHES argues, is like a machine; therefore, it is a machine, and it came from design. The jumps are equally significant here, and the resemblance is less compelling. If he tries to extend my argument a bit further and suggests that design or reason comes from the fundamental idea of reproduction that I support, I can, with just as much justification, take the liberty to extend his argument and suggest that a divine creation or theogony comes from his principle of reason. I have at least some faint hint of experience, which is the most we can ever achieve on this topic. In countless cases, reason is seen to come from the principle of reproduction, and it never arises from any other principle.

HESIOD, and all the ancient mythologists, were so struck with this analogy, that they universally explained the origin of nature from an animal birth, and copulation. PLATO too, so far as he is intelligible, seems to have adopted some such notion in his TIMAEUS.

HESIOD, along with all the ancient mythologists, was so impressed by this similarity that they all explained the origin of nature through animal reproduction and mating. PLATO, as far as he is understandable, also seems to have embraced a similar idea in his TIMAEUS.

The BRAHMINS assert, that the world arose from an infinite spider, who spun this whole complicated mass from his bowels, and annihilates afterwards the whole or any part of it, by absorbing it again, and resolving it into his own essence. Here is a species of cosmogony, which appears to us ridiculous; because a spider is a little contemptible animal, whose operations we are never likely to take for a model of the whole universe. But still here is a new species of analogy, even in our globe. And were there a planet wholly inhabited by spiders, (which is very possible,) this inference would there appear as natural and irrefragable as that which in our planet ascribes the origin of all things to design and intelligence, as explained by CLEANTHES. Why an orderly system may not be spun from the belly as well as from the brain, it will be difficult for him to give a satisfactory reason.

The Brahmins claim that the world came from an infinite spider, which spun this entire intricate mass from its insides and later destroys the whole or any part of it by absorbing it back and turning it into its own essence. This kind of creation story seems ridiculous to us because a spider is a rather insignificant creature, and we’re unlikely to see its actions as a model for the entire universe. Yet, there’s still a unique kind of analogy here, even on our planet. If there were a planet entirely populated by spiders, which is quite possible, this conclusion would seem just as natural and undeniable as the one that attributes the origin of everything to design and intelligence, as explained by Cleanthes. It would be hard for anyone to provide a convincing reason why a structured system couldn’t be spun from the belly just as easily as from the brain.

I must confess, PHILO, replied CLEANTHES, that of all men living, the task which you have undertaken, of raising doubts and objections, suits you best, and seems, in a manner, natural and unavoidable to you. So great is your fertility of invention, that I am not ashamed to acknowledge myself unable, on a sudden, to solve regularly such out-of-the-way difficulties as you incessantly start upon me: though I clearly see, in general, their fallacy and error. And I question not, but you are yourself, at present, in the same case, and have not the solution so ready as the objection: while you must be sensible, that common sense and reason are entirely against you; and that such whimsies as you have delivered, may puzzle, but never can convince us.

I have to admit, PHILO, replied CLEANTHES, that of all people, the job you've taken on of raising doubts and objections suits you best; it seems almost natural and unavoidable for you. Your creativity is so impressive that I'm not afraid to say I can't immediately solve the tricky questions you constantly throw at me, even though I can clearly see the flaws and errors in them. I'm sure you're in the same boat right now and don’t have an answer as quickly as you come up with objections. However, you must realize that common sense and reason are completely on our side, and the strange ideas you put forward may confuse us, but they can never truly convince us.




PART 8

What you ascribe to the fertility of my invention, replied PHILO, is entirely owing to the nature of the subject. In subjects adapted to the narrow compass of human reason, there is commonly but one determination, which carries probability or conviction with it; and to a man of sound judgement, all other suppositions, but that one, appear entirely absurd and chimerical. But in such questions as the present, a hundred contradictory views may preserve a kind of imperfect analogy; and invention has here full scope to exert itself. Without any great effort of thought, I believe that I could, in an instant, propose other systems of cosmogony, which would have some faint appearance of truth, though it is a thousand, a million to one, if either yours or any one of mine be the true system.

What you attribute to the creativity of my ideas, PHILO replied, is really just a result of the nature of the topic. In topics that fit within the limited capacity of human understanding, there's usually only one conclusion that seems reasonable or convincing; for a person with good judgment, all other ideas besides that one seem completely ridiculous and imaginary. However, in questions like this one, a hundred conflicting perspectives can still have some imperfect resemblance to reality, allowing for plenty of room for creativity. I believe that without much effort, I could quickly come up with other theories about the universe that might seem somewhat plausible, even though there’s a one in a thousand, a million chance that either your theory or any of mine is the true explanation.

For instance, what if I should revive the old EPICUREAN hypothesis? This is commonly, and I believe justly, esteemed the most absurd system that has yet been proposed; yet I know not whether, with a few alterations, it might not be brought to bear a faint appearance of probability. Instead of supposing matter infinite, as EPICURUS did, let us suppose it finite. A finite number of particles is only susceptible of finite transpositions: and it must happen, in an eternal duration, that every possible order or position must be tried an infinite number of times. This world, therefore, with all its events, even the most minute, has before been produced and destroyed, and will again be produced and destroyed, without any bounds and limitations. No one, who has a conception of the powers of infinite, in comparison of finite, will ever scruple this determination.

For example, what if I were to revive the old EPICUREAN theory? This is usually, and I believe rightly, considered the most ridiculous system ever proposed; yet I’m not sure if, with a few tweaks, it could gain even a slight appearance of plausibility. Instead of assuming matter is infinite, as EPICURUS did, let’s assume it’s finite. A finite number of particles can only have a finite number of arrangements: and over an infinite period, every possible order or position must be tried an infinite number of times. This world, therefore, with all its events, even the smallest ones, has been created and destroyed before, and will be created and destroyed again, without any limits. Anyone who understands the powers of the infinite compared to the finite will never question this conclusion.

But this supposes, said DEMEA, that matter can acquire motion, without any voluntary agent or first mover.

But this assumes, said DEMEA, that matter can gain motion without any voluntary agent or first mover.

And where is the difficulty, replied PHILO, of that supposition? Every event, before experience, is equally difficult and incomprehensible; and every event, after experience, is equally easy and intelligible. Motion, in many instances, from gravity, from elasticity, from electricity, begins in matter, without any known voluntary agent: and to suppose always, in these cases, an unknown voluntary agent, is mere hypothesis; and hypothesis attended with no advantages. The beginning of motion in matter itself is as conceivable a priori as its communication from mind and intelligence.

And what's the challenge with that assumption? Every event is equally difficult and hard to understand before we experience it, and once we do experience it, everything becomes clear and easy to grasp. Motion, in many cases, like with gravity, elasticity, and electricity, starts in matter without any known voluntary agent. Assuming there's always an unknown voluntary agent in these cases is just a theory, and one that doesn’t offer any benefits. The origin of motion in matter itself is just as understandable beforehand as the idea that it's transferred from a mind or intelligence.

Besides, why may not motion have been propagated by impulse through all eternity, and the same stock of it, or nearly the same, be still upheld in the universe? As much is lost by the composition of motion, as much is gained by its resolution. And whatever the causes are, the fact is certain, that matter is, and always has been, in continual agitation, as far as human experience or tradition reaches. There is not probably, at present, in the whole universe, one particle of matter at absolute rest.

Besides, why couldn't motion have been passed along by impulse throughout all eternity, with the same amount of it, or something very similar, still being maintained in the universe? The loss from the combination of motion is equal to the gain from its breakdown. And regardless of the causes, it's clear that matter is, and always has been, in constant motion, as far as human experience or tradition can tell. There probably isn't a single particle of matter anywhere in the universe that is completely at rest right now.

And this very consideration too, continued PHILO, which we have stumbled on in the course of the argument, suggests a new hypothesis of cosmogony, that is not absolutely absurd and improbable. Is there a system, an order, an economy of things, by which matter can preserve that perpetual agitation which seems essential to it, and yet maintain a constancy in the forms which it produces? There certainly is such an economy; for this is actually the case with the present world. The continual motion of matter, therefore, in less than infinite transpositions, must produce this economy or order; and by its very nature, that order, when once established, supports itself, for many ages, if not to eternity. But wherever matter is so poised, arranged, and adjusted, as to continue in perpetual motion, and yet preserve a constancy in the forms, its situation must, of necessity, have all the same appearance of art and contrivance which we observe at present. All the parts of each form must have a relation to each other, and to the whole; and the whole itself must have a relation to the other parts of the universe; to the element in which the form subsists; to the materials with which it repairs its waste and decay; and to every other form which is hostile or friendly. A defect in any of these particulars destroys the form; and the matter of which it is composed is again set loose, and is thrown into irregular motions and fermentations, till it unite itself to some other regular form. If no such form be prepared to receive it, and if there be a great quantity of this corrupted matter in the universe, the universe itself is entirely disordered; whether it be the feeble embryo of a world in its first beginnings that is thus destroyed, or the rotten carcass of one languishing in old age and infirmity. In either case, a chaos ensues; till finite, though innumerable revolutions produce at last some forms, whose parts and organs are so adjusted as to support the forms amidst a continued succession of matter.

And this very idea too, PHILO continued, which we've encountered during our discussion, suggests a new theory of how the universe began, one that isn't completely silly or unlikely. Is there a system, an order, a way things are organized, that allows matter to keep the constant movement it seems to need, while also maintaining a consistency in the shapes it creates? There definitely is such an organization; this is actually how the current world operates. The ongoing movement of matter, therefore, through countless changes, must create this order; and by its very nature, that order, once established, sustains itself for many years, if not forever. But wherever matter is balanced, arranged, and set up to remain in constant motion while still keeping a consistency in its shapes, it must necessarily have all the same signs of design and intention that we see today. All the parts of each shape must relate to each other and to the whole; and the whole itself must relate to the other parts of the universe; to the environment where the shape exists; to the materials that it uses to repair itself from wear and breakdown; and to every other shape that may be friendly or hostile. A flaw in any of these aspects destroys the shape; and the matter of which it's made becomes freed again, thrown into chaotic movements and reactions until it connects with another stable shape. If there isn't a suitable shape ready to receive it, and if there's a large amount of this disorganized matter in the universe, then the entire universe is thrown into chaos; whether it's the fragile early stage of a world that gets destroyed, or the decaying body of one suffering from age and weakness. In either case, chaos follows; until countless cycles eventually create some shapes, whose parts and functions are so aligned that they can maintain the shapes amidst ongoing changes in matter.

Suppose (for we shall endeavour to vary the expression), that matter were thrown into any position, by a blind, unguided force; it is evident that this first position must, in all probability, be the most confused and most disorderly imaginable, without any resemblance to those works of human contrivance, which, along with a symmetry of parts, discover an adjustment of means to ends, and a tendency to self-preservation. If the actuating force cease after this operation, matter must remain for ever in disorder, and continue an immense chaos, without any proportion or activity. But suppose that the actuating force, whatever it be, still continues in matter, this first position will immediately give place to a second, which will likewise in all probability be as disorderly as the first, and so on through many successions of changes and revolutions. No particular order or position ever continues a moment unaltered. The original force, still remaining in activity, gives a perpetual restlessness to matter. Every possible situation is produced, and instantly destroyed. If a glimpse or dawn of order appears for a moment, it is instantly hurried away, and confounded, by that never-ceasing force which actuates every part of matter.

Imagine that matter gets thrown into any position by a random, uncontrolled force; it's clear that this initial position is likely to be the most chaotic and disordered one possible, with no similarity to human-made structures, which show a balance of parts, a suitable alignment of means to ends, and a tendency to maintain themselves. If this force stops acting after that, matter would remain in disarray forever and stay as a vast chaos, lacking proportion or activity. However, if the force continues to act on the matter, this initial state will quickly shift to a second state, which will probably be just as disorganized as the first, and so on through many changes and transformations. No specific order or position lasts unchanged for even a moment. The original force, still active, causes a constant restlessness in matter. Every possible arrangement is created and then immediately destroyed. If a hint of order appears for even a brief moment, it is quickly swept away and mixed up by that relentless force that drives all parts of matter.

Thus the universe goes on for many ages in a continued succession of chaos and disorder. But is it not possible that it may settle at last, so as not to lose its motion and active force (for that we have supposed inherent in it), yet so as to preserve an uniformity of appearance, amidst the continual motion and fluctuation of its parts? This we find to be the case with the universe at present. Every individual is perpetually changing, and every part of every individual; and yet the whole remains, in appearance, the same. May we not hope for such a position, or rather be assured of it, from the eternal revolutions of unguided matter; and may not this account for all the appearing wisdom and contrivance which is in the universe? Let us contemplate the subject a little, and we shall find, that this adjustment, if attained by matter of a seeming stability in the forms, with a real and perpetual revolution or motion of parts, affords a plausible, if not a true solution of the difficulty.

So, the universe continues on for many ages, filled with chaos and disorder. But isn’t it possible that it could eventually settle down enough to maintain its motion and active force (which we believe is inherent in it), while also keeping a consistent appearance amid the ongoing motion and change of its parts? This is what we observe with the universe today. Every individual is always changing, as is every part of every individual; and yet the whole still seems the same. Can we not hope for such a state, or rather, be confident in it, from the eternal movements of unguided matter? Might this explain the apparent order and design we see in the universe? If we explore this idea a bit more, we'll discover that this balance, if achieved with seemingly stable forms but with a genuine and constant motion of parts, offers a reasonable, if not complete, solution to the dilemma.

It is in vain, therefore, to insist upon the uses of the parts in animals or vegetables, and their curious adjustment to each other. I would fain know, how an animal could subsist, unless its parts were so adjusted? Do we not find, that it immediately perishes whenever this adjustment ceases, and that its matter corrupting tries some new form? It happens indeed, that the parts of the world are so well adjusted, that some regular form immediately lays claim to this corrupted matter: and if it were not so, could the world subsist? Must it not dissolve as well as the animal, and pass through new positions and situations, till in great, but finite succession, it falls at last into the present or some such order?

It's pointless, then, to insist on the functions of the parts in animals or plants and their interesting interconnections. I really want to know how an animal could survive without these parts being properly connected. Don't we see that it immediately dies when this connection fails, and that its matter breaks down and attempts to take on a new form? In fact, the parts of the world are so well aligned that some regular structure instantly claims this broken-down matter: and if that weren't the case, could the world continue to exist? Wouldn't it also break down like the animal, going through new arrangements and changes until, over time, it eventually settles into its current or some similar order?

It is well, replied CLEANTHES, you told us, that this hypothesis was suggested on a sudden, in the course of the argument. Had you had leisure to examine it, you would soon have perceived the insuperable objections to which it is exposed. No form, you say, can subsist, unless it possess those powers and organs requisite for its subsistence: some new order or economy must be tried, and so on, without intermission; till at last some order, which can support and maintain itself, is fallen upon. But according to this hypothesis, whence arise the many conveniences and advantages which men and all animals possess? Two eyes, two ears, are not absolutely necessary for the subsistence of the species. Human race might have been propagated and preserved, without horses, dogs, cows, sheep, and those innumerable fruits and products which serve to our satisfaction and enjoyment. If no camels had been created for the use of man in the sandy deserts of AFRICA and ARABIA, would the world have been dissolved? If no lodestone had been framed to give that wonderful and useful direction to the needle, would human society and the human kind have been immediately extinguished? Though the maxims of Nature be in general very frugal, yet instances of this kind are far from being rare; and any one of them is a sufficient proof of design, and of a benevolent design, which gave rise to the order and arrangement of the universe.

It’s true, replied CLEANTHES, you mentioned that this idea came up suddenly during our discussion. If you had taken the time to examine it, you would have quickly noticed the major objections it faces. You say no form can exist unless it has the necessary powers and organs for its survival: some new order or system must be tried repeatedly until we eventually discover an arrangement that can support and sustain itself. But according to this idea, where do all the comforts and benefits that people and animals enjoy come from? Two eyes and two ears aren’t absolutely necessary for the survival of the species. Humanity could have continued and thrived without horses, dogs, cows, sheep, and the countless fruits and products that bring us satisfaction and pleasure. If camels hadn’t been created for human use in the sandy deserts of AFRICA and ARABIA, would the world have fallen apart? If no lodestone had been made to give that amazing and useful direction to the compass needle, would human society and mankind have been wiped out? Although Nature’s principles are generally quite economical, examples like these are not uncommon; any one of them is enough proof of intention, and of a benevolent intention, that led to the order and arrangement of the universe.

At least, you may safely infer, said PHILO, that the foregoing hypothesis is so far incomplete and imperfect, which I shall not scruple to allow. But can we ever reasonably expect greater success in any attempts of this nature? Or can we ever hope to erect a system of cosmogony, that will be liable to no exceptions, and will contain no circumstance repugnant to our limited and imperfect experience of the analogy of Nature? Your theory itself cannot surely pretend to any such advantage, even though you have run into Anthropomorphism, the better to preserve a conformity to common experience. Let us once more put it to trial. In all instances which we have ever seen, ideas are copied from real objects, and are ectypal, not archetypal, to express myself in learned terms: You reverse this order, and give thought the precedence. In all instances which we have ever seen, thought has no influence upon matter, except where that matter is so conjoined with it as to have an equal reciprocal influence upon it. No animal can move immediately any thing but the members of its own body; and indeed, the equality of action and reaction seems to be an universal law of nature: But your theory implies a contradiction to this experience. These instances, with many more, which it were easy to collect, (particularly the supposition of a mind or system of thought that is eternal, or, in other words, an animal ingenerable and immortal); these instances, I say, may teach all of us sobriety in condemning each other, and let us see, that as no system of this kind ought ever to be received from a slight analogy, so neither ought any to be rejected on account of a small incongruity. For that is an inconvenience from which we can justly pronounce no one to be exempted.

At the very least, you can reasonably conclude, said PHILO, that the previous idea is incomplete and flawed, which I'm happy to admit. But can we ever really expect to achieve more success with any attempts like this? Or can we ever hope to create a system of cosmogony that has no exceptions and contains nothing that contradicts our limited and imperfect understanding of the analogy of Nature? Your theory itself surely can't claim any such advantage, even though you've leaned into Anthropomorphism to align better with common experience. Let's put it to the test once again. In every case we've encountered, ideas are based on real objects and are secondary, not primary, using more scholarly terms: You flip this order and prioritize thought. In every instance we've seen, thought has no impact on matter unless that matter is so connected to it that it has a mutual influence. No animal can directly move anything but its own body parts; in fact, the principle of equal action and reaction seems to be a fundamental law of nature. But your theory contradicts this experience. These examples, along with many others that are easy to gather, especially the idea of an eternal mind or system of thought—essentially an immortal and uncreated being; these instances remind us to be cautious when judging one another. They show us that while no system like this should ever be accepted based on a weak analogy, it also shouldn't be dismissed just because of a minor inconsistency. That’s a problem from which we can justifiably say no one is exempt.

All religious systems, it is confessed, are subject to great and insuperable difficulties. Each disputant triumphs in his turn; while he carries on an offensive war, and exposes the absurdities, barbarities, and pernicious tenets of his antagonist. But all of them, on the whole, prepare a complete triumph for the Sceptic; who tells them, that no system ought ever to be embraced with regard to such subjects: For this plain reason, that no absurdity ought ever to be assented to with regard to any subject. A total suspense of judgement is here our only reasonable resource. And if every attack, as is commonly observed, and no defence, among Theologians, is successful; how complete must be his victory, who remains always, with all mankind, on the offensive, and has himself no fixed station or abiding city, which he is ever, on any occasion, obliged to defend?

All religious systems, it’s acknowledged, face major and insurmountable challenges. Every debater has their moment of victory; they wage a war of words, pointing out the absurdities, barbarities, and harmful beliefs of their opponent. However, in the end, all of this ultimately leads to a complete win for the Skeptic, who argues that no belief system should be accepted regarding these topics. The simple reason is this: no absurdity should ever be accepted about any subject. A total suspension of judgment is our only reasonable option here. And if every attack, as is often noted, is effective while there’s no successful defense among Theologians, how total must be the victory of someone who always stays on the offensive with everyone else and doesn’t have a fixed position or a permanent home that they ever have to defend?




PART 9

But if so many difficulties attend the argument a posteriori, said DEMEA, had we not better adhere to that simple and sublime argument a priori, which, by offering to us infallible demonstration, cuts off at once all doubt and difficulty? By this argument, too, we may prove the infinity of the Divine attributes, which, I am afraid, can never be ascertained with certainty from any other topic. For how can an effect, which either is finite, or, for aught we know, may be so; how can such an effect, I say, prove an infinite cause? The unity too of the Divine Nature, it is very difficult, if not absolutely impossible, to deduce merely from contemplating the works of nature; nor will the uniformity alone of the plan, even were it allowed, give us any assurance of that attribute. Whereas the argument a priori ...

But if there are so many challenges with the a posteriori argument, said DEMEA, wouldn't it be better to stick with that simple and powerful a priori argument, which, by providing us with undeniable proof, eliminates all doubt and difficulty? Through this argument, we can also demonstrate the infinity of Divine attributes, which I’m afraid can never be accurately determined from any other topic. How can an effect, which is either finite or, for all we know, might be finite, prove an infinite cause? It's also very difficult, if not completely impossible, to derive the unity of Divine Nature just by looking at the works of nature; and even if we allowed for the uniformity of the plan, it wouldn't give us any certainty about that attribute. Whereas the a priori argument...

You seem to reason, DEMEA, interposed CLEANTHES, as if those advantages and conveniences in the abstract argument were full proofs of its solidity. But it is first proper, in my opinion, to determine what argument of this nature you choose to insist on; and we shall afterwards, from itself, better than from its useful consequences, endeavour to determine what value we ought to put upon it.

You seem to think, DEMEA, interjected CLEANTHES, as if the advantages and conveniences in the abstract argument are complete proof of its strength. But I believe it's more important first to decide which argument of this kind you want to focus on; then we can better evaluate its worth based on the argument itself, rather than its practical outcomes.

The argument, replied DEMEA, which I would insist on, is the common one. Whatever exists must have a cause or reason of its existence; it being absolutely impossible for any thing to produce itself, or be the cause of its own existence. In mounting up, therefore, from effects to causes, we must either go on in tracing an infinite succession, without any ultimate cause at all; or must at last have recourse to some ultimate cause, that is necessarily existent: Now, that the first supposition is absurd, may be thus proved. In the infinite chain or succession of causes and effects, each single effect is determined to exist by the power and efficacy of that cause which immediately preceded; but the whole eternal chain or succession, taken together, is not determined or caused by any thing; and yet it is evident that it requires a cause or reason, as much as any particular object which begins to exist in time. The question is still reasonable, why this particular succession of causes existed from eternity, and not any other succession, or no succession at all. If there be no necessarily existent being, any supposition which can be formed is equally possible; nor is there any more absurdity in Nothing's having existed from eternity, than there is in that succession of causes which constitutes the universe. What was it, then, which determined Something to exist rather than Nothing, and bestowed being on a particular possibility, exclusive of the rest? External causes, there are supposed to be none. Chance is a word without a meaning. Was it Nothing? But that can never produce any thing. We must, therefore, have recourse to a necessarily existent Being, who carries the REASON of his existence in himself, and who cannot be supposed not to exist, without an express contradiction. There is, consequently, such a Being; that is, there is a Deity.

The argument, DEMEA replied, that I would emphasize is a common one. Everything that exists must have a cause or reason for its existence; it's completely impossible for anything to create itself or be the source of its own existence. So, when we trace effects back to their causes, we face two options: we either follow an endless chain without any ultimate cause, or we must eventually refer to some ultimate cause that necessarily exists. Now, the first option is absurd, and here's why. In this infinite chain of causes and effects, each individual effect exists because of the immediate cause that came before it. However, the entire eternal chain as a whole isn't caused by anything, and yet it's clear that it needs a cause or reason just like any specific object that begins to exist in time. The question still stands: why did this specific chain of causes exist from eternity, and not a different chain, or none at all? If there is no necessarily existing being, then any assumption made is equally possible; there's no more absurdity in Nothing having existed forever than there is in the chain of causes that makes up the universe. So, what was it that determined Something to exist instead of Nothing, and gave reality to one possibility over the others? There are assumed to be no external causes. Chance is just a meaningless concept. Was it nothing? But nothing can never bring anything into existence. Therefore, we must turn to a necessarily existing Being, whose existence is self-explanatory and whose non-existence would create a direct contradiction. Hence, such a Being exists; in other words, there is a Deity.

I shall not leave it to PHILO, said CLEANTHES, though I know that the starting objections is his chief delight, to point out the weakness of this metaphysical reasoning. It seems to me so obviously ill-grounded, and at the same time of so little consequence to the cause of true piety and religion, that I shall myself venture to show the fallacy of it.

I won't let PHILO do it, Cleantes said, even though I know that his favorite thing is pointing out the flaws in this philosophical reasoning. It seems clearly unfounded to me, and at the same time not very important to the cause of true faith and religion, so I’ll take the chance to expose its fallacy myself.

I shall begin with observing, that there is an evident absurdity in pretending to demonstrate a matter of fact, or to prove it by any arguments a priori. Nothing is demonstrable, unless the contrary implies a contradiction. Nothing, that is distinctly conceivable, implies a contradiction. Whatever we conceive as existent, we can also conceive as non-existent. There is no being, therefore, whose non-existence implies a contradiction. Consequently there is no being, whose existence is demonstrable. I propose this argument as entirely decisive, and am willing to rest the whole controversy upon it.

I want to start by pointing out that it’s clearly foolish to try to prove a fact or establish it through any arguments based on assumptions. Nothing can be proven unless the opposite leads to a contradiction. Anything that we can clearly imagine doesn’t imply a contradiction. What we think of as existing, we can also think of as not existing. Therefore, there is no being whose non-existence leads to a contradiction. As a result, there is no being whose existence can be proven. I present this argument as completely conclusive, and I'm ready to base the entire discussion on it.

It is pretended that the Deity is a necessarily existent being; and this necessity of his existence is attempted to be explained by asserting, that if we knew his whole essence or nature, we should perceive it to be as impossible for him not to exist, as for twice two not to be four. But it is evident that this can never happen, while our faculties remain the same as at present. It will still be possible for us, at any time, to conceive the non-existence of what we formerly conceived to exist; nor can the mind ever lie under a necessity of supposing any object to remain always in being; in the same manner as we lie under a necessity of always conceiving twice two to be four. The words, therefore, necessary existence, have no meaning; or, which is the same thing, none that is consistent.

It’s claimed that God is a being that must exist; and they try to explain this necessity by saying that if we fully understood His essence or nature, we would see that it’s just as impossible for Him not to exist as it is for two times two not to equal four. However, it's clear that this won’t ever happen as long as our understanding stays the same as it is now. We can always imagine the non-existence of what we once thought existed; and the mind can never be forced to assume that any object must always exist, in the same way we have to always think that two times two equals four. Therefore, the phrase necessary existence doesn’t really mean anything—or, in other words, it lacks a consistent meaning.

But further, why may not the material universe be the necessarily existent Being, according to this pretended explication of necessity? We dare not affirm that we know all the qualities of matter; and for aught we can determine, it may contain some qualities, which, were they known, would make its non-existence appear as great a contradiction as that twice two is five. I find only one argument employed to prove, that the material world is not the necessarily existent Being: and this argument is derived from the contingency both of the matter and the form of the world. "Any particle of matter," it is said[]Dr. Clarke, "may be conceived to be annihilated; and any form may be conceived to be altered. Such an annihilation or alteration, therefore, is not impossible." But it seems a great partiality not to perceive, that the same argument extends equally to the Deity, so far as we have any conception of him; and that the mind can at least imagine him to be non-existent, or his attributes to be altered. It must be some unknown, inconceivable qualities, which can make his non-existence appear impossible, or his attributes unalterable: And no reason can be assigned, why these qualities may not belong to matter. As they are altogether unknown and inconceivable, they can never be proved incompatible with it.

But further, why can't the material universe be the necessarily existing Being, according to this supposed explanation of necessity? We can't claim to know all the qualities of matter; for all we know, it may have some qualities that, if we understood them, would make its non-existence seem as much of a contradiction as the idea that two plus two equals five. I find only one argument used to prove that the material world is not the necessarily existing Being: and this argument comes from the fact that both the matter and the form of the world are contingent. "Any particle of matter," it is said by Dr. Clarke, "can be imagined to be annihilated; and any form can be imagined to be altered. Therefore, such annihilation or alteration is not impossible." But it seems quite biased not to realize that the same argument applies equally to the Deity, as far as we can conceive of him; and that the mind can at least imagine him as non-existent, or his attributes as altered. It must be some unknown, inconceivable qualities that make his non-existence seem impossible or his attributes unchangeable. And there’s no reason to believe these qualities can't apply to matter. Since they are entirely unknown and inconceivable, they can never be proven incompatible with it.

Add to this, that in tracing an eternal succession of objects, it seems absurd to inquire for a general cause or first author. How can any thing, that exists from eternity, have a cause, since that relation implies a priority in time, and a beginning of existence?

Adding to this, when we look at an endless chain of objects, it seems ridiculous to search for a general cause or first creator. How can anything that has existed for eternity have a cause, since that relationship suggests a time order and a beginning of existence?

In such a chain, too, or succession of objects, each part is caused by that which preceded it, and causes that which succeeds it. Where then is the difficulty? But the whole, you say, wants a cause. I answer, that the uniting of these parts into a whole, like the uniting of several distinct countries into one kingdom, or several distinct members into one body, is performed merely by an arbitrary act of the mind, and has no influence on the nature of things. Did I show you the particular causes of each individual in a collection of twenty particles of matter, I should think it very unreasonable, should you afterwards ask me, what was the cause of the whole twenty. This is sufficiently explained in explaining the cause of the parts.

In such a chain or sequence of objects, each part is caused by what came before it and causes what comes after it. So, where's the problem? But you say the whole needs a cause. I respond that bringing these parts together into a whole, like uniting several distinct countries into one kingdom or different members into a single body, is just an arbitrary act of the mind, and it doesn't affect the nature of things. If I showed you the specific causes for each individual in a set of twenty particles of matter, I would find it unreasonable if you then asked me what caused all twenty as a whole. This is clearly explained by detailing the causes of the parts.

Though the reasonings which you have urged, CLEANTHES, may well excuse me, said PHILO, from starting any further difficulties, yet I cannot forbear insisting still upon another topic. It is observed by arithmeticians, that the products of 9, compose always either 9, or some lesser product of 9, if you add together all the characters of which any of the former products is composed. Thus, of 18, 27, 36, which are products of 9, you make 9 by adding 1 to 8, 2 to 7, 3 to 6. Thus, 369 is a product also of 9; and if you add 3, 6, and 9, you make 18, a lesser product of 9. To a superficial observer, so wonderful a regularity may be admired as the effect either of chance or design: but a skilful algebraist immediately concludes it to be the work of necessity, and demonstrates, that it must for ever result from the nature of these numbers. Is it not probable, I ask, that the whole economy of the universe is conducted by a like necessity, though no human algebra can furnish a key which solves the difficulty? And instead of admiring the order of natural beings, may it not happen, that, could we penetrate into the intimate nature of bodies, we should clearly see why it was absolutely impossible they could ever admit of any other disposition? So dangerous is it to introduce this idea of necessity into the present question! and so naturally does it afford an inference directly opposite to the religious hypothesis!

Though the reasoning you’ve put forth, CLEANTHES, may justify me not bringing up any further problems, I can’t help but insist on another topic. Mathematicians have observed that the products of 9 always add up to either 9 or some lesser multiple of 9 when you sum all the digits that make up those products. For example, with 18, 27, and 36, which are products of 9, you can get 9 by adding 1 to 8, 2 to 7, and 3 to 6. Similarly, 369 is also a product of 9; if you add 3, 6, and 9, you get 18, which is a lesser product of 9. To someone who hasn’t thought deeply about it, this remarkable pattern might seem like a result of chance or design, but a skilled mathematician would immediately recognize it as a necessary outcome that arises from the nature of these numbers. Isn’t it likely, I ask, that the entire structure of the universe is governed by a similar necessity, even if no human mathematics can unlock the mystery? Instead of merely admiring the order of natural things, could it be that if we could understand the true nature of matter, we would see why it is utterly impossible for anything to be arranged differently? Introducing this idea of necessity into the current discussion is quite risky! It naturally suggests a conclusion that contradicts religious beliefs!

But dropping all these abstractions, continued PHILO, and confining ourselves to more familiar topics, I shall venture to add an observation, that the argument a priori has seldom been found very convincing, except to people of a metaphysical head, who have accustomed themselves to abstract reasoning, and who, finding from mathematics, that the understanding frequently leads to truth through obscurity, and, contrary to first appearances, have transferred the same habit of thinking to subjects where it ought not to have place. Other people, even of good sense and the best inclined to religion, feel always some deficiency in such arguments, though they are not perhaps able to explain distinctly where it lies; a certain proof that men ever did, and ever will derive their religion from other sources than from this species of reasoning.

But setting aside all these abstractions, PHILO continued, and focusing on more familiar topics, I’d like to share an observation: the argument from a priori reasoning is rarely very convincing, except to those who are intellectually inclined towards metaphysics, who have trained themselves in abstract thought. They often notice that mathematics can lead to truth through complexity and, counter to initial impressions, they apply the same way of thinking to topics where it doesn’t really fit. Other people, even those with common sense who are generally inclined toward religion, often sense a lack in these kinds of arguments, even if they can't quite explain why; this clearly shows that people have always drawn their religious beliefs from sources other than this kind of reasoning.




PART 10

It is my opinion, I own, replied DEMEA, that each man feels, in a manner, the truth of religion within his own breast, and, from a consciousness of his imbecility and misery, rather than from any reasoning, is led to seek protection from that Being, on whom he and all nature is dependent. So anxious or so tedious are even the best scenes of life, that futurity is still the object of all our hopes and fears. We incessantly look forward, and endeavour, by prayers, adoration, and sacrifice, to appease those unknown powers, whom we find, by experience, so able to afflict and oppress us. Wretched creatures that we are! what resource for us amidst the innumerable ills of life, did not religion suggest some methods of atonement, and appease those terrors with which we are incessantly agitated and tormented?

I believe, as DEMEA said, that everyone feels the truth of religion deep inside themselves, and it’s more about being aware of our own weaknesses and suffering than any logical reasoning that makes us look for protection from that Being on whom we and all of nature depend. Even the best moments in life can be so anxious or tiring that the future becomes the focus of all our hopes and fears. We constantly look ahead, trying to calm those unknown powers that we know, from experience, can hurt and oppress us through our prayers, worship, and sacrifices. Oh, how wretched we are! Without religion suggesting ways to atone and soothe the fears that constantly agitate and torment us, what hope would we have amidst the countless troubles of life?

I am indeed persuaded, said PHILO, that the best, and indeed the only method of bringing every one to a due sense of religion, is by just representations of the misery and wickedness of men. And for that purpose a talent of eloquence and strong imagery is more requisite than that of reasoning and argument. For is it necessary to prove what every one feels within himself? It is only necessary to make us feel it, if possible, more intimately and sensibly.

“I truly believe,” said PHILO, “that the best—and really the only—way to make everyone appreciate the importance of religion is by accurately portraying the suffering and wrongdoing of humanity. For this, a gift for eloquence and vivid imagery is far more important than reasoning and debate. Is it really necessary to prove what everyone already feels inside? What matters is to make us feel it, if possible, even more deeply and clearly.”

The people, indeed, replied DEMEA, are sufficiently convinced of this great and melancholy truth. The miseries of life; the unhappiness of man; the general corruptions of our nature; the unsatisfactory enjoyment of pleasures, riches, honours; these phrases have become almost proverbial in all languages. And who can doubt of what all men declare from their own immediate feeling and experience?

The people, indeed, replied DEMEA, are clearly convinced of this significant and sad truth. The struggles of life; the unhappiness of humanity; the widespread flaws in our nature; the disappointing enjoyment of pleasures, wealth, and honors; these phrases have become almost common in every language. And who can doubt what everyone expresses from their own direct feelings and experiences?

In this point, said PHILO, the learned are perfectly agreed with the vulgar; and in all letters, sacred and profane, the topic of human misery has been insisted on with the most pathetic eloquence that sorrow and melancholy could inspire. The poets, who speak from sentiment, without a system, and whose testimony has therefore the more authority, abound in images of this nature. From Homer down to Dr. Young, the whole inspired tribe have ever been sensible, that no other representation of things would suit the feeling and observation of each individual.

At this point, PHILO said, the educated completely agree with the common people; and throughout all literature, both sacred and secular, the theme of human suffering has been expressed with the most heartfelt eloquence that pain and sadness can evoke. Poets, who write from emotion rather than a structured approach, and whose voices carry more weight for that reason, are full of images like this. From Homer to Dr. Young, all inspired writers have understood that no other depiction would resonate with the feelings and experiences of each person.

As to authorities, replied DEMEA, you need not seek them. Look round this library of CLEANTHES. I shall venture to affirm, that, except authors of particular sciences, such as chemistry or botany, who have no occasion to treat of human life, there is scarce one of those innumerable writers, from whom the sense of human misery has not, in some passage or other, extorted a complaint and confession of it. At least, the chance is entirely on that side; and no one author has ever, so far as I can recollect, been so extravagant as to deny it.

As for authorities, replied DEMEA, you don’t need to look for them. Just take a look around this library of CLEANTHES. I’ll go out on a limb and say that, except for authors in specific fields like chemistry or botany, who don’t deal with human life, there are hardly any of those countless writers who haven’t, at some point, voiced a complaint about human suffering. At least, the odds are definitely in favor of that; and I can’t think of a single author who has been so unreasonable as to deny it.

There you must excuse me, said PHILO: LEIBNIZ has denied it; and is perhaps the first [That sentiment had been maintained by Dr. King and some few others before Leibniz; though by none of so great a fame as that German philosopher] who ventured upon so bold and paradoxical an opinion; at least, the first who made it essential to his philosophical system.

There you have to forgive me, said PHILO: LEIBNIZ has rejected it; and he might be the first [That sentiment had been maintained by Dr. King and a few others before Leibniz; though by none as famous as that German philosopher] who took such a bold and controversial stance; at least, the first who made it a key part of his philosophical system.

And by being the first, replied DEMEA, might he not have been sensible of his error? For is this a subject in which philosophers can propose to make discoveries especially in so late an age? And can any man hope by a simple denial (for the subject scarcely admits of reasoning), to bear down the united testimony of mankind, founded on sense and consciousness?

And by being the first, replied DEMEA, could he not have realized his mistake? After all, is this a topic where philosophers can really expect to make new discoveries, especially in our modern times? And can anyone think that by just denying it—since the topic hardly allows for logical reasoning—they can overpower the collective evidence of humanity, based on sense and awareness?

And why should man, added he, pretend to an exemption from the lot of all other animals? The whole earth, believe me, PHILO, is cursed and polluted. A perpetual war is kindled amongst all living creatures. Necessity, hunger, want, stimulate the strong and courageous: Fear, anxiety, terror, agitate the weak and infirm. The first entrance into life gives anguish to the new-born infant and to its wretched parent: Weakness, impotence, distress, attend each stage of that life: and it is at last finished in agony and horror.

And why should people, he added, act like they’re exempt from the fate of all other animals? The entire world, believe me, PHILO, is cursed and polluted. A constant struggle is ignited among all living beings. Necessity, hunger, and need drive the strong and brave: Fear, worry, and terror disturb the weak and fragile. The very moment of entering life brings pain to both the newborn baby and its miserable parent: Weakness, helplessness, and distress accompany every stage of that life: and it ultimately ends in agony and horror.

Observe too, says PHILO, the curious artifices of Nature, in order to embitter the life of every living being. The stronger prey upon the weaker, and keep them in perpetual terror and anxiety. The weaker too, in their turn, often prey upon the stronger, and vex and molest them without relaxation. Consider that innumerable race of insects, which either are bred on the body of each animal, or, flying about, infix their stings in him. These insects have others still less than themselves, which torment them. And thus on each hand, before and behind, above and below, every animal is surrounded with enemies, which incessantly seek his misery and destruction.

Notice too, says PHILO, the strange tricks of Nature, designed to make life tough for every living being. The strong prey on the weak and keep them in constant fear and worry. The weak, in turn, often target the strong, annoying and bothering them without pause. Think about the countless insects that either live on the bodies of animals or fly around, stinging them. These insects themselves have even smaller ones that torment them. So, all around, above and below, every animal is surrounded by enemies that relentlessly aim for their suffering and ruin.

Man alone, said DEMEA, seems to be, in part, an exception to this rule. For by combination in society, he can easily master lions, tigers, and bears, whose greater strength and agility naturally enable them to prey upon him.

Man alone, Demea said, seems to be, in part, an exception to this rule. Because when he combines with others in society, he can easily overcome lions, tigers, and bears, whose greater strength and agility would normally allow them to prey on him.

On the contrary, it is here chiefly, cried PHILO, that the uniform and equal maxims of Nature are most apparent. Man, it is true, can, by combination, surmount all his real enemies, and become master of the whole animal creation: but does he not immediately raise up to himself imaginary enemies, the demons of his fancy, who haunt him with superstitious terrors, and blast every enjoyment of life? His pleasure, as he imagines, becomes, in their eyes, a crime: his food and repose give them umbrage and offence: his very sleep and dreams furnish new materials to anxious fear: and even death, his refuge from every other ill, presents only the dread of endless and innumerable woes. Nor does the wolf molest more the timid flock, than superstition does the anxious breast of wretched mortals.

On the contrary, it's right here, shouted PHILO, that the consistent and fair laws of Nature are most clear. It's true that humans can, through collaboration, overcome all their real enemies and dominate all other animals: but don’t they instantly create imaginary enemies for themselves—phantoms of their imagination—that torment them with superstitious fears and ruin every joy in life? Their pleasure, as they see it, turns into a crime in the eyes of these imagined foes: their food and rest become sources of annoyance and offense: even their sleep and dreams feed their constant anxiety: and even death, which should be a relief from all other pain, only brings the fear of endless and countless miseries. And just as a wolf doesn’t disturb a timid flock more than superstition disrupts the troubled hearts of miserable people.

Besides, consider, DEMEA: This very society, by which we surmount those wild beasts, our natural enemies; what new enemies does it not raise to us? What woe and misery does it not occasion? Man is the greatest enemy of man. Oppression, injustice, contempt, contumely, violence, sedition, war, calumny, treachery, fraud; by these they mutually torment each other; and they would soon dissolve that society which they had formed, were it not for the dread of still greater ills, which must attend their separation.

Besides, think about it, DEMEA: This very society, which helps us rise above those wild beasts, our natural enemies; what new enemies does it create for us? What pain and suffering does it cause? Man is humanity's greatest enemy. Oppression, injustice, disdain, insults, violence, rebellion, war, slander, betrayal, deception; through these, they torment each other. They would quickly break apart the society they’ve built if it weren't for the fear of even greater problems that would come with separating.

But though these external insults, said DEMEA, from animals, from men, from all the elements, which assault us, form a frightful catalogue of woes, they are nothing in comparison of those which arise within ourselves, from the distempered condition of our mind and body. How many lie under the lingering torment of diseases? Hear the pathetic enumeration of the great poet.

But even though these outside insults, Demea said, from animals, from people, from all the elements that attack us, create an awful list of troubles, they are nothing compared to those that come from within ourselves, from the troubled state of our mind and body. How many suffer from the persistent pain of illnesses? Listen to the moving list from the great poet.


Intestine stone and ulcer, colic-pangs,
Demoniac frenzy, moping melancholy,
And moon-struck madness, pining atrophy,
Marasmus, and wide-wasting pestilence.
Dire was the tossing, deep the groans: despair
Tended the sick, busiest from couch to couch.
And over them triumphant death his dart
Shook: but delay'd to strike, though oft invok'd
With vows, as their chief good and final hope.

Intestinal stones and ulcers, cramps,
Demonic rage, deep depression,
And lunacy, fading away,
Wasting away, and widespread disease.
The tossing was dire, the groans deep: despair
Attended the sick, moving busily from bed to bed.
And over them, triumphant death held his dart
Steady: but delayed to strike, even though often called upon
With promises, as their greatest good and final hope.


The disorders of the mind, continued DEMEA, though more secret, are not perhaps less dismal and vexatious. Remorse, shame, anguish, rage, disappointment, anxiety, fear, dejection, despair; who has ever passed through life without cruel inroads from these tormentors? How many have scarcely ever felt any better sensations? Labour and poverty, so abhorred by every one, are the certain lot of the far greater number; and those few privileged persons, who enjoy ease and opulence, never reach contentment or true felicity. All the goods of life united would not make a very happy man; but all the ills united would make a wretch indeed; and any one of them almost (and who can be free from every one?) nay often the absence of one good (and who can possess all?) is sufficient to render life ineligible.

The disorders of the mind, Demea continued, though less obvious, are probably just as gloomy and frustrating. Remorse, shame, anguish, rage, disappointment, anxiety, fear, sadness, despair; who has gone through life without facing these tormentors? How many people have rarely experienced any positive feelings? Hardship and poverty, which everyone detests, are the certain fate of most people; and those few fortunate individuals who have comfort and wealth never truly find satisfaction or real happiness. All the good things in life combined wouldn’t make someone very happy, but all the bad things combined would certainly make someone miserable; and just one of those issues (and who can avoid all of them?) or often even the lack of one good thing (and who can have it all?) is enough to make life unbearable.

Were a stranger to drop on a sudden into this world, I would show him, as a specimen of its ills, a hospital full of diseases, a prison crowded with malefactors and debtors, a field of battle strewed with carcasses, a fleet foundering in the ocean, a nation languishing under tyranny, famine, or pestilence. To turn the gay side of life to him, and give him a notion of its pleasures; whither should I conduct him? to a ball, to an opera, to court? He might justly think, that I was only showing him a diversity of distress and sorrow.

If a stranger suddenly arrived in this world, I would show him, as an example of its problems, a hospital full of sick people, a prison packed with criminals and debtors, a battlefield littered with bodies, a fleet sinking in the ocean, a nation suffering under tyranny, famine, or disease. To show him the brighter side of life and give him a sense of its joys, where should I take him? To a dance, to an opera, to the palace? He might fairly think that I was just showing him a variety of suffering and sadness.

There is no evading such striking instances, said PHILO, but by apologies, which still further aggravate the charge. Why have all men, I ask, in all ages, complained incessantly of the miseries of life?... They have no just reason, says one: these complaints proceed only from their discontented, repining, anxious disposition...And can there possibly, I reply, be a more certain foundation of misery, than such a wretched temper?

There’s no avoiding such obvious examples, PHILO said, except through excuses, which only make the situation worse. Why have people throughout history constantly complained about the hardships of life?… One might say they have no valid reason: these complaints come just from their unhappy, resentful, anxious mindset… And I respond, can there be a more definite source of misery than such a miserable attitude?

But if they were really as unhappy as they pretend, says my antagonist, why do they remain in life?...

But if they were really as unhappy as they act, my opponent asks, why do they stick around?

Not satisfied with life, afraid of death.

Not happy with life, scared of death.

This is the secret chain, say I, that holds us. We are terrified, not bribed to the continuance of our existence.

This is the hidden chain, I say, that binds us. We're afraid, not coerced into continuing our existence.

It is only a false delicacy, he may insist, which a few refined spirits indulge, and which has spread these complaints among the whole race of mankind. . . . And what is this delicacy, I ask, which you blame? Is it any thing but a greater sensibility to all the pleasures and pains of life? and if the man of a delicate, refined temper, by being so much more alive than the rest of the world, is only so much more unhappy, what judgement must we form in general of human life?

It's just a false sense of delicacy, he might argue, something a few sensitive people indulge in, which has made everyone complain about the human experience. . . . And what is this delicacy you criticize? Is it anything other than a heightened sensitivity to the joys and sorrows of life? If a person with a delicate, refined temperament is much more aware of feelings than others, leading to greater unhappiness, what conclusion should we draw about human life as a whole?

Let men remain at rest, says our adversary, and they will be easy. They are willing artificers of their own misery. . . . No! reply I: an anxious languor follows their repose; disappointment, vexation, trouble, their activity and ambition.

Let men be, says our opponent, and they will be content. They are willing creators of their own suffering. . . . No! I reply: a restless fatigue comes after their peace; disappointment, frustration, and worry fuel their drive and ambition.

I can observe something like what you mention in some others, replied CLEANTHES: but I confess I feel little or nothing of it in myself, and hope that it is not so common as you represent it.

"I can see something like what you're talking about in others," replied CLEANTHES. "But I admit I feel little or nothing of it in myself, and I hope it's not as common as you say."

If you feel not human misery yourself, cried DEMEA, I congratulate you on so happy a singularity. Others, seemingly the most prosperous, have not been ashamed to vent their complaints in the most melancholy strains. Let us attend to the great, the fortunate emperor, CHARLES V, when, tired with human grandeur, he resigned all his extensive dominions into the hands of his son. In the last harangue which he made on that memorable occasion, he publicly avowed, that the greatest prosperities which he had ever enjoyed, had been mixed with so many adversities, that he might truly say he had never enjoyed any satisfaction or contentment. But did the retired life, in which he sought for shelter, afford him any greater happiness? If we may credit his son's account, his repentance commenced the very day of his resignation.

If you don't experience human misery yourself, cried DEMEA, I envy you that unique happiness. Others, who appear to be the most successful, haven't hesitated to express their complaints in the most sorrowful tones. Let’s consider the great and fortunate emperor, CHARLES V, who, exhausted by the burdens of power, gave up all his vast territories to his son. In his final speech on that memorable occasion, he openly acknowledged that the greatest successes he had ever experienced were tainted by so many hardships that he could honestly say he had never felt any true satisfaction or peace. But did the quiet life he pursued after that bring him any more happiness? According to his son's account, his regret began the very day he stepped down.

CICERO's fortune, from small beginnings, rose to the greatest lustre and renown; yet what pathetic complaints of the ills of life do his familiar letters, as well as philosophical discourses, contain? And suitably to his own experience, he introduces CATO, the great, the fortunate CATO, protesting in his old age, that had he a new life in his offer, he would reject the present.

CICERO's fortunes, from humble beginnings, grew to great success and fame; yet his personal letters and philosophical writings are filled with sad reflections on life's hardships. Reflecting his own experiences, he portrays CATO, the great and fortunate CATO, declaring in his old age that if he could live life again, he would refuse the one he has now.

Ask yourself, ask any of your acquaintance, whether they would live over again the last ten or twenty years of their life. No! but the next twenty, they say, will be better:

Ask yourself, ask any of your friends, whether they would want to relive the last ten or twenty years of their life. No! But they say the next twenty will be better:


And from the dregs of life, hope to receive
What the first sprightly running could not give.

And from the struggles of life, I hope to get
What the initial burst of energy couldn't provide.


Thus at last they find (such is the greatness of human misery, it reconciles even contradictions), that they complain at once of the shortness of life, and of its vanity and sorrow.

Thus at last they find (such is the depth of human misery, it reconciles even contradictions), that they complain at once about the brevity of life, and about its emptiness and sadness.

And is it possible, CLEANTHES, said PHILO, that after all these reflections, and infinitely more, which might be suggested, you can still persevere in your Anthropomorphism, and assert the moral attributes of the Deity, his justice, benevolence, mercy, and rectitude, to be of the same nature with these virtues in human creatures? His power we allow is infinite: whatever he wills is executed: but neither man nor any other animal is happy: therefore he does not will their happiness. His wisdom is infinite: He is never mistaken in choosing the means to any end: But the course of Nature tends not to human or animal felicity: therefore it is not established for that purpose. Through the whole compass of human knowledge, there are no inferences more certain and infallible than these. In what respect, then, do his benevolence and mercy resemble the benevolence and mercy of men?

And is it possible, Cleantes, said Philo, that after all these reflections, and even more than I could suggest, you can still stick to your anthropomorphism and claim that the moral qualities of God—his justice, kindness, mercy, and integrity—are the same as these virtues in humans? We agree that his power is limitless: whatever he wants gets done. But neither humans nor any other animals are truly happy; therefore, he does not want their happiness. His wisdom is unlimited: he never makes mistakes in choosing the means to any end. Yet, the way nature works doesn’t lead to the happiness of humans or animals; therefore, it wasn't created for that purpose. Throughout the entire range of human knowledge, there are no conclusions more certain and infallible than these. In what way, then, do his kindness and mercy resemble the kindness and mercy of humans?

EPICURUS's old questions are yet unanswered. Is he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing? then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?

EPICURUS's old questions still have no answers. Is he able to prevent evil but not willing? Then he's powerless. Is he willing but not able? Then he’s evil. Is he both able and willing? Then where does evil come from?

You ascribe, CLEANTHES (and I believe justly), a purpose and intention to Nature. But what, I beseech you, is the object of that curious artifice and machinery, which she has displayed in all animals? The preservation alone of individuals, and propagation of the species. It seems enough for her purpose, if such a rank be barely upheld in the universe, without any care or concern for the happiness of the members that compose it. No resource for this purpose: no machinery, in order merely to give pleasure or ease: no fund of pure joy and contentment: no indulgence, without some want or necessity accompanying it. At least, the few phenomena of this nature are overbalanced by opposite phenomena of still greater importance.

You, CLEANTHES (and I think rightly), attribute a purpose and intention to Nature. But what, I ask you, is the point of that intricate design and system that she showcases in all living beings? The survival of individuals and the continuation of the species. It seems sufficient for her goal if such a hierarchy is barely maintained in the universe, without any concern for the happiness of the members within it. There’s no resource for this aim: no system just to provide pleasure or comfort: no source of pure joy and contentment: no indulgence without some need or necessity linked to it. At least, the few examples of this kind are outweighed by opposing examples of even greater significance.

Our sense of music, harmony, and indeed beauty of all kinds, gives satisfaction, without being absolutely necessary to the preservation and propagation of the species. But what racking pains, on the other hand, arise from gouts, gravels, megrims, toothaches, rheumatisms, where the injury to the animal machinery is either small or incurable? Mirth, laughter, play, frolic, seem gratuitous satisfactions, which have no further tendency: spleen, melancholy, discontent, superstition, are pains of the same nature. How then does the Divine benevolence display itself, in the sense of you Anthropomorphites? None but we Mystics, as you were pleased to call us, can account for this strange mixture of phenomena, by deriving it from attributes, infinitely perfect, but incomprehensible.

Our appreciation for music, harmony, and really all types of beauty, brings us joy, even though it's not essential for our survival and reproduction. On the flip side, think about the intense suffering caused by gout, kidney stones, migraines, toothaches, and arthritis, where the damage to our bodies is either minor or incurable. Joy, laughter, games, and fun seem like unnecessary pleasures that serve no greater purpose. Feelings like frustration, sadness, dissatisfaction, and superstition are similar kinds of pain. So, how does Divine goodness show itself to you, who resemble humans? Only we Mystics, as you choose to call us, can explain this odd mix of experiences by tracing it back to attributes that are infinitely perfect but impossible to fully understand.

And have you at last, said CLEANTHES smiling, betrayed your intentions, PHILO? Your long agreement with DEMEA did indeed a little surprise me; but I find you were all the while erecting a concealed battery against me. And I must confess, that you have now fallen upon a subject worthy of your noble spirit of opposition and controversy. If you can make out the present point, and prove mankind to be unhappy or corrupted, there is an end at once of all religion. For to what purpose establish the natural attributes of the Deity, while the moral are still doubtful and uncertain?

And have you finally revealed your true intentions, PHILO? Your long agreement with DEMEA really took me by surprise; but it seems you were secretly preparing to challenge me. I have to admit, you’ve now chosen a topic that fits your spirited nature for debate and disagreement. If you can argue convincingly that people are unhappy or corrupt, that would immediately undermine all religion. After all, what’s the point in asserting the natural qualities of God if the moral ones remain questionable and ambiguous?

You take umbrage very easily, replied DEMEA, at opinions the most innocent, and the most generally received, even amongst the religious and devout themselves: and nothing can be more surprising than to find a topic like this, concerning the wickedness and misery of man, charged with no less than Atheism and profaneness. Have not all pious divines and preachers, who have indulged their rhetoric on so fertile a subject; have they not easily, I say, given a solution of any difficulties which may attend it? This world is but a point in comparison of the universe; this life but a moment in comparison of eternity. The present evil phenomena, therefore, are rectified in other regions, and in some future period of existence. And the eyes of men, being then opened to larger views of things, see the whole connection of general laws; and trace with adoration, the benevolence and rectitude of the Deity, through all the mazes and intricacies of his providence.

You get offended really easily, replied DEMEA, at opinions that are totally innocent and widely accepted, even among the religious and devout themselves. It's surprising to see a topic like this, which deals with the wickedness and suffering of humanity, accused of being nothing less than Atheism and profanity. Haven't all the pious clergy and preachers, who have enjoyed expressing their ideas on such a rich topic, easily found answers to any challenges it may present? This world is just a small dot compared to the universe; this life is merely a moment compared to eternity. Therefore, the current evil occurrences are resolved in other realms and in some future time of existence. And when people's eyes are opened to broader perspectives, they see the entire connection of universal laws and recognize with reverence the kindness and righteousness of the Deity throughout all the complexities and nuances of His providence.

No! replied CLEANTHES, No! These arbitrary suppositions can never be admitted, contrary to matter of fact, visible and uncontroverted. Whence can any cause be known but from its known effects? Whence can any hypothesis be proved but from the apparent phenomena? To establish one hypothesis upon another, is building entirely in the air; and the utmost we ever attain, by these conjectures and fictions, is to ascertain the bare possibility of our opinion; but never can we, upon such terms, establish its reality.

No! replied CLEANTHES, No! These random assumptions can never be accepted, as they go against obvious facts that are clear and undisputed. How can we know any cause except through its known effects? How can any hypothesis be proven except from the observable phenomena? Establishing one hypothesis on top of another is like building something that has no foundation; the best we can achieve through these guesses and made-up ideas is to determine the mere possibility of our opinion, but we can never, under such conditions, prove its actual reality.

The only method of supporting Divine benevolence, and it is what I willingly embrace, is to deny absolutely the misery and wickedness of man. Your representations are exaggerated; your melancholy views mostly fictitious; your inferences contrary to fact and experience. Health is more common than sickness; pleasure than pain; happiness than misery. And for one vexation which we meet with, we attain, upon computation, a hundred enjoyments.

The only way to support God's goodness, and I fully accept this, is to completely deny the suffering and evil in humanity. Your descriptions are overblown; your gloomy perspectives are mostly made up; your conclusions go against reality and experience. Health is more common than illness; pleasure is more frequent than pain; happiness outnumbers misery. And for every annoyance we encounter, we actually enjoy about a hundred good things.

Admitting your position, replied PHILO, which yet is extremely doubtful, you must at the same time allow, that if pain be less frequent than pleasure, it is infinitely more violent and durable. One hour of it is often able to outweigh a day, a week, a month of our common insipid enjoyments; and how many days, weeks, and months, are passed by several in the most acute torments? Pleasure, scarcely in one instance, is ever able to reach ecstasy and rapture; and in no one instance can it continue for any time at its highest pitch and altitude. The spirits evaporate, the nerves relax, the fabric is disordered, and the enjoyment quickly degenerates into fatigue and uneasiness. But pain often, good God, how often! rises to torture and agony; and the longer it continues, it becomes still more genuine agony and torture. Patience is exhausted, courage languishes, melancholy seizes us, and nothing terminates our misery but the removal of its cause, or another event, which is the sole cure of all evil, but which, from our natural folly, we regard with still greater horror and consternation.

"Admitting your viewpoint," PHILO replied, "which is very questionable, you also have to acknowledge that while pain is less common than pleasure, it is significantly more intense and lasting. An hour of pain can often outweigh a day, a week, or even a month of our usual dull joys; and how many days, weeks, and months do many people spend in severe torment? Pleasure, in almost every case, can rarely reach ecstasy and bliss; and it can never maintain its peak for long. Our energy fades, our nerves relax, our bodies become unbalanced, and enjoyment quickly turns into fatigue and discomfort. But pain, oh, how often it escalates to torture and agony; and the longer it lasts, the more genuine the suffering becomes. Our patience wears thin, our courage dwindles, we become consumed by sadness, and the only way to end our suffering is by removing its cause or experiencing another event, which is the only remedy for all suffering, but which, due to our natural foolishness, we often view with even greater fear and distress."

But not to insist upon these topics, continued PHILO, though most obvious, certain, and important; I must use the freedom to admonish you, CLEANTHES, that you have put the controversy upon a most dangerous issue, and are unawares introducing a total scepticism into the most essential articles of natural and revealed theology. What! no method of fixing a just foundation for religion, unless we allow the happiness of human life, and maintain a continued existence even in this world, with all our present pains, infirmities, vexations, and follies, to be eligible and desirable! But this is contrary to every one's feeling and experience: It is contrary to an authority so established as nothing can subvert. No decisive proofs can ever be produced against this authority; nor is it possible for you to compute, estimate, and compare, all the pains and all the pleasures in the lives of all men and of all animals: And thus, by your resting the whole system of religion on a point, which, from its very nature, must for ever be uncertain, you tacitly confess, that that system is equally uncertain.

But not to dwell on these topics, Philo continued, although they are quite obvious, certain, and important; I have to take the liberty to warn you, Cleanthes, that you’ve placed the debate on a very dangerous issue, and unwittingly introduced total skepticism into the most essential aspects of natural and revealed theology. What? There's no way to establish a solid foundation for religion unless we consider human happiness and accept that a continued existence—even in this world, with all our current pains, weaknesses, frustrations, and foolishness—is desirable? But this goes against everyone's feelings and experiences. It contradicts an authority so well-established that nothing can undermine it. No definitive proof can ever be provided against this authority; nor can you possibly calculate, evaluate, and compare all the pains and pleasures in the lives of all humans and all animals. And so, by anchoring the entire system of religion on something that, by its very nature, must always be uncertain, you are implicitly admitting that the system itself is equally uncertain.

But allowing you what never will be believed, at least what you never possibly can prove, that animal, or at least human happiness, in this life, exceeds its misery, you have yet done nothing: For this is not, by any means, what we expect from infinite power, infinite wisdom, and infinite goodness. Why is there any misery at all in the world? Not by chance surely. From some cause then. Is it from the intention of the Deity? But he is perfectly benevolent. Is it contrary to his intention? But he is almighty. Nothing can shake the solidity of this reasoning, so short, so clear, so decisive; except we assert, that these subjects exceed all human capacity, and that our common measures of truth and falsehood are not applicable to them; a topic which I have all along insisted on, but which you have, from the beginning, rejected with scorn and indignation.

But even if we entertain the idea that animal or human happiness in this life exceeds its misery, which you will never be able to prove, it still doesn’t change anything. This is not what we should expect from infinite power, wisdom, and goodness. Why is there any misery in the world at all? It can’t just be by chance. There has to be a cause. Is it intentional on the part of the Deity? But He is completely benevolent. Is it against His intentions? But He is all-powerful. Nothing can undermine this reasoning—it’s straightforward and decisive—unless we claim that these matters are beyond human understanding, and that our usual standards of truth and falsehood don’t apply here. This is a point I’ve consistently maintained, but you have dismissed it from the start with disdain and outrage.

But I will be contented to retire still from this entrenchment, for I deny that you can ever force me in it. I will allow, that pain or misery in man is compatible with infinite power and goodness in the Deity, even in your sense of these attributes: What are you advanced by all these concessions? A mere possible compatibility is not sufficient. You must prove these pure, unmixed, and uncontrollable attributes from the present mixed and confused phenomena, and from these alone. A hopeful undertaking! Were the phenomena ever so pure and unmixed, yet being finite, they would be insufficient for that purpose. How much more, where they are also so jarring and discordant!

But I will gladly step back from this argument, as I refuse to be cornered by it. I admit that pain or suffering in humans can coexist with limitless power and goodness in God, even in your interpretation of those qualities. What do you gain from all these concessions? Just a potential compatibility isn’t enough. You need to demonstrate these pure, distinct, and uncontrollable attributes based only on the current mixed and confusing realities. That’s an ambitious goal! Even if the phenomena were completely pure and separated, they would still be inadequate for that purpose. How much more so when they are so contradictory and chaotic!

Here, CLEANTHES, I find myself at ease in my argument. Here I triumph. Formerly, when we argued concerning the natural attributes of intelligence and design, I needed all my sceptical and metaphysical subtlety to elude your grasp. In many views of the universe, and of its parts, particularly the latter, the beauty and fitness of final causes strike us with such irresistible force, that all objections appear (what I believe they really are) mere cavils and sophisms; nor can we then imagine how it was ever possible for us to repose any weight on them. But there is no view of human life, or of the condition of mankind, from which, without the greatest violence, we can infer the moral attributes, or learn that infinite benevolence, conjoined with infinite power and infinite wisdom, which we must discover by the eyes of faith alone. It is your turn now to tug the labouring oar, and to support your philosophical subtleties against the dictates of plain reason and experience.

Here, CLEANTHES, I feel confident in my argument. Here I succeed. In the past, when we debated the natural qualities of intelligence and design, I had to use all my skepticism and philosophical cleverness to slip away from your grasp. In many perspectives of the universe, especially regarding its parts, the beauty and purpose of final causes hit us with such undeniable force that all objections seem (as I truly believe they are) mere nitpicking and fallacies; we can hardly imagine how we ever put any weight on them. However, there is no perspective on human life or the state of humanity from which we can, without significant force, infer moral qualities or learn about the infinite kindness that goes hand in hand with infinite power and infinite wisdom, which we can only discern through faith. Now it’s your turn to paddle the heavy oar and defend your philosophical subtleties against the demands of straightforward reason and experience.




PART 11

I scruple not to allow, said CLEANTHES, that I have been apt to suspect the frequent repetition of the word infinite, which we meet with in all theological writers, to savour more of panegyric than of philosophy; and that any purposes of reasoning, and even of religion, would be better served, were we to rest contented with more accurate and more moderate expressions. The terms, admirable, excellent, superlatively great, wise, and holy; these sufficiently fill the imaginations of men; and any thing beyond, besides that it leads into absurdities, has no influence on the affections or sentiments. Thus, in the present subject, if we abandon all human analogy, as seems your intention, DEMEA, I am afraid we abandon all religion, and retain no conception of the great object of our adoration. If we preserve human analogy, we must for ever find it impossible to reconcile any mixture of evil in the universe with infinite attributes; much less can we ever prove the latter from the former. But supposing the Author of Nature to be finitely perfect, though far exceeding mankind, a satisfactory account may then be given of natural and moral evil, and every untoward phenomenon be explained and adjusted. A less evil may then be chosen, in order to avoid a greater; inconveniences be submitted to, in order to reach a desirable end; and in a word, benevolence, regulated by wisdom, and limited by necessity, may produce just such a world as the present. You, PHILO, who are so prompt at starting views, and reflections, and analogies, I would gladly hear, at length, without interruption, your opinion of this new theory; and if it deserve our attention, we may afterwards, at more leisure, reduce it into form.

“I don’t hesitate to say,” said CLEANTHES, “that I often suspect the repeated use of the word ‘infinite’ found in all theological writings leans more towards praise than actual philosophy; and that our reasoning—and even our religious pursuits—would be better served if we were satisfied with more precise and moderate terms. Words like admirable, excellent, supremely great, wise, and holy; these are enough to capture people's imaginations, and anything beyond that not only leads to absurdities but also has no real effect on our feelings or sentiments. So, in this matter, if we disregard all human analogy, as you seem to intend, DEMEA, I fear we will lose all connection to religion and any understanding of the great being we worship. If we keep human analogy, we will always struggle to reconcile any presence of evil in the universe with infinite attributes; let alone prove the latter through the former. However, if we consider the Creator of Nature to be finitely perfect, even if far superior to humanity, we could then offer a satisfactory explanation for natural and moral evil, and understand every unfortunate phenomenon. In that case, a lesser evil might be chosen to avoid a greater one; inconveniences could be tolerated to achieve a desirable end; and in short, benevolence, guided by wisdom and constrained by necessity, could create a world just like this one. You, PHILO, who are so eager to share your views, reflections, and analogies, I would love to hear your opinion on this new theory without interruption; if it merits our attention, we can properly formulate it later.”

My sentiments, replied PHILO, are not worth being made a mystery of; and therefore, without any ceremony, I shall deliver what occurs to me with regard to the present subject. It must, I think, be allowed, that if a very limited intelligence, whom we shall suppose utterly unacquainted with the universe, were assured, that it were the production of a very good, wise, and powerful Being, however finite, he would, from his conjectures, form beforehand a different notion of it from what we find it to be by experience; nor would he ever imagine, merely from these attributes of the cause, of which he is informed, that the effect could be so full of vice and misery and disorder, as it appears in this life. Supposing now, that this person were brought into the world, still assured that it was the workmanship of such a sublime and benevolent Being; he might, perhaps, be surprised at the disappointment; but would never retract his former belief, if founded on any very solid argument; since such a limited intelligence must be sensible of his own blindness and ignorance, and must allow, that there may be many solutions of those phenomena, which will for ever escape his comprehension. But supposing, which is the real case with regard to man, that this creature is not antecedently convinced of a supreme intelligence, benevolent, and powerful, but is left to gather such a belief from the appearances of things; this entirely alters the case, nor will he ever find any reason for such a conclusion. He may be fully convinced of the narrow limits of his understanding; but this will not help him in forming an inference concerning the goodness of superior powers, since he must form that inference from what he knows, not from what he is ignorant of. The more you exaggerate his weakness and ignorance, the more diffident you render him, and give him the greater suspicion that such subjects are beyond the reach of his faculties. You are obliged, therefore, to reason with him merely from the known phenomena, and to drop every arbitrary supposition or conjecture.

"My feelings," PHILO replied, "aren't something to keep a secret; so without any formalities, I'll share what I think about the topic at hand. It seems reasonable to say that if a very limited intelligence—let's say someone totally unaware of the universe—were told that it was created by a good, wise, and powerful Being, even if that Being is finite, they would form a different idea of the world compared to what we actually experience. They would never guess, based solely on those attributes of the cause they were informed about, that the effects would be filled with vice, suffering, and chaos, as we see in this life. Now, if this individual were brought into the world, still believing it was the creation of such a magnificent and kind Being, they might be surprised by the disappointment, but they wouldn't change their earlier belief if it was based on solid reasoning. Such a limited intelligence would recognize their own blindness and ignorance, acknowledging that there could be many explanations for those phenomena that will forever be beyond their understanding. However, if we consider that this individual doesn’t already believe in a supreme, benevolent, and powerful intelligence and must instead infer such a belief from the appearances of things, then the situation completely changes. They likely won’t find any reason to reach that conclusion. They may be fully aware of their limited understanding, but that won't help them make a judgment about the goodness of higher powers since they must base such judgments on what they know, not what they don’t understand. The more you highlight their weaknesses and ignorance, the more hesitant they will become, leading them to suspect that these topics are beyond their grasp. Therefore, you must reason with them solely based on observable phenomena and set aside any arbitrary assumptions or speculations."

Did I show you a house or palace, where there was not one apartment convenient or agreeable; where the windows, doors, fires, passages, stairs, and the whole economy of the building, were the source of noise, confusion, fatigue, darkness, and the extremes of heat and cold; you would certainly blame the contrivance, without any further examination. The architect would in vain display his subtlety, and prove to you, that if this door or that window were altered, greater ills would ensue. What he says may be strictly true: The alteration of one particular, while the other parts of the building remain, may only augment the inconveniences. But still you would assert in general, that, if the architect had had skill and good intentions, he might have formed such a plan of the whole, and might have adjusted the parts in such a manner, as would have remedied all or most of these inconveniences. His ignorance, or even your own ignorance of such a plan, will never convince you of the impossibility of it. If you find any inconveniences and deformities in the building, you will always, without entering into any detail, condemn the architect.

If I showed you a house or a palace where not a single room was comfortable or pleasant; where the windows, doors, fireplaces, hallways, stairs, and the overall layout created noise, confusion, exhaustion, darkness, and extreme temperatures; you would definitely criticize the design without further investigation. The architect might try to convince you that if this door or that window were changed, things would get worse. What he says might actually be true: changing one part while leaving the rest intact could indeed make things less convenient. But still, you would generally argue that if the architect had skill and good intentions, he could have designed the entire building better and adjusted the parts in such a way as to fix most of these issues. His lack of knowledge, or even your own, wouldn't convince you that it was impossible to create a better plan. If you notice any flaws or inconveniences in the building, you will always, without going into specifics, blame the architect.

In short, I repeat the question: Is the world, considered in general, and as it appears to us in this life, different from what a man, or such a limited being, would, beforehand, expect from a very powerful, wise, and benevolent Deity? It must be strange prejudice to assert the contrary. And from thence I conclude, that however consistent the world may be, allowing certain suppositions and conjectures, with the idea of such a Deity, it can never afford us an inference concerning his existence. The consistence is not absolutely denied, only the inference. Conjectures, especially where infinity is excluded from the Divine attributes, may perhaps be sufficient to prove a consistence, but can never be foundations for any inference.

In short, I’ll ask the question again: Is the world, in general, and as we experience it in this life, different from what a person, or such a limited being, would expect from a very powerful, wise, and benevolent God? It must be a strange bias to argue otherwise. From this, I conclude that, no matter how consistent the world may seem—given certain assumptions and guesses—with the idea of such a God, it can never provide proof of His existence. The consistency isn’t completely denied, just the proof. Guesses, especially if we exclude infinity from the Divine attributes, may be enough to show consistency, but they can never be the basis for any proof.

There seem to be four circumstances, on which depend all, or the greatest part of the ills, that molest sensible creatures; and it is not impossible but all these circumstances may be necessary and unavoidable. We know so little beyond common life, or even of common life, that, with regard to the economy of a universe, there is no conjecture, however wild, which may not be just; nor any one, however plausible, which may not be erroneous. All that belongs to human understanding, in this deep ignorance and obscurity, is to be sceptical, or at least cautious, and not to admit of any hypothesis whatever, much less of any which is supported by no appearance of probability. Now, this I assert to be the case with regard to all the causes of evil, and the circumstances on which it depends. None of them appear to human reason in the least degree necessary or unavoidable; nor can we suppose them such, without the utmost license of imagination.

There seem to be four situations that cause most of the problems that trouble sensitive beings; and it’s not impossible that all these situations are necessary and unavoidable. We understand so little beyond everyday life, or even about ordinary life, that when it comes to the workings of the universe, there’s no speculation, no matter how outlandish, that couldn’t be true; and no idea, no matter how reasonable, that couldn’t be wrong. All we can do, given this deep ignorance and uncertainty, is to be skeptical, or at least careful, and not to accept any theory whatsoever, especially those that lack any evidence of being likely. I believe this is true for all the causes of suffering and the circumstances that lead to it. None of them seem necessary or unavoidable to human reason; nor can we assume they are without stretching our imagination to its limits.

The first circumstance which introduces evil, is that contrivance or economy of the animal creation, by which pains, as well as pleasures, are employed to excite all creatures to action, and make them vigilant in the great work of self-preservation. Now pleasure alone, in its various degrees, seems to human understanding sufficient for this purpose. All animals might be constantly in a state of enjoyment: but when urged by any of the necessities of nature, such as thirst, hunger, weariness; instead of pain, they might feel a diminution of pleasure, by which they might be prompted to seek that object which is necessary to their subsistence. Men pursue pleasure as eagerly as they avoid pain; at least they might have been so constituted. It seems, therefore, plainly possible to carry on the business of life without any pain. Why then is any animal ever rendered susceptible of such a sensation? If animals can be free from it an hour, they might enjoy a perpetual exemption from it; and it required as particular a contrivance of their organs to produce that feeling, as to endow them with sight, hearing, or any of the senses. Shall we conjecture, that such a contrivance was necessary, without any appearance of reason? and shall we build on that conjecture as on the most certain truth?

The first situation that introduces evil is the design of the animal world, where both pain and pleasure are used to motivate all creatures to act and remain alert in the crucial task of self-preservation. Pleasure alone, in its many forms, seems adequate for this purpose according to human understanding. All animals could be in a constant state of enjoyment; however, when driven by basic needs like thirst, hunger, or tiredness, rather than feeling pain, they could experience a reduction in pleasure, prompting them to seek what they need to survive. Humans chase pleasure just as intensely as they avoid pain; at least they could have been designed that way. Therefore, it seems quite possible to navigate life without any pain. So why is any animal ever able to feel such a sensation? If animals can be free from it for even an hour, they could enjoy a permanent exemption from it; and it would take just as particular a design of their organs to create that feeling as it does to give them sight, hearing, or any other senses. Should we assume that such a design was necessary without any reasonable evidence? And should we base our beliefs on that assumption as if it were the most certain truth?

But a capacity of pain would not alone produce pain, were it not for the second circumstance, viz. the conducting of the world by general laws; and this seems nowise necessary to a very perfect Being. It is true, if everything were conducted by particular volitions, the course of nature would be perpetually broken, and no man could employ his reason in the conduct of life. But might not other particular volitions remedy this inconvenience? In short, might not the Deity exterminate all ill, wherever it were to be found; and produce all good, without any preparation, or long progress of causes and effects?

But just having the ability to feel pain wouldn't cause pain on its own without the second factor, which is that the world operates according to general laws. This doesn’t seem necessary for a very perfect Being. It's true that if everything were managed by specific choices, the natural order would be constantly interrupted, and people wouldn't be able to use their reasoning in their daily lives. But couldn't other specific choices fix this problem? In short, couldn’t the Deity eliminate all evil wherever it exists and create all good without any preparation or the lengthy chain of causes and effects?

Besides, we must consider, that, according to the present economy of the world, the course of nature, though supposed exactly regular, yet to us appears not so, and many events are uncertain, and many disappoint our expectations. Health and sickness, calm and tempest, with an infinite number of other accidents, whose causes are unknown and variable, have a great influence both on the fortunes of particular persons and on the prosperity of public societies; and indeed all human life, in a manner, depends on such accidents. A being, therefore, who knows the secret springs of the universe, might easily, by particular volitions, turn all these accidents to the good of mankind, and render the whole world happy, without discovering himself in any operation. A fleet, whose purposes were salutary to society, might always meet with a fair wind. Good princes enjoy sound health and long life. Persons born to power and authority, be framed with good tempers and virtuous dispositions. A few such events as these, regularly and wisely conducted, would change the face of the world; and yet would no more seem to disturb the course of nature, or confound human conduct, than the present economy of things, where the causes are secret, and variable, and compounded. Some small touches given to CALIGULA's brain in his infancy, might have converted him into a TRAJAN. One wave, a little higher than the rest, by burying CAESAR and his fortune in the bottom of the ocean, might have restored liberty to a considerable part of mankind. There may, for aught we know, be good reasons why Providence interposes not in this manner; but they are unknown to us; and though the mere supposition, that such reasons exist, may be sufficient to save the conclusion concerning the Divine attributes, yet surely it can never be sufficient to establish that conclusion.

Besides, we have to consider that, according to today's world economy, the way things work in nature, although thought to be perfectly regular, doesn't always seem that way to us. Many events are uncertain, and many end up disappointing our expectations. Health and illness, calm and storm, along with countless other incidents whose causes are unknown and unpredictable, greatly affect not just individual fortunes but also the well-being of societies as a whole. In fact, nearly all human life relies on such occurrences. Thus, a being who understands the hidden workings of the universe could easily manipulate these events for the benefit of humanity and make the entire world happy, all without revealing themselves in any action. A fleet with good intentions for society could always have a favorable wind. Wise rulers would enjoy good health and long lives. People destined for power and authority would have good tempers and virtuous natures. Just a few well-managed such occurrences could transform the world, and yet they wouldn't seem to disrupt the natural order or confuse human actions any more than the current state of affairs, where causes are hidden, variable, and mixed. A small adjustment to CALIGULA's mind in his early years could have turned him into a TRAJAN. One slightly larger wave could have dragged CAESAR and his fate to the ocean's depths, potentially restoring freedom to many. There may well be valid reasons for why Providence doesn’t intervene in this way, but those reasons remain unknown to us. Although the simple idea that such reasons exist might be enough to support beliefs about the Divine attributes, it certainly can't be enough to firmly establish those beliefs.

If every thing in the universe be conducted by general laws, and if animals be rendered susceptible of pain, it scarcely seems possible but some ill must arise in the various shocks of matter, and the various concurrence and opposition of general laws; but this ill would be very rare, were it not for the third circumstance, which I proposed to mention, viz. the great frugality with which all powers and faculties are distributed to every particular being. So well adjusted are the organs and capacities of all animals, and so well fitted to their preservation, that, as far as history or tradition reaches, there appears not to be any single species which has yet been extinguished in the universe. Every animal has the requisite endowments; but these endowments are bestowed with so scrupulous an economy, that any considerable diminution must entirely destroy the creature. Wherever one power is increased, there is a proportional abatement in the others. Animals which excel in swiftness are commonly defective in force. Those which possess both are either imperfect in some of their senses, or are oppressed with the most craving wants. The human species, whose chief excellency is reason and sagacity, is of all others the most necessitous, and the most deficient in bodily advantages; without clothes, without arms, without food, without lodging, without any convenience of life, except what they owe to their own skill and industry. In short, nature seems to have formed an exact calculation of the necessities of her creatures; and, like a rigid master, has afforded them little more powers or endowments than what are strictly sufficient to supply those necessities. An indulgent parent would have bestowed a large stock, in order to guard against accidents, and secure the happiness and welfare of the creature in the most unfortunate concurrence of circumstances. Every course of life would not have been so surrounded with precipices, that the least departure from the true path, by mistake or necessity, must involve us in misery and ruin. Some reserve, some fund, would have been provided to ensure happiness; nor would the powers and the necessities have been adjusted with so rigid an economy. The Author of Nature is inconceivably powerful: his force is supposed great, if not altogether inexhaustible: nor is there any reason, as far as we can judge, to make him observe this strict frugality in his dealings with his creatures. It would have been better, were his power extremely limited, to have created fewer animals, and to have endowed these with more faculties for their happiness and preservation. A builder is never esteemed prudent, who undertakes a plan beyond what his stock will enable him to finish.

If everything in the universe is governed by general laws, and if animals can feel pain, it seems almost inevitable that some harm must occur through various interactions of matter and the conflicting nature of these laws. However, this harm would be quite rare if it weren't for a third factor that I want to mention: the great frugality with which all powers and abilities are distributed among individual beings. The organs and capacities of all animals are so well calibrated and suited to their survival that, as far as history or tradition indicates, there's no known species that has gone extinct. Every animal has the necessary attributes, but these attributes are bestowed with such careful economy that any significant reduction could completely eliminate the creature. Wherever one ability is enhanced, there is a corresponding decrease in others. Animals that are fast often lack strength. Those that possess both tend to have deficiencies in some senses or face overwhelming needs. The human species, whose main strength is reason and intelligence, is the most needy and least physically endowed of all. They lack clothing, weapons, food, shelter, and any comforts of life except what they create through their skill and hard work. In summary, nature seems to have calculated the needs of her creatures precisely; like a strict master, she has given them just enough powers and abilities to meet those needs. A nurturing parent would have provided a larger stock to safeguard against accidents and ensure happiness and well-being amid unfortunate circumstances. Life wouldn't be so fraught with dangers that even a small deviation from the correct path, whether by mistake or necessity, could lead us to suffering and destruction. There would be some form of reserve or safety net to guarantee happiness, and the balance between powers and needs wouldn't be so harshly managed. The Creator of Nature is unimaginably powerful: His strength is believed to be vast, if not limitless. There seems to be no reason, based on what we can observe, for Him to maintain such strict frugality in His dealings with His creatures. It would make more sense, if His power were severely limited, for Him to create fewer animals and give them more abilities for their happiness and survival. A builder is not considered wise if he takes on a project that exceeds what his resources can support.

In order to cure most of the ills of human life, I require not that man should have the wings of the eagle, the swiftness of the stag, the force of the ox, the arms of the lion, the scales of the crocodile or rhinoceros; much less do I demand the sagacity of an angel or cherubim. I am contented to take an increase in one single power or faculty of his soul. Let him be endowed with a greater propensity to industry and labour; a more vigorous spring and activity of mind; a more constant bent to business and application. Let the whole species possess naturally an equal diligence with that which many individuals are able to attain by habit and reflection; and the most beneficial consequences, without any allay of ill, is the immediate and necessary result of this endowment. Almost all the moral, as well as natural evils of human life, arise from idleness; and were our species, by the original constitution of their frame, exempt from this vice or infirmity, the perfect cultivation of land, the improvement of arts and manufactures, the exact execution of every office and duty, immediately follow; and men at once may fully reach that state of society, which is so imperfectly attained by the best regulated government. But as industry is a power, and the most valuable of any, Nature seems determined, suitably to her usual maxims, to bestow it on men with a very sparing hand; and rather to punish him severely for his deficiency in it, than to reward him for his attainments. She has so contrived his frame, that nothing but the most violent necessity can oblige him to labour; and she employs all his other wants to overcome, at least in part, the want of diligence, and to endow him with some share of a faculty of which she has thought fit naturally to bereave him. Here our demands may be allowed very humble, and therefore the more reasonable. If we required the endowments of superior penetration and judgement, of a more delicate taste of beauty, of a nicer sensibility to benevolence and friendship; we might be told, that we impiously pretend to break the order of Nature; that we want to exalt ourselves into a higher rank of being; that the presents which we require, not being suitable to our state and condition, would only be pernicious to us. But it is hard; I dare to repeat it, it is hard, that being placed in a world so full of wants and necessities, where almost every being and element is either our foe or refuses its assistance ... we should also have our own temper to struggle with, and should be deprived of that faculty which can alone fence against these multiplied evils.

To address most of the problems in human life, I don't need man to have the wings of an eagle, the speed of a stag, the strength of an ox, the might of a lion, or the armor of a crocodile or rhinoceros; I definitely don’t expect him to possess the wisdom of an angel or cherub. I’m simply looking for an increase in just one aspect of his soul. If he can have a greater inclination towards work and effort, a more energetic and active mind, and a stronger commitment to tasks and diligence, that would be enough. If the entire human race naturally had the same work ethic that many individuals develop through habit and thought, the positive outcomes, without any drawbacks, would be the immediate and inevitable result of this ability. Almost all the moral and natural troubles in human life come from idleness; if we were originally designed without this flaw, we could fully cultivate the land, enhance arts and industries, and execute every task and responsibility perfectly, allowing humanity to reach a social state that is currently only poorly achieved by the best-run governments. But since work is a powerful asset, and perhaps the most valuable one, Nature seems to be quite stingy with it, opting instead to punish humans for lacking it rather than to reward them for succeeding in it. She has designed him in such a way that only the most extreme necessity can force him to work; she uses all of his other needs to compensate, at least somewhat, for the lack of diligence, only partially granting him a skill she chose to deny him by nature. Our demands here are very modest, making them more reasonable. If we asked for gifts of greater insight and judgment, a finer appreciation of beauty, or a keener sensitivity to kindness and friendship, we might be told that we’re trying to disrupt the natural order; that we aim to elevate ourselves to a higher level of existence; that what we’re asking for, not being suited to our current state, would only bring us harm. But it’s frustrating; I must say it again, it’s frustrating that in a world so full of needs and demands, where nearly every being and element is either our enemy or unwilling to assist us... we also have to contend with our own nature and miss out on the ability that could help shield us from these many hardships.

The fourth circumstance, whence arises the misery and ill of the universe, is the inaccurate workmanship of all the springs and principles of the great machine of nature. It must be acknowledged, that there are few parts of the universe, which seem not to serve some purpose, and whose removal would not produce a visible defect and disorder in the whole. The parts hang all together; nor can one be touched without affecting the rest, in a greater or less degree. But at the same time, it must be observed, that none of these parts or principles, however useful, are so accurately adjusted, as to keep precisely within those bounds in which their utility consists; but they are, all of them, apt, on every occasion, to run into the one extreme or the other. One would imagine, that this grand production had not received the last hand of the maker; so little finished is every part, and so coarse are the strokes with which it is executed. Thus, the winds are requisite to convey the vapours along the surface of the globe, and to assist men in navigation: but how oft, rising up to tempests and hurricanes, do they become pernicious? Rains are necessary to nourish all the plants and animals of the earth: but how often are they defective? how often excessive? Heat is requisite to all life and vegetation; but is not always found in the due proportion. On the mixture and secretion of the humours and juices of the body depend the health and prosperity of the animal: but the parts perform not regularly their proper function. What more useful than all the passions of the mind, ambition, vanity, love, anger? But how oft do they break their bounds, and cause the greatest convulsions in society? There is nothing so advantageous in the universe, but what frequently becomes pernicious, by its excess or defect; nor has Nature guarded, with the requisite accuracy, against all disorder or confusion. The irregularity is never perhaps so great as to destroy any species; but is often sufficient to involve the individuals in ruin and misery.

The fourth reason for the suffering and problems in the universe is the imperfect design of all the parts and principles of the great machine of nature. It's clear that few aspects of the universe seem useless, and taking any of them away would create a noticeable flaw and chaos. Everything is interconnected; changing one part will impact the rest, to varying degrees. However, it's also important to note that none of these parts or principles, no matter how beneficial, are precisely balanced to stay within the limits of their usefulness. Instead, they tend to swing to one extreme or another at any moment. One might think that this magnificent creation hasn’t gotten the final touches from its maker; every part feels unfinished, and the craftsmanship seems rough. For instance, the winds are necessary to move vapor across the globe and help with sailing, but how often do they escalate into storms and hurricanes, causing harm? Rain is essential for nurturing all plants and animals on earth, but how often is it too little? How often is it too much? Heat is crucial for all life and growth, but it's not always present in the right amounts. The mixing and production of the body's fluids and juices are vital for health and well-being, yet the parts don't always perform their intended functions properly. What could be more valuable than all the mind's emotions—ambition, vanity, love, anger? Yet how often do they exceed their limits and lead to chaos in society? There’s nothing in the universe that doesn’t sometimes turn harmful due to its excess or deficiency; nature hasn’t always managed to prevent all disorder or confusion with the necessary precision. The irregularities may not be severe enough to wipe out an entire species, but they're often enough to bring individuals to ruin and suffering.

On the concurrence, then, of these four circumstances, does all or the greatest part of natural evil depend. Were all living creatures incapable of pain, or were the world administered by particular volitions, evil never could have found access into the universe: and were animals endowed with a large stock of powers and faculties, beyond what strict necessity requires; or were the several springs and principles of the universe so accurately framed as to preserve always the just temperament and medium; there must have been very little ill in comparison of what we feel at present. What then shall we pronounce on this occasion? Shall we say that these circumstances are not necessary, and that they might easily have been altered in the contrivance of the universe? This decision seems too presumptuous for creatures so blind and ignorant. Let us be more modest in our conclusions. Let us allow, that, if the goodness of the Deity (I mean a goodness like the human) could be established on any tolerable reasons a priori, these phenomena, however untoward, would not be sufficient to subvert that principle; but might easily, in some unknown manner, be reconcilable to it. But let us still assert, that as this goodness is not antecedently established, but must be inferred from the phenomena, there can be no grounds for such an inference, while there are so many ills in the universe, and while these ills might so easily have been remedied, as far as human understanding can be allowed to judge on such a subject. I am Sceptic enough to allow, that the bad appearances, notwithstanding all my reasonings, may be compatible with such attributes as you suppose; but surely they can never prove these attributes. Such a conclusion cannot result from Scepticism, but must arise from the phenomena, and from our confidence in the reasonings which we deduce from these phenomena.

The presence of these four circumstances is what most of the natural evil depends on. If all living beings were unable to feel pain, or if the world operated according to specific intentions, evil would never have entered the universe. And if animals had a greater range of abilities and traits than what is strictly necessary, or if the various forces and principles of the universe were perfectly arranged to maintain balance, there would be very little suffering compared to what we currently experience. So what should we conclude here? Should we argue that these circumstances are unnecessary and could easily have been changed in the universe's design? That conclusion seems too arrogant for beings as limited and ignorant as we are. Let's be more humble in our judgments. We should accept that if the goodness of the Deity (I mean a goodness like that of humans) could be established through any reasonable a priori arguments, then these troubling phenomena wouldn't be enough to contradict that principle; they might easily be reconciled with it in some unknown way. However, we should still maintain that since this goodness is not already established and must be inferred from the phenomena, there are no grounds for such an inference while facing so much suffering in the universe, especially when these sufferings could seemingly have been fixed, as far as human understanding permits us to judge. I am skeptical enough to acknowledge that the evident suffering, despite all my reasoning, might be compatible with the attributes you suggest; but surely, they can never prove these attributes. Such a conclusion cannot stem from skepticism but must arise from the phenomena themselves and our confidence in the reasoning we draw from them.

Look round this universe. What an immense profusion of beings, animated and organised, sensible and active! You admire this prodigious variety and fecundity. But inspect a little more narrowly these living existences, the only beings worth regarding. How hostile and destructive to each other! How insufficient all of them for their own happiness! How contemptible or odious to the spectator! The whole presents nothing but the idea of a blind Nature, impregnated by a great vivifying principle, and pouring forth from her lap, without discernment or parental care, her maimed and abortive children!

Look around this universe. What an incredible abundance of beings, alive and organized, aware and active! You admire this amazing variety and fertility. But take a closer look at these living entities, the only ones that truly matter. How hostile and destructive they are to one another! How inadequate they are for their own happiness! How contemptible or repulsive they can seem to an observer! The whole scene reflects nothing but the idea of a blind Nature, filled with a powerful life force, carelessly producing her flawed and failed offspring!

Here the MANICHAEAN system occurs as a proper hypothesis to solve the difficulty: and no doubt, in some respects, it is very specious, and has more probability than the common hypothesis, by giving a plausible account of the strange mixture of good and ill which appears in life. But if we consider, on the other hand, the perfect uniformity and agreement of the parts of the universe, we shall not discover in it any marks of the combat of a malevolent with a benevolent being. There is indeed an opposition of pains and pleasures in the feelings of sensible creatures: but are not all the operations of Nature carried on by an opposition of principles, of hot and cold, moist and dry, light and heavy? The true conclusion is, that the original Source of all things is entirely indifferent to all these principles; and has no more regard to good above ill, than to heat above cold, or to drought above moisture, or to light above heavy.

Here, the MANICHAEAN system presents a valid theory to address the issue: and it certainly seems appealing in some ways, having more credibility than the usual theory by offering a convincing explanation for the odd mix of good and bad in life. However, if we examine the perfect consistency and harmony of the universe's components, we won’t find any signs of a struggle between a malicious being and a benevolent one. There is indeed a contrast between pain and pleasure in the experiences of conscious beings: but aren’t all processes in Nature driven by opposing forces, such as hot and cold, wet and dry, light and heavy? The real conclusion is that the original Source of everything is completely neutral to all these forces; it has no more preference for good over evil than for heat over cold, dryness over wetness, or light over heaviness.

There may four hypotheses be framed concerning the first causes of the universe: that they are endowed with perfect goodness; that they have perfect malice; that they are opposite, and have both goodness and malice; that they have neither goodness nor malice. Mixed phenomena can never prove the two former unmixed principles; and the uniformity and steadiness of general laws seem to oppose the third. The fourth, therefore, seems by far the most probable.

There are four possible hypotheses about the first causes of the universe: that they possess perfect goodness; that they have perfect malice; that they are opposites, having both goodness and malice; and that they have neither goodness nor malice. Mixed phenomena can never prove the first two unmixed principles, and the consistency and reliability of general laws seem to contradict the third. Therefore, the fourth hypothesis appears to be the most probable.

What I have said concerning natural evil will apply to moral, with little or no variation; and we have no more reason to infer, that the rectitude of the Supreme Being resembles human rectitude, than that his benevolence resembles the human. Nay, it will be thought, that we have still greater cause to exclude from him moral sentiments, such as we feel them; since moral evil, in the opinion of many, is much more predominant above moral good than natural evil above natural good.

What I've said about natural evil also applies to moral evil, with little or no change; and we have no more reason to assume that the righteousness of the Supreme Being is like human righteousness than that His kindness is like ours. In fact, it could be argued that we have even more reason to think that He lacks moral feelings similar to ours, since many believe that moral evil is much more prevalent than moral good, just as natural evil is more common than natural good.

But even though this should not be allowed, and though the virtue which is in mankind should be acknowledged much superior to the vice, yet so long as there is any vice at all in the universe, it will very much puzzle you Anthropomorphites, how to account for it. You must assign a cause for it, without having recourse to the first cause. But as every effect must have a cause, and that cause another, you must either carry on the progression in infinitum, or rest on that original principle, who is the ultimate cause of all things...

But even though this shouldn't happen, and although the goodness in humanity should be recognized as far greater than the bad, as long as there is any wrongdoing in the universe at all, you Anthropomorphites will struggle to explain it. You need to find a reason for it without referring to the first cause. But since every effect must have a cause, and that cause another, you must either continue this chain infinitely or rely on that original principle, who is the ultimate cause of everything...

Hold! hold! cried DEMEA: Whither does your imagination hurry you? I joined in alliance with you, in order to prove the incomprehensible nature of the Divine Being, and refute the principles of CLEANTHES, who would measure every thing by human rule and standard. But I now find you running into all the topics of the greatest libertines and infidels, and betraying that holy cause which you seemingly espoused. Are you secretly, then, a more dangerous enemy than CLEANTHES himself?

Hold on! Hold on! cried DEMEA: Where is your imagination rushing off to? I teamed up with you to demonstrate the incomprehensible nature of the Divine Being and to refute CLEANTHES’ ideas, who wants to measure everything by human standards. But now I see you diving into all the topics of the most outrageous libertines and skeptics, betraying the holy cause you once seemed to support. Are you secretly a more dangerous enemy than CLEANTHES himself?

And are you so late in perceiving it? replied CLEANTHES. Believe me, DEMEA, your friend PHILO, from the beginning, has been amusing himself at both our expense; and it must be confessed, that the injudicious reasoning of our vulgar theology has given him but too just a handle of ridicule. The total infirmity of human reason, the absolute incomprehensibility of the Divine Nature, the great and universal misery, and still greater wickedness of men; these are strange topics, surely, to be so fondly cherished by orthodox divines and doctors. In ages of stupidity and ignorance, indeed, these principles may safely be espoused; and perhaps no views of things are more proper to promote superstition, than such as encourage the blind amazement, the diffidence, and melancholy of mankind. But at present...

And are you really just now figuring this out? replied CLEANTHES. Honestly, DEMEA, your friend PHILO has been playing us both for fools all along; and it has to be said, that the misguided reasoning of our common theology has given him plenty of material to mock. The complete weakness of human reason, the total mystery of the Divine Nature, the widespread suffering, and even greater evil among people; these are certainly odd subjects to be so passionately upheld by orthodox theologians and scholars. In times of ignorance and dullness, these ideas might be accepted without hesitation; and maybe there's nothing better to fuel superstition than viewpoints that encourage the blind wonder, uncertainty, and despair of humanity. But right now...

Blame not so much, interposed PHILO, the ignorance of these reverend gentlemen. They know how to change their style with the times. Formerly it was a most popular theological topic to maintain, that human life was vanity and misery, and to exaggerate all the ills and pains which are incident to men. But of late years, divines, we find, begin to retract this position; and maintain, though still with some hesitation, that there are more goods than evils, more pleasures than pains, even in this life. When religion stood entirely upon temper and education, it was thought proper to encourage melancholy; as indeed mankind never have recourse to superior powers so readily as in that disposition. But as men have now learned to form principles, and to draw consequences, it is necessary to change the batteries, and to make use of such arguments as will endure at least some scrutiny and examination. This variation is the same (and from the same causes) with that which I formerly remarked with regard to Scepticism.

"Don't place too much blame," PHILO interjected, "on the ignorance of these respected gentlemen. They're capable of adapting their views to the times. In the past, it was a widely accepted theological belief that human life was filled with vanity and suffering, and they tended to emphasize all the hardships and pains that people experience. However, in recent years, we see that theologians are starting to backtrack on this idea, and they argue—though still with some reluctance—that there are more good things than bad, more pleasure than pain, even in this life. When religion relied solely on mood and education, it was deemed appropriate to promote a sense of melancholy; after all, people tend to turn to higher powers most readily when they're feeling down. But now that individuals have learned to establish principles and draw conclusions, it's essential to shift tactics and utilize arguments that can withstand at least some level of scrutiny and examination. This change is similar (and due to the same reasons) as what I noted earlier regarding Scepticism."

Thus PHILO continued to the last his spirit of opposition, and his censure of established opinions. But I could observe that DEMEA did not at all relish the latter part of the discourse; and he took occasion soon after, on some pretence or other, to leave the company.

Thus PHILO continued to the end with his spirit of opposition and criticism of established opinions. But I noticed that DEMEA did not appreciate the latter part of the conversation at all; and he soon found some excuse to leave the group.




PART 12

After DEMEA's departure, CLEANTHES and PHILO continued the conversation in the following manner. Our friend, I am afraid, said CLEANTHES, will have little inclination to revive this topic of discourse, while you are in company; and to tell truth, PHILO, I should rather wish to reason with either of you apart on a subject so sublime and interesting. Your spirit of controversy, joined to your abhorrence of vulgar superstition, carries you strange lengths, when engaged in an argument; and there is nothing so sacred and venerable, even in your own eyes, which you spare on that occasion.

After DEMEA left, CLEANTHES and PHILO continued their conversation like this. My friend, I’m afraid, said CLEANTHES, won’t be very eager to bring up this topic while you’re around; and to be honest, PHILO, I’d much prefer to discuss such a profound and fascinating subject with either of you one-on-one. Your argumentative spirit, combined with your disdain for common superstitions, takes you to some extreme places when you're debating; there’s nothing so sacred and respected, even in your own view, that you hesitate to challenge it then.

I must confess, replied PHILO, that I am less cautious on the subject of Natural Religion than on any other; both because I know that I can never, on that head, corrupt the principles of any man of common sense; and because no one, I am confident, in whose eyes I appear a man of common sense, will ever mistake my intentions. You, in particular, CLEANTHES, with whom I live in unreserved intimacy; you are sensible, that notwithstanding the freedom of my conversation, and my love of singular arguments, no one has a deeper sense of religion impressed on his mind, or pays more profound adoration to the Divine Being, as he discovers himself to reason, in the inexplicable contrivance and artifice of nature. A purpose, an intention, a design, strikes every where the most careless, the most stupid thinker; and no man can be so hardened in absurd systems, as at all times to reject it. That Nature does nothing in vain, is a maxim established in all the schools, merely from the contemplation of the works of Nature, without any religious purpose; and, from a firm conviction of its truth, an anatomist, who had observed a new organ or canal, would never be satisfied till he had also discovered its use and intention. One great foundation of the Copernican system is the maxim, That Nature acts by the simplest methods, and chooses the most proper means to any end; and astronomers often, without thinking of it, lay this strong foundation of piety and religion. The same thing is observable in other parts of philosophy: And thus all the sciences almost lead us insensibly to acknowledge a first intelligent Author; and their authority is often so much the greater, as they do not directly profess that intention.

“I have to admit,” PHILO replied, “that I’m less careful about the topic of Natural Religion than about anything else; mainly because I know I can’t corrupt the principles of someone with common sense, and I’m sure that no one who sees me as a person of common sense will ever misinterpret my intentions. You, in particular, CLEANTHES, with whom I share such close friendship; you know that despite my open conversation and my love for unconventional arguments, no one has a deeper sense of religion in their mind or offers more profound respect to the Divine Being as I see him revealed through reason, in the mysterious design and complexity of nature. A purpose, an intention, a design is apparent to even the most careless and dull thinker, and no one can be so stuck in ridiculous beliefs that they always dismiss it. The idea that Nature does nothing in vain is a principle recognized in all schools just from observing the works of Nature, without any religious intent; and, from a strong belief in its truth, an anatomist who has discovered a new organ or canal would never rest until he also figured out its function and purpose. One major foundation of the Copernican system is the principle that Nature operates by the simplest methods and chooses the most appropriate means to achieve any goal; and astronomers often unintentionally establish this solid base of piety and faith. The same is true in other areas of philosophy: almost all sciences gradually lead us to acknowledge a first intelligent Author, and their credibility is often much greater because they don’t directly proclaim that intention.”

It is with pleasure I hear GALEN reason concerning the structure of the human body. The anatomy of a man, says he [De formatione foetus], discovers above 600 different muscles; and whoever duly considers these, will find, that, in each of them, Nature must have adjusted at least ten different circumstances, in order to attain the end which she proposed; proper figure, just magnitude, right disposition of the several ends, upper and lower position of the whole, the due insertion of the several nerves, veins, and arteries: So that, in the muscles alone, above 6000 several views and intentions must have been formed and executed. The bones he calculates to be 284: The distinct purposes aimed at in the structure of each, above forty. What a prodigious display of artifice, even in these simple and homogeneous parts! But if we consider the skin, ligaments, vessels, glandules, humours, the several limbs and members of the body; how must our astonishment rise upon us, in proportion to the number and intricacy of the parts so artificially adjusted! The further we advance in these researches, we discover new scenes of art and wisdom: But descry still, at a distance, further scenes beyond our reach; in the fine internal structure of the parts, in the economy of the brain, in the fabric of the seminal vessels. All these artifices are repeated in every different species of animal, with wonderful variety, and with exact propriety, suited to the different intentions of Nature in framing each species. And if the infidelity of GALEN, even when these natural sciences were still imperfect, could not withstand such striking appearances, to what pitch of pertinacious obstinacy must a philosopher in this age have attained, who can now doubt of a Supreme Intelligence!

I am pleased to hear GALEN discuss the structure of the human body. He says that the anatomy of a man reveals over 600 different muscles; anyone who carefully considers these will realize that Nature must have adjusted at least ten different factors for each muscle to achieve its intended purpose: the right shape, appropriate size, correct arrangement of the various ends, upper and lower positioning of the whole structure, and the proper placement of various nerves, veins, and arteries. This means that, in the muscles alone, there must be more than 6000 different designs and intentions that have been developed and executed. He estimates that there are 284 bones, each with more than forty distinct purposes in their structure. What an astonishing display of craftsmanship, even in these simple and uniform parts! But if we also consider the skin, ligaments, vessels, glands, fluids, and the various limbs and body parts, our amazement surely grows with the number and complexity of these intricately arranged components! As we delve deeper into these studies, we uncover more layers of art and wisdom, but we also glimpse even more intricate structures that remain just out of reach, such as the fine internal anatomy, the workings of the brain, and the design of the reproductive vessels. All these designs appear in every species of animal, showcasing a remarkable variety and precise features tailored to Nature's different purposes for each species. If GALEN, despite the limitations of natural sciences in his time, could not deny such compelling evidence, how stubbornly obstinate must a philosopher today be to doubt a Supreme Intelligence!

Could I meet with one of this species (who, I thank God, are very rare), I would ask him: Supposing there were a God, who did not discover himself immediately to our senses, were it possible for him to give stronger proofs of his existence, than what appear on the whole face of Nature? What indeed could such a Divine Being do, but copy the present economy of things; render many of his artifices so plain, that no stupidity could mistake them; afford glimpses of still greater artifices, which demonstrate his prodigious superiority above our narrow apprehensions; and conceal altogether a great many from such imperfect creatures? Now, according to all rules of just reasoning, every fact must pass for undisputed, when it is supported by all the arguments which its nature admits of; even though these arguments be not, in themselves, very numerous or forcible: How much more, in the present case, where no human imagination can compute their number, and no understanding estimate their cogency!

If I could meet someone from this rare group, I would ask him: If there were a God who didn't immediately reveal himself to our senses, could he provide stronger evidence of his existence than what is visible in nature? What could such a divine being do, except mimic the current state of the world; make many of his creations so obvious that no one could misunderstand them; offer glimpses of even greater designs that show his immense superiority over our limited understanding; and keep many things hidden from such imperfect beings? According to all standards of fair reasoning, every fact should be considered indisputable when supported by all possible arguments of its kind; even if those arguments aren't very numerous or convincing on their own: How much more so in this case, where no human mind can count their number, and no understanding can measure their strength!

I shall further add, said CLEANTHES, to what you have so well urged, that one great advantage of the principle of Theism, is, that it is the only system of cosmogony which can be rendered intelligible and complete, and yet can throughout preserve a strong analogy to what we every day see and experience in the world. The comparison of the universe to a machine of human contrivance, is so obvious and natural, and is justified by so many instances of order and design in Nature, that it must immediately strike all unprejudiced apprehensions, and procure universal approbation. Whoever attempts to weaken this theory, cannot pretend to succeed by establishing in its place any other that is precise and determinate: It is sufficient for him if he start doubts and difficulties; and by remote and abstract views of things, reach that suspense of judgement, which is here the utmost boundary of his wishes. But, besides that this state of mind is in itself unsatisfactory, it can never be steadily maintained against such striking appearances as continually engage us into the religious hypothesis. A false, absurd system, human nature, from the force of prejudice, is capable of adhering to with obstinacy and perseverance: But no system at all, in opposition to a theory supported by strong and obvious reason, by natural propensity, and by early education, I think it absolutely impossible to maintain or defend.

"I'll add," said CLEANTHES, "to what you've expressed so well, that one major advantage of Theism is that it's the only cosmogony that can be made understandable and complete while still reflecting what we encounter every day in the world. Comparing the universe to a machine created by humans is so clear and natural, and it's backed by numerous examples of order and design in Nature, that it must quickly catch the attention of anyone open-minded and earn widespread approval. Anyone who tries to undermine this theory can't expect to replace it with another that is clear and definitive. It's enough for them to raise doubts and difficulties, and through distant and abstract views of things, achieve that uncertainty, which is the most they can hope for. However, this state of mind is unsatisfactory in itself, and it can never be consistently maintained against the compelling evidence that continually draws us to the religious perspective. People can stubbornly cling to a false, absurd system due to bias, but I believe it’s entirely impossible to sustain or defend any system that opposes a theory backed by strong, obvious reasoning, natural inclination, and early education."

So little, replied PHILO, do I esteem this suspense of judgement in the present case to be possible, that I am apt to suspect there enters somewhat of a dispute of words into this controversy, more than is usually imagined. That the works of Nature bear a great analogy to the productions of art, is evident; and according to all the rules of good reasoning, we ought to infer, if we argue at all concerning them, that their causes have a proportional analogy. But as there are also considerable differences, we have reason to suppose a proportional difference in the causes; and in particular, ought to attribute a much higher degree of power and energy to the supreme cause, than any we have ever observed in mankind. Here then the existence of a DEITY is plainly ascertained by reason: and if we make it a question, whether, on account of these analogies, we can properly call him a mind or intelligence, notwithstanding the vast difference which may reasonably be supposed between him and human minds; what is this but a mere verbal controversy? No man can deny the analogies between the effects: To restrain ourselves from inquiring concerning the causes is scarcely possible. From this inquiry, the legitimate conclusion is, that the causes have also an analogy: And if we are not contented with calling the first and supreme cause a GOD or DEITY, but desire to vary the expression; what can we call him but MIND or THOUGHT, to which he is justly supposed to bear a considerable resemblance?

"So little," PHILO replied, "do I think this uncertainty about judgment is possible in this case that I suspect there's more of a verbal dispute in this controversy than most people realize. It's clear that the works of Nature are quite similar to the creations of art; and according to the principles of sound reasoning, if we discuss them at all, we should conclude that their causes share a similar relationship. However, since there are also significant differences, we have reason to believe that the causes differ proportionately, and particularly, we should attribute a much higher level of power and energy to the supreme cause than anything we’ve observed in humans. Therefore, the existence of a DEITY is clearly established through reason. If we question whether, due to these similarities, we can accurately refer to him as a mind or intelligence, despite the vast differences we might reasonably assume between him and human minds, isn’t this simply a verbal argument? No one can deny the similarities between the effects: It’s almost impossible for us to refrain from questioning the causes. From this inquiry, the logical conclusion is that the causes also have a similarity: And if we’re not satisfied with calling the first and supreme cause a GOD or DEITY and want to change the wording, what else can we call him but MIND or THOUGHT, to which he is rightly assumed to bear a significant resemblance?"

All men of sound reason are disgusted with verbal disputes, which abound so much in philosophical and theological inquiries; and it is found, that the only remedy for this abuse must arise from clear definitions, from the precision of those ideas which enter into any argument, and from the strict and uniform use of those terms which are employed. But there is a species of controversy, which, from the very nature of language and of human ideas, is involved in perpetual ambiguity, and can never, by any precaution or any definitions, be able to reach a reasonable certainty or precision. These are the controversies concerning the degrees of any quality or circumstance. Men may argue to all eternity, whether HANNIBAL be a great, or a very great, or a superlatively great man, what degree of beauty CLEOPATRA possessed, what epithet of praise LIVY or THUCYDIDES is entitled to, without bringing the controversy to any determination. The disputants may here agree in their sense, and differ in the terms, or vice versa; yet never be able to define their terms, so as to enter into each other's meaning: Because the degrees of these qualities are not, like quantity or number, susceptible of any exact mensuration, which may be the standard in the controversy. That the dispute concerning Theism is of this nature, and consequently is merely verbal, or perhaps, if possible, still more incurably ambiguous, will appear upon the slightest inquiry. I ask the Theist, if he does not allow, that there is a great and immeasurable, because incomprehensible difference between the human and the divine mind: The more pious he is, the more readily will he assent to the affirmative, and the more will he be disposed to magnify the difference: He will even assert, that the difference is of a nature which cannot be too much magnified. I next turn to the Atheist, who, I assert, is only nominally so, and can never possibly be in earnest; and I ask him, whether, from the coherence and apparent sympathy in all the parts of this world, there be not a certain degree of analogy among all the operations of Nature, in every situation and in every age; whether the rotting of a turnip, the generation of an animal, and the structure of human thought, be not energies that probably bear some remote analogy to each other: It is impossible he can deny it: He will readily acknowledge it. Having obtained this concession, I push him still further in his retreat; and I ask him, if it be not probable, that the principle which first arranged, and still maintains order in this universe, bears not also some remote inconceivable analogy to the other operations of nature, and, among the rest, to the economy of human mind and thought. However reluctant, he must give his assent. Where then, cry I to both these antagonists, is the subject of your dispute? The Theist allows, that the original intelligence is very different from human reason: The Atheist allows, that the original principle of order bears some remote analogy to it. Will you quarrel, Gentlemen, about the degrees, and enter into a controversy, which admits not of any precise meaning, nor consequently of any determination? If you should be so obstinate, I should not be surprised to find you insensibly change sides; while the Theist, on the one hand, exaggerates the dissimilarity between the Supreme Being, and frail, imperfect, variable, fleeting, and mortal creatures; and the Atheist, on the other, magnifies the analogy among all the operations of Nature, in every period, every situation, and every position. Consider then, where the real point of controversy lies; and if you cannot lay aside your disputes, endeavour, at least, to cure yourselves of your animosity.

All reasonable people are put off by endless arguments, which are so common in philosophical and theological discussions. It turns out that the only solution to this issue lies in clear definitions, the precision of the concepts involved in any argument, and the strict and consistent use of the terms that are used. However, there’s a type of debate that, due to the very nature of language and human concepts, is always shrouded in ambiguity and will never reach reasonable certainty or clarity, no matter what precautions or definitions are used. These debates concern the degrees of any quality or situation. People could argue forever about whether HANNIBAL is a great, very great, or extremely great man, what level of beauty CLEOPATRA had, or what praise LIVY or THUCYDIDES deserve, without ever coming to a conclusion. The debaters might agree on their meaning but disagree on the terms, or vice versa, yet they will never manage to define their terms in a way that helps them understand each other. This is because the degrees of these qualities cannot be measured accurately like quantity or number, which could serve as a standard in the argument. The debate about Theism is of this nature and is thus merely verbal, or perhaps even more hopelessly ambiguous, as will become clear with a bit of inquiry. I ask the Theist if he acknowledges that there is a vast and immeasurable—because incomprehensible—difference between the human and divine mind. The more devout he is, the more likely he will agree and feel inclined to emphasize that difference. He would even argue that the difference is of a kind that can’t be oversold. I then turn to the Atheist, whom I contend is only nominally one and can’t possibly be serious, and I ask him if, given the coherence and apparent harmony in all parts of this world, there isn’t some level of analogy among all the natural processes, at any time and in any context; whether the decay of a turnip, the birth of an animal, and the workings of human thought might not have some distant analogy to one another. It's impossible for him to deny this; he will likely concede it. After gaining this concession, I press him further and ask if it’s not likely that the principle that first organized and still upholds order in this universe also has some distant and unimaginable connection to the other processes of nature, including the workings of the human mind. No matter how reluctant he might be, he must agree. So I ask both of these opponents, where is the subject of your disagreement? The Theist agrees that the original intelligence is very different from human reasoning; the Atheist agrees that the original principle of order has some distant analogy to it. Will you, gentlemen, argue about the degrees and engage in a debate that doesn’t allow for any precise meaning or, consequently, any resolution? If you remain so stubborn, I wouldn’t be surprised to see you unconsciously switch sides; while the Theist, on one hand, exaggerates the difference between the Supreme Being and fragile, imperfect, changing, fleeting, and mortal creatures; and the Atheist, on the other hand, emphasizes the similarities among all the natural processes across every time, situation, and context. So consider where the real point of debate lies; and if you cannot set aside your arguments, at least try to rid yourselves of your hostility.

And here I must also acknowledge, CLEANTHES, that as the works of Nature have a much greater analogy to the effects of our art and contrivance, than to those of our benevolence and justice, we have reason to infer, that the natural attributes of the Deity have a greater resemblance to those of men, than his moral have to human virtues. But what is the consequence? Nothing but this, that the moral qualities of man are more defective in their kind than his natural abilities. For, as the Supreme Being is allowed to be absolutely and entirely perfect, whatever differs most from him, departs the furthest from the supreme standard of rectitude and perfection.

And here I must also point out, CLEANTHES, that the workings of Nature are much closer to the outcomes of our skills and creations than to our kindness and fairness. This leads us to believe that the natural qualities of the Deity are more similar to human traits than the moral ones are to human virtues. But what’s the result of this? Only that human moral qualities are more flawed than our natural abilities. Because, since the Supreme Being is considered completely and utterly perfect, whatever deviates the most from Him strays farthest from the highest standard of rightness and perfection.

It seems evident that the dispute between the Skeptics and Dogmatists is entirely verbal, or at least regards only the degrees of doubt and assurance which we ought to indulge with regard to all reasoning; and such disputes are commonly, at the bottom, verbal, and admit not of any precise determination. No philosophical Dogmatist denies that there are difficulties both with regard to the senses and to all science, and that these difficulties are in a regular, logical method, absolutely insolvable. No Skeptic denies that we lie under an absolute necessity, notwithstanding these difficulties, of thinking, and believing, and reasoning, with regard to all kinds of subjects, and even of frequently assenting with confidence and security. The only difference, then, between these sects, if they merit that name, is, that the Sceptic, from habit, caprice, or inclination, insists most on the difficulties; the Dogmatist, for like reasons, on the necessity.

It seems clear that the disagreement between Skeptics and Dogmatists is mostly about words, or at least focuses on the levels of doubt and certainty we should have about all reasoning; such disagreements are usually, at their core, just verbal and do not allow for any exact resolution. No philosophical Dogmatist denies that there are challenges related to our senses and to all science, and that these challenges are, in a structured, logical way, completely unsolvable. No Skeptic denies that we are absolutely forced, despite these challenges, to think, believe, and reason about all kinds of topics, and even to often agree with confidence and assurance. So, the only real difference between these groups, if they deserve that label, is that the Skeptic tends to focus more on the difficulties, while the Dogmatist, for similar reasons, emphasizes the necessity.

These, CLEANTHES, are my unfeigned sentiments on this subject; and these sentiments, you know, I have ever cherished and maintained. But in proportion to my veneration for true religion, is my abhorrence of vulgar superstitions; and I indulge a peculiar pleasure, I confess, in pushing such principles, sometimes into absurdity, sometimes into impiety. And you are sensible, that all bigots, notwithstanding their great aversion to the latter above the former, are commonly equally guilty of both.

These, CLEANTHES, are my genuine feelings on this topic; and these feelings, as you know, I have always valued and supported. However, the more I respect true religion, the more I despise common superstitions; I admit I take a certain pleasure in taking such beliefs to their extremes, sometimes to the point of absurdity, sometimes crossing into irreverence. And you know, all bigots, despite their strong dislike for the latter over the former, are usually equally guilty of both.

My inclination, replied CLEANTHES, lies, I own, a contrary way. Religion, however corrupted, is still better than no religion at all. The doctrine of a future state is so strong and necessary a security to morals, that we never ought to abandon or neglect it. For if finite and temporary rewards and punishments have so great an effect, as we daily find; how much greater must be expected from such as are infinite and eternal?

My tendency, replied CLEANTHES, I admit, is quite the opposite. Even if religion is flawed, it's still better than having no religion at all. The belief in an afterlife is such an important and necessary assurance for morals that we should never give it up or ignore it. If the limited and temporary rewards and punishments have such a significant impact, as we observe every day, how much greater must we expect from those that are infinite and eternal?

How happens it then, said PHILO, if vulgar superstition be so salutary to society, that all history abounds so much with accounts of its pernicious consequences on public affairs? Factions, civil wars, persecutions, subversions of government, oppression, slavery; these are the dismal consequences which always attend its prevalency over the minds of men. If the religious spirit be ever mentioned in any historical narration, we are sure to meet afterwards with a detail of the miseries which attend it. And no period of time can be happier or more prosperous, than those in which it is never regarded or heard of.

How is it then, said PHILO, that if common superstition is so beneficial to society, all of history is filled with accounts of its harmful effects on public matters? Factions, civil wars, persecutions, government overthrows, oppression, slavery; these are the grim outcomes that always follow its dominance over people's minds. Whenever the religious spirit is mentioned in any historical account, we can be sure to later encounter a description of the suffering that comes with it. And no time can be happier or more prosperous than those periods when it is completely ignored or unheard of.

The reason of this observation, replied CLEANTHES, is obvious. The proper office of religion is to regulate the heart of men, humanise their conduct, infuse the spirit of temperance, order, and obedience; and as its operation is silent, and only enforces the motives of morality and justice, it is in danger of being overlooked, and confounded with these other motives. When it distinguishes itself, and acts as a separate principle over men, it has departed from its proper sphere, and has become only a cover to faction and ambition.

The reason for this observation, replied CLEANTHES, is clear. The main purpose of religion is to guide people's hearts, improve their behavior, and instill values like self-control, order, and obedience. Since its influence is quiet and primarily promotes the principles of morality and justice, it risks being ignored and mixed up with these other motivations. When religion sets itself apart and operates as a distinct principle over people, it has moved out of its rightful role and has merely turned into a disguise for conflict and ambition.

And so will all religion, said PHILO, except the philosophical and rational kind. Your reasonings are more easily eluded than my facts. The inference is not just, because finite and temporary rewards and punishments have so great influence, that therefore such as are infinite and eternal must have so much greater. Consider, I beseech you, the attachment which we have to present things, and the little concern which we discover for objects so remote and uncertain. When divines are declaiming against the common behaviour and conduct of the world, they always represent this principle as the strongest imaginable (which indeed it is); and describe almost all human kind as lying under the influence of it, and sunk into the deepest lethargy and unconcern about their religious interests. Yet these same divines, when they refute their speculative antagonists, suppose the motives of religion to be so powerful, that, without them, it were impossible for civil society to subsist; nor are they ashamed of so palpable a contradiction. It is certain, from experience, that the smallest grain of natural honesty and benevolence has more effect on men's conduct, than the most pompous views suggested by theological theories and systems. A man's natural inclination works incessantly upon him; it is for ever present to the mind, and mingles itself with every view and consideration: whereas religious motives, where they act at all, operate only by starts and bounds; and it is scarcely possible for them to become altogether habitual to the mind. The force of the greatest gravity, say the philosophers, is infinitely small, in comparison of that of the least impulse: yet it is certain, that the smallest gravity will, in the end, prevail above a great impulse; because no strokes or blows can be repeated with such constancy as attraction and gravitation.

And so will all religions, said PHILO, except for the philosophical and rational type. Your arguments are easier to dodge than my facts. The reasoning isn’t fair, because finite and temporary rewards and punishments have such a strong influence that it doesn't follow that infinite and eternal ones must have even greater influence. Please consider the attachment we have to present things and how little we care for things that are so distant and uncertain. When religious leaders criticize the common behavior and conduct of the world, they often highlight this principle as the most powerful (which it is). They describe almost all of humanity as being under its influence and sinking into deep lethargy and indifference about their religious interests. Yet, these same leaders, when refuting their theoretical opponents, assume that the motives for religion are so strong that, without them, civil society couldn’t survive; they seem unbothered by such a clear contradiction. Experience shows that even the smallest amount of natural honesty and kindness has a greater impact on people's behavior than the grandest ideas suggested by theological theories and systems. A person’s natural inclination constantly affects them; it's always present in their mind and mixes with every view and consideration. In contrast, religious motives, when they do act, only kick in sporadically; they rarely become fully habitual in the mind. Philosophers say that the force of the greatest gravity is infinitely small compared to that of the slightest push; yet it’s clear that the slightest gravity will eventually overcome a strong push, because no hits or strikes can be delivered with the same consistency as attraction and gravitation.

Another advantage of inclination: It engages on its side all the wit and ingenuity of the mind; and when set in opposition to religious principles, seeks every method and art of eluding them: In which it is almost always successful. Who can explain the heart of man, or account for those strange salvos and excuses, with which people satisfy themselves, when they follow their inclinations in opposition to their religious duty? This is well understood in the world; and none but fools ever repose less trust in a man, because they hear, that from study and philosophy, he has entertained some speculative doubts with regard to theological subjects. And when we have to do with a man, who makes a great profession of religion and devotion, has this any other effect upon several, who pass for prudent, than to put them on their guard, lest they be cheated and deceived by him?

Another advantage of inclination: It taps into all the cleverness and creativity of the mind; and when it goes against religious principles, it finds every possible way to get around them: And it usually succeeds. Who can truly understand the human heart or explain the odd justifications and excuses that people come up with to feel okay about following their inclinations instead of their religious duties? This is well known in society; and only fools ever trust a person any less because they learn that he has entertained some doubts about religious topics through study and philosophy. When dealing with someone who loudly professes their faith and devotion, does this really cause those who are seen as sensible to do anything other than stay cautious, fearing they might be misled or tricked by him?

We must further consider, that philosophers, who cultivate reason and reflection, stand less in need of such motives to keep them under the restraint of morals; and that the vulgar, who alone may need them, are utterly incapable of so pure a religion as represents the Deity to be pleased with nothing but virtue in human behaviour. The recommendations to the Divinity are generally supposed to be either frivolous observances, or rapturous ecstasies, or a bigoted credulity. We need not run back into antiquity, or wander into remote regions, to find instances of this degeneracy. Amongst ourselves, some have been guilty of that atrociousness, unknown to the Egyptian and Grecian superstitions, of declaiming in express terms, against morality; and representing it as a sure forfeiture of the Divine favour, if the least trust or reliance be laid upon it.

We should also consider that philosophers, who engage in reason and reflection, need fewer incentives to adhere to moral standards. In contrast, the general public, who are the ones that might require such incentives, are completely incapable of a pure faith that believes the Divine only values virtue in human behavior. The offerings to the Divine are usually seen as either trivial rituals, ecstatic experiences, or blind faith. We don't need to look back to ancient times or distant places to find examples of this decline. Right here among us, some have committed the shocking act—unheard of in Egyptian and Greek superstitions—of explicitly arguing against morality and suggesting that even the slightest trust or reliance on it leads to the loss of Divine favor.

But even though superstition or enthusiasm should not put itself in direct opposition to morality; the very diverting of the attention, the raising up a new and frivolous species of merit, the preposterous distribution which it makes of praise and blame, must have the most pernicious consequences, and weaken extremely men's attachment to the natural motives of justice and humanity.

But even though superstition or enthusiasm shouldn't directly oppose morality, just the act of diverting attention, creating a new and trivial kind of merit, and the ridiculous way it distributes praise and blame must have harmful effects and severely weaken people's connection to the natural motivations of justice and compassion.

Such a principle of action likewise, not being any of the familiar motives of human conduct, acts only by intervals on the temper; and must be roused by continual efforts, in order to render the pious zealot satisfied with his own conduct, and make him fulfil his devotional task. Many religious exercises are entered into with seeming fervour, where the heart, at the time, feels cold and languid: A habit of dissimulation is by degrees contracted; and fraud and falsehood become the predominant principle. Hence the reason of that vulgar observation, that the highest zeal in religion and the deepest hypocrisy, so far from being inconsistent, are often or commonly united in the same individual character.

Such a principle of action, not being any of the usual motives behind human behavior, only affects the mood intermittently and needs to be stimulated through constant effort to make the devout believer feel satisfied with their actions and complete their religious duties. Many religious practices are undertaken with apparent enthusiasm, even when the heart feels cold and indifferent at that moment. This gradually leads to a habit of pretending, and deceit and falsehood become the main driving force. This explains the common saying that the greatest zeal in religion and the deepest hypocrisy are often found together in the same person.

The bad effects of such habits, even in common life, are easily imagined; but where the interests of religion are concerned, no morality can be forcible enough to bind the enthusiastic zealot. The sacredness of the cause sanctifies every measure which can be made use of to promote it.

The negative effects of such habits, even in everyday life, are easy to picture; but when it comes to the interests of religion, no moral argument can be strong enough to restrain an enthusiastic believer. The importance of the cause makes any action taken to support it seem justified.

The steady attention alone to so important an interest as that of eternal salvation, is apt to extinguish the benevolent affections, and beget a narrow, contracted selfishness. And when such a temper is encouraged, it easily eludes all the general precepts of charity and benevolence.

The constant focus on something as crucial as eternal salvation can stifle our kindness and lead to a narrow, selfish mindset. When this attitude is fostered, it easily ignores the broader principles of charity and compassion.

Thus, the motives of vulgar superstition have no great influence on general conduct; nor is their operation favourable to morality, in the instances where they predominate.

Thus, the motives of common superstition have little impact on overall behavior; nor is their effect beneficial to morality in the cases where they are dominant.

Is there any maxim in politics more certain and infallible, than that both the number and authority of priests should be confined within very narrow limits; and that the civil magistrate ought, for ever, to keep his fasces and axes from such dangerous hands? But if the spirit of popular religion were so salutary to society, a contrary maxim ought to prevail. The greater number of priests, and their greater authority and riches, will always augment the religious spirit. And though the priests have the guidance of this spirit, why may we not expect a superior sanctity of life, and greater benevolence and moderation, from persons who are set apart for religion, who are continually inculcating it upon others, and who must themselves imbibe a greater share of it? Whence comes it then, that, in fact, the utmost a wise magistrate can propose with regard to popular religions, is, as far as possible, to make a saving game of it, and to prevent their pernicious consequences with regard to society? Every expedient which he tries for so humble a purpose is surrounded with inconveniences. If he admits only one religion among his subjects, he must sacrifice, to an uncertain prospect of tranquillity, every consideration of public liberty, science, reason, industry, and even his own independency. If he gives indulgence to several sects, which is the wiser maxim, he must preserve a very philosophical indifference to all of them, and carefully restrain the pretensions of the prevailing sect; otherwise he can expect nothing but endless disputes, quarrels, factions, persecutions, and civil commotions.

Is there any political rule more certain and foolproof than that both the number and power of religious leaders should be kept within very narrow limits? The civil authority should always keep its power away from such dangerous influences. But if popular religion were truly beneficial to society, a different rule would need to apply. A greater number of religious leaders, along with their increased power and wealth, will always boost religious sentiment. And although religious leaders guide this sentiment, can’t we expect a higher standard of living, greater kindness, and moderation from those who are dedicated to religious life, who constantly teach it to others, and who must embody more of it themselves? So why is it that, in reality, the best a wise leader can hope for regarding popular religions is, as much as possible, to keep it a manageable issue and to prevent its harmful effects on society? Every strategy he tries for this modest goal is met with difficulties. If he allows only one religion among his people, he must sacrifice, for the sake of uncertain peace, all considerations of public liberty, knowledge, reason, productivity, and even his own autonomy. If he permits multiple sects, which is the smarter approach, he must maintain a very neutral attitude towards all of them and carefully limit the claims of the dominant sect; otherwise, he can anticipate nothing but endless arguments, conflicts, factions, persecutions, and civil unrest.

True religion, I allow, has no such pernicious consequences: but we must treat of religion, as it has commonly been found in the world; nor have I any thing to do with that speculative tenet of Theism, which, as it is a species of philosophy, must partake of the beneficial influence of that principle, and at the same time must lie under a like inconvenience, of being always confined to very few persons.

True religion, I agree, doesn’t have such harmful effects: but we need to discuss religion as it’s generally been practiced in the world; nor do I have anything to do with that theoretical belief in Theism, which, being a type of philosophy, must share in the positive effects of that principle, while also suffering from the same limitation of being accessible to only a small number of people.

Oaths are requisite in all courts of judicature; but it is a question whether their authority arises from any popular religion. It is the solemnity and importance of the occasion, the regard to reputation, and the reflecting on the general interests of society, which are the chief restraints upon mankind. Custom-house oaths and political oaths are but little regarded even by some who pretend to principles of honesty and religion; and a Quaker's asseveration is with us justly put upon the same footing with the oath of any other person. I know, that POLYBIUS [Lib. vi. cap. 54.] ascribes the infamy of GREEK faith to the prevalency of the EPICUREAN philosophy: but I know also, that Punic faith had as bad a reputation in ancient times as Irish evidence has in modern; though we cannot account for these vulgar observations by the same reason. Not to mention that Greek faith was infamous before the rise of the Epicurean philosophy; and EURIPIDES [Iphigenia in Tauride], in a passage which I shall point out to you, has glanced a remarkable stroke of satire against his nation, with regard to this circumstance.

Oaths are necessary in all courts of law; but it’s debatable whether their authority comes from any mainstream religion. The seriousness and significance of the occasion, concern for one’s reputation, and the consideration of society's overall interests are the main restraints on human behavior. Customs and political oaths are often disregarded even by those who claim to have principles of honesty and faith; a Quaker's affirmation is rightly viewed the same way as the oath of anyone else. I know that POLYBIUS [Lib. vi. cap. 54.] attributes the bad reputation of GREEK trust to the dominance of the EPICUREAN philosophy: but I also recognize that Punic trust had a similarly negative reputation in ancient times, just as Irish testimony does in modern times; however, we can’t explain these common perceptions with the same reasoning. Not to mention that Greek trust was already infamous before the emergence of Epicurean philosophy; and EURIPIDES [Iphigenia in Tauride], in a passage I’ll highlight for you, makes a sharp satirical comment about his people regarding this issue.

Take care, PHILO, replied CLEANTHES, take care: push not matters too far: allow not your zeal against false religion to undermine your veneration for the true. Forfeit not this principle, the chief, the only great comfort in life; and our principal support amidst all the attacks of adverse fortune. The most agreeable reflection, which it is possible for human imagination to suggest, is that of genuine Theism, which represents us as the workmanship of a Being perfectly good, wise, and powerful; who created us for happiness; and who, having implanted in us immeasurable desires of good, will prolong our existence to all eternity, and will transfer us into an infinite variety of scenes, in order to satisfy those desires, and render our felicity complete and durable. Next to such a Being himself (if the comparison be allowed), the happiest lot which we can imagine, is that of being under his guardianship and protection.

"Be careful, Philo," replied Cleanthes, "be careful: don't push things too far. Don’t let your passion against false religion undermine your respect for the true one. Don’t give up this principle, which is the main source of comfort in life and our primary support during tough times. The most comforting thought that human imagination can offer is that of genuine Theism, which portrays us as the creation of a Being who is perfectly good, wise, and powerful; who made us for happiness; and who, having instilled in us endless desires for good, will extend our existence for all eternity, moving us through an infinite variety of experiences to fulfill those desires and make our happiness complete and lasting. Next to such a Being himself (if that comparison is allowed), the best situation we can imagine is being under his guidance and protection."

These appearances, said PHILO, are most engaging and alluring; and with regard to the true philosopher, they are more than appearances. But it happens here, as in the former case, that, with regard to the greater part of mankind, the appearances are deceitful, and that the terrors of religion commonly prevail above its comforts.

These appearances, PHILO said, are really captivating and attractive; and for the true philosopher, they’re more than just appearances. But just like before, for most people, these appearances can be misleading, and often the fears associated with religion outweigh its comforts.

It is allowed, that men never have recourse to devotion so readily as when dejected with grief or depressed with sickness. Is not this a proof, that the religious spirit is not so nearly allied to joy as to sorrow?

It’s true that people often turn to prayer and devotion more easily when they’re feeling sad or unwell. Isn’t this evidence that the religious spirit is more connected to sorrow than to joy?

But men, when afflicted, find consolation in religion, replied CLEANTHES. Sometimes, said PHILO: but it is natural to imagine, that they will form a notion of those unknown beings, suitably to the present gloom and melancholy of their temper, when they betake themselves to the contemplation of them. Accordingly, we find the tremendous images to predominate in all religions; and we ourselves, after having employed the most exalted expression in our descriptions of the Deity, fall into the flattest contradiction in affirming that the damned are infinitely superior in number to the elect.

But men, when they're troubled, find comfort in religion, replied CLEANTHES. Sometimes, said PHILO, but it's natural to think that they will picture those unknown beings in a way that reflects their current sadness and gloom when they start to contemplate them. As a result, we see that frightening images dominate all religions; and we ourselves, after using the most elevated language in our descriptions of God, end up contradicting ourselves by claiming that the damned are far more numerous than the chosen few.

I shall venture to affirm, that there never was a popular religion, which represented the state of departed souls in such a light, as would render it eligible for human kind that there should be such a state. These fine models of religion are the mere product of philosophy. For as death lies between the eye and the prospect of futurity, that event is so shocking to Nature, that it must throw a gloom on all the regions which lie beyond it; and suggest to the generality of mankind the idea of CERBERUS and FURIES; devils, and torrents of fire and brimstone.

I’ll go ahead and say that there has never been a popular religion that portrayed the state of souls after death in a way that would make it appealing for people to believe there is such a state. These ideal versions of religion are just products of philosophy. Since death stands between us and the possibility of what comes next, that event is so terrifying to our nature that it casts a shadow over everything that lies beyond it; leading most people to imagine things like CERBERUS and the FURIES, devils, and rivers of fire and brimstone.

It is true, both fear and hope enter into religion; because both these passions, at different times, agitate the human mind, and each of them forms a species of divinity suitable to itself. But when a man is in a cheerful disposition, he is fit for business, or company, or entertainment of any kind; and he naturally applies himself to these, and thinks not of religion. When melancholy and dejected, he has nothing to do but brood upon the terrors of the invisible world, and to plunge himself still deeper in affliction. It may indeed happen, that after he has, in this manner, engraved the religious opinions deep into his thought and imagination, there may arrive a change of health or circumstances, which may restore his good humour, and raising cheerful prospects of futurity, make him run into the other extreme of joy and triumph. But still it must be acknowledged, that, as terror is the primary principle of religion, it is the passion which always predominates in it, and admits but of short intervals of pleasure.

It's true that both fear and hope play a role in religion; these emotions stir the human mind at different times, each creating a type of divinity that suits it. However, when someone is in a good mood, they're ready for work, socializing, or any kind of fun; they naturally focus on these activities and don’t think about religion. When feeling sad or down, all they can do is dwell on the fears of the unseen world, which only deepens their despair. It may happen that after they have really internalized these religious beliefs, a change in their health or situation might bring back their good spirits, lifting their hopes for the future and making them swing to the other side of joy and celebration. Still, it must be acknowledged that since fear is the main driving force behind religion, it remains the dominant emotion, allowing only brief moments of happiness.

Not to mention, that these fits of excessive, enthusiastic joy, by exhausting the spirits, always prepare the way for equal fits of superstitious terror and dejection; nor is there any state of mind so happy as the calm and equable. But this state it is impossible to support, where a man thinks that he lies in such profound darkness and uncertainty, between an eternity of happiness and an eternity of misery. No wonder that such an opinion disjoints the ordinary frame of the mind, and throws it into the utmost confusion. And though that opinion is seldom so steady in its operation as to influence all the actions; yet it is apt to make a considerable breach in the temper, and to produce that gloom and melancholy so remarkable in all devout people.

Not to mention that these fits of extreme, enthusiastic joy, by wearing out the spirit, always lead to equal fits of superstitious fear and gloom; and there’s no state of mind as happy as a calm and steady one. But it's impossible to maintain that state when someone feels that they are stuck in such deep darkness and uncertainty, caught between an eternity of happiness and an eternity of misery. It’s no surprise that such a belief disrupts usual thinking and leads to great confusion. And while that belief doesn’t always consistently affect every action, it can significantly impact a person’s mood, creating the gloom and sadness often seen in deeply religious individuals.

It is contrary to common sense to entertain apprehensions or terrors upon account of any opinion whatsoever, or to imagine that we run any risk hereafter, by the freest use of our reason. Such a sentiment implies both an absurdity and an inconsistency. It is an absurdity to believe that the Deity has human passions, and one of the lowest of human passions, a restless appetite for applause. It is an inconsistency to believe, that, since the Deity has this human passion, he has not others also; and, in particular, a disregard to the opinions of creatures so much inferior.

It’s unreasonable to feel fear or anxiety about any opinion at all, or to think that we’re in any danger in the future by using our reason freely. Such a belief is both foolish and contradictory. It’s foolish to think that God has human emotions, especially one of the more lowly human feelings, like an insatiable desire for praise. It’s contradictory to believe that if God has this human emotion, then He doesn’t have others as well; specifically, a lack of concern for the opinions of beings far beneath Him.

To know God, says SENECA, is to worship him. All other worship is indeed absurd, superstitious, and even impious. It degrades him to the low condition of mankind, who are delighted with entreaty, solicitation, presents, and flattery. Yet is this impiety the smallest of which superstition is guilty. Commonly, it depresses the Deity far below the condition of mankind; and represents him as a capricious DEMON, who exercises his power without reason and without humanity! And were that Divine Being disposed to be offended at the vices and follies of silly mortals, who are his own workmanship, ill would it surely fare with the votaries of most popular superstitions. Nor would any of human race merit his favour, but a very few, the philosophical Theists, who entertain, or rather indeed endeavour to entertain, suitable notions of his Divine perfections: As the only persons entitled to his compassion and indulgence would be the philosophical Sceptics, a sect almost equally rare, who, from a natural diffidence of their own capacity, suspend, or endeavour to suspend, all judgement with regard to such sublime and such extraordinary subjects.

To know God, says SENECA, is to worship Him. Any other form of worship is really absurd, superstitious, and even disrespectful. It lowers Him to the level of humanity, who are pleased by pleas, requests, gifts, and flattery. However, this disrespect is just the beginning of what superstition gets wrong. Generally, it brings the Deity down far below the state of mankind and portrays Him as a fickle DEMON, who wields His power without reason or compassion! If that Divine Being were inclined to take offense at the vices and foolishness of silly humans, who He created, it would not go well for the followers of most popular superstitions. No one from the human race would earn His favor except for a very few, the philosophical Theists, who hold or strive to hold appropriate views of His Divine qualities. The only ones worthy of His compassion and tolerance would be the philosophical Sceptics, a group that’s almost just as rare, who, out of a natural doubt in their own understanding, hold off or try to hold off any judgment on such profound and extraordinary matters.

If the whole of Natural Theology, as some people seem to maintain, resolves itself into one simple, though somewhat ambiguous, at least undefined proposition, That the cause or causes of order in the universe probably bear some remote analogy to human intelligence: If this proposition be not capable of extension, variation, or more particular explication: If it affords no inference that affects human life, or can be the source of any action or forbearance: And if the analogy, imperfect as it is, can be carried no further than to the human intelligence, and cannot be transferred, with any appearance of probability, to the other qualities of the mind; if this really be the case, what can the most inquisitive, contemplative, and religious man do more than give a plain, philosophical assent to the proposition, as often as it occurs, and believe that the arguments on which it is established exceed the objections which lie against it? Some astonishment, indeed, will naturally arise from the greatness of the object; some melancholy from its obscurity; some contempt of human reason, that it can give no solution more satisfactory with regard to so extraordinary and magnificent a question. But believe me, CLEANTHES, the most natural sentiment which a well-disposed mind will feel on this occasion, is a longing desire and expectation that Heaven would be pleased to dissipate, at least alleviate, this profound ignorance, by affording some more particular revelation to mankind, and making discoveries of the nature, attributes, and operations of the Divine object of our faith. A person, seasoned with a just sense of the imperfections of natural reason, will fly to revealed truth with the greatest avidity: While the haughty Dogmatist, persuaded that he can erect a complete system of Theology by the mere help of philosophy, disdains any further aid, and rejects this adventitious instructor. To be a philosophical Sceptic is, in a man of letters, the first and most essential step towards being a sound, believing Christian; a proposition which I would willingly recommend to the attention of PAMPHILUS: And I hope CLEANTHES will forgive me for interposing so far in the education and instruction of his pupil.

If Natural Theology, as some people seem to suggest, boils down to one simple, yet somewhat vague and undefined idea—that the causes of order in the universe likely have some distant resemblance to human intelligence: If this idea can’t be expanded, changed, or explained further: If it doesn’t lead to any implications that impact human life, or inspire any actions or restraint: And if this imperfect analogy can't be stretched beyond human intelligence and can’t likely be applied to other aspects of the mind; if that's truly the case, what can the most curious, thoughtful, and spiritual person do besides agreeing philosophically with this idea whenever it comes up, and believing that the arguments supporting it are stronger than the opposing views? Some surprise is bound to arise from the enormity of the topic; some sadness from its obscurity; some disdain for human reason that fails to provide a more satisfying answer to such an extraordinary and awe-inspiring question. But believe me, CLEANTHES, the most natural feeling for a well-disposed mind in this situation is a deep desire and expectation that Heaven would be willing to clear up, or at least lessen, this profound ignorance by giving humanity a more detailed revelation about the nature, attributes, and workings of the Divine being we believe in. A person who recognizes the limitations of natural reason will eagerly turn to revealed truth: while the arrogant Dogmatist, convinced that he can build a complete system of Theology solely through philosophy, dismisses any additional help and rejects this external guide. Being a philosophical skeptic is, for an educated person, the first and most crucial step toward becoming a true, believing Christian; a statement that I would be happy to highlight for PAMPHILUS’s attention. And I hope CLEANTHES will forgive me for stepping in a bit in the education and guidance of his student.

CLEANTHES and PHILO pursued not this conversation much further: and as nothing ever made greater impression on me, than all the reasonings of that day, so I confess, that, upon a serious review of the whole, I cannot but think, that PHILO's principles are more probable than DEMEA's; but that those of CLEANTHES approach still nearer to the truth.

CLEANTHES and PHILO didn't continue this conversation for long: and since nothing has ever impacted me more than all the arguments from that day, I admit that after seriously reviewing everything, I can’t help but think that PHILO’s ideas are more likely to be true than DEMEA’s; however, CLEANTHES’s views come even closer to the truth.






Download ePUB

If you like this ebook, consider a donation!